Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science
Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science
Editors
JURGEN RENN, Max-Planck-Institute for the History of Science and KOSTAS GAVROGLU, University of Athens
ROBERTS. COHEN, Boston University
VOLUME204
NIETZSCHE,
EPISTEMOLOGY,
AND PHILOSOPHY OF
SCIENCE
NIETZSCHE AND THE SCIENCES II
Edited by
BABETTE E. BABICH
Fordham University
in cooperation with
ROBERT S. COHEN
Boston University
Marx W artofsky
1928-1997
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgments ix
List of Abbreviations Used Xl
INTRODUCTION
ANALYTIC PERSPECTIVES:
ATOMISM, REALISM, NATURALISM, POSITIVISM
Index 367
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
lX
X ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
In general, references to Nietzsche's works are abbreviated and included in the body of the text.
References to all other works are listed in the notes to each individual contribution, though this
may vary with different authors. In addition, because this collection is not intended for the
specialist reader alone, an effort has been made to keep references as general as possible.
Specialists will not find this rigorous but it is hoped that by the same token, nonspecialists may
find the discussions less forbidding. This is an overall guide. Some essays will employ individual
conventions.
xi
xii LIST OF ABBREVIATIONS USED
referencing other translations or the original text, the section titles cor-
responding to cited page ranges are: "Foreword'': 21-22; "Maxims and
Arrows": 23-27; "The Problem of Socrates": 29-34; "'Reason" in Phi-
losophy": 35-39; "How the 'Real World' at last Became a Myth": 40-
41; "Morality as Anti-Nature: 42-46; "The Four Great Errors": 47-54;
"The 'Improvers' of Mankind": 55-59; "What the Germans Lack": 60-
66; "Expeditions of an Untimely Man": 67-104; "What I Owe to the An-
cients": 105-111.
EH Ecce Homo, ([1888] 1908), trans. R. J.Hollingdale (Harmond-
sworth!London: Penguin, 1979, 1992). Cited by page number; certain
essays list essay headings and section numbers. For convenience in ref-
erencing other translations or the original text, the section titles corre-
sponding to cited page ranges are: "Foreword''; 33-36; "Epigraph": 37;
"Why I Am So Wise": 38-50; "Why I Am So Clever": 51-68; "Why I
Write Such Excellent Books": 69-77; "The Birth of Tragedy": 78-83;
"The Untimely Essays": 84--88; "Human, All Too Human": 89-94;
"Daybreak": 95-97; ''The Gay Science": 98; "Thus Spoke Zarathustra":
99-111; "Beyond Good and Evil": 112-113; "The Genealogy of Mor-
als": 114-115; "Twilight of the Idols": 116-118; "The Wagner Case":
119-125; "Why I Am A Destiny": 126-134.
WM The Will to Power, ed. and trans. Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale
(New York: Vintage Books, 1968). Cited by section number. For corre-
sponding Nachlaj3 references please see the recent double concordance
to the KSA and KGW editions by Scott Simmons in New Nietzsche
Studies I:l/2 (1996):126-153. See also Marie-Luise Haase and Jorg
Salaquarda, "Konkordanz. Der Wille zur Macht: Nachlass in chronolo-
gischer Ordnung der Kritische Gesamtausgabe," Nietzsche-Studien 9
(1980): 446-490.
OTHER WORKS
KdrV I. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Hamburg: Meiner, 1990). Also listed
as CPR with reference to The Critique of Pure Reason, trans. N. Kemp-
Smith (New York: St. Martin's Press, 1965. London: Macmillan & Co.,
Ltd., 1929).
NSI Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, and Critical Theory:
Nietzsche and the Sciences I (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999).
NSII Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science:
Nietzsche and the Sciences II (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999).
ALASDAIR MACINTYRE
PREFACE
XV
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, xv-xvii.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
XVI ALASDAIR MACINTYRE
Duke University
ENDNOTES
1 Steven Weinberg, "Physics and History" in Daedalus 127, I. Winter 1998, p. 162.
2 Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, R. J. Hollingdale, trans., (London: Penguin Books,
1973), 14, p. 26.
3 Weinberg, p. 162.
4 Weinberg, p. 163.
BABETTE E. BABICH
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Episterrwlogy, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, l-24.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
2 BABETTE E. BABICH
With such strong language I mean to say that Nietzsche's thought is less
anathema to analytic conceptual schemes than simply outside its horizonal ken.
But in this esoteric/exoteric sense, Nietzsche's thought persists as a kind of
conceptual dynamite interior to philosophy, from both analytic and continental
perspectives. While the analytic approach has every conviction of right reason
on its side and although it has come to be interested in Nietzsche's epistemo-
logical critique from the side of this same prerogative, it lacks the resources to
read or to understand Nietzsche. By contrast, although politically inept for
reasons of powerlessness and pusillanimity, the continental approach possesses
the only resources with which what Nietzsche has to offer can be appropriated
in all its philosophical complexity. This last term is key to Nietzsche's episte-
mology. Real truth, so far from simplicitt as the real truth of the real world for
Nietzsche, is unspeakably complicated. 1
To emphasize the differences here means that the exactly cognitive disso-
nance of the initial contrast is importantly irreducible for Nietzsche's contribu-
tions as a philosopher and for the overall project of philosophy itself. Philo-
sophically, the overall, putatively plausible analytic effort to "make sense" of
Nietzsche has kept company with Nietzsche's reception in English since the
beginning of this century but efforts to tailor Nietzsche to fit the distinctive
concepts and schemes of analytic reason represent a mistaken passion. Attend-
ing to the process of Nietzsche's own manifestly provocative style of philo-
sophic thinking should move us away from errors of this kind as well as towards
a better sense of his thought.
***
From his earliest to his latest work, Nietzsche discusses the crucial philosophi-
cal questions of knowledge and truth and reflects upon the culture, significance,
and theoretical practice of science. Where he differs from professional discipli-
nary style and scholarship is in his approach to these philosophical problems:
rather than asking, for example, how knowledge is possible, he challenges the
TRUTH, ART, AND LIFE 5
factive, are not possible. In our mouths, he says, they are brazenly false
judgments: we have no right to them (BGE 11).
By emphasising that "rational thought is an interpretation according to a
schema that we cannot throw off' (KSA 12, 194) and that "all of our organs for
knowledge and sense have developed with regard to the conditions of survival
and growth" (352), 27 Nietzsche's critical supposition is strictly bio-ecological.28
For Nietzsche, the conditions of the human mind and body, its species condition
in a changing and relational world, etc., are the critical conditions of the
possibility of what we name knowledge and truth. But Nietzsche's theory of
truth is not an ecological, pragmatic, or naturalist theory because he does not
forget what is involved when one proposes that one has or seeks truth. Utility
or efficacy for life-preservation is not strictly speaking, convertible with "truth"
as such.
When Nietzsche talks about truth he does not hedge as many contemporary
philosophers today are inclined to do, invoking a watered-down or pseudo or
"weak" conception of truth. Truth for Nietzsche (the truth he contends does not
exist), is exactly Platonic, or ideal, noumenal, or ultimate truth. Nor would
Nietzsche be the only one, to paraphrase Whitehead's dry judgment on the
history of philosophy, guilty of this same presumption. Every philosophic
account of truth, even the more pragmatic or ad hoc varieties, especially
accounts redefining truth in contrast to its Platonic institution, are dependent on
Plato in the same way. From this kind of Platonic/anti-Platonic perspective,
Nietzsche declares that the world of becoming, the domain of contingency and
change, excludes the possibility of truth: "Knowledge and becoming exclude one
another" (KSA 12, 382/ WP 517). 29 Thus- in a negative exemplification of its
ideal Platonic scheme - "truth," for Nietzsche, "cannot be recognized." This
means that qua empirical "truth" (i.e., what today is called scientific or even
factual truth): there is and can be no truth. "Everything knowable is illusion"
(KSA 7, 633/ TL, 97). Thus the real world (i.e., "nature") or apparent, empirical
reality may not be identified with the ideal or metaphysical world of Platonic
truth but rather the world of appearance, its evidentiality qua phenomenal world
or illusion, betrays the inevitable reference to the same ideality. If one could, as
one cannot, go back before Plato, the world of becoming would have its closest
family resemblance to the world of the Ionian philosophers. But the claim that
everything flows is itself (it might seem, be it from the start or in the end) a
Platonic gloss on Heraclitus and not a reflection upon what Heraclitus could call
the logos - which may not be identified as a logical (Platonico-Aristotelian)
identity. To this day, post-Parmenides as much as post-Plato, it is impossible to
restore the original innocence of the notion of becoming precisely as an
innocence that includes war as its logos above all, that is: contradiction and
pain.
Claiming that ''pure logic is the impossibility which maintains science" (KSA
7, 473), Nietzsche highlights the impropriety or incoherence of logic as the
theoretical support of empirical science. (Note that this could not be thought to
undermine the pure coherence of logical abstraction as such.) Declaiming "the
pathos of truth in a world of lies," Nietzsche's project recollects for us the
8 BABETTE E. BABICH
conflict of ideal truth with the changing reality of the real world. Because the
momentary tonus of reality is resonant flux, a backwards echo of what has been
and anticipatory tremor of what is not yet, every moment of reality - that is:
empirical nature- is captivated change. The "stone" fact that no fact is stone
means that the human knowledge project cannot grasp the empirical world
because what is real in it is never beyond change or time.
This empirical, temporal, real emphasis means that when Nietzsche cele-
brates the sciences of nature in antiquity and in the works of his contemporaries
such as Robert Mayer and Ernst Mach, what he celebrates is natural science
construed as an ultimately sensual rationality. Science for Nietzsche must be a
discipline of the bod/ 0 - what he names the "great reason" as opposed to the
smaller or "square little reason" (GS 373) of mathematics and logical theory.
Thus the science of nature for Nietzsche must be the science not of ideal events
and processes but of recondite reality becoming in time. This object of science
is the dynamic "truth" of what is real not the ideal and literal "truth of truth."
For Nietzsche, the so-called (scientific and logical) truth of truth is unreal: not
figuratively but literally insofar as it is theoretically ideal. This logical ideality
is the truth of tautology: logical truth. The becoming and changing nature
Nietzsche recalls to us, as scientists and as philosophers, can only be an illogical
nature and Nietzsche calls us to that same natural world for the honest sake of
science: "We live and think amid nothing but effects of what is illogical- in
ignorance and false knowledge" (KSA 6, 496). In every way then, Nietzsche
takes his thinking on logic, on truth, and reality to its "ultimate consequences,"
to use the language he employs in a related section on the needfullawlikeness
of nature. Thus Nietzsche illustrates the exigence of such consequential
reasoning as he describes his own anti-atomistic ideal of the non-law like
working of the will to power as an alternative account of '"nature's conformity
to law'" (BGE 22)? 1 It is important to emphasize that this notion of necessity
and law reflects the cosmologies of the first philosophers, or presocratic
thinkers. (Indeed it can be argued, here as an aside, that the only way to
understand the term necessity as Nietzsche uses the term is with reference to its
expression as chance in Plato's expression of Pythagorean cosmology in the
Timaeus. [D 130; cf. GS 109J) For Nietzsche, "knowledge" as a purely logical
enterprise strives for what is humanly or naturally impossible (all natural
knowledge is inherently anthropomorphic and hence the human and the natural
are inevitably convertible). The impossibility of a logical description of the
world is not an impossibility following from Nietzsche's terms of analysis but
and precisely an impossibility on the logical, unchanging terms philosophers set
as the (unconditioned) conditions of knowledge (cf. KSA 7, 519-520).
In my companion introduction to Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical
Theory, I found it important to observe that the same Nietzsche who offers a
genealogy of morals (out of the creative force of action denied action, that is
reactivity or res sentiment) and of tragedy (from ancient dithyrambic modes to
its contemporary decline as an "artform,") also offers a genealogy oflogic (out
of the spirit of illogic or illusion) and science (out of the spirit of myth and
magic and alchemy but ultimately on the occluded paradigm of religion). 32
TRUTH, ART, AND LIFE 9
Nietzsche finds the origins of logic on the side of metaphor, metonymy, and the
other tropes of language, groping towards an apprehension of a reality in transit,
an illogical real. Nietzsche re-reads the traditional philosophical account of the
origins of logic, telling us that logic has its beginnings in illogic. The pre-history
of logic is founded in contradiction: truth begins in error: in its antithesis? 3 Just
as almost every account of the pre-history of philosophy tells us: on the basis
of myth, we advance to logos; from superstition, we progress to reasoned belief,
and critical, empirical observation, and thence to scientific truths. But Nietzsche
asks how anything can begin in its opposite? How do we get truth from lie?
Altruism from egoism? Or- in his more typically received genealogical account
of social mores or Judeao-Christian doctrine- how do the meek (really) come
to inherit the earth? In what sense does the slave prove to master the master, or
the masochist enjoy the superior advantage in contrast with the sadist, or woman
primacy over a man in Western (as in Eastern) society? Nietzsche does not
suppose a dialectic here, he challenges the conviction at its root, supposing
inversion at best (thus the meek and the slave really assume the positions of
power or mastery), delusion at worst (the feminine ideal that complicity with the
same ideal preserves transcendent value for women). If, as Nietzsche argues in
one of his more unappealing claims, the crown of Christian love grows out of
the root of Jewish hatred, it need not be assumed that hatred has been transfig-
ured or redeemed as love. Instead, Nietzsche's genealogical inquiry lays out the
still surviving roots of hatred (or res sentiment to speak obliquely) at the heart
of Christian love.
In the case of logic, our ideal of the correct is derived from error or falsity,
not from any revelation of truth and the error is not sublated but it remains.
There is, in a word, no post-lapsarian history of logic following upon a lost
moment of golden insight into or "experience" of truth, and there is also no
redemption. We retain Plato's truth ideal but we have long since dispensed with
the ideal world. Nietzsche reminds us that in sense perception, as in our
anthropomorphic linguistic and epistemological constructions, we literally
(albeit not figuratively) have only what we call the false: that is, perception,
representation, not the ideal world, not the thing in itself. From raw experience,
from the so-called given, absolutely anything can follow. Thus, for Nietzsche,
"false inferences are more correctly understood as metonymies ... rhetorically
and poetically" (KSA 6, 486). 34 And yet as it involves a reflection upon both the
Humean critique of logical causality and the logical foundation of grammar (as
the grammatical origins of our automatic associations and our deepest convic-
tions regarding God and the subject) Nietzsche's insight is complicated. Given
contemporary, rigorous categorical separations, defined like art in contrast with
knowledge, conceived as rhetoric or as poetry, such "false inferences" are other
than (merely or literally) false. Nietzsche's point is not the point of convergence
or agreement with formal or informal logical calculi but rather the nuanced
observation that although "rhetorical figures" (which he parenthetically
identifies as "the essence of language," so that we do not overlook the dynamic
scheme of his argument) "are logically invalid inferences," what is then
consequently said to be true is generated via the same invalid process by
10 BABETTE E. BABICH
contrast with the recognition of what is false as such: "this is the way reason
begins" (KSA 468), i.e., without warrant. Nietzsche's deconstructive genealogy
of the discursively theoretical character of truth in contrast with its first, mythic
or primitive origins is thus the muster for a similarly minded history of the
problem of enlightenment civilization, as of true religion, and of science, social
and natural. 35
For Nietzsche, the drive for knowledge begins with an impossible demand in
the fantastic judgment that "to be true means to be true always." This demand
cannot have grown out of experience but only on the basis of the seduction of
the words that are always the same: seemingly tokens of eternity. The philoso-
pher is "caught in the nets of language" (KSA 6, 463) and "logic itself is merely
slavery within the fetters of language" (KSA 7, 623).
Our words are imprecise apprehensions of what is intended: they do not and
cannot touch the individual object or thing. Practical knowledge of real things
in the real world "involves the identification of things which are not the same,
of things which are only similar" (KSA 6, 493). The epistemological reservation
Nietzsche introduces here is plain. Our knowledge accounts of the real or
natural world incorrigibly leave out or have to omit "what is individual" by
subsuming it under a "concept," and with this subsumption what we call
"knowledge begins: in categorizing, in the establishment of classes" (ibid.). 36
Thus Nietzsche argues that knowledge of individual or real things, i.e., the
modern knowledge of natural science, must be "essentially illogical" if it is to
aspire to any kind of approximative, tentative correspondence with the real
world, as a practical or real science of nature.
Where Nietzsche differs from traditional theories of truth, both logical and
scientific, is in his assessment of the relevant referent. The object of modern
science is nature for Nietzsche, not logic. Thus, the patron saint of modern
science is not to be Aristotle or even Descartes but Bacon, Newton, Boyle, or
indeed, any other alchemist or practical theorist. 37 This utilitarian focus is what
Nietzsche means when he writes that "science in its entirety is directed toward
becoming, not toward being" (KSA 7, 633fTL 97). But beyond the forceful
arguments of efficiency, which are sufficient for pragmatic or merely utilitiarian
purposes, the key philosophical problem for Nietzsche is the persistent problem
of truth, logical rationality, and the measure of the world.
Thus Nietzsche continually adverts to the difference between ideal types -
like elemental carbon- and real material instances. Not only does he refuse the
association (e.g., he points to the irreducible [non-chemical] difference between
diamond, coal, and graphite- [KSA 13, 374]) but he challenges the operative
application of simple mathematics (or arithmetic) to describe biological or
indeed ecological processes. Thus he frequently points out that in the real world
of real things, two halves routinely fail to add up to or equal a whole: as true for
an apple pie as it was in Solomon's judgment and as it would apply- taking
another of Nietzsche's favourite metaphors- to the lowest worm (cf. KSA 13,
98). To make this biological point, in the case of a particularly simple worm, the
halves might yield two wholes. In more advanced worms, the two halves add up
to nothing at all but can represent a subtraction, so that (providing that both
TRUTH, ART, AND LIFE 11
halves do not die, as is always likely) the one that survives is a much smaller
whole: not two but just one worm. And Nietzsche is fond of the example of
protoplasm and its dynamic of growth and division, pointing to the example of
cell-divisions to make the same point in another direction as well as to invoke
his general economy of abundance in expression. 38
Because the pure ideal of truth is inimical to the changing, impure reality of
the empirical (and that also means the scientific) world, "truth, considered as
unconditional duty, stands in a hostile and destructive relationship with the
world" (KSA 7, 623). The culture of science needs the philosopher as "physi-
cian." What Nietzsche names "the tragic conflict" is the insight that human
society and culture cannot exist without art, i.e., without the untruth of art.
Nietzsche celebrates "Art and nothing but Art!" (TI, Expeditions 24; cf. KSA
13, 194, 521), because art is "the great life-stimulus" but also because in the
creation (and reception) of art we "betray" our character as part of the world
(KSA 12, 33; cf. 385), which same world Nietzsche describes as a "self-
engendering work of art" (KSA 13, 114; 337). The value of art that elevates it
above truth is the life-saving value of illusion. Truth, by contrast, "kills - it even
kills itself (insofar as it realizes that error is its foundation ... )" (ibid.).
The ideal of art is the ideal of reality, but this is a tragic ideal. What
Nietzsche calls the tragic affirms "transitoriness and destruction." 39 Thus
Nietzsche speaks of art as a truth to life, life understood as the reality opposed
to and opposed by the ideal world of metaphysics as of logic, of religion and of
science: where "the lie of the ideal has hitherto been the curse on reality ... " 40
But for Nietzsche, the world of thought mirrors not an ideal truth but only a
simplified version of the apparent world ("reality" or "life").41 Logic itself, like
mathematics, is an artifice, an invention and not a truth. The becoming,
phenomenal world for Nietzsche (via Wittgenstein) is everything that is the
case. Or, as Nietzsche says more explicitly, there is no essence: "Das 'Wesen'
fehlt: Das 'Werdende,' 'Phanomenale" ist die einzige Art Sein" (KSA 12,
249). 42 Science must be included in the categorical claim that "all of life is
based on semblance, art, deception, points of view, and the necessity of
perspectives and error" (BT Preface 5; cf. KSA 12, 129).
Throughout his work, starting with the indulgent fable of vita brevis and
vanitas with which he began his unpublished reflections on truth and lie,
Nietzsche refers to this same tragic ideal. Later Nietzsche expresses human life
as a "hiatus between two nothings," (KSA 12, 473), and still later develops this
challenge to scientific optimism in the same words, describing life as "an
accident, an exception, a hiatus between two nothings, an event without plan,
reason, will, self-awareness, the worst kind of necessity, stupid necessity" (KSA
13, 488-489). 43 Vanity regards the vulnerability and erroneousness of our human
situtation as illusory, optimistically believing in spite of everything in the ideal
promise of a true world, if not in paradise in a life beyond life, then still to be
attained with future scientific achievements in this life.
As Nietzsche recounts the history of the illusion of knowledge, Socratic
optimism, or the Platonic/Socratic faith of theoretical science, is "the unshak-
able faith that thought, using the thread of logic, can penetrate the deepest
12 BABETTE E. BABICH
abysses of being, and that thought is capable not only of knowing being but
even of correcting it" (BT 15). This optimistic ideal endures in modern
technology and science as the durable ideal of progress. 44 Yet Nietzsche's point
is not the pessimistic correction of such a progress ideal (the simplistic meaning
of nihilism) because this, for Nietzsche, amounts to the same thing under the
sign (or the cover) of negation. The critical self-immolation of knowledge ("the
truth that he is eternally condemned to untruth" [KSA 1, 760]), must be joined
to the sober notion that insight into illusion does not abrogate it. Thus although
Nietzsche writes that from "every point of view, the erroneousness of the world
in which we live is the surest and the firmest thing we can get our eyes on ... "
(BGE 34 ), the problem must be to get beyond the notion of truth and lie, to
overcome the thought of "error as the evil par excellence" (BT 15).
Rather than remaining in the dyadic conflict between antitheses, as the binary
thinking endemic to all logical and scientific pursuits (BGE 2), Nietzsche asks
if it were not (or could not be) "enough to suppose shades of apparentness -
different valeurs, to speak in the language of painters?" (BGE 34). Against the
metaphysical faith that generates logic out of illogic, the true from the untrue,
Nietzsche proposes the notion of such artistic "refinements," exactly not as a
pragmatic making-do or "as good as" true but for the sake of the question "Why
truth? Why not error?" Asking this question, we might come to love error, not
only for its fruit in truth and knowledge but as pure illusion, as such. Art is of
greater value than truth. To parse the philosophical importance of this estima-
tion is for Nietzsche already a matter of the degree of artful illusion: There is no
truth. "All men," Nietzsche writes, "are artists." Thus error is not to be mined
for truth and what began in approximations and error is not asked to pull itself
out of the swamp of its own illusions into the heaven of truth. Nietzsche's
perspectivalism (again: more than a sheer "perspectivism" and nothing like a
relativism) articulates a more direct (less transformative or magical kind of)
evolution of thought on truth and on lie, about reality (and so too about
ourselves) than the standard historical convention of a revolutionary transit from
mythos to logos in the development of rational thought. Art trumps truth because
truth itself is illusion or art- and being seduced by illusion, taking it as really
true (being duped) is not an appropriate response either to the work of art on the
stage (in the theatre, museum gallery, public square, etc., ) or to our experience
of the world and of life.
As science is a kind of art, and truth a kind of illusion, life is a kind of death.
Nietzsche rejects the "connection between the inorganic and the organic" (KSA
11, 560) contra the singularity of the organic and supposes - in accord with
modern molecular genetics -that the organic is merely a particular kind of the
inorganic. 45 But as the living is "merely a type of what is dead" (GS 109),
Nietzsche speaks of "shades of apparentness" or seeming, beyond opposites or
antitheses: "there are no opposites" (HH 1: 1). Truth is in continuity with the lie:
truth is a type, species, "kind of error" (KSA 11, 506). Like the valeurs of the
painter (Nietzsche's specific reference is to Delacroix but one can also think of
Vermeer, Raphael or Rembrandt, even Seurat or Van Gogh, etc.), perceived
oppositions "do not exist in themselves." Like a calculated "alchemy" - in
TRUTH, ART, AND LIFE 13
I began by making the case that epistemology and the philosophy of science
might be seen as one of Nietzsche's most enduring philosophic concerns. I also
noted that the reception of this epistemological perspective was rather more
common among Nietzsche's analytic interpreters and that most continental
interpretations, at least in Anglophone expressions, have tended to be more
interested in Nietzsche's moral or social/political or cultural critiques than his
critique of truth.
In the present context, it might seem that I would do best to offer at least an
expression of thanks for those who have been gracious enough to read Nietzsche
as a philosopher and for the brave new rhetorical project of building a bridge
between the analytic and the continental traditions. Yet I have maintained that
such a "bridge" cannot be built because the span is incorrigibly ideological and
the intellectual regions that would be linked thereby are not equally stable
continents.
Yet, although the crossing-over remains to be begun, the epistemological
dimension of Nietzsche's thought, indeed: the very idea of Nietzsche's critique
of truth already joins the traditions of analytic and continental philosophy.
Without bridging two regions of philosophy, the philosopher is called upon to
be, as Nietzsche would say, a tightrope dancer. This call applies to philosophers
of every philosophical stripe, analytic as much as continental. But here too there
is a caveat. The idea of dancing is a great metaphor for the continental or
postmodem philosopher, very like the idea of play- and (recalling Nietzsche's
first postmodern antipode): much like leaping. This is appealing language. It is
as if one's concepts could take flight. Yet the metaphor should bring us back to
earth, as it were. Falling is the only thing Nietzsche's human tightrope dancers
ever did do in the end (at the start of Nietzsche's Zarathustra) and falling is the
one thing they always do in practice -- sometimes even in circus performances
to the delight of the crowd. But maybe this is the point to be made. We are told
that as walking itself is a controlled or orchestrated falling, running, dancing,
and leaping represent differently controlled styles of falling. We do not and
cannot have the foundations for the bridge. Hence the running vault as
Nietzsche recommends it as a means of ascending the heights requires above all
that we anticipate that every step we take will dislodge our footing. The light-
footed solution will be the one that takes its security not from the unshakability
of its initial point of departure but exactly from the dynamic momentum of
decadence. This is ceteris paribus, what Neurath proposed when he noted that
the only place to rework the ship of science was plank by plank, not in the dry
14 BABETTE E. BABICH
dock of secured doubt but on the open sea of experience, in the very Eleatic flux
of things that remains the open sea of science, as of art, and that is, fellow
voyagers - as we all of us are - the sea of life.
SECTION SUMMARIES
cardinal principles. Thus the same essential structure of his biologicism must be
seen to frame his broader epistemological, ethical, and metaphysical concerns.
Eric Steinhart's essay, "The Will to Power and Parallel Distributed Process-
ing," develops an entirely different scientific schema, drawn from the analytic
model of contemporary cognitive theory, or computer science, or information
systems analysis. Steinhart claims that Nietzsche's will to power may be seen
as having non-trivial physical models in the class of parallel distributed
processing systems, specifically wave-mechanical discrete dynamic systems
with cyclical entropy. Steinhart thus attempts to link the will to power to
research in non-linear self-organizing dynamical systems, including oscillons,
cellular automata, spin-glass, Ising systems, and connectionist networks.
Peter Douglas takes as point of departure for his essay, "The Fractal
Dynarrucs of a Nietzschean World," the prerillse that mathematical concepts and
relations can be appropriated for the purpose of creating new modes of
interpretation of existing texts and phenomena. Douglas brings together certain
aspects of fractal geometry and chaos theory to provide a speculative interpre-
tive frame for Nietzsche's philosophical work. Given Nietzsche's own critique
of the efforts of the mathematical project to equalize and identify, together with
science's simplification of the tremendous complexity of the world and its
democratic design to preserve life for the sake of its average and reactive
aspects, Douglas suspends any equation of Nietzsche's philosophy with the
mathematical project but rather, inversely, appropriates the mathematic concepts
and relations of his essay for the purpose of a new interpretive approach.
In the ultimate essay, "Nietzsche's Critique of Technology: A Defense of
Phenomenology Against Modem Machinery," Ullrich M. Haase attempts to
resolve the conflict between Nietzsche's thought and Heidegger's interpretation.
Haase proposes a philological prolegomenon to an interpretation of Heidegger' s
move to press Nietzsche into the position of an acolyte of the technologisation
of science, and a philosophical prolegomenon towards challenging a certain
strand of postmodem thought which sets out to "celebrate" plurality thereby
becoming the more entrapped in the net of reason. Where, philologically,
Nietzsche's work in Nietzsche's words "is one and wants, one thing," Haase's
essay offers a philosophical argument (in accord with Heidegger's philosophy)
contra Heidegger's reading of Nietzsche.
NOTES
See my Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science: Reflecting Science on the Ground of Art and Life
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994); Maudemarie Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and
Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990) and more subtly and much more
broadly. Barry Allen, Truth in Philosophy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1993 ). See also
D.A. Freeman, "Nietzsche: Will to Power as a Foundation of a Theory of Knowledge,"
International Studies in Philosophy, 20 (1988) 3-14; Ken Gemes, "Nietzsche's Critique of Truth,"
Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, no. I (March 1992): 47-65; Steven Schwartz,
'The Status of Nietzsche's Theory of the Will to Power in the Light of Contemporary Philosophy
of Science," International Studies in Philosophy, XXV/2 (1993); R. Lanier Anderson. "Nietzsche's
TRUTH, ART, AND LIFE 21
Will to Power as a Doctrine of the Unity of Science," Studies in History and Philosophy of
Science, 2515 (1995) 729-750; Steven Hales and Rex Welshon, 'Truth, Paradox, and Nietzsche's
Perspectivism." History of Philosophy Quarterly I 1:1 (1995) I 01-119. etc., and not including non-
analytic or historico-interpretive or continental treatments. See also E.E. Sleinis and Kurt Rudolf
Fischer, in B. Babich, ed., in cooperation with R.S. Cohen, Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge and
Critical Theory: Nietzsche and the Sciences 1 (Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1999 [Hereafter: NSI]). For
more detailed discussion and extensive references, see Walther Ch. Zimmerli, Rex Welshon, and
Anderson's essay below, as well as Anderson's "Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism," in
Synthese 15 (1998) 1-32.
2 This exposition of the critical dynamic of questioning is the keystone of Kant's entire
philosophy of science. The aesthetic design of the scientific question effects its judgment power
(Bxiii). Rather than a science based solely on observation (and inductive regress) which would be
no science at all in the image of logic and mathematics, Kant resolves the Humean problem of
induction in the Preface to the second edition of the Critique of Pure Reason. in the empirical
practice of questioning because the question (or experiment) both concedes and exploits the
epistemological limitations of reason (KdrV Bix) and experience (cf. A124-126 ). Just as
mathematics owes its scientific integrity to the axiomatic character of its conceptual groundwork,
so physics operates with axioms or defining assumptions on both theoretical and objective levels,
that is both in its fundamental concepts and in its experimental processes (B241/ A 196;
A713/B741-A727 /755). Two different readings of Kant's philosophy of science are useful here
if they both remain- for different reasons- oblique to the traditional or "received" account of the
philosophy of science as such: the first providing an architectonic or schematic of the Kantian
schema, Gerd Buchdahl, Kant and the Dynamic of Reason (London: Blackwell, 1992) and the
second insightfully bridging Kant's first and third critiques in Heidegger's interpretation of Kant:
Pierre Kerszberg, Critique and Totality (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997). A
recent, excellent historical (and still exactly analytic) account is Michael Friedman, Kant and the
Exact Sciences (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1992).
3 "Continental philosophy" is so named in contrast to the Anglo-American or analytic
philosophical traditions - although neither stylistic approach to philosophy is geographically
specific, and indeed analytic philosophy is far and away the more universal. See David West, An
Introduction to Continental Philosophy (Polity: Cambridge, 1995). See also my essay "Continental
Philosophy" in Ouyang Kang and Steve Fuller, eds., Contemporar)' British and American
Philosophy and Philosophers. Forthcoming. [Scheduled to be published first in Chinese translation
trans. Dezhi Duan (The People's Press, Beijing, 1999); subsequently in English.]
4 I refer to Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, as well as the wide and growing range of
contributions on the topical conjunction of Nietzsche, truth, and epistemology by analytically
formed scholars beyond the present essay's argument for an historically interpretive approach to
Nietzsche's philosophy of science.
5 See Clark, et al.
6 In the present volume, translations include: Bela Bacs6, "The Will to Truth as Art of
Interpretation"; Carl Friedrich von Weizsacker, "Nietzsche's Philosophy: Science, Art, Power";
Paul Valadier, "Science as New Religion"; Walther Ch. Zimmerli, "Nietzsche's Philosophy as
Critique of Truth and Science." In the first volume, Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, and
Critical Theory: Nietzsche and the Sciences I, translations include Tilman Borsche, "The
Epistemological Shift from Descartes to Nietzsche: Intuition and Imagination"; Jiirgen Habermas,
"Postscript from 1968: On Nietzsche's Theory of Knowledge"; Josef Kopperschmidt, "Nietzsche's
Rhetorical Philosophy as Critique of Impure Reason"; Angele Kremer-Marietti, "Nietzsche: The
Critique of Modern Reason"; Wolfgang Miiller-Lauter, "On Judgment in a World of Becoming";
Manfred Riedel, "Scientific Theory or Practical Doctrine"; Holger Schmid, "The Nietzschean
Meta-Critique of Knowledge"; Josef Simon, "Nietzsche's Critique of Truth and Grammar"; Klaus
Spiekermann, "Nietzsche and Critical Theory"; Bernhard H. F. Taureck, "Habermas's Critique of
Nietzsche's Critique of Reason." Some of these works were originally published in German or
French or Hungarian versions elsewhere but the majority were initially written specifically for this
two volume thematic collection.
7 This is how it happens that practitioners of so-called continental philosophy, which is at times
named "contemporary European" philosophy, are as professionally marginalised in Europe as in
English speaking countries. This marginalisation has many causes although perhaps the most
obvious derives from the rather universal scientism of our scientific, techno-information era which
remains evident in the still-unquestioned prestige of logical and linguistic analytic approaches to
philosophy. For a discussion of the political contours and stakes of this opposition, see my essay
on Alan Sokal's politically motivated exposee of all "theory" not properly scientifically
22 BABETTE E. BABICH
credentialed: "The Hermeneutics of a Hoax: On the Mismatch of Physics and Cultural Criticism."
Common Knowledge. 612 (September 1997) 23-33.
8 See Arthur Dantu's "Preface to the Morningside Edition," Nietzsche as Philosopher (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1980). This bluntly unreconstructed view continues to operate
as the analytic assumption shared by Schacht and Clark and many other scholars and which same
~resumption constitutes the privilege of the mainstream.
Indeed, Daniel Breazeale emphasizes this contrast even with regard to what would appear to
be a common focus on language: "the outstanding epistemological feature of Nietzsche's account
of language- a feature notably absent from most contemporary discussions of the subject- is his
constant critical interest"in Breazeale, ed. and trans., Philosophy and Truth. Selections from
Nietzsche's Notebooks of the Early 1870's (1872-3). ed. and trans., Daniel Breazeale (New Jersey:
Humanities Press, 1979), p. xxxi.
10 A call for bridge building between the two traditions of philosophy is inevitably a call
adumbrated on the terms of analytic not continental philosophy. especially where one wishes (as
f!Verred by analysts such as Stanley Cavell or Mark Sacks) to speak of only one kind of philosophy
(i.e., good, or only incidentally analytic, and bad, but only coincidentally not). The idea is that any
such stylistic difference must be irrelevant: secondary to issues of quality. Thus the author has
heard this claim from influential philosophers as different as Robert Bernasconi and Cavell (and
while both are analytically trained scholars, the one is at Harvard, blithely unaware of the real
world of scholarly struggle for acknowledged value and the other is somewhat more distant from
Cambridge on either side of the Atlantic). And to hear both scholars, as well as journals editors,
the only criterion for publication (and for other invitations) is quality. This is not nai've, expecially
in the case of important members of the philosophical profession: but at best thoughtless and, at
its worst, mean-spirited or malicious.
11 Nietzsche's first reflections "On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense'' point to the
complexities glossed over by words and concepts, and in Twilight of the Idols, challenges the
truisim, "All truths are simple-'' identifying it as a "compound lie" (TI, Maxims and Arrows, 4/
KSA VI, 59). This complexity too is the point of his claim that the world is will to power (rather
than a world of "simples,'' be they elemental or atomic substances). Thus Nietzsche criticizes the
animating parsimony of the scientific knowledge ideal in terms of what he does not hesitate to
name stupidity, reflecting that the challenge would appear to be to design or account for a
mechanism of the greatest complexity and subtlety using the stupidest, most elementary - or
elemental - elements. "Das Ideal ist, das complicirteste aile Machinenwesen zu construiren,
entstanden durch die diimmste aller miiglichen Methoden" (KSA I], 93. Cf. KSA 12. 36/WP 533;
KSA 12, 395/WP 569). For Nietzsche, again and again: "Die Welt erscheint uns logisch, wei! wir
sie erst logisirt haben" (KSA 12, 418).
12 As an illustration of the appropriative conventions characterizing analytic style thinking. this
tyronistic but sophisticated and typical author, comparing Nietzsche's departure from the epistemic
tradition to Wittgenstein's own epistemic rupture, informs the reader that epistemic questions were
"insignificant" for Nietzsche - and exactly "unlike" their same relevance for Wittgenstein. See
Brian Leiter, "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals" in R. Schacht. ed., Niet~sche,
Genealogy, Morality: Essays on Nietzsche's On the Genealogy of Morals (Berkeley University
of California Press, 1994 ), pp. 334-357. Such a prima facie absurd (and inaccurate) claim is a bit
more pathetic than astonishing (given the utter lack of justification attempted in the essay itself)
but it is the kind of claim that reflects not only the prerogative but also the grounding premise of
professional philosophy. And thus it is far more than a simple error limited to one author. For
Leiter, Nietzsche's break with the philosophic epistemic tradition, boils down (which is of course
the reason the operation is an analytic one) to a view that is "much less radical than is usually
supposed," p. 351.
13 See my essay, "Heidegger's Relation to Nietzsche: Connivance, Concinnity. and Value." New
notes in which Nietzsche poses most sharply the problem of the value of truth (which Schlechta
and Anders take to be the theme of these notes ... )" Breazeale, p. liv.
15 Sometimes this has unintentionally funny consequences, as in the variety of Prisoner's
Dilemmas, none of which have any bit of real-life plausibility (or can be reasoned) (or make sense)
apart from a course in probability or logic. Contrast this with Sartre' s much more coherent and less
forced discussion of the same quandary of Kantian consequentiality in his short story essay, "The
Wall."
16 See Paul Valadier's books, Nietzsche et Ia critique du christianisme (Paris: Cerf, 1974) and
Nietzsche, /'athee de rigueur (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 1975) as well as his "Science as New
Religion" below. For a different tack, see also the essays by Allen's "Forbidding Knowledge" in
The Monist, and Carl Friedrich von Weizsacker's chapter on Nietzsche in Wahrnehmung der
Neuzeit (Hanser: Munich, 1983), pp. 70-106, translation below. See too, Manfred Riedel,
"Scientific Theory or Practical Doctrine" and Holger Schmid, "The Nietzschean Critique of Meta-
Knowledge" in NSf. Further, see Jean-Luc Marion, L'idole et la distance (Paris: Grasset, 1977)
and Dieter Henke, Gott und Grammatik (Pfiillingen: Neske, 1981 ). And in the direction of theo-
cultural philology: Eric Blonde!, Nietzsche: The Body and Culture, trans. Sean Hand (Stanford,
Stanford University Press, 1991). I articulate this genealogical account of the ascetic ideal in
religion and science, in my chapter on "Nietzsche's Genealogy of Science: Morality and the Value
of Modernity" in Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, pp. 175-225, as well as in my review of the
ultimate coincidence of postmodern (and associated putatively alternative) and New Age
perspectives and the scientific ideal in "The Hermeneutics of a Hoax," cited above.
7 See Valadier's work in particular, as well as Riedel (both cited above), and, further, Jean
Griesch, and so on. A reflection on the complexities of the metaphor of the tree of knowledge and
its relation to the knowledge of good and evil, of perdition and salvation, is not one that any
scholar can lay rights to (including Nietzsche) if only because the metaphor is basic to the Judeao-
Christian legacy.
18 After a hermeneutic infusion, the interpretation-intoxicated analyst is prepared to deal with a
mobile army of metaphors, declaring it nothing but sound and fury: so much epistemological
d.fnamite, so little danger. See Leiter.
1 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Random
House, 1969). Samtliche Werke. Kritische Studienausgabe (Mtinchen/Berlin, New York: DTV/De
Gruyter, 1980), volume I. Cited as BT, followed by section number in the text. Citations from the
KSA are limited to volume and page number alone.
20 In this direction, to note a Nietzschean reserve against Levinas's foundational ethics, to invert
the ordering principle preserves the same distinction all over again.
21 Nietzsche, KSA 7, 459. Translations are my own, following wherever possible the exemplary
precedent of Breazeale's translation in his edition of Nietzsche's Philosophy and Truth: cf.
Breazeale, p. 33. Regrettably, and only because it does not render the now-standard sequence of
the Colli-Montinari edition, Breazeale's translation is of limited utility to the specialist scholar.
22 See my essay: "Nietzsche and the Erotic Valence of Art: The Problem of the Artist as Actor-
Jew-Woman" in the Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Issue 15: 15-33. Spring 1998.
23 Cf. Nietzsche's reserve re demonstration (similar to his reserve concerning the possibility of
communication in general): "Denn das Beweisbare appellirt an das Gemeinsamste in den Kopfen:
weshalb es nattirlich nicht mehr ist als ein Nutzlichkeits-MaBstab im Interesse der Meisten." KSA
12, 191.
24 Nietzsche contends that if mechanics is reduced to a logic ("Wenn die Mechanik nur eine Logik
ist... ") the schema of every "logic" as a kind of "vertebrate backbrace" ("eine Art Riickgrat fiir
Wirbelthiere, nichts an-sich-Wahres" IKSA ll, 359] must be read back into mechanism just as this
schema binds every logic. See further: Mtiller-Lauter's essay, "On Judgment in a World of
Becoming" in NSf.
25 For Nietzsche, both physiology and ecology are at work in this. Thus he contends "Our most
sacred convictions, our immutabilities with regard to the highest values, are the judgments of our
muscles." KSA 12, 169.
26 Nietzsche writes "Das Leben ist auf die Voraussetzung eines Glaubens an dauerndes und
regular Wiederkehrendes gegrtindet; je mach tiger das Leben, urn so breiter muB die errathbare,
gleichsam seiend gemachte Welt sein. Logisirung, Rationalisirung, Systematisirung als Htilfsmittel
des Lebens." KSA 12, 385/WP 552.
27 KSA 12, 352. "Wir haben unsre Erhaltungs-Bedingungen projicirt als Pradikate des Seins
tiberhaupt I daB wir in unserem Glauben stabil sein mtissen, urn zu gedeihen, daraus haben wir
gemacht, daB die 'wahre' Welt keine wandelbare und werdende, sondern eine seiende ist." KSA
12, 353.
24 BABETTE E. BABICH
28 Cf. KSA 13. 334. I discuss this perspective in "On the Eco-Physiological Ground of
!<now ledge: Nietzsche's Epistemology," Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, pp. 77-134.
~ 9 "Erkenntnij3 und Werden schlieBt sich aus." KSA 12, 382.
·' 0 See Taureck's essay in NSf as well as the wider German literature on this theme.
11 For different approaches, first on the question of atomism, see, in NSf, Caygill and Stephen
Gaukroger and see Robin Small below; on the question of Boscovich, see also Greg Whitlock's
and Zimmerli's contributions. See also Poellner. The Timaeus is also a source of Nietzsche's
definition of the world as a closed organic system- feeding on its own excrement. For a contrary
claim, see Duncan Large's discussion of Michel Serres' interpretation of Nietzsche below.
12 See Allen's essay below. On the question of the relation of science to religion, see too Valadier
and von Wcizsacker. And in NSf. sec Kremer-Marietti, Schmid, and Riedel.
·' 1 Cf. BGE 2; GS Ill. A number of essays in NSf address this issue, see in particular Josef
Simon, "Nietzche's Critique of Truth and Grammar," Schmid, etc.
14 Danto makes this same point in the 1980 Introduction to his Nietzsche as Philosopher. See
Routledge. 1993) and Peter Dear, Disicipline and Experience (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press: 1996). See also Allen below.
18 KSA 12. 38/WP 659. Cf. KSA 12, 38/WP 654; KSA 12, 420; 424. See too KSA 11, 536-7 .
.w "To realize in oneself the archaic tragic ideal is the eternal joy of becoming- the joy which
also encompasses joy in destruction." Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, trans. R.J. Hollingdale (Harmond-
sworth, Penguin, 1979), GT: 3, p. 8l/KSA 6, 312.
40 Ecce Homo, Foreword, 2, p. 34/KSA 6, 258. This conception of life or reality as fearful
necessity or chance, is taken in the pre-Socratic sense of the term, as it may be heard from
Anaximander to Plato's Pythagorean Timaeus.
41 Cf. KSA 12. 19, and 26, 38, 39.
42 This is also the same tragic ref1ection to be found in Nietzsche's remarks that "Man geht zu
Grunde, wenn man immer zu den Grunden geht." KSA 13, 10: cf. 562.
41 This is an experimental passage, intercalated between reflecting whether, if existence is said
to have a bad character. truth would be "yet another illusion?" and recalling the "Once upon a
time" story with which Nietzsche tells us that humanity once lived (and died) upon a small star
on which "clever beasts invented knowing" (KSA I, 882/TL 79), but here speaking of humanity
as "eine kleinc ilberspannte Thierart, die- glilcklicher Weise- ihre Zeit hat." Thus life on this
Earth is "Ein Augenblick, cin Zwischenfall, cine Ausnahme, ein Hiatus zwischen zwei Nichtsen,
ein EreigniB ohne Plan, Vernunft, Wille, SelbstbewuBtsein, die schlimmste Art des Nothwendigen,
die dumme Nothwendigkeit..." KSA 13,488-499.
44 Cf. Gaukroger in NSf, and below: Ullrich Haase, "Nietzsche's Critique of Technology: A
and outside for living or organic beings: interpreting and being interpreted by the or-
ganic/inorganic world, active beings created by and creating the supposedly objective world
around them. See my Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science. See also R. Lewontin's account of this
biologically esoteric circumstance in his Biology as Ideology. See below, Alfred F. Tauber's and
Scott Podolsky's "Nietzsche's Conception of Health: The Idealization of Struggle" as well as
Andrea Rehberg, "Nietzsche's Transvaluation of Causality," and, again, Small.
46 As featured in the analytic textbook series, The Arguments of the Philosophers, Schacht's 1983
book on Nietzsche represents the most influential era of North-American Nietzsche reception,
where English translations by Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale made the scope of
Nietzsche's published work, including those parts of the Nachlaj3 notes translated in The Will to
Pmver. widely accessible to predominantly Anglophone scholars. Schacht derives the inaugural
essay for the present collection from his second chapter on "Truth and Knowledge."
47 Cf. Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, eds., Why We Are Not Nietzscheans, trans. Robert de Loaiza
Two things must be recognized at the outset. First: when Nietzsche speaks of
"truth" and "knowledge," these terms do not have a single sense and reference
in all of their occurrences. In interpreting any particular remark he makes along
these lines, one must take care to consider precisely what sort of a remark it is,
and how broadly and on what level of analysis it is to be taken to apply. (I shall
elaborate upon this point shortly.) And second, Nietzsche's views on these
matters cannot be properly understood unless one grasps the nature of his rather
unconventional general approach to them. Like many others before and after
him, he finds it advisable to examine commonplace examples and paradigm
cases of truth and knowledge, with a view to seeing what they involve. But he
is not content simply to try to understand them and the types they exemplify on
their own terms. Rather, he considers it instructive and important to view them
in the light of other considerations pertaining to the character and circumstances
of the kind of creature we are, in the setting of whose life all such forms of truth
and knowledge are framed and attained.
Nietzsche considers it incontrovertible that in dealing with epistemological
issues one is dealing with certain sorts of human affairs, and that therefore one's
conclusions concerning them will be either superficial or erroneous if they are
not interpreted accordingly. More specifically, he observes that philosophers
have tended to understand ourselves and the elements of our conscious life as
a kind of being and set of activities to be understood in terms altogether
25
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 25-38.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
26 RICHARD SCHACHT
different from those appropriate to entities and processes occmTing in the world
of nature. And he regards this as a mistake, even though he does not think that
there are no significant differences between ourselves and other things. He
writes: "To translate man back into nature ... - that may be a strange and insane
task. but it is a task- who would deny that? Why did we choose this insane
task? Or, putting the matter differently: 'Why have knowledge at all?'" 2
To this it must immediately be added (lest one mistakenly conclude that he
thereby opts for a merely "biologistic" approach in these matters) that Nietzsche
considers it no less important also to "translate" ourselves - as thinkers and
knowers, as well as in other respects - back into society. For in this context, he
holds, the human intellect is further shaped in important ways, and the means
of all humanly possible thought and cognition are acquired. This further
"translation back" likewise does not constitute his final move and last word
where all truth and knowledge are concerned, however, as shall be seen.
At every step one has to wrestle for truth; one has had to surrender for it almost everything to
which the heart, to which our love, our trust in life, cling otherwise. That requires greatness of
soul; the service of truth is the hardest service. (A 50)
the first-order truth of most classes of propositions amounts to. On this level of
analysis one's task is to discern and set forth the principles implicit in the
making of various sorts of truth-determinations by those involved in forms of
life in which such determinations are established practices, rather as one might
try to discover and lay out the rules of a game as these are accepted and
followed by those who play it.
embellished, and which, after long usage seem to a people to be fixed, canonical, and binding. (TL
p.84)
Nietzsche not only repudiates the very idea of "absolute knowledge" and of
"truth" as an exact correspondence of thought and reality, but also maintains
that "truth" is inescapably perspectival, and "knowledge" essentially interpre-
tive. One should not be too quick, however, to draw radical conclusions from
such assertions. He undeniably also was possessed of a lively intellectual
conscience, confirmed in his view of himself as a "seeker" and "lover of
knowledge," persistent in his attempts to arrive at a deeper and clearer compre-
hension of our human reality and the character of life and the world than others
had attained, and committed to the pursuit of something he does not hesitate to
call "truth," the status of which he takes to be quite different from that of
"man's truths."
How are the truth and knowledge to which Nietzsche aspires- beyond those
more commonplace and misguided or limited varieties he analyzes - to be
conceived? Very generally put, "truth" here is to be understood as a matter of
the aptness of a characterization in relation to that which it characterizes; and
"knowledge" is conceived in terms of the interpreting of something in a manner
that does justice to it. Characterizations, like the metaphors employed in giving
them, may be more or less (or not at all) apt. The justice done by interpretations
to that which is interpreted may likewise vary greatly. On the other hand, there
is no question of an exact correspondence in the case of the former, or of
certainty and finality in the case of the latter. Some characterizations may be
seen to be inappropriate, and some interpretations found misguided, while others
may be accorded superiority in relation to various alternatives; but in both cases
the possibility can never be ruled out of further alternatives which might be
superior in aptness and justice to them. While such superiority may be genuine,
moreover, there is and can be no general set of rules for achieving it, or of
criteria for assessing it. The idea of a rigorous decision-procedure has no place
here, any more than it has in those disciplines dealing with human history,
culture, art and literature, as well as the enterprise of psychology as Nietzsche
understands it. Indeed, he regards the cases of these forms of inquiry as highly
instructive in this matter, and is in effect extrapolating from them.
In conceiving of "truth" and "knowledge" along these lines, Nietzsche
remains committed to the idea that they have a "perspectival" character even
here. He does not take this to be fatal to their epistemic significance; but he does
consider it to affect their status. The language in which any state of affairs is
characterized, he stresses, however apt the characterization may be, is never
immaculately conceived. It always bears the stamp of human invention, whether
it is of our own devising as conceptual innovators or originates in that more
ancient and impersonal legislation through which words have acquired their
conventional meanings. Indeed, what makes a characterization apt is not simply
the relation of the proposition in question to the state of affairs to which it
NIETZSCHE: TRUTH AND KNOWLEDGE 35
pertains, but also its relation to a specific sort of linguistic sensibility. The latter,
in fact, is a condition of the very possibility of its aptness. The aptness of a
metaphor in ordinary discourse obviously depends in no small measure upon its
resonance for a group of users of a language, in abstraction from which its
meaning is altered and impoverished. Its ability to articulate and convey
something about that which is spoken of is a function of the exploitability of
associations they are capable of appreciating; and this presupposes the existence
or establishment of a discursive context or perspective.
Knowing likewise for Nietzsche is always and inescapably a perspectival
knowing, because it involves a process of interpreting on the part of creatures
whose relations to that which they interpret affect their interpretations - which
relations are conditioned by their constitutions, histories and circumstances. We
are not (and cannot transform ourselves into) pure spectators of all time and
existence, whose apprehension would be independent of and uninfluenced by
anything other than the nature of that which is contemplated. Indeed, even if we
could, there would be much about our existence as human beings and the world
of which our lives are a part which would escape our grasp, since the human
relations which are largely or partially constitutive of their reality would become
opaque to us. Nietzsche considers it an error to suppose that even if it were
possible, a non-perspectival contemplation of things would yield a fuller and
deeper comprehension of them than may be attained through perspectival
interpretations of them. For he contends that the former would fail to capture
anything of them, lacking any relation to them; whereas the latter afford at least
the possibility of enabling something of them to be discerned. Their reality, on
his view, is a relational affair; and their comprehension is possible, and indeed
may meaningfully be spoken of, only by means and in terms of the adoption of
standpoints attuned to the sorts of relations constitutive of them.
Nietzsche makes much of the point that interpretation generally not only is
at once reflective and determinative of the perspectives within and in terms of
which we operate as we confront the world, but further is fundamentally bound
up with our "affects" (and so, ultimately, with the "physiological conditions" in
which they are held to be rooted). Rather than taking this to rule out the
possibility of the achievement of any sort of comprehension that might merit the
name of "knowledge," however, Nietzsche draws the opposite conclusion. The
very multiplicity and mutability of these "drives" that is characteristic of our
human constitution, on his view, lends itself to this purpose. Thus while
suggesting that it may in a sense be considered to reflect a "diseased condition
in man," he goes on to observe: "This contradictory creature has in its nature,
however, a great method of acquiring knowledge: he feels many pros and cons,
he raises himself to justice" (WP 259).
Nietzsche thus considers it at least to be possible for us to "raise ourselves to
justice" in our thinking, or at any rate to something approaching "justice,"
through the development of more sophisticated interpretations, by drawing upon
and yet transcending the narrower and more distorting perspectives attained
under the influence of the various interpretation-engendering "drives" at work
within us. The latter may themselves be indifferent to such "justice," and indeed
36 RICHARD SCHACHT
may perpetrate "injustices" to the extent that they individually dominate our
thinking. Collectively, however, they constitute the means of compensating for
their particular "injustices" sufficiently to bring the attainment of "justice" and
the acquisition of "knowledge" so understood within the realm of possibility.
These considerations enable one to make good and important sense of the
well-known passage in the Genealogy in which Nietzsche writes: "There is only
a perspective seeing, only a perspective 'knowing."· What he takes to follow,
however, is not only the untenability of the idea of a "pure knowing subject"
and of "knowledge in itself," but also something more positive: "the more
affects we allow to speak about one thing, the more complete will our 'concept'
of this thing, our "objectivity' be." This "objectivity," he continues, is to be
understood as "the ability to control one's Pro and Con and to dispose of them,
so that one knows how to employ a variety of perspectives and affective
interpretations in the service of knowledge" (GM III: 12).
Another of Nietzsche's points with respect to truth and knowledge, which is
just as easily and commonly misunderstood, pertains to their inescapably
"human" character. He considers it meaningful to speak of "truth" and "knowl-
edge" only in relation to the interpretive articulation of states of affairs in which
we ourselves are implicated, by means of concepts of our devising. It does not
follow, however, that they are thereby radically invalidated in principle. On the
contrary, it is a condition of the very possibility of truth and knowledge that
there exist creatures having access to the world and the capacity and means to
address themselves to it. Indeed, there can be truth and knowledge only where
there exists some medium in which states of affairs can be given expression: and
in the absence of something on the order of human language and thought, this
requirement would not be satisfied. Where nothing can be put into words
because there is no such expressive medium at hand, therefore, and also in
abstraction from the establishment and employment of any such interpretive
schematization, the notions of truth and error, and of knowledge and ignorance,
have no application. If the interpretive process renders everything that might be
said or thought about the world by us a "human" rather than absolute and
unconditioned formulation, it also is our means of entry with respect to it. Truth
and knowledge thus may be held to be importantly "human" without thereby
being reduced completely to the merely human and denied all larger epistemic
significance. Nietzsche may not always have appreciated this point, and may
even have lost his grip on it from time to time: but as I read him it is one of the
more important hard-won gains of his philosophical development.
The road to knowledge for Nietzsche is no royal one, leading directly and
easily to its goal by means of mechanical procedures, immediate intuitions or
revelations. Indeed, it is not even a single road, but rather a variety of circuitous
paths, enabling one to reach various vantage points from which different aspects
of life and the world become discernible. Scientific inquiry, historical and
genealogical investigation, psychological analysis, and reflection upon the
character of differing forms of activity we may observe and experience all figure
prominently among them. Each can afford some insight at certain junctures, and
complements while informing the interpretation of the issue of the rest. The
NIETZSCHE: TRUTH AND KNOWLEDGE 37
And knowledge itself: let it be something else for others ... -for me it is a world of dangers and
victories in which heroic feelings, too, find places to dance and play. "Life as a means to
knowledge"- with this principle in one's heart one can live not only boldly but even gaily, and
laugh gaily too. (GS 324)
NOTES
For a fuller treatment of these matters, see my Nietzsche (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1983), Chap. 2, from which this essay is derived. See also my Making Sense of Nietzsche (Urbana
and Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 1995), esp. Chaps. 2-4.
2 Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, section 230.
3 I shall avail myself of notes from Nietzsche's notebooks (and in particular of those gathered
together and published under the title The Willw Power), as well as his published writings, on the
38 RICHARD SCHACHT
grounds that these notes provide further valuable indications of his thinking on the matters under
consideration, even if not definitive expressions of it. For a general discussion of this issue, see
my Making Sense of Nietzsche, Chap. 6.
ROBERT C. WELSHON
That Nietzsche needs ontological views of any kind, much less perspectivist
ones, has been denied. 2 But its necessity is revealed once the depth of his
critique of the philosophical tradition is recalled. Parts of this critique are no
doubt complete without appeal to ontology, but those that apply to logic and
epistemology are not. Nietzsche frequently criticizes logic and epistemology for
hidden metaphysical commitments. One might conjecture that his argument
against logic and epistemology is only that since it is impossible to refer to
anything outside the perspectives that constitute them, neither logic nor
epistemology ever come into contact with the world as it really is. But on this
view, logical concepts cut and sculpt the world according to human interests and
knowledge becomes an imposition of those concepts on a world that is itself a
fixed entity, in the end unknowable because we cannot escape the perspectives
we are doomed to adopt in our attempts to reach it. This cannot be correct
interpretation of Nietzsche, for the world has here become a thing-in-itself.
Since Nietzsche thinks the thing-in-itself is "the horrendum pudendum of the
metaphysicians," 3 any distinction premised on its existence must be inconsistent
with his views. Hence, Nietzsche's critique of logic and epistemology goes
through only if the perspectivity characteristic of the human knower is charac-
teristic also of the world.
39
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 39-46.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
40 ROBERT C. WELSHON
What then does this perspectivist ontology look like? Infrequently in the
works prepared by him for publication and frequently in the Notebooks,
Nietzsche discusses its component claims. He repeatedly claims that the world
is ephemeral, energetic, and in motion, that it is composed of events, and that
each event is nothing more than "a determination of degrees and relations of
force" (WP 552). Take two examples:
The degree of resistance and the degree of superior power- this is the question in every event ...
A quantum of power is designated by the effect it produces and that which it resists. The
adiaphorous state is missing. though it is thinkable. It is essentially a will to violate and to defend
oneself against violation. Not self-preservation: every atom affects the whole of being - it is
thought away if one thinks away this radiation of power-will. That is why I call it a quantum of
"will to power": it expresses the characteristic that cannot be thought out of the mechanistic order
without thinking away this order itself. (WP 634)
[N]o things remain but only dynamic quanta, in a relation of tension to all other dynamic quanta:
their essence lies in their relation to all other quanta, in their "effect" upon the same. The will to
power not a being, not a becoming, but a pathos- the most elemental fact from which a becoming
and effecting first emerge- (WP 635)
In both passages it is clear that, at the microcosmic level, there are atomic
events of power, referred to by the terms "quanta of power" and "dynamic
quanta." They are individuated by the effects they produce and those they resist.
Their essence consists in their being a relation of effecting and resisting other
such events. The world is thus "a sea of forces flowing and rushing together,
eternally changing, eternally flooding back" (WP 1067), and the set of quanta
of force composes or constitutes the world. As he puts it:" ... the 'world' is only
a word for the totality of these actions. Reality consists precisely in this
particular action and reaction of every individual part toward the whole-" (WP
568; cf. 568).
These insights characterize the entire hierarchy of increasingly complex
societies of quanta of power that compose the familiar objects of our everyday
middle-sized dry goods ontology. Quanta of power cooperate to form more
structured societies or alliances of power, each of which is concerned with
extending its power. Thus, Nietzsche notes that "[every specific body] continu-
ally encounters similar efforts on the part of other bodies and ends by coming
to an arrangement ('union') with those of them that are sufficiently related to it:
thus they conspire together for power" (WP 636). As at simpler levels, societies
of power are only contingently cooperative and have only as much unity as do
organizations and cooperatives (cf. WP 561). Given that their membership
regularly changes, they do not, except in a "loose and popular" sense, attain
diachronic identity. 4 Most societies are inorganic, but some form more complex
living beings, each one of whose component parts and actions are best inter-
preted by appealing to maximization of power (cf. WP 642). All life, even a
form as simple as protoplasm (WP 551, 654 ), is "a will to the accumulation of
force; ... life strives after a maximal feeling of power" (WP 689). 5 Of course, at
organic levels too, diachronic identity obtains only loosely. Nietzsche. for
instance, also notes that "living unities continually arise and die ... the 'subject'
PERSPECTIVIST ONTOLOGY AND DE RE KNOWLEDGE 41
is not eternal" (WP 492). This should be expected, for the organs and systems
that constitute an or~anic being, and not just the quanta that constitute them, can
themselves change.
How is this ontology of power perspectivist? According to Nietzsche,
perspectives are mapped to both quanta of power and societies of power. So,
each atomic quantum event and every molecular society of events generates a
perspective. 7 Nietzsche affirms that there is an interpretation or perspective for
every quantum of power and for every level of complexity above the funda-
mental level as well. 8 Thus, where there are distinct societies offorce, there too
are distinct interpretations on the balance. Since there is an infinity of quanta
and societies of power, there is an infinity of perspectives, as claimed in The
Gay Science, section 374.
Perspectivist ontology is, pretty obviously, akin to a bundle theory of objects,
the thesis that objects are reducible to bundles of properties. For the sake of
simplicity, assume that societies are composed, not of properties, but of quanta
of power. 9 An apparent implication of this view is that any aggregate of such
quanta, no matter how spatially discontinuous, fulfills the conditions for
thinghood. For example, the aggregate composed of my geographic plot of
Denali, on the one hand, and, on the other, the Dalai Lama constitutes a thing
that has every bit as much of a claim to ontological respectablity as a tree. There
are three options Nietzsche might pursue in response to this possibility. The first
accepts that the object composed of my geographic plot of Denali and the Dalai
Lama is as robust an object as a brick. This form of the bundle theory is a kind
of conjunctivism, the view according to which any conjunction of two or more
entities of a given ontological category can compose a whole. 10 The second
option is to claim that bundles are composed and individuated by perspectives
taken on quanta of power from an external point of view. On this constellation-
ist alternative, 11 my geographic plot of Denali and the Dalai Lama may be an
object in some perspectives, but not in others, or may be an object in no
perspective. A third option, organizationism, 12 claims that something intrinsic
to the bundles is that in virtue of which they are composed. So, since there is
nothing intrinsic holding my geographic plot of Denali and the Dalai Lama
together, there will be no object composed of them. Nietzsche weighs all three,
so consider each.
(I) Conjunctivism
[T]he world, apart from our condition of living in it, the world that we have not reduced to our
being. our logic and psychological prejudices, does not exist as a world "in-itself'; it is essentially
a world of relationships; under certain conditions it has a differing aspect from every point; its
being is essentially different from every point. every point resists it -and the sum of these is in
every case quite incongruent. (WP 568)
II
knowledge of anything. For that conclusion to follow, the only things of which
we could have de re knowledge would have to be things-in-themselves. But,
after dumping the real/apparent world distinction and things-in-themselves
along with it, Nietzsche offers the bundle view of objects discussed above.
There is no good reason that there cannot be de re knowledge of these bundles. 16
It is true that he vacillates between three different views of bundle individuation,
so the view is not univocal. Since it is here that some of the extraordinary
implications of perspectivist ontology for de re knowledge begin to emerge,
consider, again, each alternative in turn.
(1) Conjunctivism. Under conjunctivism, all combinations of quanta of power
are objects. 17 Given an infinite number of power quanta, there is then an infinite
number of objects. However, that the world is composed of an infinite number
of objects does not imply that human knowledge is infinite. On the contrary,
human knowledge of conjunctivist objects is still finite because human mental
capacities are finite, as are our needs and desires. Thus humans cannot have de
recognitive attitudes towards the infinite number of conjunctivist objects in the
world. Rather, only those objects required by our perspective are ever known by
us, for it is only the objects required by our perspective about which we will
form perspectivally true and false beliefs, beliefs that then will or will fail to
qualify as knowledge. Hence, although conjunctivism countenances bundles of
every possible size - from atoms and molecules to galaxies - and countenances
every possible configuration of bundles - from cueball-cats to Ponderosa Pine-
Moonlight Sonata performances - human knowers will not form beliefs about
them unless their perspective requires them to do so. And if there are no beliefs
about them, there is no de re knowledge of them either. Thus, human knowledge
of the world is necessarily limited.
It would be a mistake to infer from these epistemological limitations anything
about the existence of a relationless and unconditioned world, a world of things-
in-themselves. Hence, it would be a mistake to infer that the bundle-objects
beyond human knowledge are unconditioned clusters of extra-perspectival
quanta of power. It is true that our knowledge is limited, but from this it follows
not that there is a world composed of unconditioned objects, but only that there
is a world composed of objects not conditioned by human knowledge. If
conjunctivism is true, the number of objects remaining after deleting those of
which humans can have de re knowledge is still infinite and still infinitely
conditioned and infinitely relational. For, ex hypothesi, every possible configu-
ration of power quanta is a bundle, and the spatial, temporal, constitutional,
mereological, causal, orginating, and other relations and conditions in virtue of
which those bundles are composed do not shrivel up and vanish because we lack
knowledge of them. Moreover, the relations in virtue of which conjunctivist
bundles are composed are, each and every one, also species of perspectives. So
the world that remains once our perspectives are deleted is still perspective-full
all the way down. Hence, although there is on conjuctivism a world of things
beyond our knowledge, there is no world of things that are in-themselves.
(2) Constellationism. According to constellationism, bundles are composed
and individuated by perspectives taken on subsets of the set of quanta of power
44 ROBERT C. WELSHON
by other subsets of that set. Thus, there is also an infinite number of constella-
tionist bundles if there is an infinite number of power quanta, for to each
quantum there is mapped a perspective. So too, constellationist bundles are
pervasively perspectivist, for their constitution and their individuation is
extrinsic to them.
As it is on conjunctivism, so too is de re knowledge of constellationist
bundle-objects bounded by our cognitive finitude, so our de re beliefs and
knowledge are finite and perspectival. Not only is composition of objects
determined by perspective on constellationism, so too is their decomposition
and destruction. If, for example, a perspective requires that objects from middle-
sized dry goods ontology such as telephones be reductively decomposed into
their atomic constituents, then there are no telephones from that perspective.
And if a perspective entails that there are no objects composed of a molecule
from my left foot and the Holy Roman Empire, then so be it. It is of course
possible that there be a perspective in which there is such a bundle-object, but
that this is a possibility rather than an actuality marks the difference between
constellationism and conjunctivism, on which every combination of quanta is
actual.
Just as it would be a mistake to infer from conjunctivism that there are
unconditioned bundle-objects beyond human knowledge, so too would it be a
mistake to infer from constellationism that there are no unconditioned bundle-
objects beyond human knowledge. Thinking that constellationism implies that
what there is is restricted to what a person or group of persons believes confuses
perspectives with beliefs. Perspectives are not beliefs - they are modalities
generated by quanta of power and societies of them, some of which societies can
generate beliefs. 18 Individual human perspectives will, of course, be partially
composed of needs and desires, so intentional attitudes will help to determine
the structure of the human world. But de re knowledge is not simply a matter of
having beliefs about objects. Rather, de re knowledge is having perspectivally
true beliefs about a bundle object licensed by one's operant perspective. These
perspectives can change, so the bundle objects of which one has de re knowl-
edge can change. Thus, one can operate within the perspective of quantum
physics and discover things about the microphysical world, but, since quantum
physics is not the only perspective on the microphysical world, one may still not
know all there is to know about it. 19 But no matter how often and how much our
perspectives change, the world of constellationist bundles is determined neither
by individual nor by social beliefs. so typical formulations of subjectivism and
social relativism are false.
(3) Organizationism. According to organizationism, bundles of quanta of
power are composed and individuated by intrinsic power maximizing principles
of organization. Hence, unlike conjunctivism, not all possible combinations of
quanta of power form actual bundles, for there are some bundles that could be
formed which would not be power maximizing. And, unlike constellation ism,
extrinsic bundle individuation is not entailed, for it is not the case that an
external perspective is required for individuation. None of this is to say that,
given a set of quanta of power of infinite cardinality, there would not be a set
PERSPECTIVIST ONTOLOGY AND DE RE KNOWLEDGE 45
III
NOTES
I have considered these questions in earlier papers. See Robert C. Welshon, "Nietzsche's
Perspectivist Ontology," International Studies in Philosophy (Summer, 1996): 77-98; Robert C.
Welshon, "Nietzsche's Perspectivist Causality" International Studies in Philosophy, forthcoming.
See also chapters 3, 4, and 5 in Nietzsche's Perspectivism, a book-length manuscript co-authored
46 ROBERT C. WELSHON
with Steven Hales. The ideas in this paper are direct and indirect implications of work done by
both of us in Nietzsche's Perspectivism, so I gratefully ackowledge Steven Hales's participation
in this paper as well.
2 See in D. B. Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche (New York: Dell Publishing, 1977), Jean Granier,
"Nietzsche's Conception of Chaos," pp. 137 and 139; Michel Haar, "Nietzsche and Metaphysical
Language," pp. 6 and 12; Sarah Kofman, "Metaphor, Symbol, Metamorphosis," pp. 201-214. Cf.
Ofelia Schutte, Beyond Nihilism: Nietzsche Without Masks. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1984), p. 47, 92-104; Alan Schrift, Nietzsche and the Question of Interpretation (New York:
Routledge, 1990), chapters 5-7.
3 Nietzsche, T1 VII 3; also GS 335, BGE II, TI V, WP 552b.
4 See GS 110, Ill; WP 520. See Roderick Chisholm, Person and Object (La Salle, Illinois: Open
Court Publishing, 1976), pp. 92-97.
5 Cf. BGE 13, 36,230, 259; GS 118, 349; AC 2; GM II 12; WP 644
6 See GM II 12
See WP 567, 637, and 639.
Cf. WP 259; BGE 34.
An alternative view, that societies are property constituted, is discussed at WP 557 and WP
558.
10
For more on mereology, see Chisholm, Person and Object, Appendix B.
11 Following Nietzsche; cf. WP 551.
12 Again following Nietzsche: WP 561.
13 See also WP 515, 559, and 639.
14 Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: L(fe as Literature (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1985), p. 83.
15 For further reflections on the other questions, see chapter 6 of Hales and Welshon, Nietzsche's
Perspectivism.
16 One (bad) argument for the conclusion that there can be no de re knowledge of Nietzschean
\\uanta.
1 Were perspectives sets of beliefs, there could be no untrue beliefs within a perspective. But
Nietzsche affirms just the opposite. In AC 23 he writes "truth and the belief that something is true:
two completely diverse worlds of interest". Compare: "a belief, however necessary it is for the
preservation of a species, has nothing to do with truth" (WP 487) and "a belief can be a condition
of life and nonetheless be false" (WP 483).
19 Thus Nietzsche claims at GM III 23 through 25 that even science is perspectival.
20 Just as denumerable infinities are smaller than non-denumerable infinities.
21 Natural kinds with a caveat: kinds are typically thought to be inhabitants of the world
regardless of perspective. But Nietzschean natural kinds are perspectivist inhabitants of a
perspectivist world.
R. LANIER ANDERSON
Nietzsche's remarks about truth are among the most notorious and philosophi-
cally problematic in his entire oeuvre. The trouble centers on his repeated claims
that there is no truth, or that all our beliefs are false in some sense - for
example, that "There exists neither spirit, nor reason, nor thinking, [... ] nor
truth: all are fictions that are of no use" (WP 480), or that "Truth is the kind of
error without which a certain species of life could not live" (WP 493). These
claims about truth are self-refuting in the most straightforward way: if they are
assumed to be truths, then by the force of their own assertion, they are false
("errors," "fictions"), and have no cognitive value. Some recent commentators
have insisted that Nietzsche's talk about truth should be evaluated rhetorically,
and not semantically. 1 Nietzsche's rejection of truth is rhetorically problematic
as well, however, for he is very willing to indulge in the rhetoric of criticizing
views by calling them false, or the like, 2 even though this would seem to be no
criticism at all, given his view that such falsity is inevitable. To add to the
paradox, Nietzsche's general denial of truth did not stop him from claiming that
some particular beliefs are true. Perhaps most famously, he closes the first
section of the Genealogy of Morals by expressing the hope that- whatever their
other faults - his much maligned "English psychologists" of morality "may be
fundamentally brave, proud, and magnanimous animals, who [... ] have trained
themselves to sacrifice all desirability to truth, every truth, even plain, harsh,
ugly, repellent, unchristian, immoral truth.- For such truths do exist.-" (GM I:
1). A more unambiguous affirmation of the existence of truths could hardly be
asked for.
In light of these difficulties of philosophical and textual coherence, it is
tempting to dismiss Nietzsche's denials of truth as slips of the pen, or at least
to find some way of interpreting his writings to show that he eventually
abandoned his denial of truth. 3 Two factors make such an interpretive strategy
difficult to carry out. First, the denial of truth is very widespread in Nietzsche's
text. The view is stated, or at least strongly suggested, in most of his published
works, and throughout his philosophical development, from the ear~, unpub-
lished essay "On Truth and Lie in the Extra-Moral Sense" (1873), down to
47
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 47-59.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
48 R. LANIER ANDERSON
Twilight of the Idols (1888). 5 Moreover, as we shall see, there are texts in which
Nietzsche makes claims to truth and statements of his denial of truth within the
space of one paragraph. It is therefore hard to imagine that all his denials of
truth could be mere slips, or that he simply failed to notice the apparent
contradictions arising from the view.
Second, Nietzsche's rejection of truth is deeply intertwined with his broader
views in epistemology. Nietzsche claims not only that there are no true
statements or beliefs, but further, that key and unavoidable features of our
highest cognitive processes work to falsify our views of the world. For example,
Nietzsche marvels at "the way in which precisely science at its best seeks most
to keep us in this simpl!fied, thoroughly artificial, suitably constructed and
suitably falsified world- the way in which, willy-nilly, it loves error, because,
being alive, it loves life"(BGE 24). As the final clause intimates, this "falsifica-
tion" is not merely a result of some special mystification found only in scientific
thinking, but is rather so general that we must "recognize untruth as a condition
of life" (BGE 4). In light of such claims about the inherently falsifying effects
of our cognitive perspectives, Maudemarie Clark has aptly characterized
Nietzsche's view as a "falsification thesis." 6
This thesis about systematic falsification arising from the very processes of
our cognition locates the denial of truth in a broader philosophical context, and
thereby makes it difficult to dismiss the truth paradoxes outright. Moreover, if
Nietzsche's denial of truth has these broader epistemological roots, then it is
hard to allay worries about the inconsistency of his thinking in truth and
knowledge through appeal to the increasingly popular gambit of denying that
Nietzsche meant to offer any "positive" theory of truth. 7 Whether Nietzsche has
a "theory" of truth or not, his falsification claims make it clear that the para-
doxical statements about truth are systematically connected to his characteristic
idea that our knowledge and evaluations of the world are limited by the
influence of perspective, and if these falsification claims are self-refuting, then
substantial parts of Nietzsche's views on knowledge - and even about the
relation between human values and the world through perspectives- may also
be implicated in the contradiction. 8
Thus, the widespread and obtrusively paradoxical character of Nietzsche's
comments about truth, coupled with the close connection between these
comments and central notions in his broader philosophy, leave Nietzsche's
readers under the obligation to confront this paradox directly, and try to make
some sense of the things he says about truth. Nietzsche's own claims to truth
arise within his self-proclaimed task as a seeker after knowledge, 9 and in fact,
the paradox emerges immediately from Nietzsche's usage of the truth predicate
in making knowledge claims. He writes relatively short texts that use the
predicates "true" or "false" in one place to make claims to truth (or falsity), and
in another place to suggest his wholesale rejection of truth. 10 If the falsification
thesis is the flagrant self-contradiction it appears to be, then it will be impossible
to make any sense at all of such texts. The project of understanding Nietzsche's
comments on truth must therefore begin at the most basic level, from the attempt
to make sense of this kind of usage.
NIETZSCHE'S VIEWS ON TRUTH 49
motion and rest, form and content" (GS 121), or again, in terms of "the synthetic
judgments apriori," along with "logic, ... the unconditional and self-identical,
... [and] numbers" (BGE 4 ). 14 Elsewhere, Nietzsche writes in an even more
Kantian vein, speaking of the way our cognition works to "simplify the
manifold" (BGE 230) in accordance with "a scheme [... ] posited by ourselves"
(WP 516). Like Kant, then, Nietzsche holds that our experience is the joint
product of empirical evidence provided by the world, and the influence of the
cognitive resources we use to organize that evidence. Nietzsche thus maintains
something of the structure of Kant's famous "Copernican revolution" in
epistemology, according to which knowledge is not simply a matter of bringing
our concepts into conformity with mind-independent objects, but is rather the
result of a process in which our own concepts have a positive influence, so that,
in an important sense, the objects of knowledge must themselves conform to a
framework arising from our cognitive activity. 15
Apparently, this last point is what leads Nietzsche to his falsification claims.
Our subjective perspectives transform our experience of the world, and thereby
prevent our knowledge from simply conforming itself to things as they are in
themselves. Clearly assuming that truth is just such a relation of conforming or
correspondence, Nietzsche concludes that our knowledge is subject to endemic
falsification: since Kant we have realized that "delusion and error [are] a
condition of cognitive and perceptual existence" (GS 107). 16 Kant himself drew
no such conclusion, however. Thus, despite the broad structural similarities
between Nietzsche and Kant I have just rehearsed, there must also be significant
differences that make Nietzsche think he is entitled to infer from the influence
of perspective to a general falsification thesis.
Perhaps the most obvious of Nietzsche's departures from Kantian orthodoxy
is his conclusion that the very notion of the thing in itself is incoherent.
Famously, Kant's considered view is that we cannot know anything about things
in themselves, but nevertheless, he never fails to think of them along the lines
of the traditional (pre-Kantian) notion of substance, i.e., as "objects of the pure
understanding" (A 264/B 320). Such things, as the proper objects of complete
conceptual descriptions of the intellect, or understanding, must be self-subsistent
(and thus independent from all other things) and completely determinate. 17 This
conception seems coherent enough at first blush, but Nietzsche ultimately finds
deep problems with it, precisely by following out the implications of Kant's
own argument that we could not have any power of the "real use" of the
intellect, 18 or intellectual intuition. Things in themselves are conceived as the
proper objects of just this cognitive power, and if we lack any such power, then
the thing in itself, qua "object of the pure intellect," could only be the com-
pletely unknowable "something in general" (B 307, cf. A 252, A 256/B 312)
that Kant posits as the underlying ground of the objects we know through
experience.
Nietzsche's worry begins from this point. The unknowability of things in
themselves is part of their very conception: it arises not from some contingent
deficiency or incompleteness in our experience or theorizing to date, but from
general and inevitable limitations on our cognitive resources, most importantly
NIETZSCHE'S VIEWS ON TRUTH 51
the "matter" of experience (A 167/B 209, see also A 20/B 34), which these
formal concepts organize, arises ultimately from the things in themselves. Both
the form and the matter in this account have a fixed, determinate character; the
basic conceptual scheme is necessary, and the things in themselves are fully
determinate (albeit unknown to us). Therefore, form and matter combine to
produce a uniquely determined world of experience, and it is to this world of
objects that our beliefs correspond when they are empirically true.
When Nietzsche abandons the necessary status of our organizing concepts,
he thereby gives up the only good Kantian grounds for positing a uniquely
determined world of objects of appearance, existing in independence from
idiosyncratic facts about the perspectives cognizers use to organize the data of
experience. This has serious implications for Nietzsche's thinking about the
possibility of truth. Truth, on the traditional way of conceiving it, is just a
relation of correspondence to a uniquely determined, and (at least relatively)
independent world of things. Nietzsche's perspectivism prevents any belief from
being true in this sense. As we saw, beliefs cannot correspond to things in
themselves for Nietzsche, since he thinks the very idea of such a correspondence
is unintelligible. But without a unique transcendental order for experience, there
is also no longer any single world of objects of appearance - necessary for all
finite knowers like us 20 - to which our beliefs could correspond. In ordering and
transforming our experience, each of our perspectives limits the legitimate,
meaningful application of its perspectival representations to a world that is
inextricably tied to potentially idiosyncratic features of that subjective perspec-
tive -that is, perspectives limit us to a "simplified, thoroughly artificial, suitably
constructed and suitably falsified world" (BGE 24). So in the end, none of our
beliefs can count as true in the traditional sense.
As the qualification "in the traditional sense" suggests, however, once the
motivations of Nietzsche's underlying philosophical position are fully out on the
table, it is easier to make sense of this paradoxical conclusion about truth. When
Nietzsche rejects truth in this way, he is rejecting just the assumption- shared
by Kant and the rationalist metaphysicians whom Kant criticized - that there is
a uniquely determinate world of objects to which our beliefs and theories
correspond (or fail to correspond). This rejection of truth is motivated by two
considerations: first, Nietzsche's broadly Kantian conception of cognition, as
knowledge of an experience that is itself formed through the "active" (GM III:
12) operation of our perspectives; and second, Nietzsche's commitment, in
contrast to orthodox Kantianism, that our perspectives are contingent and
various, and that each of them organizes the data of our experience in a
particular way, so that different claims about the basic ontology of the world
may be justified in different perspectives. According to Nietzsche, when we use
concepts like those of "enduring thing" or "causality" to organize the data of
sense, we are imposing a stable order onto experience from our own perspective,
and because this is not the only possible order, it cannot uniquely define what
counts as an object of experience. Nevertheless, we cannot do without some
concepts to organize experience, even if no particular concept (or set of
concepts) is necessary for this purpose: "That mountain there! That cloud there!
NIETZSCHE'S VIEWS ON TRUTH 53
What is 'real' in that? Subtract every phantasm and every human contribution
from it my sober friends, if you can! ... There is no 'reality' for us- not for you
either, my sober friends" (GS 57). As this anti-realist conclusion suggests, to the
extent that some of their basic features derive from the "active" operations of
our particular perspectives, the objects of knowledge themselves have a
"subjective" component: as Nietzsche puts the point, "interpretation and
subjectivity are essential to things" (WP 560). Our basic concepts therefore do
not have the objective validity claimed for them by Kant, and when we use such
perspectival concepts, we "falsif[y] the testimony of the senses" (Tl III, 2) and
are "caught in error, compelled into error" (Tl III, 5), in the sense that the
resulting claims do not correspond to a unique world of objects - whether things
in themselves or empirical objects - that are independent in a serious way from
the subjective "conditions of life" that generate our own perspective.
None of this, however, prevents Nietzsche from insisting that some perspecti-
val interpretations are cognitively or epistemically better than others. To cite
only the most obvious example, Nietzsche insists that his view of nature as "de-
deified" (GS 109) is cognitively superior to a Christian interpretation which sees
the hand of God in every event (see GS 109 and 357, and BGE 188), and he
clearly indicates that his task as a genealogist and "man of knowledge" (GM
Preface, 1) is "to replace the less plausible with the more plausible" (GM
Preface, 4)- that is, to produce new interpretations which are better than those
currently on offer. Nietzsche's argumentative practice in such contexts makes
it natural to assume that one perspective is cognitively superior to another
whenever it better meets the epistemic standards we use to evaluate theories
(e.g., plausibility, in GM Preface, 4, or, elsewhere, simplicity, empirical
adequacy, explanatory power, etc.). For example, when Nietzsche criticizes the
conception of natural selection employed by his contemporary physiologists (in
BGE 13), he does so on the explicitly methodological grounds that their
explanations made illegitimate appeal to a teleological principle (involved in the
concept of a "will to survive" attributed to organisms). Nietzsche insists that his
own explanatory strategy, based on the will to power, is better because it better
satisfies the maxim that teleological explanation should have as limited a role
as possible in the sciences of nature, and "thus method, which must be essen-
tially economy of principles, demands it" (BGE 13). 21 Many of Nietzsche's
other arguments 22 also rest crucially on claims that one interpretation satisfies
our epistemic standards better than its competitors.
I submit that Nietzsche utilized a second notion of truth, fundamentally
distinct from the traditional sense, in order to express this kind of cognitive
superiority. In this second sense, there is nothing more to being true than
meeting our epistemic standards relatively well. Thus, an interpretation is truer
if it better meets our epistemic standards, and since these standards can be met
to a greater or lesser degree, theories can be more or less true. It is just because
he uses such a conception of truth, I think, that Nietzsche insists that truth is a
matter of degree in this way (see BGE 34, WP 535). This alternative, "theory-
internal"23 conception of truth emphasizes the dependence of truth claims on the
nature of our cognitive practices (e.g., on the standards that guide those
54 R. LANIER ANDERSON
his point of view, in order to exploit the rhetorical force of the resulting
paradox. To cite only the most notorious example, he claims "God is dead" (GS
108, 125). Thus, attention to the dual senses in which Nietzsche uses "true" not
only enables us to resolve the truth paradoxes, but also allows us to see the
underlying philosophical point of his use of these paradoxical falsification
claims.
CONCLUSION
quences, are among the chief advantages of Nietzsche's "internalism" over later,
twentieth century versions of the position.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks are due to Katherine Preston, Alexander Nehamas, Gary Hatfield, Babette Babich, and
Bernard Reginster for their comments on earlier versions of this paper, and to Hatfield, especially,
for helpful conversations about Kant. Thanks also to Fred Dretske, for pushing me to become
clearer about Nietzsche's reasons for rejecting the thing in itself.
NOTES
See, e.g., Bernd Magnus, "Nietzsche Today: A View from America," International Studies in
Philosophy 15, no. 2 (1983): 95-104, Alan Schrift, Nietzsche and the Question of Interpretation
(New York: Routledge, 1990), chs. 6-7, and, in a somewhat different vein, Ken Gemes,
"Nietzsche's Critique of Truth," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52, no. I (March
1992): 47-65. The approaches of Sarah Kofman, Nietzsche and Metaphor, trans. D. Large
(Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1993), Jacques Derrida, Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles, trans.
B. Harlow (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979), and Paul de Man, Allegories of Reading
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1979) are similar to this move in spirit, but they also go
further than this claim in important respects.
2 For example, "we thus reject the Christian interpretation and condemn its meaning as
counterfeit" (GS 357); "We, too, do not deny that faith 'makes blessed': that is precisely why we
deny that faith proves anything- a strong faith that makes blessed raises suspicion against that
which is believed; it does not establish 'truth,' it establishes a certain probability- of deception"
(GM III, 24); "As for materialistic atomism, it is one of the best refuted theories there are, and in
Europe perhaps no one in the learned world is now so unscholarly as to attach serious significance
to it, except for convenient household use" (BGE 12); and perhaps most dramatically, "In the
Christian world of ideas there is nothing that has the least contact with reality- and it is in the
instinctive hatred of reality that we have recognized the only motivating force at the root of
Christianity. What follows from this? That in psychologicis too, the error here is radical,[ ... ] One
concept less, one single reality in its place, and the whole of Christianity hurtles down into
nothing" (A 39).
3 This last interpretive tack is most prominently and thoroughly pursued by Maudemarie Clark,
Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990). Although the
reading of Nietzsche I advocate here bears some similarities to Clark's informative treatment, I
cannot accept her central claim that Nietzsche eventually abandoned his denial of truth. For a
fuller treatment, see R. Lanier Anderson, "Overcoming Charity: the Case of Maudemarie Clark's
Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy," Nietzsche-Studien 25 (1996): 307-41.
4 "What then is truth? A movable host of metaphors, metonymies, and anthropomorphisms: in
short, a sum of human relations which have been poetically and rhetorically intensified,
transferred, and embellished, and which, after long usage, seem to a people to be fixed, canonical
and binding. Truths are illusions which we have forgotten are illusions; they are metaphors that
have become worn out and have been drained of sensuous force, coins which have lost their
embossing and are now considered as metal and no longer as coins" (TL, 84).
5 "They [the senses] do not lie at all. What we make of their testimony, that alone introduces lies;
for example, the lie of unity, the lie of thinghood, of substance, of permanence. 'Reason' is the
cause of our falsification of the testimony of the senses" (TI III, 2).
6 Clark, Nietzsche on Truth, 95.
7 This claim has been prominently made by Alexander Nehamas, Nietzsche: Life as Literature
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 52-55, and also by Gemes, "Nietzsche's
Critique," and Randall Havas, Nietzsche's Genealogy: Nihilism and the Will to Knowledge (Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press, 1995). Nehamas seems to share my contention that this point by
itself does not resolve the truth paradoxes, since he goes on to offer additional considerations to
resolve those problems. See Nehamas, Life as Literature, 56-63 and 65-69. By contrast, Gemes
and Havas try to get more work out of simply :insisting that Nietzsche was not offering any theory
58 R. LANIER ANDERSON
of truth, and was indeed "not interested in the notion of truth per se" (Gemes. "Nietzsche's
Critique," 64).
8 According to Nietzsche, our perspectives organize our experience. and thereby give things a
certain "look" for us. Such perspectives include our most basic logical, metaphysical. and
scientific concepts (e.g., "logic" (BGE 3), mathematics, the "self-identical." and the "synthetic
judgments a priori" (BGE 4 ), "bodies, lines, planes, causes and effects, motion and rest. form and
content" (GS 121) ). We adopt the perspectives we do because they respond to our needs, interests,
and values (see BGE 3, 4; GS 110, 112, 121 ). Nietzsche makes it clear in BGE 4 that he thinks this
organization of experience in accord with our concepts and values amounts to a "falsification··
(BGE 4), and therefore Nietzsche's basic epistemology and his account of the relation between our
values and the world are deeply bound up with the falsification thesis. I give a fuller interpretation
of perspectivism along these lines, and propose a resolution for other self-referential difficulties
besides the truth paradox, in R. Lanier Anderson, "Truth and Objectivity in Perspectiv-
ism,"Svnthese 115 (1998): 1-32.
9 In addition to the famous passage from GM I: l, quoted above, see, e.g., "Let us say once more
what we have already said a hundred times, for today's ears resist such truths- our truths" (BGE
202); and "In late ages that may be proud of their humanity, so much fear remains. so much
superstitious fear of the 'savage cruel beast' whose conquest is the very pride of these more
humane ages, that even palpable truths remain unspoken for centuries [... j. Perhaps I dare
something when I let one of these truths slip out: let others catch it again and give it 'milk of the
pious ways of thinking'" (BGE 229). On the importance of the pursuit of knowledge within
Nietzsche's conception ofhis task, see GS 110, 324, and 325. GM Preface. and BGE 227-230.
Claims to truth naturally arise in connection with such a task.
10 See, e.g., BGE 229-30, and even more dramatically WP 535. Both passages are discussed in
section 2, below.
11 See Richard Schacht, Nietzsche (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983). ch. 2.
12 The following discussion is based on my "overcoming Charity: The Case of Maudemaric
Charity." Others have also noted the broadly Kantian character of Nietzsche's perspcctivism. See
esp. Friedrich Kaulbach, Philosophie des Perspektivismus, 1 Teil: Wahrheit und Per.1pektive bei
Kant, Hegel, und Nietzsche (Tiibingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck), 1990), and also Clark.
':iietzsche on Truth and Philosophy. esp. ch. 5.
See the lists of concepts at BGE 21 and 34, GS II 0, and WP 497, 516, and 574.
15 See Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason, trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St.
Martin's 1962) citations to the Critique will be made parenthetically in the text. Kant describes
his position as a second Copernican revolution in the Preface to the second edition of the Critique
of Pure Reason, because it reverses the traditional approach to knowledge: "Hitherto it has been
assumed that all our knowledge must conform to objects. But [... j we might have more success in
the tasks of metaphysics if we suppose that objects must conform to our knowledge" (B xvi).
Objects "conform to our knowledge" in the sense that possible objects of knowledge appear to us
only through the framework we use to conceptualize our experience. All objects of knowledge thus
bear the influence of that framework.
16 I have altered Kaufmann's translation of this passage.
17 On the conception of things in themselves as "objects of the pure intellect." see. e.g .. A 254/8
310, and A 264-5/B 320-1. A complete conceptual description of the intellect, capable of
determining a thing in itself, would be a description which determined, for every possible
predicate, that the object in question had that predicate, or had its opposite. This is the sense in
which things in themselves are completely determinate and self-subsistent, in Kant's way of
thinking about them. Such a conception is clearly implicit, for example, in Kant's discussion of
Leibniz at A 281/B 337, and also in his inference to transcendental idealism as the solution for the
Antinomies of reason, at A 506-7/B 534-5.
18 In his so-called "Inaugural Dissertation,'' Kant makes much of the distinction between the "real
use" of the intellect and its merely "logical use." See Immanuel Kant, On the Form and Principles
of the Sensible and Intelligible World, in Theoretical Philosoph.v, 1755-1770, trans. and ed., D.
Walford and R. Meerbote (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), pp. 385, 386, 406 (Ak.
pp. 393, 394, 411). By the time of the Critique of Pure Reason. however. (and especially in the
second edition) Kant comes to reject the possibility of any such "real use." See, e.g., B 68, B 71-2.
A 51/B 75, B 135, B 138-9, and B 145. Gary Hatfield, The Natural and the Normative: Theories
of Spatial Perception from Kant to Helmholtz (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1990) has pointed out
that this is one of the central insights separating Kant's mature thought from his "pre-critical"
NIETZSCHE'S VIEWS ON TRUTH 59
writings, and also that this rejection of any real use of the intellect was of fundamental importance
in changing our understanding of the powers of the mind. See esp. pp. 59, 78-9, 81, 93, 127, and
213. For the broad story of how this point influenced conceptions of the mind, see also Gary
Hatfield, "The Workings of the Intellect," in Logic and the Workings of the Mind: the Logic of
Ideas and Faculty Psychology in Early Modern Philosophy, ed. Patricia Easton, (North American
Kant Society, 1997).
19 There are two other potential ways to justify the posit of something like things in themselves,
and thus to underwrite our ability to make sense of the notion. Things in themselves could be
understood as the underlying cause of the objects of experience, or they could be posited as what
Kant called the transcendental "correlate" (A 250) of the world of experience, i.e., as the ultimate
source of the "matter" which our "formal" cognitive resources organize in order to produce
experience. Nietzsche follows Schopenhauer's point that the first way involves an illegitimate
application of the concept of causality beyond the realm of possible experience, and he rejects the
second way since he denies that our cognitive resources have the transcendental status attributed
to them by Kant. I discuss these points more fully in Anderson, "Truth and Objectivity in
Perspectivism."
20 In this Kantian context, "like us" would cover the very broad class of all finite intellects that
have space and time as forms of intuition, a class which comprises (at least) all human beings.
21 For a fuller discussion of this argument, and how it fits into Nietzsche's larger defense of his
will to power doctrine, see R. Lanier Anderson, "Nietzsche's Will to Power as a Doctrine of the
Unity of Science," Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25, no. 5 (October 1994): 729-50.
22 Including. for example, his argument for a particular interpretation of punishment at GM II:
12-14, and his arguments against the hypotheses of the "English psychologists" about the origins
of morality at GM I: 1-4.
23 Elsewhere (Anderson, "Truth and Objectivity in Perspectivism"), I have distinguished these
two conceptions of truth as "internal" and "external." Nietzsche's new sense of truth is "internal"
because it depends on notions drawn from within our cognitive practices (epistemic standards),
while the traditional conception of truth is "eli:ternal" because it posits a standard of truth which
is outside the circle of our cognitive practices (independent things).
24 As I noted in section 1, above, Richard Schacht. Nietzsche, ch. 2, has also suggested that
fails to correspond to the way things are "in themselves" with our cognition, since the very notion
of such a way things are is incoherent.
27 Thanks are due to Bernard Reginster for forcing me to become clearer on the issues connected
°
3 Clark, Nietzsche on Truth, 107.
31 Clark, Nietzsche on Truth, 134.
32 Clark, Nietzsche on Truth, 107.
33 Clark, Nietzsche on Truth, 107.
PAUL J. M. VAN TONGEREN
Apart from his plentiful contact with the ancient philosophers from his years in
Schulpforta, from his courses at the university, and from his weekly lessons on
Plato at the Piidagogium in Basel, Nietzsche's most influential experience with
philosophy was his discovery of Schopenhauer's The World as Will and Repres-
entation. For Schopenhauer, it is well-known there were only two philosophers
towards whom he felt indebted: Plato and Kant. Nietzsche wrote in a letter in
1866 how much he was impressed by F.A. Lange's History of Materialism, a
book in which the author elaborates a strong but liberally interpreted Kantianism
in skeptical and positivistic directions. Nietzsche concludes in his letter sayin§
that he did not need more than "Kant, Schopenhauer and this book of Lange."
We may assume that Plato was too obviously important to Nietzsche to be
included in this remark.
61
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II. 61-71.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
62 PAUL J. M. VAN TONGEREN
NIETZSCHE'S SKEPTICISM
The main strategies of Nietzsche's skepticism are the arguments that the theory
of truth is a linguistic (metaphorical) construction with the aim of securing a
type of life, and that a naturalistic understanding of knowledge is produced by
the instincts and needs of the knower.
Language plays an important role in the external determination of thinking.
Indeed, that a verb presupposes a subject and that therefore an effect presup-
poses a cause is not an immediate insight but a "grammatical habit" (BGE 17-
16). Or, that to the single word "will" corresponds also a reality which is one is
not self-evident but a prejudice (BGE 19). Philosophies are dominated by
prejudicial grammatical schemes (BGE 20). This idea of the enormous influence
of language on our thinking and knowing, language itself being a product of
physiological needs, desires, and instincts, is a permanent theme in Nietzsche's
writings from the very beginning. In On Truth and Lies in A Nonmoral Sense he
points out that the intellect was the means through which the human being, this
weak animal, managed to become stronger than its enemies:
As a means for the preserving of the individual, the intellect unfolds its principle powers in
dissimulation, which is the means by which weaker, less robust individuals preserve themselves
-since they have been denied the chance to wage the battle for existence with horns or with the
sharp teeth of beasts of prey. (TL, 80)
equal and through forgetting about the individual and particular. These concepts
and abstractions become, then, the elements with which the human being starts
to think about reality! All structure and "intelligibility" that we discover in
reality are discovered with the help of this language of words and concepts;
thus, they are a creation of man. "Genuine knowledge" uses language according
to conventions and reproduces these conventions in ever more interpretations.
Since we always think within the constraints of language (KSA 12, 193-4),
and since language is the product of some type of life, we can understand the
thoughts of the philosophers as symptoms of the type of life that expresses itself
in them. This is what Nietzsche does when he criticizes "the philosophers" (and
it explains why for Nietzsche the differences between many of the thinkers from
the history of philosophy are less interesting than the similarities; cf. BGE 20).
Genealogy is the name of Nietzsche's method of reading philosophical and
scientific theories suspiciously, reading them as symptoms of the kind of life
that expresses itself in them. The faith in opposite values emerges only from a
"frog perspective" (BGE 2), logic is dominated by the physiological demand for
the preservation of a certain type of life (BGE 3), sensualism gives witness of
a plebeian taste (BGE 14), and so forth. Philosophers are guided by their
dominating instincts (BGE 6) which determine the type of life they represent.
This genealogy characterizes Nietzsche once again as a skeptic insofar as it
undermines the truth-claims ofthe theories. Nietzsche's critique of the epistemic
claims of the philosophers consists to a large extent in his showing the psychol-
ogical and physiological demands from which the epistemic claims descend. He
replaces "the Kantian question, 'How are synthetic judgments a priori possi-
ble?' by another question, 'Why is belief in such judgments necessary?"' (BGE
11). He tries to comprehend why "creatures like ourselves" need to believe in
the truth of such judgments (ibid.), that is, what type of life we represent. A
genealogical analysis always fights the interpretations which pretend to be the
truth and it shows that they are merely perspectival interpretations. It fights their
claims to being self-evidently true, beyond discussion, necessary, and eternal.
It exposes them as descended from a certain type of life, as mere possibilities
next to which other interpretations are possible. The history of a phenomenon
is the history of overpowering interpretations. There is not one "true" meaning.
There is not even one phenomenon: the phenomenon to be interpreted is itself
already an interpretation. What exists is merely a series of interpretations of
which the presently prevailing one is just one possibility: "facts is precisely
what there is not, only interpretations" (WP 481; KSA 12, 315).
6. The true world-we have abolished. What world has remained~ The apparent one perhaps? But
no! With the true world we have also abolished the apparent one. (Noon; moment of the briefest
shadow; end of the longest error; high point of humanity; INCIPIT ZARATHUSTRA.) (Tl, 486)
WEAK SKEPTICISM
Philosophy reduced to 'theory of knowledge,' in fact no more than a timid epochism and doctrine
of abstinence- a philosophy that never gets beyond the threshold and takes pains to deny itself the
right to enter- that is philosophy in its last throes, an end, an agony, something inspiring pity.
(BGE 204)
I am the conscientious in spirit,' replied the man; 'and in matters of the spirit there may well be
none stricter, narrower, and harder than I( ... )
'Rather know nothing than half-know much! ( ... )A hand's breadth of ground- on that one can
stand. In the conscience of science there is nothing great and nothing small.'
'Then perhaps you are the man who knows the leech?' Zarathustra asked. ( ... )
'0 Zarathustra,' replied the man who had been stepped on, 'that would be an immensity; how
could I presume so much! That of which I am the master and expert is the brain of the leech: that
is my world. ( ... )Here is my realm. For its sake I have thrown away everything else; for its sake
everything else has become indifferent to me; and close to my knowledge lies black my ignorance.
( ... )
'Where my honesty ceases, I am blind and I also want to be blind.' (Z IV, Leech)
It is this attitude which Nietzsche calls skepticism, even if it would call itself
'"objectivity,' 'being scientific,' 'l'art pour l'art,' 'pure knowledge, free of
will'" (BGE 208). This may sound odd unless we keep in mind the fact that
Nietzsche does not point to one specific philosophical position but to an attitude
that can be recognized in several positions. Whether it is Descartes' feeling of
being forced by the evidence of the cogito, Kant's or Schopenhauer' s disinter-
ested knowledge, or the positivism of Nietzsche's contemporaries, the attitude
of abstention from one's own personality is similar in every case. This attitude
limits its own epistemic claims to what can be established by observation. And
Nietzsche suggests that this attitude is a symptom of an illness which he
diagnoses as "nervous exhaustion and sickliness" or "paralysis of the will"
(BGE 208). What kind of an illness is this, and what is its cause?
A reference to ancient skepticism might be helpful here. Anciently, skepti-
cism was primarily an ethical doctrine, aiming at inner peace or tranquillity of
the mind. Skepticism was a means to liberation from unrest. Nietzsche compares
it with a poppy and he calls it a "soporific and sedative" (ibid.). The desire for
rest is always a symptom of a disease. It indicates someone's suffering from
something which causes unrest. It is not the unrest which is the disease, but this
particular reaction to it: the inability or unwillingness to sustain it.
68 PAUL J. M. VAN TONGEREN
A FUTURE SKEPTICISM
There is, however, also another type of skepticism which can be introduced by
a quote from The Antichrist:
One should not be deceived: great spirits are sceptics. Zarathustra is a sceptic. Strength,Jreedom
which of the strength and overstrength of the spirit, proves itself by skepticism. Men of conviction
are not worthy of the least consideration in fundamental questions of value and disvalue.
Convictions are prisons.( ... ) A spirit who wants great things, who also wants the means to them,
is necessarily a sceptic. (A, 54)
In sections 209-211 of Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche describes this other
form of skepticism. But it is not easy to understand what exactly it is. He calls
it "another and stronger type," a "more dangerous and harder new type," "the
skepticism of audacious manliness," "the German form of skepticism" (all209).
What does this all mean?
In these sections of Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche describes this form of
skepticism in two different ways with the help of antitheses. In section 209 there
is an antithesis within the skeptical attitude itself. And in sections 210 and 211
skepticism forms itself an antithesis to other characteristics of the new philoso-
pher.
This skepticism despises and nevertheless seizes; it undermines and takes possession; it does not
believe but does not lose itself in the process; it gives the spirit dangerous freedom, but it is severe
on the heart; (BGE 209)
addition to their being skeptical). They will be skeptics and critics, experiment-
ers, passionate seekers; they use evaluative criteria, they hold a rigorous
method, are courageous, are able to justify, etc.
These characteristics of the philosopher of the future show once more the
problem of the weak skeptics. Their skepticism prevented them from making
commitments. Because there is no truth and thus no true criteria, they cannot
judge. Because nothing is really worthwhile, they cannot engage with anything.
Because of the absence of truth, they cannot really seek for knowledge. How
could they be accountable if there is no basis for any justification? This
relativism which is unable to make any commitment must become hypocritical
and hide itself behind moral virtues ("tolerance") and behind scientific values
("objectivity") to protect itself against its own nihilism.
But this confirmation of the diagnosis of the weak skeptic is only a negative
result. We still do not know how Nietzsche's other skepticism is possible? How
can this other skeptic be anything else besides skeptical? How can she escape
from nihilism? How can she seek knowledge, knowing that there is no truth?
Let's summarize what we have discussed up to now. In terms of the Kantian
distinction, Nietzsche radicalizes the unknowability of the thing-in-itself- with
the help of a theory of the relation between life, language, and knowledge -
until the real reality disappears and the distinction between reality and appear-
ance is neutralized. In his genealogical analyses he criticizes the philosophers
because of their dogmatism which presents itself in two seemingly opposed
ways: in the claim for genuine knowledge of a real (really existing and
intelligible) reality, and in the positivistic concealment of a skeptical-relativistic
denial of the possibility of such knowledge. Nietzsche shows that such
prejudices or unconsciously determining forces exist behind each and every
epistemic claim, indicating that it is not reality which is represented but the
reflection of the knower. Skepticism, however, is also criticized because its
thesis - that reality is not to be known - is just a means to maintain the belief
in the existence of reality. Episternic claims and skepticism are both explained
from a sick and weak life which tries to protect itself by clinging to this real
reality.
Nietzsche's position from which he criticizes dogmatists and skeptics alike
is itself skeptical to some extent: he attempts to show the illegitimacy of their
open or concealed claims for knowledge. The radicalness of his critique,
however, sometimes makes him go beyond skepticism into a "metaphysics"
which denies any kind of "real" world. But even without discussing his
"metaphysics" of the will to power, we may assume that we are not to identify
Nietzsche with his critique of other positions. He distances himself explicitly
from the popular idea of nowadays that
"Philosophy itself is criticism and critical science - and nothing whatever besides." This
evaluation of philosophy may elicit applause from all the positivists of France and Germany (and
it might even have pleased the heart and taste of Kant [ ... J); our new philosophers will say
nevertheless: critics are instruments of the philosopher and for that very reason, being instruments,
a long way from being philosophers themselves." (BGE 210)
NIETZSCHE'S SYMPTOMATOLOGY OF SKEPTICISM 71
We should, however, also not forget that these "new philosophers" are not yet
present today. They are needed (BGE 211). One of the reasons for the typical
"postponing" characteristic of Nietzsche's descriptions of the new philosophers
might be that these philosophers are at the same time involved in two conflicting
activities. On the one hand they are beyond skepticism in their recognition that
there is not even a real world of which one could even want to obtain genuine
knowledge. And on the other hand they are engaged in a passionate experiment
and a creative evaluation as if they did not feel any urge for doubt or suspension
of judgement (epoche). The realization of this contradiction cannot but be
postponed to a future to which Nietzsche only gives us a prelude.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
NOTES
1 See Nietzsche's Beyond Good and Evil, Preface.
2 Cf. Matte Hossenfelder, "Skepsis," Handbuch Philosophischer Grundbegriffe, (Munich:
Hanser, 1974), Bd. III, 1359-1367, p. 1359.
3 Letter from November 1866, quoted from: C.P. Janz, Friedrich Nietzsche. Biographie. vol. I,
~Munich/Vienna: Hanser Verlag, 1978), p.l98.
Illustrative in this respect are the titles of some of the main writings of nineteenth century
thinkers who were read by Nietzsche. E.g., Schopenhauer, The World as Will and Representation
(Die Welt als Wille und Vorstellung). A. Sp:1r's most important book is Thinking and Reality
(Denken und Wirklichkeit) (1873). See also 0. Liebmann, On the Analysis of Reality (Zur Analysis
der Wirklichkeit) (1880) and Thoughts and Facts (Gedanken und Tatsachen) (1882).
5 SeeforexampleHuman,All-Too-Human,I,9-II, 16, 19.
6 And Nietzsche does not abandon this conception of truth as adequacy. See the excellent article
on Nietzsche's concept of truth by Rudiger Bittner: "Nietzsches Begriff der Wahrheit," Nietzsche-
Studien, 16 (1987): 70-90.
7 The problems indicated here are thoroughly elaborated in Peter Poellner, Nietzsche and
Metaphysics, (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1995).
ROBIN SMALL
WE SENSUALISTS
"Today all of us are sensualists," Nietzsche writes in Book Five of The Gay
Science.' This striking assertion provides a signal for a set of problems
concerning knowledge or, more particularly, the relation between knowledge
and life. Nietzsche had been concerned with these questions for a long time, but
only after Thus Spake Zarathustra did he define them in the ways that provide
the theme of this discussion. As his thinking found its own path more and more,
Nietzsche moved decisively away from the pessimism and romanticism which
had earlier influenced him, and gained a new appreciation of the philosophers
of the French Enlightenment, even describing their sensualism and hedonism as
the "best inheritance" available to his own century. 2 Hence, for example, his
suggestion that the credit for Stendhal, in his opinion the greatest French writer
of the nineteenth century, must go to "the best, most rigorous philosophical
school in Europe, that of Condillac and Destutt de Tracy." 3 The term "sensual-
ist," as used here, refers in the first instance to these thinkers who, proceeding
from the empiricism of Locke, attempted to derive all ideas from elementary
sensations. (Hence the alternative expression, "sensationalism.") It does not
imply a preoccupation with sensual pleasure, although the English word may be
used most often in that sense. 4 On the other hand, it can hardly be denied that
any moral philosophy which finds its basic evidence in sensation will be
naturally inclined towards hedonism, or at least utilitarianism. Less evident, but
equally seen in these French writers, is the affinity between sensualism and a
materialist interpretation of human nature.
Nietzsche is aware of these points, but his own concern with sensualism is
prompted by its relevance to the problem of knowledge: he considers it as a
respect for the worth of the evidence of the senses. Quite apart from his
announcement that "we" are all sensualists, it might be assumed that Nietzsche
is clearly a supporter of this view. Even at an earlier stage, he described his
thinking as an "inverted Platonism." 5 For it not only refuses to devalue
appearance in favour of some reality which is accessible to thought alone, but
asserts that the further we depart from "being," the more we encounter what is
beautiful and valuable. Is this what his endorsement of sensualism in the
passage just cited means? The main concern of the section is to draw a contrast
between certain "new" philosophers of today - the "fearless ones" of Book
Five's title- and the thinkers of the past, in terms of their relation to the senses.
73
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II. 73-89.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
74 ROBIN SMALL
A "scientific" interpretation of the world, as you understand it, might even be one of the most
stupid, that is, poorest in meaning (sinn-iirmsten ), of all possible interpretations of the world. This
thought is intended for the ears and consciences of our mechanists who nowadays like to pass as
philosophers and insist that mechanics is a doctrine of the first and last laws on which all existence
must be based as on a ground floor. But an essentially mechanistic world would be an essentially
meaningless (sinnlose) world. Assuming that one estimated the value of a piece of music according
WE SENSUALISTS 75
to how much of it could be counted, calculated and expressed in formulas: how absurd would such
a "scientific" estimation of music be! What would one have comprehended, understood, known
of it? Nothing, really nothing of what is "music" in it! 6
element of teleology within their systems, in the nous of Anaxagoras and the
"love" and "hate" of Empedocles. Democritus alone is fully consistent in that
he admits only concepts that refer to what is visible and tangible. These ideas
were revived by modern atomism, to such an extent that Nietzsche could
describe Democritus as "the only philosopher that is still alive." 10
The other main source for Nietzsche's preoccupation with materialism is F.A.
Lange's History of Materialism, which he read shortly after its first publication
in 1866 and at many later times. The importance of this work for Nietzsche has
been described at length by several commentators. 11 A sympathetic critic, Lange
gives full credit to the contributions of the materialist standpoint in both
philosophy and science, while in the end rejecting it in favour of a Kantian
idealism. According to Lange, the great appeal of materialism lies in its use of
the vocabulary of the senses:
Materialism trusts the senses. Even its metaphysics is formed by analogy with the world of
experience. Its atoms are small corpuscles. Certainly one cannot represent them as small as they
are, because that goes beyond human perception, but one can represent them by analogy, as if one
were seeing and feeling them. 12
It has eyes and fingers in its favour, it has visual evidence and palpableness in its favour; this
strikes an age with fundamentally plebeian tastes as fascinating, persuasive and convincing- after
all, it follows instinctively the canon of truth of eternally popular sensualism. What is clear. what
can be "explained"? Only what can be seen and felt - every problem has to be pursued to that
point. 14
In the next section of Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche continues to discuss
sensualism, but in a completely different way: this time in refutation of an
argument which uses the evidence of the senses to prove the inadequacy of
philosophical materialism. Nietzsche's target here, although unnamed, is clearly
Lange; for the position addressed is one adopted by Lange in the course of his
critique of materialism. We may summarise his main line of thought, rather
briefly, along the following lines. Lange gives full credit to the materialist
contribution: the many successes of modem science arise from a research
program whose aims and methods are inspired by the Democritean doctrine that
"nothing exists but atoms and empty space: everything else is mere opinion."
Yet this reductionist orientation reveals both the strength and the weakness of
atomism. For despite all its advances, natural science has never explained the
occurrence of even the simplest sensation. There seems to be an unbridgeable
gap between material motion and consciousness, and this failure to account for
an entire domain of reality makes philosophical materialism an untenable
doctrine.
Even if this problem were somehow solved, Lange argues, there would be
another fatal objection to materialism. When natural science turns its attention
to the human subject and its capacity for gaining knowledge, a surprising
outcome is seen. The science of physiology points to idealism by demonstrating
that the senses cannot be regarded as providing an accurate picture of the real
character of the world. Lange endorses Helmholtz's theory that all perception
involves a hidden process of inference from what is given to the senses. 15
Hence, scientific theory confirms the Kantian claim that the world as we
perceive and understand it is a product of our own organisation. Even our own
bodies and their organs, Lange concludes, are pictures of something that
transcends our knowledge and must remain unknown to us.
Just as it was once amazingly difficult for people to think of this fixed earth on which we stand,
the prototype of rest and stability, as moving, so it will be even harder for them to recognise their
own body, the prototype of all reality for them, as a mere scheme of representation, a product of
our optical apparatus, which must be distinguished from the object that occasions it as much as
any other representational picture. 16
Thus, the bodily senses too are only representations, like the objects of the
outside world: "The eye, with which we believe we see, is only a product of our
ideas." 17
It is this line of thought that inspires the admiration expressed in Beyond
Good and Evil for those contemporary thinkers who are bold enough to deny the
reality of the whole world of appearance. Nietzsche says they "rank the
credibility of their own bodies about as low as the credibility of the visual
evidence that 'the earth stands still,' and thus, apparently in good humour, let
their securest possession go (for in what does one at present believe more firmly
than in one's body?)" 18 But this praise is soon followed by a firm rebuttal of any
scepticism concerning the body:
78 ROBIN SMALL
To study physiology with a clear conscience, one must insist that the sense organs are not
appearances in the sense of idealistic philosophy; as such they could not be causes' Sensualism,
therefore, at least as a regulative hypothesis, not to say as a heuristic principle. 19
Heraclitus too did the senses an injustice. They lie neither in the way the Eleatics believed, nor as
he believed- they do not lie at all. What we make of their testimony, that alone introduces lies;
for example, the lie of unity, the lie of thinghood, of substance, of permanence. "Reason'' is the
cause of our falsification of the testimony of the senses. 22
Thus, rather unexpectedly, Nietzsche seems to be saying that most people are
sensualists in theory but not in practice. For while they trust the evidence of the
senses, they are not committed to developing this approach to knowledge as far
as it can go. In that case, they are unlikely to encounter the problem to be
addressed in the next part of our discussion. The distinction between primary
and secondary properties, already present in early Greek thought, has been a
prominent theme in modem philosophy from Locke onwards. Empirical
knowledge encourages us to make this distinction, in order to establish a single
scheme of categories which will cover the greatest possible range of phenom-
WE SEJ\SUALISTS 79
ena. If this does not lead to the general scepticism inferred by Lange, it does
pose the problem of relating a scientific description of reality to the evidence of
the senses. Nietzsche's reflections on this issue are scattered and incomplete, but
they also bear on some important themes in his thought.
Fundamentally what was possible once could only be possible a second time if the Pythagoreans
were right in believing that with the same com.tellation of the heavenly bodies the same events had
to be repeated on earth down to each small detail: so that whenever the stars have a certain relation
to each other a Stoic will join with an Epicurean and murder Caesar, and ever again with a
different configuration Columbus will discover America. 25
It is clear enough that Nietzsche does not accept the picture he attributes to
the Pythagoreans. He does not seem Ito doubt that the same constellation of the
heavenly bodies might occur again, although this assumption had been
questioned by some critics of astrology, such as the fourteenth-century natural
philosopher Nicole Oresme?6 Rather, what Nietzsche doubts is whether such an
event would lead to a return of the corresponding events of human history. But
this raises the same issue that faces his own later doctrine. Even the terminology
is very similar: the question is whether the same "constellation" of points of
force would condition a return of the same things and their properties "down to
80 ROBIN SMALL
the smallest detail." 27 Again, it is the relation between these two sets of concepts
that constitutes the problem. How does the language of scientific knowledge
translate into a discourse which we can recognise as an expression of our own
experience?
On looking more closely at Nietzsche's own vocabulary, we see that he
speaks of properties (Eigenschaften) and of qualities (Qualitiiten) in quite
different ways. In discussing the world as a collection of elements, Nietzsche
asserts that their properties are to be identified with their relations to other
things. The sum of a thing's relation to other things he calls its "state" (Lage).
"The state in which people find themselves, in relation to nature and other
people, makes their properties- it is the same as with atoms." 28 The world as
a whole has a "general state" (Gesammtlage) which is just the totality of the
relations between its elements. This idea figures prominently in some discus-
sions of eternal recurrence. When Nietzsche speaks of the world as consisting
of "centers of force" rather than the solid atoms of mechanistic materialism, he
uses the word "constellation" - as in the earlier reference to the stars and planets
-to designate the overall configuration of these centers at any given time.
Properties are closely linked with the project of a systematic formulation of
knowledge and, on that basis, a scientific understanding of the world. Quantity
is prominent in this conception, because measurement and calculation are
powerful procedures for organising knowledge. Quality, on the other hand,
seems to be an idea not driven by any theoretical need, but expressing directly
what we experience through our various senses. Nietzsche sometimes charac-
terises qualities as the effects that things have on us: a familiar claim made by
empiricist theories of knowledge. This means that the same things may have
different qualities for different perceivers, according to their constitutions. In
addition, some beings are aware of aspects of the world that others fail to
perceive: for instance, those animals that hear sounds or see colours outside the
human range of experience. Nietzsche concludes that our human experience of
the world is an idiosyncratic perspective which should not be generalised: "It is
obvious that every creature different from us senses different qualities and
consequently lives in a different world from that in which we live." 29
How can these different worlds be reconciled with the single world of
objective knowledge? This is just the task of finding some relation between
quality and quantity. One answer is already found in Nietzsche's early lectures
on pre-Platonic philosophy, where it is attributed to Democritus: "All qualities
are conventions, things vary only quantitatively. Thus all qualities are to be
traced back to variations in quantity." 30 The idea here is that quality arises from
quantity by way of difference. In a later notebook, Nietzsche writes:
Our "knowing" limits itself to establishing quantities; but we cannot help sensing these differences
in quantity as qualities. Quality is a perspectival truth for us; not an "in-itself." Our senses have
a definite quantum as a mean within which they function; i.e., we sense bigness and smallness in
relation to the conditions of our existence. If we sharpened or blunted our senses tenfold, we
should perish; i.e., with regard to making possible our existence we sense even relations between
magnitudes as qualities. 31
WE SENSUALISTS 81
All this is still a long way from "thoughts" and "hours," no doubt, but it
suggests that a dismissal of the problem posed by the differences between
Nietzsche's vocabularies may be premature. Despite their dissimilarity, the life-
world and that of objective knowledge have a common ground. Nietzsche
writes: "Belief in the 'senses' is the basis of all science, as of alllife." 38 Should
we take the word "belief' at face value here? He has already insisted that
sensualism need not be a dogmatic claim, amounting to one of those convictions
which he says "are more dangerous enemies oftruth than lies."39 Rather, it may
serve as a regulative hypothesis or a heuristic principle, both in science and in
life. In that case, the relation between scientific concepts and the ideas of sense
experience is still an open question, for which a closer analysis of the nature of
sensation is an appropriate procedure.
As well as bodily sensations, there are what Nietzsche refers to in Human, All-
too-Human as "the moral sensations." The term is borrowed from his friend Paul
Ree, whose book On the Origin of the Moral Sensations had offered a specula-
tive account of feelings such as sympathy, gratitude, justice and self-regard,
along the lines suggested by Darwin's theory of evolution by means of natural
selection. 40 In his later writings, Nietzsche suggests that all sensations are
valuations: he notes that "all our value sensations (i.e., simply our sensations)
adhere precisely to qualities."41 Our senses have evolved in accordance with our
conditions of life, and so the qualities we attribute to things are determined by
what has been beneficial or harmful in the past. 42 Every sensation thus involves
assumptions about benefit or harm; and this is especially evident with pleasure
and pain.
I shall approach Nietzsche's ideas on the subject of pleasure and pain by way
of a contemporary writer whose "scientific theory of sensibility" links pleasure
and pain with sensation in general. Leon Dumont (1837-77) was a French author
on philosophical psychology and aesthetics. Dumont was not an academic
philosopher but the sort of marginal figure that appealed to Nietzsche. 43 His
principal work, published in 1875, is an attempt to formulate a scientific theory
of pleasure and pain. 44 As Dumont observes, this has never been done before;
and he expresses the hope that his theory will make possible a science of
aesthetics, as part of a more general science of feeling. 45 The framework for his
approach is a scientific reductionism which, it is argued, modem psychology has
substantiated by explaining all facts of consciousness as combinations of
elementary sensations, eliminating both a separate self and any notion of free
will.
With this in mind, one may at first suppose that pleasure and pain are simply
elementary sensations, which are irreducible and hence indefinable. The
association of these sensations with others will vary greatly, since we know that
the same perception may give pleasure on one occasion and displeasure on
another. In that case, Dumont points out, there could hardly be general laws, and
a science of pleasure (and hence of aesthetics) would be impossible. His own
84 ROBIN SMALL
opinion is that, while pleasure and pain arise from sensations, they are not
themselves sensations. Rather, they correspond to certain rebtions between
successive mental states: "What we have said is sufficient to show that pleasure
and pain are not real phenomena, like sensations, ideas, perceptions, concepts;
that they are, rather, strictly speaking, the transition from one phenomenon to
another, that they correspond to a change and not to a state."46
This theory explains why we cannot identify pleasure and pain with qualities
of the object, as we do with sensations: such feelings express what is happening
within the subject itself, and are related to objects only indirectly. Again, since
pleasure and pain are not particular states, they have no place in the causally
connected sequence of our experiences and actions. They accompany these
phenomena, but are not their antecedent conditions: in other words, pleasure and
pain do not act as motives for the will. But, one may object, is not there such a
thing as a love of pleasure, which may readily be a cause of action? Dumont
agrees, but says that it is found only in higher animals, who are capable of
memory and foresight in judging the consequences of their actions. 47 As a
motive, then, this is not reducible to a mode of feeling, taken by itself.
Dumont has a further theory about the sorts of change involved in feelings of
pleasure and pain: that they are symptoms of the union and dispersal of forces.
Pleasure arises when the sum of force that constitutes the self undergoes an
increase (provided this is not sufficient to disrupt its organisation) and pain
when a corresponding decrease in force occurs. 48 So although pleasure and pain
have a relative character - they do not arise from a single sensation or set of
sensations, and are not caused by a single kind of external object - they
nevertheless occur according to a general principle, which in turn points to a
more detailed theory. Later, Dumont goes on to discuss kinds of pleasure and
pain which differ from one another not just because they are located in different
locations or activities but, more significantly, because force increases or
decreases in them in different ways. For example, the sum of force may
decrease owing to an increased output (as in fatigue and related states) or to a
decreased input (as in boredom, doubt, impatience, grief, pity and fear, or more
generally, the frustration of our desires). The rest of his discussion outlines a
classification of pains and pleasures which will provide the plan for a general
science of feeling.
Sensations themselves, in so far as we are conscious of them, are identical
with brain states: they are the "subjective side" of these observable phenomena.
Similarly, pleasure and pain are the subjective side of the causal relations
between successive states. Dumont considers that pleasure and pain - and
feeling in general - extend beyond consciousness to processes located within the
human organism but outside the system that constitutes the self. Local anaesthe-
sia, he thinks, confirms this idea: sensations go on occurring in the organs
concerned, but are not communicated to the brain. 49 Further, if feeling is just
one aspect of motion, it may even occur in the inorganic world, despite the
absence of organisation there; for the nerve system does not create sensations,
but only carries and combines them. It may be, Dumont speculates, that pleasure
and pain are found throughout nature, wherever force is gathered or dispersed. 5°
WE SENSUALISTS 85
The metaphysical character of his theory is evident here: its ultimate aim is to
provide knowledge of the absolute being which, he believes, underlies and
expresses itself in all phenomena.
Nietzsche owned a copy of Dumont's treatise, which had been translated into
German and published in 1876 as Vergniigen und Schmerz. That he was reading
Dumont in early 1883 is clear from a notebook which contains several quota-
tions from that work. 5 1 Only later does Nietzsche go into the subject of pleasure
and pain on his own account, and then he endorses several of Dumont's leading
propositions. He agrees that pleasure and pain are not primary facts of con-
sciousness but only epiphenomena. 52 Hence the absurdity of those philosophies,
such as hedonism and utilitarianism, which take pleasure and pain as their
standard for evaluating the world. He repeats Dumont's claim that these feelings
are not part of the causal process: "Upon reflection, however, we should
concede that everything would have taken the same course, according to exactly
the same sequence of causes and effects, if these states 'pleasure and displeas-
ure' had been absent, and that one is simply deceiving oneself if one thinks they
cause anything at all." 53 And because they are only epiphenomena, Nietzsche
concludes that pleasure and pain are not motives for action: "- there is no
striving for pleasure: but pleasure occurs when what is being striven for is
attained: pleasure is an accompaniment, pleasure is not a motive ... " 54
One aspect of Dumont's theory is of particular importance for Nietzsche: his
identification of pleasure with an increase of force, which is readily assimilable
to Nietzsche's own theory of the will to power. Hence he can refer to '"that
general feelin~ of overabundant, overflowing power that constitutes the essence
of pleasure." This description is part of a much broader picture. Nietzsche
postulates an economy of force which entails a cyclical process of accumulation
and release of force (or rather energy, in modem terms) in all living things, and
includes a conception of power as a relation of control and submission between
such forces. In a speculative mode, he suggests that the instinct which drives the
development of organic beings is a drive to discharge their strength, rather than
the imperative of self-preservation which he supposes to be the leading principle
of a Darwinian approach in biology. 56 Even more speculatively, he sometimes
hints at a cosmic cycle with a similar pattern, resembling that of pre-Socratic
thinkers like Heraclitus. But these are wider areas, which will not be entered
here.
Despite these overlaps, Nietzsche advances other ideas which make his
account of pleasure and pain quite distinct from Dumont's. One is an emphasis
on the role of interpretation, especiallly in the case of pain. In The Gay Science,
Nietzsche had written: "Second, when a strong stimulus is experienced as
pleasure or displeasure, this depends on the interpretation of the intellect which,
to be sure, generally does this work without rising to our consciousness: one and
the same stimulus can be experienced as pleasure or displeasure." 57 The
interpretation Nietzsche has in mind is a judgment about the benefit or harm
expected to follow from the phenomenon: a more or less complex calculation
which is condensed into an immediate reaction, presumably as a result of the
past history of the individual or species. In contrast, Dumont explains the
86 ROBIN SMALL
variability of pleasure and pain in terms of the varying context within which the
stimulus occurs, and excludes a process of thinking, even unconscious, from his
account. 5 8
Further, Nietzsche's ideas often resemble a theory of pleasure and pain which
Dumont has considered and rejected. The "Epicurean" view, as he labels it, is
that pain arises from obstacles to the satisfaction of our wishes, and that
pleasure is the overcoming of such obstacles. Hence, pleasure is always bound
up with pain. Pessimistic thinkers such as Schopenhauer and Hartmann, arguing
that pain must always outweigh pleasure, recommend a policy of renunciation
as the only solution for the predicament. The conclusion usually drawn from the
"Epicurean" theory, according to Dumont, is that avoiding pain is more
important than achieving pleasure. However, he notes, Jerome Cardan suggested
that we must seek out what causes pain, in order to gain greater pleasure by
overcoming it. It is significant that this is a reference noted down by Nietzsche
for his own use. 59 While Dumont may have reported Cardan's idea only as a
curiosity, or as a reductio ad absurdum of the theory, Nietzsche takes it
seriously. He is prepared not only to admit the interdependence of pleasure and
pain, but to go further, questioning whether they are really distinct, let alone
opposites. Pleasure may be a series of small pains, he suggests, a "game of
.
resistance an d victory.
. ,60
NOTES
GS 372. Apart from published works of Nietzsche, including the notes included in The Will to
Power, all remaining translations are my own, unless otherwise stated.
2 Nietzsche. Kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke [hereafter: KGW], ed. G. Colli and M. Montinari
~Berlin-New York: Walter de Gruyter, 1973-), VII/2. 234.
· KGW VIII/3, 455.
4 Not trusting his readers on this point, Kaufmann translates Sensualisten as "believers in the
senses," a rather misleading phrase in view of the qualification Nietzsche goes on to make in this
passage.
KGW III/3, 207.
6 GS 373.
7 KGW VII/2, 264.
8 BGE, 12. One may here recall the admiring words of Galileo when referring to the heliocentric
theories of Aristarchus and Copernicus: "Nor can I ever sufficiently admire the outstanding
acumen of those who have taken hold of this opinion and accepted it as true; they have through
sheer force of intellect done such violence to their senses as to prefer what reason told them over
that which sensible experience plainly showed them to the contrary." Dialogues Concerning the
Two Chief World Systems, trans. Stillman Drake, 2nd ed. (Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press, 1967), 328.
9 Daybreak, 168. See also KGW VII/3, 278 (WP 443).
10 Nietzsche, Historische-Kritische Gesamtausgabe: Werke, Band 4, ed. H.J. Mette and K.
Schlechta (Miinchen: C.H. Beck'sche Verlagsbuchhandlung, 1937), 84.
11 See G.J. Stack, "Nietzsche and Lange," The Modern Schoolman 57 (1980), 137-49, Ji:irg
Salaquarda, "Nietzsche und Lange," Nietzsche-Studien 7 (1978), 236-53 and GJ. Stack, Lange and
Nietzsche (Berlin-New York: de Gruyter, 1983).
12 F.A. Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart
(lserlohn: Verlag von J. Baedecker, 1866), 345.
13 See e.g. Geschichte des Materialismus, 405, for this phrase which is often used by Nietzsche:
BGE, 21; also KGW VII/3, 224 and 288 (WP 618). KGW VII/3, 439 and KGW VIII/1, 90 and 110
(WP 622).
14 BGE, 14.
15 Geschichte des Materialismus, 500.
16 Ibid., 485.
88 ROBIN SMALL
17 !hid., 496.
18 BGE, 10.
19 BGE, 15. See also KGW VIlli, 88 and 230.
20 Twilight of the Idols, '"Reason' in Philosophy," sect. 3. Similarly, Zarathustra says, "You
should think your own senses through to the end." Thus Spake Zarathustra, "Upon the Blessed
Isles." Cf. KGW VII/2, 124 (WP I 046).
21 GS, 112.
22 Twilight of the Idols, "''Reason' in Philosophy," sect. 2.
23 KGW V/2, 422.
24 Heidegger, Nietzsche (Pfullingen: Neske, 1961), Band 1, 375.
25 On the Uses and Disadvantages of HistOI)' for Life, 2 (in the translation of Peter Preuss). A
somewhat similar passage occurs in the book which was the occasion of Nietzsche's first
"untimelv meditation," David Friedrich Strauss's Der alte und der neue Glauhe. Strauss writes:
"When the great year of the world has thus elapsed, the formation of a new world begins, in which
- according to the Stoic fancy- the earlier one repeats itself precisely, down to particular events
and persons (Socrates and Xanthippe)." Der alte und der neue Glaube (Leipzig: Verlag von S.
Hirzel, 1872), 155.
26 See Robin Small, "Incommensurability and Recurrence: from Oresme to Simmel," Journal of
Verlag), 334.
31 KGW VIII/I, 201 (WP 563).
32 KGW VIII/1, 244 (WP 565).
33 Critique of Pure Reason, A162 = B203 and Al68 = B210.
34 The proposition that intensive magnitudes cannot be added together has been put to ingenious
use by C.S. Lewis. He begins by observing that if two people are each suffering a toothache of
intensity x, it does not follow that anyone is suffering a toothache of intensity 2x. He goes on:
"There is no such thing as a sum of suffering, for no one suffers it. When we have reached the
· maximum that a single person can suffer, we have, no doubt, reached something very horrible, but
we have reached all the suffering there can ever be in the universe. The addition of a million
fellow-sufferers adds no more pain." The Problem of Pain (London: Geoffrey Bles, 1940), 103-04.
A reply is that sensations have not only intensive but also extensive magnitude, in the multiplicity
of subjects who experience them and, within a single person, in their bodily extent and temporal
duration. Accordingly, we can say that there is more or less pain in so far as any of these
magnitudes increases or decreases. Someone who overlooks that consideration might attempt to
prove that eternal punishment is no more severe than the most brief or even momentary
punishment, since the intensities of the successive states of pain cannot be added together. Anyone
arguing in that way, though, would be forced to concede that eternal bliss is no more rewarding
than a very fleeting pleasure.
35 Critique of Pure Reason, B207.
36 The pioneers in this area were E.H. Weber and G.T. Fechner, who developed a model for
estimating the intensities of sensations, and on that basis postulated a formula in which the
magnitudes of sensation and stimulus are related in a logarithmic function.
37 He goes on: "It is the same with morality. Here accompanying feelings of beneficence or utility
arise in someone who perceives a human characteristic in a certain quantum; doubled or tripled,
he is afraid of it..." KGW VII/2, 238.
38 KGW VII/2, 234; reading die 'Sinne' for das 'Sein,' as indicated by KGW VII/4/2, 654.
39 Human, All-too-Human, i 483.
40 Paul Ree, Der Ursprung der moralischen Empfindungen (Chemnitz: Verlag von Ernst
Schmeitzner, 1877).
41 KGW VIII/I, 244 (WP 565).
42 KGW Vll/2, 183.
43 For an outline of Dumont's life and work, see Alexander Buechner, Un philosophe amateur.
Essai biographique sur Leon Dumont ( 1837-1877) avec des extra its de sa correspondance (Paris:
Librairie Felix Alcan, 1884).
WE SENSUALISTS 89
44 Leon Dumont, Vergniigen und Schmerz. Zur Lehre den Gefiihlen (Leipzig: F.A. Brockhaus,
1876). This volume is a translation of Theorie scientifique de Ia sensibilite. Le plaisir et la peine
~Paris: Librairie Germer Bailliere, 1875).
5 The term "science" may suggest consistency with a reductionist and materialist program in
psychology, but does not imply a reliance on empirical evidence; indeed, Dumont argues that a
science of pleasure and pain is like dynamics or mathematics, in being concerned not with facts,
but with more general and abstract objects. Vergniigen und Schmerz, 100.
46 Vergniigen und Schmerz, 98.
47 Ibid., 307.
48 Ibid., 82.
49 Ibid., 129.
50 Ibid., 136. An equally surprising result of his theory emerges when the principle of the
conservation of energy is taken into account. This law implies that any increase of energy in one
location must correspond to a decrease of energy elsewhere. According to Dumont's theory, these
processes are identical with pleasure and pain respectively. Hence, the amount of pleasure in the
world must always be exactly equal to the amount of pain. This invalidates any claim that
existence as a whole contains more pain than pleasure, or vice versa - in other words, it disposes
of both pessimism and optimism, so understood. It has an even more startling implication: that for
every subject experiencing pleasure, another must experience pain. Dumont acknowledges this
only by referring to the successes of the human race at the expense of other species in the struggle
for existence. He forbears to mention that a similar conclusion must also apply to individuals.
Accordingly, he does not address the novel ethical problems that would arise from an assumption
that one person's pleasure necessitates another's pain.
51 KGW VIlfl, 308 and 322.
52 BGE 225. See also KGW VIII/I, 338; VIII/2, 272 and 275; VIII/3, 127 and 152 (WP 579, 701,
°
6 KGW VIII/3, 150 (WP 699).
61 Twilight of the Idols, "Maxims and Arrows," sect. 12. It is only fair to point out that this is not
how Englishmen see themselves. As A.P. Herbert puts it, "The Englishman never enjoys himself
except for a noble purpose." Uncommon Law (London: Eyre Methuen, 1977), 198.
62 KGW VIII/3, 70 (WP 695).
63 KGW VIII/2, 33 (WP 516).
64 KGW VIII/I, 200 (WP 1045).
ROBERT NOLA
NIETZSCHE'S NATURALISM
Perspectivism is only a complex form of specificity. My idea is that every specific body strives
to become master over all space and to extend its force ( - its will to power:) and to thrust back
all that resists its extension. But it continually encounters similar efforts on the part of other bodies
and ends by coming to an arrangement ("union") with those of them that are sufficiently related
to it: they then conspire together for power. And the process goes on - (WP 636)
(5) Nietzsche also adopts a Humean position in claiming that there are no
substances, and no causal or law-like natural necessity, in the world. However
there are regularities that allow calculation of how one centre of force-power
acts on another (see WP 551-2 and 634 ).
91
B. Babich (ed.). Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 91-100.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
92 ROBERT NOLA
(1) to (5) comprise the core of Nietzschean naturalism: "This world is the will
to power- and nothing else besides! And you yourselves are also this will to
power- and nothing besides!" (WP 1067). Nietzsche's force-power naturalism
encompasses not only the non-human world but also the individual and social
realm of humans with their psychological drives. As a program Nietzsche's
naturalism has much in common with current scientific naturalism; but with its
single ontological category of force-power it is a quite distinct rival.
Like all naturalisms, Nietzsche's extreme version needs to account for those
things not in its ontology but which have been commonly thought to exist, or
have been postulated in the sciences. How this is done is a large interpretive
project which cannot be undertaken here. Instead in what follows some brief
comments will be made about Nietzsche's naturalism concerning three matters:
ordinary objects; its rivalry with scientific naturalism; and its account of belief
and knowledge.
(1) All objects are substances, or are bits of substantive matter, with identity
conditions.
(2) Anything which is a nexus of force-power (NFP) has no identity condi-
tions.
(3) Therefore a NFP cannot be a substance, or substantive matter.
(4) The only thing which exists is the total set of NFPs.
(5) Therefore, there are no substances or bits of substantive matter, with
identity conditions.
(6) Therefore there are no objects (they are fictitious projections or con-
structions we impose).
If we accept (4) which expresses Nietzsche's naturalism, the only premises
left to examine in this valid argument are (1) and (2).
Nietzsche's argument for the rejection of substantial objects is quite unlike
the epistemological arguments that can be found in Berkeley or Hume; instead
his argument turns on metaphysical matters to do with identity conditions, as
indicated in (2). Since Nietzsche's world is in such a state of flux, given the
changing kaleidoscope of the NFPs, nothing has any continuing identity:
"Continual transition forbids us to speak of 'individuals' etc: the number of
beings is itself in flux" (WP 520). But is this correct? We humans are said to
change, albeit over a period of about seven years, all the cells in our body, yet
we preserve our bodily continuity. Each new part has a historical connection
with some other earlier part, and performs a functional role similar to the part
it replaces. It is the host of such historical and functional continuities that give
us our bodily identity despite total change in its parts. Much the same could be
said of Nietzschean NFPs; though the magnitude, direction, and even center of
action of force-power might change, it does not follow that there is no continu-
ing identity for any such NFP. There may be sufficient historical continuity
within one NFP to establish identity over time.
Historical continuity conditions may suffice to establish identity where much
stronger conditions would fail to establish any. Thus consider what may be
called mereological essentialism: 3 for strong [weak] mereological essentialism,
a whole has identity just when all [at least one of] its parts (such as its sub-
stance) must have identity and be co-present throughout the life of the whole.
Clearly strong mereological essentialism is too strong since it requires a whole
to change none of its parts; in contrast the weak version only requires that at
least one thing remain the same for the lifetime of the whole. But even the weak
version is too strong a requirement for bodily identity if we allegedly change all
our cell-parts within a seven year period. And it is too strong a requirement for
the identity of NFPs if at least one direction, or magnitude or center of some
NFP must remain the same. It would appear that to support premise (2),
Nietzsche, the "Nay" -sayer to all essentialism, says "Yea" to essentialist identity
conditions. It is some such view that underlies that claim that "continual
transition forbids us to speak of 'individuals."'
What of premise (1 )? The philosophical doctrine of substances does much
work in different contexts. One such piece of work is to ensure that if anything
is a substance, then it must come equipped with identity conditions; there can
94 ROBERT NOLA
be no substance that lacks identity. But do we think that all our commonsense
objects are substances? Though not obviously part of our common sense
framework of objects, such as pebbles, the idea that objects are substances has
been a constantly accompanying philosophical doctrine that has many advocates
from Aristotle to Kant. Locke, Berkeley and Hume raised epistemological
worries about our knowledge of substances which Kant attempted to answer.
However Nietzsche's challenge does not proceed from their epistemological
stance. Rather he seems to accept the Kantian view that objects are substances
in accepting ( 1) - but then so much the worse for our talk of ordinary objects,
as the argument shows!
Though (1) seems plausible there are many reasons provided by twentieth-
century philosophy of language and metaphysics for rejecting it. The work of
Kripke and Putnam (for which there are some antecedents in Kant) shows that
even if we were to discover that objects were not substances but were NFPs, our
reference to them would remain invariant despite the falsification of a fairly
constantly accompanying philosophical theory of objects as substances. As an
example, we have rejected the Aristotelian view that air and fire are pure
substances yet we continue to talk of the very same stuff that Aristotle and other
Ancient Greeks breathed, or warmed their hands by. That there are pebbles is
an existence claim that remains unaltered, even if we were to discover that they
were not substances but some nexus of force-power.
If we reject (1) and (2), we can also reject (5), viz., Nietzsche's elirninativism
with respect to objects; this leaves open a more plausible reductionist view in
which ordinary objects are nothing but NFPs. Since the argument above is
intended to be a diagnostic reconstruction, it remains to show that (5) is a
pervasive feature of Nietzsche's philosophy. It appears in his early writings:
"Logic too depends on presuppositions with which nothing in the real world
corresponds, for example on the presupposition that there are identical things,
that the same thing is identical at different points in time; but this science came
into existence through the opposite belief (that such conditions do obtain in the
real world)" (HH 11). And it also appears in his late writings: 4
The falseness of a judgment is for us not necessarily an objection to a judgment; in this respect our
new language may sound strangest. The question is to what extent it is life-promoting. life-
preserving, species-preserving, perhaps even species-cultivating. And we are fundamentally
inclined to claim that the falsest judgements (which include the synthetic judgements a priori) are
the most indispensable for us; that without accepting the fictions of logic, without measuring
reality against the purely invented world of the unconditional and self-identical, without a constant
falsification of the world by means of numbers, man could not live - that renouncing false
judgments would mean renouncing life and a denial of life. To recognise untruth as a condition
of life - that certainly means resisting accustomed value feelings in a dangerous way; and a
philosophy that risks this would by that token alone place itself beyond good and evil. (BGE. 4)
Nietzsche used his theory of force-power, i.e., the will to power, as the basis of
an ambitious program which rivals explanations in sciences such as mechanics,
biology and psychology, as well as theories of morality and society. Sometimes
the rivalry is metaphysical as when Nietzsche contrasts the interpretations of
phenomena offered by sciences which suppose that there are laws of nature with
his own power hypothesis which eschews such laws. Nietzsche thinks, wrongly,
that all talk of"nature's conformity to laws" is an anthropomorphism based on
our own conformity to laws we have promulgated. There is a genetic fallacy
here; perhaps an anthropomorphic model might have suggested that nature is
also bound by laws; but whether or not there are laws of nature cannot be
established in this way. 5
Setting this aside, Nietzsche's contrast is between the belief that nature does
conform to laws, and interpretations of the same nature using the law-less will
to power: "somebody might come along who, with opposite intentions and
modes of interpretation, could read out of the same 'nature,' and with regard to
the same phenomena, rather the tyrannically inconsiderate and relentless
enforcement of claims of power -- an interpreter who would picture the
unexceptional and unconditional aspects of all 'will to power"' (BGE 22).
However Nietzsche recognises that even within his own theory, the actions of
power are not entirely law-less and by his own admission are calculable using
formulae expressing regularities(§ 1, thesis (5)). In adopting Hume's view that
there is no natural necessity (but not for Hume's reasons), Nietzsche thinks that
necessity is just one interpretation which we have imposed on the world. But he
also recognises that there is nothing privileged about his denial of necessity, this
being merely yet another interpretation: "Supposing that this also is only
interpretation- and you will be eager enough to make this objection?- well, so
much the better."
This provides no grounds for arguing that no adjudication between rival
interpretations is possible. Even though the debate between Humeans and anti-
Humeans over natural necessity has been long-lasting, there are no grounds for
assuming that no argument is better than any other in this area. But this is not
the only rivalry that Nietzsche envisages; there are also the rival interpretations
of the same nature and phenomena provided by sciences (which employ laws of
nature) and by his power theory (which supposes regularities but no natural
necessity). How do these fare?
Nietzsche claims in BGE that the explanations and/or interpretations provided
by the power hypothesis are superior to all other hypotheses. In discussing
exploitation within society Nietzsche harshly declares: '"Exploitation' does not
belong to a corrupt or imperfect and primitive society; it belongs to the essence
of what lives, as a basic organic function; it is a consequence of the will to
power ... If this should be an innovation as a theory - as reality it is the
primordial fact of all history" (BGE 259). In Nietzsche's view not only is it a
fact that exploitation is an organic function, but also the power hypothesis is
supported by all of history; moreover the power hypothesis explains this better
96 ROBERT NOLA
than any other hypothesis because it appeals to the very "essence of what lives
as a basic organic function." Explanations which allegedly go to the essence of
things are taken to be better explanations than those which do not.
The wide scope of the power hypothesis is best illustrated in the following
extended passage. Nietzsche begins by supposing that the only reality is our
inner drives and speculates whether a more general hypothesis about the will to
power would suffice for an understanding of even "the so-called mechanistic (or
'material') world":
In short, one has to risk the hypothesis whether will does not affect will wherever "effects" are
recognised- and whether all mechanical occurrences are not, in so far as a force is active in them,
will force. effects of will. Suppose, finally, we succeeded in explaining our entire instinctive life
as the development and ramification of one basic form of the will- namely, of the will to power,
as my proposition has it; suppose all organic functions could be traced back to this will to power
and one could also find in it the solution of the problem of procreation and nourishment- it is one
problem- then one would have gained the right to determine all efficient force univocally as- will
to power. The world viewed from inside, the world defined and determined according to its
"intelligible character"- it would be "will to power" and nothing else. (BGE 36)
force from within, and not only external to, organisms. To illustrate, it is alleged
that, say, muscle-builders can pass on larger muscles to their off-spring by
somehow passing on genes for large muscles. But this is precisely what is ruled
out by Darwinian theory. No matter how active they may be in replicating
themselves, genes do not exploit or use external circumstances. Rather it is
external circumstances, either acting through natural or sexual processes of
selection, which determine which genes in a gene pool manage to have their
frequency increased. 6
The above are brief comments on the lack of success of Nietzsche's natural-
ism compared with two rival areas of scientific naturalism. Though the
program's best known application concerns the genealogy of morals, we will
consider only its attempt to account naturalistically for one human cognitive
ability -belief.
Not only are our bodies and sense-organs the product of evolution, but also our
minds: "We have senses for only a selection of perceptions- those with which
we have to concern ourselves in order to preserve ourselves. Consciousness is
present only to the extent that consciousness is usefur' (WP 505). And: "All our
organs of knowledge and our senses are developed only with regard to condi-
tions of preservation and growth" (WP 507; cf. BGE 36 and WP 498). Thus
Nietzsche's naturalism explores the same issues as recent naturalistic ap-
proaches to the mind, cognition and belief, albeit within a different explanatory
framework.
Nietzsche also maintains that our (almost) unique human ability to have
beliefs has evolved from the long history of the action of the will to power. For
Nietzsche all our beliefs, i.e., what we hold-true, need to be explained naturalis-
tically: "Believing is the primal beginning even in every sense impression: a
kind of affirmation the first intellectual activity! A 'holding-true' in the
beginning! Therefore it is to be explained: how 'holding-true' arose!"; and "The
valuation 'I believe that this and that is so' as the essence of 'truth'" (WP 506-
7). Though it will not be argued here, Nietzsche often advocates a view of truth
in which it is to be analysed in terms of what we hold-true, rather than analysed
in terms of an independent substantive property of our beliefs, that of corre-
sponding to the world. Thus Nietzsche rejects the idea that the truth of our
beliefs is to be explained in terms of a substantive truth property. Rather what
has to be explained is why we hold-true the beliefs we do; and what does the
explaining is the particular operation of the will to power, i.e., the drives, or
will, that lead us to believe some prather than an alternative q.
This casts Nietzsche's talk of "the will to truth" in a new light. Above we
discussed Nietzsche's view that self-identical objects are fictions that are
necessary both for thought, reason, logic and even our survival. From whence
these fictitious beliefs which we (allegedly) hold-true? Two important notebook
passages tell us:
98 ROBERT NOLA
Toward an understanding of logic: the will to equality is the will to power - the belief that
something is thus and thus (the essence of judgement) is the consequence of a will that as much
as possible shall be equal (WP S II).
Logic is bound to the condition: assume there are identical cases. In fact, to make possible logical
thinking and inferences, this condition must first be treated fictitiously as fulfilled. That is: the will
to logical truth can be carried through only after a fundamental falsification of all events is
assumed. From which it follows that a drive rules here that is capable of employing both means,
firstly falsification, then the implementation of its own point of view: logic does not spring from
will to truth. (WP 512)
NOTES
See Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, "How the 'Real World' at Last Became a Myth."
This is a quite minimal account of Nietzsche's ontology (not unlike that attributed to Boscovich
in BGE § 12) that omits many other aspects of his metaphysics, including a metaphysical version
of eternal recurrence (WP §1062-3) and the doctrine of perspectivism. The first of these is an
independent adjunct that can easily be dropped; but the second may well render his metaphysical
system incoherent. The latter matter is raised and well discussed in chapter 6 § 2 of Peter Poellner,
Nietzsche and Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon, 1995).
100 ROBERT NOLA
See Peter Simons, Parts: A Study in Ontology (Oxford, Clarendon, 1987), especially index
under "essentialism, mereological"; see also D. Wiggins Sameness and Substance (Cambridge
MA, Harvard University Press, 1980) chapters 4 and 6.
4 Cf. BGE 11 and WP 511-2.
5 See F. Weinert (ed), Laws of Nature: Essays on the Philosophical, Scientific and Historical
Dimensions (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1995) which contains a number of papers on what are laws
of nature. The paper by Giere argues for a conception of physical sciences without laws, and the
papers by Ruby and Steinle discuss the history and sociology of the concept laws of nature,
including the thesis of their anthropomorphic origin.
6 See Chapter 16, section 2, "Friedrich Nietzsche's Just So Stories" in Daniel Dennett, Darwin's
Dangerous Idea (London: Penguin, 1996) for an account of Nietzsche's view of the theory of
evolution proposed by Darwin and especially his remark that "Nietzsche's idea of a will to power
[in biology and evolution] is one of the stranger incarnations of sky hook hunger." p. 466.
JONATHAN COHEN
By "positivism" (which can mean many things) I mean here a stance which
prizes science for its ability to both produce reliable knowledge and contribute
crucially to human flourishing. By "fling" here I mean merely a temporary
attachment. Nietzsche was, by any definition, an ardent anti-positivist for most
of his philosophical career. My thesis here is that he can nevertheless be
described as a positivist (at least in the above sense) during a certain phase in
(what must now be called) his philosophical development. I am thus arguing
that we must periodize Nietzsche with regard to issues of science and episte-
mology: positivism belongs to Nietzsche's middle phase, beginning with
Human, All Too Human (published in 1878) and concluding some time before
The Gay Science (published in 1882). The connotation of "fling" as being
somewhat fleeting and not especially serious or heartfelt is also intended, for not
only does Nietzsche give up his positivism after a short time, but even while
professing it holds at the same time some of the views which will develop into
the perspectivism for which he is better known in his later works.
By "Nietzsche," then, I refer to a philosopher whose primary philosophical
concerns are not in the areas of science and epistemology. Rather, I see
Nietzsche as changing the views he holds in these areas so as to better fit and
contribute to his primary project, the cultural/spiritual growth of humanity.
While it is true that this latter project changes somewhat too during the course
of Nietzsche's career, the changes in his views are much more dramatic in the
areas of science and epistemology; this indicates, I take it, which is the tail and
which is the dog.
That Nietzsche was an anti-positivist in his early period is not controversial;
however, I locate and characterize his opposition to positivism in a somewhat
different way than is usual. For this reason I will begin by looking briefly at his
account of science during this period before devoting most of my space here to
outlining and explaining Nietzsche's turn to positivism. I will then offer an
explanation as well of why Nietzsche turned away from positivism in his later
works.
Opposition to positivism is strong and unmistakable in Nietzsche's unpub-
lished writings of the period prior to 1878, especially (and famously) in the
sketch for an essay entitled On Truth and Lie in an Extramoral Sense. However,
I will pay only scant attention to this essay here, for two reasons. On the one
101
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 101-107.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
102 JONATHAN COHEN
(O)ne believes that the more profoundly a man thinks, the more tenderly he feels, the more highly
he rates himself, the greater the distance grows between him and the other animals-the more he
appears as the genius among animals-the closer he will get to the true nature of the world and to
a knowledge of it (urn so naher werde er dem wirklichen We sen der Welt und deren Erkenntniss
kommen): this he does in fact do through science (diess thut er auch wirklich durch die
Wissenschaft), but he thinks he does so even more through his arts and religions.
Here the preference of the early works for artistic knowledge is turned on its
head; now, instead of tragedy, it is science which reveals the true nature of the
world. 11 Whence this about-face from the anti-positivism of the early works?
The rhetoric of HH 1, which argues that "(h)istorical philosophy ... can no longer
be separated from natural science," seems to imply that Nietzsche now believes
science has developed to the point where his earlier worries about science and
its effect on artistic culture no longer apply. However, there were no earthshak-
ing scientific discoveries between 1874 (when Untimely Meditations II and III
were published) and 1878 (when Human, All Too Human was), nor did
Nietzsche become aware only then of earlier advances. 12
The key, I believe, is that science means something different to Nietzsche in
Human, All Too Human than it did in the early works. There science was
conceived as an almanac of random, unfocussed objective facts whose cumula-
tive effect was to disillusion belief in the values which true culture must
propound and undercut the love which culture producing work requires. In
Human, All Too Human, however, science is valued as a method which teaches
discipline, "how to achieve an objective by the appropriate means." 13 "Men who
are gifted but unscientific value every token of spirit, whether it is on the right
track or not... .Scientific natures, on the other hand, know that the talent for
having ideas of all kinds must be rigorously curbed by the spirit of science." 14
'The school has no more important task than to teach rigorous thinking,
cautious judgment and consistent reasoning." 15 Thus science in Human, All Too
Human is a discipline in the most literal sense, rather than a compendium of
random facts. It does of course produce such facts, as the above quotes make
clear, but science's knowledge-producing capacity is valued only secondarily;
what Nietzsche values above all is the training science provides. "(I)t is
invaluable, with re~ard to everything one will afterwards do, once to have been
a man of science." 6
But why should Nietzsche's opinion of science have changed between the
early works and Human, All Too Human? The answer, I suggest, is that this
change is actually secondary to a change in Nietzsche's conception of culture.
104 JONATHAN COHEN
In the early works culture is explicitly defined as "the unity of artistic style in
all the expressions of the life of a people." 17 In Human, All Too Human there is
no explicit definition of culture; instead one must glean Nietzsche's new
understanding of culture from oblique references such as the one in which
culture is placed in ':?position with "the sum of sensations, items of knowledge,
(and) experiences." 1 Now Nietzsche recommends, instead of adopting a unified
focus, turning oneself into a vast "hall of culture" which can include both
science and the arts, and describes higher culture as "many-stringed." 19 Such a
change in conception of culture necessarily requires a new look at science. If
culture is a matter of unified focus, then science's demand for objectivity and
impartiality-privileging no particular focus -is a threat. However, if culture is
loosely defined and hard to grasp, then scientific method, as an orderly way of
thinking which helps one proceed in an orderly way towards one's objectives.
becomes quite valuable and even necessary for navigating the vast new hall of
culture Nietzsche envisions.
Thus our question about why Nietzsche reversed his evaluation of science
must become instead a question about why he changed his understanding of
culture. Here it is easy to locate a motivation for his change, for between 1874
and 1878 there was indeed a crucial change in Nietzsche's cultural world: the
Wagner festival at Bayreuth was inaugurated. Although Nietzsche began this
period as a Wagnerian, having closed The Birth of Tragedy with a paean to
Wagner, even the full length encomium published in 1876 as the fourth
Untimely Meditation, "Richard Wagner in Bayreuth," already sounds forced and
artificial. For in fact Nietzsche was appalled by the ignorant jingoism of the
Wagnerians. At Bayreuth, he saw the dangers of understanding culture as
artistic unity; he may have even seen the political dangers (note the use of the
word "people" (V olk) in the early definition of culture). In particular, he came
to see that anti-scientism can degenerate into emotionalism and irrationalism.
In Human, All Too Human, he takes a stand in favor of a crucial role for reason
in our cultural/spiritual growth. To effect this cultural correction on the
emotionally overheated Wagnerian age, he reaches for science as a cooling
bath. 20
Thus Nietzsche turns to science in Human, All Too Human in order to battle
Wagnerian culture and promote his own more cosmopolitan vision in its place.
This leads him to espouse his own form of positivism, as noted above. However,
though he turns to science for its value as a discipline, he praises along with its
educative and cooling powers its ability to reach truth; this is not a necessary
corollary and so demands its own explanation. It is possible that the claim that
science lays bare "the true nature of the world" (HH 29) is mere rhetoric
designed to get the reader to tum to science seriously and so reap its cultural
benefits. However, I believe there is more afoot. Had it appeared in BT, the
phrase "the true nature of the world" would have referred to that mysterious
metaphysical ground in which the principium individuationis breaks down, a
ground attainable only by Dionysian tragic insight. The knowledge which
Nietzsche agrees in the early works is indeed attained by science concerns only
the foreground world of our empirical experience, which Nietzsche calls the
NIETZSCHE'S FLING WITH POSITIVISM 105
"discarded covering" of the world (BT 15). Here in Human, All Too Human,
Nietzsche's primary target is any metaphysics (such as those of Kant and
Schopenhauer) which asserts the existence of a "second" world beyond the
natural one. 21 Once that world is discarded (and Nietzsche's argument against
it in Human, All Too Human has for the most part been given already (at least
programmatically) in the sections preceding 29), the one true world left is the
empirical world. Thus Nietzsche's claim in favor of science in HH 29 conveys
not only a view about science but at the same time a certain epistemology and
metaphysics as well. Thus this claim is not merely a rhetorical push to take
science seriously for its cultural benefits, even though the latter are what
motivates Nietzsche to change his view of science in the first place.
However, this turn to positivism is but a fling, for alongside positivism,
Nietzsche also expresses in Human, A.ll Too Human certain views which work
to undercut science's claim to truth. Under the heading of an attack on meta-
physics, he offers searching criticisms of the efficacy of language, logic, and
mathematics.
The sculptor of language was not so modest as to believe that he was only giving things
designations, he conceived rather that with words he was expressing supreme knowledge of things;
language is, in fact, the first stage of the occupation with science .... (O)nly now- it dawns on men
that in their belief in language they have propagated a tremendous error. Happily, it is too late for
the evolution of reason, which depends on this belief, to be again put back -Logic too depends
on presuppositions with which nothing in the real world corresponds, for example on the
presupposition that there are identical things ... .It is the same with mathematics, which would
certainly not have come into existence if one had known from the beginning that there was in
nature no exactly straight line, no real circle, no absolute magnitude. (HH II)
The appeal to a coherence theory of truth does not of itself disqualify one
from being a positivist (and is certainly in keeping with Nietzsche's Kantian
heritage). And Nietzsche elsewhere22 defends the idea that scientific truth is
"enduring" rather than eternal; this point too need not vitiate positivism.Z 3 How-
ever, the claim that science succeeds in attaining knowledge of the true nature
of the world made in section 29 must still be considered untenable. Though
coherent with each other, scientific facts need not reach the true nature of the
world. It seems that Nietzsche's battle against a metaphysical world has led him
to claim too much in favor of the ability of science to succeed cognitively in its
106 JONATHAN COHEN
world. He claims too much, that is, in view of his own post-Kantian perspectiv-
ist instincts, which are visible in Human, All Too Human as well. 24 This fling,
then, must be considered somewhat half-hearted.
When the fling ends, in The Gay Scienci 5 , Nietzsche emerges with the
perspectivism most readers know him for, a view which (among other things)
denies that the phrase "true nature of the world" is epistemically coherent, and
which sees science as one perspective among others, no better equipped to yield
knowledge than they. Why did Nietzsche tum away from his positivism to
realize and assert the perspectivism which indeed seems latent in certain
sections of Human, All Too Human? 26 The answer is threefold. First, perspec-
tivism does indeed seem to be more consistent with the Kantian framework in
which Nietzsche is working than does positivism. Second, for polemical
reasons, Nietzsche found it advantageous, while breaking with Wagner and with
Schopenhauer, to side with the science which they both anathematized, but once
the polemic receded, Nietzsche believed he could attack science again, now with
himself, not Schopenhauer, representing the cause of philosophy. 27 Third, with
his attack on metaphysics in Human, All Too Human having failed to win a
decisive victory, Nietzsche came to realize that the only way to conclusively
undercut the claims to absolute truth made by metaphysics was to abandon
science's similar claim as well. 28
Having done so, Nietzsche in his later works would reject both aspects of
positivism as defined above. First, science does not attain truth, but is rather
itself an interpretation of the world; qua interpretation, it is no more legitimate
than any other. Second, science inhibits the highest life, first because it does not
admit its perspectival character and is thus mendacious, and second because it
represents merely another form of Christian asceticism. In the early works the
task was to limit science's drive for knowledge for knowledge's sake in favor
of knowledge for the sake of an entire national culture. Now in the later works,
the task is again to control and limit science, only now the unit with which
Nietzsche is working is the strong individual. Such an individual adopts a
perspective suitable to his own flourishing, thus creating a sort of "culture of
one." 29
As final defense of my reading, I close by noting that Nietzsche himself,
looking back on his career, sees a pair of periodizing shifts. In the preface to
Human, All Too Human, added in 1886 from the perspective of his later work,
Nietzsche uses the image of a bird first going aloft and then returning to earth.
Its ascent is necessary to free itself from former attachments; at its height it sees
from a disinterested distance; finally it de-scends to rejoin the cultural fray. 30 So
too Nietzsche's free spirit goes through a phase of training in the detachment
and objectivity of science, so as better to "become what one is," 31 so as to be
able to know one's own perspective for what it is. For Nietzsche, this middle
period of growth, of detachment from former views, involved the adoption of
positivism.
NOTES
dissertation, Science, Culture, and Free Spirits, available from University Microfilms, 1991.
24 Cf., for example, the notion of interpretation in section 16.
25 Cf. especially sections 110 ff.
26 By this token TL can be seen as latent perspectivism as well, taken up again after the
overall societal culture; see my "Nietzsche's Elitism and the Cultural Division of Labor," in
Rending and Renewing the Social Order, ed. Yeager Hudson, (Lewiston, NY: The Edwin Mellen
Press, 1996), pp. 389-400.
30 See HH Preface, sections 3 through 6, especially 4.
31 HH 263.
DANIEL CONWAY
Nietzsche should have known better. His withering critique of the Kantian Ding
an sich launched the anti-foundationalism that continues to define the agenda
of twentieth-century philosophy. His figural definition of truth issued marchin§
orders to a "movable host of metaphors, metonymies, and anthropomorphisms,"
which, having established command centers in Paris and New Haven, quickly
colonized a transatlantic empire. His celebrated "perspectivism," which is now
firmly entrenched as the official dogma of post-Kantian epistemology, linked
the pursuit of objectivity to the "castration of the intellect." His textbook
debunking of the metaphysical prejudices of folk psychology paved the way for
behaviorism, epiphenomenalism, functionalism, eliminative materialism, and
various other reductionist approaches to the philosophy of mind. His stirring
exhortations to "become what we are," and thereby own the world that we have
pre-reflectively fashioned from our primitive superstitions and archaic fetish-
isms, have spurred the development of cottage industries in worldmaking and
narrative redescription. Widely recognized as a "master of suspicion," he is
revered as the progenitor of post-modern philosophy and the arch-villain of
speculative system-building. In short, his anti-metaphysical influences on the
career of twentieth-century philosophy are indisputable.
Equally indisputable, however, is the robust realism that emerges in his
writings from 1888, his final year of sanity. Despite having recorded the anti-
109
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, I 09-122.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
110 DANIEL CONWAY
It is here and nowhere else that one must make a start to comprehend what Zarathustra wants: this
type of man ... conceives reality as it is [concipirt die Realitat, wie sie ist], being strong enough
to do so; this type is not estranged or removed from reality but is reality itself and exemplifies all
that is terrible and questionable in it- only in that way can man attain greatness. (EH:destiny 5)4
SECTION ONE
In his famous recounting of "How the 'True World' ['wahre Welt'] Finally
Became a Fable" (TI), Nietzsche offers a compact, six-step synopsis of the
history of Western metaphysics. Beginning with Plato's epiphanic experience
of himself as the truth, breezing through the metaphysical calisthenics per-
formed by scholastic theologians, Kantian skeptics, and obtuse positivists, he
arrives at the final, consummatory stage in the evolution of Western meta-
physics:
6. The true [wahre] world- we have abolished [abgeschafft]. What world has remained? The
apparent [scheinbare] one perhaps? But no! With the true world we have also abolished the
apparent one. (Noon; moment of the briefest shadow; end of the longest error; high point of
humanity; INCIPIT ZARATHUSTRA.) (TI 'Real World'i
Does this double abolition perhaps betoken the dawn of a post-metaphysical era,
which Nietzsche inaugurates by deconstructing the most stubborn binarism of
Western philosophy? Many scholars have reached precisely this conclusion,
happily conscripting Nietzsche as the progenitor of post-modern philosophy. If
the true and apparent worlds are both abolished, or so the story goes, then the
world must be a fiction, a construct, a narrative artifact created by that exceed-
ingly clever animal, homo faber.
BEYOND TRUTH AND APPEARANCE 111
Here we must be careful, however, lest the "moment of the briefest shadow"
temporarily obnubilate the truth of Nietzsche's rnisplaudited achievement. The
time of day recorded in this passage is not dawn, but noontide. Although the
abolition of the true and apparent worlds may herald a new beginning for
Zarathustra, it more distinctly marks the midpoint in a larger process of
development. Distracted perhaps by the "pandemonium of all free spirits,"
Zarathustra makes precisely this mistake in his own initial solar calculations,
assuming that the way is now clear for him to promulgate a revolutionary, new
teaching: the Vbermensch. Zarathustra may begin his ill-fated Untergang at
dawn, saluting the rising sun while vowing to emulate its autarkic independence
(Z Preface 1), but Zarathustra, unbeknownst to its eponymous hero, begins at
high noon [Mittag] (ibid.). Plato's embarrassed blush, it seems, is extremely
contagious.
Having adjusted our chronometers, let us investigate the conclusion that
Nietzsche draws from his brief history of Western metaphysics. What does it
mean for him to announce that we have abolished the true and apparent worlds?
What, in short, is the logic of abolition? This unspecified "we" cannot comprise
humankind as a whole, for we know from Nietzsche's writings in 1888 that the
sick and infirm masses continue, involuntarily, to invest their fading belief in
these ersatz worlds. Even if he means to refer here to a more restricted "we,"
perhaps comprising himself and his merry band of (fictitious) free spirits (HH
I Preface 2), it is simply not the case that their collaborative "abolition" renders
these worlds nugatory or otiose. While it is perhaps true that he has exploded the
mendacious lies that sustain this bogus metaphysical distinction - a signal
achievement in its own right - his expose in itself need not prove to be
liberatory. As Nietzsche himself immediately cautions upon announcing the
death of God, "given the ways of men, there may still be caves for thousands of
years in which his shadow will be shown" (GS 108). In the post-Zarathustran
cosmos, that is, knowledge does not readily translate into virtue.
Rather than knell the death of metaphysics per se, 6 Nietzsche's account of
"The History of an Error" exposes the basic fabrications that Western meta-
physics has perpetuated. In the symptomatology developed in his post-
Zarathustran writings, he summarily reduces all philosophical judgments, pro
and contra, to signs (or symptoms) of an underlying physiological condition:
Judgments, judgments of value, concerning life, for it or against it, can, in the end, never be true:
they have value only as symptoms, they are worthy of consideration only as symptoms; in
themselves such judgments are stupidities (Tl Socrates 2/
To invent fables about a world "other" than this one has no meaning at all, unless an instinct of
slander, detraction, and suspicion against life has gained the upper hand in us. In that case we
avenge ourselves against life with a phantasmagoria of "another," a "better" life ... Any distinction
between a "true" and an "apparent" world ... is only a suggestion of decadence. (Tl Reason 6)
112 DANIEL CONWAY
Nietzsche's "History of an Error" thus exposes the decadence that lies at the
heart of the Western metaphysical tradition. In fact, philosophical allegiances
either to "truth" or to "appearance" are equally symptomatic of decadence.
These allegiances therefore tell us a great deal about the physiological disarray
of the philosophers who pledge them, but virtually nothing about the real world
itself. All we know about the real world is that it induces in these decadents the
pathological recoil that defines the essence of metaphysical thinking:
The instinctive hatred of reality [Realitiit]: a consequence of an extreme capacity for suffering and
excitement which no longer wants any contact at all because it feels every contact too deeply ...
The fear of pain, even of infinitely minute pain- that can end in no other way than in a religion
of love. (AC 30)R
Any distinction between a "true" and an "apparent" world ... is only a suggestion of decadence,
a symptom of the decline of life. That the artist esteems appearance higher than reality [Realitiit]
is no objection to this proposition. For "appearance" in this case means reality [Realitat] once
more, only by way of selection, reinforcement.. and correction. (TI Socrates 6) 10
Nietzsche's abolition of the true and apparent worlds thus discloses the real
world, for all who can afford to behold it in its amoral, undifferentiated
immanence.
Hence it is not the case, as Nietzsche's post-modem scions are wont to
maintain, that he deconstructs the distinction between truth and appearance in
order to set aside a pernicious binarism and frolic in the resulting play of
dif.ferance. Rather, he rejects the philosophical distinction between truth and
appearance because it occludes the precise binarism that he wishes to invoke.
In the following passage, in fact, he proposes a new distinction to replace the
recently debunked distinction between truth and appearance:
Moral judgments, like religious ones, belong to a stage of ignorance at which the very concept of
the real [der Begriff des Rea/en] and the distinction between what is real and imaginary [die
Unterscheidung des Realen und Imaginaren], are still lacking; thus "truth," at this stage,
designates all sorts of things which we today call "imaginings." Moral judgments are therefore
never to be taken literally: so understood, they always contain mere absurdity. Semeiotically,
however, they remain invaluable: they reveaL at least for those who know, the most valuable
realities [Realitaten1 of cultures and inwardnesses which did not know enough to "understand"
themselves. Morality is mere sign language, mere symptomatology: one must know what it is all
about to be able to profit from it. (TI 'Improvers' 1) 11
"apparent world" is in fact the real world, which they cannot afford to behold
in the immanence of its ownmost existence.
SECTION TWO
Our attention to Nietzsche's abolition of the "true" and "apparent" worlds thus
sheds light on his understanding of "The History of an Error," but it also raises
a host of difficult questions about his matter-of-fact appeals to Realitat. What
are we to make of this tertium quid that he so calmly introduces into his account
of the history of Western metaphysics? What is the ontological status of this real
world- especially if it is neither the "true" nor the "apparent" world?
As is typically the case with the basic, central terms of Nietzsche's philoso-
phizing, the concept of Realitiit receives neither a precise definition nor an
extended elaboration. As we have seen, precious little can be said about the real
world without idealizing/slandering it in the process, and Nietzsche generally
observes this limitation by maintaining an uncharacteristic, quasi-reverential
silence. Unlike my own practice in this essay, he is loathe to describe his
ongoing investigations of the real world under the heading of "realism" - or of
any other -ism, for that matter.
As one might expect of a fully-initiated disciple of Dionysus (BT Preface 6),
he typically refuses to convey his "realism" directly, for fear of profaning the
world he wishes to engage. In this respect, his "realism" more closely resembles
a (this-worldly) religious position, whereby he adopts a posture of receptive
attunement to the Dionysian whirl and flux of reality. 13 In an apparent display
of reverence and humility in the face of an immeasurably dense, undifferentiated
Ur-eine, he tends to refer to the real world only by explaining what it is not, or
by describing its typical effects on the representative philosophers who
encounter it. Rather than attempt to articulate a position or theory of realism, he
prefers to rely on concrete examples. He singles out Thucydides and Machia-
velli as realists whom he admires, and he confers similar honors upon Pilate,
Bacon, Napoleon, Goethe, and Leopold Ranke. Most deserving of the title
"realist," however, are the tragedians whom he praises in his first book, for
tragedy affirms Life itself in the entirety of its painful immanence: "The tragic
artist is no pessimist: he is precisely the one who says yes to everything
questionable, even to the terrible- he is Dionysian" (TI Socrates 6). Deaf to the
siren song of metaphysics, these arch-realists celebrate the innocence of
Becoming and proudly profess their amor fati; they alone could fearlessly will
the eternal return of the same.
Nietzsche also (if indirectly) sheds light on his realism by contrasting it with
idealism, which he generally identifies with metaphysical thinking. An ideal
suggests to him a "flight from reality," a theoretical construct that may or may
not admit of concrete instantiation (EH:gb 1). Defending his alternative to
idealism, he thus maintains that "What justifies man is his reality [Realitat] -
it will eternally justify him. How much greater is the worth of the real[wirkli-
che] man, compared with any merely desired, dreamed-up, foully fabricated
man? with any ideal man?" (TI Expeditions 32). 14
BEYOND TRUTH AND APPEARANCE 115
Reality [die Wirklichkeit] shows us an enchanting wealth of types, the abundance of a lavish play
and change of forms- and some wretched loafer of a moralist comments: "No! Man ought to be
different." He even knows what man should be like, this wretched bigot and prig: he paints himself
on the wall and comments "Ecce homo!" (TI Morality 6) 16
Nietzsche's realism thus furnishes both the context and the impetus for the
fatalism expressed in his 18 88 writings. The truth of the real world, it turns out,
lies in the fatality of the undifferentiated Whole that it encompasses. Contrary
to the popular wisdom of idealists and moralists alike, the real world cannot be
altered or ameliorated in piecemeal fashion. Any wish to change a "part" of the
Whole conveys an unstated desire to slander and reject the Whole. In the
following passage, Nietzsche not only clarifies the nature of his realism, but also
speaks from the realist perspective he wishes to endorse:
But even when the moralist addresses himself only to the single human being and says to him,
"You ought to be such and such!" he does not cease to make himself ridiculous. The individual
human being is a piece of fatum from the front and from the rear, one law more, one necessity
more for all that is yet to come and to be. To say to him, "Change yourself!'' is to demand that
everything be changed, even retroactively. (ibid.)
What alone can our teaching be? That ... no one is responsible for man's being there at all, for his
being such-and-such, or for his being in these circumstances or in this environment. (TI Errors 8)
116 DANIEL CONWAY
Unlike most human beings, to whom the future remains unknown, the author
of Ecce Homo actually "knows his fate"; he consequently assures us that "one
day [his] name will be associated with the memory of something tremendous
(EH:destiny l)."
In sharp contrast to the bristling voluntarism of Zarathustra's teachings,
Nietzsche's 1888 writings propose a recognition of one's fatality as emblematic
of human greatness. He consequently concludes his critique of metaphysics by
proposing amor fati as the antithesis of all idealism:
My formula for greatness in a human being is amor fati: that one wants nothing to be different,
not forward, not backward, not in all eternity. Not merely bear what is necessary, still less conceal
it- all idealism is mendaciousness in the face of what is necessary- but love it. (EH:clever I 0)
A condemnation of life by the living remains in the end a mere symptom of a certain kind of life:
the question whether it is justified or unjustified is not even raised thereby ... [B]ut of what life?
of what kind of life? I have already given the answer: of declining, weakened, weary, condemned
life. (Tl Morality 5)
BEYOND TRUTH AND APPEARANCE 117
Who alone has good reason to lie his way out of reality [Wirklichkeit]? He who suffers from it. But
to suffer from reality is to be a piece of reality that has come to grief. The preponderance of
feelings of displeasure over feelings of pleasure is the cause of this fictitious morality and religion;
but such a preponderance provides the very formula of decadence. (AC 15) 17
One should use [metaphysical categories] 18 only as pure concepts, that is to say, as conventional
fictions for the purpose of designation [Bezeichnung] and understanding [Verstiindigung]- not for
explanation !Erkliirung]. (BGE 21, emphasis added)
SECTION THREE
Nietzsche identifies warranted belief in the existence of the real world as one of
the most significant casualties of the advance of decadence in late modernity.
Unable to withstand the suffering endemic to any confrontation with the real
world as it is, decadent philosophers presumptuously conclude that no real
world exists to which human agents enjoy empirical access. Rather than
acknowledge, simply, that they cannot penetrate the veil of Maya, philosophers
characteristically attempt to valorize their debilitating infirmities by generaliz-
ing them across the compass of humankind as a whole.
Nietzsche does not doubt that most philosophers are ill-constituted to behold
the world in its painful, amoral existence; nor does he dispute that for them, the
world is unknown (and probably unknowable) in its ownmost reality. He simply
objects to the validity of these (decadent) experiences for the rest of humankind.
That decadent philosophers have variously projected their sickness onto the
118 DANIEL CONWAY
world as a whole tells us a great deal about their besetting illness, but virtually
nothing about the real world. Contrary to popular interpretation, Nietzsche's
"perspectivism" does not decree that the world is unknowable in itself; any such
decree would simp,ly implicate him in the pathology that he detects in predeces-
sor philosophers. 9 His "perspectivism" instead stands as a reminder that the
failure of decadent philosophers to engage with the real world need bear no
relevance for his (or our) own attempts to know the world? 0
Although Nietzsche's "perspectivism" helpfully deflects the pessimism of
decadent philosophers, it also raises serious epistemic questions about the
validity of his realism. How, after all, can he legitimately discount the epistemic
value of the subjective realities to which priests, invalids, and decadents
regularly appeal? 1 With what epistemic warrant can he say, for example, that
"Whatever a theologian feels to be true must be false: this is almost a criterion
of truth" (AC 9). Indeed, if he rejects the traditional epistemic appeal to
objective validity, then by what mode of apprehension or attunement does one
come to know the world as it is?
Nietzsche's apparent solution to these epistemic problems is to appeal to a
notion of subjectively valid knowledge. One gains access to the real world not
by adopting the detached, external standpoint of the disinterested, panoptic
observer, but by immersing oneself in the chaotic affective engagements
afforded by an imbricated plurality of competing perspectives. One comes to
know the real world, as it is, by virtue of the range and depth of the opposing
perspectives one has mastered- by virtue, that is, of one's capacity to suffer
reality as it is, unmediated by metaphysical buffers. In an attempt to secure an
immanent critical standpoint, Nietzsche consequently endeavors to view the
world "from inside," as "will to power and nothing else" (BGE 36). In the
writings from 1888, he thus presents his own multiplex perspective as valid (or
more valid than others), because it draws on the various, antipodal perspectives
at his unique disposal.
In fact, Nietzsche explicitly links the validity of his realism to his decadence,
which has endowed him with the capacity to command antipodal perspectives.
He thus attributes his own excessive "wisdom" to his mastery of the art of
reversing perspectives (EH:wise 1). As evidence of this mastery, he points to his
unique, dual experience of the decadence that besets late modernity: "Apart
from the fact that I am a decadent, I am also the opposite" (EH:wise 2, emphasis
added). Owing to the dual descent of his patriarchal and matriarchal lineages,
respectively, he is, "at the same time a decadent and a beginning" (EH:wise I).
He furthermore advertises this mastery in the reversal of perspectives as "the
first reason why a revaluation of all values is perhaps possible for [him] alone''
(EH:wise 1). Precisely because he is decadent, he perversely insists, he has
glimpsed the truth of his age (EH:wise 1).
In attributing his copious wisdom to this acquired mastery at reversing
perspectives, Nietzsche renews a familiar line of argumentation, in which he
links the richness and value of knowledge to the range of perspectives the
knower commands. In his most famous sustained account of the position now
BEYOND TRUTH AND APPEARANCE 119
[L]et us be on guard against the dangerous old conceptual fiction that posited a "pure, will-less,
painless, timeless knowing subject"; let us guard against the snares of such contradictory concepts
as "pure reason," "absolute spirituality," "knowledge in itself'; these always demand that we
should think of an eye that is completely unthinkable, an eye turned in no particular direction, in
which the active and interpreting forces, through which alone seeing becomes seeing something,
are supposed to be lacking ... There is only a perspectival seeing [perspektivisches Sehen], only
a perspectival "knowing" ... (GM III: 12)
IT] he truth speaks out of me.- But my truth is terrible; for so far one has called lies truth ... It is
my fate that I have to be the first decent human being; that I know myself to stand in opposition
to the mendaciousness of millennia. - I was the first to discover the truth by being the first to
experience lies as lies- smelling them out.- My genius is in my nostrils. (EH:destiny I)
Revaluation of all values: that is my formula for an act of supreme self-examination on the part
of humanity, become .flesh and genius in me ... For all that, I am also the man of calamity. For
when truth enters into a fight with the lies of millennia, we shall have upheavals, a convulsion of
earthquakes, a moving of mountains and valleys, the like of which has never been dreamed of.
(EH:destiny 1, emphasis added)
CONCLUSION
fact, Nietzsche brazenly defends the superiority of his own multiplex perspec-
tive by invoking its inaccessibility to lesser noses (EH:gb 1).
Even more damaging for his own project, however, is the eerie "family
resemblance" that obtains between his own realism and the romantic pessimism
against which he regularly inveighs. He bravely insists, after all, that his
iibennenschlich capacity for suffering secures his unprecedented access to the
real world, and that his elevated state of soul renders him friendless and
misunderstood (EH:gb 1). Owing to the subjective validity of his realism,
moreover, he is tragically consigned to bear without respite the burden of his
knowledge, while fools and vulgarians tirelessly mock his unverifiable wisdom.
His only response is to decree, loudly and resentfully, that he alone is aesthesi-
ologically equipped to descend into the well of Being, that his true readers and
kindred spirits belong only to the audiences of a distant posterity. In the end, is
his enhanced olfaction all that far removed from the hyper-refined sensibilities
of, say, the young Werther, who was similarly convinced of the subjective
validity of his own communion with the beautiful soul of the cosmos?
NOTES
1 With the exception of occasional emendations, I rely throughout this essay on Walter
Kaufmann's translations/editions of Nietzsche's books for Viking Press/Random House, and on
R.J. Hollingdale's translations for Cambridge University Press ..
2 Friedrich Nietzsche: Siimtliche Werke, Kritische Studienausgabe in 15 Biinden, hrsg. G. Colli
und M. Montinari (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter/Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag, 1980), Vol. 6, p. 174
3 Philosophy and Truth: Selections from Nietzsche's Notebooks from the Early 1870s, ed. and
trans. Daniel Breazeale (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press International, 1990) p. 84.
4 KSA 6, 370.
5 KSA 6, 81.
6 The failure of Nietzsche's "abolition" to bring to an end the tradition of Western metaphysics
would appear to confirm Heidegger's famous interpretation: "This makes clear in what respect the
modern metaphysics of subjectness is consummated in Nietzsche's doctrine of will to power as
the 'essence'of everything real." "The Word of Nietzsche: God is Dead," The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, William Lovitt, trans. and ed. (New York: Harper &
Row, 1977), p. 83. While Heidegger is surely right to point to the metaphysical residue of
Nietzsche's teaching of will to power, it is not likely that Nietzsche ever undertook the (Heideg-
gerian) project of bringing metaphysics to an end. If, as Nietzsche's symptomatology suggests,
metaphysical judgments are symptoms of advanced decay, then the "overcoming:"of metaphysics
would neces>.arily involve the eradication or remission of decadence itself. On the question of
Nietzsche's vexed relationship to metaphysics, see Wolfgang Miiller-Lauter, "Nietzsche's
Teaching of Will to Power," trans. Drew Griffin, The Journal of Nietzsche Studies, Issue 4/5,
Autumn 1992-Spring 1993, pp. 37-101.
7 In an alternate statement of his symptomatological turn, Nietzsche explains that "All those bold
insanities of metaphysics, especially answers to the question about the value of existence ... lack
any grain of significance when measured scientifically, [but] they are the more valuable for the
historian and psychologist as hints or symptoms of the body, of its success or failure, its plenitude,
power, and autocracy in history, or of its frustrations, weariness, impoverishment, its premonitions
of the end, its will to the end" (GS P2).
8 KSA 6, 200-01.
9 KSA 6, 78.
10 KSA 6, 79.
II KSA 6 98
12 KSA 6: 25S.
122 DANIEL CONWAY
13 For an insightful treatment of Nietzsche's realism within the context of his understanding of
science, see Babette Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science: Reflecting Science on the Ground
o[ Art for Life (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1994), especially pp. 109-119.
I KSA 6, 131
15 KSA 6, 258.
16 KSA 6, 86-87.
17 KSA 6, 181-82.
18 Nietzsche says explicitly '"cause' and 'effect'," but his discussion suggests that he means all
such metaphysical categories, including "sequence, for-each-other, relativity, constraint, number.
law, freedom, motive, and purpose" (BGE 21).
19 For this interpretation of Nietzsche's "perspectivism," I am indebted to the discussion by
require us to use terms that perspectivism effectively disallows: "But in order to say what [the
world] is, beyond saying that it is what our perspectives are perspectives of. we must use terms
that every point of view must acknowledge; and this is either to dispense with points of view
altogether or to claim that one of them is inherently superior to the rest and represents the world
as it really is" (Nietzsche: Life as Literature [Camb1idge: Harvard University Press, 1985). p. 49).
This is a curious argument, however, insofar as it appears to yoke our philosophical investigation
of the real world to the "use [of] terms that every point of view must acknowledge." As I have
attempted to demonstrate, Nietzsche's writings from 1888 defend a perspective that "is inherently
superior to the rest and represents the world as it really is."
21 Nietzsche claims that Jesus "accepted only inner realities as realities, as 'truths"'(AC 34),
thereby suggesting that a distinction between subjective reality and reality is in fact epistemically
meaningful.
22 The following discussion of Nietzsche's "perspectivism" draws from my essay, "The Eyes
Have It: Perspectives and Affective Investment," International Studies in Philosophy, Volume
XXIII, No.2, 1991, pp. 103-113.
23 See Babich, pp. 175-79.
24 Clark persuasively demonstrates that Nietzsche "overcomes his denial of truth" in the books
of the post-Zarathustran period (pp. 109-117). Clark also astutely points out that Nietzsche's
"perspectivism" makes little sense as a reductionist version of anti-foundationalism (pp. 150-158).
BARRY ALLEN
123
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietuche, Episterrwlogy, and Philosophy of Science: Nietuche and the Sciences II, 123- I40.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
124 BARRY ALLEN
EXPERIMENTAL KNOWLEDGE
Two ideas of knowledge have competed throughout our history, offering two
conceptions of what the best knowledge is and why it is desirable. One is the
contemplative ideal of Greek philosophy from Parmenides to Aristotle to
Plotinus. The best knowledge is an impassive, contemplative state, with the
things known clearly and distinctly present to the mind. Such knowledge is self-
evident truth of self-evident, intrinsic value. The other idea of knowledge, which
may be traced to the Greek idea of metis or cunnin3 or, to reach back further, to
the Egyptian culture of magic, understands the best knowledge to be powerful,
operational knowledge, knowledge that can be tried and works. Such knowledge
is not contemplative knowledge of truth, but experimental knowledge, a
capacity for a reliable performance, tested by trials and perfected through
experience. It is valuable partly for the effects it allows an operator to produce,
and partly for the effect of such effectiveness on the lives and environment of
those who know, enhancing their existence, making their environment at once
more expansive and more coherent.
The contemplative ideal prevailed in Western philosophy through the
sixteenth century, though never so exclusively that the experimental, magical
idea of the best knowledge was lost; instead, it remained a dark undercurrent,
the forbidden, irrational, heretical "constitutive outside" of philosophical,
scientific, rational, orthodox knowledge. The pursuit of this other knowledge is
furtive, esoteric, the very desire for it morally suspicious, as the cautionary tale
of Dr. Faustus and, before him, of Simon Magus and Noah's son Ham con-
firmed.3 From the sixteenth century, however, the relationship between these
two ideas of knowledge begins to change. Sixteenth-century thinkers such as
ALL THE DARING OF THE LOVER OF KNOWLEDGE 125
Della Porta, Cornelius Agrippa, Giordano Bruno, and John Dee prominently
advanced the "magical" idea of the best knowledge. For their trouble each one
became infamous as a "magician." Yet by the seventeenth century, the Lord
Chancellor of England was openly calling for experiments, for the perfection of
an operational knowledge that even he called "magic," at the expense of "the
contemplation of truth" and "the quielt and tranquillity of abstract wisdom." And
since, on his view, it is the ignorance of causes which produces the failure of
works, the "truthfulness" of the best knowledge is not some abstract formal
adequation to beings in themselves, but only the completeness of someone's
working knowledge of causes. 4
Bacon, Boyle, and other early-modem philosophers of experimental
knowledge endeavored to relieve the conception of knowledge they took from
the esoteric tradition of everything that had long linked the pursuit of forbidden
knowledge to deviant ritual, heresy, and morally dubious secrecy. 5 Their
demystification of magic also disembeds the pursuit of experimental knowledge
from the ethical context of a self-fashioning "aesthetics of existence" in which
esotericism had maintained it, and gives such knowledge over to a political
institution, the social embodiment of correct scientific discipline. A bureaucratic
administration replaces the ethical work of individuals, and a magus-figure like
Agrippa, Dee, or Faustus becomes increasingly difficult to take seriously. The
inductive labor of the new experimental philosophy is not performed for
"selfish" or self-fashioning motives, but "selflessly," from charity, for the good
of society, or the future perfection of humankind (Boyle called the experimen-
talist a "priest of nature," and approved of laboratory work performed, like
divine service, on Sundays). 6
Nietzsche implicitly declares his "Baconianism" when, in a variation on
Bacon's trademark trope of departing beyond the Pillars of Hercules, he paints
the picture of "a new dawn ... At long last our ships may venture out again ... all
the daring of the lover of knowledge is permitted again" (GS 343). What had
been holding them back? The "old god." The one that Bacon, Boyle, and many
other enlightened experimental philosophers still worshiped: the utilitarian
pieties and mythological methodology with which they endeavored to discipline
the experimental life and disengage knowledge from ethical self-fashioning.
Nietzsche claims the modern virtues of the experimental life for his own; it
is the experimental knowledge of a Galileo, Boyle, or Franklin which presup-
poses and discloses that "world of dangers and victories" of the lover of
knowledge (GS 324). This interest in the experimental life leads Nietzsche, as
it led early-modern philosophers from Bacon to Kant, to offer a critique of the
contemplative or what I shall call "representational" philosophy of knowledge.
Yet there is a difference between Nietzsche and the experimental philosophers
of the Enlightenment, and we shall see how he goes beyond their assumptions
about knowledge. First, however, let us turn to Nietzsche's "anti-
representationalism."
126 BARRY ALLEN
NIETZSCHE'S ANTI-REPRESENTATIONALISM
Henceforth, my dear philosophers, let us be on guard against ... such contradictory concepts as
"pure reason" ... [or] "knowledge in itself': these always demand that we should think of an eye
that is completely unthinkable, an eye turned in no particular direction, in which the active and
interpretive forces, through which alone seeing becomes seeing something, are supposed to be
lacking; these always demand of the eye an absurdity and a nonsense. There is only a perspective
seeing, only a perspective "knowing." (GM Ill: 12)
How far the perspective character of existence (Dasein) extends or indeed whether existence has
any other character than this; whether existence without interpretation (Dasein ohne Auslegung),
whether "sense," does not become "nonsense"; whether, on the other hand, all existence is not
essentially actively engaged in interpretation- that cannot be decided (nicht ausgemacht werden)
even by the most industrious and most scrupulous conscientious analysis and self-examination of
the intellect; for in the course of this analysis the human intellect cannot avoid seeing itself in its
own perspectives, and only in these. We cannot look around our own corner: it is hopeless
curiosity that wants to know what other kinds of intellects and perspectives there might be. (GS
374)
yet under what relations a thing falls depends on the perspective from which it
is considered. There is no non-relational, transcendent, god's-eye view on a
world of unlimited relations. Nothing is "substantial," nothing "identical to
itself." Having dissolved substance into an infinite plexus of relations and made
"identity" relative and perspectival, Nietzsche must repudiate the classical
conception of the being of beings (EH 273). "The criteria which have been
bestowed on the 'true being' of things are the criteria of not-being, of naught"
(TI Reason 5). "Nothing is" (WP 570); "a kind of becoming must itself create
the deception of beings" (WP 517).
With nothing but relations and relations of relations, "what a thing is" or "the
way the world is" gives way to an interpretation of things, a partial, interested
cross-section or perspective texture of its relations. If representationalism or
truth-as-correspondence are axiomatic for knowledge, or necessary conditions
on its existence, then Nietzsche must say that there is simply no such thing as
knowledge. But those "axioms" hold, if at all, only in the brain of a few
Platonizing philosophers. It would be more realistic to think of "knowing" not
as any sort of passive, mimetic contemplation of true being, but as an active,
interested, situated, circumstantial activity, its product (knowledge) a selection,
a map, a partial cross-section of a relational plexus tailored to an exigent human
context. Knowing is not copying but interpreting, not passively contemplating
things in themselves but actively constructing an artifact, a "reading," whose
value consists not in its vicegerent mimetic fealty but in the capacity with which
it endows the knower for a reliable performance. 12
When knowledge is thought in terms of representations, "error" is a discrep-
ancy between proposition and fact. To ensure the dignity and purity of truth's
essence, whether a belief or statement enjoys the requisite correspondence must
be independent of any performative success, which can at most be inconclusive
evidence of correspondence. In other words, whether a belief corresponds with
reality might vary even though nothing else varies, or vary in a way that makes
no difference to anything else. That is one problem with the idea of truth-as-
correspondence. It gives no account of why we should value the truth, why it is
preferable to error. Supposing the essence of truth were correspondence, it
would be a wide-open question which is better for life, truth or error, truth or
myth, truth or systematic misrepresentation.
These are, of course, Nietzsche's own questions. Yet apart from the assump-
tions of "representationalism" which he seems to reject, it is unhelpful to
suggest that "the conditions of life might include error" (GS 121 ), or that "we
must love and cultivate erring (das Irren): it is the motherwomb of knowl-
edge." 13 If knowledge is an interpretative, circumstantial artifact and not the
imitation of being, the conclusion to draw about error is not that it is "just as
good" as knowledge, but that its difference and specific disvalue lies not in a
formal discrepancy between representation and true being but in a practical
discrepancy between expectation and performance. An error is some disruption
(or latency for disruption) in somebody' s performance; it is unexpected,
disturbing, and not attributable to chance. 14 It is not plausible to say that that
ALL THE DARING OF THE LOVER OF KNOWLEDGE 129
might be useful for life, least of all for the life staked on a successful perform-
ance.
If reading Nietzsche as an anti-representationalist makes fair sense of what
he says about knowledge, it risks his assimilation to the pragmatism in whose
name Rorty introduced his critical anti-representationalism. 15 Nietzsche might
agree with the pragmatists that truth is not any sort of intrinsic, final good-in-
itself, yet he goes much further than they do in rethinking its value. A principal
aim, from Peirce to Dewey, of the so-called pragmatic theory of truth is to
establish a new rationale (or rationalization) for truth's superior value. For
Platonists, what is not true cannot be good to know or good at all (except as an
expedient lie for the wise). For pragmatists, on the other hand, if a belief,
statement, or theory were not of some definite practical good, it just wouldn't
be true. Pragmatists and Platonists thus agree that "of all things good, truth
holds first place," while they differ over the terms in which to understand its
presumptive, taken-for-granted value. 16 For Pragmatists, the good of truth is
wrongly understood as the intuitive contemplation of Being, but when under-
stood by their lights as the greater practical grasp, to which inquiry conduces,
of whatever concrete good any situation promises, truth retains its place among
the highest values.
Nietzsche might be preemptory with this pragmatism. Once philosophy
outgrows conceptions like Being and God, the idea of truth's superior worth
becomes more strangely difficult than pragmatists seem to see. "Consider on
this question both the earliest and most recent philosophers: they are all
oblivious of how much the will to truth itself first requires justification; here
there is a lacuna in every philosophy" (GM III: 24). Pragmatists make a show
of questioning truth's supposedly intrinsic value, but at no point is there a
serious doubt that truth is and must remain among the highest goods. "The
conclusions that ought to be the result of their most rigorous reflection were
always settled from the start" (BGE 188).
Rorty is especially careful not to exaggerate the value of truth, yet in doing
so he backs away from the pragmatism of Peirce, James, and Dewey (and Quine
and Putnam), and takes a step in Nietzsche's direction. Whatever their differ-
ences, Peirce, James, Mead, and Dewey were far from sharing Rorty's view that
truth "is not the sort of thing one should expect to have a philosophically
interesting theory about." 17 In a surprising swerve from any normative philo-
sophical discourse about truth, Rorty sets aside their interest in advancing a
theory, or telling a story, that newly rationalizes truth's place among the highest
values. In his view, that is too much, or the wrong thing, to ask of philosophy.
An exaggerated evaluation of knowledge and truth is a metaphysical stumbling
block in the way of the "post-Philosophical" culture Rorty envisions.
Rorty's pragmatism may, as he says, consist "very largely in the claim that
only if we drop the whole idea of 'corresponding with reality' can we avoid
pseudoproblems"; it may be less a "theory of truth" than "an explanation of
why, in this area, less is more- of why therapy is better than system-building."
But he combines this theoretical minimalism about truth with a quite substantial
and properly controversial understanding of knowledge. To have not mere belief
130 BARRY ALLEN
or opinion but knowledge is to have the belief plus the agreement of some
community. Knowledge is not "a relation between mind and an object," but
merely "the ability to get agreement by using persuasion rather than force."
Insofar as Rorty's pragmatist makes a distinction between knowledge and
opinion, "it is simply the distinction between topics on which such [unforced]
agreement is relatively easy to get and topics on which agreement is relatively
hard to get." Having reduced knowledge to nothing more than a socio-political
"right, by current standards, to believe," Rorty is only being consistent when he
declares that "we are well on the way to seeing conversation as the ultimate
context within which knowledge is to be understood." 18
This colloquial conception of knowledge disables any "philosophical" or
"epistemological" criticism of anything that manages to elicit unforced
agreement and pass for knowledge. None of this is any more or less knowledge,
and, as Wittgenstein said, philosophy must leave everything as it is. Rorty does
not so much revive the pragmatic tradition as overcome what, from a
Nietzschean perspective, are its limitations, and then take a step from Nietzsche
to Wittgenstein, to the idea of tradition as pseudoproblem and philosophy as
therapy. Any idea of what else (if not epistemology) philosophy could be
disappears in the swirl of Rorty' s debunking of what philosophy has been since
the Enlightenment. In the process he transforms pragmatism into something its
founders never dreamed of: A philosophy for those who have lost confidence
in the value of philosophy. The result is less a new pragmatism than an
unintentional demonstration of Nietzsche's observation that "all great things
bring about their destruction through an act of self-overcoming: (GM III: 27).
On the contrary, I find it truer, more desirable and mysterious every year- ever since the day when
the great liberator came to me: the idea that life could be an experiment of the seeker for
knowledge (Experiment des Erkennenden)- and not a duty, not a calamity, not trickery.- And
knowledge itself: let it be something else for others; for example, a bed to rest on, or the way to
such a bed, or a diversion, or a form of leisure- for me it is a world of dangers and victories in
which heroic feelings, too, find places to dance and play. "Life as a means to knowledge"- with
this principle in one's heart one can live not only boldly but even gaily, and laugh gaily, too. And
who knows how to laugh anyway and live well if he does not first know a good deal about war and
victory? (GS 324)
Hans Blumenberg reminds us that for the Greeks of the classical period
knowledge was not supposed to make practical life possible; it was to perfect
the happiness of a life lived in retirement from the need to make a living. "That
life was pleasanter for one who knew than for one who sought knowledge was
a premise Aristotle took for granted; it corresponded to his concept of God, and
especially to his physics of finite space, [which implied] finite natural motions
justified only by- and ending in- a goal-state of rest." The promised connec-
tion between purely theoretical knowing and happiness was predicated on the
assumption that truth discloses the self-identity of beings-in-themselves, and
ALL THE DARING OF THE LOVER OF KNOWLEDGE 131
that the good of that disclosure somehow goes without saying (why the
sojourner in the cave ventures beyond the shadows in the first place Plato never
explains). To make a coherent break with Aristotle, the new experimental
natural philosophy of the seventeenth century "had to reconstruct the connection
between cognitive truth and finding happiness in a different way." Bacon, for
instance, carefully separates the pursuit of knowledge from both ethical
excellence (virtue) and existential fulfillment (eudaimonia, flourishing,
happiness). Bacon's inductive drudge need not and indeed should not have any
coherent ethical understanding that connects the knowledge he seeks as a man
of science with the "selfish" (or sellf-fashioning) happiness that he naturally
seeks for himself. In Bacon's imaginary institution of science "it [is] sufficient
if the combination of everyone's theoretical achievements guarantee[s] a state
of stable domination over reality, a state of which the individual could be a
beneficiary even without having insight into the totality of its conditions. The
subject of theory and the subject of the successful life no longer need to be
identical." 19
Another early-modern revaluation concerns error, which is relieved of its
moral taint; no longer a sign of viciousness, error is as it were decriminalized.
Having cast off the moral inhibitions that used to connect the pursuit of
operational knowledge with the ethical life of the knower, error can no longer
make sense as a sign of moral fault. The motto of Enlightenment, Sapere aude!
(Dare to know!), implicitly also means Dare to err! Dare mischance! The
marked nervousness about method among natural philosophers in the seven-
teenth and eighteenth centuries corresponds with an equally marked repudiation
of all the old fixed points. "Method" is the only compass for those who depart
on Bacon's new seas. The more reassuring the philosophical blather about
method, the more careless, daring, risky, and potentially enlightening experi-
mental knowledge was free to become.
Alchemists, innocent of correct methodology, were in their way far more
rigorous about error than any practitioner of modern experimental science.
According to the West's most authoritative Arabic source, the eighth-century
Shi'ite Jiibir ibn Hayyiin ("Gerber"), the alchemist's art "is reserved in the
divine will of God, and is given to, or withheld from, whom he will."
And perhaps for the punishment of your sophistical work God denies you the art, and lamentably
thrusts you into the by-paths of error, and from your error into perpetual infelicity and wretched-
ness; for he is most miserable and unhappy to whom, after the end of his work and labor, God
denies the sight of truth. For such a man is doomed to perpetual labor, beset with misfortune and
infelicity, loseth the consolation, joy, and delight of this life, and consumes his whole time in grief
without profit. 20
a
On the same day my dear wife sickened, being Friday, at the same time of day, namely in the
evening, my gracious God did put into my heart the Secret of extracting the oyle of Halcali, which
I had once accidentally found att the Pinner of Wakefield, in the dayes of my most dear wife. But
it was again taken from mee by a most wonderful! judgment of God, for I could never remember
how I did it, but made a hundred attempts in vain. And now my glorious God (whose name bee
praysed for ever) hath brought it again into my mind, and on the same day my dear wife sickened;
and on the Saturday following, which was the day shee dyed on, I extracted it by the former
practice: soe that on the same dayes, which proved the most sorrowfull to mee, whatever can bee:
God was pleased to conferre upon mee ye greatest joy I can ever have in this world, after her
death 22
the court position he obtained though his discovery of the Medician stars,
Galileo "was expected to maintain a high profile by producing new philosophi-
cal claims and engaging in controversial debates." A "realist" (or non-
hypothetical) interpretation of Copernicus helped Galileo sustain his effort to
refashion himself from a mathematician, good for casting horoscopes and
erecting fortifications, into what he most wanted to be - philosopher to the
Grand Duke of Tuscany. 24
Bacon also shares the esoteric idealization of operational knowledge, but
instead of perpetuating the facade of its awesome power, he published the only
real secret of "secret knowledge": that it does not work. He thereby forces an
issue that the esoteric tradition had been able to evade in its old argument with
the Church: Can the magical operator really operate? Christian theologians
called the pursuit of "forbidden knowledge" vain, not because they thought such
knowledge was impossible or could not do what it claimed to be able to do, but
because they thought that whatever powers the operator may win from the black
arts would eventually cost him his eternal soul. Unlike these theologians, who
implicitly confirm the magus's supposed power, Bacon calls the magician's
bluff; the fact is, he cannot operate. Yet the experimental knowledge Bacon
seeks is exactly what the esoteric tradition promised: The capacity to "disclose
and bring forward (though it has never yet been done) things which neither the
vicissitudes of nature, nor the industry of experiment, nor chance itself, would
ever have brought about." Such knowledge, the pinnacle of Baconian science,
merits the name of magic "in its ancient and honorable sense," namely, "that
science, which leads to the knowledge of hidden forms, for producing great
effects, and by joining agents to patients setting the capital works of nature to
view"- though it has never yet been done. 25
Bacon carefully strips away all links between the desire for magical knowl-
edge and the furtiveness of the heretic or the esoteric secrecy of the magus. His
experimentalist is an inductive drudge, the very anti-type of a Renaissance
magus. "My way of discovering sciences goes far to level men's wits, and
leaves but little to individual excellence." Reorganized as he proposes, the
pursuit of natural knowledge "leaves but little work for genius and mental
abilities." "We have greater hopes from our constant concentration with nature
than from our force of genius." 26 Bacon's "liberation" of the desire for once-
forbidden knowledge also displaces responsibility for the consequences of
effective, operational knowledge from individuals to an authoritarian institution.
It is no longer the responsibility of those who pursue knowledge to see to its
right use; use, or application, is to be a political responsibility discharged by the
bureaucracy assigned to oversee the production of experimental knowledge.
Bacon did not envision the publicity of experimental knowledge, for which, on
the contrary, he suggested a new and more rigorous mode of secrecy: Not the
ruses of hermetism but a more stringent codification of the language of
knowledge. Bacon's is a vision of the experimental life disciplined by a method
designed to bore the amateur, silence the heretic, and reorganize the production
of knowledge along corporate lines within an institution whose walls cannot be
broached by the undisciplined outsider. 27
134 BARRY ALLEN
Do you really believe that the sciences would ever have originated and grown if the way had not
been prepared by magicians, alchemists, astrologers, and witches whose promises and pretensions
first had to create a thirst, a hunger, a taste for hidden and forbidden powers? Indeed, infinitely
more had to be promised than could ever be fulfilled in order that anything at all might be fulfilled
in the realm of knowledge. (GS 300)
When Nietzsche calls for philosophers who have reconquered their "courage
for error, for experimentation, for accepting provisionally (D 501), he makes a
mix of the "modern" imperative to dare mischance with the classical Greek idea
that knowledge is not supposed to make everyday material life possible but
rather to perfect the happiness of the happy few. However catastrophic error
may be, it could not be worse than the life of unknowing complacency of
Nietzsche's "last men," men who do not, will not, depart from themselves,
question themselves, or dare knowledge. A life in which nothing is tried,
nothing dared, is wasted, worth nothing. Knowledge is not knowledge unless it
is in continual flux, contested, threatened with error, leading and misleading
alike. Knowledge and error are not opposites; knowledge is the refinement of
error (BGE 24 ). They are a necessary pair, and mischance a necessary risk, if
one is enticed by the prospect of life as an experiment of knowledge. We have,
if anything, been deficient in errors; "the greatest sacrifices have not yet been
offered to knowledge" (D 501 ). The way of wisdom leads not to last things but
new contests, new seas. "Unconcerned, mocking, violent- thus wisdom want
us: she is a woman and always loves only a warrior" (Z Reading and Writing).
Experimental knowledge need not imply a strict and rigorous methodology.
The myth of methodology was one of the ways seventeenth-century thought
tried to discipline the experimental life. But experimentation can be disciplined
(rigorous) without being disciplinary, without dressage. Nor must the passion
for knowledge be a passion for the truth, conceived as the terminus of inquiry,
where the labor of knowledge comes to rest. Nietzsche also refuses to let the
good of knowledge disappear in a utilitarian abstraction. Instead of seeking its
fulfillment elsewhere, in something that knowledge is good for, life itself
becomes an experiment of knowledge (GS 324 ).
In this way Nietzsche reintroduces the aesthetic-existential dimension to the
pursuit of knowledge that Bacon, Boyle, and other Enlightenment thinkers
anxiously omitted when they appropriated the esoteric ideal of experimental
knowledge. The experimental life becomes what it had been before the
ALL THE DARING OF THE LOVER OF KNOWLEDGE 135
"Perhaps nobody has yet been truthful enough about what 'truthfulness' is"
(BGE 177). Truth, as classical philosophy conceives it, subordinates the pursuit
of knowledge to the contemplative telos of an intuitive representation. Conse-
quently it must have the experimental conscience against it. A true representa-
tion is not the ultimate goal of experimental knowledge but only a chimera and
a specious limitation. The experimental life is not a search for truth, not if truth
is something that should stop the contest, stop the arguments, the agon, and risk
of mischance. Hence Nietzsche's "experiment" with truth, suspending the
presumptive value of "that famous truthfulness of which all philosophers so far
have spoken with respect" (BGE 1).
The will to truth requires a critique- let us thus define our own task- the value of truth must for
once be experimentally called into question. (GM III: 24)
After Christian truthfulness has drawn one inference after another, it must end by drawing its most
striking inference, its inference against itself; this will happen, however, when it poses the
question "what is the meaning of all will to truth?"
And here again I touch on my problem, on our problem, my unknown friends (for as yet I know
of no friend): What meaning would our whole being possess if it were not this, that in us the will
to truth becomes conscious of itself as a problem? (GM III: 27)
all those things and questions which do not permit experiments. This is the limit
of my 'truthfulness'; for there courage has lost its rights" (GS 51).
Unlike the onto-logical truthfulness of knowledge, the ethical truthfulness of
the knower concerns not final perception but evolving conception, presupposing
constant change rather than eternal order, its circumstantial mutability, not its
eternal permanence, being partly what confirms a conception as knowledge
rather than dogma or doctrine.
The view that truth is found and that ignorance and error are at an end is one of the most potent
seductions there is. Supposing it is believed, then the will to examination, investigation, caution,
experiment is paralyzed. 'Truth" is therefore more fateful than error and ignorance. because it cuts
off the forces that work toward enlightenment and knowledge. (WP 452)
The "more laudable truthfulness" of the knower (rather than the knowledge)
primarily consists not in the beliefs one holds, nor in the sincerity with which
one communicates them, but in the questions one asks, in incertitude and
intellectual restlessness, in the daring with which one experiments and loves the
search for new knowledge.
Take care, you philosophers and friends of knowledge, and beware of martyrdom! Of suffering
"for the sake of the truth"! ... [A]s though "the truth" were such an innocuous and incompetent
creature as to require protectors! and you of all people, you knights of the most sorrowful
countenance, dear loafers and cobweb-spinners of the spirit! ... you know that no philosopher so
far has been proved right, and that there might be a more praiseworthy truthfulness (preiswiir-
digere Wahrhaftigkeit) in every little question mark that you place after your favorite words and
favorite theories (and occasionally after yourselves). (BGE 25; cf. GM III: 8)
the scientific method was grasped and promoted by those who divined in it a weapon of war- an
instrument of destruction - To make their opposition honorable, they needed, moreover, an
apparatus similar in kind to that used by those they were attacking: - they adopted the concept
"truth" just as ostentatiously and unconditionally as their opponents - they became fanatics, at
least they posed as such, because no other pose was taken seriously. What remained to be done
was accomplished by persecution, passion and the insecurity of the persecuted- hatred grew and
consequently the precondition for remaining scientific was diminished. Ultimately, they all wanted
to be right in the same absurd fashion as their opponents- ... As martyrs they compromised their
own deed. (WP 457)
ALL THE DARING OF THE LOVER OF KNOWLEDGE 137
is so very important! ... The greatest sacrifices have not yet been offered to
knowledge" (D 501).
Here I think we see an ancient prejudice that Nietzsche did not know how to
question: that the best knowledge belongs to the lucky few whose freedom to
live an experimental life is sustained by those who must work to get their living.
Nietzsche's conception of the best knowledge as that won from the risk of
(possibly fatal) mischance reflects this assumption that the knowledge he seeks
is somehow higher, better, truer than the workaday knowledge of practical
material-technical culture. In a silly passage, he says that it is "we thinkers who
first have to determine the palpableness of things and, if necessary, decree it.
Practical people in the end take it from us, their dependence on us is incon-
ceivably great and the most ludicrous spectacle in the world, however little they
may realize it and however proudly they may love to ignore us impractical
people; indeed, they should deprecate their practical life if we should choose to
deprecate it: - a thing to which a little desire for revenge might now and then
incite us" (D 505). It is probably safe to say that this idea gets matters exactly
backwards. The "relativism" that one hears so much about today is the work of
this spirit of revenge, as are other recent fads in philosophy, including decon-
struction and postmodemism. These tendencies are not, however, merely silly;
for we need the knowledge they pretend were no different from any arbitrary
"hegemonic" doctrine or mythology. Despite their sophistry, knowledge and
doctrine, knowledge and opinion, knowledge and consensus, knowledge and
what passes for known are not the same, nor will they ever be so long as human
beings have a serious future on this planet.
Nietzsche may think that because truthfulness is an ethical matter first and
last, because it is a question of ethos, of self-fashioning, or an aesthetics of
existence, that means the only "being" there is to be true to is oneself. This
romantic egoism is pale and limited beside the more challenging goal of erotic
truthfulness to another. The freedom to experiment, to risk error, has to be
tempered by a profoundly "unNietzschean" respect for consequences, and for
the consequences of consequences for others. Another disturbing quality of our
"academic-technoscientific complex" is that it does very little to limit our
exposure to such risks, while living off our willingness to alienate the produc-
tion and circulation of powerful, technical, how-to knowledge to self-certified
academic and professional experts, on the false assumption that this division of
epistemic labor makes us safer and smarter.
NOTES
1 Bertrand Russell probably speaks for many philosophers when he says, "what we firmly
believe, if it is true, is called knowledge ... what we firmly believe, if it is not true, is called error."
The Problems of Philosophy (London. 1912; Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1978), p. 81.
' A. J. Ayer. The Problem of Knowledge (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1956), p. 25.
3 On Faustus, see Michael Keefer, Christopher Marlowe ·s "Doctor Faustus": A 1604-version
Edition (Peterborough, Ont.: Broadview Press, 1991 ), pp. xxxvii-xlv; and loan P. Couliano. Eros
and Magic in the Renaissance, trans. M. Cook (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987). chap.
ALL THE DARING OF THE LOVER OF KNOWLEDGE 139
10. On Simon Magus and Ham, see Valerie Flint, The Rise of Magic in Early Medieval Europe
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1991), pp. 337-338, 341-342. On forbidden knowledge,
my "Forbidding Knowledge," The Monist 79 ( 1996): 294-310.
4 Francis Bacon, Novum Organum I, CXXIV; Paolo Rossi, "Truth and Utility in the Science of
Francis Bacon," Philosophy, Technology, and the Arts in the Early Modern Era, trans. S. Attanasio
~New York: Harper & Row, 1970), pp. 160-161.
On magic and religious deviance, see C. A. Faraone and D. Obbink, ed. Magika Hiera: Ancient
Greek Magic and Religion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), p. vii. On magic and the
Royal Society, see Charles Webster, From Paracelsus to Newton: Magic and the Making of
Modern Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1982), and William Eamon, Science
and the Secrets of Nature: Books of Secrets in Medieval and Early Modern Culture (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1994 ), pp. 332-350.
6 See Steven Shapin, A Social History of Truth: Civility and Science in Seventeenth-Century
England (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1994 ), pp. 158, 173.
7 Ludwig Wittgenstein, Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans. D. F. Pears and B. F. McGuinness
~London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1961 ), 2.201, 2.21.
John McDowell, Mind and World (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1994), p. 162.
I describe the Greek, or classical interpretation of truth as "onto-logic" because its fundamental
assumption is that a logically consistent predication owes its possibility of being true to the antic
possibility of the entity whose being (existence and identity) makes it true. Logical possibilities
of truth and ontic possibilities of being are therefore exactly coextensive. See my Truth in
Philosophy (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993), esp. chap. I.
9 See Richard Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, Philosophical Papers, vol. I (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), pp. 2-12.
10 "Talk of 'representation of the facts' ... incorporates a philosophically correct- as we might
say, seriously dyadic- perspective on the truth predicate." Crispin Wright, Truth and Objectivity
(Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1992), p. 83.
11 Nietzsche, Nachlafi; cited in Babette E. Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science (Albany:
Body and Culture, trans. S. Hand (London: Athlone Press, 1991), p. 146.
13 Nietzsche, NachlajJ, cited in Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy, p. 103; see also GS 107, BGE 24,
and WP493.
14 James Reason, Human Error (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990), p. 9.
15 Some of the first German thinkers Nietzsche stimulated were aware of an affinity with
pragmatism, which Georg Simmel is supposed to have described as "the part of Nietzsche which
the Americans adopted." Rorty suggests that Nietzsche is "the figure who did most to convince
European intellectuals of the doctrines which were purveyed to Americans by James and Dewey."
Essays on Heidegger and Others (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), p. 2. On
Nietzsche and pragmatism, seeM. A. Weinstein, The Wilderness and the City: American Classical
Philosophy as a Moral Quest (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1982), esp. pp. 129-
137; and my 'Truth in America," Cohesion and Dissent in America, ed. C. Colatrella and J.
Alkana (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993).
16 Plato, Laws 730c.
17 Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), p.
XIII.
18 Rorty, Objectivity, Relativism, and Truth, pp. 132, 128, 88, 23; and Philosophy and the Mirror
existence," see Michel Foucault, "On the Genealogy of Ethics," in H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow,
Michel Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1983); and my "Foucault and Modern Political Philosophy," The Later Foucault, ed. J.
Moss (London: Sage, 1998).
22 The Magical Writings of Thomas Vaughan, ed. A. E. Waite (Kila, Mont.: Kessinger Publishing
Co., 1992), p. ix.
140 BARRY ALLEN
23 Jerome R. Ravetz, Scientific Knowledge and its Social Problems (Oxford: Oxford University
~Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1993), pp. 5, 100, 105, 156, 149.
5 Bacon, Novum Organum II. 3 (my emphasis); and The Advancement of Learning III, 5; cf.
Novum Organum II, XI. The eleventh-century Byzantine philosopher Michael Psellus defined
magic as natura/is philosophiae absoluta consummatio. The definition was repeated by nearly all
of the philosophical defenders of magic from Ficino and Pico to Agrippa, Gasper Schott, and
friends of the Royal Society, including Elias Ashmole and Seth Ward.
26 Bacon, cited in R. F. Jones, Ancients and Moderns: A Study of the Rise of the Scientific
Movement in Seventeenth-Century England, revised ed. (St. Louis: Washington University Press,
1936, 1961; rpt. New York: Dover, 1982), p. 55; and Advancement of Learning, Preface.
27 See J. C. Briggs, Francis Bacon and the Rhetoric of Nature (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1989), pp. 8-9, 41; and Bacon, New Atlantis (Kila, Mont.: Kessinger Publishing
Co., 1992), pp. 303, 321, 330, 331-332.
28 Nietzsche, Nachlaj3, in Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, p. 104
29 It is perhaps doubtful that Diderot would subscribe to this characterization of atheism. In a
letter to Voltaire (1749) he writes, "It is ... very important not to mistake hemlock for parsley; but
to believe or not to believe in God is not so important at all." SeeM. J. Buckley, At the Origins
o[ Modern Atheism (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1987), p. 225.
3 On Nietzsche and Enlightenment atheism, see my "Atheism, Relativism, Enlightenment, and
Truth," Studies in Religion 23 (1994): 167-177.
JUSTIN BARTON
141
B. Babich ( ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 141-149.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
142 JUSTIN BARTON
in this sense is mostly done by people who are not called philosophers - by
artists and scientists and social theorists (Nietzsche would have used Goethe as
an example at this point, and he would have added that some philosophers have
to some extent been refused acceptance as was the case with Schopenhauer).
Very obviously it is also the case that the non-philosophical domains and micro-
domains of creation/development of problems (which are also ideas) continually
undergo intensifying transformations that have nothing to do with the function-
ing of philosophy.
For Nietzsche, the central issue that can illustrate what is at stake here would
be the problem of what lines of transformation of human thought/activity can
be opened up (and are being opened up) in the context, and in part through the
analysis of, the decaying constricting functions of concepts such as the divine,
teleology, transcendent morality and truth, representational negation, and
identity. To explore these issues - in relation always to specific domains of
constitution - is to diagram the relations between the elements at work
(functions of constriction and tendencies toward transformation) and it is to
critique in the sense of breaking open directions that are in excess of those being
accessed by the current framework of constitution of activity. This is not so
much to be seen as revealing what is the case - partly because what is the case
is in principle utterly in excess of any level of constitution - it is to intensify the
thinking involved, and this in tum means to intensify activity, because there is
no excluding distinction between thought and activity (thought is the term that
gets used for one end of the spectrum of creative activity, which is another way
of saying that creative activity is the term that gets used for one end of the
spectrum of thought ... ).
Up to a point, nothing has changed here in relation to the issue of truth. It is
still a question of rigorous analysis, and it is still for now a question, from a
certain unimportant perspective, of there being elements, continually being
added to, and continually being removed, functioning as constants within fields
of thought ("Are they new friends of 'truth,' these coming philosophers? In all
probability: for all philosophers have hitherto loved their truths" [BGE 43]).
And moreover it is a question, in part, of an intensifying of the process of the
realisation, the bringing into effect, of new problematics, and new solutions,
which was what was always at stake in any non-reactive discussion of truth.
However in relation to the issues of philosophy and of thought in general the
role of truth has been displaced. Truth is no longer pivotal for understanding
processes of knowledge, because it is only a background stabilising aspect of
what these processes do (in a similar way to the way in which grammar is only
a stabilising aspect of the functioning of language). Knowledge processes
(which include philosophy) can no longer be seen as dedicated to truth, any
more than a human body can be seen as dedicated to its kidneys. And what is
more, it is important to realise that the vigilant constitution of philosophy and
the acquiring of knowledge as dedicated to truth has been nothing other than a
constriction of its activity. This is what Nietzsche means by his aphorism in
Beyond Good and Evil: "'Knowledge for its own sake'- this is the last snare set
by morality: one therewith gets completely entangled in morality once more"
HOW EPISTEMOLOGY BECOMES WHAT IT IS 143
(BGE 64). The other way of coming at the displacement is the fact that thought
is not about representation in any sense other than constitution. The "moment"
of positing something is a point in the constitution of a field of problems, or of
a set of strategies for handling problems, or of a field of activity in the widest
sense. It makes sense to talk about, say, the representation of a thing as x, but
only in this sense of constitution. Philosophy for Nietzsche is generative, rather
than representational. Philosophy diagrams and critiques, employing (initially)
a thought of a continual excess of constitutability over constitution, involving
continually escalating circuits of the realisation of new forms of thought, that
is, new escaping forms of activity. Truth remains the same as it was, only
something more extraordinary (which was always the heart of the process) has
emerged to the point of explicitly shaping strategies, and it is into this new
conception that truth has been inserted. Everything that was at stake is now
taken up into the idea of an accelerated wave of actualisation that refuses the
classical distinction between appearance and reality, because it has recognised
that the thought of new domains of constitution pressing toward mobilisation
from an "immanent noumenon" is in fact the thought of the continual emerging
of an intensified reality - "reality once more, only selected, strengthened,
corrected." 1 The outside as part of the inside. Immanence.
Taking up the problem of genealogy is a crucial way of extending the main
ideas at stake here. Genealogy is the study of the tensions and of the field of
functioning problems at the inception of an institution or a discipline, and it is
the study of the overall trajectory, on the part of the institution/discipline, of
external struggles, assimilations, and exclusions. Genealogy is not directly about
disproving institutionalised metaphysical claims. Nor is it helpful to think about
it simply in terms of uncovering origins, partly because there is more to the
basic process than this (development beyond the inception is crucial as well),
but mostly because genealogy is about breaking open new lines of thought, and
new lines of transformation, through rigorously taking the whole of the past as
a resource of important exclusions and of forgotten or suppressed initial aims.
Genealogy is therefore coming into focus as, in part, a modality of critique. If
a scientist begins to look at long buried "heretical" work, or work which no-one
could see an application for (as with the physicist Fiegenbaum tracking down
Goethe's work on coloud they are beginning to practice genealogy. A
mathematician studying the manifestations of mathematics that were abandoned
with the instigation of calculus is doing genealogy. It becomes obvious that
genealogy is an idea which has been functioning at a relatively low level of
subtlety. This is partly because Nietzsche made only occasional direct refer-
ences, which have failed to generate a widened scope. It is also because the
work which uses the idea in the title has a project which is easily interpreted as
simply negative - rather than being seen in terms of the self-overcoming of
morals. The Genealogy of Morals has recurrently been seen as simply a
methodologically aberrant set of proofs of the falsity of certain metaphysical
positions. So far as this last issue is concerned, it is important to recognise that
the whole of Nietzsche's engagement with the history of philosophy is geneal-
ogy, and here it is perhaps more obvious that the aim is to create new directions,
144 JUSTIN BARTON
in part through the taking up into the circuit of what has been left behind or
suppressed. Nietzsche has Zarathustra say "He who has grown wise concerning
old origins, behold, he will at last seek new springs of the future and new
origins." 3 This leads on to the problem of thinking of genealogical method only
in terms of origins. The point here can be made by reference to the fact that in
his preface to The Genealogy of Morals Nietzsche says that what is needed in
relation to the issue of morals is "knowledge of the conditions and circum-
stances in which they grew" and "under which they evolved and changed." 4
Genealogy is an intricately relational method which stresses the complexities of
the inception of the institution studied, but is also dedicated to analysing the
pressures and internal rifts of its overall development. Deleuze is perhaps failing
to capture this point in Nietzsche and Philosophy when he says "Genealogy [... ]
means origin or birth, but also distance or difference in the origin." 5 However,
it can be said at this stage that including the whole 'trajectory' in a way gives
you the same idea, only at a higher level of effectiveness. This is because in
terms of their past the current manifestations of an institution (or a social
practise, a discipline, an art medium. .. ) have the whole line of their development
as their origin. And Deleuze does incorporate the crucial point about the
intensificatory nature of genealogy when he writes about the "differential
element" of both genealogy and critique, and then goes on to say "The differen-
tial element is both a critique of the value of values and the positive element of
a creation." 6 Foucault also goes a long way in this direction in his essay
"Nietzsche, Genealogy, History." He says that the "search for descent [... ]
shows the heterogeneity of what was imagined consistent with itself'7 and later
he goes on to say:
History becomes "effective'" to the degree that it introduces discontinuity into our very being- as
it divides. dramatises our instincts, multiplies our body and sets it against itself. "Effective'" history
deprives the self of the reasuring stability of life and nature, and it will not permit itself to be
transported toward a milennial ending. It will uproot its traditional foundations and relentlessly
disrupt its pretended continuity.
This is because knowledge is not made for understanding; it is made for cutting. 8
The problem is that this account is built around the idea of differentiation
within genealogy, but it fails to concentrate on the intensificatory circuit that
genealogy is as a process. Which is partly to say that it fails to see the process
properly as the generation of new lines of thought (new dimensions of becom-
ing); as the production of new problematics, new ideas. Foucault is on the edge
of this way of thinking, but the problem is that a reaction against thought being
conceived in terms of identity has lead to it being conceived in terms of
differentiation. This is partly right, but thought is also generation of problems,
constitution of fields of problems, and interpretation within these fields. And
Foucault's concentration on "cutting" and on "dividing," in the absence of any
strong account of the overall circuit, is liable to allow his thought to be taken
back into a structure of the revealing of static lines of originary, suppressed
difference, as opposed to the idea of the production of mutant lines of thought
through the heightened contact between the "present" and that other part of the
HOW EPISTEMOLOGY BECOMES WHAT IT IS 145
rather than assisting it through analysis (even though this will not always have
been true in many of the cases). Among the suppressively functioning concepts
here (to give another non-inclusive list) are identity, negation, the subject, the
object, purpose, universality ...
Some subtle shifts have taken place now. The contention in relation to the
inhibitory functioning of concepts in the domain (concepts functioning not as
instigators of lines of thought, but as blocking elements) is a first piece of
diagramming. It lays out an empirically testable and alterable relation between
the functioning of certain concepts in the domain and the development of the
field of the generation of knowledge. In part this is to say that in order to
understand knowledge better it is necessary to take part in a critique of the
representation of it (it is important to point out that that this is not the illusion
-which Nietzsche explicity attacks- of a critique of knowledge as a whole, 9 but
the critique of a particular knowledge institution) but, more importantly, it is to
say that epistemology is in part responsible for a negative aspect of what it
studies - knowledge in general. Clearly this negative aspect is not something
that can be regarded as external to the field of epistemology - the first aspect of
an excess in relation to the ideas of the domain appears here. This is therefore
not a weak claim to the effect that some of the concepts of epistemology are in
need of modification: in fact the claim is that the representation of knowledge
is not only caught up to some extent in inneffective ways of thinking, but is a
"dark workshop" that functions in many ways as an inhibitor of what it studies
(the question as to how this happens also becomes important at this stage:
Nietzsche's account of this centres around the reactive, transcendence values of
Christianity).
Another crucial shift is at work in there-articulation of knowledge in terms
of a generative (creative) process which does not involve unified subjects.
Instead, the account Nietzsche advances of what had been called the "subject"
involves an immanently interacting multiplicity of centres or drives, which
make up the constituting "ends" of a radiating zone of relations of incur-
sion/constitution. And the crucial aspect of the domain of knowledge here is its
genetic aspect: the aspect which in the case of the generation of new lines of
thought involves an encounter which takes the form, in part, of a transformation
of the faculties and concepts at work so that the encounter can become an idea
rather than just a fascination. What this means is that the "subject" is not just
multiple, it is is also such that it can undergo a shift in its faculties and concepts
as a result of the incursion of something new, so that the knowledge o.fwhat is
the problem being worked on will only appear at the point where the initial
solution appears. And what this means in turn for Nietzsche is that less time
should be spent on looking for a criterion of certainty, and for fixed. justifiable
categories (given that the whole field of knowledge is constantly altering) and
more time should be spent studying the fields of conditions under which
thinking takes place. The intensifying of this element of the genetic, of the
creative, is what Nietzsche holds to be at stake here: it is what causes him to say
that "the question of certainty' is "a dependent question, a question of the
HOW EPISTEMOLOGY BECOMES WHAT IT IS 147
second rank," (WP 587) and it is what lies behind this attack- "The desire for
'solid facts"- epistemology: how much pessimism there is in it!" (WP 591)
This overall account of the representation of knowledge, and of that with
which it is engaged, forms a very complex diagram, a diagram with different
kinds of dimensions (it is heterogeneity of dimensions which is here being used
as the defining aspect of what are being called diagrams). The dimension of
networks of faculties, the dimension of interactions/capacities, the dimension
of suppresive institutional conceptual systems, the dimension of encounters, the
dimension of lines of becoming. Here, in the lines of thought through which this
diagram is manifested, is the crucial, immense, excess in relation to the ideas of
the domain of conventional epistemology. The diagram is a set of strategic,
methodological coordinates. What Nietzsche has instigated here is not episte-
mology in any conventional sense of the word. But then atonal music was also
villified in a way which is structurally the same as the way in which Nietzsche
is dismissed- as "not really being music."
The issue of values has not been left behind. It has been at work in the form
of a process of comparison of modalities, strategies, and methods ("The most
valuable insights are arrived at last, but the most valuable insights are methods"
(WP 469) ), and this process has been bound up with the idea that there are
assumptions of unity, regularity and identity that express themselves as
strategies of thinking and living that are constrictive, relative to other modes.
This is what Nietzsche is arguing towards in this note: "The question of values
is more fundamental than the question of certainty: the latter becomes serious
only by presupposing that the value question has already been answered" (WP
588). What is being shown to be that which must be "passed by" is an ultimately
religiously sustained privileging of regularity, which hampers experimentation,
and which treats the analysis of, or of how to attain, algorithmically functioning,
fixed elements (truths, certainties) as the key to understanding and furthering
knowledge processes, rather than this key being the analysis and fostering of
networks of ideas and strategies which have (as a whole, and individually) a
plasticity and non-transparency of functioning which is a response to the
plasticity and complexity of the "Dionysian" world of which they are a part, and
with which they are engaging. The immanent play of functionally non-specific
elements, with its mergings and emergences, and with its predominant absence
of the mechanistic constriction of governing codes (the immanent play which
Nietzsche calls the "will to power"), engaged with in turn by the play of an
extension of itself in the form of the irreverent experiments, and diagrammings
of processes of knowledge. It is not a question of fields of knowledge converg-
ing on the truth, it is a question of institutionalised (and non-institutional)
methods coming to have more in common with the vast majority of that which
they study., and therefore, of an intensification of the mutual becoming between
the two.
What is it to say that Nietzsche is writing through the untimely perspective
of an immanent "outside"? To use one of his own terms, it is to say that he is
writing beyond "gravity," beyond the gravitational fields of particular domains
of conceptual articulations. More broadly, the 'outside' is an aspect of all
148 JUSTIN BARTON
NOTES
1 Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, in Twilight of the Idols/The Anti-Christ, trans.
R.J.Hollingdale (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1990), p. 49.
2 For an account of this, see James Gleick, Chaos: The Making of a New Science (London:
Abacus, 1987), p.l64.
3 Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. R.J.Hollingdale (Harmondsworth: Penguin,
1961), in "Of Old and New Law-Tables," p. 228.
4 Friedrich Nietzsche, On The Genealogy Of Morals, trans. W.Kaufman and R.J.Hollingdale
~New York: Random House, 1967), Preface, section 6, p.20. My Italics
Gilles Deleuze, Nietzsche and Philosophy (London: Athlone, 1983), p.2.
6 Ibid. p.2.
7 Michel Foucault, Language, Counter-Memory, Practice (New York: Cornell Univ. Press,
1977), p.147.
8 Ibid., p. 154.
9 "A critique of the faculty of knowledge is senseless: how should a tool be able to criticize itself
when it can use only itself for the critique?" (WP 486).
10 The works of Deleuze (and Deleuze and Guattari) are a very influential presence behind many
of the ideas at work in this essay, although not so much the Deleuze of Nietzsche and Philosophy.
A crucial coordinate is the brilliant chapter "The Image of Thought' in De leuze's Diffe renee and
Repetition" (London: Athlone, 1994). For Deleuze/Guattari's indispensable (and more complex)
versions of the ideas of lines of becoming and diagrams see Anti-Oedipus (London: Athlone, 1984)
and A Thousand Plateaus (London: Athlone, 1988) (only A Thousand Plateaus for diagrams). It
needs to be said, following from this, that the works of Nietzsche are in turn a strong presence
behind those of Deleuze and Guattari, and therefore it is not surprising that their writings are
valuable in trying to give an account of Nietzsche's thought.
11 See BGE l88.
DUNCAN LARGE
Michel Serres is one of the most prolific and increasingly influential contempo-
rary thinkers who has analysed developments in philosophy, literature, and
across the arts against the backdrop of the history of science in a series of highly
original interdisciplinary studies which collectively represent one of the most
illuminating contributions to bridging the divide between "the two cultures."
One of the many ways in which Serres stands out among philosophers of his
generation in France is by his antipathy to Nietzsche, for where Nietzsche styles
himself "the last disciple of the philosopher Dionysus,"' Serres places his own
work under the sign of a different deity, Hermes, and devotes five volumes to
his celebration, the first of which (1968) concludes with an opposition of the
two gods- respectively, "the father of Tragedy" and "the father of Comedy" 2
- which sets Serres programmatically at odds with "Nietzsche's French
Moment." 3
Serres continues to engage with Nietzsche thereafter, and references and
allusions to Nietzsche are in fact scattered throughout his writings: he occasion-
ally uses a word "in a Nietzschean sense," 4 his writings are peppered with
Nietzschean dicta quoted en passant; 5 and he is best known to Nietzschean
commentators through a full-length article which first appeared in Hermes IV,
"Corruption- The Antichrist: A Chemistry of Sensations and Ideas."6
In general, Serres refuses to be swayed by Nietzsche's rhetoric of radical
novelty and consummate self-promotion. Approaching Nietzsche's philosophy
from the perspective of the history of science, Serres reads it as an interesting
but ultimately misguided historical document, merely an episode in the
dissemination of scientific ideas across nineteenth century culture, a typical late-
nineteenth century reaction to the truly innovative theoretical work which had
been carried out at least fifty years before, in the natural sciences in general and
the field of thermodynamics in particular. There is something deliberately
provocative about Serres's brand of scientistic reductivism, which sees the death
of God and the eternal return precisely prefigured in the schemas of Poinsot, for
example. 7 [n one sense it is an extremely Nietzschean reading of Nietzsche -
Serres plays Nietzsche at his own game by reading his philosophy in a sympto-
matological, genealogical, and ungenerously iconoclastic fashion, predating his
supposed "innovations" to distant predecessors and reducing this self-declared
151
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 151-159.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
152 DUNCAN LARGE
"Philosophers sing Nietzsche's praises for having suddenly linked back up with
the Greeks through his dazzling intuition of the Eternal Return," 8 Serres writes
in a short article in Hermes IV entitled simply "The Eternal Return,"9 but these
philosophers are wrong, or else short-sighted, he argues here, since Nietzsche
is in this respect merely a belated heir to a tradition which dates back, in its
modern form, to the end of the eighteenth century, to Laplace and Kant. 10 The
eternal return has about it what Serres calls elsewhere a "transhistorical
perenniality"; 11 with "his" theory of the eternal return, Nietzsche is merely
"recapitulating" an argument which is ultimately pre-Socratic in origin:
"Nietzsche rose at mid-day and his predecessors at dawn." 12 Across his work,
Serres repeatedly notes the ubiquity of "this universal form of the Return" 13 in
Nietzsche's age: the eternal return "remains a constant and a kind of tonality
maintained behind the philosophies of history"; 14 "it is the whole adventure of
the nineteenth century." 15 The lineage which Serres usually traces leads from
Kane 6 through Comte and Engels 17 up to Nietzsche- and beyond: "Nietzsche
would be more or less the last, had he not had imitators, Gustave Le Bon, Abel
Rey." 18 Outside of Serres's strictly philosophical and scientific genealogy, the
return is to be found also in Zola (above all in Doctor Pascal) and in Michelet
(The Sea), and it is an "essential idea" in Jules Verne (Hermes!).
If one wonders why this idea assumed such a central position in the ideologi-
cal complexion of the nineteenth century, Serres leaves one in no doubt: the
catalyst which led to its expanding into every corner of culture is the formula-
tion of the principles of thermodynamics: "the constancy of the eternal return
in the 19th century is a response to the theoretical and superstructural fact that
everyone was just constructing motors." 19 Nietzsche and thermodynamics?
Nothing could be more natural for Serres: "thermodynamics inaugurates a
history of gestures and metaphors, concepts and operations, from which I do not
see that we have yet emerged." 20 Nietzsche is thus inserted into the "serried"
ranks of philosophers, theoreticians, novelists, and painters who find inspiration
(for the most part an unconscious, subterranean inspiration) in the scientific and
technical revolution inaugurated in 1824 by Sadi Carnot, subsequently general-
ized by Mayer, Helmholtz, and Clausius: those who "no doubt did nothing but"
sketch out this new sptem, with its thermodynamic model, 21 those who "all
assembled a motor," 2 or in whose writings "the reservoir is expressed really
everywhere." 23 For Serres, the impact of Carnot's principles on culture in
general can be encapsulated in three key words which sum up the whole
ideology of the industrial revolution: "difference, reservoir, and circulation." 24
It is these "three fundamental notions" which "make their appearance with Sadi
Carnot and then spread everywhere into work, the world, and texts." 25
HERMES CONTRA DIONYSUS 153
ground noise" of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, 43 is the eternal return not in any case
once more the order of the day, plat du jour in the restaurant at the end of the
universe? The heat death of the universe is far from being a given in contempo-
rary cosmology, which presents us instead with a variety of possible eschato-
logical scenarios. These include the spawning of a near-infinite number of
"parallel universes" by quantum events, the eventual contraction of our
currently expanding universe towards a terminal singularity (the "big crunch"),
but also an infinite cycle of cosmic regeneration as the oscillating universe
"bounces back" from the brink into a phase of renewed expansion. 44 Cosmology
is currently a more open field than ever before, and there are too many variables
for the question of the ultimate fate of the universe to be definitively settled one
way or the other. Although Nietzsche's theory of eternal return purposely spurns
scientific validation, it might yet be vindicated by the very scientists whose
"mechanistic world-view" he so roundly condemned (GS 373 ).
PASTEURIZED PHILOSOPHY
Not only is Nietzsche's (meta)physics outdated in Serres's book(s), but so, too,
is his medicine, even if he introduces a new inflexion into the struggle against
entropy (and here Serres grants him a certain unwonted originality, if only as an
intermediary), since "it is Nietzsche who will introduce Pasteur into cultural
life." 45 The text in which Nietzsche performs this "pasteurization" of culture is
The Antichrist (1888), to which Serres devotes his most detailed analysis, his
article "Corruption- The Antichrist." Here he argues that, in this late text, "the
couple good-evil has rotated a quarter turn onto the couple healthy-sick, " 46 and
the archetypal sickness is Christianity perceived as "decay, decomposition,
contamination, and corruption."47 The Antichrist is thus "a handbook of
medicine [... ] -and dated medicine at that. [... ] The age of Pasteur dates this
text." Nietzsche here shows an obsession with purity and cleanliness; he recoils
before "the horror- puritan, Victorian, ascetic, phantasmatic- of dirtying one's
hands"; 48 he seeks to separate the sheep from the goats with the aid of a cordon
sanitaire. So he has become a decadent malgre lui: 49 in spite of the tenacious
criticism of the ascetic ideal which he has just carried out in the Third Essay of
On the Genealogy of Morals (1887), he has become its servant, and his oft-
vaunted overcoming of decadence is but an expression of it: "he writes a holy
book, a sacred text like any other." 50 When Nietzsche writes in Ecce Homo:
"there is nothing in me of a founder of a religion- religions are affairs of the
rabble; I find it necessary to wash my hands after I have come into contact with
religious people," 51 this denegatory gesture of Pontius Pilate is precisely what
makes him ... a founder of a religion.
Now Serres acknowledges that Nietzsche was not always this "partitioning
puritan," 52 and that previously he was even the very first to recognize the
(caseous) form of feedback which renders this kind of monomaniac frenzy
absurd. Was it not Nietzsche who previously sang the praises of hybridity,
heterogeneity, and heterogeny? 53 Let us not forget that the ''new world-
conception" which he was sketching out as late as the Spring of 1888 envisages
HERMES CONTRA DIONYSUS 155
a universe whose "excrements are its food" (WP 1066). So one must ask
whether The Antichrist really does mark a definitive volte-face, an absolute
denial of the "philosophy of mixed bodies" of before. To judge from his
hypothetical tone, Serres himself is not entirely sure: "if, without recomr,ense,
The Antichrist reverts to dichotomies, it indeed marks the breakdown." 4 It is
true that the characteristic physiologico-medicallexicon of The Antichrist55 is
an innovation of the period 1887-1888 which attests to Nietzsche's readin~ of
French theoreticians of decadence such as Paul Bourget and Charles Fere, 6 a
reading which at last gave him the means to become the "philosopher as cultural
physician" which he had been contemplating since 1873. Yet I would argue that,
even at the end of the last year of his philosophical career, Nietzsche continues
to recognize the tonicity, the necessity of sickness. His ideal is not the total
extirpation of Christianity, for excision is merely the weapon of the weakest
who have no other means of defending themselves - it is the speciality of the
Christians themselves. 57 No, Nietzsche recognizes right to the end the impor-
tance of having enemies and respecting them. "Whatever does not kill me makes
me stronger" (TI, Maxims 8) is a maxim he uses not only in Twilight of the
Idols, written immediately before The Antichrist, but also in Ecce Homo, written
immediately afterwards. "Michelet [... ] asserts in La montagne that one should
live in Sils--Maria. High, cold, pure places. Microbes are contracted at Genoa,
at Genoa where impurity takes the form of the treponema pallidum," 58 but it is
nevertheless "not far from Genoa" 59 that the mountain-loving philosophy of
Thus Spoke Zarathustra is born, a book which is "not only the highest book
there is, the book that is truly characterized by the air of the heights," but also
"the deepest. " 60 "Great health" needs always to be opposed, or else it is
dissipated and lost: even the Ubermensch has dirty hands (in Sartre's sense); the
"blond beast" is a beefeater, and, appropriately enough, he likes his burgers
Swiss. 61 Nietzsche's medical model, I would argue, is not Pasteur but Jenner;
his solution to the corruption of culture is not pasteurization but inoculation. 62
It should be noted that Serres persists in reading the title of The Antichrist
perversely because of a misunderstanding caused by its French translation as
L'Antechrist: "The Antichrist [L'antechrist]: ante has never, to my knowledge,
meant 'contrary to,' but, rather, 'in front of,' 'in face of' [... ]. The Antechrist
comes before Christ [L'antechrist est avant le Christ]. [... ]Antichrist, before the
sacred [Antechrist, avant le sacre]."63 Now the German title Nietzsche chooses
is Der Antichrist, which means both "The Anti-Christ" and "The Anti-
Christian," but there is no escaping the fact that he uses a prefix which means
"contrary to," just as in the last words of Ecce Homo, "Dionysus versus the
Crucified:' (EH, Destiny 9), or in the title of his last text, Nietzsche contra
Wagner. Serres's favourite preposition is "between"; 64 Nietzsche's is undoubt-
edly "against," and one cannot so easily despatch his "Iranian" (or Heraclitean)
inheritance, with the aid of a false etymology. Nor with the aid of an imaginary
itinerary such as this: "Having started off in Greece, Nietzsche remains for a
long time in Persia before ending up with Buddhism, in The Antichrist."65 In my
opinion one must acknowledge that Nietzsche's rhetoric of purification in the
final period is itself mixed with a continued rhetoric of war. The polemos and
156 DUNCAN LARGE
agon of the Greeks remain his most profound sources of inspiration, and till the
very end, right up to the "great declaration of war" which is his "little work"
Twilight of the Idols, 66 right up to his very last unpublished text, the declaration
of "Deadly War against the House of Hohenzollern."67 And Serres makes
perfectly plain his distaste for polemics, 68 for science's "agonistic model," 69 for
"the occupation of places by the soldierly," 70 for disciplinary regi-mentality and
critical "strategies,"71 for the "martial" spirit, 72 for war tout court, the "eternal
.
return of d1spute.
,73
"Formed by war, by all wars, I love and seek peace, which seems to me the
supreme good" 74 - with such repeated declarations of "irenism,"75 Serres
positions himself at the furthest remove from Nietzsche, from "the philosoph);
of the fragment" 76 and the "genuinely police-like" philosophy of suspicion. 7
His reading of Nietzsche, and of The Antichrist above all, seems to me never-
theless to be motivated by a paradoxical critical "strategy" which seeks to
defuse the dangerous polemics of this self-styled "explosive" philosopher,n and
diminish his importance in the history of western philosophy by resituating him
in the context of a different history, that of the natural sciences. Serres refuses
to consider this master of suspicion in relation to the usual suspects: not for him
Nietzsche and Schopenhauer or Nietzsche and Wagner, Nietzsche and meta-
physics or Nietzsche and music; he prefers to write of Nietzsche and cosmology,
mathematics, thermodynamics, medicine, of Nietzsche and Laplace, Carnot,
Poinsot, Pasteur, Poincare. It is a deliberately reductive, even humiliating
context, and he does not always escape condescension. 79
Serres assures us that Hermes, the god who unifies his work, 80 is the "god of
the 20th century" who succeeded in supplanting "Prometheus, the outmoded
demi-god of the 19th,"81 but did he also succeed in supplanting Dionysus? Have
we really left behind us the tragic age in Nietzsche's sense? Is Nietzsche himself
condemned to remain a prisoner of the old thermodynamics without gaining
access to Serres's "hermodynamic" age? "Laughter is the human phenomenon
of communication (reciprocal definition)": 82 Serres defines Hermes as the father
of Comedy, but Dionysus also knows how to laugh, and his laughter is still
infectious. 83
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This article is derived from a longer French version published as: "Hermes contra Dionysus
(Serres et Nietzsche)." Horizons philosophiques. 811 (Autumn, 1997: Le Monde de Michel
Serres"): 23-39.
HERMES CONTRA DIONYSUS 157
NOTES
1 Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols and The Anti-Christ, trans. RJ. Hollingdale (Harmondsworth:
Penguin, 1968), Ancients 5, pp. 110-111.
2 Michel Serres, Hermes: Literature, Science, Philosophy, ed. Josue V. Harari and David F. Bell
~Baltimore and London: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982), hereafter cited asH, p.l3.
Cf. Vincent Descombes, "Le moment fran<;ais de Nietzsche," in Alain Boyer et al., Pourquoi
nous ne sommes pas nietzscheens (Paris: Gras set, 1991 ), pp. 99-128.
4 H, p. 4. Cf. Hermes Ill: La traduction (Paris: Minuit, 1974), hereafter cited as H3, p. 76.
5 Serres, H3, p. 45; Hermes V: Le passage du Nord-Ouest (Paris: Minuit, 1980), hereafter cited
as H5, p. 150.
6 "Corruption- The Antichrist: A Chemistry of Sensations and Ideas," trans. Chris Bongie, in
Nietzsche in Italy, ed. Thomas Harrison (Stanford, CA: ANMA Libri, 1988), hereafter cited as CA.
7 Serres, Hermes IV: La distribution (Paris: Minuit. 1977), hereafter cited as H4, p. 46.
8 Serres, H4, p. 115.
9 Ibid., pp. 115-24.
10 H4, pp. 115-116.
II H3, p. 26.
12 H4, p. 116.
13 Ibid., p. 163.
14 Ibid., p. 69; cf. H4, p. 222
15 H5, p. 65.
16 H4, p. 69; H5, p. 65; Eclaircissements: Cinq entretiens avec Bruno Latour (Paris: Flammarion,
°
2 FSZ, p. 71.
21 Ibid., p. 27.
22 Ibid., p. 211.
23 H4, p. 60.
24 FSZ, p. 210; cf. H4, p. 62.
25 H4, p. 282.
26 Serres thus goes further than Prigogine and Stengers who attribute this generalization of
difference to Nietzsche, citing Deleuze: cf. Order Out of Chaos: Man's New Dialogue with Nature
(London: Flamingo, 1985), p. 111. Harari and Bell read this argument as a not-so-veiled attack on
Derrida himself (H, xxxviin. 49).
27 H4, p. 52.
28 Cf. KSA 12, 205/WP 1063: "The law of the conservation of energy demands eternal
recurrence."
29 FSZ, p. 79, p. 109.
3 °
For Nietzsche's response to Mayer and Proctor, cf. KSA 9, 451; for Thomson, cf. KSA 13,
375/WP 1066. For Nietzsche's intense interest in the scientific theories of his day, cf. Karl
Schlechta and Anni Anders, Friedrich Nietzsche: Von den verborgenen Anfiingen seines
Philosophierens (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstatt: Frommann, 1962), and Babette E. Babich, Nietzsche's
Philosophy of Science: Reflecting Science on the Ground of Art and Life (Albany: SUNY Press,
1994).
31 Cf. especially the critique of scientism in GM, III: 23-25, and Deleuze, "Nietzsche and
Science," in Nietzsche and Philosophy, trans. Hugh Tomlinson (London: Athlone Press; New
York: Columbia University Press, 1983), pp. 44-46.
32 Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Harmondsworth: Penguin. 1992), p. 128.
33 H4, p. 72.
34 Serres, Jouvences: Sur Jules Verne (Paris: Minuit, 1974), p. 278; cf. CA, p. 43.
35 H3, p. 60.
36 FSZ, p. 77; H4, p. 69.
37 Ibid., p. 113.
38 Serres, Eloge de Ia philosophie en langue fran(:aise (Paris: Fayard, 1995), pp. 89-90.
39 Serres, Le Tiers-Instruit (Paris: Fran<;ois Bourin, 1991), p. 213.
40 H4, p. 115.
!58 DUNCAN LARGE
41 Cf. Walter Kaufmann, Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, 3rd edn (New York:
Vintage Books, 1968), pp. 326-28; Bernard Pautrat, "Position de l'eternel retour," in Versions du
solei/: Figures et systeme de Nietzsche (Paris: Seuil, 1971), pp. 348-58; Alain Juranville, Physique
de Nietzsche (Paris: Denoel/Gonthier, 1973), p. 85.
42 Cf. GS 341; Z, III, "Of the Vision and the Riddle"; and Bernd Magnus, Nietzsche's Existential
End of the Universe," in God and the New Physics (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984), pp. 199-213
and The Last Three Minutes: Conjectures about the Ultimate Fate of the Universe (London:
Weidenfeld & Nicolson, 1994); William Poundstone, The Recursive Universe: Cosmic Complexity
and the Limits of Scient(fic Knowledge (Oxford and New York: Oxford University Press, 1985);
Stephen Hawking, "The Origin and Fate of the Universe" and "The Arrow of Time" (in A Brief
History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes (New York: Bantam Books, 1988), pp. 127-
70), and "The Future of the Universe" (in Black Holes and Baby Universes and other Essays (New
York: Bantam Books, 1993), pp. 127-41).
45 H4, p. 156. Even this originality of Nietzsche's is nevertheless qualified in Jouvences: Sur
Jules Verne, where Serres traces the pasteurization of culture back to Lucretius: seep. 259.
46 CA, p. 42. I have modified Chris Boogie's English translation, which is confusing: "the couple
recompense, The Antichrist reverts to dichotomies, it marks nonetheless their breakdown." The
Pleakdown Serres means is clearly Nietzsche's.
CA, p. 31.
56 Cf. my forthcoming Introduction to Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. Duncan
"Killer Cheese," in Entropy and the Magic Flute (New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1993), pp. 67-74.
62 "Nietzsche discovers that it is in his becoming-sick, in his 'blood-poisoning,' that human
promise is to be found," notes Keith Ansell Pearson in his remarkable recent book Viroid Life:
Perspectives on Nietzsche and the Transhuman Condition (London and New York: Routledge,
1997), p. 15. In my article "Nietzsche and the Figure of Copernicus: Grande Fantaisie on Polish
Airs" (New Readings, 2 (1996): 65-87), I attempt to demonstrate that this notion of "mixed blood"
persists even into the phantasmatic delirium of Ecce Homo, where Nietzsche (in the version
restored in 1969) declares himself to be "a pure-blooded Polish nobleman" (p. 41 ).
63 CA, pp. 46-48. I have modified Boogie's translation, which tidies up this misreading by
introducing an extraneous additional step into Serres's argument: "The Antichrist is an Ante-
Christ" (CA, p. 47).
64 E, p. 99.
65 JV, p. 279.
66 Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, "Preface"; cf. EH, Wise 7.
67 KSA 13, 643-46. In this context one can note that the Camot of whom Nietzsche writes is not
Sadi but his father Lazare, "the soldier and republican." (Nietzsche, Daybreak, 167.)
68 H3, p. 71; H4, p. 148; E, p. 58.
69 H, p. 21.
70 H4, p. 53.
71 H, p. 28; H4, pp. 288-90; HS, p. 22.
HERMES CONTRA DIONYSUS 159
There are interpreters of Nietzsche's work who artlessly fit the philosophy of his
last period under the unifying or equalizing umbrella of hermeneutics - which
I regard as unjust. Such a seemingly infinite extension of hermeneutics
generates manifest uncertainty and disquiet on the poorly protected margins of
philosophical hermeneutics. The best tactical move for hermeneutics is to leave
other fields of interpretation open while yet simultaneously preserving its own
territory. Nietzsche's interpretive philosophy, providing us with the opportunity
to reconsider the problems of interpretation, language, consciousness, etc., thus
offers an essential challenge.
Since Schleiermacher, hermeneutics has been designated the art of interpre-
tation (Auslegungskunst), and thus, given Nietzsche's words quoted in the title
above, the will to truth would be nothing but an art of this interpretive kind.
Consequently, we could say "the will to truth" is hermeneutics. With this initial
statement, we immediately confront a serious problem of interpretation, for
Nietzsche gives us to understand that "the will to truth" is "merely the desire for
a world of the constant" (WP 585). What kind of interpretation results if the
interpreter, in understanding himself and his world, merely longs for a familar
and imperishable world? Such an interpretive approach to the world would
attempt to stabilize it as a world of "identical cases," 1 and, with this familiarity,
move farther and farther away from the truth. Nietzsche, like Heidegger in his
early lectures on hermeneutics, obviously took "the history of the decline of
truth" 2 as his starting point. The articulation of the world into the knowable and
enduring ultimately effects the elimination or annihilation of the human world
that is to be understood, and thus the world turns squarely into its own opposite.
"Man seeks 'the truth': a world that is not self-contradictory, not deceptive, does
not change, a true world- a world in which one does not suffer ... " (WP 585).
Humanity is inclined [die "Verfallensgeneigtheit" des Menschen] to fall back
upon an enduring, consistent world representing reality as ultimate, a reality
which, for Nietzsche, could be described in terms of "'unworldliness,' 'unsen-
suality'" (BGE 62). This unwordly metaphysical reality is the anti-truth. In its
161
B. Babich (ed. ). Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 161-167.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
162 BELA BACS6
For his critique involves the most extreme, radical alienation which affects us with regard to what
is our ownmost [Eigensten], namely consciousness itself. That conciousness and self-
consciousness gives no unambivalent witness concerning itself, that that which it reveals as what
is meant perhaps masks, perhaps inverts what is really in it, is so hammered into modern thought
through Nietzsche that we now recognize it everywhere, not only in that excessive, self-destructive
disillusionment with which Nietzsche tore one mask after the other from the ego, until finally no
mask but also no ego remained?
What does this unmasking of the consciousness of the self mean concerning
the vanishing, estranged "ownmost" [Eigenstes] of the man of understanding,
if future thinking strives to approach this, and what does thinking without a self
look like? Can humanity's "ownmost" be saved at all? Or, to ask, with Heideg-
ger: how can we retrieve from Nietzsche's philosophy "what thought cannot
bear to have lost"? 4
It has been pointed out that the will to truth is the art of interpretation which
ultioately simulates the world as uniquely true and, "at this stage," discards all
the lively and challenging elements of life accordingly: "In summa: the world
as it ought to be exists; this world, in which we live, is an error- this world of
ours ought not to exist" (WP 585). Nietzsche used the term reversal (Umke-
hrung)5 for the formula by which he unmasks the anti-true, simulated world. In
this reversal, he pursues self-contained, metaphysical thinking to its furthest
limit where catastrophe ensues. The arbitrary deliberation of metaphysics, the
attempt at a humanistic self-liberation from metaphysical preposessions is
clearly insufficient. There is one recourse: releasing ourselves in tragic reversal.
It is in this sense that Nietzsche's interpreters are right to call this a tragic way
of thinking. Moreover, the "new way" of thinking the world (mere negation
would only mean relapse into a false metaphysics of truth), follows the world
affirmatively up until its own reversal, where, in this most extreme being-
beyond-itself, it can no longer deny itself. Standing before ourselves is
cathartic; it is to glance, purified, at erroneous-errant life. Assuming this
interpretive position without reserve, we shudder knowingly at what Rene Char
called the "territoire agonistique," and here stepping before and skipping up to
it, we nonetheless retreat, intruding upon inner tremors already too well
understood, deprived of their liveliness (and superficially dead). The philoso-
pher mapping the movements of the Earth with a seismographic sensibility
almost unintentionally destroys the world as he interprets it. The world,
stiffened into a solid crust, is beheld as familiar by the interpreter who believes
that in the articulation (legomenon) simulating certainty he pronounces the
ultimate truth qua logos of the world. "Rather has the world become 'infinite'
THE WILL TO TRUTH 163
for us all over again" (GS 374)- becomes comprehensible, as approached from
the tragic reversal of interpretation.
Nietzsche obviously has misgivings concerning the world expressed qua
legomenon in linguistic interpretation. This way of interpreting the world tends
to limit the varying-multifarious world of becoming. That is, it wants to make
the world, first and foremost, superficial and graspable. 6 Interpretation
accomplished through the art of schematisation and abbreviation means no more
than "signification for the sake of understanding" and deliberately aims to
"discard" all life's painful occurrences. 7 The suspicion of a painless interpreta-
tion of philosophy, that is a future of interpretation poised to mistrust itself
restores the infinity of pain in the world: "I doubt that such pain makes us
'better'; but I know that it makes us more profound."8 To Nietzsche's mind, the
ideal of painless interpretation is an ascetic ideal which, as a result of an
unworldly nai"vete, believes that life can constantly be improved, while through
the "reductive art" [Abkiirzungskunst], it attains the finite-truncated interpreta-
tion of Dasein: an interpretation which poses values. The ascetic ideal "permits
no other interpretation, no other goal; it rejects, denies, affirms, and sanctions
solely from the point of view of its interpretation ... " (GM III: 23). Ascetic
interpretation conceals the highest degree of will to power, and wants to imagine
"its absolute superiority of rank over every other power." (Ibid.) In other words,
for Nietzsche, the destruction of the ascetic ideal is the disclosure of the ascetic
ideal as sheer will to power, which reveals the antimetaphysical character of his
philosophy. This, however, does not allow us to step freely beyond the
metaphysical era. As Heidegger says, one can recover only temporarily from
metaphysics; one can never overcome it conclusively: one can never be cured
once and for al1. 9 Or as Nietzsche put it, "we, too, still derive our flame from the
fire ignited by a faith millenia old," and "from the moment faith in the God of
the ascetic ideal is denied, a new problem arises: that of the value of truth" (GM
III: 24). Nietzsche's philosophy reaches a crossroad where, destroying the
absolute, it chooses to regard the problem of truth. And could it really be that
with this decision, Nietzsche is unable to sidestep "an inextricable entanglement
in metaphysics," as Heidegger maintains? 10
Let us return to the fragment I took as the title for this essay where Nietzsche
clearly takes up a position against ocular metaphysics. About this opposition he
says: "The senses deceive, reason corrects the errors; consequently, one
concluded, reason is the road to the constant; the least sensual ideas must be
closest to the 'true world'" (WP 585). On the one hand, Nietzsche holds that the
purpose of reason is to rid the world of its mutable vitality - an ideal world, a
fundamentally non-true world projected by the subject. On the other hand, this
immediate, seemingly "true" world can only prevail via "the hyperbolic naivete"'
of man. 11 In this naivete, Nietzsche discovers the ever prevalent devaluation, the
modern nihilistic tendency of our world-interpretation. Every postulation of
values is related to "a purely fictitious world." 12 Indeed, Nietzsche criticizes this
union with being, a union pretending immediacy, intimacy with humanity. This
was the radical turning point in his antimetaphysical philosophy. And Heidegger
only seems to replay Nietzsche's radical turn: "Man remains mired in narvete
164 BELA BACSO
as long as he does not really act on the knowledge that he alone is the one who
posits values, that only through him can values ever be the conditioned
conditions of the preservation, securing, and enhancement of his life." 13
For Heidegger, Nietzsche remains enmired in Cartesian thinking: "that Being
means 'representedness,' being established in thinking, and that truth means
'certitude. "' 14 Yet by taking anti-true "categories" to their extreme, Nietzsche
effects a destructive reversal of metaphysics. Perhaps we may ask- precisely
with Heidegger- whether Nietzsche's critique does not offer a comprehensive
explanation of "the forgottenness of Being" which Heidegger described as "a
complete insensitivity towards the ambiguous?" 15 Nietzsche was just about to
"invert the perspectival glance" 16 in order to intensify sensitivity for the
multiply explicable. Instead, he dismantled or deconstructed perspectival truths
simply to reduce all groundless "foreground philosophy" (BGE 289). Beyond
this reduction of "foreground philosophy," we know that the nearest nearness
of the familiar world and of all our perspectival truths restrict our openness to
the strange. "We are necessarily strangers to ourselves, we do not comprehend
ourselves, we have to misunderstand ourselves, for us the law 'Each is furthest
from himself' applies to all eternity - we are not 'men of knowledge' with
respect to ourselves" (GM Preface 1). Is there really a "metaphysics of
subjectivity," 17 - or is this not rather an heroic preparation for the overcoming
of metaphysics? It is not suprising that Rodolphe Gascht\ for one, emphasises
a different interpretation of this fragment: "Take, for instance, Nietzsche's
critique of reflection and self-consciousness, which places a necessary gap
between knowledge, on the one hand, and, on the other, self-cognition .... Here,
self-reflection loses all foundational capacity with respect to knowledge." 18 If
this is true, how are we to trace such a recurrently groundless, self-destructive
interpretation? We already know that all interpretations seek to obscure this
"necessary gap." To this end, we apply whatever means are applicable to reduce
the world to be understood to its surface appearance. 19 This foreground
philosophy uses words as masks and pretends or makes a fiction of an ultimate
understanding of there-being (Dasein), able to achieve the "truth." But
Nietzsche supposes another understanding not inclined to conceal this same
chasm: "logic and mechanics are only applicable on the most superficial level:
indeed, no more than an art of schematisation and reduction, mastering
multiplicity through an art of expression - not understanding but signification
for the sake of understanding. To think the world reduced to its superficial level
ultimately means to render it 'comprehensible. "' 20
I would like to refer to a useful possibility for building a bridge from
Nietzsche's philosophy to a recent, and, I believe, relevant, kind of hermeneu-
tics. In his early lectures on Plato's Sophist, Heidegger underlined the indispen-
sable destruction of fundamental "word-knowledge" [WortwissenJ. What is
important in his approach is an understanding "on the basis of the uncovering
of the thing" ["auf Grund des Aufgedeckthabens der Sache" e.g.: dia logon],
which offers a strong critique of vacuous word-knowledge. 21 With such an
"insight with regard to surplus understanding," Heidegger goes against the
superficial interpretation that suppresses the world beneath conceptual machin-
THE WILL TO TRUTH 165
NOTES
1 KSA 12, 418.
2 Martin Heidegger, Platon: Sophistes ( Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1992), p. 27.
3 Hans-Georg Gadamer, "Die philosophischen Grundlagen des zwanzigsten Jahrhunderts" in
Gesammelte Werke Bd. 4 (Tiibingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1987), p. 11.
4 Martin Heidegger, What is Called Thinking, trans. J. Glenn Gray (New York: Harper & Row,
1968), p. 23.
5 See Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. R.J. Hollingdale (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1990),
"The Four Great Errors, § 2," p. 58. KSA 6, 89.
6 See KSA 3, 190.
7 Cf. GM III: 24.
8 Nietzsche, The Gay Science, 'Preface for the Second Edition, § 3,' KSA 3, p. 350.
9 Heidegger, "Uberwindung der Metaphysik," in Vortriige und Aufsiitze (Pfullingen: Neske,
1978), p. 75.
10 Heidegger, "The Word of Nietzsche: God is Dead," in The Question Concerning Technology,
and Other Essays, trans. W. Lovitt (New York: Harper & Row, 1977), p. 61.
11 See KSA 13, 49.
12 Ibid.
13 Heidegger, Nietzsche. Volume Four: Nihilism, trans. D.F. Krell (New York: Harper & Row:
1982), p. SO. Heidegger, Nietzsche II (Pfullingen: Neske, 1961), p. 122.
THE WILL TO TRUTH 167
Dialogue and Deconstruction: The Gadamer-Derrida Encounter (Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1989) p. 107.
23 Nietzsche, The Will to Power, § 517: KSA 12, 382. See Babette E. Babich, Nietzsche's
Philosophy of Science: Reflecting Science on the Ground of Art and Life (Albany: State University
of New York Press, 1994) p. 264.
24 Ibid.
25 See KSA 12, 494.
26 Jacques Derrida, Spurs: Nietzsche's Styles, trans. B. Harlow (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1978), pp. 49-51.
27 "Es giebt gar keinen Willen." KSA 12, 187.
28 Holger Schmid, Nietzsches Gedanke der tragischen Erkenntnis (Wiirzburg: Konigshausen &
°
3 KSA 6, 138.
31 KSA 12, 107.
32 Gadamer, Truth and Method (New York: Continuum, 1975), p. 228.
DAVID OWEN
169
· B. Babich (ed. ). Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 169-177.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
170 DAVID OWEN
element in articulating the meaning and value of human existence. The urgency
of this task is grounded in the fact that human beings confront an awareness of
their own mortality- of the inevitability of ceasing to be- and are, thus, driven
to seek a purpose in, and for, human existence. - Consequently, the task of
accounting for suffering, of assigning a meaning and value to suffering, is a
necessary condition of being able to provide an account of the meaning and
value of human existence and, more particularly, of one's own existence.- If
this task is not accomplished, if human existence is characterised by inevitable
suffering from the meaninglessness of inevitable suffering, the question "why
be?'' finds no answer- and suicidal nihilism follows.
The ascetic ideal is an accomplishment of genius, for Nietzsche, precisely
because it provides a meaning and value for suffering and, concomitantly, for
human existence: "Within it [the ascetic ideal], suffering was given an interpre-
tation; the enormous emptiness seemed filled; the door was shut on suicidal
nihilism" (GM III: 28). Given that this is the case, why does Nietzsche seek to
attack the ascetic ideal?
The crucial issue, for Nietzsche, is how the ascetic ideal provides an answer
to the problem of the meaning of suffering- namely, by making life itself an
ascetic procedure:
The ascetic ideal has a goal, - which is so general, that all the interests of human existence appear
petty and narrow when measured against it; it inexorably interprets epochs, peoples, man, all with
reference to this one goal, it permits of no other interpretation, no other goal and rejects, denies,
affirms. confirms only with reference to its interpretation[ ... ] it believes there is nothing on earth
of any power which does not first have to receive a meaning, a right to existence, a value from it,
as a tool to its work, as a way and means to its goal, to one goal ... (GM III: 23)
What is this goal? In the final section of the third essay of the Genealogy,
Nietzsche offers an answer:
It is absolutely impossible for us to conceal what was expressed by that whole willing, which was
given direction by the ascetic ideal: this hatred of the human, and even more of the animalistic,
even more of the material, [... ] this longing to get away from appearance, transcience, growth,
death, wishing, longing itself- all that means, let us dare grasp it. a will to nothingness, an
aversion of life. a rebellion against the most fundamental prerequisites of life, ... (GM III: 28)
In other words, the goal of the ascetic ideal is the denial of the tragic
character of human existence, the refusal of chance and necessity - and this
hated of fate, Nietzsche contends, is a denial of life itself. How, though, does the
ascetic ideal construct its goal as the one goal?
Abstracting the general features of the specific instantiations of the ascetic
ideal presented in the third essay of the Genealogy provides the following
general mechanism: 1) A metaphysical distinction between "real" and "appar-
ent' world in which the "real" world is conceptualised as the unitary source of
value. 2) A metaphysical realist account of truth as characterised by finality and
completeness, and, concomitantly, of the value of truth as inestimable. 3) A
commitment to the unconditional authority of truth and to the will to truth as an
absolute (categorial) imperative. 4) The expression of this commitment through
SCIENCE, VALUE, AND THE ASCETIC IDEAL 171
a single form of truth-telling such that those qualified in this form of truth-
telling can claim legitimate authority over any and all others. 8
In other words, the ascetic ideal seeks to secure its goal as the one goal by
positing it as the transcendent goal - in which the unity of value is expressed in
the idea of truth as final, complete and inestimable- and, thereby, ruling out the
possibility of tragedy. However, the general structure of the ascetic ideal can be
manifested through a variety of specific ascetic ideals and this point is crucial
to an understanding of Nietzsche's theses on science- to which we now return.
Nietzsche's first thesis is the pivot on which his account turns. The point is
simply this: even if one could provide a scientific account of the prudential
value of science with respect to the satisfaction of human needs, such an account
would not be sufficient to ground the value of science - it would not tell us, for
example, why we ought to value the satisfaction of human needs. An implica-
tion of this thesis is elaborated in the second thesis in that our understanding of
the meaning of science is governed by the system of purposes in which this
activity is embedded and the direction of science is governed by the telos
expressed in this system of purposes. Thus, for example, under the aegis of the
Christian ascetic ideal, the meaning and direction of scientific activity is given
in an understanding of science as a pathway to God. As Karl Li:iwith notes:
Copernicus, Kepler, Galileo and Newton were all equally convinced that God had ordained the
world mathematically and that they could come to know Him by reading from what, by analogy
with the Bible, they termed the "book" of Nature. The biologist Swammerdamm's triumphant
declaration "I bring you here proof of God's Providence in the anatomy of a louse," gives an
indication of the confidence with which a belief in natural science as a pathway to God could be
assumed before Kant produced his critique of physico-teleological arguments for God's existence. 9
The third thesis is established by combining the first and second thesis with
Nietzsche's general claim concerning the ascetic ideal: "Except for the ascetic
ideal: man, the animal man, had no meaning up to now" (GM III: 28). In other
words, science is a tool of the ascetic ideal simply because this has been the
only ideal thus far. 10
However, science is not just any tool of the ascetic ideal - and this brings us
to the fourth thesis. Nietzsche's point is this: the ascetic ideal's construction of
the will to truth as categorically imperative entails a commitment to truthfulness
- to intellectual cleanliness - which is expressed in science as a ruthless paring
away of forms of argument which fail to satisfy the requisite criteria of
coherence, comprehensiveness, simplicity, etc. In this respect, Kant's critique
of physico-teleological proofs of the existence of God is entirely compatible
with Nietzsche's account of Kant as an advocate of the ascetic ideal. As
Nietzsche somwhat caustically comments:
Do people in all seriousness still really believe (as theologians imagined for a while), that, say,
Kant's victory over theological conceptual dogmatism ("God," "soul," "freedom," "immortality")
damaged that [ascetic] ideal? - [... ] What is certain is that every sort of transcendentalist since
Kant has had a winning hand- they are emancipated from the theologians: what good luck! -he
showed them the secret path on which, from now on, they could, independently, and with the best
scientific decorum, pursue "their heart's desires." (GM III: 25)
172 DAVID OWEN
[Science's] relationship to the ascetic ideal is certainly not yet inherently antagonistic; indeed it
is much more the case, in general, that it still represents the driving force in the inner evolution
of that ideal. [ ... ] Both of them, science and the ascetic ideal are still on the same foundation - ...
(GM III: 25, my emphasis)
This thesis follows from the first thesis combined with the additional claim
that an alternative to the ascetic ideal is possible. I will address this issue further
in the third section of this essay.
We can conclude this section by noting that Nietzsche's theses can be
plausibly reconstructed as an internally coherent set of claims which structure
his engagement with science. However, the philosophical cogency of this
argument hangs on the sustainability of these claims. For reasons of space I
cannot provide a full analysis; consequently, I will restrict myself to those which
are most significant for the purposes of this essay. Thus, in the next section I
will address the cogency of the first thesis which I take to be pivotal to
Nietzsche's account, while in the third section I will return to Nietzsche's final
thesis and elaborate its significance in terms of his epistemological critique of
metaphysical realism and his ethical reflections on the fragmentation of value.
SCIENCE, VALUE, AND THE ASCETIC IDEAL 173
II
Can science provide a (reflexive) ground for its own right to existence? What
would be required to respond affirmatively to this question? It seems that such
an account would have to satisfy two criteria: first, it would have to show why
we do value science and, second, it would have to show that that why we ought
to value science is reducible to why we do value science. The first of these
criteria does not seem especially problematic; indeed, Nietzsche's own account
can be grasped as an attempt to provide a naturalistic account of how we have
come to value science. It is the second criterion in which the central issue of
contention is contained.
Nietzsche's position is this: we can provide a naturalistic account of how
human beings come to reflect morally on themselves and to pose the question
of the meaning and value of human existence, and we can even provide a
naturalistic account of how different styles of moral reflection emerge -but this
does not entail that "ought" -statements are reducible to natural facts about
human beings. This requires an additional step. However, to take this additional
step is to become enmired in a grammatical confusion, namely, to treat the
causal origin of values in natural facts about the world as identical to the
reasons for holding these values. The nature of this confusion is illustrated by
reflecting on the fact that while I may recognise that I have come to hold certain
values as a result of various causal processes (evolution, socialisation, etc.), this
recognition is only disturbing if I am unable to offer reasons as to why these
values are worth holding. Thus, I may start asking myself questions such as
"why do I (as a rational being) value science?"- and a causal account cannot
not provide the appropriate sort of answer to this query precisely because it is
the recognition that I seem only able to provide this type of account which
promotes this kind of question. Consequently, we may conclude that science
cannot ground its own value and that Nietzsche's thesis that science requires an
extra-scientific ideal to secure its right to existence is cogent.
III
In this section, we return to Nietzsche's implicit claim that science need not be
in the service of the ascetic ideal. To grasp the implications of this claim for the
philosophy of science, we need to focus briefly on Nietzsche's critique to the
ascetic ideal as a "closed system of will, goal and interpretation." This critique
takes the form of an epistemological and ethical critique of metaphysical
realism; an appropriate starting point is Nietzsche's critique of the idea of the
thing-in-itself.
The idea of the thing-in-itself expresses a condition of possibility of the
distinction between the "real world" of truth and being which is the unitary
source of value and the "apparent world" of appearance and becoming which is
the site of diverse embedded and embodied desires. But what is the sense of this
distinction? Nietzsche comments: "What is 'appearance' for me now? Certainly
not the opposite of some essence: what could I say about any essence except to
174 DAVID OWEN
name the attributes of its appearance! Certainly not a dead mask that one could
place on an unknown x or remove from it!" (GS 54)
Nietzsche's argument is that the idea of the thing-in-itself "contains a
contradictio in adjecto" (BGE 16) because "we can have no conception, or only
a contradictory one," of something independent of any description (appearance)
of it "because to conceive of something is always to conceive of it as satisfying
some description or other." 12 However, it might be argued that this is "compati-
ble with understanding its essence as independent of its possible appearances to
human beings, thus insisting on the possibility of a metaphysical world." 13 Yet,
as Maudmarie Clark goes on to point out, 14 this argument is also incoherent.
This is because while we may cheerfully admit that beings with greater
cognitive powers than our own might discover our best theory to be false and
present a better theory, the only way to make sense of this idea- without being
thrown back onto the incoherent idea of truth as independent of all possible
knowers - is that this "alien" theory gives us more of what we want, that is,
better satisfies our cognitive interests (comprehensivess, coherence, simplicity,
etc.). Consequently, the metaphysical realist claim that truth is independent of
the cognitive constitution of human beings (our capacities and interests) is
identical with the incoherent claim that truth is independent of all possible
knowers. Thus Nietzsche remarks that the idea of a view from nowhere which
is expressed in the idea of the thing-in-itself demands "that we should think af
an eye that is completely unthinkable" (GM III: 12)- and goes on to draw the
appropriate conclusion: "We have abolished the real world: what world is left?
the apparent world perhaps? ... But no! with the real world we have also
abolished the apparent world!" 15
Where does this leave us? Perhaps with two initial thoughts: first, that the
concept of truth does not entail any conceptual commitment to the categories of
finality and completeness, and, second, that the value of truth is estimable.
This second thought can be drawn out by noting that the critique of meta-
physical realism entails that no goal can secure itself as the one goal by claiming
to be the transcendent goal; the plethora of diverse goals manifest in the various
ways in which human beings engage purposively with the world are freed from
their subordination to the ascetic ideal. The question of value enters this
discussion in two ways, both of which are relevant to question of the value of
truth: firstly, via the topic of the value of a perspective and, secondly, via the
topic of the values immanent to a system of purposes.
On the question of the value of a perspective, we can note that the incoher-
ence of the idea of a view from nowhere entails that truth-claims are necessarily
always the product of a view from somewhere, that is, the product of our
purposive activity in the world 16 . In other words, a condition of possibility of
any given kind of truth is a system of purposes within which this kind of truth
is sought - and the value of this kind of truth is dependent on the value of the
purposes that this kind of truth is sought for. More precisely, the value of
knowing that p is true is that value of knowing that p - and the value of knowing
that p is dependent on the value of knowing that p for a given system (or
systems) of purposes which is, in tum, dependent on the value of that (or those)
SCIENCE, VALUE, AND THE ASCETIC IDEAL 175
system(s) of purposes. For example, consider the value of knowing that "X
survived the car crash" from the following perspectives: friend, business rival,
parent, para-medic and fellow human being - and then consider how this value
is estimable and variable depending on the value that one or more of these
perspectives/systems of purposes holds for a given person (it is obviously the
case that considerable contextual detail would need to be filled in to make an
actual estimation of the value of knowing this but hopefully the main point is
clear).
Nietzsche's recognition of the estimability of the value of truth is expressed
in the account of 'objectivity' which attends his doctrine of perspectivism. This
account involves two elements. The first is presented as part of his general
presentation of perspectivism as an analytic of knowledge:
There is only perspective seeing, only perspective "knowing"; and the more affects we allow to
speak about one thing, the more eyes, different eyes, we use to observe one thing, the more
complete will our "concept" of this thing, our "objectivity," be. But to eliminate the will
altogether, to suspend each and every affect, supposing we were capable of this - what would that
mean but to castrate the intellect? (GM III: 12)
["Objectivity"] understood not as "contemplation without interest" (which is, as such, a non-
concept and an absurdity), but as having in our power our "'pros" and "cons": so as to be able to
engage and disengage them so that we can use the difference in perspectives and affective
interpretations for knowledge. (GM III: 12)
CONCLUSION
NOTES
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morality in On the Genealogy of Morality, ed. K.
Ansell-Pearson, trans. C. Diethe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994). Henceforth cited
as GM. Cf. GS 344, GM III 24.
SCIENCE, VALUE, AND THE ASCETIC IDEAL 177
given Nietzsche's remarks on the good( -bad) conscience of the ancient Greek nobility which is
expressed in Greek tragic drama (at least prior to Euripides).
11 For some cogent observations on this aspect of Nietzsche's thought with respect to popular
scientism, see H. Cay gill, "Drafts for a Metaphysics of the Gene," Tekhnema Vol.3, 1996, pp. 00-
00.
12 M. Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy (Cambridge: CUP, 1990) pp. 46-7
13 Ibid., p. 100.
14 Ibid., pp. 49-50
15 Twilight of the Idols in Twilight of the ldolsfJhe AntiChrist, trans. R.J. Hollingdale (H
armondsworth: Penguin, 1968.) TI 'How the "Real World" at last became a Myth' 6.
16 For some further pertinent reflections on perspectivism, see B. Leiter "Perspectivism in
179
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 179-185.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
180 DAVID B. ALLISON
They [the senses] do not lie at all. What we make of their testimony, that alone introduces lies; for
example, the lie of unity, the lie of thinghood, of substance, of permanence. "Reason" is the cause
of our falsification of the testimony of the senses. Insofar as the senses show becoming, passing
away, and change, they do not lie. But Heraclitus will remain eternally right with his assertion that
Being is an empty fiction. The "apparent" world [die "scheinbare" Welt] is the only one; the
"true" world is merely added by a lie. 6
Reason thus distorts and falsifies the testimony of the senses. It imposes a
demand that the real be other than what the senses yield, and furthermore,
reason demands that this other, Being itself, substance and permanence, be
understood conceptually. 7 Thus, the real world, or Being, stands opposed to the
merely apparent world of sense experience, which discloses only change and
passing, i.e., becoming. In this respect, Nietzsche likens traditional philosophers
to iconolators, or as he says, idolaters: whatever is real can only be admitted or
grasped to the extent that it is first transformed into a concept, the concept of
Being. The actual world thus is judged lacking in Being, and is dismissed as
impermanent, transistory, aleatory, as false - it consists in mere appearance,
becoming. Or, as Nietzsche quite simply says, they mummify it:
All that philosophers have handled for thousands of years have been concept-mummies; nothing
real escaped their grasp alive. When these honorable idolaters of concepts [Begrif.fs-Gotzendiener]
worship something, they kill it and stuff it; they threaten the life of everything they worship.
Death, change, old age, as well as procreation and growth, are to their minds objections - even
refutations. Whatever has Being does not become; whatever becomes does not have being. Now
they all believe, desperately even, in what has being. But since they never grasp it, they seek for
reasons why it is kept from them. 8
It is no different in this case than with the movement of the sun: there, our eye is the constant
advocate of error, here it is our language. In its origin, language belongs in the age of the most
rudimentary form of psychology. We enter a realm of crude fetishism when we summon before
consciousness the basic presuppositions of the metaphysics of language - in plain talk, the
presuppositions of reason. Everywhere, it sees a doer and doing; it believes in the will as the cause,
it believes in the ego, in the ego as being, in the ego as substance, and it projects this faith in the
ego-substance upon all things - only thereby does it first create the concept of "thing."
Everywhere "being" is projected by thought, pushed underneath, as the cause; the concept of being
follows, and is derivative of, the concept of ego .... Indeed, nothing has yet possessed a more naive
power of persuasion than the error concerning being ... After all, every word we say and every
sentence speak in its favor. .. "Reason" in language- oh, what an old deceptive female she is! I am
afraid we are not rid of God because we still have faith in grammar! 11
Nietzsche then goes on to sum up his account of this genesis of the double
simulacrum, i.e., of the merely "apparent world," and the so-called "real world,"
that of "true being," in two brief propositions:
1) The reasons for which "this" world has been characterized as "apparent" [scheinbar ] are the
very reasons which indicate its reality; any other kind of reality is absolutely indemonstrable.
2) The criteria which have been bestowed on the "true being" of things are the criteria of non-
being, of naught- of nothing; the "true world" has been constructed out of the contradiction to the
actual world; indeed [this is] an apparent world [eine scheinbare Welt], insofar as it is merely a
moral-optical illusion [eine moralisch-optische Tiiuschung ]. 12
Fine: genesis of both the "apparent" and the "true" worlds, each deriving
from our inordinate faith in discursive rationality, or in short, our grammar. An
inherited grammar subtends our capacity to reason, which, as a universal- or,
at least Western - characterization of human understanding, serves as the
foundation for our belief in a true world. Yet that belief, as expressed in the
concept of being, is already in Nietzsche's words, an illusion, a fable. As such,
Nietzsche's paradigm is even more complex, perhaps more sinister, than that of
Baudrillard, since Nietzsche begins his account - "How the 'True World'
Finally Became a Fable," or "The History of an Error," which corresponds to
Baudrillard's "successive phases of the image"- with the prior suspension of
the reference relation.
182 DAVID B. ALLISON
It's interesting then, to see the elaboration of Nietzsche's account as both the
exhaustion of the very semantic content of the image, sign, or concept - i.e.,
"the true world" - as well as a reaffirmation of the broken reference. Thus,
reference emerges as but a dream, an idyll: but even more so, the concept,
image, idea, or sign, which is described as "the true world," is itself shown to
be evacuated of sense. The history, then, is of an error, which is the evolving
development, the genealogy of an Idea. And as Nietzsche frequently remarked,
some ideas or concepts, simply become effaced: they lose their distinctive
signifying marks, their power or place, in a signifying system. Ideas, in this
sense, are precisely like icons, images, or as he says, idols, in that they are
fetishes. As such, they are significantly overinvested. Or, as Baudrillard would
have it: hyperreal.
Deflated, thence devalued - no longer even a medium of exchange - of
exchange value or symbolic value, they are dis-invested, divested. Let us follow
this very curious and picaresque itinerary of an error:
1) The true world- attainable for the sage. the pious, the virtuous man; he lives in it, he is it. (The
oldest form of the idea, relatively sensible, simple, and persuasive. A circumlocution for the
sentence, "1, Plato, am the truth.")
2) The true world- unattainable for now, but promised for the sage, the pious, the virtuous man
("for the sinner who repents"). (Progress of the idea; it becomes more subtle, insidious.
incomprehensible- it becomes female, it becomes Christian.)
3) The true world- unattainable, indemonstrable, unpromisable; but the very thought of it- a
consolation, an obligation, an imperative. (At bottom, the old sun, but seen through mist and
skepticism. The idea has become elusive, pale, Nordic, Kiinigsbergian [i.e .. "Kantian"j.)
4) The true world- unattainable? At any rate, unattained. And being unattained, also unknown.
Consequently, not consoling, redeeming, or obligating: how could something unknown obligate
us? (Gray morning. The first yawn of reason. The cock-crow of positivism.)
5) The "true" world- an idea which is no longer good for anything, not even obligating- an idea
which has become useless and superfluous- consequently, a refuted idea: let us abolish it! (Bright
day; breakfast, return of bon sens and cheerfulness; Plato's embarassed blush; pandemonium of
all free spirits.)
6) The true world- we have abolished. What world has remained? The apparent one perhaps~ But
no! With the true world we have also abolished the apparent one. (Noon; moment of the briefest
shadow; end of the longest error; high point of humanity; INCIPIT ZARATHUSTRA.) 13
significance. But, for all that, it is nonetheless the repository of all possible
forms, events, history, and future- humanity included.
Like Nietzsche, Baudrillard would locate the nihilism of his own age - our
age - in the hyperreal world of simulation, which would resurrect the real in the
form of exclusively and universally determining codes of signification:
precisely, as the hyperreal. With the sublation of reference and signification,
however, the real is short-circuited, and the system becomes infinitely orbital
and refractory, ever changing its values and significance by virtue of its
governing operationalism. Hence, Baudrillard's charge that the system of
meaning kills, that all value is sundered by it, rendered into its opposite,
negated, and ultimately, left indifferent. 16 All this facilitated by the unas-
similable speed of the electronic media, which effectively mediates nothing, but
can explain everything according to an infinity of symbolic axes, such that
everything becomes transparent, neutral, inconsequential, without effect or
affect. This would be the terrorism of the system itself, its capacity to render
everything indifferent, adiaphorous, a series of images which, in their effulgent
succession, no longer refer to anything - of communication, which endlessly
circulates information, only to be transformed, reversed, countered, debated,
rearticulated politically, economically, aesthetically, ideololgically, according
to yet another symbolic index. Handguns don't cause crime, public assistance
causes welfare, ketchup is a vegetable, God must be brought back to the schools,
sex education causes teenage pregnancies, condoms promote AIDS, dictator-
ships are emerging democracies, everyone profits from the globalization of
trade, the free market will restore human rights, equal opportunity is racist and
sexist, etc. Mindless saturation, meltdown, indifference.
Yet, just as Nietzsche had concluded his "History of an Error" by invoking
Zarathustra - indeed, Twilight of the Idols itself ends with a quotation from
Zarathustra - so does Baudrillard sound much the same call at the close of his
discusssion of nihilism ("Sur le nihilisme"), concluding Simulacres et Simula-
tion.17 Instead of "Incipit Zarathustra," his final remark in the book is "C'est la
ou commence Ia seduction." 18 Seduction would in large part constitute Baudril-
lard' s return to the actual, to the primacy of the objective domain in its sensible
integrity, its objective necessity. Expressed in terms quite reminiscent of
Zarathustra's account of Will to Power, such an objective dimension is framed
to challenge the original sin of a significant and purposive "world order," one
so transparent in its hyperreality as to leave practically no clue that the entire
order is itself what he would come to term "the perfect crime." 19 Baudrillard's
inquiry into the transfiguring and transforming play- the seductive game- of
objective appearances would serve as a modest beginning to counter the
totalizing systems of purposive interpretation, whose legitimate agency, we
finally and fatally come to realize, may be largely nominal. The interminable
age of this "moral-optical illusion" may well be returned, as Nietzsche had
hoped, to the domain of bon sens - of good sense - where chance and necessity
would give rise to the fatality of a tragic wisdom, a joyous wisdom. And this
was Zarathustra' s "secret":
TWILIGHT OF THE ICONS 185
... and I whispered something into her [Life's] ear, right through her tangled yellow foolish tresses.
"You know that, 0 Zarathustra? Nobody knows that."
And we looked at each other and gazed on the green meadow over which the cool evening was
running just then, and we wept together. But then life was dearer to me than all my wisdom ever
was. 20
NOTES
For an extended discussion of these issues in the works of Nietzsche, Plato, and Baudrillard,
see D. Allison, "lconologies: Reading Simulations with Plato and Nietzsche," in Recherches
semiotiques I Semiotic Inquiry, Vol. 16 (1996), nos. 1-2, pp. 89-111.
2 In his Simulations, Eng. tr., P. Foss, P. Patton, P. Beitchman (New York: Semiotexte, 1983),
Baudrillard ostensibly models his genesis of the hyperreal according to the terms of the
Iconoclastic Controversy. At its first instance, the image or icon was held to represent or to reflect
the divine referent. In this case, the real (A) is represented by the image or icon of the real (A').
Thus, A = A'. In its second instance, the image or icon masks or distorts the real. Thus the real is
represented by an image which is a disfigurement of the real. Let X = additional signification and
-X= reduced signification. Restated: A= A'(XV-X). In its third instance or "phase," the image
or icon masks the absence of a basic reality, in which case dissimulation occurs. Thus, A'= -(-A).
Finally, the image or icon bears no relation to any reality whatsoever. In this case, the reference
relation is dropped altogether, and the image or icon emerges as pure simulation , as the hyperreal
. For such a situation, A' = -A. Baudrillard's discussion is to be found in Part One, "The
Precession of Simulacra," Chap. 1, "The Divine Irreference of Images," pp. 5-13.
3 F. Nietzsche, The Twilight of the Idols, in The Portable Nietzsche, trans. by W. Kaufmann
~New York: Viking, 1968), pp. 463-563.
Nietzsche would briefly summarize this account in his work of 1888, Ecce Homo: "The last
thing I should promise would be to 'improve' mankind. No new idols are erected by me; let the
old ones learn what feet of clay mean. Overthrowing idols (my word for 'ideals')- that comes
closer to being part of my craft. One has deprived reality of its value, its meaning, its truthfulness,
to precisely the extent to which one has mendaciously invented an ideal world. The 'true world'
and the 'apparent world' -that means: the mendaciously invented world and reality .... What is
called idol on the title page is simply what has been called truth so far. Twilight of the Idols - that
is: the old truth is approaching its end" (Ecce Homo, in F. Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals
and Ecce Homo, trans. W. Kaufmann [New York: Vintage, 1969], pp. 217-18, 314).
5 Nietzsche, The Antichrst, in The Portable Nietzsche, pp. 565-656.
6 Nietzsche, Twilight, pp. 480-81.
7 Somewhat analogously, when Descartes in the Meditations, has reduced the contents of the
imagination to the analytical simples (out of which he can reconstruct the world according to his
mathematical mechanics and dynamics), he sees no reason not to doubt the existence of the world.
God may always be conveniently invoked as a guarantor that the world exists, but the claim that
the Mathes is Universalis corresponds to the world is an assertion at best, and not a troubling one,
since the "nature" of Cartesian bodies is defined mathematically, in any case, as magnitude.
8 Twilight, pp. 479-80.
9 Baudrillard, op. cit., pp. 4, 12.
10 Twilight, p. 482.
11 Ibid., pp. 482-83.
12 Ibid., p. 485.
13 Ibid., pp. 485-86.
14 The Antichrist, in The Portable Nietzsche, p. 581.
15 Twilight, p. 486.
16 J. Baudrillard, Simulacres et simulation (Paris: Galilee, 1981), p. 234.
17 Ibid., pp. 229-36.
18 Ibid., p. 236.
19 J. Baudrillard, Le Crime parfait (Paris: Galilee, 1995).
20 Thus Spoke Zarathustra, in The Portable Nietzsche, op. cit., p. 339.
GREG WHITLOCK
INTRODUCTION
When I reflect upon my own philosophical genealogy, I feel kinship to the antiteleological, i.e.
spinozistic, movement of our time, yet with the difference that, I also consider "purpose" and
"will" in us an error; and as well, to the mechanistic movement [ ... ], yet with the difference that,
I do not believe in "matter" and consider Boscovich one of the great turning points like Copernicus
[ ... ].2
187
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 187-201.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
188 GREG WHITLOCK
a more speculative, less rigorous, stance and interpret the Spirit of Science from
Thus Spoke Zarathustra in light of Roger Joseph Boscovich (Part IV).
Karl Schlechta and Anni Anders first discovered the existence of a Bo-
scovich-Nietzsche connection in their collaborative work, Friedrich Nietzsche.
Von den verborgenen Anfiingen seines Philosophierens (1962). 4 But from there
the track goes cold, until George Stack gives Boscovich a central role in
creation of the theory of will to power in his Lange and Nietzsche (1981). 5 But
none of these authors accurately evaluated the real range of influence Boscovich
had on Nietzsche.
Gunter Abel masterfully places Boscovich and Spinoza in an extensive study
of the theoretical foundations of Nietzsche's worldview, 6 but he did not find
some of the connections and evidence presented here. And one can still lose
sight of Boscovich in the depth and breadth of Abel's work. A recent work by
Babette E. Babich entitled Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, 7 rejects the
opinion that Boscovich is unimportant for Nietzsche, but the author does not
consider Boscovich or his ideas at length. And so it is still necessary to tell the
story of Nietzsche's profound debt to Roger Joseph Boscovich. Boscovich 's
theory of force is the parent theory to both the eternal return of the same and
the theory of will to power.
What I am suggesting here has a number of important implications for
Nietzsche studies. Perhaps the most surprising aspect of this account is the
image of the young Nietzsche, seeking scientific support for the cornerstones of
a later philosophy. This image shatters the notion of a "positivist phase" which
some commentators have suggested, since my account traces a sustained
development of thought through every stage of the NachlajJ. My analysis also
casts the history of the notion of eternal return in a new light - one might say
that light is cast on certain aspects for the very first time. For the discovery of
finite force was the decisive moment in the "new world conception." Nietzsche's
new world conception consisted of the idea of eternal return and its theoretical
supposition, will to power. And the source of this scientific conception was
Boscovich's Theoria. This completely rejects Martin Heidegger's representation
of Nietzsche's relation to science. A final, very unusual, feature of this account
is the list of major figures here, most of 'Vhom otherwise remain invisible in
Nietzsche's corpus: Boscovich himself, Lord Kelvin, Balfoure Stewart, Johann
Carl Friedrich Zollner, Robert Mayer and many others.
And in August, 1883, Nietzsche writes to Gast of his first exposure to the Jesuit
Boscovich, "who first mathematically demonstrated that, the assumption of
solid [eifiillter] atomic points is an unusable hypothesis for the most rigorous
science of mechanics [... ]."9 It is clear from the correspondence with Gast that
the primary significance of Boscovich as a thinker, so far as Nietzsche is
concerned, lies in his rejection of the massy corpuscular atom of newtonian
natural philosophy and in his discovery of point particle atomic theory.
In understanding the correspondence between Nietzsche and Gast, one should
realize that, Boscovich represents "the dynamic view of the world" to Nietzsche,
whereas Robert Mayer represents what he calls "the mechanistic view of the
world." Also within this latter group one finds Eugen Diihring and Lord Kelvin,
according to Nietzsche. The mechanistic worldview believes in the massy,
corpuscular, "little clump-atoms" of Newtonian physics, "cause and effect,"
"laws of nature," and especially irritating to Nietzsche, the "law of entropy."
Ultimately Nietzsche chose Boscovich over Robert Mayer as the scientific
underpinnings for his own theory of reality. This caused Gast to write painfully
of the slight as late as November 29, 1913, lamenting that instead of Mayer,
Nietzsche had
brought Boscovich of Ragusan into play, a mere mathematical thinking astronomer, who, as a
consequence of his mistaken notion of the nature of force, has arrived at the point of denying the
existence of matter: there is only force. Boscovich arrives to this nonsense from his atomistic
speculations: and since method lies therein, he pleased Nietzsche that much more, as the
physicist's insights, having become instinctual for him, went out of control. 10
In the meantime his [Nietzsche's] speculations had become much more responsive to the physical
theories of the Dalmatian mathematician Roger Boscovich [ ... ]. Unprejudiced by a thorough
grounding in contemporary physics, Nietzsche's thinking was in fact much closer to the spirit of
the nuclear age than to the views of the day prevalent in the experimental sciences. 11
He [Boscovich] has thought atomic theory to its conclusion. Gravity is certainly not a "property
of matter" at all, simply because there is no matter. Gravitation, as well as vis inertiae, is certainly
a manifestation of force (simply because there is nothing other than force!): only the logical
relation of this manifestation to the others, e.g. to heat, is not yet entirely clear. [... ] Kinematic
theory must minimally still grant forces of cohaesion and gravity, in addition to energy for motion,
to atoms. All materialistic physicists and chemists also do this!" 13
Such evidence proves beyond doubt that Nietzsche was thinking of Bos-
covich 's theory in its intricacies in 1882. Given this letter and other such
evidence, it no longer seems unlikely, but instead necessary, to link dozens of
previously unconnected, unexplained or cryptic notes in the Nachla~ of 1873-82
to Nietzsche's study of Boscovich. Further, it will be proven that notes of a
scientific nature directly related to Boscovich appear in the Nachlaj3 well into
the year 1888. I believe as many as one hundred notes may be clarified for the
first time in light of this discovery of Boscovich' s significance.
Gast' s comment that Nietzsche had "gone out of control" in his studies of the
mathematician, signifies not only that, Nietzsche was indeed intensively
studying Boscovich, but also that, Nietzsche did so without any mention of
Boscovich to his reading public, confiding only to the trustworthy Gast of his
intellectual struggle with Boscovich. Nietzsche's notes leave relatively few
mentions of his name, but his instinctual affinity to Roger Boscovich' s atomism,
once "out of control," resulted in the core of the massive Nachlaj3 of the years
1883-1888.
Gast was personally taken aback by the vehemence he found in Nietzsche's
attack on Robert Mayer. When Gast became editor of the Nachlaj3 for the
Groj3oktav-Ausgabe, he may have remembered the slight. Gast would have been
alerted from correspondence (SB 6 Brief 460), that Nietzsche discovered
Boscovich for himself during the early Basel years, when he had read a number
of atomic theorists. Purposely or not, Gast must have found the crucial
Boscovich study that Nietzsche left behind. This fragment, called the "Time
Atom Theory" ("Zeitatomenlehre"), appeared in the first edition of the GOA,
but not thereafter. Once the first, hurried and unsatisfactory, printing of the
GOA was withdrawn from the public and a more meticulous, carefully edited
ROGER J. BOSCOVICH AND FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE 191
printing was prepared, Gast realized what he had found in the "Time Atom
Theory." Thus it was expunged without a trace, until Schlechta and Anders
reprinted the text with photocopies of the handwritten manuscript in 1962.
Science- this has been hitherto a way of putting an end to the complete confusion in which things
exist, by hypotheses that "explain" everything- so it has come from the intellect's dislike of
chaos. -This same dislike seizes me when I consider myself: I should like to form an image of the
inner world, too, by means of some schema, and thus triumph over intellectual confusion. [... ]
Physics proves to be a boon for the heart: science (as the way to knowledge) acquires a new charm
after morality has been eliminated- and because it is here alone that we find consistency, we have
to construct our life so as to preserve it. This yields a sort of practical reflection on the conditions
of our existence as men of knowledge. 14
As for materialistic atomism, it belongs among the best-refuted things there are: perhaps no
scholar in Europe today is so unlearned as to still grant it serious meaning other than as a handy
device (namely. as an abbreviated means of expression)- Thanks above all to the Pole Boscovich,
who, along with the Pole Copernicus, has been the greatest and most victorious opponent of
appearances. While Copernicus has persuaded us, against all senses, that the Earth does not stand
stilL Boscovich taught us to renounce belief in the last thing of earth to "stand fast." belief in
"substance," in "matter," in the last remnant of Earth, the corpuscular atom [Kliimpchen-Atom]:
it was the greatest triumph over the senses achieved on Earth to this time. 15
Aside from the fact that Boscovich was a Dalmatian, and not a Pole, it is clear
from this section that Nietzsche understands Boscovich's place in the history of
atomism; for the latter adopts point particles - unextended and dynamic -the
"first elements of matter" in his atomism. He rejects the solid, extended
corpuscles of all atomism hitherto - what Nietzsche calls the "Kliimpchen-
Atom." With his doctrine of atomism, which modified the massy corpuscles of
Newtonian natural philosophy into immaterial centers of force, Boscovich
helped emancipate physics from naive atomism's uncritical assumption that the
ultimate units of matter are small, individual, rigid pieces possessing shape, size,
weight and other properties.
Nietzsche's notebooks reinforce the impression that Boscovich' s significance
as a thinker, according to Nietzsche, lies in the former's rejection of any and all
materiality. Nietzsche credits Boscovich with annihilation of "superstition"
about matter (KSA 9, 643), and elsewhere he credits Boscovich with the idea of
"no matter" (KSA 11, 231). In tracing his own intellectual development,
Nietzsche writes, " .. .1 do not believe in 'matter' and consider Boscovich one of
the great turning points like Copernicus [... ]" 16
Before concluding this section, I should note that Nietzsche refers to Johann
Gustav Vogt 17 and African Spir, 18 including page numbers and quotations,
proving that Nietzsche was reading Vogt and Spir in 1885, twelve years after the
'Time Atom Theory." In direct proximity to these notes, one finds a series of
aphorisms concerning "force-atoms," "force-combinations," "atoms," "shape of
space," and then a reference to Boscovich so clear as to be undeniable, once
recognized. "Mathematical physicists cannot employ corpuscular atoms
[Kliimpchen-Atome] for their science: consequently, they construe a force-point-
world, with which one can reckon." 19
ROGER J. BOSCOVICH AND FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE 193
Close to this aphorism are two more notes connecting Boscovich's dynamic
worldview to the idea of force and in turn connecting force to the idea of will
to power. 20 Also in this cluster is an aphorism entitled, "Following the trail of
the body" ("Am Leitfaden des Leibes"), a phrase Nietzsche used to describe
Boscovich's project. Notes crucial to the transformation of force into will to
power cluster in close proximity to these other important notes. This entire
series of notes decisively shows that Boscovich was foundational to develop-
ment of a theory of will to power, and that Nietzsche was employing the
former's concept of force while declining to note intellectual indebtedness. I
conclude from the evidence that every aphorism in the section designated,
"Presentation of the doctrine and its theoretical presuppositions and conse-
quences," in the 1885 notebooks, 21 relates directly to Roger Joseph Boscovich
and proves beyond a shadow of a doubt that his concept of force is the parent
theory to the notion of will to power.
It will be shown soon that Nietzsche was contemplating a long work on the
eternal return and its theoretical assumptions. Although the project was never
completed, he still wants to make clear "Our presuppositions: no God: finite
force." This is the great divide between metaphysics of substance and his new
world conception. In his notebooks of 1880-1882, we find a number of
significant aphorisms arguing for the finitude of force. These notes constitute
forerunners to an aphorism of extreme importance for my interpretation. It poses
the question,
There are no eternally enduring substances, matter is as much of an error as the God of the
Eleatics. But when shall we ever be done with our caution and care? When will all these shadows
of God cease to darken our minds? When will we complete our de-deification of nature? When
may we begin to "naturalize" humanity in terms of a pure, newly discovered, newly redeemed
nature? (GS 109)
Yet this section does not contain the full answer to its own question. That awaits
a note from 1885:
What, then, is the Jaw and belief with which the decisive change, the recently attained preponder-
ance of the scientific spirit over the religious, God-inventing spirit, is most clearly formulated? Is
it not: the world, as force, may not be thought of as unlimited, for it cannot be so thought of; we
forbid ourselves the concept of an infinite force as incompatible with the concept "force." (WP
1062)
This note explicitly identifies Spinoza with the notion that the world intention-
ally avoids a goal and even knows artifices for keeping itself from entering into
a circular course. These artifices are infinite power: the infinite modification of
an infinite number of attributes endlessly into time, Nietzsche evidently reasons,
would require infinite force for its duration.
194 GREG WHITLOCK
The world, even if it is no longer a god, is still supposed to be capable of the divine power of
creation, the power of infinite transformations; it is supposed to consciously prevent itself from
returning to any of its old forms; it is supposed to possess not only the intention but the means of
avoiding any repetition; to that end, it is supposed to control every one of its movements at every
moment so as to escape goals, final states, repetitions - and whatever else may follow from such
an unforgiveably insane way of thinking and desiring. It is still the old religious way of thinking
and desiring, a kind of longing to believe that in some way the world is after all like the old
beloved, infinite, boundlessly creative God - that in some way "the old God still lives" - that
longing of Spinoza which was expressed in the words "deus sive natura" (he even felt "natura sive
deus"). (WP 1062)
One finds in the notebooks of 1880-82 several notes which reason that infinite
force implies infinite novelty and finite force implies finite novelty. 22 Consid-
ering that this period is one of intensive study of Spinoza, and that he is one of
the few sources of this obscure phrase, it is reasonable to conclude that
Nietzsche is working here with a principle found originally in Spinoza.
Proposition XVI of Spinoza's Ethics (Book One) deduces an infinite novelty of
modifications of substance from its infinite power: "From the necessity of the
divine nature there must follow infinite things in infinite ways [... ]." And
Nietzsche likewise reasons that finite power entails finite novelty in the
umverse:
This notion - that the world intentionally avoids a goal and even knows artifices for keeping itself
from entering into a circular course - must occur to all those who would like to force on the world
the ability for eternal novelty, i.e., on a finite, definite, unchangeable force of constant size, such
as the world is, the miraculous power of infinite novelty in its forms and states. (WP I 062)
Nietzsche completes this crucial note with the conclusion, "Thus - the world
also lacks the capacity for eternal novelty."
ROGER J. BOSCOVICH AND FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE 195
And so while it was Boscovich's reasoning that had lead from rejection of
substance to finite force, it is Spinoza's reasoning (albeit inverted) which leads
from finite force to finite novelty. And this makes sense, since any finite
universe will only be able to contain a finite amount of anything. Indeed,
Boscovich says that infinitude is not found in nature, even though there may be
an infinite insertibility of points in a finite space. Whether or not the scientific
spirit requires the postulates of finite space and force remains a peripheral
question to my inquiry. What is of import here is the fact that once Nietzsche
began his elucidation of the theoretical presuppositions of his notion of eternal
return, he correctly saw the implications of Spinoza' s proposition and its
converse. It is in the notebooks of 1880-1882 that this reasoning may be found.
The world of forces never attains equilibrium, never has a moment of rest, its force and its
movement are equally great at all times. (KSA 9, 498)
The cycle is not something that has become, it is fundamental principle, just as quantitative force
is fundamental principle, without exceptions and violations. All beconting is within the cycle and
its quantitative force[ ... ]. (KSA 9, 502)
In such a world there is no matter, there is only force. From the notes of
1880-82 we may stitch together a worldview showing decisive contributions by
Boscovich. Dozens of notes in KSA 9 evidence the influence of Boscovich on
Nietzsche's vocabulary and ideas. In close proximity to this early sketch of
eternal return, one finds evidence of continued interest in pointal "sensation
theory" (KSA 9, 312). There is an important early shift from force to the feeling
offorce (KSA 9, 438-9). Continued interest in atomism is evident in many other
notes as well. 23 And there is an attempt to bridge the world of atomic force to
organic life (KSA 9, 493).
Strong echoes of the "Time Atom Theory" may be heard in various other
notes: "the instant as highest reality" " (KSA 9, 502); "states of force" (530);
"impact" (542); "currents of force" (548); "movement is time" (549); "absolute
flux" (554); "time point" (558); "force centers of the universe" (560); "timeless-
ness and succession" (565]); "force requires time" (603]); "Being is the sum of
all relations" (620).
There are a number of notes employing the concept of force (KSA 9, 11 [169],
KSA 9, 11 [ 184], KSA 9, 11 [20 1]) and a number of passages based on the
finitude of force in the universe (KSA 9, 11 [202], KSA 9, 11 [292] and KSA 9,
11 [345]), both representing legacies of Boscovich studies. 24
If one remains unconvinced that Boscovich is the source of the concept of
force underlying so many notes, Nietzsche's reference to "the last consequence"
of the mechanist idea of motion as "force in mathematical points and mathe-
196 GREG WHITLOCK
Any interval whatever will be finite, and at least divisible indefinitely by the interpolation of other
points, and still others; each such set however, when they have been interpolated, will be also
finite in number. So that there is only an infinity of possible points, but not of existing points. [... ]
Further, in this way, by doin~ awa:S with all idea of an actual infinity in existing things. truly
countless difficulties are got nd of. ·
But most especially, they (non-extended points) do away with the idea of everything continuous
coexisting. [... ] Further, nothing infinite is found actually existing; the only thing possible is a
series of finite things produced indefinitely. 26
Yet Boscovich deduces not an indefinite repetition of finite things, but rather
an indefinite duration of forces in a finite space. This is possible without
repetition for Boscovich, because space has infinite componibility, allowing that
no point of matter ever occupy the same point of space occupied by another
point of matter, nor that the same point of space is ever occupied by itself at any
other time.
We come now to perhaps the strangest chapter in an already surprising
intellectual history. For in the Appendix on Mind and God to the Theoria
Philosophia: Natura/is, Boscovich argues from the finitude of force to infinite
novelty, and from there to the necessary existence of God, whom he calls "the
External Being." It will flabbergast even the casual reader of the Theoria to
come upon the sentence, "[ ... ] now, as regards the Divine Founder of Nature
ROGER J. BOSCOVICH AND FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE 197
Himself, there shines forth very clearly in my Theory, not only the necessity of
admitting His existence in every way, but also His excellent and infinite Power,
Wisdom and Foresight [... ]," 27 since his theory explicitly rejects infinite force,
and since there is no necessity whatsoever for God in the physical theory of the
Thea ria. Indeed, Boscovich calls God the External Being, because He is the
Being perfectly external to force. In a letter to Gast, Nietzsche emphasizes the
fact that God is unnecessary to Boscovich's theory, whereas God is essential to
Robert Mayer's theory.
Now of course, as previously noted, Boscovich was a devout Jesuit and was
expected to include in any such major work some clear admission of orthodoxy.
Thus with his Appendix, Boscovich won the approval of the "Censors of the
College of Padua" and the "Inquisitor General of the Holy Office in Venice,"
and was then successfully "registered in the High Court for the Prevention of
Blasphemy" on September 18, 1758. It is a forgotten quirk of intellectual history
that Boscovich's "proof' of God's existence rests on actual infinity, a supposi-
tion that the entire Theoria Philosophice Natura/is rejects out of necessity and
accepts only here. But then the Censors of the College were not likely to read
any of the text, one assumes, and would instead go directly to the Appendix on
Mind and God.
I must conclude from this evidence that Nietzsche knew Boscovich followed
the logic of eternal return to the brink of its conclusion, but averted it by
denying his own tenets. In arguing for the necessity of God, Boscovich argued
against three counter-views: first, that the universe is fortuitous; second, that the
universe is the result of fate; and third, that the universe has existed through
time by laws of its own. All these positions play a role in the idea of eternal
return. In each of his arguments, Boscovich suddenly suspends a basic tenet to
introduce a necessary premiss for the Creator's existence. Thus we read with
completely new insight a passage from 1888:
We need not worry for a moment about the hypothesis of a created world. [... ] I have come across
this idea in earlier thinkers: every time it was determined by other ulterior considerations(- mostly
theological, in favor of the creator spiritus). 28
Boscovich could be relied upon to furnish a dynamic worldview that does not
require God in any meaningful way. Once Nietzsche gathered the scientific
principles he desired from the Theoria, Boscovich would not play a wider role
in his philosophy. This earns Boscovich the title of head engineer for the
construction crew of Nietzsche's "new world conception." For, although
Nietzsche knew of several atomists ·- Johann Gustav Vogt, Thomas Fechner,
Schmitz-Dumont, Otto Liebmann and of course Democritus - , it was only
Boscovich who had "die atomische Theorie zu Ende gedacht." In Nietzsche's
eyes, only Boscovich had disproven the notion of matter, and with it the last
semblance of substance and God. Nietzsche recognized the ulterior theological
motives of such smoke screens as the Appendix on Mind and God. In overcom-
ing Newtonian atomism, Boscovich achieved what even the great Spinoza could
not do: namely, to let go of the last metaphysical refuge of God.
198 GREG WHITLOCK
FINAL NOTE
All his work, finally, may be read as physical essays in the working out of an epistemology and
metaphysic that styled his career in a way, again, not at all characteristic of his century. 1... ] Sharp
in thought, bold in spirit, independent in judgment, zealous to be exact, BoskoviC was a man of
eighteenth-century European science in some respects and far ahead of his time in others. Among
his works are writings that still repay study. and not only from a historical point of view. 29
Boscovich was accomplished in the art of poetry, or gai saber. A sort of knight
of la gaya scienza, he lived his life in Mediterranean cultures (Dalmatia, Italy
and France), which Nietzsche closely associated with ')oyful science." Indeed,
Boscovich warned that, in order to reach the center of his untimely "medita-
tions," his readers would require acrior mentis acies atque animi audentior vis
(a great sharpness of mind and a high audacity of spirit) -how appropriate a
description of Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche! Even though Nietzsche probably
knew little ofBoscovich's personal history, the latter's Theoria, well-known to
Nietzsche, was a tour de force of joyful science.
Not only was Boscovich a sort of higher type in the Nietzschean sense,
Nietzsche seemed to believe that his new scientific conception of the world,
with some alterations, would provide an alternative to superstition for all other
higher types, just as the Spirit of Science rescues higher mankind from the
Wagnerian Magician in Part IV of Zarathustra. While we may not be certain
that the Spirit of Science loosely characterizes Boscovich, consider that it was
only Boscovich' s new conception of "the force-point world" that cleared the air
for Nietzsche himself, immediately after his flight from Wagner's Bayreuther
Festspiel, just as, after an Ass Festival, the Spirit of Science rescues Zarathus-
tra's higher man from the Magician's Wagnerian spell in the chapter "On
Science." During his period as a publicist and enthusiast for Wagner at
Tribschen, Nietzsche's scientific interests were cloaked; after his break with
Wagner, however, Nietzsche wrote a series of books showing special interest in
science (and rejection of Wagnerian and Schopenhauerian ideas). By returning
to his early interest in science, Nietzsche rediscovered himself, as well as
Boscovich' s scientific spirit.
By comparing the Boscovichian Scientific Spirit to the other higher men, we
may get a rough estimation of Boscovich's importance to Nietzsche relative to
the latter's other intellectual predecessors. For example, although David
Friedrich Strauss had "killed God," Boscovich's "force-point world" goes still
further, in Nietzsche's opinion, to refute the last vestige of Substance meta-
physics; i.e. belief in the solid atom. Much like the Ugliest Man in Part IV of
ROGER J. BOSCOVICH AND FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE 199
NOTES
1 Roger Joseph Boscovich (Rudjer Josef Boskovic) was born on September 18, 1711, in
Ragusan, Dalmatia. In 1744 he entered the Jesuit priesthood. Branislav Petronievic, professor of
philosophy at University of Belgrade, writes that "Boscovich was at once philosopher, astronomer,
physicist, mathematician, historian, engineer, architect and poet. In addition he was a diplomat and
a man of the world; and yet a good Catholic and a devoted member of the Jesuit order." Boscovich
published about one hundred scientific treatises (most in Latin) and had an academic scientific
reputation on the entire European continent and England. He finished his principal work, Theoria
Philosophice Naturalis Redacta ad Unicam Legem Virium in Natura Existenrium (A Theory of
Natural Philosophy Reduced to a Single Law c{ the Actions Existing in Nature), in Vienna in 1758,
issuing a definitive edition in Latin and English under the author's supervision in 1763. Boscovich,
in the words of L. L. Whyte, was "the first scientist to develop a general physical theory using
point particles," antedating modern atomic theory by one hundred years. [... ] Boscovich's work
marked an important stage in the history of our ideas about the universe, and his system will
remain the paradigm of the theory of point particles." In other words, Roger Joseph Boscovich is
the undisputed founder of one of the three families of atomic theory. Boscovich travelled
extensively and was highly esteemed in social circles in France, Italy and elsewhere. He met
200 GREG WHITLOCK
fellow free-thinker Benjamin Franklin in London and observed Franklin experimenting with
electricity. Boscovich knew Serbo-Croatian, Italian, Latin and French. Roger Joseph Boscovich
died on February 13, 1787, due to an extended lung ailment.
2 My translation of KSA 11, 26[432]: ··wenn ich an meine philosophische Genealogie denke,
so fuhle ich mich im Zusammenhang mit der antiteleologischen, d. h. spinozistischen Bewegung
unserer Zeit, doch mit dem Unterschied, daB ich auch ,den Zweck' und ,den Willen' in uns fur
eine Tauschung halte; ebenso mit der mechanistischcn Bewegung [... ] doch mit dem Unterschied,
daB ich nicht an ,Materie' glaube und Boscovich fiir einen der groBen Wendepunkte halte, wie
Copernicus [... ]."
3 Boscovich, Roger Joseph: Theoria Philosophia: Naturalis Redacta ad Unicam Legem Virium
in Natura Existentium. Chicago, London, 1922. Latin-English edition from the text of the first
Venetian edition published under the personal superintendence of the author in 1763.
4 Karl Schlechta und Anders, Anni: Friedrich Nietzsche. Von den verborgenen Anfiingen seines
Philosophierens, (Stuttgart, Bad Cannstadt, 1962), pp. 60-72.
' George J. Stack, Lange and Nietzsche (Berlin: De Gruyter, New York, 1983).
6 Gunter Abel, Nietzsche. Die Dynamik der Willen zur Macht und die ewige Wiederkehr (Berlin:
De Gruytcr, 1984).
7 Babette E. Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science: Reflecting Science on the Ground of Art
and Life (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994).
s "Wenn irgend Etwas gut widerlegt ist so ist cs das Vorurteil vom "Stoffe": und zwar nicht
durch einen Idealisten sondern durch einen Mathematiker- durch Boscovich. Er und Copernikus
sind die beiden gross ten Gegner des Augenscheins: Seit ihm giebt es keinen Stoff mehr, es sei denn
als populare Erleicherung. Er hat die atomische Theorie zu En de gedacht." Nietzsche, Siimtliche
Briefe 6 Brief213; henceforth: SB.
9 " ... der zuerst mathematisch demonstrirt hat, daB die Annahme erfUllter Atompunkte eine fiir
die strengste Wissenschaft der Mechanik unbrauchbare Hypothese sei [... ]" SB 6 Brief 460.
10 Correspondence cited in Frederick R. Love, Nietzsche's Saint Peter. Genesis and Cultivation
of an Tllusion, (Berlin, New York, de Gruyter, 1981) p.l88. The German text reads: " ... den
Ragusaner Boscovich ins Feld fiihrt, einen bloB mathematisch denkenden Astronomen, der infolge
seiner irrigen Vorstellung vom Wesen der Kraft an den Punkt gelangt, die Existenz der Materie
zu leugnen: es gebe nur Kraft. Boscovich kommt von seinen atomistischen Spekulationen auf
diesen Unsinn: und da Methode darin lag, so gefie1 er Nietzsche urn so mehr, als diesem die
instinktgewordenen Physiker-Einsichten zur Kontrolle abgingen."
11 Love, Nietzsche's Saint Peter. pp. 187-188.
12 Lancelot Law Whyte, Roger Boscovich S.J.. F.R.S., 1711-1787: Studies of His Life and Work
o,n the 250th Anniversary of His Birth (London and New York, 1961 and 1964 ), p. 102.
1_, "Er [Boscovich] hat die atomische Theorie zu Ende gedacht. Schwere ist ganz gewif3 keine
,Eigenschaft der Materie,' einfach wei! es keine Materie giebt. Schwerkraft ist, ebenso wie die vis
inertiae, gewiB eine Erscheinungsform der Kraft (einfach wei! es nichts anderes giebt als Kraft'):
nur ist das logische VerhaltniB dieser Erscheinungsform zu andercn, z. B. zur Warme, noch ganz
undurchsichtig. [... 1 Die kinetische Theorie muB den Atomen mindestens auBer der Bewegung-
senergie noch die beiden Krafte der Cohaesion und der Schwere zuerkennen. Dies tun auch a lie
materialistischen Physiker und Chemiker 1" SB 6 Brief 213.
14 "Die Wissenschaft- das war bisher die Beseitigung der vollkomrnenen Verworrenheit der
Dinge durch Hypothesen, welche alles 'erklaren' -also aus dem Widerwillen des Intellekts an dem
Chaos.- Dieser selbe Widerwillen ergreift mich bei Betrachtung meiner seiher: die innere Welt
mochte ich auch durch ein Schema mir bildlich vorstellen und tiber die intellektuelle Verworren-
heit herauskommen. [... ]Die Physik ergibt sich als eine Wohltat ftir das Gemtith: die Wissenschaft
(als der Weg zur Kenntnij]) bekommt einen neuen Zauber nach der Beiseitigung der Moral- und
wei/ wir hier aile in Consequenz finden, so mtissen wir unser Leben darauf einrichten, sie uns zu
erhalten. Dies ergiebt eine Art praktischen Nachdenkens tiber unsere Existenzbedingungen als
Erkennende." (All emphases in original.) KSA 10, 24118]; WP 594.
15 My translation of Jenseits von Gut und Bose §12: "Was die materialistische Atomistik betrifft:
so gehort dieselbe zu den bestwiderlegten Dingen, die es giebt; vielleicht ist heute in Europa
Niemand unter den Gelehrten mehr so ungelehrt, ihr ausser zum bequemen Hand- und Hausge-
brauch (namlich als einer Abktirzung der Ausdrucksmittel) noch eine crnstliche Bedeutung
zuzumessen- Dank vorerstjenem Polen Boscovich, der, mitsammt dem Polen Kopemicus, bisher
der grosste und siegreichste Gegner des Augenscheins war. Wahrend namlich Kopernicus uns
tiberredet hat zu glauben, wider aile Sinne, dass die Erde nicht fest steht, lehrte Boscovich dem
Glauben an das Letzte, was von der Erde ,feststand,' abschworen, dem Glauben an den , Stoff,'
an die ,Materie, · an das Erdenrest- und K!Umpchen-Atom: es warder grosste Triumph tiber die
ROGER J. BOSCOVICH AND FRIEDRICH NIETZSCHE 201
Sinne, der bisher auf Erden errungen worden ist." Both translations of this section by Walter
Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale contain noteworthy flaws. Kaufmann alters Nietzsche's text
without so much as a footnote: in the German Nietzsche (mis)identifies Boscovich as a Pole,
whereas Kaufmann changes the text to identify Boscovich (correctly) as Dalmatian. While
probably attempting to save Nietzsche from error, Kaufmann misinforms the English reader about
the text and robs Nietzsche of his purposeful, if questionable, misidentification of the Dalmatian
as a Pole. Hollingdale mistranslates "Kliimpchen-Atom" as "particle atom," whereas Nietzsche
means by this term, more specifically, a solid-particle atom, or corpuscular atom.
16 " •• .ich nicht an ,Materie' glaube und Boscovich fiir einen der groBen Wendepunkte halte, wie
KSA 9, 11[345].
25 Roger Joseph Boscovich, Theoria Philosophire Natura/is Redacta ad Unicam Legem Virium
in Natura Existentium (Chicago, London, 1922), p. 89.
26 Ibid. p. 21.
27 Ibid. p. 379.
28 Kaufmann's translation of KSA 13, 14[188] as Will to Power 1066: "Die Hypothese einer
geschaffenen Welt sol! uns nicht einen Augenblick bekiimmern. [... ] Ich bin auf diesen Gedanken
bei friiheren Denkern gesto~en: jedes Mal war er durch andere Hintergedanken bestimmt ( -
meistens theo1ogische, zu Gunsten des creator spiritus)."
29 Zeljko Markovic, Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Volume II. Charles Gillespie (ed.), (NY:
Scribner and Sons, 1970). See entry for Boskovic. Rudger J., pp. 326-332. Quotations are found
on pp. 328 and 331.
PATRICK A. HEELAN
INTRODUCTION
Nietzsche was the first to draw attention to what was later to be called the crisis
of modernity. 2 This he saw as a moral challenge flowing from the metaphysical
commitment of German- and all Western- culture to the Platonic-Socratic or
Apollinian myth of science (and all scholarship) as giving absolute privilege to
theoretical knowledge. 3 This created a false optimism based on the theoretical
notion of human equality and the human conviction that through science the
social and physical environment could be managed in the interests of human
fulfillment. It also implied the rejection of the tragic Dionysian myth of human
existence that alone, according to Nietzsche, made possible the life-enhancing
203
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 203-220.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
204 PATRICK A. HEELAN
virtues of creativity and freedom or (what he called) the Will to Power. 4 The
special scientific Apollinian (alternatively, Alexandrian) metaphysics sustaining
this culture5 is to be rejected, because it has lost or forgotten the implicit role of
the human subject in the constitution of all theoretical knowledge- of both facts
and concepts. The inquiring theorizing spirit characteristic of "modem man" or
"theoretical man" claims in the name of this metaphysics to "explain" or
"clarify" the life world by substituting for a practical understanding of nature and
culture a theoretical explanatory system, that is, a system of abstract, objective
-usually mathematical- representational models. 6 While the practicallifeworld
revealed to human knowers the environment constituted by human action, and
thus by (what he called) the Will to Power, the explanatory scientific models
that took its place in the metaphysical order were (in his view) mistakenly
presented as "truth," that is, representational truth (in the objective sense) as the
picture of reality as it is independently of human culture. What our culture then
takes to be scientific "facts" are not so: "No, facts are precisely what they are
not, only interpretations," (WP 481) and what it takes to be "truth," is not truth,
but an "illusion of truth" (cf. BT 14-18; GS 112 and 354; BGE 24; TL 84).
In his view, then, Apollinian metaphysics or the metaphysics of theory
identifies reality with a fixed framework of pure possibilities that explicitly
voids all moral and cultural ends while implicitly supporting the conservative
ends of (what he called) the "weak" or "mediocre [political] majority." This puts
the life-enhancing Will to Power, basic to authentic moral and cultural action,
at a metaphysical disadvantage within modern public culture. He concludes: a
society constituted on the metaphysical basis of scientific explanations is
doomed to sterility, meaninglessness, and nihilism.
Nietzsche's own judgment about scientific theories was that they function as
"over-simplified" and "error-ridden" 7 instruments of environmental control
implicitly oriented toward the same life's purposes that illumine the lifeworld
of modernity, and hence as conservative life-sustaining powers that are the
antithesis of life-enhancing powers (cf. BGE 21, 22, and 24; WP 610). He
concludes: a philosophy and epistemology of perspectivalism (WP 481) is
needed as the only way to ensure the return of theories to the service of
creativity and freedom, or the Will to Power.
Such a very anti-Kantian, anti-realist, now called postmodern, analysis of
science- and, of course, of all scholarship- is not as negative as it sounds. Nor
indeed is the option for perspectivalism as revolutionary about religion and
morality as one fears, no matter how one understands the ground for an
authentic moral cultural life which Nietzsche called the Will to Power. "The
illusion of truth," "the truth of illusion," "Will to Power," and "nihilism" - all
key terms for Nietzsche - need not be saddled with fearful and demonic
meanings pace Nietzsche's apocalyptic rhetoric. They are forceful terms used
to rock the boat of a very entrenched metaphysics, the metaphysics of modernity
and its moral failures, seen now in hindsight as it were prophetically in
anticipation of the European and global social and environmental tragedies of
this century. Nietzsche's charges were repeated in a more academically
acceptable rhetoric by later German philosophers, notably Husser! in his critique
NIETZSCHE'S PERSPECTIV ALISM 205
thought. 15 The temporal nature of the human inquirer as Dasein 16 followed from
the fact that Dasein was "thrown" into the life-world at a particular time and
place with a basic orientation of "circumspection" or "care," and from Dasein 's
awareness of the inevitability of death. These seem to limit the possibilities of
recollection, and to permit no more than the limited ability and responsibility of
Dasein 's living authentically in the midst of inauthenticity. This implies that in
all human projects handed down by tradition the disclosedness of Being is
conditioned by the partial hiddenness or forgottenness of a background only
revealed by and partially recoverable from the texts and other cultural legacies
of tradition. 17
While Husserl and Heidegger knew of Nietzsche's work and were to some
extent responding to it, American pragmatism was responding to its own sense
of dissatisfaction with British and German idealism and home-grown religious
dogmatism. While fundamentally "realist" (committed to an objective, progres-
sively knowable, order of things), pragmatists would nevertheless have been
sympathetic toward Nietzsche's criticism of the "metaphysics" of scientific
theory- Dewey named it critically, the "spectator theory of knowledge"- and
for reasons other than those that motivated Nietzsche's pessimism, they coopted
scientific method with optimism as a willing partner in the life-enhancing
transformation of public values and culture.
Returning to Neitzsche, it would be a great mistake to think that Nietzsche
undertook the task of refuting physical or scholarly theories in general. Like any
German professor he was used to intellectual debate, accepting challenges, and
making counterchallenges in the society of his academic peers - hence his
exclamation, "Long live physics!" (GS 335). What he meant was, "Long live
Wissenschaft in all the faculties!" But he wanted to distinguish what properly
belonged to science, namely, that it should promote - or, at least, not offend
against - moral life and cultural freedom, and what did not, namely, the
imperialistic and morally decadent tendency to use scientific knowledge in the
interests of universal social and environmental management. 18 It is within this
context that he addressed the epistemological and ontological foundation of
scientific theorizing in the life-world.
The discussion that follows attempts to address this question in a contempo-
rary way. 19 The views expressed here are not proposed as a historical recon-
struction of Nietzsche's own (insofar as scholars are able to reconstruct his
views historically), but as a contemporary philosophical answer to Nietzsche's
challenge that surely derives from his work (I will indicate relevant textual loci
in the notes) and from the reflections of others, particularly, Heidegger, who in
a similar spirit have confronted this challenge.
Let me start with a discussion of meaning and its production by henneneutic
methods.
MEANING
Meaning is not a private mental entity but a shared social entity embodied in
language (understood always to include other language-like inscriptions,
NIETZSCHE'S PERSPECTIVALISM 207
provide. In this work lies the significance and power of hermeneutic philosophy
or perspectivalism for the history and philosophy of science. And not just for
these, but also for understanding how quantitative empirical methods function
in science to give meaning to empirical contents, in particular, how measure-
ment equipment plays a double role creating two concinnous perspectives,
theoretical and cultural, and how through these joint perspectives theory-laden
data depend on the successful public self-presentation in measurement of the
measured entity as a public cultural entity.
As a prelude to our attempt to address these topics further we need to
consider the nature of philosophical inquiry.
THEORETICAL UNDERSTANDING
By focusing his discussion initially on equipment and the like, Heidefger makes
a special and highly critical point about theoretical understandini . Since the
characteristic goal of all scientific or scholarly inquiry is theoretical under-
standing, it is important to understand what theory does. The theoretical
perspective, as in the case of the broken hammer, is always connected with
some piece of equipment -not excluding words, sentences, and representations
- designed to fill some social or cultural function. Theory-making arises then
out of some public need and the requirement of learning how to fulfill that need.
In this respect, Nietzsche and Heidegger are in parallel with pragmatism. 36
Heidegger would remind us that, when presented with a real piece of equipment,
say, a hammer, we must realize on the one hand that the physical theory of a
hammer does not assign to it an exclusive or "objective" essence, for that which
can function as a hammer can function in other ways too, as door stop,
nutcracker, etc., and on the other hand that old shoes and wooden mallets can
also be used to hammer nails. 37 All real tools or equipment are (as Heidegger
says) no more than a mere resource 38 unless they are in actual use or designated
for use, when they become dedicated (or designated) resources. Equipment is
a dedicated resource when it is pragmatically related to the fulfillment of its role
within a cultural function-as-meant. 39 The distinction is significant because only
dedicated resources belong to the furniture of the lifeworld and so have antic
status.
These distinctions are reflected in the use of words. The sentence, "I want a
hammer," can be used in a theory-laden 40 perspective where the sentence refers
to the physical structure that makes hammering possible, or in a praxis-laden
perspective where the sentence refers to something that is in actual use or
designated for use in construction. Words and sentences about tools or equip-
ment take on different meanings according to whether they are used in one or
other of these perspectives.
Returning to the cultural praxis-laden perspective: what is the meaning of the
hammer in this perspective? It is what ties a thing- the hammer- to construc-
tion or building projects. This is different from its meaning in the theory-laden
perspective which relates the hammer to its specifications as a tool and
NIETZSCHE'S PERSPECTIVALISM 211
"explains" the thing qua hammer by specifying the physical conditions under
which it can be the host of the cultural meaning of a hammer. There are then
two c:oncinnous perspectives inseparably joined in dialogue, a theory-laden
perspective and a cultural praxis-laden perspective. They are concinnous
because the theory-laden meaning makes sense only if the real hammer is
praxis-laden within the function of construction.
Despite the fact then that (hammer-) theory "explains" (hammering-) praxis,
the language of theory and the language of praxis belong to different concinnous
perspectives. Concinnity does not imply that there is a one-to-one correlation
between the two perspectives,41 for the (hammer-) theory-ladenness of a thing
is just a mere possibility of serving as a real hammer (it could alternatively serve
as a nutcracker), and the (hammering-) praxis-ladenness of the thing in the
context of construction could be served by means other than the use of ham-
mers.42 Theory can inaugurate revolutionary changes at the practical and
cultural level such as, for instance, when theory-based research makes available
new plastic construction materials that can be shaped into complex ready-made
units by molding, bypassing (let us assume) the need for carpentry. And
practical inventions can inaugurate revolutionary changes in theory, such as, for
instance, when the practical development of steam power in the nineteenth
century called forth a new calorific science, thermodynamics. 43
Moreover, when new measurement-based technologies are added to the
life-world, scientific terms, such as "temperature," can be introduced into
everyday descriptive language endowed with new non-theoretical and practical
life-world meanings which can be used to create, designate, employ, and control
new classes of entities, such as thermometers, in the lifeworld. With the help of
these increased resources, it is possible for the old cultural environment to be
changed in significant, even revolutionary, ways. In the quattrocento during the
Italian Renaissance, for example, perceptual space came to be subjected to
universal measurement and to analysis according to the principles of the newly
discovered mathematical perspective; in this process public space was trans-
formed from one with variable, local geometries into one with a single Euclid-
e.an ~ometry, thus preparing the way for Galileo and the Copernican revolu-
tion.
In any case, to be theory-laden means to "explain," that is, to lay out the
conditions, why something can play a particular socio-cultural role, but it does
not explain whether, or if so why, it is in fact playing that role or has been
designated to play that role. "To be theory-laden" then always implies an
implicit cultural hypothetical, "provided the real (individual, historical)
explanandum has been chosen for the appropriate role." Otherwise "to be
theory-laden" implies no more than "to be a mere resource,"- and this no more
entitles it to be included in the furniture of the world than every old shoe under
the category of hammer.
What kind of entity then is a hammer as a dedicated resource? It is a public
cultural reality, a physical reality constituted by a socio-cultural meaning. 45 It
has a theory-laden meaning that conceals (renders tacit/implicit) but does not
replace (say, by a reductive move) the cultural perspective of construction and
212 PATRICK A. HEELAN
MEASUREMENT
TRUTH
Nietzsche's "illusion of truth" and "truth of illusion" find a partial clarification
in this analysis. But it was Heidegger who embodied this multiplicity of
meaning in his choice of the Greek term, aletheia (literally "uncovering") for
truth. 55 It signaled a change in the notion of truth from the classical model of
full transparency to the human mind 56 - what Nietzsche called the "illusion of
truth"- towards one of only partial, practical, or perspectival transparency-
which Nietzsche called the "truth of illusion." 57 Let us reflect on the history of
this transformation of the notion of truth.
People everywhere and always have lived in a socially, linguistically
represented, action-oriented world in which what a thing is must be derived
from what it comes to mean within human life, that is, from (what Nietzsche
called) the Will to Power. This is what Husserl, Heidegger, and the pragmatists
called "the lifeworld,"58 and for which W. Sellars coined the term "manifest
image of the world." 59 Within this perspective, many things are first grasped as
having fixed essences dedicated "by nature" (as it were) to a single function.
214 PATRICK A. HEELAN
Such was the opinion of the Platonic Socrates and Aristotle, Aquinas and
Descartes, Bacon and Newton, and it is a view that continues to be shared by
many scientists and philosophers today.
With the advent of modernity, however, the world changed, adopting as its
defining characteristic an inquiring theorizing scientific spirit. 60 This declares
open season for scientific inquiry into whatever is given in human experience;
not just hammers, but also political society, perception, food, athletics,
emotions, love, and even religion, all present themselves as possible subjects for
scientific scrutiny. From each study, a theory emerges that "explains" a
socio-cultural phenomenon by a set of (physical or cultural) theoretical
parameters. Modernity took its metaphysics from this set of parameters and
embraced it as the independently objective real, to know which was to possess
"truth."
This, as Nietzsche, Husser!, and Heidegger saw, was a radical rnistake. 61 As
in the case of the hammer, the theoretical set of parameters addresses just one
aspect of the real exemplars, the explanandum, namely, the aspect what was
chosen for explanation. Other aspects of these are overlooked and generally
forgotten. Moreover, in the search to explain the explanandum, the theorizing
process discovers the extent to which the function of the explanandum can be
taken over by different things or artifacts from the exemplars studied. One
(surprising?) outcome of this process is that it shows: what makes this or any
real hammer to be a hammer - or what makes this or any real thing in human
experience to be what it is perceived to be - is not a defining essence but a
movable contextual set of properties that can be found or engineered in many
different ways in many different physical hosts.
In summary, the hermeneutic- and Nietzschean - truth about things in the
lifeworld is: their meanings are not essential but cultural (and historical) and
disclosed by implicitly theory-laden praxes, which, when (under successful
scientific inquiry) their theory-ladenness is made explicit, can be re-engineered
with a consequent transformation of cultural meaning. This cycle of meaning
change takes place under the Will to Power and it can and does repeat itself
endlessly within the historicality of Being resulting in a diversity of new
perspectives and a possible loss of some of the old ones through (inevitable)
62
cultural forgetfulness.
TECHNOLOGY
Nietzsche's fear, shared strongly by Heidegger, was that to the extent that
theorizing scientific inquiry is successful, it turns the focus of inquiry away
from "life-enhancing" moral activity toward "life-preserving" "calculative"
thinking within an assumed "objective" frame of "reality" congruent with
today's modernity and aimed at management and control. 63
This is not to deny, however, that great benefits can and do flow from
scientific theories, not just in tradition-bound domains, such as, for example,
agriculture, housing, and construction, but in every domain from health care to
astronomy, even to human fertility and sexuality, for there is no domain that
NIETZSCHE'S PERSPECTIVALISM 215
Two aspects of Nietzsche's perspectivalism call for special notice. The first is
the indispensability of metaphor to the pursuit of perspectival insights. 67
Theoretical inquiry, as Nietzsche declares, always embarks on a project whose
goal is to construct a theory about a starting point that is anchored in the cultural
life of people. Scientific research is one such cultural forum. The creative
discovery process then is always at once constrained and promoted by the
condition that a meaningful relationship to some public, scientific or
non-scientific, often shifting cultural forum be maintained throughout the
inquiry. Here the role of metaphor is fundamental. 68 The history of science is
full of such examples where discovery is mediated by metaphors, from images
of billiard balls, elastic bands, aethers, mechanical devices, and molecular bench
models, to mathematical models like computer simulations, harmonic oscilla-
tors, ten-dimensional spaces, and hermetic religious concepts about the
cosmos. 69 Nor is it possible for a youthful scientist to come to understand
modern physics, biology, or any science without passing through stages of
metaphor. As in the search for theory, so in its application, theoretical instru-
ments apply to real situations in socially negotiated ways usually mediated by
metaphors, because these instruments of knowing function of necessity in a
cultural milieu that, being praxis-laden, does not need or support unlimited
univocity, fixity, or precision. 70
The second is the role of the Dionysian myth in the discovery process of
scientific research. Epistemological perspectivalism as a hermeneutic philoso-
phy treats science (and in general all scholarship) as a form of human culture
constituted by the search for and eventual discovery and articulation of new
meaning. From the viewpoint of Heidegger, meanings emerge into public
216 PATRICK A. HEELAN
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
This essay contains parts that were later elaborated in two essays: "Why a Hermeneutical
Philosophy of Natural Science?"' Man and World ( 1997): 271-298 and "Scope of Hermeneutics
in the Philosophy of Natural Science," Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29 (1998)
273-298.
NOTES
Babette E. Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science (Albany: State University of New York
Press, 1994) and "Continental Philosophies of Science: Mach, Duhem, and Bachelard," in
Routledge History of Philosophy, Volume VIII, Continental Philosophy in the Twentieth-Century
Philosophy (London and New York: Routledge), pp. 175-221.
2 Since Nietzsche wrote from multiple and varying perspectives, the interpretion of Nietzsche's
writings is best left to Nietzsche scholars and I have relied greatly on their work. I give special
thanks to Babette Babich and David Allison for their help. I have relied particularly on Babich,
Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science.
3 Within the German context of Nietzsche's writing, the term "science" applies not just to the
natural sciences, but to the goals of all scholarship. The orientation of the present paper is more
toward the natural than the human sciences.
4 Nietzsche's orientation is best seen in the Birth of Tragedy (New York: Vintage Books, 1966).
There he develops his critique of the Platonic Socrates and of the Apollinian - or alternatively,
Alexandrian - approach to culture which seeks theoretical explanations and logical clarifications.
There he also expounds the Dionysian approach to culture which is through myth, tragedy, and
music.
5 The word "culture" has many meanings. In this paper, I mean it in the cultural anthropological
sense defined by Clifford Gertz in "Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture,"
in Geertz, Local Knowledge, (New York: Basic Books, 1973), pp. 3-30.
6 See, for example, BT, Preface 2. Nietzsche's notion of theory was much influenced by the
positivists. For him, theory making is characterized by the organization of empirical facts under
clear, unambiguous, abstract, and universal concepts. Theory in a narrower sense is mathematical
and best exemplified in physics. The term "model" is taken as synonomous with "theory."
7 Referring to the inescapable divergence between abstract. particularly mathematical. purity and
precision, and real exemplars.
I was greatly helped here by Babich's discussion of Nietzsche's style in Nietzsche's Philosophy
of Science, Chap. I.
NIETZSCHE'S PERSPECTIVALISM 217
See Martin Heidegger, Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. Trans. by William
Levitt (New York: Harper and Row, 1977), pp. 133-134. Hereafter abbreviated as QCT.
10 In BT 14-18, Nietzsche compares scientific thinking associated with Socrates and Apollo to
the plastic arts and great moral thinking associated with the "mystical cry of Dionysus" to the art
of music. The sections referred to are important for understanding Nietzsche's suspicion of the
false optimism of scientific rationality and his opting for the pessimism of Dionysian multiper-
spectival thought.
1 See Babich, "On Nietzsche's Concinnity: An Analysis of Style," Nietzsche-Studien, 19, 1990,
Pf· 59-79 and EH, Z.
See Babich "On Nietzsche's Concinnity'"' where the notion of concinnity is explored as
describing Nietzsche's musical metaphor for perspectivalism in philosophy and culture.
13 See Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, chap. 2.
14 Edmund Husser!, The Crisis of European Science and Transcendental Philosophy. Trans. by
Blackwell, 1962). Originally published as Sein und Zeit, 1927. Hereafter abbreviated as SZ.
16 Heidegger's term for the human being; see SZ 27.
17 See BT, 43.
18 In this regard, Nietzsche saw parallels between science and Christian theology: in his view both
provided no more than theoretical enlightenment which led to weak and decadent moral
leadership; see GM, 25.
19 See the author's "Why a Hermeneutical Philosophy of the Natural Sciences?" for a more
distinct categorial being in the world, "ontological" signifying the background of Being in which
human life is lived and which defines what people are as Dasein or Being-in-the-World antecedent
to all descriptive categories.
22 This is what Husser! and Heidegger call the return to "die Sache selbst." This is, as it were, a
return to the Cartesian Cogito with a new and critical look. Husserl's return brought forth the
Cogito cogitatum as a correction of the Cartesian Cogito, and thereby introduced contextuality into
the analysis of experience. Heideggger probed deeper into the Cogito to discover the role of
fore-understanding - this is the active inquirer working with circumspective care within
experience before categories are formed or used to assert what is disclosed in experience. This is
the hermeneutical pre-predicative dimension of the Cogito cogitatum as "die Sac he selbst."
23 See the essays in C. Geertz, The Interpretation of Culture (New York: Basic Books, 1973) and
Local Knowledge.
24 The process of hermeneutic inquiry involves on the part of the receiver/interpreter what
Heidegger calls the Vorhabe (or background) and Vorsicht (clues to meaning) before moving to
the Vorgriff(data or outcome) of the inquiry. The clues to meaning can spring from many sources
- metaphors, analogies, models and, of course, the traditions of the researcher's discipline. See
SZ 191 on the "hermeneutical circle."
25 For the term "alchemy," our current resources may be poorer than the past; for the term
Volume 10, Constructing Knowledge in the History of Science, (1995): 139-163 for the difficulties
that philosophers and historians of science have in understanding one another.
27 There is a vibrant and copious cross-disciplinary literature about historical, religious, ethical,
political, and other cultural meanings of topics ranging from Big Bang Cosmology to ethical and
environmental aspects of science. Contributors include both scientists such as Stephen Hawking,
Steven Weinberg, Paul Davies, and Richard Dawkins, and ethicians, historians, sociologists, and
cultural anthropologists of science, and feminists.
28 Such traditions of interpretation tend to possess a rigidity of interpretation and an inauthenticity
that has to be overcome for the growth of knowledge; cf. BT, p. 29.
29 Paradigm revolutions are also associated with the temporality of Dasein and human communi-
33 See SZ 409.
34 See SZ 95-107.
35 For the purposes of this paper, "theories" and "categories" are taken to be reflexively defined
abstract objects such as scholarship and science provide; they have more or less clarity, more in
physics than in biology, and more in biology than in the human sciences. Theories are "explana-
tions" because they attempt to determine the (physical or cultural) pre-conditions sufficient
(perhaps, necessary) for an entity to fulfil its cultural function. An explanatory theory is
descriptive when it captures the cultural pre-conditions necessary for an entity to fulfil its cultural
function. Thus, among theories about hammering, we can distinguish an "explanatory" (hammer-)
theory that gives the physical specifications of the hammer as a tool, from an "explanatory and
descriptive" (hammering-) theory that describes the architectural and engineering environment
within which hammering plays a functional role. In neither case, however, does the theory refer
to a culture-independent entity.
36 Cf. BGE, 42; and SZ 408-415. "Hermeneutical Philosophy and Pragmatism: A Philosophy of
den," and later "Gestell." Okrent (1988), p. 74, translates it as " the extant (non-equipmental,
natural beings)." Mere resource is opposed to dedicated resource which translates Heidegger' s
Zuhanden, the difference being in a social choice.
39 See SZ 410.
°
4 For the notion of "theory-ladenness," see Norwood Russell Hanson, Patterns of Discoven·
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1961), pp. 19-30, and its source in Pierre Duhem, The
Aim and Structure of Physical Theory. (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1914/1954 ), Part
II, chaps. IV and VI. Among commentaries on observables as theory-laden, see also Heelan,
Space-Perception, pp. 202-204, and Ragnar Fjelland, 'The Theory-ladenness of Observations. the
Role of Scientific Instruments, and the Kantian A Priori," lnternat. Stud. in the Philosophy of'
Science, 5, 1991, pp. 269-280.
41 These two perspectives result in two ways of speaking, two context-dependent languages. about
the same thing that are related among themselves within a lattice structure which includes a least
upper bound (lub) and a greatest lower bound (glb) as well as complements. See Heelan, Space-
Perception, chaps. 10 and 13, where this thesis is presented. See also SZ 405-415.
42 Construction itself could be theory-laden; if so, its theory is not at the level of assigning
specifications for construction tools but rather at the level of architecture and engineering which
comprise the goals of construction.
43 Cf. SZ 29.
44 See Heelan, Space-Perception.
45 Cf., for example, "Common Sense as a Cultural System," pp. 73-93, in Geertz, Local
Knowledge.
46 The socio-cultural meaning then is not something that can be dropped, like slag from ore when
strictly philosophical but methodological. Philosophers of science have also written on measure-
ment but mostly from the viewpoint that empirical measures are grounded on ideal. objective, and
realistic values. For a hermeneutic view on measurement and data, see Heelan, "After Experiment:
Research and Reality," Amer. Philos. Qrtly., 26, #4, 1989, pp. 297-308. For its background in
Heidegger, see SZ 408-415.
48 In physics, these are sometimes called "preparation" or "measurement of the first kind" and
°
5 Cf. BGE 42.
51 Cf. WP 481.
52 It is also applicable to the representation of, what is called, a "closed" system, one that is not
interacting with its environment. The notion of a "closed system" needs further analysis within thi'
context - as indeed does its counterpart, "open system." Such an analysis would also include a
study of the space/time notions of "body," e.g., a body's "spatial boundaries," its "size," "mass.''
"quantity," etc. and how the notions of "macroscopic" and "microscopic" apply. Some of these
have been partially addressed in recent literature, e.g., see Paul Needham, "Macroscopic Objects:
An Exercise in Duhemian Ontology," Philosophy of Science, 63, 1996, pp. 205-224 and the
references he gives, but these studies are against a philosophical background that is object- and
NIETZSCHE'S PERSPECTIVALISM 219
concept-oriented. None of these studies addresses satisfactorily how the meaning of these terms
relate to a body's use, particularly, in measurement.
53 Joseph Rouse, Engaging Science (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1996), p. 27 and in chap.
9.
54 There is an alternative strategy: the researcher may re-evaluate the interpretative context of the
experiment and pursue another goal. For a more detailed study of data, see Heelan, "After
Experiment", also Space-Perception.
55 See SZ 256.
56 Such as the Tarskian notion of truth.
57 See SZ 58-63. Polanyi says the same in different terms: the focal meaning conceals a tacit
meaning; see Michael Polanyi, Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy (New
York: Harper Torchbooks, 1964).
58 See Husser!, The Crisis, Alfred Schutz, The Problem of Social Reality. Vol. I of Collected
in contrast took the "scientific image" to be the real or noumenal world, while he relegated the
contents of the manifest image to mere phenomena.
°
6 Cf. Nietzsche's BT 14-18; see also, for example, Heidegger's Discourse on Thinking:
Translation of Gelassenheit. Trans. by John Anderson and E. Hans Freund (New York: Harper and
Row, 1966), p. 46 and What is Called Thinking? Trans. by J.G. Gray (New York: Harper and Row,
1968), p.8; QCT 133.
61 Pragmatism, however, takes an ambiguous stand preferring not to see it as a radical mistake.
62 These conclusions prepare the ground for Babich's reading of Nietzsche's philosophy of
science in which the author explores with elegance Nietzsche's perspectivalism or musical
"concinnity" in relation to truth, morality, and the critique of science. Cf. also BT 29.
63 See, for example, BT 15; GS 347. Cf. Heidegger's QCT 3-35 and Discourse on Thinking, p.
46.
64 Gianni Vattimo, The Transparent Society (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992).
65 Robert Bly, The Sibling Society (Addison-Wesley, 1996).
66 The New Republic, Sept. 9 # 23, 1996, p. 34.
67 See, for example, GS, 300, 355. In particular, see TL, p. 84: "What is truth? a movable host of
metaphors, metonyns, anthropomorphisms: in short, a sum of human relations which have been
poetically and rhetorically intensified, transferred, and embellished, and which after long usage
seem to a people to be fixed, canonical, and binding. Truths are illusions which we have forgotten
are illusions, they are metaphors that have become worn out and have lost their sensuous force,
coins which have lost their image and are now considered as metal, and no longer as coins."
68 See Babich, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science, chap. 1, for an excellent account of Nietzsche's
views. For metaphor and discovery, see Gemma Corradi Fiumara, The Metaphoric Process:
Connections between Language and Life (London: Routledge, 1996); Mary Hesse and Michael
Arbib, The Construction of Reality (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986); and George
Lakoff and Mark Johnson, Philosophy in the Flesh (New York: Basic Books, 1999).
69 In Alistair C. Crombie, Styles of Scientific Thinking in the European Tradition: A History of
Argument and Explanation in the Mathematical and Biomedical Sciences and the Arts. Vols. 1 -
III (London: Duckworth, 1994) these topics are excellently covered. Marta Feher, "The Role of
Metaphor and Analogy in the Birth of the Principle of Least Action of Maupertuis ( 1698-1759),"
Internal. Stud. in the Philosophy of Science, 2, 1988, pp. 175-188, contains an interesting historical
discussion of the surprising absence of references to current hermetic literature in Galileo's work
which indicates that Galileo, unlike Newton, deliberately set aside or consigned to "forgetfulness"
a large part of the then-current scientific literature and praxis in order to establish his "new
sciences." See also Mario Bagioli, Galileo, Courtier (Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1993).
°
7 Cf., for example, Mara Beller, "The Rhetoric of Antirealism and the Copenhagen Spirit,"
Philosophy of Science, 63, 1996, pp. 183-204 and Heelan, Quantum Mechanics and Objectivity.
The Physical Philosophy of Werner Heisenberg (The Hague: Nijhoff, 1965). Some brief reflections
on the limits of precision: the chaos situation in physics is an anti-Cartesian phenomenon that
arises when the unlimited precision of a theory in mapping inputs and outputs breaks down (fails
in relation to the cultural scientific goal of control), as when small changes in practice produce
large and uncontrollable outcomes. Perhaps, a like anti-Cartesian phenomenon occurs in dielectical
discourse when unlimited clarity is pursued to a point where the overall cultural point of the
discourse (better understanding? ideological control?) is no longer attainable. On the side of the
social studies of science Bruno Latour, Science in Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press) seems to be most aware of this impasse.
220 PATRICK A. HEELAN
71 BT 16, where Nietzsche makes this allusion to Goethe's Faust, lines 6216ff.
72 See BT 10, for music, art, and the myth of Dionysos.
CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
221
B. Babich (ed.). Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 221-240.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
222 CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
And:
The stanzas about "God is dead" were not original. They reflected the sense
prevailing around 1930 of a fundamental crisis, perhaps subjectively colored by
the instinctive anticipation of a second world war, a war which in our anticipa-
tion would not be the last. The distancing moves in the four-liner on change are
more personal. Here one egocentric person differentiates himself from another,
claiming for his part the living water rather than consuming fire as the element
of his soul; a soul that believed itself never to have been tempted to steal away
from Apollo's followers to join the party of the Bacchants.
Re-reading Nietzsche today, five decades later, I see that the themes which
drove his philosophy of morality and history have in the seventh decade of my
life, only now, pushed me- without any direct influence from him- beyond the
phase of instinctive reaction into one of systematic reflection. It took my
encounter with physics, classical philosophy, and political responsibility and a
lifelong effort at working through religious experience. Now, if time remained
for me, I could begin the task of unders•anding Nietzsche critically and in this
way learn from him.
I have one further reservation, reiterating what others have previously
observed. I state it at this point to avoid a jarring interruption when we turn to
the issues themselves. For me, now that I am able, as I believe, to appreciate his
style more fully, Nietzsche the great stylist of language is as a stylist even more
unbearable than to the na"ive youth of fifty years ago. Zarathustra which I then
read innocently as prophesy, I today experience as an artistic product through
and through: the product of a great philosopher, of a genuine poet, with a
Wagnerian defenselessness against the temptation of the discordant notes of an
exaggerated pathos. The very flight into the world of Christian religiosity of
which Nietzsche accused Wagner's Parsifal is realized here at even more
unfathomable depths as he usurps the language that characterizes the sayings of
Jesus,- a kind of flight from despair of a profound visionary. Another variant,
this time in the aphoristic-systematic writings, is the overstated intellectual
brilliance of an author of intellectual brilliance. He shouts witticisms at us like
NIETZSCHE: PERCEPTIONS OF MODERNITY 223
someone who cannot be led back into human dialogue. For friends I wait, come,
'tis time, 'tis time.
"I teach you the Ubermensch. Man is something that must be overcome ... All beings thus far have
created something beyond themselves ... What is the ape for man? An occasion for derision or a
painful pang of shame. And that is exactly what man shall be for the Ubermensch: an occasion for
derision or a painful pang of shame."
Anyone beginning his prophesy with sentences like these declares the
intellectual victory of evolutionary doctrine, that is: of the natural sciences, the
hard core of modernity. Everything else in Nietzsche's philosophy is unthink-
able without this premise. Here I use the word "declare" advisedly, as in the
term "declaration of war." War exists by its declaration.
But "declared" evolutionary doctrine is not merely a postulated theoretical
statement but an invocation. Theory and evaluation are inseparable for
Nietzsche. Such inseparability is perfectly natural to his mind, it is their
distinction that would require explanation. Georg Picht brought to my attention
the fact that Nietzsche read Darwin early on and very soon interpreted him in
Lamarckian fashion. Seen in this Lamarckian way, his call for the Vbermensch
is theoretically consistent, and positing this invocation is itself a historical act.
Just as you shall, for generations, live according to the Will, so your descen-
dants shall at some point be born according to Nature. The Ubermensch is the
image which is to guide your artistic will in a fashion that is formative of man.
Similarly, Zarathustra's second thought, that of the Eternal Return, is based
on causal-scientific thinking. "Souls are as mortal as are bodies. But the knot of
causes into which I am bound up itself returns - it will create me anew. I myself
belong to the causes of the Eternal Return? Granted, a thought of this kind
cannot have arisen from such weak arguments. Thus its affirmation is primarily
evaluative. Nietzsche first experiences it as a horrifying revelation; later, its
affirmation becomes his expression of his own affirmation of Being: for all joy
wants eternity. But as is the case for so much of modem thinking, for Nietzsche
too, I seek to retain the thesis of the natural sciences as the central core.
Scientific facts or opinions remain invariant in the turbulent whirl of passions
and interpretations.
For a physicist, however, both of Zarathustra's thoughts are unproven from
the scientific point of view and in their most extreme expression have an
overwhelming probability of being false. They are the dreams of a poet made
up of the material of the dreams of natural science. Nietzsche could not evaluate
their strong claims. But the same inability to fully penetrate them applies as well
to his most able contemporaries in the natural sciences, such as Darwin and
224 CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
Boltzmann. In the following two sections I will briefly provide some scientific
discussion of these two questions. At this point, however, permit me to note
that, at best, we can consider Lamarckianism only if it is reinterpreted;
furthermore, we presuppose that the history of the cosmos is irreversible. Both
observations lead to subtleties which are, presumably, of no import for assessing
Nietzsche. Here I merely note that the doctrine of an Eternal Return stands in
contradiction to unlimited evolutionism. Almost without exception Nietzsche's
arguments refer only to human history, a brief second on the cosmic clock; they
are legitimate only historically-evolutionary. Structurally, the doctrine of the
Eternal Return remains without consequences for him; what matters is only its
pathos focused on eternity.
The victory of science for Nietzsche, in turn, refers not only and not primarily
to the natural sciences. The critically interpretive sciences, philology and
history, celebrate the victory of science as well. Nietzsche justly delighted in
referring to himself as a philologist. Even the two Zarathustra-thoughts deliver
proof to that effect: Lamarckianism is the altogether sensible reaction to Darwin
of someone who believes in the power of education, of the good teacher of
Greek; the Eternal Return is a philosophical tenet of antiquity, hailing from the
Stoics, perhaps even earlier from Pythagoras. 3
The humanities and social sciences of the nineteenth century taught us textual
criticism and perspective. Textual criticism forever destroys the possibility of
an orthodoxy bound by the letter (wherever it still exists today it makes its
appearance with the fury of a bad conscience precisely for that reason). What
is more important is that we acknowledge the role of perspective, that we learn
to see many people, many ages, and many cultures from their own respective
premises. Perspective dissolves subtle moral, cultural, and philosophical
orthodoxies. In the preamble to Beyond Good and Evil Nietzsche lays claim to
"the Perspectival" (his italics) as the "central condition of life," in contrast with
the dogmatism of Plato's metaphysics. And, indeed, he attains his mastery not
in the pathos of a Yes! or a No!, but in a perspectivalist way of seeing, the
special virtue of a scholar in the human sciences.
With this begins the strength of Nietzsche's philosophy, its headlong assault
into the unknown. Nietzsche is enough of a philosopher to apply the perspecti-
valism which hails from the sciences to the sciences themselves. The dogmatic
concept of truth does not hold up: our truths are really our perspectives. What,
then, honored professor, is science? Nietzsche proclaimed Art as the essence of
Science, as I noted earlier on. More than any other philosopher since Plato or
perhaps Schelling, Nietzsche incorporates the experience of the artist into his
reflections about truth, but now with a perspectivalist orientation. Our philo-
sophical dogmas, even those of "positive" science, are works of art, images of
our gods, the work of our hands.
But what does the artist aspire to? I said earlier that Nietzsche proclaimed
Power as the essence of Art. And what is Power? For Nietzsche, Schopenhau-
erian Will is the-thing-in-itself. "Overcoming" the denial of Will, he maintained
the doctrine of Will.
NIETZSCHE: PERCEPTIONS OF MODERNITY 225
"The world seen from within, the world described and defined according to
'intelligible character' -it would be 'will to power' - and nothing else- ." In
this phrase "and nothing else," repeated elsewhere, lies the pathos of this
teaching. Why the questionable addendum "to power"? It is not merely the outer
symbol for his having learned to affirm Will. Power has a specific meaning.
Power is Possibility. Possibility is Future. Future is Time.
ON LAMARCKIANISM
pace (approximately within 4112 billion years) and not only in principle. I have
repeatedly argued against the claim that one can prove this time span to be too
short. 4 Due precisely to the process by which the "fittest" are selected, the real
path of development is that which is the fastest given sufficient probability.
Consequently, any recalculation which follows another possible developmental
path results in a (much!) overstated time period. Naturally, this argument does
not exclude the previous reflection, namely that the actual speed of development
could have resulted precisely from a Lamarckian mechanism.
I end with non liquet and enduring skepticism vis-a-vis current neo-
Lamarckian explanations. For the time being I would not bet on a Lamarckian
development of the Ubermensch in a few thousand years. Much rather, as was
formerly done via the mores of marriage in aristocracies, one may well
undertake to breed humans with a clear conscience.
At best one can say that contemporary physics is unable to exclude with
complete certainty the notion of an Eternal Return. However, there is no positive
argument for the hypothesis of the Eternal Return.
Astrophysics teaches us a cosmic past of approximately 10 billion years. All
dates regarding age, often obtained in very different ways, fall completely
within the framework of these assumptions, namely constant irreversible
development and uniform expansion of the total system. True, cosmological
models do exist which, after a finite time, contract again and therefore admit
periodic return. However, in two senses these present little evidence for an
identical return of individual events. First, these models neglect irreversible
thermodynamic processes; if these were in fact included they would, presuma-
bly, not yield a strictly symmetrical contraction of the previous expansion and
therefore would not constitute strict periodicity from the cosmological stand-
point. Secondly, quantum theory suggests that individual processes like the
generation of a Zarathustra and even the accumulation of an earth with its
present characteristics are subject to statistical laws and would not repeat
themselves in a generally strongly periodical cosmos.
Around 1900, in the field of abstract theory, Zermelo raised objections to the
statistical interpretation of the Second Law of Thermodynamics, the so-called
Recurrence Objection. That is, the present condition of a system of n mass
points can be represented as "a point" in its 6 n-dimensional "phase space"; the
6 n-coordinates of the point represent respectively the three locational coordi-
nates and the three momentum coordinates of n mass points. That part of the
phase space accessible to a system otherwise sufficiently isolated from its
environment, the so-called "energy envelope" (the totality of all points of a
given energy constant), is compact; it possesses a large, but finite "volume" in
the phase space. Within it moves the phase point. Because of the finiteness of
the volume the phase point must, in finite time, approach arbitrarily close to its
initial position ("arbitrary" inasmuch as one can arbitrarily specify how minimal
be the desired distance from the original position; from this specification one
NIETZSCHE: PERCEPTIONS OF MODERNITY 227
can calculate how long it will take for the near coincidence to take place). Due
to the determinism and the continuity characteristic of the presupposed laws of
classical dynamics the point will, starting with this "Return", follow a trajectory
that deviates by an arbitrarily preassigned small amount from the original
trajectory.
This argument does not refute the statistical interpretation of the Second Law
where this interpretation describes developments contradicting normal progno-
ses not as impossible but only as highly improbable occurrences, i.e., admitted
only after very long intervals. As can be easily calculated, the length of time in
question is an indefinitely large multiple of the currently known age estimates
for the cosmos. Furthermore, the argument presupposes the finiteness of the
cosmos. Finally, it can be presumed to be "softened" by quantum theory. It
would be difficult to base an affirmation of Existence on this kind of Return.
Thus far in my reflections I have tacitly assumed that time is described by a
real linear coordinate. I believe, however, that a substantive discussion of the
meaning of the symbolism of the Return must begin with a critique of that
premise.
The first part of Beyond Good and Evil critiques the "Prejudices of the Philoso-
phers."5 I do not recall when I first read it but I assume it did not disturb me too
much. A physicist who, before the age of 20, had met Werner Heisenberg and
Niels Bohr as life-shaping scientific-philosophical personalities, who had as a
young man read Ernst Mach and had found the Vienna School insufficiently
critical, could not be startled by Nietzsche's critique of metaphysics. My
problem was not whether substance existed, be that the substance of atoms
(which Boscovich, a Croat, who was as far away from being Polish as
Nietzsche, had understood not as space-filling but just as points in space, a
modest step for today's physicists; cf. BGE 12) or of the soul (cf. the superb
critique of "I think," BGE 16, and the appropriate Kant interpretation, BGE 54).
Instead, my problem was to ascertain what exactly we mean when we say that
substance does or does not exist, what we mean when we assert or deny
knowledge a priori. I had to read the Greeks in order to begin to understand the
phenomena behind words like ousia or idea. In short, I was already infected
before Nietzsche's virus reached me, and had been so infected by a school from
which he himself had learned.
Even so, Nietzsche's critique contains two aspects which should have caused
me to reflect further: the search for moral motives behind the dogmatism of
metaphysics and his critique of the notion of Truth itself. Both issues take aim
at his Big Brother, Plato.
The view that the secret aim of an ontological metaphysics is the stabilization
of the rule of the Good and of good people today strikes me as an original
contribution by Nietzsche to the critique of knowledge and as one of the most
important. I do not know the eighteenth and nineteenth century Enlightenment
authors he read, particularly the French authors. But it seems to me that the
228 CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
definition mathematics is an art, and art is the hard core of theory. I am moving
toward my interpretation of Nietzsche.
But Nietzsche, the Greek, is also capable of recognizing the Jewish figure of
our culture. He sees the irresistible force of a moral imperative, of moral self-
criticism, of moral subtlety which to this day shapes the Jewish people. To the
believing Jew and, following in his heritage, to the believing Christian it is
absurd to wish to base morality on rationality or on a rational concept like
Nature. The Law has been given by God. Herein is mirrored a historical fact,
and Nietzsche notes that. The covenant at Sinai, the history of the Jewish people
from Moses to Elijah, created this figure of morality. The Law is given, the
Covenant made. Nietzsche recognizes in this what had to remain forever veiled
to the believer, what an Enlightenment enamored with rationality saw and hated
to the core: the Will of the Law-giver, his Will to Power. It is not for the
feelings of the obedient, but for the Will of those who command that
Nietzsche's heart beats faster, even where he is convinced that he, Nietzsche,
must give a new and diametrically opposed commandment.
On the third level, such reflections make the mind spin. Is rational morality
the victory of theory over practice? Or was the Good invented in order to enable
the rule of the good people? Theory and moral law are works of art, but what is
Art? If it is a creating of Gestalt (figure, eidos), is it not then theory alone that
tells us what constitutes a Gestalt? Phrasing the issue in terms of cultural
accents, however, should clarify from the beginning that theory, morality, and
art are products of history and can only be understood in light of history. As
accents they leap out from the unity of the whole, at times laying claim to (but
incapable of) guaranteeing that unity.
On the fourth level I have in previous presentations of this scaffolding located
religion and only religion. This is the airiest construction at the loftiest heights.
Here I draw on a lecture on Bonhoeffer and a subsequent reflection about
Luther, where both dealt with Christian theology. 7 The question of the fourth
level is the question about the unity behind the accents. For Plato philosophy
itself stood on the fourth level of the line- and cave-parable, a non-hypothetical
theory, a seeing movement of ideas through ideas to ideas, of eidos through
eidos to eidos. For us time is not, as for Platonism, the circularly advancing
image of an Eternity that remains in the One. Time appears to us as open. An
existing Gestalt is the result of creation, a new Gestalt will appear. Accents are
historically created configurations. Should we want to find unity for them, we
are remanded to history, to their origins or possible goals.
Historically, unity has indeed appeared to us only in the form of religion. In
the Bonhoeffer lecture I "rhapsodically united" four aspects of religion: religion
as the carrier of culture, as radical ethics, as inner experience, and as theology.
Subsequently I came to realize that these are the very accents that mark the
scaffolding. Theology is theory, radical ethics is morality, inner experience here
as so often is an undefined residual category within which we lodge the
forgotten essentials, such as was done for affect on the first level and values on
the second, both of which can at best express themselves in the third level in art.
Religion as carrier of a culture, however, refers to its status as the historical
232 CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
figure of a unity. But I also observed that this unity actually appears only to that
kind of reflection which can see it from the outside looking in, because it has
lost it.
This is Nietzsche's situation as well. But his reaction is unique. He does not
mourn lost unity, and he most certainly does not wish to restore it. But he sees,
in its full weight, the enormous sacrifice its loss constitutes. Beyond Good and
Evil, Section 55, the three sacrifices: the human sacrifices of ancient religions,
the sacrifice of the Self in ascetic religions, the sacrifice of God in our time:
God is dead, we have killed him. Nietzsche sees himself and the philosophers
he heralds as those who must form a new unity by willing it. Truth is not
recognized, it is willed.
I have never been able to accept this in the form in which it was stated. Do
not Nietzsche's experiences of inspirations express that he is not the one who
wills but the pen in someone else's hand? The historicity of truth is not thereby
eliminated. What do we learn from Nietzsche in that regard?
Evil, 186, his italics) "which is always accustomed to choose the more modest
expressions." Most convincingly, and with a great potential for inspiring prose
writers, he recommends "assembly of material, conceptual comprehension and
arrangement of a vast domain of delicate value-feelings and value-distinctions
which live, grow, beget and perish- and perhaps attempts to display the more
frequent and recurring forms of these living crystallizations - as preparation of
a typology of morals." Even so, his critical but also critically-admiring affect is
fixated on only a single type of morality which we can call the ascetic. That is,
Platonism, in high style, that is the demand of the Jewish God, Christianity or
"Platonism for the People" (Beyond Good and Evil, Prologue). I will not now
address Nietzsche's broad casuistry and polemic against such morality. I ask,
instead, about the consequences of this moral background for the philosophical
interpretation of the phenomenon of theory.
A belief in opposing values is indeed the expression of an ascetic disposition.
You must avoid one thing in order to be able to attain the other. Nietzsche sees
with great clarity asceticism's aristocratic provenance: self-control is demanded
of those who rule, self-restraint of those being ruled; and those who engage in
such denial, who model this strict renunciation, socially hail primarily from the
aristocratic class. 9 What Nietzsche despises most deeply is the democratization
of the ascetic world view, the victory of those who came up short, whose
modesty thereby is automatically false modesty: a modicum of wealth is
permitted since everyone can achieve that today, but aristocracy and being
different are strictly prohibited. According to Nietzsche what is thereby lost is
precisely the culture-generating force of asceticism: a voluntary renunciation of
that which we all possess because he who renounces can attain, in this way
alone, to a good which no one who consumes can even remotely imagine.
What does this view of asceticism teach us about theory? In my discussion
of functional rationality above, I treated asceticism by opposing it to immediate
action, as a way of enabling judgment which thereby replaces the reacting of the
animal with the acting of man. Theory is at all times an ascetic act, often a very
joyous one. Thinking (according to Plato) is a soliloquy, speaking is acting; the
asserting sentence, however, is a kind of acting that explicitly does not wish to
act, which states and does not change. How noble! -in the Nietzschean sense.
However, in order for the quiet asserting judgment to be able to interrupt the
flow of sensations, of the emotional affects and of reactions, there must be
something upon which judgment can rest. In my analysis of temporal logic and
the physics on which it is based, this is the irreversible fact, an axiom of
thermodynamics. Facts exist, as it were, only for us; our own hypothesis
regarding a reversible fundamental theory makes the irreversibility of facts into
a merely statistical phenomenon, a foreground.
Perhaps we can more easily approach the analysis of such relationships and
do so with fewer emotional reservations if we, along with Nietzsche, clarify for
ourselves the Will to Power that has enjoined the world view of classical
physics with its ontology. Of course one cannot solely conduct such an analysis
with this kind of affective material. Only conceptual work on concepts can help
us here. For the contemporary physicist neither the truth nor the illusions of
234 CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
core, art as aesthetic value is without essence, becomes irrelevantly private. The
stability of a culture which derived from these accents is overburdened, topples,
and collapses.
What will replace it Nietzsche does not know any better than we do, but he
saw earlier than "we" did what is no longer tenable. His pathos is that of truth,
he takes his symbol of Zarathustra from the treasure of images in the history of
religion. The Persian sage, historically so distant from us, the inventor of moral-
metaphysical dualism, might in Nietzsche's view also be the first to vanquish
it.
Georg Picht has written an essay about this question which is not available to
me as I write this piece. Thus I am quoting imprecisely from memory. A story
from late antiquity tells of Mediterranean seafarers who heard the following
lament on an island: "The great Pan is dead!" Gods can die, they are part of
history. The god whose death Nietzsche experienced is the god of the philoso-
phers who made his epiphany in Parmenides' didactic poem. If I climb the
scaffolding, I can follow that thought. It is the god of the philosophers who
makes theory possible, the lofty summit of which is the concern of metaphysics,
who guarantees the unity of being with the good, oftheory with morality. This
is most particularly the god of the European Enlightenment. If this god is dead,
then the Enlightenment is dead. Just take a look at our contemporary world!
Obviously that does not mean that thinking is dead. Science and scholarship
are not dead. What is dead, however, is the claim that these can sufficiently
orient us in the world. They become what they have always been, namely
research. However there are two diseases from which such research cannot
escape: the ideologizing of its "basic research" procedures caused by its
dependence on financing and the loss of an orientation with regard to the moral
value of its consequences. Not that alert scientists don't realize that. But
"Science," the ideal, does not answer these questions.
Nietzsche, however, would have protested against the misinterpretation of
those apologists who say that the god of the Christians, the god of the Bible, is
not dead as well, merely the god of the philosophers. Every reading of his works
makes it evident that this runs contrary to his personal opinion. I believe it is
impossible to limit his resonant sensitivity exclusively to the god of the
philosophers. Theology, as manifested in historical Christianity, is theory; a
radical Christian ethics, where it appeared at all, was morality. Understood like
that, Christianity was the carrier of a culture coming to an end.
What survives conceals itself on the scaffolding within the dark residual
category of "religion-as-inner-experience." Interpreters have pointed out the
mystical element in the Zarathustra figure and in the history of its creation
("Inspiration," Ecce homo). Zarathustra's solitude is a kind of mystical retreat.
The doctrine of the Eternal Return is interpretable only as a type of mystical
experience of eternity. We associate Dionysus with ecstatic mysticism. The
history of religion tells us that visions, auditions, and the "themes" of mystical
NIETZSCHE: PERCEPTIONS OF MODERNITY 237
experiences normally derive from the cultural context and the religious
traditions of the mystic in question, while the presumed substance of the
experience is almost totally indistinguishable from one mystic to the next. Was
this the reason why a musician, poet, ethicist of the science-beholden 19th
century had to clothe his experiences in the Zarathustra-Dionysus garment?
But Nietzsche is simultaneously a philosopher of history and points us toward
a historical task that yet awaits. The task of the future is not self-preservation
of traditional religions in their respective isolation - all will fail in that respect.
Likewise, the task to be accomplished is not their syncretic amalgamation, the
watering down of their differences. What will be necessary for survival is a
fruitful wrestling with their contents.
project. I do not know where Nietzsche gets his opinion. In any case, no other
great Greek cultural accomplishment should be presumed to have attained its
zenith as late as did the natural sciences. It was not a moralizing interest that
killed the natural sciences in antiquity; at best moralization was what remained
once science was dead.
So much for historical details, in themselves perhaps not totally irrelevant.
But how will a contemporary natural scientist react to Nietzsche's conceptuali-
zation of nature and science?
Would a natural scientist today look upon nature as a sphinx? Looking at the
majority of my colleagues, I suspect the following: not during the work week,
but perhaps when a glass of wine loosens the tongue on Saturday night. In the
work-a-day activities of the biological sciences physicalism today reigns
supreme. However, to biologists and medical professionals physics represents
the medium of rationality precisely because the basic problems of physics are
beyond them. The same applies to most physicists. One senses the sphinx, but
even with good will it is beyond one's powers to get it to speak.
When I confront my view of physics with Nietzsche's thought I stumble upon
the passage: "Much like mathematics and mechanics were for a long time
considered to be sciences possessing absolute validity and the suspicion only
now cautiously surfaces that they are nothing more and nothing less than applied
logic which proceeds from the specific and provable assumption that there is
such a thing as "identical cases" - logic itself being a consistent symbolic
language based on that shared presupposition (that identical cases do exist) ... "
Yet: "Even now the genuine critique of concepts or (as I once called it) an actual
history of the development of thought totally eludes most philosophers. One
should uncover and evaluate anew the value judgments which surround logic:
for instance, 'certainty is worth more than uncertainty'; 'thinking is our highest
function'; likewise one should investigate the optimism in logic, the sense of
victory in each conclusion, the imperative quality of judgment, the innocence
o~ a faith ~n the ap~rehend~bil~~?; of the concept [die Unschuld im Glauben an
dze Begreifbarkezt zm Begrif./]. -
I could place the first half of this quote as motto above my attempt of a
reconstruction of quantum theory. Nietzsche could not have perceived the extent
to which his insight in that regard could be put into practice. However, he
precisely designates the critical point: the possibility of speaking of identical
cases. With insightful irony the second half suggests a contemporary pathos
which today holds a tragic political future ("after World War III one will hang
the physicists," a physicist said to me in 1944). From the epistemological
standpoint my subjective pathos is the exact opposite. Knowing full well that
there are no identical cases, I am amazed at how well a procedure works which
nevertheless makes that assumption. Nietzsche does not enlighten me in this
regard.
But I would surely not be able to describe the task of a natural philosopher
any better than Nietzsche describes his own: "the dehumanization of nature and
then the naturalization of man, after attaining the pure concept of "nature." 13 Hie
Rhodus.
NIETZSCHE: PERCEPTIONS OF MODERNITY 239
POSTSCRIPT
Georg Picht and Enno Rudolph pointed out Nietzsche's knowledge of Kant and
interpreted Nietzsche's philosophy as a radicalization of Kant's problem
statement. We dream- such is life. The philosopher awakens, but only to the
point of knowing that he is dreaming. With that knowledge it becomes possible
to continue to dream, that is, to continue to live. Dream here becomes the
metaphor for life in time. That is, this metaphor hails from the Platonic
differentiation which begins the Timaeus, to use one example: what always is
and never becomes, as contrasted with what always becomes and never is. From
the Kantian perspective, the dream qua dream is the necessary transcendental
appearance which we come to understand as appearance, but cannot discard.
How I would have to express that is the subject of another piece of writing. In
any case "error" is thereby proven as a legitimate term for any logical knowl-
edge, that is, any knowledge that is based on identities.
One must see the Eternal Return in this context as "the most difficult
thought." Picht points out that, not only in the conversation with the dwarf (E.
Rudolph) but also in the passage which I cite, it is not Zarathustra who utters the
doctrine of the identical return of individual events: but rather in the former it
is the dwarf, in the latter, the animals. To the dwarf Zarathustra says: "Don't
make it too easy for yourself," in the case of the "babbling" of the animals
Zarathustra begins conversing with his soul and in the end does not even hear
that they are silent. I insist that one should not carry the deep meaning of
Nietzsche's statement that "two times two are four" to the extreme of conclud-
ing that he cannot possibly have meant by that anything other than "two times
two are five." But I do admit that, for me, the absurd-sounding doctrine of the
Eternal Return gets meaning only in this fashion. The collision of the two
unending paths in the doorway of the moment, the irresolvable contradiction of
past and present, their puzzling reconciliation in infinity can be presented to our
thinking, in the eschatological vision of an Eternal Return of opposites, as a
puzzle, as a secret. Imagining this in linear time implies that it can appear only
as the identical return of the same; therefore the dwarf and the animals can talk
like that without receiving a reply. The paradox becomes palpable if one
considers that "Return" suggests a memory which differentiates the earlier
occurrence from the current one, whereby it simply does not constitute an
identical return. The structure of a "past that does not pass" is irreconcilable
with an identical return.
Philosophically, Nietzsche leaves us with meaningful puzzles. 14
Starnberg, Germany
NOTES
1 This text was originally prepared as an oral presentation written for a conference on Nietzsche
at the Research Center of the Evangelical Student Organization, Heidelberg, 1981, with the title
240 CARL FRIEDRICH VON WEIZSACKER
A POSITIVIST NIETZSCHE?
241
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistenwlogy, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 241-252.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
242 PAUL VALADIER, S.J.
has remained hidden dominating our feelings and judgments. "So far," one reads
in The Gay Science, "all that has given color to existence still lacks a history.
Where could you find a history of love, of avarice, of envy, of conscience, of
pious respect for tradition, or of cruelty?"; even, "the most industrious people
will find that it involves too much work." According to the final lines of this
passage only a vast ambition would render such a work possible: " ... centuries
of experimentation that might eclipse all the great projects and sacrifices of
history to date." 2 And just so that no one overlooks the fact that the ambition is
strictly scientific, a seemingly unambiguous sentence concludes the section: "So
far, science has not yet built its cyclopic buildings; but the time for that, too,
will come. " 3
It is to such a plan Nietzsche that devotes himself and in the service of which
he engages all the friends of knowledge and all the "free spirits." Of course, this
seems to be advanced in complete coherence with what is usually called the
intellectual, or the "enlightened" philosopher, dating from the period of Human,
All Too Human - a work that in a highly symbolic manner is dedicated to
Voltaire, "one of the greatest liberators of the spirit." Nietzsche's perspective
there is to "bear the banner of the Enlightenment," a project Nietzsche thought
was betrayed by Schopenhauer (who in the name of "progress" only reinforced
"the reaction" to the Enlightenment, according to the title of the aphorism). 4 It
is necessary to go further in the critical unveiling of illusions, and therefore, to
complete the work initiated by "Petarch, Erasmus, and Voltaire," so that science
triumphs totally over the "old familiar 'metaphysical need'" (HH 27). This
program-text is worked out in a series of propositions that date from the period
of science's confidence in destroying religious needs, i.e., in proposing, "the
passage from religion to a scientific mode of thought." Such a passage would
not take place by a "violent and perilous leap": rather, it is first a question of
"weakening," then of "exterminating," so-called religious metaphysical needs.
Art can help "effect a transition," but in any case: "scientific man is the further
evolution of the artistic" (ibid.). No doubt is expressed regarding the capacity
of science to account for the origins of our religious sentiments, nor are there
any doubts about the results. Once this knowledge is obtained, humanity will in
some way be turned away from all quests of the religious type: knowledge as
such is liberating. The "victory of knowledge over radical evil" (the title of the
aphorism) will free man from "a host of tormenting ideas, the expressions 'pains
of Hell,' 'sinfulness,' 'incapacity for good' will no longer have any effect on
him," since he has learned "to know as fully as possible," that knowledge which
"will make him cool and soothe everything savage in his disposition" (HH 56).
With knowledge as the therapy for anguish and as the gravedigger of guilt-
ridden imaginations -the ancient home of religion - the diagnosis could not be
clearer.
The section, "Truth in religion," articulates science and religion once again
in antinomic terms, explicitly situated in the wake of the Enlightenment. It is
said that this century did not render justice to religion for it critiqued it falsely
or in untenable terms. But the romanticism that followed was hardly more
equitable in its reversed position towards religion, as it thought to have
SCIENCE AS NEW RELIGION 243
reader. Thus, we should resist hastily identifying the one who claims to adopt
new paths with the old tags of well-known positions, and, instead, try to
illuminate the untimely hidden purpose underneath such seductive appearances.
Yet, we must be cautious: after the period of Human, All Too Human, Nietzsche
in fact identifies himself with "we knowing ones" (wir Erkennenden), naming
his task a "gay science" (jrohliche Wissenschaft). But if this science is truly a
form of knowing (Erkenntnis), should it not be asked if this knowledge is of the
same kind as the cold, sad, inert, devitalized understanding of those frogs
Nietzsche cruelly identifies as the modem wise men? 5
The break we set out to expose continues to enlarge throughout the mature
works, notably the aphorisms of the fifth book of The Gay Science. It is difficult
to contest that Nietzsche there adopts very different positions than those noted
in Human, all too Human, as will be shown below. Should we thereby indict the
philosopher's inconstancy, attributing a break bordering on incoherence and a
lack of rigor to account for his well-known contradictions, or can we nonethe-
less advert to a continuity of thought and attempt to understand his reasons?
Nietzsche gradually comes to realize that at a certain point he had fully
expected science to unveil the truth and to expose humanity's millennium-old
illusions - soliciting from the scientific method the same requirements with
regard to truth as the believer had expected to obtain from religion. Just as the
believer thinks to penetrate the mystery of things, to understand the movement
of the world, so, too, a scientism naive in its presuppositions transposes the
quest for truth from the religious domain to the scientific domain. Now, through
the trial of suffering and the rending of the flesh from which was born the will
to believe, the will to know at any price, Nietzsche will attain to a presentiment
that the same illusion runs from religion throughout the sciences: that a similar
thirst for knowledge and for penetrating the foundation of things sharpens the
expectation of the believer (of old) and the scientist (of our day) and this same
attitude is destructive of man and his relation to the world- that, ultimately, this
attitude will bring humanity to a dissatisfaction which is none other than the
dissatisfaction rationalism has always embraced. An identical illusion is at the
root of the will to know, the desire to convert the unknown to the well-known,
as well as the ambition to descend into the depths of things in order to seize the
nature of the surface or appearances. This illusion is in part tied to the rationalist
illness which has never ceased to torment and torture mankind since the time of
Socrates' Greece. Already, from The Birth of Tragedy, a diagnosis was made
which will never be negated:
A profound illusion that first saw the light of the world in the person of Socrates: the unshakable
faith that thought, using the thread of causality, can penetrate the deepest abysses of being, and
that thought is capable not only of knowing being but even of correcting it. This sublime
metaphysical illusion accompanies science as an instinct ... 6
SCIENCE AS NEW RELIGION 245
- but in a more subtle and perverse manner, perhaps, because they pretend to
serve as principles of liberation and emancipation from belief.
Similarly, when Nietzsche questions "What is the meaning of ascetic ideals?"
in the third essay of the Genealogy of Morals, he seeks to know what kind of
will do we have today that opposes the influence of such an ideal. 8 We will find
here a position identical toGS 344, which Nietzsche explicitly quotes in order
to emphasize the continuity of his analysis. Using the vocabulary of the ascetic
ideal, he does not say anything other than what he said with regard to the will
to believe: is there really an adversary to the ascetic ideal? "Where is the match
of this closed system of will, goal, and interpretation?" "But they tell me," he
adds in GM III: 23, the opposite " .. .is not lacking":
All of modern science is supposed to bear witness to that- modern science which, as a genuine
philosophy of reality, clearly believes in itself alone, clearly possesses the courage for itself and
the will to itself, and has up to now survived well enough without God, the beyond, and the virtues
of denial. [For] Such noisy agitators' chatter, however, does not impress me, [because[ science
today has absolutely no belief in itself, let alone an ideal above it - and where it still inspires
passion, love, ardor, and suffering at all, it is not the opposite of the ascetic ideal but rather the
latest and noblest form of it. (GM III: 23)
And if it seems to fight such a ideal (probably an allusion to the ideal of the
Enlightenment), it only opposes, "its exteriors, its guise, and masquerade" (GM
III: 25). In reality:
This pair, science and the ascetic ideal, both rest on the same foundation- I have already indicated
it: on the same overestimation of truth (more exactly: on the same belief that truth is inestimable
and cannot be criticized). Therefore they are necessarily allies, so that if they are to be fought they
can only be fought and called into question together. (Ibid.)
Science and religion are thus dependent on the same system of asceticism that
takes shape in the will to truth at any cost, the essence of every will to believe.
One indication of this would be, according to GS 344, that in both cases
sacrifice is at work: what beliefs or values did we not sacrifice on the altar of
science? (Clearly the altar metaphor has weight!) Since we hold that there is no
higher value than knowledge, there is also no higher value than its quest and
therefore no higher value than the will to truth. A scent of sacrifice and blood
always surrounds the will to believe: science as well as morals requires the
shedding of blood. Indeed, it is in just such a way that, in the name of modern
science, we have precipitously shaken our system of values, our social relations,
our traditional conceptions as well as our very relationship to the cosmos. Thus,
the enterprise of science cannot owe its origin to a calculus of utility, a relative
and flexible value, "it must have originated in spite ofthe fact that the disutility
and dangerousness of 'the will to truth,' of 'truth at any price' is proved to us
constantly" (GS 344). The scientific project proceeds from a moral system, from
a will to not be deceived, or to better the human condition, but this moral draws
its incoercible force from a metaphysics and finally from a religion. This
religion holds that nothing is more valuable than the truth, that truth alone has
value, and that any other value should be sacrificed on its altar. One might as
SCIENCE AS NEW RELIGION 247
well say that the religious postulate of science is identical with the belief that
truth is divine and, therefore, that it is an absolute and unconditional value. One
will have guessed that:
... What I am driving at. namely, that it is still a metaphysical faith upon which our faith in science
rests- that even we seekers after knowledge today, we godless anti-metaphysicians still take our
fire, too, from the flame lit by a faith that is thousands of years old, that Christian faith which was
also the faith of Plato, that God is the truth, that truth is divine. (GS 344)
Since science acquires its meaning and form from the long quest for
unconditional truth, science depends upon the somber history of nihilism. Far
from constituting a process that would be emancipated and delivered from
nihilism, science is the subtlest expression of it; indeed, science seems com-
pletely removed from any metaphysical conviction. At least this is what the
positivist or the scientist naively think, holding that a fact is a fact and that in
their case they are unencumbered by unjustifiable prejudices, unlike the
metaphysician and the believer. But they fail to recognize that they hold as
indisputable the fact that knowledge is more valuable than anything else and that
this knowledge will have beneficial and protective effects against the dangers
of life. The positivists and scientists thus fail to see that they support the secular
enterprise of impoverishing life, weakening its defiant vitality, even to the point
of declaring themselves against life itself since they effectively emasculate the
entirety of its darker and frightening components. In this sense, they corroborate
the petty expectations of "the last man," in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, ever in
search of a small happiness as security against life's dangers. Nihilistic in its
dualistic and metaphysical origin (truth's idealism and unconditionality) modem
science furthermore is nihilistic in its very destiny. Just as Christianity collapses
under the weight of its contradictions, the scientific method collapses with its
demand for rigor against dogma and moralism. Once the scientific method is
brought back to the rigors of sober interpretation, it turns against "the will to
truth at any cost," which heretofore had resided within it. The scientific method
recognizes that it can at most produce revisable hypotheses, and thus, far from
penetrating the secret of things, it can only produce "useful illusions," transi-
tory, artificial and not at all the carrier of truth. Or, as is mentioned in a
posthumous note from the spring of 1888, "It is not the victory of science that
distinguishes our nineteenth century, but the victory of scientific method over
science" (WP 466).
spurred on by its infinite quest for an inaccessible mirage. But, the exploration
of the labyrinth is hardly complete because we still have to highligt a veritable
reversal of the starting postulate. Not only is science not compelled to destroy
religion, not only do they share in the same nihilistic destiny, but science also
discovered the very conditions for its possibility and birth in religion - to the
extent to which it has to be said that without the mythical religious universe,
nothing like the scientific conscience would have been born, and nothing like
the rigorous method of control over nature could have been perfected.
Against "le petit faitalisme" (petty facticism) which holds that the grasping
of a fact requires nothing more than observation of the superficiality of things,
Nietzsche never ceased to affirm that the "objective" regard always supposes
more than itself (in which respect he broke from Spinoza, who was over-
confident about such objectivity). 9 Likewise, he never ceased to affirm that we
cannot understand science exclusively on its own terms, and that the imagina-
tion needs to anticipate and to apprehend what it grasps beyond the immediately
sensible. It is on this level that we can interpret the surprising aphorism GS 300,
justly entitled "Preludes of science." We needed that "avant-garde" of magi-
cians, alchemists, astrologers and sorcerers in order to give birth to the scientific
curiosity, for these men were able to "to create a thirst, a hunger, a taste for
hidden and forbidden powers?" They opened a world of promise that fully
encroached upon the quotidian and sensible universe. Thus they grounded the
inquiry in the direction of those powers that excited the ardor to understand.
Moreover, the text adds, " ... would man ever have learned without the benefit of
such a religious training and prehistory to experience a hunger a thirst for
himself, and to find satisfaction and fullness in himself!" (GS 300). Not only do
religions evoke a thirst to penetrate the mystery of things, they also turn their
regard in the direction of man himself in order to render him ''interesting" to
himself- another condition of scientific inquiry that is often not fully appreci-
ated. Other texts, however, explicitly attribute the origin of this meticulousness
to the Christian moral practices of examining one's conscience, numbering and
recounting one's sins through confession. This same meticulousness is then
turned upon itself and is able to be extended to any exterior reality. 10 But, one
is surprised to find similar positions in the aphorisms of the first book of
Human, All Too Human, which at first seemed to be diametrically opposed.
Thus, for example, "in the age of barbarous primordial culture," the dream
enabled us to gain access to "a second, real world," to the origin of metaphysics
and thereby, to a deeper understanding. Magic, expressing a will to tame nature
and to direct it, "for the benefit of mankind," to "impress upon it a regularity
and rule of law which it does not first possess," is related to the scientific
enterprise, at least in the form of a preamble. With magic, man practices an
original relation to the real, even if the man of magic conceives nature as given
over to capricious and therefore unmasterable powers. 11 With these remarks,
Nietzsche situates himself at the antipodes of those moderns who believe they
need only thank themselves, thinking that they inaugurate an unprecedented era
-as if the past had not somehow prepared the present. Because he is attentive
to the conditions by which the human spirit matures and becomes educated,
SCIENCE AS NEW RELIGION 249
Nietzsche forcefully insists upon the modem's debt to the ancient tradition, and
in this context he does not think that the birth and development of modem
science is wholly divorced from humanity's religious past. "The best in us," we
read again in the same book of Human, All Too Human, "has perhaps been
inherited from the sensibilities of earlier ages to which we hardly any longer
have access by direct paths; the sun has already set, but the sky of our life still
glows with its light, even though we no longer see it" (HH 111).
Religion has been a matrix of science in that it rendered possible the scientific
regard toward the world, in that it was born of curiosity, of ambition to see
beyond immediate appearances, that it was also made of the will to decipher, to
interpret the ways of the world - in this is implied a supplementary and
paradoxical argument for the kinship between modem science and religion with
nihilism. Far from being so opposed to each other that one could assert the
decline and the death of the other, science and religion go together, bound as
they are by an identical "will to truth at any price." Modern man in his superfi-
ciality however, simply regards himself as "emancipated." He does not notice
that under strikingly different surface appearances, science draws nourishment
from the same sources as religion and both find sustenance from the same feeble
will - a will which, unable to put up with the abyssal character of the world,
needs to correct it, needs to amend it, and bring it back to the dimension of the
well-known, the familiar. It should also be said that the effects of the scientific
enterprise are quite comparable to the effects religion has on man. Because of
its fundamentally unstable, i.e., nihilistic nature - furrowed by negation and
incapable of affirmation - science oscillates between blissful optimism and the
blackest pessimism. Thus, after having exalted our human powers and having
brought us to believe in the conquering power of the mind, science concludes
by dethroning the subject it once raised so high, just - inversely - as religions
needed to crush man as a sinner only to be able, afterwards, to exalt him as "son
of God," promised to eternal life. When Nietzsche affirms the kinship between
science, the ascetic ideal and the overestimation of truth, he notes that since
Copernicus, modern science has borrowed, "the same route" as Christianity, to
"the old ideal" (GM III: 25). Indeed:
All science, natural as well as unnatural- whlch is what I call the self-critique of knowledge- has
at present the object of dissuading man from his former respect for himself, as if this had been
nothing but a piece of bizarre conceit. One might even say that its own pride, its own austere form
of stoical ataraxy, consists in sustaining this hard-won self-contempt of man as his ultimate and
most serious claim to self-respect (and quite rightly, indeed: for he that despises is always one who
'has not forgotten how to respect' ... ) Is this really to work against the ascetic ideal? (Ibid.)
Even Kant must have recognized that modern science "damaged that ideal."
But is this not the pursuit by other means of what nihilistic religion has always
done, what was impossible for it not to do? Another trait demonstrates a very
surprising kinship: after having dethroned man from his unique importance in
the universe and faced with the impossibility of achieving ultimate truth,
scientific deception transforms itself into the infinite and self-willed quest for
incertitude. Instead of adoring the divinity (or truth as divine), our contemporary
250 PAUL VALADIER, S.J.
agnostics, "as votaries of the unknown and mysterious as such, they now
worship the question mark itself as God." Hence, the syllogism Nietzsche sneers
at: '"There is no knowledge: consequently - there is a God': what a new
elegantia syllogismi! what a triumph for the ascetic ideal!" (ibid.). We no longer
believe the truth to be accessible, but we still believe that it is worth the trouble
to search at any cost- to search for the sake of searching: in vain and under the
dominion of what is not, or no longer: nothingness.
Does such an identification between modem science and religion, molded by
the same obsessive will for truth at any price, does this oblige us to put
Nietzsche among detractors of scientific modernity? Doesn't this identification
tend to relativize as well his plan of establishing a genealogy of morals, much
less to question his pretension of including himself among, "those who know"
(wir Erkennenden)? Indeed, haven't our conclusions overthrown our very
starting point?
If the proposed interpretation is correct, it at least warns us not be deceived
by a simple and obviously false identification between the Nietzschean project
of a "gay science" and some ambition of a scientific nature. The "understand-
ing" (Erkenntnis) in question here is surely a manner of comprehending reality,
not an irrationalism or a leap into the absurd, and in this respect Nietzsche's
insistence on calling his thought a "doctrine," as he says in Twilight of the Idols,
shouldn't be minirnized. 12 But the understanding we address does not occur by
means of the judgmental canons of comprehension or through the Socratic
dialectic, which embrace the real through a conceptual apprehension. Rather, the
understanding is explicitly described as "das Jasagen zu Realitiit," sajing yes
to reality as it is, not as the "ideal" of the weak would like to have it. 1 On the
contrary, this is:
A formula for the highest affirmation. born of fullness, of overfullness, a Yes-saying without
reservation, even to suffering, even to guilt, even to everything that is questionable and strange
in existence. This ultimate, most joyous, most wantonly extravagant Yes to life represents not only
the highest insight but also the deepest, that which is most strictly confirmed and born out by truth
and science. Nothing in existence may be subtracted, nothing is dispensable. 14
This yes-saying, which is the genuine antinomy of the ascetic ideal, clearly
rejoins the objectives of science, but with the understanding that the latter is
thereby stripped of the temptation to correct "existence" and that it has
recovered from the temptation that truth be conquered solely according to the
categories of comprehension- all this in favor of the yes-saying which would
be a poetic benediction in the style of Zarathustra's songs. An understanding
so conceived would be more truthful than all understanding of comprehension
because it lets go and is willing to dance even over abysses without being afraid.
Such is the gay science: not a sad, i.e., always unsatisfied understanding, but a
joyful wisdom: since it is enough to say yes once in order that all be saved. " .. .If
our soul has trembled with happiness and sounded like a harp string just once,
all eternity was needed to produce this one event - and in this single moment of
affirmation all eternity was called good, redeemed, justified, and affirmed" (WP
1032). 15
SCIENCE AS NEW RELIGION 251
This "doctrine" also enables us to grasp the sense and import of what a
genealogy of values might be. Contrary to what certain texts give us to
understand and in opposition to a generally received opinion, genealogy does
not have a reductive or deterministic objective that tries to explain the superior
by the inferior, or the highest values by the lower instincts and drives. Even if
Nietzsche was able to lend some support to this theory, the coherence of the
doctrine as a whole obliges us to interpret the concept of genealogy otherwise.
In short, given the complexity and interwovenness of things, the attempt at
genealogy would be contradictory if it resulted in a clearly and fully certain
account about what is fundamentally complex - especially in the domain of
morality and, therefore, also in the subject of the will of the one who wills.
Rightly understood however, genealogy sets forth the positive or negative and
the affirmative or destructive forces (which are implied in every human act),
before the complex intertwining of instincts and drives and tries to measure
them. Genealogy advances a more or a less strong or weak will in place of a
more or a less strong or weak affirmation, or negation, of weakness or strength,
slavery or mastery. It makes us realize that there is no pure will, either in the
sense of weakness or in the sense of mastery. Thus genealogy does not pretend
to bring some fallacious clarity to the obscurity of the will. Rather, it allows us
better to accept the complexity and the ineluctable weight of the necessity of
what is as it is, and in so doing, to accept its "metamorphosis"
Furthermore, it should be added that genealogy is founded on interpretation,
not on an univocal and definitive diagnosis. It calls for the play of replay and of
rereading. Therefore, the same recourse to a reality which is itself caught up in
the becoming of a will that is never fixed - save for that point of falling back
into the web of the will to believe. These conclusions compel us to strongly
qualify the encyclopedic projects Nietzsche called for, for which he invoked a
multi-disiplinary collaboration. Did their initiator ever believe such propostions,
or did he only do it to mask an intuition which, he said often, cannot be
understood - neither by the first to arrive nor by "the last to come"? Thus
beyond the assimilation of modern science to religion - which, at first sight
seems strange if not scandalous - for those who have ears to hear the eminently
Nietzschean solicitation: be done with the will to confinement and self-closure,
which still goes by the name of the "will to believe," and that still proliferates
even well outside of conventional religion, and say yes to what is and, thereby,
find joy in eternally singing this yes-saying.
Paris, France
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Thanks are due to David B. Allison for preliminary assistance with correcting this translation.-
Ed.
252 PAUL VALADIER, S.J.
NOTES
Nietzsche, Friedrich, Genealogy of Morals, Walter Kaufmann, ed., trans., in Basic Writings of
Nietzsche, (New York: Random House, 1968), end note to the First Essay, p. 491. Hereafter GM.
2 Nietzsche, The Gay Science, Kaufmann, trans. (New York: Random House, 1974), section 7,
P· 82.Hereafter GS.
. Ibtd.
4 Nietzsche, Human, All Too Human, R.J. Hollingdale, trans. (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. 1986), Book One, Section 26, p. 26. Hereafter HH.
5 E.g., Section One of The Gay Science, or the Second Part of Thus Spoke Zarathustra. [Or GM
1: l-Ed.]
6 Nietzsche, The Birth of Tragedy, Kaufmann, trans. (New York: Random House, 1967), 15, p.
95.
7 GS, Sections 281 & 344, pp. 221, 281.
GM, the title of the Third Essay, p. 533.
10
GM III: 24, p. 587.
II GS 357, pp. 304-310.
HH, 5, p. 14.
12 Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, in The Portable Nietzsche. (New York: Penguin, 1982), "The
istic "anything goes" attitude falling victim to two category mistakes at the same
time:
Many philosophers - erroneously - would consider it fatal to Friedrich
Nietzsche's philosophy if his obvious criticism of absolute truth-claims and his
advocating cognitive and moral perspectivism on an object-level would also
apply on a meta-level, implying that he himself held no claims as to the truth of
his thoughts or that he himself was of the opinion that his ideas represented just
one perspective among others. -I will be trying to argue that this is not fatal at
all.
Many - and in some cases even the same - writers nevertheless find
consolation in Nietzsche's apparent "irrationalism" inferring that if Nietzsche
was critical with respect to truth claims and was inconsistently advocating
cognitive and moral perspectivism both on the object- and on the meta-level
then, of course, they themselves were also entitled to inconsistency, to
irrationality and to abandoning all truth-claims in exchange for moral and
cognitive perspectivism.- In what follows I will be trying to demonstrate that
to take this stand is completely mistaken: Even if Nietzsche himself were
pragmatically inconsistent (which he isn't) this would neither ask nor even
allow for any inconsistency on the part of the interpretation.
Both of these mistakes are due to a lack of reflexive clarity. Reflection,
however, consists in revealing at least some of the previously unquestioned
presuppositions and preconditions of one's own thinking. Thus, to avoid falling
victim to one or both of these two category mistakes, systematically guided
reflection is needed. Trying to deal with Nietzsche's position as a philosophical
and consistent one in a philosophical and consistent way, I therefore have to
reveal my own presuppositions (I) and the ones of Nietzsche as far as his theory
of truth and his criticism of science is concerned (III) before I can go on
developing his semiotic theory of truth (III), his criticism of science resulting
in his theorum of eternal recurrence (IV) and finally his criticism of science
resulting in his theorem of will to power (V).
title of his book (Nietzsche as philosopher) "the snottiest title I ever saw,"3 and
Danto himself confessed, that "the title was intended to be (mildly) offensive."
(2) It is furthermore one of my hermeneutical presuppositions that the relation
between the literary remains (i.e., the Nachlaj3), which include, e.g., the
aphorisms widely known by the infamous title of The Will to Power, and the
published writings, is neither crucial nor negligible. Now that the previously
unpublished or misleadingly published literary remains are available in the
critical edition by Colli and Montinari, they can serve as keys to the
understanding of difficult and enigmatic passages in the published writings. This
is what I would like to call the "hermeneutical iceberg-principle": diving under
the surface and take a look at the formerly hidden ten-elevenths may in some
cases help to get the right idea of the visible one eleventh and sometimes even
help to avoid catastrophes as well. Taking into account the, as it were, "esoteric"
part of Nietzsche's writings is nowadays an unavoidable necessity. It would,
however, violate some of the best-established rules of hermeneutics to look at
just a few randomly chosen parts of the previously unpublished texts.
(3) If one consistently confronts the published writings with the literary
remainings the philosophy of Nietzsche appears in quite different light. I take
it for granted that one of the decisive problems for Nietzsche, being a nineteenth
century thinker through and through, was the problem of science and humanities
(the German term Wissenschaft including both) and their influence on as well
as their debts to history, society and life as a whole. Given the fact that the very
notion of "philosophy of science" has softened its intensional characteristics and
therefore broadened its extension considerably since the early 1960s, one could
today even call Nietzsche a "philosopher of science."4 Not only the "esoteric"
writings let him appear as such, in all of the published writings the science
related topics arise as well; but they become visible and fall into place only if
you look at them from the angle of the Nachlaj3.
(4) His attitude towards science, however, is neither pure affirmation nor pure
negation; it is rather one of philosophical criticism. As Nietzsche himself says
in the fourth book of the The Gay Science: "When we criticize something, this
is no arbitrary and impersonal event; it is, at least very often, evidence of vital
energies in us that are growing and shedding a skin. We negate and must negate
because something in us wants to live and to affirm- something that we perhaps
do not know or see as yet" (GS 307). And he concludes without leaving even a
chance of possible misreading: 'This is said in favor of criticism." So it is quite
plausible to expect at least two different types of attitude towards science in
Nietzsche. These two attitudes towards science, however, correlate rather neatly
with two different concepts of science. So it is not even necessary to stylize
Nietzsche either as a scientist in disguise or as a prophetic seer.
In what follows I intend to defend these presuppositions (which, having been
made explicit, are properly speaking not presuppositions any longer, but are
rather to be regarded as hypotheses) by narrowing them down to some
exemplary cases. I am especially interested in showing that the seemingly rather
metaphysical or obscure constraints in Nietzsche's mature thoughts, e.g. the
ideas of "eternal recurrence" and even of "will to power," can be consistently
256 WALTHER CH. ZIMMERLY
Those who know that they are profound strive for clarity. Those who would like to seem profound
to the crowd strive for obscurity. For the crowd believes that if it cannot see to the bottom of
something it must be profound. It is so timid and dislikes going into the water. (GS 173)
What l then got hold of. something frightful and dangerous, a problem with horns but not
necessarily a bull. in any case a new problem- today I should say that it was the problem of
science itself; science considered for the first time as problematic, as questionable. (BT, Preface
2)
II
Without assuming a certain kind of being, opposed to the true reality, we should have nothing
for it to be measured against, compared with. and projected upon: error is a precondition of truth.
Partial inertia, relative solids, equal events, similar events - by those concepts we falsify the true
state of affairs, but it would be impossible to know anything about it at all without having it thus
falsified in the first place. For every cognition therefore is still false indeed, but at least thus some
kind of representing does exist and among the representations again many degrees of the false
exist. To find out the degrees of the false as well as the necessity of the fundamental error being
the condition of life for the representing Being - task of science. The question is not how error
could be possible, but: How is a certain kind of truth possible, despite the fundamental untruth? 7
In addition to this, he says: "It is not the cognition which belongs to the
essence of the things, but the error" (KSA 9, 566). The logical symmetry of
True and False as expressed in the logical function of contradiction and in the
related logical principles of Non-contradiction and of the Excluded Middle, is
to the eyes of Nietzsche nothing but an abstraction, whereas in our conscious
being among other beings, i.e. as far as knowledge is concerned, a fundamental
asymmetry between error and truth is to be observed or rather: to be
experienced. Not only is it the case that one can perceive that an opinion or-
scientifically speaking - a hypothesis was wrong, without being able to infer
from this what the true assumption or hypothesis might be - this quite
satisfactorily could be explained by the difference between contrariety and
contradiction. But it is also the case that, given the truth-value of a proposition
p would be F, not any contradicting sentence non-p would necessarily have the
truth-value T. It is quite evident, then, that such a logically irritating
epistemological assumption needs further explanation. At any rate: what needs
no explanation at all, however, is that an assumption of this kind would be of
greatest importance to the respective philosophy.
(2) With respect to methodological questions 8 Nietzsche quite obviously
holds that the methodological differences between the sciences and the arts and
humanities, extensively and intensely discussed in his day, are not decisive at
all. He locates the difference and the related difficulties at quite another place
and on quite another level. As he does not think of science and arts or
258 WALTHER CH. ZIMMERLI
III
What we could have known already from the work of Schlechta has been
confirmed by almost all of the recent scholarly writing on Nietzsche: One of his
main interests was to examine thoroughly the previously unquestioned ideal of
the pure scientific "drive for truth" which is both ascetic and self-referential.
Science and knowledge are thought of as being their own means and ends, and
mankind had to strive for (logical or empirical) truth for its own sake. The
presupposition of this idea again was a correspondence-theory of truth which on
its part presupposed both a realistic epistemology and an ontology of the
identity or analogy type.
To speak in rather historical terms, the ideal of scientific truth as it was held
by nineteenth century scientists was in Nietzsche's view an anachronism:
modem empirical science, backed up with a Platonic-Thomistic ontology and
a pre-Kantian epistemology! So Nietzsche, (at least in the first period of his
thinking) strongly influenced by Schopenhauer, decided to follow the Kantian
way of critical philosophy and to even outdo Kant in the question of the theory
of truth which, having allegedly not undergone any progress since Aristotle,
Kant had skipped as is well known 16 . The interesting way Nietzsche approached
this problem is again to be found in the NachlajJ, especially in different small
essays. 17 In the famous essay "On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense"
which has almost become a "cult-book" for the French Nietzscheans, Nietzsche
most surprisingly did already anticipate the linguistic tum and its pragmatical
version. He there connects semiotics, logic and science in a theoretical frame
which I would like to break down into the following steps of argument:
(1) Traditionally one would, following the correspondence-theory of truth,
define truth as "adequatio rei et intellectus" (St. Thomas Aquinas), i.e. as
correspondence between concept and thing, respectively between proposition
and state of affairs. Belonging to the class of semantical definitions of truth this
definition presupposes that there is something like a definite relation, called
"adequatio" or "correspondence" between concept (sign) and thing (referent),
resp. between proposition and state of affairs. But - and this is what Nietzsche
claims in the first place - one cannot possibly name a non-circular or non-
tautological criterion for the adequacy of this relation. This would only be the
case if something like a natural signification existed as, for instance, the early
Plato in his dialogue "Kratylos" thought. Because, however, a natural
signification does not exist, the correspondence-theory of truth is not sufficient,
plausible as it may be. Therefore, Nietzsche claims that the relation between
signs and referents is originally an arbitrary, even aesthetical one, and the signs
are rather metaphors than copies or analogous images of the referents. And he
defines metaphors in a short note, written down in the fall 1872, as follows:
"Metaphor means to treat something as identical which has been recognized as
similar in one point." 18 But as the notion of "similarity between these two
levels" is not (or rather cannot possibly be) well defined, not even similarity is
to be found between signs and referents.
(2) That leaves the theory of truth with the formal criterion of consistency or
- linguistically speaking - with the syntactical criterion: True is a sentence if
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TRUTH AND SCIENCE 261
and only if it can be deductively inferred from another true sentence by means
of tautological transformation. But by using this criterion we obviously get but
"shallow tautologies" (Kant), and again the task of finding a non-circular or
non-tautological criterion of truth is not fulfilled. So the consistency-theory of
truth will not do either.
(3) The only possible way out would therefore be the - again linguistically
speaking - pragmatical criterion. Because, as later on Wittgenstein will put it,
the meaning of a sign is the use you make of it, what we mean by "truth" does
obviously also depend on use and the situation of the use as well. In short: we
have to name the criteria for truth by telling the story of the different situations
in which it turned out to be useful to distinguish some metaphors from others by
attributing "truth" to them. The resulting "theory" of truth consists therefore of
two parts: a) of the theory of metaphors and b) of the history of replacing the
knowledge that signs are essentially metaphorical, by the opinion that consistent
use of the same metaphors in the same situations is useful for human beings.
What then is truth? A movable host of metaphors, metonymies, and anthropomorphisms: in short,
a sum of human relations which have been poetically and rhetorically intensified. transferred, and
embellished, and which, after long usage, seem to a people to be fixed, canonical, and binding.
Truths are illusions we have forgotten are illusions; they are metaphors that have become worn
out and have been drained of sensuous force, coins which have lost their embossing and are now
considered metal and no longer coins. (TL, 84)
The only criterion left is therefore the principle of usefulness; human beings
in actual fact desire not truth, but rather "the pleasant, life-preserving
consequences of truth" (PT, 65). 19
(4) Therefore the criterion for truth lies beyond reasoning and is connected
with the principle of self-preservation in a not individually restricted sense. The
invention of language being the invention of a reliable way for human beings
to communicate and live together is thus embedded in an evolutionary
framework, 20 and therefore, using language and knowing coincide in this
interpretation. In one of the five unpublished prefaces titled "On the Pathos of
Truth," Nietzsche formulates this evolutionary approach in rather poetical
language, expressing at the same time the marginal position of mankind sub
specie aeternitatis.
Once upon a time, in some out of the way corner of the universe which is dispersed into
numberless twinkling solar systems, there was a star upon which clever beasts invented knowing.
It was the most arrogant and mendacious minute of world history, but nevertheless only a minute.
After nature had drawn a few breaths the star cooled and solidified, and the clever beasts had to
die. The time had come too, for although they boasted of how much they had understood, in the
end they discovered to their great annoyance that they had understood everything falsely. They
died, and in dying they cursed truth. (PT, 65)
Using his assumption of the asymmetry between error and truth Nietzsche
emphasizes here that just because of the metaphorical "lie" -character of
language, to totally rely on it (as the nineteenth century ideology of pure
scientific truth does) would tum out to be a completely false understanding of
262 WALTHER CH. ZIMMERLI
knowing. And this is exactly why- in Nietzsche's poetical language- "in dying
they cursed truth." The abstract idea of truth, in disregarding the ultimate
connection with the criterion of truth, turns out to be absurd and disfunctional.
(5) The issue of language and knowledge to construct a firm, reliable edifice
of concepts is, according to the anthropomorphism-assumption of Nietzsche, on
the one hand definitely in vain, but on the other hand even conquers its own
actors: the human beings. In the second part of "On Truth and Lies in an
Extramoral Sense," Nietzsche describes this connection by using the metaphor
of the Babylonian tower, thus evoking the idea of an encompassing chaos
caused by different languages, different types of knowledge and different
sciences:
We have seen how it is originally language which works on the construction [in German: "Bau"
which could mean both "construction" and "edifice"] of concepts, a labor taken over in later ages
by science. Just as the bee simultaneously constructs cells and fills them with honey. so science
works unceasingly on this great columbarium of concepts, the graveyard of perceptions. It is
always building new, higher stories and shoring up, cleaning, and renovating the old cells; above
all, it takes pains to fill up this monstrously towering framework and to arrange therein the entire
empirical world, which is to say. the anthromorphic world. (TL. 88)
IV
Having thus uncovered Nietzsche's semiotic theory of truth as making use of the
asymmetry-assumption and implying consequences for the understanding of the
historicity and anthropomorphism of science, I now will proceed to different
cases of criticism of the natural sciences in Nietzsche's philosophy and to their
connections with some of his cardinal ideas. As we know both from the records
of the university-library of Basee 1 and from notes Nietzsche took as well as
from letters he wrote, he was during the 70's and 80's very much concerned to
keep up with the development of new ideas in the sciences and to gain a proper
understanding of these innovations. His readings of the primary sources have
been guided primarily by rather popular authors: Johann Karl Friedrich Zollner
and Johann Gustav Vogt were two of the interesting ones. Nietzsche read
Zollner's book on the nature of the comets22 already in 1872; we know that he
borrowed it four times from the library (Nov. 6, 1872; March 28, Oct. 2, 1873
and April 13, 1874), and in the NachlaJ3 of the SO's (and once in the published
writings), he quotes Zollner obviously approving of his thoughts, whereas
otherwise Zollner was harshly criticized. 23 What seems to have impressed him
most were not Zollner's nationalistic ideas or his attacks on Helrnholtz 24 but his
epistemological contention that in the sciences much too many useless
experiments were put through. In the fall of 1873 Nietzsche notes:
The same deficiencies Zollner is deploring, the endless carrying through of experiments and the
lack of logical-deductive power, can be found within the historical disciplines- underestimation
of the Classical compared with the Antiquarian: in this way the sense of historical science is going
to be lost, everything becomes shallow. Similar to the fact that in the natural sciences the "image
of the world" is becoming increasingly mean and common, the "image of the past" decays in the
historical sciences 25
Closely connected with this criticism is the objection that general laws in
nature and in history are of no use for the individual case because they tell only
something about averages. Thus Nietzsche poses an even more radical
methodological question than Zollner.
From this sceptical point of view (as far as the value of experimental
confirmation and especially inductive methods is concerned), Nietzsche starts
to review different scientific theories. It goes without mentioning that he does
not just eclectically pick results which have been accomplished by reiterated
experiments. He speaks of the "abuse of knowledge by eternally reproducing
experiments and collecting materials whereas the conclusion would already
result from few experiments and materials." 26 He is rather interested in the
theoretical parts especially of physics, astrophysics, cosmology and chemistry.
One of the most fascinating scientific projects of his days was the ongoing
change of the foundations of theoretical physics. Nietzsche therefore took a
great interest in the discussions about e.g. the principles of thermodynamics. As
far as the principle of the conservation of energy is concerned we know that he
read Julius Robert Mayer's book Mechanik der Warme. 27 He quotes the title of
Helmholtz's essay Uber die Erhaltung der Kraft (1847), apparently without
explicitly referring to him. He probably knew Ernst Mach's essay on "Die
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQCE OF TRUTH AND SCIENCE 265
Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes von der Erhaltung der Arbeit" (1872).
However this may have been, he certainly did use Johann Gustav Vogt's book
on Die Kraft. Eine realmonistische Weltanschauung (1878) which Overbeck
sent 1881 to Nietzsche who, after having read a critical discussion of this book
and other books in Otto Cas pari's collected essays titled Der Zusammenhang
der Dinge (1881), had asked for it. 28 Besides these books, Nietzsche also
possessed numerous books which dealt with the second principle of
thermodynamics and with the problem of entropy implied therein.
The traces of his persistent occupation with these theoretical debates within
the natural sciences can be found in the unpublished as well as in other
published writings, in the 80's turning from logical, epistemological and
methodological to rather content-oriented questions. His criticism of science
therefore changes its direction considerably: It is not scientific attitude and the
ideal of objectivity any more that are to blame, but the as it were "blinders" with
which each special scientific discipline equips itself. If one would combine
different angles or perspectives one could - genealogically - utilize them in
order to erect what he himself calls in an unpublished fragment of spring 1888
"the new world-conception." Incited by Johann Gustav Vogt's assumption that
Mayer's principle of the limited and constant amount of energy
[Konstanzprinzip] necessarily presupposes circularity, and using as an
unquestioned first premise his own assumption of the impossibility of rigid
persistence of power, Nietzsche develops his argument in a five-step-sequence
which I will analyze as follows:
(1) The world exists in the way of corning into being and fading, but it does
not itself originate or pass away; in coming into being it persists.
(2) The world has no beginning; the idea of creation uses not only the
undefinable concept of "creation," but it also tries to give an explanation by
using "nothing" (cf. "creatio ex nihilo") as explanans and "world" as
explanandum.
(3) It is neither impossible nor self-contradictory to think of an infinitude of
time in the future. "Finitude of time" would mean that the world could
temporally come to an end, i.e. become nothing or become rigidly persistent
without any change in it. But if this was possible, it would have already had
happened given that an infinite time had already passed.
(5) From this the theory of eternal recurrence follows as a logical
consequence. I quote the respective text literally:
If the world may be conceived as a definite quantity of energy [Kraft] and as a definite number of
energy-centres [Kraftzentren]- and all other conceptions remain indefinite and therefore useless
- it follows that it has to pass a calculable number of combinations in the great dice game of its
existence. In an infinite time every possible combination would be reached at some time;
moreover, it would be reached infinitely often. And because between any given "combination" and
its "recurrence" all other possible combinations would had to have run down and because every
one of these other combinations condition the whole sequence of combinations in the same order,
this would be the proof for a succession which has been repeated infinite times and which will play
its game in infinitum.
This conception is not necessarily a mechanistical one: for, if it were, it would not condition
an infinite recurrence, but a final stage. Because the world has not reached this final stage the
266 WALTHER CH. ZIMMERLI
mechanistical point of view has to be considered an imperfect and only preliminary hypothesis.
(KSA 13, 376)
By which statement and by which belief the decisive change best expresses itself which came
about because of the preponderance of the scientific spirit over the religious spirit that invents
fictitious gods? We insist that the world as energy [Kraft] must not be thought of as being infinite
-we prohibit ourselves from using a concept of infinite energy being incompatible with the very
concept of "energy." (KSA 9, 574)
Nietzsche formulates this in a fragment from between spring and fall 1881 as
follows:
Consequently, the number of situations, changes, combinations and developments of this energy
("Kraft") is tremendously great and almost "immeasurable," but in any case definite and by no
means indefinite. But the time during which the universe exerts its energy is indeed infinite, i.e.
the energy is forever the same and forever active. 30
v
In the aforesaid, two thoughts need further explanation: the change of energy
situations and the consequences it has for the again inversely (and reflexively)
relevant question of the situation of the thinking human beings including the
scientists (as well as the philosophers) and therefore including the development
of science (and philosophy) as a whole. I hold that a good possibility to at least
approximating these explanations consists in discussing them in their relation
to both the concept of will to power and, again, Nietzsche's criticism of science.
Until now we have discussed the idea of eternal recurrence as a conclusion
drawn from hypothetically or counterfactually connected premises which, in
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TRUTH AND SCIENCE 269
I need the starting point "will to power" as origin of motion. Therefore the motion must not be
externally conditioned- not caused ... I need initiatory points and centres of motion for the will
to gain ground ... (KSA 13, 274)
And a few pages later he connects this concept explicitly with recurrence:
"As a matter of fact science has emptied the concept "causality" and has left it
as a simile for which it fundamentally doesn't matter on which side cause, on
which side effect. It is ascertained that in two complex states (constellations of
energy) the quanta of energy stay equal. The calculability of an event is not due
to the fact that a law has been followed, that something obeyed a necessity or
270 WALTHER CH. ZIMMERLI
that a law of causality has been projected in every event: it is due to the
recurrence ofidentical cases." (276)
The meaning of "recurrence," however, is somehow different here: to a
twentieth century reader familiar with epistemology and philosophy of science
this sounds less mystical. "Recurrence" now turns out to be nothing but a notion
for what we usually call a "case" of a "law." In Nietzsche's view, however,
there are no "laws" of nature. To think of laws is merely again another
anthropomorphism or- to put it differently- another counterfactual conditional.
By this rather semiotic and pragmatic argumentation the theory of eternal
recurrence and the concept of will to power are linked together.
So "will to power" becomes the conceptual mark for the already quantified
quality of the initiatory points or centres of motion, in the physical world as well
as in that of the spirit. Or rather: the difference between nature and spirit, being
in itself a product of a hypothetical counterfactual world-view in a given
perspective is overcome by this notion itself. Therefore the notion "will to
power" does not denotate anything in the "real world"; what it in actual fact
does, however, is to designate the universal function 37 and by doing so to
replace, on the side of natural sciences, what previously had been called "atom."
Nietzsche is not concerned with what the elements of the world are, but with
different ways of perceiving them; and to his mind they are to be perceived not
as small static parts of matter, but rather as immaterial and yet quantifiable bits
of energy, "power quanta" as Nietzsche calls them.
It has frequently been discussed that Nietzsche, in his early unpublished
manuscripts, was already trying to overcome the atomistic conception by an
elaborated "doctrine of time-atoms" outlining a possibility to introduce
temporality into matter. 38 In trying to do that he undoubtedly was strongly
indebted to the eighteenth century Jesuit astronomer and mathematician Robert
Boscovich? 9 Greg Whitlock has recently even called Boscovich' s theory of
force "the parent theory to both the eternal return of the same and the theory of
will to power." 40 Nietzsche probably, as is widely accepted by the relevant
scholarly literature41 , made the acquaintance ofBoscovich's "Theory of Natural
Philosophy" 42 by the mediation of Gustav Th. Fechner's book Uber die
physikalische und philosophische Atomenlehre. 43 In the second edition of his
book Fechner discusses Boscovich's theory to some extent44 because he was
surprised about the similarities between it and his own conception of force-
points without extension. It is the neo-kantian historian of materialism, Friedrich
Albert Lange, then who in turn discusses Fechner's theory of a "philosophical
atomism," and Lange is, as we know e.g. from the work of Salaquarda and of
Stack, 45 one of the main sources of Nietzsche's early discussions of atomistic
materialism. 46 These are the background ideas Nietzsche used when he replaced
the conception of material atoms by the conception of "power quanta."
In his later unpublished writings Nietzsche connects this idea with his
doctrine of anthropomorphism and universal perspectivism, i.e., with his theory
of truth, knowledge and science as discussed above. In the context of his
discussion of the will to power and the eternal recurrence we find a note which
he wrote also in spring of 1888:
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TRUTH AND SCIENCE 271
The physicists believe in their peculiar way in a "true world": a rigid systematization of atoms in
necessary motions, identical for all beings. The "apparent world" for them is therefore reduced to
that side of the general and universally necessary Being which is accessible to every being in its
own way (accessible and in addition adapted- made "subjective"). But by doing so the physicists
got lost: the atom that they take for granted is constructed according to the logic of the
perspectivism of consciousness- it therefore is itself a subjective fiction. This physicalist image
of the world which they thus project is not at all different in essence from the "Subjective-World-
Image": it is only constructed by our senses extended into thought, but still with our senses ... And
finally they omitted something in the constellation without being aware of it: just the necessary
perspectivism by virtue of which each centre of energy [Kraftzentrum]- not only man- constructs
the world by itself, i.e. measures it against its own energy, touches it, forms it... They forgot to
include this perspective-giving energy into the "true Being." To say it in the language of
Academia: they forgot the "Subject-being." (KSA 13, 373)
This line of criticism leads back to our second question: the role of thinking
human beings within the whole conception of will to power and eternal
recurrence. It has been commonly acknowledged by the Nietzsche-scholars'
community that the will to power is singular only as far as it is regarded as a
principle of knowledge. But insofar as it is considered to be a principle
concerning the appearance, however adapted it may be, it has to explain the
difference between single appearances without which no appearance could be
perceived at all. Because difference includes plurality, the appearing will to
power is to be conceived as being, in itself, pluralistic: Therefore we should
only speak of the "wills to power" in plural. 4
The wills to power could in their part again be dealt with under different
headings which correspond with our regular general concepts. Nietzsche himself
gives various examples in the form of lists. I quote for the sake of clarification
just one of them (also from the spring of 1888):
The steady and arduous process of science, which will ultimately celebrate its greatest triumph in
an ontogeny of thought, will deal with all these views. Its conclusion might perhaps end up with
this tenet: That which we now call the world is the result of a number of errors and fantasies,
which came about gradually in the overall development of organic beings, fusing with one another,
and now handed down to us as a collected treasure or our entire past- a treasure: for the value of
our humanity rests upon it. From this the world of ideal strict science can, in fact, release us only
to a small extent (something we by no means desire), in that it is unable to break significantly the
power of ancient habits of feeling. But it can illuminate, quite gradually, step by step, the history
of the origin of that world as an idea- and lift us, for moments at least, above the whole process.
(HH 16)
Abel, G., Nietzsche: Die Dynamik der Willen zur Macht und die ewige Wiederkehr, (Berlin/New
York: de Gruyter, 1984).
Anderson, R.L., "Nietzsche's Will to Power as a Doctrine of the Unity of Science," Studies in the
History and Philosophy of Science (1995) 25/5:729-750.
Babich, B., Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science: Reflecting Science on the Ground of Art and Life,
(Albany: State University of New York Press, 1994).
Boscovich, R., Philosophia Natura/is Theoria redacta ad unicam legem virium in natura
existentium ( 1759), trans!. by J.M. Child: A 1heory of Natural Philosophy, (Cambridge, Mass.:
M.l.T. Press, 1966).
Breazeale, D., Philosophy and Truth, (New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1979).
Bauer, M., "Zur Genealogie von Nietzsches Kraftbegriff. Nietzsches Auseinandersetzung mit J.G.
Vogt,"Nietzsche-Studien 13 (1984): 211-227.
Clark, M., "Nietzsche's Doctrine of the Will to Power," Nietzsche-Studien 12 (1983): 211-227.
Clark, M., Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
Conway, D.W., "Beyond Realism: Nietzsche's New Infinite" International Studies in Philosophy
XXII/2 (1990): 93-109.
Crescenzi, C., "Verzeichnis der von Nietzsche aus der Universitatsbibliothek in Basel ent-
liehenen Bucher (1869-1879)," Nietzsche-Studien 23 ( 1994): 388-442.
Danto, A., Nietzsche as Philosopher. An Original Study, 2nd. ed. (New York: Columbia University
Press, 1980).
d'Iorio, P., La lineae il circolo: cosmologia e filosofia dell' eterno ritomo in Nietzsche, Genova:
Pantograf, 1995.
d'Iorio, P., "Cosmologie de I' eternel retour," Nietzsche-Studien 24 (1995): 62-123.
Djuric, M. and Simon, J. (eds.), Zur Aktualiti:it Nietzsches, II (Wtirzburg: Konigshausen &
Neumann, 1984).
Drews, A., Nietzsches Philosophie, (Heidelberg: Winter, 1904).
Fechner, G.T., Ober die physikalische und philosophische Atomenlehre, Leipzig: H. Mendelssohn,
2nd ed. 1864.
Freeman, D.A., "Nietzsche: Will to Power as a Foundation of a Theory of Knowledge,"
International Studies in Philosophy 20 (1988): 3-14.
v. Helmholtz, H., Ober die Erhaltung der Kraft, eine physikalische Abhandlung, vorgetragen in
der Sitzung der physikalischen Gesellschaft zu Berlin am 23sten Juli, 1847. (Berlin: Reimer,
1847).
Henke, D., "Nietzsches Darwinismuskritik aus der Sicht gegenwartiger Evolutionsforschung,"
Nietzsche-Studien 13 (1984): 189-210.
Kaufmann, W., Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist, (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1974 ).
Krueger, J, "Nietzschean Recurrence as a Cosmological Hypothesis," Journal of the History of
Philosophy XVI/4 (1978): 435-444.
Lange, F. A., Geschichte des Materialismus und Kritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart, 2 vol.
(1866), repr. ed. by A. Schmidt, (Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp, 1974).
Mach, E., "Die Geschichte und die Wurzel des Satzes von der Erhaltung der Arbeit," (1872), repr.
in: E. Mach, Abhandlungen, ed. by J. Thiele, Amsterdam: Bouset, 1969.
Magnus, B., "Eternal Recurrence," Nietzsche-Studien 8 (1979):362-377.
Marton, S., "L'eternel retour du meme: these cosmologique ou imperatif ethique?" Nietzsche-
Studien 25 (1996): 42-63.
Mayer, J.R., Die Mechanik der Waerme in gesammelten Schriften, Zweite, umgearbeitete und
vermehrte Auf!., (Stuttgart: Cotta, 1874).
Mittelmann, W., "The Relation between Nietzsche's Theory of the Will to Power and his Earlier
Conceptions of Power," Nietzsche-Studien 9 ( 1980): 122-141.
Moles, A., Nietzsche's Philosophy a,( Nature and Cosmology, (New York: Peter Lang, 1990).
274 WALTHER CH. ZIMMERLI
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
Inspired by some of the early critical scholarship on Nietzsche's indebtedness to the scientific
developments of his day, 50 I did my first lecture courses on "Nietzsche as a philosopher of science"
in 1982 at Georgia Augusta University in Gottingen, 1983 at Carola Wilhemina Technical
University in Braunschweig and at the University of Ziirich. Since then I have taught similar
lecture courses, graduate courses and seminars at Emory University (1985), Indiana University in
Bloomington (1991) and Philipps University in Marburg (1997). The occupation with this topic
has also resulted in some articles: cf. Zimrnerli, '"Alles ist Schein'. Bemerkungen zu einer
A.sthetik post Nietzsche und Derrida," in: W. Oelmiiller (ed.), Asthetischer Schein, (Paderborn:
Schoningh, 1982), pp. 147-167; W.Ch. Zimmerli, "Jenseits von Kunst und Wissenschaft. Wie
unzeitgemiiB ist Friedrich Nietzsche?" in: Mesotes, 411992, pp. 334-350; Zimrnerli, "Kombination
und Kommunikation. Zur Differenz des ewig wiederkehrenden Gleichen," (forthcoming).
Different versions of the present essay have been presented on different occasions at different
universities literally all over the world, including the Boston series on philosophy of science, the
University of Pittsburgh colloquium on philosophy of science, the philosophy colloquium at the
Australian National University in Canberra, and the philosophy colloquium at the University of
Stellenbosch, South Africa. I am most grateful to Babette Babich (New York) who first
commented on the paper, then encouraged, and later patiently but insistently urged me to write the
present new version and submit it for publication in this volume. Furthermore I should like to
thank Bob Cohen (Boston), Adolf Grunbaum (Pittsburgh), Rudolf Makreel (Atlanta) and
Alexander Nehamas (Princeton) who also were among the first to critically comment on earlier
versions of this paper, and Joachim Landkammer (Marburg) for his invaluable help in my 1997
Marburg Nietzsche seminar. I would also like to extend my gratitude to the Institute for Advanced
Study (lAS) at Indiana University in Bloomington, especially to Jim Patterson and Henry Remak
who kindly invited me to the Institute for Advanced Studies, now for the second time. Without this
opportunity I couldn't have spent a part of my 1997/98 sabbatical peacefully working on this
paper.
NOTES
13 Briefwechsel. Kritische Gesamtausgabe, ed. by. G. Colli and M. Montinari, (Berlin/New York:
New Jersey: Humanities Press, 1979- and in a rather good translation too'
18 KSA 7, 498 (trans!. by Schrift, 1985, op.cit., p. 374):
19 KSA 1, 878 (trans!. by Breazeale, 1979, op.cit., p. 65).
°
2 Cf. C.U.M. Smith, "'Clever Beasts Who Invented Knowing': Nietzsche's Evolutionary Biology
of Knowledge," Biology and Philosophy, 2 (1987): 65-91; G.J. Stack, "Nietzsche's Evolutionary
Epistemology," Dialogos. Revista del Departemento de Filosofia Universidad de Puerto Rico,
XXVII/59 (1992): 75-101.
21 Cf. L. Crescenzi, "Verzeichnis der von Nietzsche aus der Universitatsbibliothek in Basel
claiming that, due to the inferiority of the British to the German physicist, Germany was destined
to become the "showplace" of the new epoch of deductive reasoning in science, and at the same
time attacking Hermann von Helmholtz, the dominating figure in German science, cf. Robin
Small, "Nietzsche, Zollner, and the Fourth Dimension," Archiv fiir Geschichte der Philosophic
~1994) 76:278-301, esp. 279-282.
5 KSA 7, 635, my translation.
26 KSA 7, 450 my translation.
27 J.R. Mayer, Die Mechanik der Wiirme in gesammelten Schriften, Zweite umgearbeitete und
Riemann's geometry or any other theory of the fourth dimension; cf. the debate between Alistair
Moles and George J. Stack: A. Moles, "Nietzsche's Eternal Recurrence as Riemannian Cosmol-
ogy," International Studies in Philosophy, 16 (1991): 21-35; G.J. Stack, "Riemann's Geometry
and Eternal Recurrence as Cosmological Hypothesis. A Reply," International Studies in
Philosophy 16 (1991):37-40; cf. again R. Small, 1994, op. cit., esp. pp. 290 sqq.: "Transcendental
physics and the fourth dimension."- And as this is a paper on Nietzsche's theory of truth in
relation to his criticism of science I will not even pretend to discuss the possible ethical
implications of the theorum of the eternal recurrence; cf. S. Marton, "L'eternel retour du meme:
these cosmologique ou imperatif ethique?," Nietzsche-Studien 25 (1996): 42-63.
36 This is obviously not seen by R.L. Anderson who- although in an intelligent way- constructs
a dilemma between perspectivism and the will to power doctrine as a "claim about the unique
underlying essence of the world." Anderson's attempt to "save" this doctrine by reading it "as an
interpretation of the unity of science, i.e. as a view about our way of knowing the world is, of
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TRUTH AND SCIENCE 277
course, no solution, because there is no such thind as a unity of science in Nietzsche's perspectival
thinking: R.L. Anderson, "Nietzsche's Will to Power as a Doctrine of the Unity of Science,"
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 2515 (1995): 729-750; cf. also - earlier and less
determined - D.A. Freeman, Nietzsche: Wi!I to Power as a Foundation of a Theory of Knowl-
edge," in: International Studies in Philosophy, 20 (1988):3-14.- Still another, although similar
dilemma between the will to power as a metaphysical and as an empirical theory has been posed
by M. Clark, Nietzsche on Truth and Philosophy, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990),
p. 211 sq. In the words of S. Schwartz, 'The Status of Nietzsche's Theory of the Will to Power
in the Light of Contemporary Philosophy of Science," International Studies in Philosophy, XXV12
(1993): 86 sq.: "Either the will to power theory is metaphysical or it is empirical. If it is
metaphysical, Nietzsche could not have propounded it, since he eschews metaphysics, but if it is
empirical, it is so obviously false that no one would have held it." The "solutions" both of these
authors offer are, however, not very satisfying: Clark concludes that Nietzsche because of this
dilemma does not hold the will to power theory, whereas Schwartz tries to argue that he did hold
it and that it is an empirically falsifiable theory. Both these conclusions suffer from the same
weakness: For a very simple logical and epistemological reason there exists no dilemma: One of
the necessary conditions for a situation to be called "dilemmatic" is complete disjunction: there
have to be two and only two possibilities. The notions of "metaphysical theory" and "empirical
theory" do, however, not constitute a complete disjunction. As we know from recent developments
in the philosophy of science there is a lot more to find in the world of theories than just empirical
and metaphysical ones! Evolution theory e.g. is neither empirically falsifiable nor metaphysical
- and that is true for most fundamental scientific theories and, of course, for all epistemologies!
37 This universal function is what allows for both plurality of perspectives and non-relativistic
contribution of Copernicus to human knowledge: KGW V/2, p.541 and VII/2, p.264; cf. R. Small,
"Boscovich Contra Nietzsche," Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XL VI/3 ( 1986): p.
419.
40 G. Whitlock, "Roger Boscovich, Benedict de Spinoza and Friedrich Nietzsche: The Untold
existentium, 1759; transl.by J.M. Child, (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1966); cf. G.J. Stack,
"Nietzsche and Boscovich's Natural Philosophy", Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62 (1981 ): 69-
87; for differences between the two thinkers, especially with respect to the fact that Boscovich by
way of developing his theory of indivisible ''points of force" in actual fact brings forward quite
forceful arguments against the idea of eternal return, cf. R. Small, 1986, op.cit., esp. p. 420 ..
43 G.T. Fechner, Uber die physikalische und philosophische Atomenlehre, Leipzig: H. Mendels-
sohn, 1864).
44 Op.cit., 2nd ed. 1864, pp. 239-244.
45 Salaquarda, 1978, op.cit., pp.242 sq., 253; Stack, 1983, op.cit., pp. 316, 322 et passim.
46 Stack 1983, op. cit., pp. 37 sq.
47 W. Miiller-Lauter, "Nietzsches Lehre vom Willen zur Macht," Nietzsche-Srudien, 3 (1974):1-
279
B. Babich (ed.), Nietz,5che, Episterrwlogy, and Philosophy of Science: Nietz,5che and the Sciences II, 279-286.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
280 ANDREA REHBERG
As regards the concept of causality, the only question which Kant needs to
address is whether it is one of the a priori concepts according to which
experience is always necessarily structured, given the constitution of human
faculties? It is clear that Kant's theory of the production of knowledge for and
by the natural sciences, insofar as it claims that this knowledge is produced in
accordance with the concept of causality, is adequate. But the issue which
remains entirely unquestioned in this is what type of knowledge (Wissen) or
science (Wissenschaft) ensue when causality is accepted as the fundamental
organising principle. In short, according to Nietzsche, any discipline's adher-
ence to causality as the chief principle of production needs to be considered
from the point of view of value.
By taking the body as the point of departure for his transvaluative project,
Nietzsche instantly displaces one of the founding moves of all metaphysical
forms of thinking, namely the denial of the body, and he thereby puts the will
to power on a firmly materialist footing. But just as important as its materialist
nature is the fact that the will to power marks a radically anti-humanist stance.
To identify the will to power with any exclusively human perspective is too
reductive. The physiological perspective which is elaborated here should not be
taken as yet another reassuring confirmation of a philosophical anthropomor-
phism. On the contrary, in the displacement of all anti-materialist metaphysical
impulses, and their replacement by a physiological thought, the anthropomor-
phisation of nature is also overcome. In its place arises the conception of a self-
excessive materiality to which human life is only ever utterly incidental.
II
The will to power interprets: the formation of an organ is a question of interpretation; it delimits,
determines degrees, differentials of power ... interpretation is itself a means of becoming master
over something. (The organic process presupposes continual interpreting). (WP 643, translation
modified)
It is clear that "becoming master over something" mentioned in this note does
not refer to any human individual becoming master over something or someone.
It is, rather, human being, especially in its calculative-instrumental mode, its
mode of self-preservation, which is mastered by the interpretative excesses of
the will to power, by the will to power positing values, especially those of
enhancement.
Two types of values can therefore be distinguished: those which have an
originary status and which determine each particular physiology they shape and
inhabit in a very immediate sense and may therefore be called physiological
values; and those which pervade activities- for instance, philosophy, science,
politics etc. - in which human being traditionally believes itself to be the origin
of values and which may therefore be termed anthropocentric values. The
relation between the two kinds of values is discussed in the following passage:
When we speak of values we speak under the inspiration, from the perspective of life: life itself
forces us to posit values, life itself values through us when we posit values. (Twilight of the Idols,
4 p. 45, translation modified)
This is to say that physiological values are not produced by any form of
human activity but by life, the will to power itself. They can best be described
as, in a sense, transcendental. This means that they precede, and are themselves
constitutive of, human being and its anthropocentric values. It follows from this
that an examination of metaphysical structures of thought according to this
"theory" of values will have to retrace the conscious, manifest or anthropocen-
tric values inherent in them to the unconscious, latent or physiological values
of which they are an expression.
On the basis of this assumption, namely that of the primacy of physiological
values, it becomes necessary to re-examine phenomena under the aspect of these
types of values which have shaped and continue to shape them. The question in
each case is transformed from the previous "what is it?" (which enquires into,
and is ultimately predicated on the assumption of, the identity of that to which
it is addressed), to "which values are productive in this case?" and thereby turns
into a question concerning the processes constitutive of a physiology ("The
question of values is more fundamental than the question of certainty." WP
588). It is clear that the latter question belongs to a radically different philo-
sophical project than the former. Because truth is no longer the ultimate measure
but has instead become problematised for a physiologically oriented philosophy,
the hitherto central question of modem philosophy of the possibility of
knowledge and the concomitant theories of knowledge have lost their allure.
282 ANDREA REHBERG
Physiologists should think again about positing the drive for preservation as the cardinal drive of
an organic being. Above all else something that is alive [etwas Lebendigesj wants to expend its
force; "preservation" is only one of the consequences of this. (WP 650, translation modified)
power) expends itself in truth as an error to which it gives rise, even though, as
Nietzsche shows, this is a most perilous adventure which ultimately endangers
life itself. This is to say that preservation and expenditure are not simply
opposed to one another but that the economy in which they interact is itself only
possible because of life's insatiable desire for expenditure.
But there is a further twist to the transvaluation of this economy, for it must
be asked which is the site of the ruinous adventure of life in combat with itself.
Nietzsche names human physiology as the battleground on which life's active
forces of expenditure and its reactive forces of preservation are in combat with
each other. There it is being determined whether the affirmation of life in
dissemination or the negation of it in preservation is to become dominant. This
ongoing process may lead to the devastation of the human body, as has been the
case with the incorporation of the truths of the metaphysical tradition, as
Zarathustra deplores: " .. .1 tread amongst humans as amongst fragments and
limbs of humans .. .! [find] human being smashed and scattered as over a field of
battle and butchery." 5
Or else it may bring about the dissipation of the human body in a joyous
exchange with other flows of matter. Through these processes life is able, in the
latter case, to replenish its productive powers or, as in the former case, it can
become temporarily impaired in its disseminative capacities. Thus when, in the
following note, Nietzsche speaks of life-threatening physiological errors, the
threat which the error that is truth poses does not only concern life in its
physiological instantiation (for instance as human life, where the error is
sustained like a cancerous growth) but concerns even life "itself':
Error is the most costly luxury which human being can permit itself; and if the error is even a
physiological error it becomes life-threatening. For what has humanity consequently payed the
most, atoned the worst? For its "truths," for these were all errors in physiologicis ... (WP 454,
translation modified).
Against positivism which halts at the phenomenon "there are only facts," I would say: no, there
are especially no facts, only interpretations. We can determine no fact "in itself," perhaps it is a
nonsense to want something like that. (WP 481, translation modified).
And so the question as to which values inform them must be addressed to the
sciences and to any kind of philosophy which acts as apologists of these ideals.
If these discourses display signs of an exhausted physiology, if they support
ideals of decadence, they will betray themselves by aspirations to an implicit
model of preservation- of themselves as of their respective objects. That is to
284 ANDREA REHBERG
say that their objects will be conceived or projected in terms of being (preserva-
tion), rather than becoming (expenditure). The question is, conversely, how
would a "science" of becoming, a non-representational "science" be organised,
to what extent could this differently conceived activity still be understood by
reference to the category of science and what would be the nature of its
conceptuality, i.e., what would supersede its traditional objectivity. Because it
is only by believing in a world of being that the formation of an object as such
can procede:
A world of becoming could not, in the strict sense, be "comprehended," be "known"; only insofar
as the "comprehending" and "knowing" intellect finds an already created crude world, constructed
from mere semblances, but become fixed, insofar as this kind of appearance has preserved life -
only insofar is there something like "knowledge" ... (WP 520, translation modified).
III
The most believed in a priori "truths" are for me- assumptions until fUrther notice, for example
the law of causality, very well rehearsed habits of belief, so incorporated that not to believe in
them would ruin the race. But are they therefore truths? What a conclusion! As if truth were
proven by the fact that human being endures. (WP 497) 7
When Nietzsche speaks of "a priori truths," a priori being most immediately
associated with Kantian terminology, he clearly means "eternal" truths, the
"truths" of the metaphysical tradition from which Kant himself at other times
so eagerly wished to dissociate his own philosophy.
Nietzsche paints causality as one of the "eternal truths" behind which a
dogmatically inclined reason likes to hide from the perpetual onslaught of
nature, or simply matter, which, in its most primary modes, is profoundly
indifferent to the interests of self-preservation which occupy human being. What
is called "truth" by that tradition is in fact no more than one of the tenets by
means of which a particular life form tries to preserve itself. This "truth," the
law of causality, is thus the prime example of what was above described as an
anthropocentric value, a belief which helps to structure the world into a
regularity based on the primacy of being for the purposes of human being and
which reciprocally determines the human being which enters into commerce
with the world on the basis of'this concept. Thus it is possible to see how
Nietzsche's "theory" of values supersedes Kant's theory of knowledge.
We can now sum up why Nietzsche views causality as such a reductive
concept. He is concerned with rethinking change in non-representational ways,
NIETZSCHE'S TRANSVALUATION OF CAUSALITY 285
that is to say, before the imposition of subject and object or, as he often puts it8 ,
doer and deed, upon a multifarious becoming. For him it is grammar, as a
function of self-preservation, rather than truth (which he, at any rate, greatly
problematises), which demands the separation of an occurrence into doer and
deed, the former of which is conceived in terms of being and substance, and as
causing the latter to take place as its effect:
The division of "doing" from the "doer," of the occurrence from a something that produces the
occurring, of the process from a something that is not process but rather endures, that is substance,
thing, body, soul etc., the attempt to comprehend an occurrence as a kind of shifting and change
of position of "beings" [Seiendes], of the permanent: this old mythology has fixated the belief in
"cause and effect" after it had found a fixed form in the linguistico-grammatical functions. (WP
631, translation modified)
If I say "lightning flashes" I have posited the f1ashing once as activity and another time as subject;
so that in addition to an occurrence I have presupposed a being which is not at one with the
occurrence, which rather endures, is, and does not "become." (WP 531, translation modified)
Nietzsche sums up this entire act of simplification as: " ... we have posited the
effect [Wirkung] as something that effects [Wirkendes] and the something that
effects as being" (Ibid.). That is to say, a multiple becoming is first of all
reduced to a mere effect which is in tum posited as "something that effects." In
the next step the "something that effects" is then posited as being, as subject or
substance or any of the other metaphysical terms which have been construed as
exempt from becoming and its insatiable temporality.
Nietzsche here describes the processes of increasing hypostatisation and
ossification through which a traditional metaphysical conceptuality turns an
essentially irreducible becoming into a profoundly atemporal being (cf. for
example WP 631, quoted above). But Nietzsche's excavatory work is able to
restore the primordiality of a becoming which has been given a reactive
direction through the imposition of anthropocentric values. The advantage
which human being gains by imposing such a category of essentially temporal
identity (resulting in the effacement of a complex or recurring temporality) upon
fundamentally non-identical processes of becoming lies in the construal of fixed
points which seem to correspond to the supposed fixity from which the "I" is in
each case enunciated, thereby underwriting the comforting humanist idee fixe
that a self-identical subject and a self-identical object correspond to one another.
But, as Nietzsche consistently demonstrates, thinking, unlike traditional
metaphysics steeped in theological concerns, need not be comforting, need not
reassure anyone of their "security in certainty:" "We put a word where our
ignorance commences, where we cannot see any farther ... - those are perhaps
the horizons of our knowledge but no truths"' (WP 482, translation modified).
286 ANDREA REHBERG
NOTES
Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (London: Macmillan, 1964 ). Hereafter CPR.
Cf. especially the "Second Analogy," CPR B 232-256.
Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power (New York: Random, 1968). Hereafter WP.
4 Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984 ). Hereafter TI.
5 Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1980), p. 160, translation
modified.
6 Cf., for instance, CPR A194 ff., B 239 ff. and A 201 ff., B 247.
7 Translation modified. Nietzsche's most famous critique of causality does of course occur in
"The Four Great Errors" in TI, pp. 58-65. In this paper I have mainly concentrated on sections
from WP precisely because they have received less attention to date.
8 For instance in On the Genealogy of Morals, (New York: Vintage, 1969), I, 13.
PETER POELLNER
We have no "sense for the causa efficiens": here Hume was right; habit (but not only that of the
individual') makes us expect that a certain often-observed occurrence will follow another [.... 1
That which gives the extraordinary firmness to our belief in causality is not the [... ]habit of seeing
one occurrence following another but our inability to interpret events otherwise than as events
caused by intentions. Is is belief in the living and thinking as the only effective force- in will, in
intention- it is belief that every event is a deed, that every deed presupposes a doer, it is belief
in the "subject." (WP 550)
According to this fragment, Hume was right in noting that we do not perceive
any "capacity to produce effects" (WP 551) in the objects - in this sense we
have indeed "absolutely no experience of a cause" (ibid.). But Nietzsche
disagrees with Hume on two important points. First, individual "custom" - i.e.
frequent past experience of specific conjunctions - cannot adequately explain
our strong propensity to expect the future to resemble the past. This seems
indeed correct. It is very implausible to hold that children only acquire a belief
in the "uniformity principle" with respect to sequences of specific event-types
once they have observed "constant conjunction" between events of the relevant
types in the past. With many of these types they seem to form the belief in
question without having had occasion to observe repeated conjunctions . While
it might be replied that they have nevertheless had overwhelming experience of
nature in general taking a uniform course, and no experience of it not doing so,
this also is by no means obvious. In fact, many "naively" observed event
sequences seem at first sight to disconfirm the expectation that nature takes a
uniform course (and thus that the future will resemble the past), because the
initial conditions are (unbeknownst to the non-scientific observer) different, and
CAUSATION AND FORCE IN NIETZSCHE 289
the uniformity is only detected after the cause-effect system in question has
been examined more carefully, has been isolated from initially undetected
external interferences, and so forth? Moreover - and this is of course a general
problem of classical empiricism - Burne can give no plausible answer to the
question of what makes it possible for us to pick out the relevant similarities
which enable us to identify different tokens of causal sequences as being of the
same type. Any two sequences "resemble" one another in an indefinite number
of respects. Burne's genetic theory simply assumes that we have identified the
relevant similarities - for only in this way is the experience of causally
significant "constant conjunction" of properties possible - but he offers no
explanation of why we are so remarkably successful in doing this. 4 In contrast
to Burne, Nietzsche's parenthetical remark in the extract cited above hints at the
need for an evolutionary explanation both of our ability to focus on causally
relevant similarities and of our belief that the future will resemble the past.
A second important difference from Burne is this. While for Nietzsche, also,
there is a projection of something "inner" onto "external" objects, what is
projected is not an associative compulsion, the result of the frequent encounter-
ing of A's followed by B's, but rather the (possibly misleading) experience of
apparent volitional agency. Indeed, it is this projection of an efficacious power
seemingly accessible by acquaintance in intentional activity, which is responsi-
ble for the sense that we have causally "understood" or "comprehended" an
occurrence:
Causality is created by thinking compulsion into the process. A certain "comprehension" is the
consequence, i.e. we have made the process more human, "more familiar": the familiar is the
familiar habit of human compulsion associated with the feeling of force. (WP 664)
Our "understanding of an event" has consisted in our inventing a subject which was made
responsible for something that happens[ ... ]: causa efficiens and causafinalis are fundamentally
one. (WP 551)
It is clear from these as well as from many other passages5 that the concep-
tions of comprehension and of its correlative "explanation" which Nietzsche
adopts are rather stringent, if not entirely original: to explain an event is to
"reduce" [zuriickfiihren] it to something with which we are "acquainted" [ein
Bekanntes] or familiar [vertraut]. Now this requirement may prima facie be
interpreted in a variety of ways. For instance, on one reading, the covering law
explanations which came to furnish the model of explanation accepted by many
philosophers of science in the present century might well be thought to comply
with it. "Explaining" a phenomenon at the most basic level of explanation
means, according to this paradigm, identifying it as one of the terms of an
instantiation of some universal law-like correlation of the form "all A's are
(concomitant with) B 's." Thus, in order to explain some particular event x, on
this construal, we need to identify x as an instance of type A and to know the
relevant nomic universal "all A's are B's," which enables us to deduce the cause
of x from the conjunction of the proposition stating the occurrence of x and the
290 PETER POELLNER
Cause and effect-- "Explanation" we call it: but it is description that distinguishes us from former
stages of knowledge and of science. We describe better - but we explain just as little as all
previous ones [.... ] The series of "causes"' stands in front of us much more completely in every
case, we reason: this and this has to precede if that is to follow- but thereby we have compre-
hended nothing. The quality, for instance, in any chemical process appears now as ever as a
"miracle," just as any locomotion does; no one has yet "explained" impact. (GS 112)
The point is rather this: people would not ordinarily be prepared to reject the
idea that there could be basic causal correlations obtaining in a closed set of
instances merely on definitional grounds, i.e. by virtue of the meaning of the
term "causation."
Aside from technical difficulties, the regularity theory (when combined with
the denial of natural necessity) faces of course powerful "intuitive" or common-
sense objections. Perhaps the most simple, but by no means least forceful, is that
it asks us to contemplate something really quite astonishing and, one may feel,
virtually incredible: the thought that uncountable events ("distinct existences,"
according to Hume) appear to have occurred since the beginning of the universe,
and continue to do so, in a regular, law-like manner, without there being any
reason for this. It asks us to accept this as a brute, contingent fact, in effect as
an extraordinary accumulation of accidents. 11 Could there be, one may be
inclined to ask, a theory more fanciful, more fantastic than this? My purpose in
making these remarks is obviously not to offer an exhaustive discussion of the
matter, but to indicate that the Nietzschean requirements concerning what causal
explanations should accomplish have not been clearly superseded by more
recent developments in the philosophy of science. On the contrary, there are
good reasons to believe that his statements capture what we standardly, pre-
philosophically, understand by (adequate) causal explanation and comprehen-
sion, and that theories which attempt to revise this "naive" understanding so as
to make Nietzsche's demands obsolete face formidable difficulties of their
own. 12
It is instructive to consider the particular application of Nietzsche's sceptical
strategy in his observations on the dynamist physics developed by Roger Joseph
Boscovich. He repeatedly refers to Boscovich's arguments against corpusculari-
anism in complete agreement so that it may indeed rightly be said that "Bo-
scovich had become a building block in Nietzsche's own philosophy." 13 In his
Theory of Natural Philosophy Boscovich argued that corpuscularianism -
according to which matter is composed of extended, absolutely rigid particles
moving in empty space and interacting by impact and pressure - is internally
inconsistent and should therefore be abandoned. Corpuscularianism implies that
the constituent particles become accelerated instantaneously and discontinu-
ously by finite, often quite large, increments upon impact. Such a discontinuous
change of velocity not only violates the law of continuity, a violation which
entails, according to Boscovich, that the system of interacting particles is in two
different states at the same instant; 14 it would also require, on the principles of
Newtonian physics, an infinite force. Boscovich concludes that change of
motion does not take place instantaneously and discontinuously upon contact
between moving particles, but rather continuously, on account of a repulsive
force acting at short distances between the elements of matter and increasing
asymptotically as the distance between them decreases. Since the magnitude of
this repulsive force approaches infinity with diminishing distance, it makes
direct contact between the elements impossible. Hence the ultimate constituents
of matter must be assumed to be perfectly simple and at some distance from
each other, for they must be indivisible in principle, that is, indivisible by any
294 PETER POELLNER
force, however large. This in tum implies (pace Locke) that the constituents of
matter cannot be extended, for "we see, in all those bodies that we can bring
under observation, that whatever occupies a distinct position is itself also a
distinct thing; so that those that occugy different parts of space can be separated
by using a sufficiently large force." 5 Boscovich's argument here is inductive,
rather than- like Leibniz's- conceptual. Leibniz asked, no less pertinently:
what could it mean to say that something is an actual, space-filling, extended
thing, and yet in principle indivisible? 16
For Boscovich, his arguments make it at least very likely that matter consists
of unextended physical points at some distance from each other, surrounded by
repulsive forces of the kind mentioned above, these turning into attractive forces
at a definite but as yet unknown distance from each point centre, so that for
larger distances Newton's gravitational laws continue to hold. Since Bo-
scovich's "points" have no volume, hence no mass in Newton's sense, his
"forces" also are defined differently from Newton's- they are in fact (when
actualized) accelerations, or otherwise propensities of acceleration. The upshot
of Boscovich's theory of matter is that matter consists of unextended point
centres surrounded by fields of "force." In Locke's language, matter does not
have the primary quality of solidity distinguishing it from empty space and
constituting the basis of its "powers" to make "a change in the bulk, figure,
texture and motion of another body." 17
Nietzsche takes Boscovich to have "refuted" mechanist atomism (BGE 12),
and he assimilates Boscovichean dynamism in various ways into his own
thought. It may be worth mentioning briefly in this context that it is partly
Boscovichean considerations which seem to motivate his denial of a substantial
"subject" as the basis or cause of the activities which appear to issue from it (see
esp. GM I: 13). Just as the material object, for Boscovich, consists of certain
"actions" and propensities, so the subject, for Nietzsche, consists of action-
events [Tun, Geschehen] and, possibly (although he is not explicit on this), of
dispositional propensities to act, which neither inhere in a Cartesian soul
substratum nor are dependent upon, or caused by, any actual and purely intrinsic
("primary") properties. This is what he means when he makes the often
misunderstood claim that the cause [das Wirkende] is not logically separable
from what it effects, or rather, from its "effecting" [das Wirken] (ibid.).
For Boscovich, the "forces" he postulates are both real 18 and ultimate, in the
sense of being irreducible to mechanical phenomena. Nietzsche, however,
follows Berkeley, Schopenhauer and Lange in denying any properly explanatory
value to both the Newtonian and the Boscovichean concepts of force: 19
One cannot "explain" pressure and impact themselves, one cannot get free of the actio in dis tans:
- one has lost the belief in being able to explain at all, and admits with a wry expression that
description and not explanation is all that is possible, that the dynamic interpretation of the world
with its denial of "empty space" and its little Jumps of atoms, will shortly come to dominate
physics[ ... ] (WP 618)
Nietzsche's point here is that terms like "force," "attraction" and "repulsion"
as used in physics may appear (especially to the non-scientific layperson) to
CAUSATION AND FORCE IN NIETZSCHE 295
The calculability of the world. the expressibility of all events in formulae - is this really
"comprehension''? (WP 624)
It is an illusion that something is known when we possess a mathematical formula for an event:
it is only designated, described; nothing more. (WP 628)
that force's are perfectly well observable, and that we may think of them (for
example) as the ob~ective correlates of certain sorts of experiences such as the
"feeling of strain,"-0 Nietzsche's rejoinder would presumably be this. We tend
to think that we can concretely, intuitively, conceive of (i.e. "imagine") the
objective correlate of feelings like the sensation of hardness as a quantity of
matter being intrinsically solid, voluminous, and of a certain shape (although
Nietzsche will eventually deny the coherence of this common sense belief, too),
but it seems simply bizzare to want to think of a presumed objective correlate
in inanimate nature of "feelings of strain" as in itself characterized by qualities
which could in any relevant way "resemble" the latter. Hence, while feelings of
strain may well serve as indications or signs of forces or powers, they do not
enlighten us about their "quality" - about what it is that makes them efficacious
- unless we are prepared to apply mentalistic predicates to them. And, as we
have seen, it is an understanding of qualities which "explanation" - or,
moderating Nietzsche's demand somewhat: adequate explanation- would have
to provide.
Modern physical science began with an attack on the "occult qualities" of
Aristotelianism, adopting as its battlecry the slogan that "to explicate a
phenomenon [isJ to deduce it from something else more known to us than the
thing to be explained by it." 21 But with the advent of Newtonian and, more
radically, Boscovichean forces, the wheel seems to have come full circle. The
apparently familiar is reduced to powers whose nature- their efficacy- is left
opaque. Hence Nietzsche's remark that "[t]he development of science resolves
the 'familiar' more and more into the unfamiliar: - it desires, however, the
reverse and proceeds from the impetus to trace the unfamiliar back to the
familiar" (WP 608). It is this exigency which gives rise to his own endeavour
- to which he devotes many pages in the later notebooks - to "supplement" the
"victorious concept 'force'" by an "inner will": 'There is nothing for it: one is
obliged to understand all motion, all 'appearances,' all 'laws,' only as symptoms
of an inner event and to employ man as an analogy to this end" (WP 619; cf.
WP 689; KGW VII.3.40.37)? 2
NOTES
1 References are given in the text to Friedrich Nietzsche, Werke: Kritische Gesamtausgabe, eds.
G. Colli and M. Montinari (Berlin, 1967-) KGW. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, ed. W.
Kaufmann (New York, 1968). Trans. W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale.
2 David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford, 1975), 165.
: Cf. William James, Principles of Psychology (New York, 1950), 2 vo1s., vol. ii, 634f.
Karl Popper, Conjectures and Refutations (London, 1963), 46-8.
5 E.g. GS 355; KGW Ylll.l.5.10; KGW VII.3.34.246.
6 The contrast I have in mind here is with formal analogies, a distinction analysed in detail by
M. Hesse, Models and Analogies in Science (Notre Dame, 1966 ), 60-70.
7 This interpretation of Nietzsche's criticism of theories of volitional causality is shared by A.
Mittasch in his classic commentary on Nietzsche's physics, Friedrich Nietzsche als Naturphi-
losoph (Stuttgart, 1952), 227.
x Ernest Nagel, The Structure of Science (London, 1961 ), 59.
CAUSATION AND FORCE IN NIETZSCHE 297
9 H.R. Harre and E.H. Madden, Causal Powers (Oxford, 1975), 30.
10 Nagel, The Structure of Science, 63.
11 Cf. Galen Strawson, The Secret Connexion (Oxford, 1989), 20-31.
12 A more radical rejection of the Nietzsche an conception of adequate explanation would be one
that denies that any qualities figure in "objective reality"- as opposed to "subjective" registerings
of it- at all. Nietzsche briskly dismisses a quasi-Pythagorean conception of objective reality in
exclusively formal or quantitative terms as unintelligible: "The reduction of all qualities to
~uantities is nonsense" (WP 564).
1 K. Schlechta and A. Anders, Friedrich Nietzsche - Von den verborgenen Anfiingen seines
Philosophierens, (Stuttgart-Bad Cannstadt, 1962), 136.
14 R. Boscovich, A Theory of Natural Philosophy (Chicago, 1922), 65.
15 Ibid., 85.
16 See e.g. G.W. Leibniz, "Primary Truths," in G. H. R. Parkinson (ed.), Philosophical Writings
Philosophical Works (London, 1993), 255-276; A. Schopenhauer, The World as Will and
Representation (New York, 1966), 2 vols., vol. i, 112-124; F.A. Lange,Geschichte des Materialis-
mus (Iserlohn, 1866), 360f. The latter two works are likely to have directly influenced Nietzsche's
thinking on the subject.
2 °
C.D. Broad, Scientific Thought (London. 1923), 162-3.
21 Robert Boyle, "The Origins of Forms and Qualities," in M.A. Stewart (ed.), Selected
With Darwin, a materialistic basis was established for explaining the emergence
and transformation of species, shaking to its very foundation the preceding
conception of natural order. By the end of the last century, it was generally
recognized that the crucial role played by Darwin was the introduction of
historical analysis to the center of biological thinking. Both the species and the
organism became less entities than processes, dynamically evolving and ever-
different. Being was fully realized as a Heraclitean flux, a becoming. This
metaphysical revolution of how we would henceforth regard time, the biological
world, and most fundamentally, ourselves, was the challenge to which Friedrich
Nietzsche responded; and in that response he challenged the pre-Darwinian
notions of health. Specifically, what Bernard had championed as the "normal,"
a stable interior milieu (or what Walter Cannon would later call "homeostasis"),
Nietzsche would endeavor to replace with inner turmoil as the essence of
biological function. While evolutionary biologists would refer to "fitness,"
Nietzsche would pervade his entire philosophy with the elusive maximal
adaptation of the striving organism. This struggle was directed towards some
unspecified and unknowable ideal, and Nietzsche invoked this struggle as the
essence of health.
Evolution offered Nietzsche an ethic in nature's seemingly ceaseless striving.
He found meaning not in something absolute and definitive, but in the Uber-
mensch (the Overman) as evolution embodied. What is potential and germinal
awakens to greater expansion and finer expression of its essence. With the
Overman, life becomes fuller and richer. "He is not a fixed goal which gives
meaning to evolution, but only expresses the fact that there is no need for such
a goal, that life in itself, in the process [of evolution] has its own value." 1 This
goaless evolution, where only potentialities are recognized, allows for evolution
to assume sui generis, a value in itself. Characteristic and central to this view
(echoed by others of the period, e.g. Henri Bergson) would be the reliance on
life to assume its own purposive character (through its evolutionary nature) and
the denial of the need for external forces or deities. When such a philosophy
would assume its expression in the self, jolting consequences would ensue.
299
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 299-311.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
300 SCOTT H. PODOLSKY AND ALFRED I. TAUBER
The individual itself as a struggle between parts (for food, space, etc.): its evolution tied to the
victory or predominance of individual parts, to an atrophy, a "becoming an organ" of other parts .
... The aristocracy in the body, the majority of the rulers (struggle between cells and tissues).
Slavery and division of labor: the higher type possible only through the subjugation of the lower,
so that it becomes a function. 12
eventually to dominate his worldview and ultimately serve as the basis of a new
morality.
Although his view of health changed, i.e., different elements were added and
elaborated over time, a consistent reading of "health" can be applied to
Nietzsche's use of the concept at all times, even if certain of its elements at any
given moment were more implicit than explicit. In general, the following six
components characterized the Nietzschean conception of health: I) Life is
characterized by disharmony and resultant struggle at all levels, with the ability
to harmonize and create order from chaos a measure of individual power. This
may represent Apollo taming Dionysus or the will to power, but the underlying
conception is the same. 2) In the absence of truth, God, and absolute good and
evil, one can only live well, looking for those values most useful to the good,
powerful, self-creative life. Such resultant activities may range from aesthetic
creation to warlike conquest in the name of such values. 3) Since self-creation
involves constant redefinition in a changing environment, one must continually
pose resistances to oneself and overcome them. The inability to even pose such
resistance represents sickliness. 14 The inability to overcome such resistance
reveals sickness. The abilities both to pose and overcome such resistance
represents health- perhaps even great health. 4) Since each individual is the
outcome of a unique, contingent history of struggle, and since greatness can be
accomplished in many ways, no two types of individual greatness need be equal.
Hence, there is no single static norm of health -the only constant of the many
expressions of health is the degree of power which individuals expend success-
fully. 5) Health of the body and health of the mind are not only physiologically
related, but operate according to parallel principles of resistance, struggle, and
creative overcoming. Therefore, the great thinker is healthy when he can
challenge his principles and incorporate anomalies into new and expanded
worldviews. 6) Hence, the philosopher as "physician of culture" and "physician
of the soul" - as Nietzsche was attempting to function - acts by challenging
prevailing principles and by forcing society and its individuals to acknowledge
and incorporate anomalies into their own worldviews. Note that while we have
attempted to depict Nietzsche's system as somewhat logically derived, it was
not constructed as such chronologically. However, the more fundamental
conceptions were always implicit, with his ideas only gradually exposed and
developed. Such a process should be kept in mind throughout the rest of this
section, where the development of Nietzsche's views of health will be presented
in three groupings.
The activity of the older philosophers ... tended toward the healing and the purification of the
whole. It is the mighty flow of Greek culture that shall not be impeded; the terrible dangers in its
path shall be cleared away: thus did the philosopher protect and defend his native land. 17
Moreover, just as the individual at the psychological level could absorb and
assimilate conflicting worldviews, so could the Greeks, who "invariably
absorbed other living cultures," 18 extend their domain at the cultural level. Thus,
without even mentioning the physiological organism, Nietzsche first created a
fledgling depiction of health in terms of the responses of the mind and the social
body to philosophical challenges.
In "The Philosopher as Cultural Physician," Nietzsche would repeat and
extend such views. He first reiterated the role of the philosopher as described
in Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks. 19 However, Nietzsche here made
the further, albeit brief and subtle, extension of such tension between dishar-
mony and harmony at the psychological and social levels - levels mediated by
philosophers - to the level of the biological organism itself. Life itself could be
seen as characterized by "the essential imperfection of things," 20 where
Dionysian chaos and struggle reside on the foundation of all things and where
Apollonian harmonizing is required to follow. Such an embryonic conception
was not fully fleshed out until The Will to Power, wherein all the different levels
- from the biological to the social - would be seen to have their own domains
of struggle, each affecting the levels above and below them. Nonetheless, while
Nietzsche allowed his conception of health to remain grounded primarily in
society at large at this time, he had begun to illustrate its ramifications at the
organismallevel.
304 SCOTT H. PODOLSKY AND ALFRED I. TAUBER
The end of this early stage was reached in section 52 of Daybreak (1881),
entitled "Where are the New Physicians of the Soul?" This would represent a
concise summary of his early call to philosophy to counter, not condone, the
type of comforting, life-negating philosophy stemming from Plato to Christian-
ity. Nietzsche proposed that the Greek model of the philosopher-as-resistor be
brought forward into the world which he had previously entitled "diseased." 21
His attempt to bring the Greek physician of cultural health - the philosopher-
into the modern age marked the end of his first stage.
The Gay Science and On the Genealogy of Morals serve as the central reposito-
ries of Nietzsche's mature concept of health; they can truly be said to be
dominated by such a concern. The former work is far less radical than the latter;
but more than any other text, The Gay Science (1882, 1887) moves the theme
of health to a central position in Nietzsche's thinking. There it develops all but
the first of the six postulates of Nietzsche's conception of health stated above,
and these may be presented in three groupings. First, Nietzsche chose this text
to elucidate the theme of health at the individual, rather than the societal, level.
The preface is filled with the concept of birth, of labor and creation produced
out of individual pain and struggle: "From such abysses, from such severe
sickness, ... one returns newborn, having shed one's skin." 22 In short, the
individual grows and become healthy by overcoming pain and engaging
struggle.
Second, alluding to the will to power without here labeling that conception,
Nietzsche next fully explicates the notion of health as arising from continuous
individual struggle and contradiction, from the posing and overcoming of
obstacles. In section 382, discussing "great health," Nietzsche most explicitly
relates such instructions:
Whoever wants to know from the adventures of his own most authentic experience how a
discoverer and conqueror of the ideal feels ... -needs one thing above everything else: the great
health -that one does not merely have but also acquires continually, and must acquire because one
gives up again and again, and must give it up. 23
Great health therefore results in the individual so powerful that he can not only
withstand, but even look forward to, defeats from which he can recover and
grow (GS 163). However, at the same time, health has become the elusive ideal:
"And now, after we have long been on our way in this manner, we argonauts of
the ideal, with more daring perhaps than is prudent, and have suffered shipwreck
and damage often enough, but are, to repeat it, healthier than one likes to permit
us, dangerously healthy, ever again healthy" (GS 382).
This is the essence behind his famous dictum in section 283 to "live danger-
ously," and it reveals Nietzsche's emphasis upon those who continually
contradict and redefine themselves and others. In fact, not only is great health
an elusive ideal, but it is not even a single definable ultimate state. In the critical
section 120, Nietzsche maintains that there is no normal health - and this
NIETZSCHE'S CONCEPTION OF HEALTH 305
applies to both the health of the soul and the health of the body upon which it
is based (note Nietzsche's encroaching physiologism here):
Even the determination of what is healthy for your body depends on your goal, your horizon, your
energies, your impulses, your errors, and above all on the ideals and phantasms of your soul. Thus
there are innumerable healths of the body; and the more we allow the unique and incomparable
to raise its head again, and the more we abjure the dogma of the "equality of men," the more must
the concept of a normal health, along with a normal diet and the normal course of an illness, be
abandoned by medical men. Only then would the time have come to reflect on the health and
illness of the soul, and to find the peculiar virtue of each man in the health of his soul. (GS 120)
I am still waiting for a philosophical physician in the exceptional sense of that word- one who
has to pursue the problem of the total health of a people, time, race, or of humanity- to muster the
courage to push my suspicion to its limits and to risk the proposition: what was at stake in all
philosophizing hitherto was not at all "truth" but something else - let us say, health, future,
growth, power, life. (GS, Preface 2)
This idea, still embryonic here, would serve as the foundation of On the
Genealogy o.f Morals. In fact, the many conceptions of health introduced in The
Gay Science may be said to represent the foundation upon which Morals would
build to logical completion.
On the Genealogy of Morals (1887) may be said to represent the Nietzschean
account of health, and more broadly, health is the key to reading all three of its
essays. Therein, Nietzsche fully fleshed out his replacement of truth with health.
As several critics have noted, the first essay, with its juxtaposition of the
good/evil and good/bad dichotomies, may just as well have juxtaposed good/evil
with healthy/sick. Nietzsche repeatedly contrasted in this first essay the healthy,
active noble lifestyle with the sickly, reactive slave lifestyle. Note, moreover,
in this context, the striking prelude to the eventual identification of health with
the will to power:
To demand of such strength that it should not be a desire to overcome, a desire to throw down, a
desire to become master, a thirst for enemies and resistances and triumphs, is just as absurd as to
demand of weakness that it should express itself as strength. 24
Health was being reduced to the expression of the will to power itself seeking
out and overcoming resistances. This final aspect of health was at last coming
into place.
306 SCOTT H. PODOLSKY AND ALFRED I. TAUBER
The second essay, historically delineating the emergence of the bad con-
science, extends the concept of health to yet another level of organization: not
that of a single community or individual, but that of all humanity since the
painful inception of civilization. This essay serves as a lucid illustration of how
mankind's endemic sickness, the painful historical onset of the bad conscience,
could itself be incorporated by the strong and transformed into such traits
necessary for future, great health as personal discipline and endurance. The bad
conscience was a "serious illness," but it was "an illness as pregnancy is an
illness," 25 and this theme would dominate the second essay. The very onset of
the sickness of the bad conscious stimulates the strong to overcome future
sickness and attain still greater health. Finally, the third essay, derived from the
first, attempted yet another device to demonstrate Nietzsche's conception of
health. Almost rhetorically, he exposed its antithesis, asceticism, as the
medicine of nihilism - as a quack remedy for mankind, hoping for his readers
to derive their own therapeutic conceptions therefrom. As he wrote:
It would be pointless to indulge in criticism of this kind of priestly medication, the "guilty" kind.
Who would want to maintain that such orgies of feeling as the ascetic priest prescribed to his sick
people ... ever benefitted them? ... The ascetic priest has ruined physical health wherever he has
come to power 26
Both his own remedy and his diametrical opposition's had been presented; it
was for his readers to choose their cure.
Thus, On the Genealogy of Morals served as a bridge between the pre-axial
and post-axial conceptions of health. In it, we see still more clearly an underly-
ing use of the will to power and the Overman (see, for instance, GM II: 10)
which was a decidedly post-Zarathustra modification. These conceptions had
been implicit before this period, but only at this time could they be said to fully
shape Nietzsche's presentation of health. The healthy man was becoming the
Ubermensch, and the striving for health was becoming the will to power, as
Nietzsche reduced his system to several crucial foundation-points. This process
would achieve its fullest clarification in The Will to Power, written at the same
time as On the Genealogy of Morals.
The Will to Power at last offered the full identification of life's ceaseless
struggle, the first component in the "logical" construction of Nietzschean health.
This component had been implicit all along, but now life itself was to be
explicitly viewed as the result of internal strife and overcoming. "Health" could
now be regarded as representing the identical essence of competition, whether
viewed at the more complex societal and organismic levels or extrapolated to
the simplest protozoa or individual cells. Health, in sum, was proclaimed as just
one aspect of the will to power. The philosopher as cultural physician, or
physician of the soul, was merely a favorable resistance for such a will. The
forming, shaping, healthy individual was now no "healthier" than amoebae
themselves, extending their pseudopods, overwhelming and incorporating their
NIETZSCHE'S CONCEPTION OF HEALTH 307
environment. 27 Thus, Nietzsche had firmly placed humanity within its naturalis-
tic, physiological context; all the aesthetics and philosophisizing of the Greeks
were at last to be seen as no more than the stretching of mental pseudopods.
Health, and humanity, had been fully naturalized, and Nietzsche's system of
health had been completed in terms of a sweeping biological synthesis.
Nietzsche espoused such views of health as finally developed in the axial
period until the very end of his writing. In Ecce Homo ("Why I Am So Wise,"
section 2), Nietzsche presented the same theory of the healthy Overman that he
had been espousing for nearly two decades. Having fully confessed his own
decadence in section 1, Nietzsche devoted section 2 to his own overcoming of
nihilism. He had become, of course, his own model for the healthy Overman,
and he declared his philosophy to represent his own autobiography. Many critics
have shown how Nietzsche's theory of health derived from his own manifold
health concems?8 A single quote will summarize Nietzsche's own circumspect
view quite well:
I took myself in hand. I made myself healthy again: the condition for this - every physiologist
would admit that - is that one be healthy at bottom. A typically morbid being cannot become
healthy, much less make itself healthy. For a typically healthy person, conversely, being sick can
even become an energetic stimulus for life, for living more. This, in fact, is how that long period
of sickness appears to me now: as it were, I discovered life anew, including myself; I tasted all
good and even little things, as others cannot easily taste them- I turned my will to health, to life,
into a philosophy. 29
Thus, the will to health finally equalled not only the will to power, but
Nietzsche's will to life and to philosophize. It is from this point that we might
discern our own indebtedness as these themes have filtered into our medical
culture at large, a topic which will be discussed below.
More might have been written concerning Nietzsche's views on health. 3 Certain °
writers, in a manner similar to ours, do discuss Nietzsche's health as the
antithesis of the avoidance of health? 1 A few summary remarks will therefore
be made before presenting our own argument. Fundamentally, though, our
interpretation hinges upon the assumption that Nietzsche applied the same
Darwinian orientation he espoused in his view of the body to his understanding
of health: struggle, competition, and overcoming. As a caveat, it is important to
note that no one attributes to Nietzsche the type of Bemardian conception of
health-as-passive-normalcy.
However, contrary to our view, several critics do interpret Nietzsche as
envisioning sickness as extrinsic to the body, as something to be overcome by
a fundamentally normalized organism which will then rise to a higher level of
normalcy. In their analyses, health= self= normal, sickness= other= harmful,
and the harm must be overcome. 32 This may lead to a dynamic, progressive,
ascending spiral of health, but it is not a conception of health as the
non-progressive, elusive ideal. With Pasley our disagreement lies in the will to
308 SCOTT H. PODOLSKY AND ALFRED I. TAUBER
power. He places no emphasis upon the internal struggle for health epitomized
by and generalized as the will to power. The subject is, for him, still a unity,
countering a specific other. This lack of a conception of multitude, a subject
unified by the will to power seeking an ideal of health, distinguishes this
"non-Darwinian" reading. Health occurs when sickness happens to be over-
come; it is not a fundamental process of striving for resistance. It is still
mediated by a "reactive," rather than an "active," organism. Kaufmann shares
Pasley's opinion, but based on a different interpretation of the eternal recurrence
from our own, 33 and it is here that the full implications of Nietzschean health
can be understood.
Nietzsche's philosophy assumes its most profound biological orientation in
the eternal recurrence, which is fundamentally organic in its implicit connota-
tions of renewal, regeneration, and return. There are those who understand
eternal recurrence as a cosmological princM;le; the reasons for rejecting this
interpretation are amply argued elsewhere. 4 Philosophically, Nietzsche uses
eternal recurrence as a theory not of the world, but of the self. The interpretation
of the eternal recurrence must reside in a consistent reading of Nietzsche's
concepts of the will to power and its corollary, becoming as true being. In a
profound sense, Nietzsche envisioned that the eternal recurrence is the fulfill-
ment of living each moment, each act, each choice without the demurrals of past
remorse or future judgement. We are enjoined to live as if each moment is to be
relived, unchanged, into eternity. The eternal recurrence is the final destination
of a deeply rooted evolutionary process, a calling which should become an ethic
of our biological being, independent of any transcendent principle. With that
perspective, each moment is not only immutable, but precious, and forever
accountable to ourselves. Nietzsche's recurrence does not refer "to a life
precisely like this one, but to this very life." 35 In Nietzsche's words:
I come again, with this sun, with this earth, with this eagle, with this serpent- not to a new life
or a better life or a similar life: I come back eternally to this same, selfsame life ... to each again the
eternal recurrence of all things ... to proclaim the overman again to men. 16
Nietzsche thus would imbue the quality of eternity into every moment, and
he would lead us to a supreme self-awareness of the ultimate and inescapable
responsibility for our acts. The last element of the ethic then is to accept the
irrevocability of every choice allowing us to assume the mandate of responsibil-
ity for our life, a life to be lived again and again, eternally. If God is dead, then
our morality must be based on our self-willed sovereignty. Responsibility then
resides solely in the self, whose identity is based on fully acknowledging the
primacy of the will to power and living its mandate freed of false and encum-
bering moral restrictions. This is a commitment only the strong can assume, for
the sick sigh, "If only I were some else." (GM III: 14) If life is to be eternally
recurrent, then we must accept living in the present in its full and self-sufficient
complement. Time is framed not in the past or future, but accompanies us,
moving steadily forward in the present. In this sense, Nietzsche accepts
"becoming"; but he does so with the particular proviso of apprehending the
NIETZSCHE'S CONCEPTION OF HEALTH 309
omnipotent present as full being, which in turn entails the rejection of becoming
as an end or goal. (WP 53)
Thus, by removing extraneous moral context, life is lived as full and
unencumbered will. The will, alone on its own axis, unselfconsciously knows
no past or future. The eternal recurrence, as an ethical mandate, becomes the
ultimate assertion of that will. It is precisely the raising of man, the animal, from
the one-dimensional will to a second ethical dimension that allows a moral
exercise of will to alter the self and thereby become freed and healed. Here then
is an expansive ethic, in which a fully creative will is celebrated, and redemp-
tion may be thus attained. And further, if the eternal recurrence is regarded as
the essence of "becoming" with no end point, then health - as the appropriate
expression of that activity- is never achieved but remains an elusive ideal. To
be sick is not to strive; health is the expression of the will's ceaseless struggle
- never fulfilled, but always becoming.
CONCLUSION
Aside from the interest Nietzsche generates in his own right, what lessons might
we learn from his philosophy of health? If we refer to the opening passages of
this essay, we posited that Nietzsche offers us a window, as it were, into the
metaphysical foundations of how we might view ourselves as healers or
patients. This is not to say that we need adopt his proposal of the body as a
crucible for Darwinian struggle of competing drives, but rather to contemplate
the general sense of responsibility for one's health. He argued we are funda-
mentally our bodies, demanded that rather than being subject to divine fate, we
assume to the extent our self-will permits, our own life course. This is a heroic
Romantic anthem to be sure, and it was enunciated in different guises by others.
But Nietzsche most clearly articulated the very modern notion that we must
rediscover ourselves in, or better, as our bodies. It is a theme picked up by later
phenomenologists, e.g., Merleau-Ponty, and has drifted into our common culture
in myriad ways. But these are not our direct concern.
Most fundamentally, we are struck with the general ethos in medicine that
there is a close correlation between life-style and health. Ethos perhaps is a
strange way of posing this current truism given the epidemiological information
to support this medical "fact," but there is a strong ethical correspondence
between the interpretation of such medical data. Our culture no longer accepts
normalcy; we aspire to an idealized health, from our premature infants to our
growing number of octogenarians and beyond. Our medical expectations are
driven not by population norms but by the ideals (ala Galton). 37 We should
recall that the Nietzschean notion of health was a radical rejoinder to the
pre-Darwinian concept of balance and normalcy. The norm was a discovery of
Bernard's generation; 38 the ideal of Nietzsche was to eclipse it. The "norm"
today is to be ill; we complain of ailments more than twice as frequently as fifty
years ago. 39 An idealized ideal of health has in fact become a national mandate
as we hear public health officialdom proclaim the benefits of recommended diet
and exercise.
310 SCOTT H. PODOLSKY AND ALFRED I. TAUBER
This is not the place to critique our modem health aspirations, but it is of
interest to probe one seminal philosophical source for their origin. Nietzsche
thus focuses our interest, for we have grasped a cardinal axiom of Nietzschean
insight- we may aspire to an idealized state of health from multiple points of
origin. We do so both because of our biological character that he defined as the
will to power, but also applied as an ethical mandate in the eternal recurrence.
The problematic nature of Nietzsche's morality remains undiscussed here, and
we would not be construed as endorsing his position. The issue explicated here
is more modest, namely on what basis did Nietzsche propose health as both a
medical (qua biological) and ethical concern?
We perceive a deep resonance in our culture's current concerns with
Nietzsche's notions that we strive for health on the basis that evolution demands
the organism struggle for its existence and pursue self-aggrandizement
(Darwin), as well as fulfill its ethical mandate (Nietzsche). Thus following
Darwin, the organism is no longer given, static and defined, but must be
regarded as dynamic and ever-changing. Within a Darwinian construct,
Nietzsche bequeathed an ethos of how this fundamental character of our
biological nature would be transformed into a new morality, one in which
human beings, as both a society and as individuals, are ultimately responsible
for, and to, ourselves. It is a pervasive ethic, whose full influence in medicine
we suspect remains to be fully expressed.
NOTES
1 G. Simmel, Schopenhauer and Nietzsche [1907] (Loiskandl H, Weinstein D, Weinstein M.,
trans.] (Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1991), p. 7.
2 A. 1. Tauber, "A Typology of Nietzsche's Biology," Biology and Philosophy 9 (1994): 25-45.
3 L. Buss, The Evolution of Individuality (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1987).
4 L. Nordenfelt, On the Nature of Health: An Action-Theoretic Approach (Dordrecht: Kluwer
Academic Publishers, 1987), p. 65.
5 W.M. Brown, "On Defining 'Disease'," Journal of Medical Philosophv 10 (1985): 311-328.
6 -
Nordenfelt, On the Nature of Health.
7 I. Porn, "An Equilibrium Model of Health," in: L. Nordenfelt, B.I.B. Lindahl, eds., Health,
Disease, and Causal Explanation in Medicine (Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1984),
fP· 3-9.
C. Whitbeck, "Four Basic Concepts of Medical Science" PSA l (1978) 210-222; C. Whitbeck,
"A Theory of Health" in A. L. Caplan, H. T. Engelhardt, Jr, J.J. McCartney, eds., Interdisciplinary
Perspectives (Reading, Massachusetts: Addison-Wesley Publications, 1981) pp. 611-626.
9 C. Boorse, "Health as a Theoretical Concept," Philosophy of Science 44 (1977) 542-573.
10 Tauber, "A Typology of Nietzsche's Biology"; A. Moles, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Nature and
Cosmology (New York: Peter Lang Publishing, 1990); E. Blonde!, Nietzsche: The Bodv and
Culture, trans. S. Hand (Palo Alto: Stanford University Press, 1991), T. Long, "Nietzsche's
Philosophy of Medicine," Nietzsche-Studien 19 (1990): 112-128.
11 Moles, op. cit.
12 F. Nietzsche, The Will To Power [1904] trans. W. Kaufmann, R.J. Hollingdale (New York:
WP47.
15 Nietzsche, Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks [1872], trans. M. Cowan (Washington,
16 Ibid., p. 28.
17 Ibid., p. 35.
18 Ibid., p. 30.
19 Nietzsche, "The Philosopher as Cultural Physician," in D. Breazeale, ed. and trans., Philosophy
and Truth, Selections from Nietzsche's Notebook of the Early 1870s (Atlantic Highlands:
Humanities Press, International, 1990), pp. 71-73.
20 Ibid., p. 69.
21 Nietzsche, Daybreak [1881], trans. R.J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Thought- A Collection of Essays (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978), pp. 123-158.
29 Nietzsche, Ecce Homo [1888], trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Vintage Books, 1967), p. 4
30 [See however the comprehensive contribution to this theme by the German philosopher and
physician, Pia Daniela Volz, Nietzsche im Labyrinth seiner Krankheit. Eine medizinisch-
biographische Untersuchung (Wiirzburg: Kbnigshausen & Neuman, 1990) as well as, in part,
Sarah Kofman's massive two volume study, Explosions. Del' "Ecce Homo" de Nietzsche (Paris:
Galilee, 1992); English translation by Duncan Large forthcoming.- Ed.)
31 See Long, "Nietzsche's Philosophy of Medicine." Long points to Karl Jaspers' influence in this
INTRODUCTION
The world, according to Nietzsche, is will to power, and nothing besides (WP
1067; BGE 36). 1 But the world as will to power remains enigmatic, despite
Nietzsche's many efforts to explicate its operation in physics, chemistry,
biology, psychology, and politics. 2
In what follows I am to clarify the will to power by interpreting its activity
as that of a parallel distributed processing (henceforth abbreviated as PDP)
system. PDP systems are populations of dynamical units whose independent but
synchronized operations make a whole whose behavior is typically more than
the sum of the behaviors of its parts. PDP systems form the basis for work in
chaos, fractals, cellular automata, non-linear dynamical systems, self-organizing
systems, and neural nets.
313
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Episterrwlogy, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 313-322.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
314 ERIC STEINHART
The world as will to power is a finite, conserved quantity of force (Z III: 10/1;
WP 595, 1062, 1066, 1067). It is discrete insofar as the number of configura-
tions of forces in it is calculable and definite (WP 1066). The will to power is
bounded (WP 1067). It is, consequently, a self-contained granular medium
shaken by internal detonations (i.e. percussive power-discharges). In such a
medium, patterns like Chladni's "sound-figures" appear (PT, p. 24; cf. p. 82);
these patterns are the invariants of interacting waves. They are treaty-drafts of
will (WP 715), power-constellations. Strikingly, experiments with vibrated
granular media have demonstrated the emergence of patterns ("oscillons")
acting like charged particles. 6 These oscillons combine to form atomic and
molecular structures: vibrated discrete media support non-trivial physics.
Our model of the will to power as a self-enclosed granular medium shaken
by internal detonations is a PDP model. Several further features of PDP systems
motivate their use as models for the will to power: (1) PDP systems are
inherently relational, directly modeling the perspectival nature of the will to
power; (2) processing in PDP systems is holistic, and so is activity in the will
to power;7 (3) PDP theorists have put forth thennodynamic theories of computa-
tion, and Nietzsche describes the will to power in thermodynamic and philologi-
cal (informational) terms; (4) certain PDP systems are self-organizing dynami-
cal systems, and Nietzsche describes the will to power as just such a system; 8
(5) PDP accounts of recursive auto-associative memories square well with
Nietzsche's view of memory as active; (6) PDP theorists have opposed their
distributed models of cognition to centralized models, and Nietzsche makes the
same opposition; (7) PDP accounts of how cooperative strategies (e.g. conven-
tions) emerge within collectives of agents accord well with Nietzsche's accounts
of how language & knowledge emerge in the herd. We use these parallels to
make sense of the will to power in contemporary scientific terms.
Nietzsche describes the will to power in thermodynamic terms (WP 1067). 9 The
will to power cycles between a hot high point and a cold low point (GS 277; WP
639, 712, 1067). This thermal cycle is both global (WP 1067) and local (WP
567, 636). 10 The global cycle is the eternal return (GS 109, 341; WP 1000-
1067).11 The local cycle is superimposed on the global cycle, much as the
diurnal cycle of daily heating and nocturnal cooling is superimposed on the
yearly cycle of summer heating and winter cooling.
These thermal cycles constitute the inner will (WP 619) that distinguishes the
will to power from merely mechanical force. Both the local and global cycles
are best modeled physically as waves (GS 310), 12 that is, as sinusoidal functions
of time. 13 The incongruence of the will to power with itself (WP 568) prevents
these cycles from being damped out, thereby rendering entropy cyclical (WP
639, 1063, 1064, 1066) rather than always increasing. The will to power is a
discrete dynamical system oscillating through evolutionary self-organization
and devolutionary self-disorganization (WP 712, 796).
THE WILL TO POWER AND PDP SYSTEMS 315
What distinguishes the will to power from mechanistic systems (GS 373; WP
618-639) is that its entropy is cyclical: time's arrow reverses direction at both
low and high points (WP 712). From high to low, entropy goes up; from low to
high, it goes down. As entropy increases, the world as a whole becomes more
homogeneous: thermal contrasts decrease, energy disperses itself, hotspots
disappear; as entropy decreases, the world becomes more heterogeneous:
thermal contrasts increase, energy concentrates itself, hotspots appear.
The entropy of the world as will to power is naturally factored into two
opposed but directly proportional (i.e. agonistic) qualities: turbulence and
agility. These are (roughly) the Dionysian and Apollinian aspects of the will to
power. 14 At the high point, both are maximal; at the low point, both are minimal.
Exemplars of maximal agility in maximal turbulence include dancing near the
abyss (GS 347), the tree that raises its branches into the lightning (GS 19, 371),
and the ship in the storm. (GS 318, 382) The more agile Stoic lives best in more
turbulent times; the less agile Epicurean lives best in less turbulent times (GS
154, 306, 375).
Turbulence and agility determine the temperature of the will to power both
locally and globally in space and time. As the will to power heats up from low
(coldest) to high (hottest), both agility and turbulence intensify. Increasing
heterogeneity yields hot action: the most skillful mastery of the greatest chaos
by the greatest artistry (i.e. ordering power). 15 A master of musical improvisa-
tion is hot insofar as he or she plays skillfully with chance as a partner (GS 303),
and at the high points in life we are all such masters (GS 277). As the will to
power cools down from high to low, both agility and turbulence slacken.
Increasing homogeneity yields cool action. The hot insights and actions of the
individual freeze into the linguistic and moral conventions of the herd.
Physics today recognizes a deep analogy between entropy and information-
processing.16 This analogy binds thermodynamics and philology: the will to
power as a self-interpreting text (GS 374; WP 481, 556, 643; BGE 14, 22) is a
t herma1 m .
. f ormatiOn-processor. 17
The thermal cycle of the will to power from low point to high point and back
down precisely parallels the thermal cycle of PDP information-processing
systems l 1.ke B o 1tzmann mac h.mes, 18 ..h armony mac h"mes, 19 spm-g
. 1asses, 20 an d
Ising systems. 21 Thermodynamics and interpretation focus our model of the will
to power as a PDP system: power-constellations in the will to power are
information-bearing patterns transformed by recurrent cycles of melting and
freezing. Insofar as the will to power is a PDP system transforming information-
bearing patterns, its interpretation is computation.
Our view that the will to power computes like a Boltzmann or harmony
machine is reinforced by Nietzsche's conception of an extremely simple kind
of cognition. Since all of existence is engaged in interpretation, that is, in
computation, even crystals compute. Indeed, such computation is a primitive
form of cognition that proceeds by annealing (WP 499). 22 Such primitive
thinking remains operative even in humans (GS 54).
316 ERIC STEINHART
Our wave-mechanical conception of the will to power helps to clarify its action
as percussion and repercussion (WP 567, 636). At each moment, driven by the
inner will (the internal oscillation of the will to power) each center of force
detonates, radiating a shockwave into the whole of the will to power (WP 636).
Other centers of force (organized into power-constellations) resist (WP 568) by
reflecting and modulating the shockwaves they receive as they transmit their
own. The reverberations of these shockwaves (WP 633) ground the musicality
of the will to power, so that rhythm, tempo, melody, and harmony become
legitimate cosmological categories. (Cf. GS 84, 109, 373; WP 552) Waves
mirror waves, hence new unities (WP 552, 561) and patterns of functional
organization form in the will to power (WP 636). The cycle of percussion and
repercussion is a thermodynamic one on which informational (auto-philological)
processes supervene.
Percussion and repercussion explain how each power-structure adopts a
perspective to all others (WP 567, 636) via perception and appearance.
Perception is not limited to sentient animals (BGE 36): every power-
constellation perceives (PT, 96). Inorganic compounds, simple organisms,
plants, animals, and human beings all perceive. The regularity of interactions
among inorganic power-structures presupposes perception (PT, 92-1 02). The
capacity of protoplasm to assimilate and integrate other power-constellations is
a primitive kind of perception. (WP 500, 510) Plants also perceive the world
(PT, I 0 I, 102). The whole genealogical series of cognitive mechanisms operates
in animal and human perception (GS 54).
Perception and appearance supervene on the percussive and repercussive
cycle. The percussive radiation of the shockwave from each power-constellation
begins the act of perception. Insofar as it begins with the transmission of a
wave-front, perception is thus like sonar or radar. Perception is not passive
reception of sense data but rather the emission of a signal and consequent
interpretation of its reverberations. As they transmit their own shockwaves
proportional to their strength, other power-constellations act as mirrors
reflecting perspectivally modulated signals back to their origins.
Waves mirror waves, so that all things receive echoes of their original
transmissions. The strength of these echoes is proportional to the distance (GS
162; WP 637) so that spatial locality emerges in the holistic interplay of
wavefronts. Originally transmitted signals are modulated as they are ret1ected
by other power-constellations, and these modulations carry information. The
totality of reflected and modulated wavefronts is the appearance of the rest of
the world to each power-constellation (WP 567-569). Appearance is dynamic
(GS 54): it distributes information throughout the world.
The world as the reflections of all wave-fronts is the will prior to any
interpretation; it is "the formless unformulable world of the chaos of sensations"
(WP 569). Sensations are stimuli: sources of force differentials that need to be
integrated or assimilated (WP 499, 500, 510, 511, 521, 532; BGE 230) into
existing power-constellations. Perception ends with the assimilation of reflected
THE WILL TO POWER AND PDP SYSTEMS 317
wave-forms; it is a cooling down from the high point (hottest; the point at which
all transmitted wave-fronts bounce back) to the low point (coldest; all wave-
fronts assimilated). All power-constellations are defined by their exchanges of
appearances with one another and are thus not things-in-themselves but
perspectival effects on one another (WP 553-569). Here the informational
mechanics of the will to power are exactly analogous to those of Boltzmann or
harmony machines.
The will to power is a self-organizing chaos. 23 It is "a work of art that gives
birth to itself' (WP 796). Order (functional complexity as measured by
algorithmic compressibility or logical depth) 24 is not imposed from above or
outside in accordance with an eternal plan. 25 The world as will to power is a
work of art without an artist (WP 796), no Platonic Demiurge or Christian God
needed. Order emerges spontaneously in the will to power through the wave-
mechanical (percussive and repercussive) interactions of its centers of force.
The thermal information-processin~ activity of the will to power (its self-
interpretation) is self-organization?
Self-organization does not mean that chaos decreases as order increases; it
means that ever greater agility artistically orders ever greater turbulence
wherever the will to power is far from thermal equilibrium in its entropic cycle.
Self-organization as will to power produces forms (arrangements) of increasing
functional complexity. The notion of self-organization is a central PDP
concept. 27
The will to power organizes itself into a perspectival system of self-
reproducing power-constellations. Such patterns are pre-forms of life (BGE 36)
able to reconstitute their structures (but never their identities) over time. 28 All
enduring things, from quarks to quasars, are self-reproducing patterns. Accord-
ing to the eternal return (GS 109, 341; WP 1053-67), the whole universe is a
self-reproducing power-constellation. Organisms are the paradigms of such self-
reproducing power-constellations. (See WP 640-658.)
Self-reproducing patterns presuppose massively parallel media able to
support structures of high and increasing complexity. Self-reproducing patterns
have long been studied by PDP theorists? 9 The massively parallel computational
media used in the field of synthetic biology (artificial life) permit research into
many different models of biological and ecological processes. 30 Such PDP
systems are the laboratories in which to study Nietzsche's theories of life as will
to power (GS 349; BGE 13; WP 681, 691, 702, 704), in particular his theories
of organism-environment interaction (WP 499, 500, 510, 511, 521, 532, 655-
658), his theories of interactions in the organism (WP 660), and his anti-
Darwinian approaches to ecology and evolution (GS 349; TI IX:14; WP 647,
679-685).
Self-reproducing power-constellations do not just reproduce themselves; they
also evolve. But evolution requires continuity, and consequently requires the
repetition of a primitive past in a more sophisticated present. The past is
318 ERIC STEINHART
repeated in the present only insofar as the present preserves the past. Evolution
thus requires memory. (WP 646) Memory, like sensation, is active everywhere
in the series of types: memory operates in the inorganic (PT, 92-102); plants
have memory (PT, 97); animals and humans have memory as well. For
Nietzsche, memory is active. (See GS 54)
Memory is the power of the past to project an image of itself into the present
via the recognition of what it has in common with the present. (Cf. WP 499,
521; GS 114; BGE 230) The past assimilates the present to itself by reproducing
itself in the present, that is, by encoding itself within the present. 31 Each self-
reproducing pattern in the will to power contains a compressed description of
its history or genealogy (WP 682), as every living organism (a self-reproducing
pattern) contains a self-description in its DNA (its genotype). 32
At each moment, fading patterns in the will to power encode compressed
descriptions of themselves within emerging patterns. Such compressed
descriptions are memories, and the encoding of them and their relations with the
present is learning. In a PDP system, learning occurs through a change in
connection weights. Connectionists have constructed mnemonic networks in
which compressed descriptions are nested in other descriptions; such nets are
called recursive auto-associative memories. 33 Nietzschean memory acts in a
similar fashion.
CONCLUSION
NOTES
Unless otherwise indicated, all references to Nietzsche's works are by text and section number.
The texts arc Beyond Good and Evil (BGE), trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Random House,
1966); The Gay Science (GS), trans. W. Kaufmann (New York: Random House, 1974); The Will
to Power (WP). trans. W. Kaufmann & R. J. Hollingdalc (New York: Random House, 1968);
Twilight of the Idols (TI), trans. R. J. Hollingdale (New York: Penguin Books, 1984); Philosophy
and Truth (PT), trans. D. Breazeale (London: Humanities Press, 1979).
2 Many writings on the will to power are from the Nachlass. Scholars such as Kaufmann and
Magnus wish to devalue or discredit these notebooks; others, such as Danto and Moles. value them
as highly as the published writings. We side with Danto and Moles, for precisely the reasons
offered by Moles. See A. Moles, Nietzsche's Philosophy of Nature and Cosmology, (New York:
Peter Lang, 1990), Introduction, section II.
3 In doing this we need to be sensitive to Nietzsche's own philosophy of science. To this end we
are guided by B. Babich's Nietzsche's Philosophy of Science (Albany, NY: SUNY Press, 1994).
4 Here Nietzsche is inspired by R. J. Boscovich's A Theory of Natural Philosophy (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 1967/1763). See also G. Stack, "Nietzsche and Boscovich's Natural Philosophy,"
Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 62, 198 I, pp. 69-87; G. Whitlock, "Roger Boscovitch, Benedict
de Spinoza and Friedrich Nietzsche: The Untold Story," Nietzsche-Studien 25, 1996, pp. 200-220.
5 Such a statement is striking to ears acquainted with quantum physics. See Alistair Moles,
Nietzsche's Philosophy of Nature and Cosmology, p. xii. In it we find (however darkly guessed),
something very much like Bohm's notion of a particle and its pilot-wave. Nietzsche's entirely
holistic treatment of the will to power cannot but reinforce the relation to Bohm. See D. Bohm,
Wholeness and the Implicate Order (London: Routlege & Kegan Paul, 1980).
6 P. Umbanhowar, F. Melo, & H. Swinney, "Localized Excitations in a Vertically Vibrated
Granular Layer," Nature. Vol. 382 (29 August 1996), pp. 793-6.
7 PDP systems manifest deep holism, such as rearranging the parts in a whole without
decomposing the whole into its parts (i.e. rearranging the parts without manipulating the parts
themselves, but just the whole). See D. Blank, L. Meeden, and J. Marshal, "Exploring the
Symbolic/Subsymbolic Continuum: A Case study of RAAM," in J. Dinsmore (Ed.). The Symbolic
and Connectionist Paradigms: Closing the Gap (Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1992), pp. 113-
148. See especially sec. 6. and 6.2 for holistic transformations.
8 T. Horgan & J. Tienson, "Cognitive Systems as Dynamical Systems," Topoi 11(1), pp. 27-43.
THE WILL TO POWER AND PDP SYSTEMS 321
In thermodynamics, energy, entropy, and temperature are all carefully distinguished. For a very
readable and highly engaging introduction to thermodynamics, particularly the second law, see R.
Penrose, The Emporer's New Mind (New York: Penguin Books, 1991), ch. 7.
10 Nietzsche is explicit about the global thermal cycle in WTP 1067, describing the will to power
as alternating between hottest forms and coldest forms. The local cycle is not explicitly discussed,
but the cycle described in WTP 636 exactly parallels the global cycle described in WTP 1067.
11 For the relation of the eternal return to thermodynamics, see Moles, Nietzsche's Philosophy of
troughs and by global tidal flows and ebbs) in GS 310, whose title is "Will and Wave."
13 Supposing the Great Year of Zarathustra (Z III:l3/2) to have duration G, the global cycle is
sin(t/G) and the local cycle is sin(t) where tis (discrete) time.
14 W. Kaufmann, Nietzsche: Philosopher, Psychologist, Antichrist (Princeton, NJ: Princeton UP,
1974), p. 235.
15 In a tennis match, for instance, the play becomes hotter as the motion of the ball becomes more
chaotic and the players exercise more and more ordering power (i.e. skill) to keep the ball in play.
16 See W. H. Zurek (ed.) Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information. Santa Fe Institute
Studies in the Sciences of Complexity, Vol. VIII. (Redwood, CA: Addison-Wesley, 1990).
17 We emphatically do not want to understand the interpretive activity of the will to power in
Rumelhart & J. L. McClelland (eds.), Parallel Distributed Processing (Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press, 1986), Vol. I, ch. 7.
19 P. Smolensky, "Information Processing in Dynamical Systems: Foundations of Harmony
become stable; the system commits itself to decisions as it cools; it passes from fluid behavior to
the rigid adoption of an answer. The decision-making process resembles the crystallization of a
liquid into a solid" (Smolensky, ibid., vol. 1, ch. 6, p. 233).
23 In this respect Nietzsche's views anticipate the theories of I. Prigogine, winner of a Nobel Prize
in 1977 for his work on self-organizing systems. Prigogine contends that order emerges
spontaneously in systems far from thermal equilibrium. See I. Prigogine and I. Stengers, Order
out o.f Chaos: Man's New Dialogue with Nature (New York: Bantam, 1984). Note the reference
to Nietzsche on p. 136. See also J. Lothar, "Nietzsche: Dekonstruktionist oder Konstruktivist?,"
Nietzsche-Studien 23, 1994, pp. 226-240.
24 For algorithmic compressibility, see G. Chaitin, "Randomness and mathematical proof,"
Scientific American 232 (5), 1975, pp. 47-52. For logical depth and other definitions of
complexity, see C. H. Bennett, "How to define complexity in physics, and why," in W. H. Zurek
~ed.) Complexity, Entropy, and the Physics of Information, pp. 137-148.
5 This is perhaps the most important feature of Nietzshe's entire philosophy, yet commentators
still get it wrong. Consider R. H. Grimm, who says that form "is something imposed upon the
chaos of power-quanta ... ( ... analogous ... to the process whereby a potter may impose any form
he chooses on a formless lump of clay)" R. H. Grimm, Nietzsche's Theory of Knowledge, (Berlin:
Walter de Gruyter, 1977). Grimm's account is precisely what does not happen.
26 Jean Granier, "Nietzsche's Conception of Chaos," in The New Nietzsche, ed. David B. Allison
29 For self-reproducing patterns in PDP systems known as cellular automata, see: J. von
Neumann,Theory of Self-Reproducing Automata (Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press, 1966);
E. Codd,Cellular Automata (New York: Academic Press, 1968); C. Langton, "Self-reproduction
in cellular automata" Physica D 10, 1984, pp. 135-144; E. Berlekamp, J. Conway, & R.
Guy, Winning Ways (New York: Academic Press, 1982), vol. 2, ch. 25.
°
3 C. G. Langton (ed.) Artificial Life (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1995).
31 A pattern C(t) encodes itself within C(t+1), but then (C(t) encoded within C(t+1)) encodes itself
within C(t+2), and ((C(t) encoded within C(t+1)) encoded within C(t+2)) encodes itself within
C(t+3). Earlier organizations recursively nest themselves within later organizations. This nesting
structure is the genealogical structure of memory; it is the basis for the temporal order.
32 The point fits with Nietzsche's Lamarckian understanding of evolution.
33 J. Pollack, "Recursive distributed representations," Artificial Intelligence 46, 1994, pp. 77-105.
34 D. E. Rumelhart & J. L. McClelland, Parallel Distributed Processing (Cambridge, MA: MIT
This essay proceeds from the premise that mathematical concepts and relations
can be appropriated for the purpose of creating new modes of interpretation of
existing texts and phenomena. 1 More specifically, it brings together certain
aspects of fractal geometry and chaos theory to provide an interpretive frame for
the philosophical work of Friedrich Nietzsche. What follows from this concate-
nation is purely speculative, neither mathematical in its form and intent nor
exegetical in its reading of Nietzsche. There is no concerted attempt made here
to justify this method of interpretation in the context of Nietzsche's own
epistemological speculations. In fact such a task might well be quite difficult
given his criticisms of the mathematical project - its efforts to equalize and
make the same, its simplification of the tremendous complexity of the world,
and its democratic design to preserve life for its average and reactive aspects.
Rather if any justification is sought at all, it is from the results of this interpreta-
tion and whether or not it carries with it the spirit of Nietzsche's thought. What
follows then is the explication of a method of interpretation, and this is offered
under the auspices of Nietzsche's argument that if knowledge is always a means
to something, a means to the creation of certain effects, then "the most valuable
insights are methods."2
CHAOTIC DYNAMICS
treatment is such that any unaccounted for effects are kept within predictable
bounds, leaving the integrity of the analysis intact. However the inherent
instability of some nonlinear deterministic systems gives rise to unpredictable
behavior which cannot be neatly described by analytic approaches. While the
evolution of such "chaotic" systems is predictable in the sense of being confined
to a subset of state space called the "attractor," its position at any specific
moment can only be fathomed by allowing the system unfold numerically. The
instability of chaotic systems derives from the nonlinear interactions of their
components which amplify even slight perturbations into effects which
influence their macroscopic behavior. Given that the phenomena which chaotic
systems seek to model exist within an extended network of similar systems
which continually swap energy with their surroundings, there is a continual
source of effective randomness and innovation as adjacent systems feed into one
another to produce "self-organising" patterns of dynamic stability.
Despite the differences between chaotic and more stable systems, chaos
theory still retains the possibility that simple deterministic laws with probabilis-
tic outcomes may underlie complex phenomena that resist attempts to describe
them analytically. Nietzsche was critical of epistemological approaches of this
kind, arguing that they represent attempts by "man" to "find formulas so as to
simplify the tremendous quantity of his experiences" (WP 640). 3 However chaos
theory also posits the possibility that the world might be thought of as an
extended network of "individual" chaotic systems, each following their own
behavioural imperatives while interacting with one another in complex and
unpredictable ways. In acknowledging the relational character of phenomena
in this manner, chaos theory can be interpreted as providing an argument
against the search for immutable and universally applicable laws, with any
"law-like" behaviour operating within "individual" systems whose interactions
with one another would produce unpredictable effects incapable of analytic
treatment. In an analogous way, Nietzsche posits the existence of what he refers
to variously as "quanta," "quanta of force," "quanta of power," "quanta of will
to power" and "dynamic quanta," which do not follow laws but rather the
dictates of the "will to power" which operates through them. "If something
happens thus and thus and not otherwise, that does not imply a 'principle,'
'law,' 'order,' [but the operation of] quanta of force the essence of which
consists of exercising power against other quanta of force"(WP 689).
Nietzsche ascribed great significance to the will to power, describing it as
"the essence of life," 4 "the ultimate ground and character of all change" (WP
685), and even arguing that "[t]he world seen from within, the world described
and defined according to its 'intelligible character' -it would be 'will to power'
and nothing else." 5 Each quanta is therefore a particular expression of the will
to power, the phenomenal outgrowth of its drive to express its superfluity- not
as a law, but as a necessity, as "that which must overcome itself again and
again" 6 in its role as the iterative imperative or dynamic of quanta here
characterized as chaotic systems. Given that the will to power "can manifest
itself only against resistances" (WP 656), quanta necessarily exist "in a relation
of tension to all other dynamic quanta" (WP 635), forming a complex relational
THE FRACTAL DYNAMICS OF A NIETZSCHEAN WORLD 325
network in the same manner as extended chaotic systems. The iteration of the
will to power therefore takes place in as many sites as there are quanta,
operating not as a universal law but as an imperative which drives the dynamical
evolution of quanta in their multifarious manifestations.
Quanta exist by virtue of the effects they produce and that which they resist,
and so each quanta is a unique perspective towards the world by virtue of this
necessity to differentiate. Their essence therefore lies in their relations with all
other quanta, in the way they effect and are affected by all other expressions of
the will to power. Hence the world is no more and no less than a collective of
perspectives, wherein each "construes all the rest of the world from its own
viewpoint, i.e., measures, feels, forms, according to its own force" (WP 636).
However to describe a perspective or quanta as unique, as having its "own
viewpoint ... its own force" is to posit the existence of some sort of structure or
identity which both arises through the iteration of the will to power and enables
its expression. Nietzsche further desc1ibes the will to power as "not a being, not
a becoming, but a pathos - the most elemental fact from which a becoming and
effecting first emerge" (WP 635), and in this context we can interpret the
iteration of the will to power as an occasion or opportunity for the dynamism of
becoming and the structure of being to be expressed- not as mutually exclusive
but mutually dependent, each being the necessary condition for the other's
presence. An iteration of the will to power therefore presents for the world an
opening, and it is within this opening that perspectives or quanta arise, persist,
decay and perish.
The structure or identity of a perspective is the manifestation of its effort to
"impose upon becoming the character of being" what Nietzsche refers to as "the
supreme will to power" (WP 617). Perspectives therefore reproduce themselves
through a process which seeks to create a continuity of becoming from the
discontinuity of the will to power's iteration, while also using the "mask" of
being to cover the underlying multiplicity they have influence over. Becoming
might therefore be said to provide a sense of temporal continuity, while being
enforces a sense of spatial identity. 7 1be underlying multiplicity, both temporal
and spatial, is structured in a fractal manner, revealing a complex of perspec-
tives within perspectives. 8 Fractals are the result of an iterative dynamic
operating at an increasing number of scales to produce self-similar complex
structures with no inherent scale and infinite detail. In much the same manner,
the opportunities or openings that each iteration of the will to power presents for
the world arise within all perspectives, and so must be incorporated into their
structure if they are to retain their identity. The apparent unity of a perspective
is therefore a "unity only as organisation and co-operation ... as a pattern of
domination that signifies a unity but is not a unity" (WP 561). The "pattern of
domination" that characterizes a perspective extends as far as spheres of
influence of adjacent perspectives on the same fractal scale of organization,
while also extending within to structure its constituent perspectives. These in
turn cooperate to varying degrees in the formation of the organizational unity
of the "higher order" perspective, while simultaneously seeking to maintain and
further their own influence. The sphere of influence of a perspective therefore
326 PETER DOUGLAS
extends as far as the imposition of its structure, and this is achieved through the
"appropriation and assimilation" of other perspectives which become its
constituents. Nietzsche explains this process as "above all a desire to over-
whelm, a forming, shaping and reshaping, until at length that which has been
overwhelmed has entirely gone over into the power domain of the aggressor and
has increased the same" (WP 656). The structure of a perspective is never
completely stable then, as it is "continually growing or periodically increasing
and decreasing according to the favourability or unfavourability of circum-
stances" (WP 715) as it strives to maintain and extend its sphere of influence.
All change must therefore be understood "as the encroachment of one power
upon another power" (WP 689) as perpsectives are strengthened, modified or
overwhelmed in the incessant interactions that take place between perspectives
under the iterative imperative of the will to power.
As well as the fractal complexity of the inner structure of perspectives, the
surfaces or boundaries between perspectives are also fractal, purveying an
intricate and dynamic complexity across all scales of interaction. 9 These fractal
surfaces are formed by the incessant struggle for influence and dominion
between perspectives that is the process of interpretation; for as Nietzsche
argues, "interpretation is itself a means of becoming master of something" and
it is the will to power that interprets: that is, "it defines limits, determines
degrees, variations of power" (WP 643) as manifest in the structure of perspec-
tives. Interpretation is therefore the process that the will to power initiates
through its iteration, being and becoming are the dual aspects of its operation
as we understand it, and perspectives are the structural manifestation of its
activity. The characteristic structure of a perspective therefore represents a
particular interpretation, and the characteristics manifested are derived in
relation to adjacent perspectives and the necessity to differentiate to exist.
The process of interpretation involves either the assimilation or appropriation
of one perspective by another through the reinterpretation of a previous
structure, or the incorporation into an existing perspective of a fresh opening
onto the world as brought about by the most recent iteration of the will to
power. While the latter always entails the imposition of structure by a higher
order perspective on its constituents, the former may occur either across the
same fractal scale as the overpowering of a contemporary, or as a "revolution
from within" between different levels of organization as a constituent perspec-
tive expands its own sphere of influence "upwards" to overpower a higher order
structure and either diminish or completely dispel its dominion. The structural
transformations caused by reinterpretions may be sudden: immediately
obscuring the structures of the previous interpretation; or more gradual:
beginning with a change in "meaning" which, if imposed unchallenged for long
enough, eventually becomes part of the core structure of a perspective such that
it is considered to be part of its "nature" - what seems unchangeable and
enduring.
The incessant interpretive struggles that form the fractal surfaces between
perspectives provides what might be referred to as the sensory data that a
perspective organizes according to its characteristic structure. Given the
THE FRACTAL DYNAMICS OF A NIETZSCHEAN WORLD 327
Will to truth is a making firm, a making true and durable, an abolition of the false character of
things, a reinterpretation of it into beings. "Truth" is therefore not something there, that might be
found or discovered- but something that must be created and that gives a name to a process, or
rather to a will to overcome that has in itself no end - introducing truth, as a processus in
infinitum, an active determining- not a becoming-conscious of something that is itself firm and
determined. It is a word for the "will to power." (WP 552)
The more powerful a perspective's will to truth, the greater its capacity to
impose being upon becoming and so the more stable its structure. However the
stability imposed by the will to truth inhibits the dynamism of becoming, and
this is essential for a perspective's struggle to expand its sphere of influence.
There is always a tension, therefore, between stability and dynamism- between
the imposition of being which strives to preserve, and the dynamism of
becoming which seeks expansion and growth.
through, and so is part of the same process and serves the same purpose as the
phenomenal manifestations of a perspective. Just as phenomenal manifestations
have been described as a self-referential horizon then, knowledge is as
Nietzsche suggested "a referring back: in its essence a regressus in infinitum"
(WP 575) which deals only with things of its own making. "We operate only
with things that do not exists: lines, planes, bodies, atoms, divisible time spans,
divisible space. How should explanations be at all possible when we first turn
everything into an image, our image:!" (GS 112). 11
However within the frame provided by this interpretation of Nietzsche's
work, even the understanding of our own "image" gives us some understanding
of the processes we are and the encompassing perspective we partly constitute.
So a system of knowledge such as mathematics which this interpretation takes
as its starting point enables us "to determine our human relations to things" and
is for Nietzsche a "means for general and ultimate knowledge of man" (GS
246). This knowledge is part of the structure of what we are as the epi-
phenomena of interpretive processes beyond our phenomenal experiences, and
so mathematics might be said to provide some insight into these structures.
However as a particularly systematic and rigorous form of knowledge, it can
also be argued that mathematics is a strategy which aims to "fix" the world into
a more coherent and orderly structure, and that the more we use mathematics in
order to "know" the world, the more stable and mathematical the world we seek
to know becomes. In other words mathematics in part constitutes the orderly
world it seeks to understand.
While it has been argued so far that knowledge is an attempt to stabilize the
structure of a perspective under the impetus of the will to truth's drive to impose
being upon becoming, it must also remembered that the fundamental imperative
of the will to power is not self-preservation but self-overcoming. This aspect is
embodied in the notion of becoming which strives for fluidity and dynamism
rather than the stability of being. So while this tension between being and
becoming - stability and dynamism-- set the necessity conditions of the will to
power's manifestations, it is also the guarantee of their eventual demise as the
drive for self-overcoming leads inevitably towards the nihilistic self-destruction
of all perspectives. Nietzsche strove to come to terms with this tension in his
philosophy, endeavouring to reveal a world of becoming while acknowledging
that "knowledge is possible only on the basis of belief in being" (WP 518). The
compromise is always between a stability within which coherent and universal
claims to knowledge are validated, and a fluidity which denies such foundations
by acknowledging the shifting process of becoming which being masks.
However given the prevailing tendency towards stability, Nietzsche took it upon
himself to emphasize the possibilities of fluidity, openness and new possibilities
for knowledge: "There are many souls one will never uncover, unless one
invents them first." 12 His fundamental notion of the will to power does not
legislate form and meaning then, but attempts to break open the horizon created
by knowledge into a proliferation of chance relationships which have a different
appearance from every perspective.
330 PETER DOUGLAS
Bringing Nietzsche's work together with fractal geometry and chaos theory
seeks to provide a structural basis for his thought without foreclosing on the
dynamism required for the creation of new possibilities from existing condi-
tions. The emphasis from chaos theory has provided the possibility of unpredict-
able and novel conditions arising from the interaction of dynamic systems
driven by localized functions, while the emphasis from fractal geometry has
stressed the rich and intricate possibilities of structures which offer an inex-
haustible font of detail. The aim is to explore the possibilities of forms of
knowledge which expand the world rather than foreclosing on its possibilities
in the vein of Nietzsche's own project: "But one thing is certain: you will never
travel around the world (which you yourself are!) but will remain an impenetra-
ble enigma to yourselves!" 13 as knowledge in part creates the world we seek to
know, and so new knowledge allows us to create new worlds.
NOTES
1 This essay is an abbreviated and revised version of my "Nietzschean Geometry," SubStance
81 (1996) 132-152.
2 Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (London: Penguin Books,
1990), p. 135.
3 Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann & R. J. Hollingdale (New
York: Vintage Books, 1968). Subsequent citations are listed in the text followed by section
numbers. For a concordance to the German critical editions, see S. Simmons, "Concordance
Indexing The Will to Power with the Notebooks and the Critical German Editions," New Nietzsche
Studies, I (1996) 1/2:126-153.
4 Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vintage
Books, 1969), p. 79.
5 Friedrich Nietzsche, Beyond Good and Evil, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (London: Penguin Books,
1990), p. 67.
6 Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (London: Penguin Books,
1969), p. 138.
7 This process does not so much take place in space and time as it is constitutive of space and
time in a manner similar to that developed in the philosophical work of Alfred North Whitehead.
8 The fractal structure of perspectives might be likened to the Cantor set, a self-identicallinear
fractal constructed by removing the middle third of a solid line in an infinite series of iterations.
The internal structure of any line segment is revealed upon closer inspection (or magnification)
to be identical to that of the collection of line segments it is associated with. No matter the scale
of inspection then, the identical structure is revealed.
9 What is envisaged here is somewhat similar to the Koch curve. If we take a line segment and
raise an equilateral triangle over its middle third and then repeat this process on each subsequent
line segment ad infinitum, the result is a curve of infinite detail and length. As with the Cantor set,
closer inspection on any scale reveals the identical structure as the original, and so any measure
of its length is dependent upon an arbitaray choice as to the scale of inquiry.
10 See Crutchfield, J. P., Farmer, J. D., Packard, H., & Shaw, R. S. "Chaos," Scientific American,
The modern philosophers, "are these still human beings, one then
asks oneself, or only machines that think, write and talk"?
- Friedrich Nietzsche
the origin of historical education [Bildung] ... must itself in turn be historically understood, history
must itself dissolve the problem of history, knowledge must tum its sting against itself- this
threefold must is the imperative of the spirit of the "new age", if it really does contain something
new, mighty, original and a promise of life.'
331
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Episterrwlogy, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 331-339.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
332 ULLRICH MICHAEL HAASE
taken in its ambiguity, between that which is traditionally called the truth of
being, that is, the identification of truth with being -a conception that cannot
simply be changed nominally- and that which now appears as the truth, namely
that there is no truth; in other words, that being, that which alone can be true, is
only an illusion. And yet, this truth cannot even be said, or rather, its being said
should change the whole framework of thinking, so that it can approach the
knowledge that there is only becoming. The first understanding of truth has,
since Plato, been determined through the notion of death, and hence resists
incorporation, while the second cannot even be incorporated as a truth, since it
signifies the dispersal of existence.
What are we to do with this impossible necessity of truth? While Nietzsche's
point does not necessarily imply that we are confined to Kant's "Island of
Reason," it does mean that we have to take the question of the essence of know-
ledge more seriously than before, where "serious" implies that the question of
knowledge can no longer be restricted to a position of conscious standpoints,
nor appear to consciousness in the form of a systematic propositional structure.
Instead of simply ignoring the question of the identity necessary for any under-
standing - by claiming, for example, that all interpretations are valid, while
some are better than others - it shall be "our serious striving to understand
everything as becoming, to deny our being as individuals, possibly to look into
the world with many eyes, to live in drives and our daily occupations, in order
to make oneself some eyes from it, to give oneself temporarily over to life, in
order then to rest temporarily with the eye above life."
From here my claim should become clearer, in that it is the three writings
here in question, which offer themselves to be counted for the first of these
periods, while in the Zarathustra an essential attempt is made to rest with the eye
above life. What does not change in the move of these different stances of the
philosopher, is the attempt to make an experiment with truth - and hence an
attempt at a critique of truth in the sense of bringing it to appearance in its own
crisis -while in each case the question remains, what kind of experiment applies
to which understanding of truth: the question being whether the experimental
character of Nietzsche's thinking, a thinking whose sense for truth restricts itself
"temporarily" to experiment, 4 gives way to an apology of the unrestricted reign
of the techno-sciences, as the twentieth century has experienced it, or if the aim
of Nietzsche's affirmations consists in instituting work-shops for the struggle
against our present age. 5 At least it should be clear that, in order eventually to
leave nihilism behind, in order to find one's way back to something, 6 it will be
necessary to surmount the state of "mere" experimentation.
If the task of philosophy can be described as pushing its time to the point of
crisis, then this crisis- from the early 1880's up to the end of the twentieth
century and beyond- will turn around the question of technology, as it is here
that the central philosophical question of the unity of necessity and freedom
finds itself so clearly set apart and counterpoised, that what are differentials can
appear as opponents, taking as their battle field the essence of the human being.
In other words, the age of technology brings into the open the crux of modernity
in its separation between inside and outside, this non-culture and non-science,
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TECHNOLOGY 333
hence places the very possibility of the existence of consciousness in the world
under scrutiny.
The paradox of conscious existence consists in the fact that consciousness can
only reassure itself through its very acts, while the existing act does not point
back at consciousness as its cause. While the Christian world has always
promised its intelligibility by way of the creation of a God who, in its turn,
creates in the same way as we produce, so that we could understand the world
by analogy with our actions, it is precisely insofar as we act, that we cannot
understand ourselves. In the creative act mankind transcends itself, in that the
human being becomes natura naturans, 13 nature itself, insofar as she is active.
Consequently, the human being cannot contain its being by means of a
subjection to the divine.
And yet, insofar as freedom can only be determined in relation to knowledge,
a freedom that cannot be known is no freedom at all. Or, insofar as the under-
standing, by its very nature, tends towards the ideal of mechanism, the only way
that it can take hold of freedom is by reconciling it with necessity. The first step
of this reconciliation then consists of its negation: "everything here is necessary,
every motion mathematically calculable .... The actor's deception regarding
himself, the assumption of free-will, is itself part of this calculable mecha-
nism."14 While giving itself over to life, the actor shall give up the illusion of
freedom precisely to become a free spirit, that is, freed through the teaching of
absolute irresponsibility. 15
But through the very assumption of a universal mechanism, following from
an observation of life, mechanism itself has been proven wrong, as Nietzsche
argues, 16 once the moment has been reached at which it is necessary to rest with
the eye above life. While this moment presents itself, in abstraction, as a move
transcending life, and hence as a move towards idealism - it does so only if
posited as a theoretical standpoint. What remains is the insight into the impos-
sibility to explain human action through conscious deliberation, that is, through
a falsified will. That technology cannot be countered consciously - not even
through a dream of the automatic unconscious -, this would be the significance
of our experiment with truth: namely, following Heidegger's words, to realise
that the universality of technology, as the reduction of truth to the unconcealed-
ness of that which has been "stocked up" [ Unverborgenheit des Bestandes], 17
has to be willed, so that the will itself runs out of steam. This turning of the will
against itself, this esoteric insight, that "there is no such thing as a will," 18 which
could transcend life and hence determine itself, according to Descartes, as
divine, is the second step towards the liberation of freedom from the will.
It is hence not very difficult to jump from that premise towards the idea of
technology as that which finally frees the human being from itself, by freeing
it from the illusion of its free will. And yet, according to Nietzsche one can
already see that the way this is done, namely through the explicit denial of free
will, falls short of fulfilling the task as radical as necessary, namely by laying
the ideal calmly on ice. 19 If it was the case that the fundamental character of the
world were, in all eternity, mechanism, then one should easily be able to
understand why "it is not that the machine will replace the human being: it is the
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TECHNOLOGY 335
human being that has supplemented, up to the industrial revolution, the absence
of machines." 20 In a way it is quite uncanny how the will to truth, reaching the
point where it can no longer be incorporated by the human stomach, abolishes
the latter, accompanied by the cheery affirmation of the stomach's bearer. The
human being has suffered enough, and, as it suffers from indigestion, it turns
with ressentiment against its very stomach, affirming with all glory that the need
for nourishment has been overcome, that nature has finally played her part -
attempting, as a true follower of the Nietzschean spirit, to help the weak and ill-
.
constitute d to pens
. h .21
And yet, having established that it is an illness of the stomach that has been
diagnosed, one could as well have accepted the warning that all this reasoning
might constitute a huge misunderstanding. The first misunderstanding concerns
the right with which this "materialism" does claim Nietzsche as its predecessor;
the second, and more serious, concerns a misunderstanding as well about
Nietzsche's exposition of affirmation as an antidote to the idealised concept of
negation, as of the essence of the age of technology. And it does not help in this
respect, if one tries to cover over this misunderstanding by the explicit interdic-
tion of any critical distancing from the development of technology, as expressed
by Bernard Stiegler in the following way: "the reactions provoked by the
techno-scientific revolutions, might they be immediate, or mediate and
mediated, 'epidermal' or calculated, are the real danger and have to be over-
.
come 1mperat1 .ve1y. ,22
The philosophical climate is already heated up: every questioning attitude
towards technology is understood as romantic and dangerous. Every critique of
our age, which does not affirm its height, as it goes pregnant with colourful
possibilities of an inhuman future, will be happily and laughingly denounced as
melancholy, and hence as an illness. As Freud has complained about the lie with
which children are educated - that is, not being made aware of the brutal nature
of reality - here the attitude of encouragement to understand the facts of life,
which demand that one adapt oneself or that one perish, presupposes that one
has already understood, or, rather, is designed so as to avoid the question for the
nature of the age of technology. One is asked to make one's choice while the
cards are already dealt. What is interesting regarding this forced affirmation of
technology, this mistaken identification of affirmation with acquiescence -
ending in a perverted Hegelianism, in so far as it affirms its self-effacement in
the face of the real - is its motivation. This motivation is, as I have claimed
above, idealistic in essence. The age of technology, as the unconditional reign
of cybernetics, is the realisation of idealism especially in its Christian mission
against nature and history.
Even if the attempt is made to escape this mission through the detennination
of technical organisation as neither mechanic nor organic, what remains is
precisely this hidden objectivity, that takes the world as a whole as its object,
representing it independently from the human being and independently from its
time. It is such a view which first of all makes it possible to characterise the age
of the human as supplementing the absence of machines.
336 ULLRICH MICHAEL HAASE
And yet, does not this idea of a neither mechanic nor organic organisation
derive from Nietzsche, who argues in section 109 of the Gay Science that one
shall not call the universe an organism- since an organism is dependent on that
on which it feeds - while the idea of a universal mechanism is equally de-
throned? However, to make such an insight into a positive and affirmative
theory presupposes in its turn an eternalised and thus Christian idea of truth. As
such it misses the centre of philosophy, in that it only knows either necessity or
freedom. Furthermore, this idea derives itself from the existence of organisms
and their fallacies, insofar as "it is from the period of the lower organisms that
man has inherited the belief that there are identical things.'m
This misunderstanding as to the historial nature of the real - and conse-
quently as well the failure to grasp the utmost importance of all our knowledge
for the future - engenders itself through the repetition of just this trait of
philosophy, that it thinks that thinking itself has to have a disregard of history,
especially insofar as history seems to place too much emphasis on the ailings of
a human being, overestimating the importance of its existence. The hypothe-
sized universality of technology and the "machinic," their absolute rights against
a human being which has to be humanistic in order to will its survival, reduces
history to the poetical chemistry of mechanic couplings, which is supposed to
account for the passing of centuries. As if we had only to remove the riddle of
the human being from history in order to acquire an objective stance deprived
of its reason.Z4 This objectivity then asks, if from a different perspective, the
central question of idealism: "what remains of the world, after one has cut one's
head off?" 25 Here one strives from a blindness to being into the direction of a
blindness towards history- in Nietzsche's words: a blindness towards the whole
of reality. In this installation of technology, furthered and demanded by those
acolytes of its prolific qualities, the discourse on technology acquires its
tautological grounding. In the same way as the modern natural sciences had
attempted to turn their practise of truth into the presupposition of all knowledge
generally, so as to make a historical discourse on science meaningless, the
discourse on technology attempts to make an argument out of its success. It is
in this discourse that we can find a symptom of the phenomenon of technology,
which, as the will to will, is itself the tendency towards the un-historical.
Consequently it remains possible to think technology as fulfilled metaphysics?6
If the conjunction of science and technology is understood as the foundational
character of modernity, then it does not only become obvious that in fact the
conception of ;;e xvrt is a necessary condition of the ascent of metaphysics, but
furthermore, that the whole discourse of the human being, which temporarily
supplements for the absence of machines, goes back to Descartes. The materia-
lism that ensues from the Cartesian position is hence the consequence of the
belief that one can leave the dualism behind, by making a decision for one of the
two sides. And, as one would rather become a machine than having one's head
cut off, the decision appears not to be that difficult.
Maurice Merleau-Ponty has already warned us of the logic that employs itself
in this dialectic of objectivity leading from the natural sciences to the "ma-
chinic" sciences:
NIETZSCHE'S CRITIQUE OF TECHNOLOGY 337
Thus science began by excluding all the predicates that come to the things from our encounter with
them. The exclusion is however only provisional: when it will have learned to invest it, science
will little by little reintroduce what it first put aside as subjective; .... Then the world will close in
over itself, and, except for what within us thinks and builds science, ... , we will have become parts
or moments of the Great Object. 27
In order to be able to understand the logic that moves us from the natural
sciences to the machine-sciences and from the humanities to journalism, as
Heidegger puts it, 28 it is helpful to note that Leibniz has supplied a decisive
stepping stone for this development of scientific thought, precisely in his
argument against those philosophers, who are too materialistic. That the logical
foundation of the freedom of the soul in its self-determination gives rise to the
infinitely machinistic character of the world, grounds - once stripped of the
teleological character of Leibniz' philosophy- the development, at the end of
which the voluntarism of modern philosophy will have been transformed into
the will to power as technology. 29
On the one hand, there is no sense in denying this development, all that I am
concerned with here, is Nietzsche's attempt to think the necessity of the techno-
logisation of modern culture, and the need to persist throughout this fate by
means of an experiment that will eventually exhaust its historial power and lead
back to "some-thing." It is in this respect, that Nietzsche's words of experi-
mentation and function can be understood as a prolegomena to the concept of
technology. In the happiness and the forced nature of the analyses of technology
that demand our approval, on the other hand, one can discern, not only the spell
cast by the natural sciences, which have been taken in by the concept of pure
apperception, 30 and which reach this purity precisely through conjuring up the
dissolution of the human being in a technologically understood reality, but also
Heidegger' s analysis of the forgetfulness of being:
:n:otY)OL£- 'te)CVY). Where do machinations (die Machenschaft) lead us? To experience. How does
this happen? (Ens creatum- modern nature and history- technology) through the profanation
[Entzauberung] of that which is, a profanation which hands power over to a cast spelled by itself.
Bewitchment and experience.
The perennial reinforcement of the desolation of Being in the forgetfulness of Being. 31
***
One of the first points of reservation against a reading of Nietzsche as given
above, will be that it attempts to unify his thought. If he intended it to be unified
in such a way, then he would easily have been able to say that which we make
him say. And yet, on the level of our interpretation, while we might say less
than that what Nietzsche had to say, we still say more than that what we would
have been able to say, if we had suspended all difficulties by simply claiming
that Nietzsche's truth is multiple. Taken from this stance, the placid affirmers
of Nietzsche's multiplicities proliferate bad philology and a nihilism, which is
riddled by such fear of a misunderstood truth, that it hardly dares to open its
mouth. Whoever is of the opinion that it would be enough simply to deny the
conception of identity, has not yet understood much about the necessities of
thinking, and will consequently always be too occupied with the word "being"
338 ULLRICH MICHAEL HAASE
than having any other choice left but to deny the phenomenon. Whoever tries
to give up on retracing the movement of Nietzsche's thought in its coherency,
will always remain lost in a muddle, which will once affirm that the will can
only be found in intelligent creatures, 32 who will then say that there is no will
at all, and finally come to the conclusion that all is will against will.
The claim ensuing from the threefold "must," in the course of which the
thought of the Eternal Return of the Same will have accomplished the move-
ment of knowledge turning its sting against itself, hence aims at an actualisation
of the difference between freedom and necessity, in a way which for some might
sound more humanistic than open to the boundless challenge of Cybernetics.
While the thought of the Eternal Return of the Same has to remain small and
powerless for millennia, finally it will lead to the realization of the "infinite
importance of our knowledge, our errors, our habits, and our ways of life for all
that is to come." 33 The promise given by this age of thought, named as there-
naturalisation of the human being, will hence lead us away from any idealism
of number, away from a mathematically determined space, in which reality does
not even appear as a problem34 - which was, after all, precisely its promise -
towards a new and old reality:
What we have won back for ourselves today with an unspeakable amount of self-constraint- the
free view of reality, the cautious hand, patience and seriousness in the smallest things, the whole
integrity of knowledge- was already there! Already more than two millennia ago! And good and
delicate taste and tact! ... as body, as gesture, as instinct- in a word, as reality ... 35
NOTES
1 Friedrich Nietzsche, "Vom Nutzen und Nachtheil der Historie fiir das Leben," Kritische
Studienausgabe, (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1967-77 and 1988), 1, 306; English translation by
Peter Preuss: On the Advantage and Disadvantage of History for Life, (Indianapolis: Hackett,
1980), p. 45.
2 Ibid., KSA 1, 272; English translation: p. 23.
3 Friedrich Nietzsche, NachlajJ, V 11 [141], KSA 9, 494 ff.
4 Cf., Nietzsche, Die frohliche Wissenschaft, § 51, KSA 3, 416, trans. W. Kaufman, The Gay
Science, (New York: Vintage, 1974), p. 115.
5 Nietzsche, NachlajJ, III 8 [104], KSA 7, 262, "Werkstatten des Kampfes gegen die Gegenwart."
6 Cf., Nietzsche, Siimtliche Briefe: Kritische Studienausgabe, (Berlin: de Gruyter, 1975-1984),
~uoted as KSB, followed by volume/page numbers, KSB 8/81.
Cf., Nietzsche, Menschliches, Allzumenschliches, I§ 157, KSA 2, 148; trans. R. J. Hollingdale,
Human, All Too Human, (Cambridge, New York and Melbourne: Cambridge University Press,
1986), p. 84.
8 Compare the Rundgesang- in its varying names -at the end of the last but one section of Also
Sprach Zarathustra, KSA 4, 404; Thus Spoke Zarathustra, trans. R.J. Hollindale, (London:
Penguin, 1969), p. 333.
9 Diefrohliche Wissenschaft, § 109, KSA 3, 469, The Gay Science, p. 169; translation modified.
10 Ibid., § 125, "Der Tolle Mensch"; Nietzsche here conjures up the image of contemporary
culture, where everybody always already knows everything, without having understood much.
11 NachlajJ, III 29 [20], KSA 7, 633
12 Nach/ajJ, V 11 [162], KSA 9, 503.
13 Cf.: Vom Nutzen und Nachtheil ... , § 8, KSA 1, 310; On the Advantage ... , p. 48.
14 Menschliches, Allzumenschliches, I§ 106, KSA 2, 103; Human, All Too Human, p. 57,
point about this statement is, that it appears as point 2, following on "1. - everything is will against
will": the whole note bears the title: "Exoteric- esoteric."
19 Cf.: Ecce Homo, KSA 6, 321 ff.
20 Bernard Stiegler, La technique et le temps, vol. 1, (Paris: Galilee, 1994), p. 82.
21 Cf., Nietzsche, Der Antichrist, § 2, KSA 6, 170.
22 Quotation taken from the back-cover of Stiegler, La technique et le temps.
23 Nietzsche, Menschliches, Allzumenschliches, I§ 18; Human, All To Human, p. 21.
24 And yet, the reason of objectivity, namely the promise of communication, does still support the
dream of technology and its metaphorics of free flows.
25 Cf.. Nietzsche, Menschliches, Allzumenschliches, I§ 9, KSA 2, 29.
26 Cf., Heidegger, "i.iberwindung der Metaphysik," in: Vortriige und Aufsiitze, (Pfullingen: Neske,
and the Invisible, trans. Alphonso Lingis, (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1968), p. 15.
28 Cf., Heidegger, Beitriige zur Philosophie, (Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann, 1989), p. 158.
29 While reminding us of the etymology of the word "machine," which derives from machina,
1-llJXIiVl], ~-tT\XO£, which in tum goes back to the sanscrit mah, to prepare, to grow, magham,
rcower, and to the Gothic mag, "I can," and mahts, power.
0 Nietzsche, NachlajJ, VII 26 [413], KSA 11, 262.
31 Heidegger, Beitriige ... , §50, p. 107; ":rtotl]OL£ --cexvlJ. Wohin fiihrt die Machenschaft? Zum
Erlebnis. Wie geschieht das? (Ens creatum- die neuzeitliche Natur und Geschichte- die Technik)
Durch die Entzauberung des Seienden, die einer durch sie selbst vollzogenen Verzauberung die
Macht einriiumt. Verzauberung und Erlebnis. Die endgiiltige Verfestigung der Seinsverlassenbeit
in der Seinsvergessenheit."
32 Cf.: Nietzsche, Diefrohliche Wissenschaft, § 127, KSA 3, 483.
33 NachlajJ, V 11 [141], KSA 9, 494ff: "Das neue Schwergewicht: die ewige Wiederkunft des
Philosophy," § 3, p. 46.
35 Nietzsche, Der Antichrist, § 59, KSA 6/248
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
341
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 341-358.
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
342 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
--"Nietzsche and Freud, Or: How to Be Within Philosophy While Criticizing it From Without."
Jacob Golomb eta!., eds., Nietzsche and Depth Psychology." Albany. SUNY. 171-203.
Boning, Thomas. Metaphysik, Kunst und Sprache beim friihen Nietzsche. Berlin. Walter de
Gruyter. 1988.
- - "Das Buch eines Musikers ist eben nicht das Buch eines Augenmenschen. Metaphysik und
Sprache beim friihen Nietzsche." Nietzsche-Studien. 15 (1986): 72-106.
Bolz, Norbert W. "Von Nietzsche zu Freud: Sympathy for the Devil." Norbert Bolz & Wolfgang
Hiibner, eds., Spiegel und Gleichnis. Festschrift fiir Jacob Taubes. Wiirzburg: Konigshausen
& Neumann. 1983. 388-403.
- - "Nietzsches Genealogie der Wissenschaften." Literaturmagazin 12 Sonderband Nietzsche.
Hamburg. Rohwohlt. 1980. 262-286.
--Booth, David. Nietzsche's 'Woman' Rhetoric: How Nietzsche's Misogyny Curtails his
Critique of Metaphsyics." History of Philosophy Quarterly. 8/3 (1991): 311-325.
Borsche, Tilman. Was etwas ist. Fragen nach der Wahrheit der Bedeutung bei Platon, Augustin,
Nikolaus von Kues und Nietzsche. Munich. Fink. 1990.
- - "The Epistemological Shift from Descartes to Newton: Intuition and Imagination." In
Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 51-66.
Borsche, T., F. Gerratana and A. Venturelli, eds., "Centauren-Geburten ". Wissenschaft, Kunst und
Philosophie beimjungen Nietzsche. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1994.
Boudot, Pierre. L'ontologie de Nietzsche. Paris. Presses Universitaires de France. 1971.
Bougas, Tassos. Nietzsche und die Verweltlichung der Welt. Mihailo Djuric and Josef Simon, eds.
Zur Aktualitiit Nietzsches. Wiirzburg. Konigshausen & Neumann. 1984. 29-44.
- - Brusotti, Marco. Die Leidenschaft der Erkenntnis: Philosophie und iisthetische Lebens-
gestaltung bei Nietzsche von Morgenrothe bis Also Sprach Zarathustra. Berlin. Walter de
Gruyter. 1997.
Boyer, Alain, "Hierarchy and Truth." Luc Ferry and Alain Renaut, eds., Why We are Not
Nietzscheans. Chicago. University of Chicago Press. 1997. 1-20.
Breazeale, Daniel. Towards A Nihilist Epistemalogy: Hume and Nietzsche. Yale University. Diss.
1971.
--"The Word, the World, and Nietzsche." Philosophical Forum. 6-213 (1975): 301-320.
--"Aground on the Ground of Values: Friedrich Nietzsche." A-T. Tymieniecka & C. 0. Schrag,
eds., Analecta Husserliana. XV. Dordrecht. Kluwer. 1983. 335-349.
--"The Hegel-Nietzsche Problem." Nietzsche-Studien. 4 (1975): 146-164.
Brown, RichardS. G. "Does the 'True World' Not Remain a Fable?" Goicoechea. ed., The Great
Year of Zarathustra. 39-52.
Bruder, Kennenth. "Necessity and Becoming in Nietzsche." Journal of the British Society for
Phenomenology. 14/3 ( 1983): 225-239.
Brusotti, Marco. Die Leidenschaft der Erkenntnis: Philosophie und iisthetische Lebensgestaltung
bei Nietzsche von Morgenrothe bis Also Sprach Zarathustra. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1997.
Buchanan, James. "Pathological Forms of the Will to Power." Philosophy Today. 27: (1983): 52ff.
Burney-Davis, Terri and E. Stephen Krebs. "The 'Vita Femina' and Truth." History of European
Ideas. 11 (1989): 841-47.
Call, Lewis, "Anti-Darwin, Anti-Spencer: Friedrich Nietzsche's Critique of Darwin and
'Darwinism'." History of Science. XXVI (1998): 1-22.
Canning, Peter. "How the Fable Becomes a World." Lawrence A. Rickels, ed., Looking After
Nietzsche. Albany. SUNY Press. 1990. 175-193.
Capek, Milic. "The Theory of Eternal Recurrence in Modem Philosophy of Science, with Special
Reference to C.S. Peirce." Journal of Philosophy. 57 (1960): 289-96. See also Bas van Fraas-
sen.
--"Eternal Recurrence," in Paul Edwards, ed., The Encyclopedia of Philosophy. New York:
The Macmillan Company and The Free Press, 1967. Vol. 3. 61-63.
--"Eternal Recurrence- Once More." Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society. 19 (1983),
141-53. [Reprinted: Capek. The New Aspects of Time. Dordrecht. Kluwer. 1991. 265-77.]
Caputo, John. '"Supposing Truth To Be a Woman': Heidegger, Nietzsche, Derrida." Tulane
Studies in Philosophy. 32. (1984): 15-21.
344 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
Gebhard, Walter. Der Zusammenhang der Dinge: Weltgleichnis und Naturglaube im Totalitiits-
bewusstsein des 19. Jahrhunderts. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1983.
- - (ed.), Friedrich Nietzsche. Strukturen der Negativitiit. Bern. Peter Lang. 1984.
- - "Erkennen und Entsetzen. Zur Tradition der Chaos-Annahmen im Denken Nietzsches."
Friedrich Nietzsche. Strukturen der Negativitiit. 13-47.
- - (ed.) Friedrich Nietzsche: Perspectivitiit und Tiefe. Bern. Peter Lang. 1982
- - "Zur Gleichnissprache Nietzsches. Problem der Bildlichkeit und Wissenschaftlichkeit."
Nietzsche-Studien. 9 (1980): 61-90.
Gemes, Ken. "Nietzsche's Critique of Truth." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 52/1
(1992): 47-65.
Gerhardt, Volker. Pathos und Distanz: Studien zur Philosophie Friedrich Nietzsches. Stuttgart.
Reclam. 1988.
- - "Artisten-Metaphysik." Djuric and Simon, eds., Zur Aktualitiit Nietzsches. 81-98.
Gillespie, Michael Allen & Tracy B. Strong, eds., Nietzsche's New Seas: Explorations in
Philosophy, Aesthetics, and Politics. Chicago. University of Chicago Press. 1988.
Goldman, Harvey S. "Weber's Ascetic Practices of the Self." Hartmut Lehmann and Guenther
Roth, eds., Weber's Protestant Ethic: Origins, Evidence, Contexts. Cambridge. Cambridge
University Press. 1993. 161-177.
Golomb, Jacob. Nietzsche's Enticing Psychology of Power. Ames. Iowa State University Press.
1987.
--"Nietzsche's Phenomenology of Power." Nietzsche-Studien. 15 (1985): 289-305.
Gooding-Williams, Robert. "Zarathustra's Descent: Incipit tragoedia, incipit parodia." Journal of
Nietzsche Studies. 9110 (1995): 50-76.
Granarolo, Philippe. L'individu eternel. L'experience nietzscheenne de /'eremite. Paris. Vrin.
1993.
Granier, Jean. Le probleme de la verite dans Ia philosophie de Nietzsche. Paris. Editions du Seuil.
1966. 1969.
--"Nietzsche's Conception of Chaos."Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche. 135- 141. ["La pensee
nietzschienne du chaos." Revue de la Metaphysique et de Ia Morale. 1977: 129-166].
- - "Perspectivism and Interpretation." Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche. 190-200.
- - "Le Statut de Ia philosophie selon Nietzsche et Freud." Nietzsche-Studien. 8 (1979): 210-224.
Grau, Gerd Gunther. Ideologie und Wille zur Macht. ZeitgemiijJe Betrachtungen iiber Nietzsche.
Berlin/New York. Walter de Gruyter. 1984.
Graumann, C.F. Grundlagen einer Phenomenologie und Psychologie der Perspektivitiit. Berlin.
Walter de Gruyter. 1960.
Grimm, Ruediger Hermann. Nietzsche's Theory of Knowledge. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1977.
--"Circularity and Self-Reference in Nietzsche." Metaphilosophy. 10 (1979): 289-305.
Grosz, Elizabeth. "Nietzsche and the Stomach for Knowledge." Paul Patton, ed., Nietzsche,
Feminism and Political Theory. London. Routledge. 1993. 49-70.
Gustafsson, Lars. Sprach und Liige - Drei sprachphilosophische Extremisten: Friedrich Nietzsche.
A.B. Johnson, Fritz Mauthner. Miinchen. Hanser. 1980.
Haaparanta, Leila. "A Note on Nietzsche's Argument." The Philosophical Quarterly. 38/153
(1988): 490-495.
Haar, Michel. "The Institution and Destitution of the Political According to Nietzsche." New
Nietzsche Studies. 2:112 (1997): 1-36.
--"La critique nietzschienne de Ia Subjectivite." Nietzsche-Studien. 12 (1983): 80-110.
--"Nietzsche and Metaphysical Language." Allison, ed., The New Nietzsche. 5-36.
Haase, Ullrich M. "Nietzsche's Critique of Technology: A Defense of Phenomenology Against
Modern Machinery." Babich, ed., NS/1. 321-329.
Habermas, Jiirgen, "Postscript: On Nietzsche's Epistemological Writings [1968]." Babich, ed.,
Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 209-233.
- - "Nachwort." Friedrich Nietzsche. Erkenntnistheoretische Schriften. Nachwort von Jiirgen
Habermas. Frankfurt am Main. Suhrkamp. 1968. 237-261.]
Hales, Steven. "Was Nietzsche a Consequentialist?" International Studies in Philosophy. 1995.
XXVII/3:25-34.
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY 347
Hoover, A.J. "Nietzsche's Universe." Friederich Nietzsche. His Life and Thought. Westport,
Connecticut. Praeger.l994. 59-78
--"Our Meddling Intellect: The Problem of Knowledge." 30-57: Friedrich Nietzsche.
Horneffer, Ernst. Nietzsches Lehre von der ewigen Wiederkunft und deren bisherigen Veroffentli-
chung. Leipzig. Kroner. 1900.
Hough, Sheridan. "Epistemology: The 'land' and the 'sea."' Nietzsche's Noontide Friend: The Self
as Metphoric Double. University Park. Pennsylvania University Press. 53-83.
Houlgate, Stephen. Hegel, Nietzsche, and the Criticism, of Metaphysics. Cambridge. Cambridge
University Press. 1986.
--"Kant, Nietzsche, and the 'Thing in Itself'." Nietzsche-Studien. 22 (1993).
Hoy, David. "Nietzsche, Hume, and the Genealogical Method." Schacht, ed., Nietzsche,
Genealogy, Morality. 251-268.
- - "Philosophy as Rigorous Philology? Nietzsche and Poststructuralism." Fragments:
Incompletions and Discontinuity. New York Literary Forum. 8-9 (1981): 171-85.
Hiibner, Kurt. "Yom theoretischen Nachteil und praktischen Nutzen der Historie. UnzeitgemaBes
tiber Nietzsches unzeitgemiiBe Betrachtgungen." Borchmeyer, Dieter, ed., «Vom Nutzen und
Nachteil des Historie fiir das Leben." 28-75.
Jaspers, Karl. "Die Frage nach der Wahrheit bei Nietzsche." Alfredo Guzzoni, ed., 100 Jahre
philosophische Nietzsche-Rezeption. Frankfur am Main. Anton Hain. 1991. 57-72.
Jiihnig, Dieter. "Die Befreiung der Kunsterkenntnis von der Metaphysik in Nietzsches Geburt der
Tragi:idie."Welt-Geschichte: Kunst-Geschichte. DuMont. Koln. 1975. 225 ff.
- - "Nietzsches Kritik der historischen Wissenschaften." Zagreb. Praxis 6 (1970): 223-236.
Jenkins, Fiona. "Performative Identity: Nietzsche and the Force of Art and Language." Salim
Kemal, et al., eds., Nietzsche, Philosophy and the Arts. Berkeley. University of California
Press. 212-238.
Joos, Walter. Die desperate Erkenntnis. Ein Zugange zur Nihilismusproblematic bei Friedrich
Nietzsche. Bern. Peter Lang. 1983.
Juranville, Alain. Physique de Nietzsche. Paris. Denoel/Gonthier. 1973.
Just, Dieter. Nietzsche kontra Nietzsche. Zur Psycho-Logie seines Philosophierens. Konigshausen
& Neumann. Wiirzburg. 1998.
Kain, Philip J.. "Nietzsche, Skepticism, and Eternal Recurrence." Canadian Journal of Philosophy.
13 (1983): 365-87.
Kaulbach, Friedrich. Wahrheit und Perspektive bei Kant, Hegel und Nietzsche. Mohr. Tiibingen.
1990.
- - Nietzsches Idee seiner Experimentalphilosophie. Koln!Wien. Bohlau. 1980.
- - "Das Drama in der Auseinandersetzung zwischen Kunst und Wissensmoral in Nietzsches
Geburt der Tragodie." Djuric & Simon, eds., Kunst und Wissenschaft. 112-129.
- - "Asthetische und philosophische Erkenntnis beim friihen Nietzsche." Djuric & Simon, eds.,
Zur Aktualitlit Nietzsches. Wiirzburg, Konigshausen & Neumann. 1984. 63-80.
- - "Nietzsches Kritik an der Wissensmoral und die Quelle der philosophischen Erkenntnis: die
Autarkie der perspektivischen Vemunft in der Philosophie." Rudolph Berlinger & Wiebke
Schrader, eds., Nietzsche kontrovers: IV. Konigshausen & Neumann. Wiirzburg. 1984. 71-90.
- - "Nietzsches Interpretation der Natur." Nietzsche-Studien. (1981/82): 442-481.
--"Friedrich Nietzsche und der monadologische Gedanke." Nietzsche-Studien. 8 (1979): 127ff.
Kerger, Henry. Autoritiit und Recht im Denken Nietzsches. Berlin. Duncker & Humblot. 1988.
Kimmerle, Gerd. Die Aporie der Wahrheit. Anmwerkungen zu Nietzsches "Genealogie der Moral."
Konkursbuchverlag. Tiibingen. 1983.
Kirchhoff, Jochen. "Zum Problem der Erkenntnis bei Nietzsche." Nietzsche-Studien. 6 (1977):
16-44.
Kittler, Friedrich A. "Vergessen." Texthermeneutik. Nassen. 1979. 195-221.
Klages, Ludwig. Die psychologischen Errungenschaften Nietzsches. Leipzig. 1926. Bonn. Bouvier.
1979.
Klein, Wayne. "Reading Nietzsche's Naturalism." Nietzsche and the Promise of Philosophy.
Albany. SUNY Press. 1997. 138-179.
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY 349
Kloch-Komitz, Peter von. "Der 'Gorgias' Platons und die Philosophie Nietzsches." Zeitschriftfiir
philosophische Forschung. 17 (1963).
Klossowski, Pierre. Nietzsche and the Vicious Circle, trans. Daniel W. Smith. Chicago. The
University of Chicago Press. 1997.
Knopf, Jan. "Kritik der Erkenntniskritik. Zur Klarstellung einiger Irrtiimer: Nietzsche in der
bundesdeutschen Germanistik." Literaturmagazin 12. Hamburg. 1980. 372-392.
Koelb, Clayton, ed., Nietzsche as Postmodernist: Essays Pro and Contra. Albany. SUNY Press.
1990.
Kohler, Joachim. Zarathustras Geheimnis. Friedrich Nietzsche und seine verschliisselte Botschaft.
Nordingen. Greno. 1989.
- - "Die frohliche Wissenschaft." Versuch iiber die sprachliche Selbstkonstitution Nietzsches.
Diss. Wiirzburg. 1977.
Koster, Peter. "Die Problematik wissenschaflichen Nietzsche-Interpretation." Nietzsche-Studien.
2 (1973): 31-60.
- - "Nietzsches Beschworung des Chaos." Tiibingen Theological Quartalshrift. 153 (1973):
132-163.
Kofman, Sarah. Nietzsche and Metaphor. Translated by Duncan Large. London. Athlone. 1993.
[Nietzsche et Ia metaphore. Paris. Payot. 1972.]
- - "Wagner's Ascetic Ideal According to Nietzsche." Schacht, ed., Nietzsche, Genealogy,
Morality. 193-213.
- - "BaubO: Theological Perversion and Fetishism." Gillespie and Strong, eds., Nietzsche's New
Seas. 175-202.
Kopperschmidt, Josef & Helmut Schanze. Nietzsche oder 'Die Sprache ist Rhetorik'. Miinchen.
Fink. 1994.
Kopperschmidt, Josef. "Nietzsche's Rhetorical Philosophy As Critique of Impure Reason."
Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 199-207.
Krell, David Farrell. Nietzsche and the Task of Thinking. Ann Arbor, Dissertation. 1971.
Kremer-Marietti, Angele. Nietzsche et Ia rhetorique. Paris. Presses Universitaires de France. 1992.
- - L 'homme et ses labyrinthes. Paris. 1972 .
- - "Nietzsche: The Critique of Modem Reason."Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge,
Critical Theory. 87-102.
--"De Kant a Lacan: une genealogie critique de Ia raison."La Raison Creatrice. Moderne ou
postmoderne. Paris. Kime. 1996. 37-57.
- - "Metaphore, Connaissance." Etudes Romanesques. 3 (1995): 9-18.
--"Nietzsche et Ia verite." Revue de metaphysique et de morale. 72 (1967): 486-496.
Krueger, J. "Nietzschean Recurrence as a Cosmological Hypothesis," Journal of the History of
Philosophy, XVII 4 ( 1978): 435-444.
Kriiger, Heinz. "Der Aphorismus Nietzsche als philosophische Form."Studien Uber den
Aphorismus als philosophische Form. Frankfurt am Main. Nest. 1956. 81-141.
Lacoue-Labarthe, Philippe. "The Detour."The Subject of Philosophy. Minneapolis. University of
Minnesota Press. 1993. 14-36. ["Le detour (Nietzsche et Ia rhetorique)." Poetique. 5 (1971):
53-00.]
--"Apocryphal Nietzsche."The Subject of Philosophy. 37-56.
- - "Typography."Typography. Mimesis, Philosophy, Politics. Cambridge. Harvard University
Press. 1989.43-138.
Lampert, Lawrence. Nietzsche and Modern Times. A Study of Bacon, Descartes, and Nietzsche.
New Haven. Yale University Press. 1993.
- - "Nietzsche, the History of Philosophy, and Esotericism." Journal of Nietzsche Studies
(1995): 36-49.
Land, Nick. The Thirst for Annihilation: Georges Bataille and Virulent Nihilism. London.
Routledge. 1992.
Large, Duncan. "Hermes contra Dionysus (Serres et Nietzsche)." Horizons philosophiques. 811
(Autumn, 1997: Le Monde de Michel Serres"): 23-39.
Leiter, Brian. "Perspectivism in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals." Schacht, ed., Nietzsche,
Genealogy, Morality. 334-357.
350 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
Levine, Peter. Nietzsche and the Modem Crisis of the Humanities. Albany. SUNY Press. 1995.
Liebmann, Walter. Nietzsche fur und gegen Vaihinger. Die Rolle der Fiktionenen in der
Erkenntnistheorie. Munich. 1923.
Lingis, Alphonso. "Black Stars: The Pedigree of the Evaluators." Graduate Faculty Journal. 15/2
( 1991): 67-91.
--"The Vicious Circle of Mastery." "The Work of the Masters." Deathbound Subjectivity.
Bloomington. Indiana University Press. 1989. 59-87; 87-106.
--"Theory and Idealization in Nietzsche." Goicoechea. ed., The Great Year of Zarathustra.
257-278.
--"The Last Form of the Will to Power." Philosophy Today. 22 (1978): 192-205.
Lob, Walther. "Naturwissenschaftliche Elemente in Nietzsches Gedanken." Deutsche Rundschau.
1908: 137 ff.
Loeb, Paul S. "The Moment of Tragic Death in Nietzsche's Dionysian Doctrine of Eternal
Recurrence: An Exegesis of Aphorism 341." International Studies in Philosophy. XXX/3
(1998): 131-143.
--"Is there a Genetic Fallacy in Nietzsche's Genealogy of Morals?" International Studies in
Philosophy XXVII/3 (1995): 125-141.
Low, Reinhard. Nietzsche. Sophist und Erzieher. Philosophische Untersuchungen zur systema-
tischen ort von Friedrich Nietzsches Denken. Weinheim. Acta Humaniora. 1984.
--"Die Aktua1itat von Nietzsches Wissenschaftskritik." Merkur. 38 (1984): 399-409.
Lowith, Karl. Nietzsche's Philosophy of the Eternal Recurrence of the Same. Trans. Harvey
Lomax. Berkeley. University of California Press. 1997. [Nietzsches Philosophie der ewigen
Wiederkehr des Gleichen. [Berlin. 1935.] Stuttgart. Kohlhammer. 1956.]
--From Hegel to Nietzsche. Trans. D.E. Green. New York. Doubleday. 1967. [Von Hegel zu
Nietzsche. Der revolutioniire bruch im Denken des neunzehnten Jahrhunderts. Stuttgart. 1964.]
Long, Thomas. "Nietzsche's Philosophy of Medicine." Nietzsche-Studien. 19 (1990): 112-128.
Longo, Silvano. Die Aufdeckung der leiblichen Vemunft bei Friedrich Nietzsche. Wiirzburg.
Konigshausen & Neumann. 1987.
Love, Frederick R. Nietzsche's Saint Peter: Genesis and Cultivation of an Illusion. Berlin/New
York. Walter de Gruyter. 1981.
Lukacher, Ned. Time-Fetishes: The Secret History of the Eternal Recurrence. Durham. Duke
University Press. 1998.
Lukacs, Georg. Die Zerst6rung der Vemunft. Berlin. Luchterhand. 1962.
Lyotard, Jean-Fran,.:ois. The Post-Modern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Trans. Geoff
Bennington and Brian Massumi. Minneapolis. University of Minnesota Press. 1984.
- - "Nietzsche and the Inhuman. Interview With Richard Beardsworth." Journal of Nietzsche
Studies. 7 (1994): 67-130.
- - "Bemerkungen tiber die Wiederkehr und das Kapital." Intensiti:iten. Berlin. 1978.
Maurer, Reinhart. "Nietzsche und das Experimentelle." Djuric & Simon, eds., Zur Aktualiti:it
Nietzsches I. 7-28
--"Nietzsche und die kritische Theorie." Nietzsche-Studien. 10111(1981/82): 34-56.
--"The Origins of Modern Technology in Millenarianism." Paul T. Durbin & Friedrich Rapp,
eds., Philosophy and Technology. D. Reidel. Dordrecht. 1983. 253-65.
Macintyre, Alastaire. "Genealogies and Subversions." Schacht, ed., Nietzsche, Genealogy,
Morality. 284-305.
--"Philosophy and Sanity: Nietzsche's Titanism." Encounter. 32 ( 1969): 79-82.
Magnus, Bernd. "Eternal Recurrence." Nietzsche-Studien. 8 (1979): 362-377.
--"Nietzsche's Eternalistic Counter-Myth." Review of Metaphysics. XXVI (1973): 604-616.
Mahon, Michael. Foucault's Nietzschean Genealogy: Truth, Power, and the Subject. Albany. State
University of New York Press. 1992.
Marton, S. "L'eternel retour du meme: These cosmologique ou imperatif ethique?" Nietzsche-
Studien. 25 (1996): 42-63.
McGinn, Robert. "Nietzsche on Technology." Journal of the History of Ideas. 41 (1980): 679-691.
Meijers, Anthonie. "Gustav Gerber und Friedrich Nietzsche." Nietzsche-Studien, 17 (1988): 369-
390.
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY 351
Miller, J. Hillis. "Gleichnis in the Text of Nietzsche." International Studies in Philology. XV, No.
2 (1983): 3-16.
Mittasc:h, Alwin. Friedrich Nietzsche als Naturphilosoph. Stuttgart. Alfred Kroner. 1952.
- - Unverganglichkeit? Naturforschergedanken iiber Unsterblichkeit. Heidelberg. (no publ.
data). 1947.
--Friedrich Nietzsches Stellung zur Chemie. Berlin (no publ. data). 1944.
--"Friedrich Nietzsches Verhiiltnis zu Robert Mayer." Blatter fiir Desutsche Philosophie. 16.
1943.
- - "Der Kraftbegriffbei Leibniz, Robert Mayer, Nietzsche." Proteus. 3 (1942): 139-61.
Mittelmann, William. "Perspectivism, Becoming, and Truth in Nietzsche." International Studies
in Philosophy. 1984 XVU2.
--"The Relation between Nietzsche's Theory of the Will to Power and his Earlier Conceptions
of Power," Nietzsche-Studien, 9 ( 1980): 122-141.
Moles, Alistair. Nietzsche's Philosophy of Nature and Cosmology. Bern. Peter Lang. 1990.
- - "Nietzsche's Eternal Recurrence as Riemannian Cosmology." International Studies in
Philosophy. 16 (1991): 21-35.
Montinari, Mazzino. "Nietzsches Philosophie als Leidenschaft der Erkenntnis.'' Studi Germani.
7 (1969): 337-52. [Also in Nietzsche lesen. Berlin. Walter de Guyter. 1982. 64-78.]
Morgan, George. What Nietzsche Means. New York. Harper & Row. 1965.
Mortensen, Ellen. "Irigaray and Nietzsche: Echo and Narcissus Revisited." Ansell-Pearson and
Caygill, eds., The Fate of the New Nietzsche.
Miiller, Severin. "Perspektivitiit der Erkenntnis und Perspektivitiit des Willens: Zur Pluralitiit des
Wirklichen bei Leibniz und Nietzsche." Gebhard, ed., Friedrich Nietzsche: Perspektivitiit und
Tiefe. 15-70.
Miiller-Lauter, Wolfgang. Nietzsche: His Philosophy a,{ Contradictions and the Contradictions of
His Philosophy. Trans. David J. Parent. Urbana and Chicago. University of Illinois Press. 1999.
[Nietzsche: Seine Philosophie der Gegensdtze und die Gegensatze seiner Philosophie. Ber-
lin/New York. Walter de Gruyter. 1971.]
- - Ober Werden und Wille zur Macht. Nietzsche-Interpretationen I. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter.
1999. Includes later version of :
--"On Judgment in a World of Becoming." Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge,
Critical Theory. 165-185.
- - Ober Freiheit und Chaos. Nietzsche-Interpretationen II. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1999.
--"The Organism as Inner Struggle: Wilhelm Roux's Influence on Nietzsche." Nietzsche: His
Philosophy of Contradictions and the Contradictions of His Philosophy. 161- 182.
- - "Der Organismus als innere Kampf. Der Einfluss von Wilhelm Roux auf Friedrich
Nietzsche." Nietzsche-Studien. 7 (1978): 189-223.
- - "Nietzsches Lehre vom Willen zur Macht." Nietzsche-Studien. 3 (1974): 1-60. Translated
as "Nietzsche's Doctrine of the Will to Power." Nietzsche: His Philosophy of Contradictions
and the Contradictions of His Philosophy. 122-160.
Murin, Charles, Nietzsche Probleme. Genealogie d'une pensee. Montreal. Les Presses de
l'Universite de Montreal et Ia Librairie ph1losophie Vrin. 1979.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. "Nietzsche's Thesis on Telelogy." "'Our Probity' -On Truth in the Moral Sense
in Nietzsche." Rickels, ed., Looking After Nietzsche. 49-65; 67-87.
Nash, Margaret. "Nietzschean Debris: Truth as Circe." Bat-Ami Bar On, ed., Modern Engender-
ing: Critical Feminist Readings in Modem Western Philosophy. Albany. State University of
New York Press. 1994.219-229.
Nehamas, Alexander. Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cambridge. Harvard University Press. 1985.
--"Truth and Value Diverge: On Arthur Danto's Nietzsche as Philosopher." Inernational
Studies in Philosophy. (1998): 1-12.
Nemeth, Elisabeth. "Nietzsche, Neurath und die Reflexivitiit der Moderne." Philosophie,
Psychoanalyse, Emigration. Vienna. Braumiiller. 1992.
Neumann, Harry. "Socrates and History: A Nietzschean Interpretation of History."
Nietzsche-Studien. 6 (1977): 64-74.
352 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
Newman, Michael. "Reading the Future of Genealogy: Kant, Nietzsche, and Plato." Ansell-
Pearson, ed., Nietzsche and Modern German Thought. London. Routledge. 1991. 257-282.
Nimis, Stephen. "FuBnoten: Das Fundament der Wissenschaft." Arethusa XVII, no. 2 (!984), 105-
134.
Noh!, H. "Eine historische Quelle zu Nietzsches Perspectivismus: G. Teichmiiller, die wirkliche
und scheinbare Welt." Zeitschrift fur Philosophie und philosophische Kritik. 149 (1913 ): 106-
15.
Nola, Robert, "Nietzsche's Theory of Truth and Belief." Philosophy & Phenomenological
Research. 47 (1987): 525-562.
O'Connor, Brian. "Nietzsche and Enlightenment Science: Adorno's Response." Babich, ed.,
Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 243-252.
Oehler, Richard. Friedrich Nietzsche und die Vorsokratiker. Leipzig. Kroner. 1904.
Okochi, Ryogi, "Nietzsches Naturbegriff aus ostlicher Sicht. Nietzsche-Studien. 17. (1988): 108-
124.
Oliver, Kelly. "Women as Truth in Nietzsche's Writing." Kelly Oliver and Marilyn Pearsall, eds.,
Feminist Interpretations of Friedrich Nietzsche. The Pennsylvania State University Press.
1998. 66-80.
de Oliveira, Nythamar. "Habermas on Nietzsche and Knowledge." New Nietzsche Studies. 21!-2
(1997): 110-120.
Ottman, Henning. Philo sophie und Politik bei Nietzsche. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1987.
- - "Nietzsches Stellung zur antiken und modernen Aufkliirung." Simon, ed., Nietzsche und die
Philosophische Tradition. 9ff.
Owen, David. "Truth and Eros: A Critique of the Philosophical Commitments of Liberal Reason."
Nietzsche, Politics, & Modernity. London. Sage. 1995. 20-53.
Parkes, Graham. "Nietzsche on the Fabric(ation) of Experience." Journal of Nietzsche Studies.
9/!0. 11995): 17-35.
--"Nietzsche, Nishitani, and the Self-Over-Coming of Nihilism." International Studies in
Philosophy. XXV/2 (1993): 51-60.
- - "Human/Nature in Nietzsche and Taoism." J. Baird Callicott and Roger T. Ames, eds.,
Nature in Asian Traduitions of Thought: Essays in Environmental Philosophy. Albany. SUNY
Press. 1989. 79-98.
Pasley, Malcolm. "Nietzsche's Use of Medical Terms." Nietzsche Imagery and Thought: A
Collection of Essays. Berkeley. University of California Press. 1978. 123-158.
Patt, Walter. Formen des Anti-Platonismus bei Kant, Nietzsche und Heidegger. Frankfurt am
MaKlostermann. 1997.
Patton, Paul. "Politics and the Concept of Power in Hobbes and Nietzsche." Paul Patton, ed.,
Nietzsche, Feminism and Political Theory, London. Routledge. 1993. 144-161.
Pavur, Claude, Nietzsche Humanist. Milwaukee. Marquette University Press. 1998.
Pensky, Max. "Truth and Interest: On Habermas's Postscript to Nietzsche's Theory of Knowledge"
Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 265-271.
Perkins, Richard. "Ana1ogistic Strategies in Zarathustra." Goicoechea, ed., The Great Year of
Zarathustra. 316-338.
- - "MA 628: Preliminary Analysis of the Aphorism and its Precursors." Nietzsche-Studien. 6
(1977): 203-39.
Pickard, Dean. "Nietzsche, Emancipation, and Truth." New Nietzsche Studies. Fall/ Winter. 1997.
2:1/2: 85-110.
Picht, Georg. Nietzsche. Stuttgart. Klett Cotta. 1988.
Pines, Schlomo. "Nietzsche: Psychology vs. Pilosophy, and Freedom." Yovel, Yirmiyahu, ed.
Nietzsche as Affirmative Thinker: Papers Presented at the Fifth Jerusalem Philosophical
Encounter, Apri/1983. The Hague. Martinus Nijhoff. 1986. 147-159.
Pippin, Robert B. "Truth and Lies in the Early Nietzsche." Journal of Nietzsche Studies ( 1996):
35-52.
--"Irony and Affirmation in Nietzsche's Thus Spoke Zarathustra." Gillespie and Strong, eds.,
Nietzsche's New Seas. 45-71.
--"Nietzsche and the Origin of the Idea of Modernity." Inquiry. 26 (1988): 154-80.
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY 353
Pizer, John. "The Use and Abuse of 'Ursprung': On Foucault's Reading of Nietzsche."
Nietzsche-Studien. 19 (1990): 462-78.
Poellner, Peter. Nietzsche and Metaphysics. Oxford. Oxford University Press. 1997.
Poltner, Gunther. Zu Einer Phiinomenologie Des Fragens: Ein Fragend-Fraglicher Versuche.
Freiburg/Miinchen. Verlag Karl Alber. 1972.
Piitz, Peter. "Nietzsche im Licht der Kritische Theorie." Nietzsche-Studien. 3 (1974): 175-191.
--"Nietzsche: Art and Intellectual Inquiry." Pasley, ed., Nietzsche: Imagery and Thought.
Quinot, Armand. Friedrich Nietzsche. pages mystiques. Paris. Gallimard. 1945.
Rammoux, Charles. "Les Fragments d'un Empedocle de Friedrich Nietzsche." Revue de
metaphysique et de morale. 70 (1965): 199-212.
Rath, Norbert. "Zur Nietzsche-Rezeption Horkheimers und Adomos." Willem van Reijen &
Gunzelin Schmid. Vierzing Jahre Flaschenpost: "Dialektik der Aufkliirung. Frankfurt. Noerr.
1987.73 ff.
Reboul, Olivier. Nietzsches critique de Kant. Vendome. Presses Universitaires de France. 1974.
Reckermann, Alfons. "Nietzsche und Parmenides." Phil. Jahrbuch. 89 (1982): 325-346.
Redding, Paul. "Child of the English Genealogists: Nietzsche's Affiliation with the Critical
Historical Mode of the Enlightenment." Patton, ed., Nietzsche, Feminism and Political Theory.
204-224.
Reginster, Bernard. "Ressentiment, Evaluation and Integrity." International Studies in Philosophy.
XXVII/3 (1995): 117-124.
Rethy, Robert. "Schein in Nietzsche's Philosophy." Ansell-Pearson, ed., Nietzsche and Modem
German Thought. 59-87.
Rey, Abel, Nietzsche. Le retour etemel et de Ia philosophie de Ia physique. Paris. 1927.
Rey, Jean-Michel. L'Enjeu des signes. lecture de Nietzsche. Paris. Editions du Seuil. 1971.
--"La genealogie Nietzscheenne." Fran~ois Chatelet, ed., La philosophie du monde scientifique
et industriel. Paris. Hachette. 1973. 151-189.
Richardson, John. Nietzsche's System. Oxford. Oxford University Press. 1996.
Riedel, Manfred. Nietzsche in Weimar. Ein deutsches Drama. Leipzig. Reclam. 1997.
- - "Scientific Theory or Practical Doctrine."Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge,
Critical Theory. 187-197.
Riehl, Alois. Friedrich Nietzsche, der Kiinstler und Denker. Stuttgart. Frommann. 1897.
Ries, Wiebrecht. Friedrich Nietzsche. Wie die 'wahre Welt' endlich zur Fabel wurde. Hannover.
1977.
Rottges, Heinz. Nietzsche und der Dialektik der Aufkliirung. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1972.
Roos, Richard. "Nietzsche et Epicure: L'idylle heroique." Revue d'Allegmagne et des pays du
l~ngue allemande. XIII. 4. (1980).
- - "Regles pour une lecture philologique de Nietzsche." Nietzsche aujourd'hui. Paris. II (1973):
283-324.
Rorty, Richard. "Beyond Nietzsche and Marx." London Review of Books. February 19, 1981.
Roth, Florian. "Nietzsches Wahrheitsbegriff in seiner selbstwiderspruchlichen Problematik."
Nietzsche-Studien. 22 ( 1993): 94-114.
Roth, Robin. "Nietzsche's Metaperspectivism." International Studies in Philosophy. XXII/2
(1990): 67-77.
Rupp, Gerhard. "Der 'ungeheure Consensus der Menschen tiber die Dinge' oder Das gesell-
schaftlich wirksame Rhetorische: Zum Nietzsche des Philosophenbuchs." Literaturmagazin 12.
Hamburg. Rowohlt/Reinbek. 1980. 179-203.
Sadler, Ted. Nietzsche. Truth and Redemption. Critique of the Postmodernist Nietzsche. Athlone.
London. 1995.
Safranski, Rudiger. Wieviel Wahrheit braucht der Mensch? Uber das Denkbare unddas Lebbare.
Miinchen. Hanser. 1990.
Salaquarda, Jorg, ed., Nietzsche. Darmstadt. Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. 1982.
- - "Art is More Powerful Than Knowledge: Nietzsche on the Relationship Between Art and
Science" trans. V. Jakoby and KG. Ullah. New Nietzsche Studies. Forthcoming. 1999.
--Translation above first published in Croatian as: "'Umjetnostje mocnija od spoznaje.' Fr.
Nietzsche e odnusu umjetnosti i znanosti." trans. Z. Pavic, Filozosfska Istrazivanja 59 God. 15
354 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
Sv. 4 (1995): 683-695. ['"Die Kunst is machtiger als die Erkenntnis". Fr. Nietzsche tiber das
Verhaltnis von Kunst und Wissenschaft," Synthesis Philosophica. 21 vol. II, fasc. I (1996)
(lnternationale Ausgabe der Zeitschrift Filozofska lstrazivanja): 46-63.]
- - "Der Standpunkt des Ideals bei Lange und Nietzsche." Studi Tedeschi. 29 (1979): 133-60.
--"Nietzsche and Lange." Nietzsche-Studien. 7 (1978): 236-253.
Sallis, John. "Nietzsche and the Problem of Knowledge." Tulane Studies in Philosophy. 18 (1969):
105-30.
Sandktihler, Hans-Jorg. "Die Entdeckung und Rehabilitierung des Unbewul3ten." Die Wirklichkeit
des Wissens. Einfiihrung in die Epistemologie und Theorie des Erkennens. Frankfurt am Main.
Suhrkamp. 1991. 225-231.
Savouret, Marie. Nietzsche et Du Bos. Paris. M. J. Minard. 1960.
Sax, Benjamin. "On the Genealogical Method: Nietzsche and Foucault." International Studies in
Philosophy. XXII/2 (1990): 129-141.
Schacht, Richard. "Nietzsche's Gay Science or How to Naturalize Cheerfully." Robert Solomon
and Kathleen Higgins, ed., Reading Nietzsche. Oxford. Oxford University Press. 1988. 68-86.
- - "Nietzsche and Nihilism." Journal of the History of Philosophy. IX/I ( 1973): 65-144.
- - "Philosophy as Linguistic Analysis: A Nietzschean Critique." Philosophical Studies 25
(1973): 153-171.
Scharff, Robert. "Nietzsche and the "Use" of History." Man and World. VII (1974): 67-77.
Scheer, Brigitte. "Die Bedeutung der Sprache im Verhaltnis von Kunst und Wissenschaft bei
Nietzsche." DjuriC & Simon, eds., Kunst und Wissenschaft. I 01-111.
Scheier, Claus-Artur. "Einleitung.'' vii-cxxiii: Ecce auctor. Die Vorreden von 1886.Hamburg.
Meiner. 1990.
Schipperges, Heinrich. Am Leitfaden des Leibes. Zur Anlhropologie und Therapeutik Friedrich
Nietzsches. Stuttgart. Klett Cotta. 1971.
Schliipmann, Heide. Friedrich Nietzsches aesthetische Opposition. Der Zusammenhang von
Sprache, Natur und Kultur in seinen Schriften 1869-1876. Stuttgart. Metzler. 1977.
Schlechta, Karl. Der Fall Nietzsche. Mtinchen. Carl Hanser. 1958.
--Nietzsche Chronik: Dalen zu Leben und Werk. Mtinchen. Carl Hanser. 1975.
--"Nietzsche tiber den Glauben an die Grammatik." Nietzsche-Studien. I ( 1972): 353ff.
- - & Anni Anders. Friedrich Nietzsche. Von den verborgenen Anfiingen seines Philosophierens.
Stuttgart/Bad Cannstatt. Friedrich Froomrnann. 1962.
Schlol3berger, Mathias. "Uber Nietzsche und die Philosophische Anthropologie.'' Nietzschefor-
schung. 4 (1998): 147-168.
Schmid, Holger. Nietzsches Gedanke der tragischen Erkenntnis. Wtirzburg. Konigshausen &
Neumann. 1984.
- - "The Nietzschean Meta-Critique of Knowledge." Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of
Knowledge, Critical Theory. 153-163.
Schmid, Josef. '"Die Sprossen zurtick"! Die ideologiekritischesn Erfahrung des Jahrhunderts im
Lichte Friedrich Nietzsches." Nietzscheforschung. 4 (1998): 271-284.
Schmidt, Alfred. "Uber Nietzsche's Erkenntnistheorie." Salaquarda, ed., Nietzsche. 124-152.
[Reprint of "Zur Frage der Dialektik in Nietzsches Erkenntnistheorie." M. Horkheimer, ed.,
Zeugnisse: Theodore W. Adorno zum sechszigsten Geburtstag. Frankfurt am Main. 1969.
15-132. And "Die Praxislehre in Nietzsches Metaphysik des Willens zur Macht." From
"Praxis." In H. Krings., H.M.Baumgartner & Ch. Wild, eds., handbuch philosophisher Grund-
begriffe. Band II. Mtinchen. 1973.]
Schreiber, Jens. "Die Ordnung des Geniel3ens. Nietzsche mit Lacan." Literaturmagazin 12.
Hamburg. Rowohlt. 1980. 204-235.
Schrift, Alan. "Between Perspectivism and Philology: Genealogy and Hermeneutics."
Nietzsche-Studien. 16 (1987): 91-111.
--"Language, Metaphors and Rhetoric: Nietzsche's Deconstruction of Epistemology", Journal
of the History of Philosophy, XXIII/3, 3 (1985): 71-375.
Schroter, Hartmut. Historische Theorie und geschichtliches Handeln. Zur wissenschaftskritik
Nietzsches. Mittenwald. Meander. 1972.
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY 355
Schulte, Giinter. Das Verhdltnis von Kunst und Erkennen in der Philosophie Nietzsches. Koln.
1964.
Schute, Ofelia. Beyond Nihilism: Nietzsche Without Masks. Chicago. The University of Chicago
Press. 1984.
Schwartz, Steven, P., "The Status of Nietzsche's Theory of the Will to Power in the Light of
Contemporary Philosophy of Science." International Studies in Philosophy, XXV/2 (1993):
85-92.
Schweder, Richard A. "Post-Nietzschean Anthropology." Michael Krausz, ed., Relativism:
Interpretation and Confrontation. Notre Dame. University of Notre Dame Press. 1989. 99-139.
Shapiro, Gary. "Festival, Parody, and Carnival in Zarathustra IV." Goicoechea, ed., The Great
Year of Zarathustra. 45- 62.
- - "The Writing on the Wall: The Antichrist and the Semiotics of History." Solomon and
Higgins, eds., Reading Nietzsche. 192-217.
Siegfried, Hans. "Autonomy and Quantum Physics: Nietzsche, Heidegger, and Heisenberg."
Philosophy of Science. 57. 1990.
Simmel, Georg. Shopenhauer and Nietzsche. Trans. Loiskandl, H., Weinstein, D., Weinstein, M.
trans. Urbana. University of Illinois. 1991. [Leipzig. Duncker und Humb1ott. 1907.]
- - "Die Problem des Geschichtsphilosophie. Eine Erkenntnistheoretische Studie"
Miinchen/Leipzig. 1923.
Simon, Josef, "Nietzsche's Critique of Truth and Grammar."Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of
Knowledge, Critical Theory. 129-151. ["Grammatik und Wahrheit: Uber das Verha1tnis zur
metaphysischen Tradition." Nietzsche-Studien. 1 (1972): 1-26. Also: 185-218 in Jorg
Salaquarda, ed., Nietzsche. Darmstadt, Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. 1979.]
- - "Aufk!arung im Denken Nietzsches."Jochen Schmidt, ed., Aujkldrung und Gegenaujkldrung
in der europdischen Literatur, Philosophie und Politik von der Antike his zur Gegenwart.
Darmstadt. Wissenschaft1iche Buchgesellschaft. 1989. 459-474.
--"Die Krise der Wahrheitsbegriffs als Krise der Metaphysik." Nietzsche-Studien. 18 (1989):
242-259.
- - "Sprache und Sprachkritik bei Nietzsche."Mathias Lutz-Bachman, ed., Uber Friedrich
Nietzsche. Eine Einfiihrung in seine Philosophie. Frankfurt!M. Josef Knecht. 1985. 63-97.
Sini, Carlo. Semiotica e filosofia: segno e linguaggio in Pierce, Nietzsche, Heidegger e Foucault.
Bologna. 11 Mulino. 1978.
Sloterdijk, Peter. Der Denker auf der Biihne. Nietzsches Materialismus. Frankfurt/M. Suhrkamp.
1986.
Small, Robin."Disturbing Thoughts And Eternal Perspectives: Some Uses Of Symbolism In
Nietzsche." New Nietzsche Studies. Forthcoming.
- - "Zarathustra's Gateway.' History of Philosophy Quarterly. 1511 (1998):79-98.
--"Nietzsche, Spir, and Time." Journal of the History of Philosophy. XXXIII I (1994): 85-102.
--"Nietzsche, Zollner, and the Fourth Dimension." Archiv fii.r Geschichte der Philosophie. 76
(1994 ): 279-282.
--"Incommensurability and Recurrence: From Oresme to Simmel." Journal of the History of
Ideas. (1991): 121-137.
- - "Boscovich Contra Nietzsche." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. XLVI/3 (1986):
419-435.
--"Three Interpretations of Eternal Recurrence." Canadian Philosophical Review Dialogue.
XXII/I (1983): 92-112.
- - "Nietzsche and a Platonist Tradition of the Cosmos: Center Everywhere and Circumference
Nowhere." Journal of the History of Ideas 4411 (1983): 89-104.
Smith, C.U.M .. '"Clever Beasts Who Invented Knowing': Nietzsche's Evolutionary Biology of
Knowledge." Biology and Philosophy. 2 (1987): 65-91.
Solomon, Robert. "Postscript to a Philosophy of the Future." International Studies in Philosophy.
XVIII/3. (1996): 113-119.
Spiekermann, Klaus. Naturwissenschaft als subjektlose Macht? Nietzsches Kritik physikalischer
Grundkonzepte. Berlin/New York. Walter de Gruyter. 1992.
356 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
- - "Nietzsche and Critical Theory." Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical
Theory. 225-242.
- - "Nietzsches Beweis fiir die ewige Wiederkehr." Nietzsche-Studien. 17 (1988): 492-538.
Stack, George J. Nietzsche: Man, Knowledge. and Will to Power. Durango, Colorado. Hollow-
brook Publishing. 1994.
--Lange and Nietzsche. Berlin. Walter de Gruyter. 1983.
--"Nietzsche's Evolutionary Epistemology." Dialogos. Revista del Departemento de Filosofia
Universidad de Puerto Rico, XXVII/59 (1992): 75-101.
--"Kant, Lange, and Nietzsche: Critique of Knowledge." Ansell-Pearson, ed., Nietzsche and
Modem German Thought. 30-58.
--"Riemann's Geometry and Eternal Recurrence as Cosmological Hypothesis. A Reply."
International Studies in Philosophy. 16 (1991): 37-40.
--"Nietzsche's Analysis of Causality." Idealistic Studies. 12 (1982): 260-275.
- - "Nietzsche and Boscovich's Natural Philosophy." Pacific Philosophical Quarterly. 62
(1981): 69-87.
Stegmaier, Werner. "Nietzsches Neubestimmung der Wahrheit." Nietzsche-Studien. 14 (1985):
69-95.
- - "Darwin, Darwinismus, Nietzsche: Zur problem der Evolution." Nietzsche-Studien. 16
(1987): 264-288.
Steinhart, Eric. 'The Will to Power and Parallel Distributed Processing." Babich, ed. Nietzsche,
Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science. 303-311.
Stelzer, Steffen. Der Zug der Zeit: Nietzsches Versuch du Philosophie. Meisenheim am Glan.
Anton Hain. 1979.
Stenger, Ursula. "Die Welt als ein sich selbst gebiirendes Kunstwerk": Nietzsches Phiinomenone
des schopferischen. Freiburg. Rombach. 1997.
Sterling, M.C. "Recent Discussions of Eternal Recurrence: Some Critical Comments." Nietzsche-
Studien 6 (1977): 261-291.
Stern, Joseph. P .. A Study of Nietzsche. Cambridge. Cambridge University Press. 1979.
Steverding, Bernhard. Nietzsches Verhiiltnis zu Natur. Wissenschaft und Naturphilosophie. Diss.
Munster. 1951.
Stingelin, Martin. "Nietzsche's Wort-Spiel als Reflexion auf poet(olog)ische Verfahren,"
Nietzsche-Studien. 17(1988): 326-349.
Strobel, Eva. Das "Pathos der Distanz." Nietzsches Entscheidung fur den Aphorismenstil.
Wiirzburg. Konigshausen & Neumann. 1998.
Strong, Tracy. Friedrich Nietzsche and the Politics of Transfiguration. Berkeley. University of
California Press. 1975.
- - "A Postscript on Habermas, Nietzsche, and Politics." Babich, ed., Nietzsche, Theories of
Knowledge, Critical Theory. 307-324.
--"Texts and Pretexts: Reflections on Perspectivism in Nietzsche." Political Theory. 13/2
(1985): 164-182.
- - "Language and Nihilism: Nietzsche's Critique of Epistemology." Theory and Society. 3
(1976): 239-263.
Swindal, James "Nietzsche, Critical Theory, and a Theory of Knowledge." Babich, ed., Nietzsche,
Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 253-264.
Taminiaux, Jacques. "Art and Truth in Schopenhauer and Nietzsche." Man and World. 20 (1987):
85-102.
Taureck, Bernhard B. F. "Habermas's Critique of Nietzsche's Critique of Reason." Babich, ed.,
Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, Critical Theory. 289-294.
Taylor, Charles S. "Some Thoughts on Nietzsche, Kazantzakis and the Meaning of Art."
Nietzsche-Studien. 12 (1983): 379-386.
Tauber, Alfred I. "A Typology of Nietzsche's Biology." Biology and Philosophy. 9 (1994): 25-45.
Thomas, Douglas. "Utilising Foucault's Nietzsche: Nietzsche, Genealogy, Autobography."
Journal of Nietzsche Studies. 6 (1993): 103-129.
Thurner, Rainer. "Sprache und Welt bei Friedrich Nietzsche." Nietzsche-Studien. 9 (1980): 38-60.
Titkemeyer, H. Die Erkenntnistheorie Kants bei Friedrich Nietzsche. Konigsberg. 19938. Diss.
SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY 357
Treiber, Hubert. '"Das Ausland' - die 'reichste und gediegenste Registratur' naturwissen-
schaftlichphilosophischer Titel in Nietzsches idealer Bibliothek." Nietzsche-Studien, 25 (1996):
394-412.
--"Nietzsche's Monastery for Free Spirits and Weber's Sect." Hartmut Lehmann and Guenther
Roth, eds., Weber's Protestant Ethic: Origins, Evidence, Contexts. Cambridge. Cambridge
University Press. 1993. 133-159.
Tiircke, Christoph. Der toile Mensche: Nietzsche und der Wahnsinn der Vernunft. Frankfurt am
Main. Fischer. 1989.
Ulmer, K. "Nietzsches Idee der Wahrheit und die Wahrheit in der Philosophie." Philosophisches
Jahrbuch der Gorresges. 70 ( Jg. 1962/63).
van Fraassen, Bas C. "Capek on Eternal Recurrence." Journal of Philosophy. 59 (1962),
371-75.Vaihinger, Hans. The Philosophy of "As If": A System of the Theoretical, Practical and
Relgious Fictions of Mankind. Trans. C. K. Ogden. New York. Harcourt, Brace. 1935. [Die
Philosophie des Als Ob. System der theoretischen, praktischen und religiosen Fiktionen der
Menschheit auf Grund eine idealistische Positivismus: mit einem Anhang iiber Kant und
Nietzsche. Leipzig. F. Meiner. 1911.]
--Nietzsche als Philosoph. Berlin. Reuther & Reichard. 1902. (Fourth edition, 1916)
--"Nietzsche and his Doctrine of Conscious Illusion." R. Solomon, ed., Nietzsche; A Collection
of Critical Essays. New York. Doubleday. 1973. 83-104. [From the Philosophy of "As If:
German in Guzzoni, 100 Jahre philosophischer Nietzsche-Rezeption.]
Valadier, Paul. Nietzsche, l'athee de rigueur. Paris. Desclee de Brouwer. 1975.
--Nietzsche et Ia critique du christianisme. Paris. Cerf. 1974.
Volkmann-Schluck, Karl-Heinz. Die Philosophte Nietzsches. Der Untergang der abend-liindischen
Metaphysik. Konigshausen & Neumann. Wtirzburg. 1991.
- - "Die metaphyische Rescendence urn Denken Nietzsches." Berlinger & Schrader, eds.,
Nietzsche kontrovers I. 77-92.
Volz, Pia Daniela. Nietzsche im Labyrinth st,iner Krankheit. Eine medizinisch-biographische
Untersuchung. Wiirzburg. Konigshausen & Neumann. 1990.
Volz, Pia D. & Johann Prossliner. Friedrich Nietzsche im Urteil seiner Zeitgenossen. Mtinchen,
Kastel!. 1998.
Warin, Franc,:ois. Nietzsche et Bataille. La parodie ii l'infini. Paris. PUF. 1994.
Warnock, Mary. "Nietzsche's Conception ofTruth."Pasley, ed., Nietzsche: Imagery and Thought.
33-63.
Wagenvoort, H. "Die Entstehung von Nietzsches Geburt der Tragodie." Mnemosyne. (New Series)
1959. 4.
Waite, Geoff. Nietzsche's Corps/e. Aesthetics, Politics, Prophecy, or, the Spectacular Technocul-
ture of Everyday Life. Durham. Duke University Press. 1996.
Wahl, Jean. "Le probleme du temps chez Nietzsche." Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale. 67
(1961).
- - "Le Nietzsche de Fink." Revue de Metaphysique et de Morale. 68 (1962): 00-000.
Wandel, Fritz. Bewusstsein und Wille/ Dialektik als Mavens fiir Nietzsche. Bonn. Bouvier. 1972.
Warren, Mark. Nietzsche and Political Thought. Cambridge. MIT Press. 1988.
Weisshaupt, Kurt. "Maske und Gehalt. Stufen des Esoterischen bei Nietzsche." Helmut Holzhey
& Walther Ch. Zimmerli, eds., Esoterik und Exoterik der Philosophie: Beitriige zu Geschichte
und Sinn philosophischer Selbstbestimmung. Basel/Stuttgart. Scwabe & Co. Verlag. 1977. 191-
205.
- - "Nietzsche: Wahrheit und Unwahrheit. Exkurs zum Wahrheitsbegriff Nietzsches." Die
Zeitlichkeit der Wahrheit. Freiburg. 1973. l40ff.
Westphal, Kenneth R. "Was Nietzsche a Cognitivist?" Journal of the History of Philosophy. 2311
(1985): 343-63.
- - "Nietzsche's Sting and the Possibility of Good Philology." International Studies in
Philosophy. 16 (1984): 71-90.
Welshon, Rex. "Perspectivist Causality." International Studies in Philosophy. XXX/3 (1998): 39-
48.
358 SELECTED RESEARCH BIBLIOGRAPHY
359
B. Babich (ed. ), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 359-363.
360 NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS
Scott Podolsky has written on the role of virus research in the origin of life-
theories, the development of post-World War II immunology, and late nine-
teenth century theories of nutrition. He is co-author with Alred I. Tauber of
Generation of Diversity (1997), a history of how molecular biology was
introduced into immunology. He is currently a medical resident at Boston's
Brigham and Women's hospital.
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Acknowledgements IX
List of Abbreviations Used xi
INTRODUCTION
365
366 TABLE OF CONTENTS- VOLUME l
Index 335
INDEX
Abel, G., 188, 200n, 273n, 275n Berlecamp, E. [& J. Conway & R. Guy],
Achilles, 126 322n
Agrippa, H.C., 125, 140n Bernard, C., 299, 307, 309
Alcibiades, 183 Bernasconi, R., 22n
Allen, B., 3, 16, 18, 20n, 23n, 24n, 140n Biagioli, M., 132, 140n, 219n
Allison, D.B., 17, 24n, 175n, 216n Bittner, R., 71n
Anaxagoras, 75-76 Blank, D, [& L. Meeden & J. Marshal],
Anax:imander, 24n 320n
Anders, A. [with Schlechta], 22n-23n, 157n, Blonde!, E., 23n, 139n, 319n
187,200n,297n Bloor, D., xv
Anderson, R.L., 3, 15, 21n, 57n-59n, 273n, Blumenberg, H., 130, 139n
276n,277n Bly, R., 215, 219n
Ansell-Pearson, K., 158n Bohm, D., 320n
Apollo, 203-204,216, 216n, 302-303,315 Bohr, N., 227
Aquinas, Saint Thomas, 5, 214, 260 Boltzmann, L., 315, 321n
Arbib, M. [with Hesse], 219n Bongie, C., 158n
Aristarchus, 97n Bonhoeffer, D., 231
Aristotle, 5. 7, 10, 94, 124, 131,207,214, Boorse, C., 301
230,232,296 Borsche, T., 21n, 24n
Ashmole, E., 140n Boscovich, R.J., xv, 17, 19, 75, 99n, 187-
Augustus, 221 199, 199n-201n, 227, 270,273n, 277n,
Austin, J., 229 291,294,297n,320n
Axelrod, 322n Bourget, P., 155
Ayer, A.J., 123, 138n Boyle, R., 10, 16, 75, 125, 134, 297n
Breazeale, D., 22n, 23n, 107n, 273n
Babich, B.E., xvii, 20n-23n, 57 a, 122n, Briggs, J.C., 140n
139n, 157n, 167n, 188,200n,203,205, Broad, C.D., 297n
216n, 217n, 219n, 273n, 275a, 275n, Bromwich, D., 215
320n Brown, W.M., 301, 310n
Bachelard, G., 216n Bruno, G., 125
Bacon, F., 10, 16, 125, 131, 133-134, 136, Buchdahl, G., 21n
139n, 140n, 214 Buckley, M.J., 140n
Bacs6, B., 21n Buechner, A., 88n
Barton, J., 16 Burckhardt, J., 187
Baudrillard, J., 17, 179-184, 185n Buss, L., 310n
Bauer, M., 258, 273n, 275n, 276n
Bell [with Harari], 157n Caesar, 79, 221
Beller, M., 219 Canguilhem, G., 311 n
Bennett, C. H., 321n Cannon, W., 299
Bergson, H., 299 Cardan, J., 86
Berkeley, G., 93, 94, 294, 297n Carnot, L., 158n
367
B. Babich (ed.), Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science: Nietzsche and the Sciences II, 367-371
© 1999 Kluwer Academic Publishers.
368 INDEX
Carnot, S., 152-153, 156, 158n, 268 Douglas, P., 20, 330n
Caspari, 0., 265 Dretske, F., 57n
Cavell, S., 22n Drews, A., 273n, 275n
Caygill, H., 24n, 177n Dtihring, E., 189, 268
Chaitin, G., 321 n Duhem, P., 216n, 218n
Char, R., 161, 162 Dumont, L., 83-86, 88n, 89n
Chisholm, R., 46n
Clark, M., I, 14, 20n, 21n, 22n, 48, 57n, Eamon, W., 139n
58n,59n, 122n, 174,273n,276n,277n Elijah, 231
Clausius, 152-153, 268 Emerson, R. W., 228
Clement XIV, 199 Empedocles, 75-76
Cohen, J., 16. 107n Engels, F., 152, 154
Cohen, R.S., 24n, 275a Epicurus, 86, 315
Colli, G. [with Montinari], 253, 255 Erasmus, 242
Columbus, C., 79, 158n Evans, F., 321n
Comte, A .. 152
Codd, E., 322n Faraone, C.A. [with Obbink], 139n
Conway, D., 16, 273n, 276n Faust, Faustus, 16, 124-125, 135, 138n,
Condillac, E.B. de, 73 209n
Copernicus, N., 75, 87n, 132-133, 158n, Faraday, M., 75
!71, 189, 192, 200n, 211,249 Fechner, G.T., 88n, 197, 270, 273n
Couliano, I., 138n Feher, M., 219n
Crescenzi, C., 273n, 276n Fere, c., 155
Crombie, A., 219 Feuerbach, L., 112, 136
Crutchfield, J.P. [&J.D. Farmer, H. Pack- Ficino, M., 140n
ard, R.S. Shaw], 330n Feigenbaum, 143
Fischer, K.R., 21n
Dalai Lama, 41 Fish, S., xv
Dante, 221 Fiumara, G.C., 219n
Danto, A., 2, 14. 21n, 253,267, 273n, 275n, Fjelland, R., 218n
276n,277n,320n Flint, V., 139n
Darwin, C., xv, 19-20, 83, 85, 96-97, lOOn, Foucault, M., 4, 99, 131, 139n, 141, 149n
107n,223-225,253, 258,272,299,307, Franklin, B., 125, 200n
309, 310 Freeman, D.A., 20n, 273n, 276n
Davies, P., 157n, 217n Frege, G., 6
Dawkins, R., 96, 217n Freud, S., 17, 335
Dear, P., 24n Friedman, M., 21n
Dee, J., 125
Delacroix, E., 12 Gadamer, H.-G., 162, 165, 166n, 167n
Deleuze, G., 141, 144, 149n, 153, 157n Galileo, G., 87n, 125, 132-133, 140n, 171,
de Man, P., 57n 199,205,208,211, 219n
Democritus, 75-77,80, 197,237 Galton, F., 309
Dennett, D., I OOn Gasche, R., 164, 167n
Derrida, J., 4, 57n, 153, 157n, 165, 167n Cast, Peter [Koselitz, H.] 188
Descartes, R., 10, 63, 67, 136, 185n, 214, Gaukroger, S., 24n
217n.228,232,294, 334,336 Geertz, C., 216, 217n, 218n
Descombes, V., 156n Gemes, K., 20n, 57n
Destutt de Tracy, A.L.C., 73 Gerber[Sh'iteJabiribnHayyan], 131, 139n
Dewey, J., 129, 139n, 206 Georg, S., 221
Diderot, D., 136 Giere, R., lOOn
Diogenes Laertius, 75 Gleick. J., 149n
Dionysus, 18, 114, 147, 151, 155, 156,203, Goethe, J.,W., 18, 87, 114, 141, 143, 209n
215,216, 219n, 236-237,302-303,315 Granet, M., 229
d'Iorio, P., 273n, 276n Granier, 1., 46n, 321n
Djuric. M. [with Simon], 273n Greisch, J., 23n
INDEX 369
Mayer, J.R., 8, 19, 152-153, 157n, 188, 189, Plato, 5, 7-9,11, 24n, 21,61-63,73-74,91,
190. 197, 258, 264-265, 266, 273n, 276n 110-111, 129, 137, 139n, 164, 182-183,
Maxwell, J.C., xv 185n,207,214, 224,227-228,230,232-
McDowell, J., 126, 139n 234,239,247,260,317
Mead, G., 129 Podolsky, S. [with Tauber], 19-20, 24n
M.erleau-Ponty, M., 309, 333. 336, 339n Poellner, P., 19, 24n, 7ln, 99n, 297n
Michele!, J., 152, 155 Poincare, H., 153, 156
Minsky, M., 319, 322n Poinsot, J. [John of St. Thomas], 151, !56
Mittasch, A., 296n Polanyi, M., 219n
Mittelmann, W., 273n Pollack, J., 322n
Moles, A., 273n, 276n, 301, 310n, 320n, Pontius Pilate, 154
321n Popper, K., 271, 296n
Montaigne, M., 187 Porn, I., 300-301, 310n
Montinari, M. [with Colli], 253, 255 Porta, D., 125, 140n
Morowitz, H.J .. 158n Poundstone, W., 158n
Moses, 231 Prigogine, I., 321n; [with Stengers], 157n,
Miiller-Lauter, W., 21n, 23n, 121n, 274n, 32ln
277n Proctor, 157n
Protagoras, 183
Nageli, C. von, 268 Psellus, M., !40n
Nagel, T., 296n Putnam, H., 129
Napoleon, I 14 Pythagoras, 8, 24n, 79, 224, 297n
Needham, P., 218n
Nehamas. A., 42, 46n, 57 a, 57n, 122n, 274n, Quine, W.v.O., 129
275a, 277n, 311n
Neumann, J. von, 322n Ranke, L., 114
Newton, I., 10, 18, 19, 171, 197,208, 219n, Raphael, 12
291,294 Ravetz, J., 140n
Neurath, 0., 13 Reason, J ., 139n
Nickles, T., 217n Ree P., 83, 88n, 187
Nola. R., 15 Reginster, B., 57a, 59n
Nordenfelt, L., 301, 310n Rehberg, A., 19, 24n
Remak, H., 275a
Obbink, D. [with Faraone] 139n Rembrandt, 12
Oehler, M., 274n Rey, A., 152
Okrent, M., 218n Ridley, A .. 177n
Oresme, N .. 79 Riedel, M., 2ln, 23n, 24n
Overbeck, F., 265 Rimbaud, A., 12
Owen, D., 17, 177n Rorty, R., 126, 129-130, 139n
Rossie, P ., 139n
Pan, 236 Rouse, J., 213, 218n
Parmenides, 7, 124, 179, 234,236,258 Rousseau, J.-J., 187
Pascal. B., 187, 199 Ruby, lOOn
Pasley, M., 311 n, Rudolph, E., 239
Pasteur. L.. 17, 154-156 Rumelhart, D.E., [& J.L. McClelland], 322n
Patterson, 1.. 275a Russell, B., !38n, 237, 263
Pautrat. B., 157n
Peirce, C. S., 129 Sacks, M., 22n
Penrose, R., 321 n Salaquarda, J., 270, 274n, 275n, 277n
Pericles, 7 5 Sartre, J.-P., 23n
Petrarch. 242 Schacht, R., 14, 22n, 24n, 37n, 48-49, 58n,
Petronievic, B., 199n 59n
Pfeffer, R., 274n, 277n Schelling, F.W.J., 63
Picht, G., 223, 229, 236, 239 Schlechta, K., 260, 274n; [with Anders],
Pico della. M .. 140n 22n-23n, 157n, 187, 200n,274n,277n
INDEX 371
1. M.W. Wartofsky (ed.): Proceedings ofthe Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science,
196111962. [Synthese Library 6] 1963 ISBN 90-277-0021-4
2. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philo-
sophy of Science, 196211964. In Honor of P. Frank. [Synthese Library 10] 1965
ISBN 90-277-9004-0
3. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philo-
sophy of Science, 1964!1966. In Memory of Norwood Russell Hanson. [Synthese Library 14]
1967 ISBN 90-277-0013-3
4. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Proceedings ofthe Boston Colloquium for the Philo-
sophy of Science, 196611968. [Synthese Library 18] 1969 ISBN 90-277-0014-l
5. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Proceedings ofthe Boston Colloquium for the Philo-
sophy of Science, 1966! 1968. [Synthese Library 19] 1969 ISBN 90-277-0015-X
6. R.S. Cohen and R.J. Seeger (eds.): Ernst Mach, Physicist and Philosopher. [Synthese Library
27] 1970 ISBN 90-277-0016-8
7. M. Capek: Bergson and Modern Physics. A Reinterpretation and Re-evaluation. [Synthese
Library 37] 1971 ISBN 90-277-0186-5
8. R.C. Buck and R.S. Cohen (eds.): PSA 1970. Proceedings of the 2nd Biennial Meeting of
the Philosophy and Science Association (Boston, Fall 1970). In Memory of Rudolf Camap.
[Synthese Library 39] 1971 ISBN 90-277-0187-3; Pb 90-277-0309-4
9. A.A. Zinov'ev: Foundations of the Logical Theory of Scientific Knowledge (Complex Logic).
Translated from Russian. Revised and enlarged English Edition, with an Appendix by G.A.
Smimov, E.A. Sidorenko, A.M. Fedina and L.A. Bobrova. [Synthese Library 46] 1973
ISBN 90-277-0193-8; Pb 90-277-0324-8
10. L. Tondl: Scientific Procedures. A Contribution Concerning the Methodological Problems of
Scientific Concepts and Scientific Explanation.Translated from Czech. [Synthese Library 47]
1973 ISBN 90-277-0147-4; Pb 90-277-0323-X
11. R.J. Seeger and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Philosophical Foundations of Science. Proceedings of
Section L, 1969, American Association for the Advancement of Science. [Synthese Library
58] 1974 ISBN 90-277-0390-6; Pb 90-277-0376-0
12. A. Gr-nbaum: Philosophical Problems of Space and Times. 2nd enlarged ed. [Synthese Library
55] 1973 ISBN 90-277-0357-4; Pb 90-277-0358-2
13. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary
Physics. Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science, 1969/72, Part
I. [Synthese Library 59] 1974 ISBN 90-277-0391-4; Pb 90-277-0377-9
14. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Methodological and Historical Essays in the Natural
and Social Sciences. Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science,
1969/72, Part II. [Synthese Library 60] 1974 ISBN 90-277-0392-2; Pb 90-277-0378-7
15. R.S. Cohen, J.J. Stachel and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): For Dirk Struik. Scientific, Historical and
Political Essays in Honor of Dirk J. Struik. [Synthese Library 61] 1974
ISBN 90-277-0393-0; Pb 90-277-0379-5
16. N. Geschwind: Selected Papers on Language and the Brains. [Synthese Library 68] 1974
ISBN 90-277-0262-4; Pb 90-277-0263-2
17. B.G. Kuznetsov: Reason and Being. Translated from Russian. Edited by C.R. Fawcett and R.S.
Cohen. 1987 ISBN 90-277-2181-5
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
18. P. Mittelstaedt: Philosophical Problems of Modern Physics. Translated from the revised 4th
German edition by W. Riemer and edited by R.S. Cohen. [Synthese Library 95] 1976
ISBN 90-277-0285-3; Pb 90-277-0506-2
19. H. Mehlberg: Time, Causality, and the Quantum Theory. Studies in the Philosophy of Science.
Vol. 1: Essay on the Causal Theory of Time. Vol. II: Time in a Quantized Universe. Translated
from French. Edited by R.S. Cohen. 1980 Vol. 1: ISBN 90-277-0721-9; Pb 90-277-1074-0
Vol. II: ISBN 90-277-1075-9; Pb 90-277-1076-7
20. K.F. Schaffner and R.S. Cohen (eds.): PSA 1972. Proceedings of the 3rd Biennial Meeting of
the Philosophy of Science Association (Lansing, Michigan, Fall 1972). [Synthese Library 64]
1974 ISBN 90-277-0408-2; Pb 90-277-0409-0
21. R.S. Cohen and J.J. Stachel (eds.): Selected Papers ofL9on Rosenfeld. [Synthese Library 100]
1979 ISBN 90-277-0651-4; Pb 90-277-0652-2
22. M. Capek (ed.): The Concepts of Space and Time. Their Structure and Their Development.
[Synthese Library 74] 1976 ISBN 90-277-0355-8; Pb 90-277-0375-2
23. M. Grene: The Understanding of Nature. Essays in the Philosophy of Biology. [Synthese
Library 66] 1974 ISBN 90-277-0462-7; Pb 90-277-0463-5
24. D. Ihde: Technics and Praxis. A Philosophy of Technology. [Synthese Library 130] 1979
ISBN 90-277-0953-X; Pb 90-277-0954-8
25. J. Hintikka and U. Remes: The Method of Analysis. Its Geometrical Origin and Its General
Significance. [Synthese Library 75] 1974 ISBN 90-277-0532-1; Pb 90-277-0543-7
26. J.E. Murdoch and E.D. Sylla (eds.): The Cultural Context of Medieval Learning. Proceedings
of the First International Colloquium on Philosophy, Science, and Theology in the Middle
Ages, 1973. [Synthese Library 76] 1975 ISBN 90-277-0560-7; Pb 90-277-0587-9
27. M. Grene and E. Mendelsohn (eds.): Topics in the Philosophy of Biology. [Synthese Library
84] 1976 ISBN 90-277-0595-X; Pb 90-277-0596-8
28. J. Agassi: Science in Flux. [Synthese Library 80] 1975
ISBN 90-277-0584-4; Pb 90-277-0612-3
29. J.J. Wiatr (ed.): Polish Essays in the Methodology of the Social Sciences. [Synthese Library
131] 1979 ISBN 90-277-0723-5; Pb 90-277-0956-4
30. P. Janich: Protophysics of Time. Constructive Foundation and History of Time Measurement.
Translated from German. 1985 ISBN 90-277-0724-3
31. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Language, Logic, and Method. 1983
ISBN 90-277-0725-1
32. R.S. Cohen, C.A. Hooker, A.C. Michalos and J.W. van Evra (eds.): PSA 1974. Proceedings
of the 4th Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association. [Synthese Library I0 I]
1976 ISBN 90-277-0647-6; Pb 90-277-0648-4
33. G. Holton and W.A. Blanpied (eds.): Science and Its Public. The Changing Relationship.
[Synthese Library 96] 1976 ISBN 90-277-0657-3; Pb 90-277-0658-1
34. M.D. Grmek, R.S. Cohen and G. Cimino (eds.): On Scientific Discovery. The 1977 Erice
Lectures. 1981 ISBN 90-277-1122-4; Pb 90-277-1123-2
35. S. Amsterdamski: Between Experience and Metaphysics. Philosophical Problems of the Evol-
ution of Science. Translated from Polish. [Synthese Library 77] 1975
ISBN 90-277-0568-2; Pb 90-277-0580-1
36. M. Markovic and G. Petrovic (eds.): Praxis. Yugoslav Essays in the Philosophy and Method-
ology of the Social Sciences. [S ynthese Library 134] 1979
ISBN 90-277-0727-8; Pb 90-277-0968-8
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
37. H. von Helmholtz: Epistemological Writings. The Paul Hertz I Moritz Schlick Centenary
Edition of 1921. Translated from German by M.F. Lowe. Edited with an Introduction and
Bibliography by R.S. Cohen andY. Elkana. [Synthese Library 79] 1977
ISBN 90-277-0290-X; Pb 90-277-0582-8
38. R.M. Martin: Pragmatics, Truth and Language. 1979
ISBN 90-277-0992-0; Pb 90-277-0993-9
39. R.S. Cohen, P.K. Feyerabend and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Essays in Memory ofimre Lakatos.
[Synthese Library 99] 1976 ISBN 90-277-0654-9; Pb 90-277-0655-7
40. Not published.
41. Not published.
42. H.R. Maturana and F.J. Varela: Autopoiesis and Cognition. The Realization of the Living. With
a Preface to "Autopoiesis' by S. Beer. 1980 ISBN 90-277-1015-5; Pb 90-277-1016-3
43. A. Kasher (ed.): Language in Focus: Foundations, Methods and Systems. Essays in Memory
of Yehoshua Bar-Hillel. [Synthese Library 89] 1976
ISBN 90-277-0644-1; Pb 90-277-0645-X
44. T.D. Thao: Investigations into the Origin of Language and Consciousness. 1984
ISBN 90-277-0827-4
45. F.G.-1. Nagasaka (ed.): Japanese Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 1997
ISBN 0-7923-4781-1
46. P.L. Kapitza: Experiment, Theory, Practice. Articles and Addresses. Edited by R.S. Cohen.
1980 ISBN 90-277-1061-9; Pb 90-277-1062-7
47. M.L. Dalla Chiara (ed.): Italian Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 1981
ISBN 90-277-0735-9; Pb 90-277-1073-2
48. M.W. Wartofsky: Models. Representation and the Scientific Understanding. [Synthese Library
129] 1979 ISBN 90-277-0736-7; Pb 90-277-0947-5
49. T.D. Thao: Phenomenology and Dialectical Materialism. Edited by R.S. Cohen. 1986
ISBN 90-277-0737-5
50. Y. Fried and J. Agassi: Paranoia. A Study in Diagnosis. [Synthese Library 102] 1976
ISBN 90-277-0704-9; Pb 90-277-0705-7
51. K.H. Wolff: Surrender and Cath. Experience and Inquiry Today. [Synthese Library 105] 1976
ISBN 90-277-0758-8; Pb 90-277-0765-0
52. K. Kosik: Dialectics of the Concrete. A Study on Problems of Man and World. 1976
ISBN 90-277-0761-8; Pb 90-277-0764-2
53. N. Goodman: The Structure ofAppearance. [Synthese Library 107] 1977
ISBN 90-277-0773-1; Pb 90-277-0774-X
54. H.A. Simon: Models of Discovery and Other Topics in the Methods of Science. [Synthese
Library 114] 1977 ISBN 90-277-0812-6; Pb 90-277-0858-4
55. M. Lazerowitz: The Language of Philosophy. Freud and Wittgenstein. [Synthese Library 117]
1977 ISBN 90-277-0826-6; Pb 90-277-0862-2
56. T. Nickles (ed.): Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality. 1980
ISBN 90-277-1069-4; Pb 90-277-1070-8
57. J. Margolis: Persons and Mind. The Prospects ofNonreductive Materialism. [Synthese Library
121] 1978 ISBN 90-277-0854-1; Pb 90-277-0863-0
58. G. Radnitzky and G. Andersson (eds.): Progress and Rationality in Science. [Synthese Library
125] 1978 ISBN 90-277-0921-1; Pb 90-277-0922-X
59. G. Radnitzky and G. Andersson (eds.): The Structure and Development of Science. [Synthese
Library 136] 1979 ISBN 90-277-0994-7; Pb 90-277-0995-5
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
60. T. Nickles (ed.): Scientific Discovery. Case Studies. 1980
ISBN 90-277-1092-9; Pb 90-277-1093-7
61. M.A. Finocchiaro: Galileo and the Art of Reasoning. Rhetorical Foundation of Logic and
Scientific Method. 1980 ISBN 90-277-1094-5; Pb 90-277-1095-3
62. W.A. Wallace: Prelude to Galileo. Essays on Medieval and 16th-Century Sources of Galilee's
Thought. 1981 ISBN 90-277-1215-8; Pb 90-277-1216-6
63. F. Rapp: Analytical Philosophy of Technology. Translated from German. 1981
ISBN 90-277-1221-2; Pb 90-277-1222-0
64. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Hegel and the Sciences. 1984 ISBN 90-277-0726-X
65. J. Agassi: Science and Society. Studies in the Sociology of Science. 1981
ISBN 90-277-1244-1; Pb 90-277-1245-X
66. L. Tondl: Problems of Semantics. A Contribution to the Analysis of the Language of Science.
Translated from Czech. 1981 ISBN 90-277-0148-2; Pb 90-277-0316-7
67. J. Agassi and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Scientific Philosophy Today. Essays in Honor of Mario Bunge.
1982 ISBN 90-277-1262-X; Pb 90-277-1263-8
68. W. Krajewski (ed.): Polish Essays in the Philosophy of the Natural Sciences. Translated from
Polish and edited by R.S. Cohen and C.R. Fawcett. 1982
ISBN 90-277-1286-7; Pb 90-277-1287-5
69. J.H. Fetzer: Scientific Knowledge. Causation, Explanation and Corroboration. 1981
ISBN 90-277-1335-9; Pb 90-277-1336-7
70. S. Grossberg: Studies ofMind and Brain. Neural Principles of Learning, Perception, Develop-
ment, Cognition, and Motor Control. 1982 ISBN 90-277-1359-6; Pb 90-277-1360-X
71. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Epistemology, Methodology, and the Social Sciences.
1983. ISBN 90-277-1454-1
72. K. Berka: Measurement. Its Concepts, Theories and Problems. Translated from Czech. 1983
ISBN 90-277-1416-9
73. G.L. Pandit: The Structure and Growth of Scientific Knowledge. A Study in the Methodology
ofEpistemic Appraisal. 1983 ISBN 90-277-1434-7
74. A.A. Zinov'ev: Logical Physics. Translated from Russian. Edited by R.S. Cohen. 1983
[see also Volume 9) ISBN 90-277-0734-0
75. G-G. Granger: Formal Thought and the Sciences of Man. Translated from French. With and
Introduction by A. Rosenberg. 1983 ISBN 90-277-1524-6
76. R.S. Cohen and L. Laudan (eds.): Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis. Ess<iys in Honor
of Adolf Gr-nbaum. 1983 ISBN 90-277-1533-5
77. G. Bhme, W. van den Daele, R. Hohlfeld, W. Krohn and W. Schlfer: Finalization in Science.
The Social Orientation of Scientific Progress. Translated from German. Edited by W. Schlfer.
1983 ISBN 90-277-1549-1
78. D. Shapere: Reason and the Search for Knowledge. Investigations in the Philosophy of Science.
1984 ISBN 90-277-1551-3; Pb 90-277-1641-2
79. G. Andersson (ed.): Rationality in Science and Politics. Translated from German. 1984
ISBN 90-277-1575-0; Pb 90-277-1953-5
80. P.T. Durbin and F. Rapp (eds.): Philosophy and Technology. [Also Philosophy and Technology
Series, Vol. 1)1983 ISBN 90-277-1576-9
81. M. Markovic: Dialectical Theory of Meaning. Translated from Serbo-Croat. 1984
ISBN 90-277-1596-3
82. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Physical Sciences and History of Physics. 1984.
ISBN 90-277-1615-3
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
83. E. Meyerson: The Relativistic Deduction. Epistemological Implications of the Theory of
Relativity. Translated from French. With a Review by Albert Einstein and an Introduction
by Milic Capek. 1985 ISBN 90-277-1699-4
84. R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Methodology, Metaphysics and the History of Science.
In Memory of Benjamin Nelson. 1984 ISBN 90-277-1711-7
85. G. Tams: The Logic of Categories. Translated from Hungarian. Edited by R.S. Cohen. 1986
ISBN 90-277-1742-7
86. S.L. de C. Fernandes: Foundations of Objective Knowledge. The Relations of Popper's Theory
of Knowledge to That of Kant. 1985 ISBN 90-277-1809-1
87. R.S. Cohen and T. Schnelle (eds.): Cognition and Fact. Materials on Ludwik Fleck. 1986
ISBN 90-277-1902-0
88. G. Freudenthal: Atom and Individual in the Age of Newton. On the Genesis of the Mechanistic
World View. Translated from German. 1986 ISBN 90-277-1905-5
89. A. Donagan, A.N. Perovich Jr and M.V. Wedin (eds.): Human Nature and Natural Knowledge.
Essays presented to Marjorie Grene on the Occasion of Her 75th Birthday. 1986
ISBN 90-277-1974-8
90. C. Mitcham and A. Running (eds.): Philosophy and Technology//. Information Technology
and Computers in Theory and Practice. [Also Philosophy and Technology Series, Vol. 2] 1986
ISBN 90-277-1975-6
91. M. Grene and D. Nails (eds.): Spinoza and the Sciences. 1986 ISBN 90-277-1976-4
92. S.P. Turner: The Search for a Methodology of Social Science. Durkheim, Weber, and the
19th-Century Problem of Cause, Probability, and Action. 1986. ISBN 90-277-2067-3
93. I.C. Jarvie: Thinking about Society. Theory and Practice. 1986 ISBN 90-277-2068-1
94. E. Ullmann-Margalit (ed.): The Kaleidoscope of Science. The Israel Colloquium: Studies in
History, Philosophy, and Sociology of Science, Vol. 1. 1986
ISBN 90-277-2158-0; Pb 90-277-2159-9
95. E. Ullmann-Margalit (ed.): The Prism of Science. The Israel Colloquium: Studies in History,
Philosophy, and Sociology of Science, Vol. 2. 1986
ISBN 90-277-2160-2; Pb 90-277-2161-0
96. G. Mrkus: Language and Production. A Critique of the Paradigms. Translated from French.
1986 ISBN 90-277-2169-6
97. F. Amrine, F.J. Zucker and H. Wheeler (eds.): Goethe and the Sciences: A Reappraisal. 1987
ISBN 90-277-2265-X; Pb 90-277-2400-8
98. J.C. Pitt and M. Pera (eds.): Rational Changes in Science. Essays on Scientific Reasoning.
Translated from Italian. 1987 ISBN 90-277-2417-2
99. 0. Costa de Beauregard: Time, the Physical Magnitude. 1987 ISBN 90-277-2444-X
100. A. Shimony and D. Nails (eds.): Naturalistic Epistemology. A Symposium of 1\vo Decades.
1987 ISBN 90-277-2337-0
101. N. Rotenstreich: Time and Meaning in History. 1987 ISBN 90-277-2467-9
102. D.B. Zilberman: The Birth of Meaning in Hindu Thought. Edited by R.S. Cohen. 1988
ISBN 90-277-2497-0
103. T.F. Glick (ed.): The Comparative Reception of Relativity. 1987 ISBN 90-277-2498-9
104. Z. Harris, M. Gottfried, T. Ryckman, P. Mattick Jr, A. Daladier, T.N. Harris and S. Harris: The
Form of Information in Science. Analysis of an Immunology Sublanguage. With a Preface by
Hilary Putnam. 1989 ISBN 90-277-2516-0
105. F. Burwick (ed.): Approaches to Organic Form. Permutations in Science and Culture. 1987
ISBN 90-277-2541-1
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
I06. M. Almsi: The Philosophy ofAppearances. Translated from Hungarian. 1989
ISBN 90-277-2150-5
107. S. Hook, W.L. O'Neill and R. O'Toole (eds.): Philosophy, History and Social Action. Essays
in Honor of Lewis Feuer. With an Autobiographical Essay by L. Feuer. 1988
ISBN 90-277-2644-2
108. I. Hronszky, M. Feh<;r and B. Dajka: Scientific Knowledge Socialized. Selected Proceedings
of the 5th Joint International Conference on the History and Philosophy of Science organized
by the IUHPS (Veszpr<;m, Hungary, 1984). 1988 ISBN 90-277-2284-6
109. P. Tillers and E.D. Green (eds.): Probability and Inference in the Law of Evidence. The Uses
and Limits of Bayesianism. 1988 ISBN 90-277-2689-2
110. E. Ullmann-Margalit (ed.): Science in Reflection. The Israel Colloquium: Studies in History,
Philosophy, and Sociology of Science, Vol. 3. 1988
ISBN 90-277-2712-0; Pb 90-277-2713-9
Ill. K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis and P. Nicolacopoulos (eds.): lmre Lakatos and Theories of
Scientific Change. 1989 ISBN 90-277-2766-X
112. B. Glassner and J.D. Moreno (eds.): The Qualitative-Quantitative Distinction in the Social
Sciences. 1989 ISBN 90-277-2829-1
113. K. Arens: Structures of Knowing. Psychologies of the 19th Century. 1989
ISBN 0-7923-0009-2
114. A. Janik: Style, Politics and the Future of Philosophy. 1989 ISBN 0-7923-0056-4
115. F. Amrine (ed.): Literature and Science as Modes of Expression. With an Introduction by S.
Weininger. 1989 ISBN 0-7923-0133-1
116. J.R. Brown and J. Mittelstrass (eds.): An Intimate Relation. Studies in the History and Philo-
sophy of Science. Presented to Robert E. Butts on His 60th Birthday. 1989
ISBN 0-7923-0169-2
117. F. D'Agostino and I.C. Jarvie (eds.): Freedom and Rationality. Essays in Honor of John
Watkins. 1989 ISBN 0-7923-0264-8
118. D. Zolo: Reflexive Epistemology. The Philosophical Legacy of Otto Neurath. 1989
ISBN 0-7923-0320-2
119. M. Kearn, B.S. Philips and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Georg Simmel and Contemporary Sociology.
1989 ISBN 0-7923-0407-1
120. T.H. Levere and W.R. Shea (eds.): Nature, Experiment and the Science. Essays on Galileo and
the Nature of Science. In Honour of Stillman Drake. 1989 ISBN 0-7923-0420-9
121. P. Nicolacopoulos (ed.): Greek Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science. 1990
ISBN 0-7923-0717-8
122. R. Cooke and D. Costantini (eds.): Statistics in Science. The Foundations of Statistical Methods
in Biology, Physics and Economics. 1990 ISBN 0-7923-0797-6
123. P. Duhem: The Origins of Statics. Translated from French by G.F. Leneaux, V.N. Vagliente
and G.H. Wagner. With an Introduction by S.L. Jaki. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-0898-0
124. H. Kamerlingh Onnes: Through Measurement to Knowledge. The Selected Papers, 1853-1926.
Edited and with an Introduction by K. Gavroglu andY. Goudaroulis. 1991
ISBN 0-7923-0825-5
125. M. Capek: The New Aspects of Time: Its Continuity and Novelties. Selected Papers in the
Philosophy of Science. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-0911-1
126. S. Unguru (ed.): Physics, Cosmology and Astronomy, 1300-1700. Tension and Accommoda-
tion. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1022-5
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
127. Z. Bechler: Newton's Physics on the Conceptual Structure of the Scientific Revolution. 1991
ISBN 0-7923-1054-3
128. E. Meyerson: Explanation in the Sciences. Translated from French by M-A. Siple and D.A.
Siple. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1129-9
129. A.I. Tauber (ed.): Organism and the Origins of Self. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1185-X
130. F.J. Varela and J-P. Dupuy (eds.): Understanding Origins. Contemporary Views on the Origin
of Life, Mind and Society. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1251-1
131. G.L. Pandit: Methodological Variance. Essays in Epistemological Ontology and the Method-
ology of Science. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1263-5
132. G. Mun<;var (ed.): Beyond Reason. Essays on the Philosophy of Paul Feyerabend. 1991
ISBN 0-7923-1272-4
133. T.E. Uebel (ed.): Rediscovering the Forgotten Vienna Circle. Austrian Studies on Otto Neurath
and the Vienna Circle. Partly translated from German. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1276-7
134. W.R. Woodward and R.S. Cohen (eds.): World Views and Scientific Discipline Formation.
Science Studies in the [former] German Democratic Republic. Partly translated from German
by W.R. Woodward. 1991 ISBN 0-7923-1286-4
135. P. Zambelli: The Speculum Astronomiae and Its Enigma. Astrology, Theology and Science in
Albertus Magnus and His Contemporaries. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1380-1
136. P. Petitjean, C. Jami and A.M. Moulin (eds.): Science and Empires. Historical Studies about
Scientific Development and European Expansion. ISBN 0-7923-1518-9
137. W.A. Wallace: Galileo's Logic ofDiscovery and Proof. The Background, Content, and Use of
His Appropriated Treatises on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1577-4
138. W.A. Wallace: Galileo' s Logical Treatises. A Translation, with Notes and Commentary, of His
Appropriated Latin Questions on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1578-2
Set (137 + 138) ISBN 0-7923-1579-0
139. M.J. Nye, J.L. Richards and R.H. Sn1ewer (eds.): The Invention of Physical Science. Intersec-
tions of Mathematics, Theology and Natural Philosophy since the Seventeenth Century. Essays
in Honor of Erwin N. Hiebert. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1753-X
140. G. Corsi, M.L. dalla Chiara and G.C. Ghirardi (eds.): Bridging the Gap: Philosophy, Mathem-
atics and Physics. Lectures on the Foundations of Science. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1761-0
141. C.-H. Lin and D. Fu (eds.): Philosophy and Conceptual History of Science in Taiwan. 1992
ISBN 0-7923-1766-1
142. S. Sarkar (ed.): The Founders of Evolutionary Genetics. A Centenary Reappraisal. 1992
ISBN 0-7923-1777-7
143. J. Blackmore (ed.): Ernst Mach -A Deeper Look. Documents and New Perspectives. 1992
ISBN 0-7923-1853-6
144. P. Kroes and M. Bakker (eds.): Technological Development and Science in the Industrial Age.
New Perspectives on the Science-Technology Relationship. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1898-6
145. S. Amsterdamski: Between History and Method. Disputes about the Rationality of Science.
1992 ISBN 0-7923-1941-9
146. E. Ullmann-Margalit (ed.): The Scientific Enterprise. The Bar-Hillel Colloquium: Studies in
History, Philosophy, and Sociology of Science, Volume 4. 1992 ISBN 0-7923-1992-3
147. L. Embree (ed.): Metaarchaeology. Reflections by Archaeologists and Philosophers. 1992
ISBN 0-7923-2023-9
148. S. French and H. Kamminga (eds.): Correspondence, Invariance and Heuristics. Essays in
Honour of Heinz Post. 1993 ISBN 0-7923-2085-9
149. M. Bunzl: The Context of Explanation. 1993 ISBN 0-7923-2153-7
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
150. I.B. Cohen (ed.): The Natural Sciences and the Social Sciences. Some Critical and Historical
Perspectives. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2223-1
151. K. Gavroglu, Y. Christianidis and E. Nicolaidis (eds.): Trends in the Historiography of Science.
1994 ISBN 0-7923-2255-X
152. S. Poggi and M. Bossi (eds.): Romanticism in Science. Science in Europe, 1790-1840. 1994
ISBN 0-7923-2336-X
153. J. Faye and H.J. Folse (eds.): Niels Bohr and Contemporary Philosophy. 1994
ISBN 0-7923-2378-5
154. C.C. Gould and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Artifacts, Representations, and Social Practice. Essays for
Marx W. Wartofsky. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2481-1
155. R.E. Butts: Historical Pragmatics. Philosophical Essays. 1993 ISBN 0-7923-2498-6
156. R. Rashed: The Development ofArabic Mathematics: Between Arithmetic and Algebra. Trans-
lated from French by A.F.W. Armstrong. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2565-6
157. I. Szumilewicz-Lachman (ed.): Zygmunt Zawirski: His Life and Work. With Selected Writings
on Time, Logic and the Methodology of Science. Translations by Feliks Lachman. Ed. by R.S.
Cohen, with the assistance of B. Bergo. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2566-4
158. S.N. Hag: Names, Natures and Things. The AlchemistJabir ibn Hayyan and His Kitiib al-Ahjiir
(BookofStones).l994 ISBN0-7923-2587-7
159. P. Plaass: Kant's Theory ofNatural Science. Translation, Analytic Introduction and Comment-
ary by Alfred E. and Maria G. Miller. 1994 ISBN 0-7923-2750-0
160. J. Misiek (ed·.): The Problem of Rationality in Science and its Philosophy. On Popper vs.
Polanyi. The Polish Conferences 1988-89. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-2925-2
161. I.C. Jarvie and N. Laor (eds.): Critical Rationalism. Metaphysics and Science. Essays for
Joseph Agassi, Volume I. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-2960-0
162. I.C. Jarvie and N. Laor (eds.): Critical Rationalism, the Social Sciences and the Humanities.
Essays for Joseph Agassi, Volume II. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-2961-9
Set (161-162) ISBN 0-7923-2962-7
163. K. Gavroglu, J. Stachel and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Physics, Philosophy, and the Scientific
Community. Essays in the Philosophy and History of the Natural Sciences and Mathematics.
In Honor of Robert S. Cohen. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-2988-0
164. K. Gavroglu, J. Stachel and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Science, Politics and Social Practice.
Essays on Marxism and Science, Philosophy of Culture and the Social Sciences. In Honor of
RobertS. Cohen. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-2989-9
165. K. Gavroglu, J. Stachel and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): Science, Mind and Art. Essays on Science
and the Humanistic Understanding in Art, Epistemology, Religion and Ethics. Essays in Honor
of Robert S. Cohen. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-2990-2
Set (163-165) ISBN 0-7923-2991-0
166. K.H. Wolff: Transformation in the Writing. A Case of Surrender~and-Catch. 1995
ISBN 0-7923-3178-8
167. A.J. Kox and D.M. Siegel (eds.): No Truth Except in the Details. Essays in Honor of Martin J.
Klein. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3195-8
168. J. Blackmore: Ludwig Boltzmann, His Later Life and Philosophy, 1900-1906. Book One: A
Documentary History. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3231-8
169. R.S. Cohen, R. Hilpinen and R. Qiu (eds.): Realism and Anti-Realism in the Philosophy of
Science. Beijing International Conference, 1992. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-3233-4
170. I. Ku9uradi and R.S. Cohen (eds.): The Concept of Knowledge. The Ankara Seminar. 1995
ISBN 0-7923-3241-5
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
171. M.A. Grodin (ed.): Meta Medical Ethics: The Philosophical Foundations of Bioethics. 1995
ISBN 0-7923-3344-6
172. S. Ramirez and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Mexican Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.
1995 ISBN 0-7923-3462-0
173. C. Dilworth: The Metaphysics of Science. An Account of Modem Science in Terms of Prin-
ciples, Laws and Theories. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3693-3
174. J. Blackmore: Ludwig Boltzmann, His Later Life and Philosophy, 1900-1906 Book Two: The
Philosopher. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3464-7
175. P. Damerow: Abstraction and Representation. Essays on the Cultural Evolution of Thinking.
1996 ISBN 0-7923-3816-2
176. M.S. Macrakis: Scarcity's Ways: The Origins ofCapital. A Critical Essay on Thermodynamics,
Statistical Mechanics and Economics. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4760-9
177. M. Marion and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Qu(:bec Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Part I: Logic,
Mathematics, Physics and History of Science. Essays in Honor of Hugues Leblanc. 1995
ISBN 0-7923-3559-7
178. M. Marion and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Qu(:bec Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Part II:
Biology, Psychology, Cognitive Science and Economics. Essays in Honor of Hugues Leblanc.
1996
ISBN 0-7923-3560-0
Set ( 177-178) ISBN 0-7923-3561-9
179. Fan Dainian and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Chinese Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science
and Technology. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-3463-9
180. P. Forman and J.M. Snchez-Ron (eds.): National Military Establishments and the Advancement
of Science and Technology. Studies in 20th Century History. 1996
ISBN 0-7923-3541-4
181. E.J. Post: Quantum Reprogramming. Ensembles and Single Systems: A 1\vo-Tier Approach
to Quantum Mechanics. 1995 ISBN 0-7923-3565-1
182. A.I. Tauber (ed.): The Elusive Synthesis: Aesthetics and Science. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-3904-5
183. S. Sarkar (ed.): The Philosophy and History of Molecular Biology: New Perspectives. 1996
ISBN 0-7923-3947-9
184. J.T. Cushing, A. Fine and S. Goldstein (eds.): Bohmian Mechanics and Quantum Theory: An
Appraisal. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-4028-0
185. K. Michalski: Logic and Time. An Essay on Husserl's Theory of Meaning. 1996
ISBN 0-7923-4082-5
186. G. Mun<;:var (ed.): Spanish Studies in the Philosophy of Science. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-4147-3
187. G. Schubring (ed.): Hermann G-nther GrajJmann (1809-1877): Visionary Mathematician,
Scientist and Neohumanist Scholar. Papers from a Sesquicentennial Conference. 1996
ISBN 0-7923-4261-5
188. M. Bitbol: Schrdinger's Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-42fi6-6
189. J. Faye, U. Scheffler and M. Urchs (eds.): Perspectives on Time. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4330-1
190. K. Lehrer and J.C. Marek (eds.): Austrian Philosophy Past and Present. Essays in Honor of
Rudolf Haller. 1996 ISBN 0-7923-4347-6
191. J.L. Lagrange: Analytical Mechanics. Translated and edited by Auguste Boissonade and Victor
N. Vagliente. Translated from the M(:canique Analytique, novelle (:dition of 1811. 1997
ISBN 0-7923-4349-2
192. D. Ginev and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Issues and Images in the Philosophy of Science. Scientific
and Philosophical Essays in Honour of Azarya Polikarov. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4444-8
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science
193. R.S. Cohen, M. Home and J. Stachel (eds.): Experimental Metaphysics. Quantum Mechanical
Studies for Abner Shimony, Volume One. 1997 ISBN 0-7923-4452-9
194. R.S. Cohen, M. Home and J. Stachel (eds.): Potentiality. Entanglement and Passion-at-a-
Distance. Quantum Mechanical Studies for Abner Shimony, Volume Two. 1997
ISBN 0-7923-4453-7; Set 0-7923-4454-5
195. R.S. Cohen and A.l. Tauber (eds.): Philosophies of Nature: The Human Dimension. 1998
ISBN 0-7923-4579-7
196. M. Otte and M. Panza (eds.): Analysis and Synthesis in Mathematics. History and Philosophy.
1997 ISBN 0-7923-4570-3
197. A. Denkel: The Natural Background of Meaning. 1999 ISBN 0-7923-5331-5
198. D. Baird, R.I.G. Hughes and A. Nordmann (eds.): Heinrich Hertz: Classical Physicist, Modern
Philosopher. 1999 ISBN 0-7923-4653-X
199. A. Franklin: Can That be Right? Essays on Experiment, Evidence, and Science. 1999
ISBN 0-7923-5464-8
200. Reserved
20 I. Reserved
202. Reserved
203. B. Babich and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Nietzsche, Theories of Knowledge, and Critical Theory.
Nietzsche and the Sciences I. 1999
ISBN 0-7923-57 42-6
204. B. Babich and R.S. Cohen (eds.): Nietzsche, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science. Nietz-
sche and the Sciences II. 1999
ISBN 0-7923-5743-4; Set 0-7923-5778-7
Also of interest:
R.S. Cohen and M.W. Wartofsky (eds.): A Portrait of Twenty-Five Years Boston Colloquia for the
Philosophy of Science, 1960-1985. 1985 ISBN Pb 90-277-1971-3
Previous volumes are still available.