Uwe Wirth - Derrida and Peirce On Indeterminacy
Uwe Wirth - Derrida and Peirce On Indeterminacy
UWE WIRTH
Peirce goes very far in the direction that I have called the deconstruction of the
transcendental signified, which, at one time or another, would place a reassuring
end to the reference from sign to sign. I have identified logocentrism and the
metaphysics of presence as the exigent, powerful, systematic, and irrepressible
desire for such a signified. Now, Peirce considers the indefiniteness of reference as
the criterion that allows us to recognize that we are indeed dealing with a system of
signs. What broaches the movement of signification is what makes its interruption
impossible. The thing itself is a sign. (Derrida 1976 [1967]: 49)
In his chapter on ‘Unlimited semiosis and drift’, Eco (1990: 36) raises the
question as to whether Peirce ‘would have been satisfied with Derrida’s
interpretation’. The answer to this question is, of course, negative since
‘deconstructive drift and unlimited semiosis cannot be equivalent con-
cepts’ (ibid.). Eco’s argumentative strategy is to admit, on the one hand,
the ‘openness’ of Peirce’s concept of unlimited semiosis ‘for further
determination’. On the other hand, Eco suggests that Derrida had to
refuse the idea of such a determination since the ‘deferral’ of diffe´rance
implies a fundamental ‘indeterminacy’ of the whole dynamics of inter-
pretation, not only in the past and present, but also in the future. ‘I am
simply repeating with Peirce’, Eco (1990: 39) writes, ‘that ‘‘an endless
series of representations, each representing the one behind it’’ (and until
this point Derrida could not but agree with this formula), ‘‘may be
conceived to have an absolute object as its limit’’ (CP 1.339)’. Eco claims
that the idea of an ‘absolute object’ is incompatible with the decon-
structive framework, since it implies that ‘outside the immediate
interpretant, the emotional, the energetic, and the logical one — all
internal to the course of semiosis — there is a final logical interpretant,
that is, Habit’ (Ibid.). Let us disregard whether Peirce would be satisfied
with Eco’s interpretation of the final interpretant as something ‘outside
semiosis’. Instead, let us complete the passages from Peirce that Eco
wisely left out in his quotation:
[A sign] is a vehicle conveying into the mind something from without. That for
which it stands is called its object; that which it conveys, its meaning; and the idea
to which it gives rise, its interpretant. The object of representation can be nothing
but a representation of which the first representation is the interpretant. But
an endless series of representations, each representing the one behind it, may be
conceived to have an absolute object at its limit. (CP 1.339)
Of course, we understand why Eco left out the passage that ‘the object
of representation can be nothing but a representation of which the first
representation is the interpretant’. It sounds as if Derrida had formulated
it and, furthermore, it does not fit in with Eco’s argumentation. Since
the object of representation as well as its interpretant is ‘nothing but
a representation’, there cannot be, at least if we take Peirce seriously,
anything ‘outside semiosis’: neither an ‘absolute object’ nor a ‘final
interpretant’.
At this point, we are apparently confronted with a ‘critical situ-
ation’, which is a ‘crisis of interpretation’ rather than a ‘crisis of
representation’. As in any crisis,1 there is a ‘general uncertainty’ at this
point. We do not know whether it is the Peircean account of semiosis
that is equivocal and vague or whether it is Eco who is molding Peirce
in order to make his theories fit in with Eco’s own strategic purpose,
namely a critique of Derrida’s interpretation of the Peircean account
of semiosis.
In the following discussion, I will raise two points. Firstly, I will call
into question whether the so-called ‘Derridaean problem’ of indetermi-
nacy can be resolved by using the Peircean notion of a limiting ‘final
interpretant’ conceived of as ‘habit’. Secondly, I will discuss Derrida’s
notion of ‘iterability’ in the context of Peircean semiotics and relate it to
representation in general and to the type-token relation of replica signs in
particular.
Derrida and Peirce 37
[It] is noticeable that the iteration of the action is often said to be indispensable
to the formation of a habit; but a very moderate exercise of observation suffices
to refute this error. A single reading yesterday of a casual statement that ‘shtar
chindis’ means in Romany ‘four shillings’ _ is likely to produce the habit of
thinking that ‘four’ in the Gypsy tongue is ‘shtar’, that will last for months, if not
for years, though I should never call it to mind in the interval. (CP 5.477)3
In a certain way, this quote links our first topic concerning the deter-
mination of the sign with our second topic concerning its iterability, but
if repetition is essential to representation, we are faced with the question,
what is it that gets repeated? According to Derrida (1988 [1977]: 7; see
previous discussion) there is a ‘repeating and thus identifying [of ] the
marks’. However, Searle (1993: 8) objects that ‘actual marks and signs,
that is, actual physical tokens, are precisely not iterable. It is, rather, the
type of mark that can have different instantiations. This is one way of
saying that it is types and not tokens that allow for repeated instances of
the same’.4
In this passage, Peirce seems to refer to two different rules. The first
concerns the sign itself — I would like to call it the law of replication —
and the second concerns the relation between the sign and its meaning.
This ‘general rule of meaning’ is a rule of signification, i.e., a code. The
‘significative value of a symbol consists in a regularity of association’
(CP 4.500), which ‘depends either upon a convention, a habit, or a natural
disposition’ (CP 8.335). However, since symbols are always abstract and
general, because habits are general rules to which the organism has
become subjected’ (CP 3.360), they must be embodied in replicas, in order
to be informational. Peirce describes this act of application as ‘translat-
ing every abstractly expressed proposition into its precise meaning in
reference to an individual experience. _ A symbol is not an individual,
it is true. But any information about a symbol is information about every
replica of it; and a replica is strictly an individual’ (CP 2.315). The
interesting point about this definition of replicas is that ‘individuation’ is
a mode of determination. An individual is ‘absolutely determinate in all
respects’ (CP 5.299), since existence implies ‘entire determinateness, in the
sense that nothing remains undecided’ (CP 4.431).7
This raises the question as to whether a replica token is determined
by the fact that it is an existing individual or whether it is determined by
the fact that it is an application of a general law. The answer is not easy
because, according to Peirce, replica tokens are ‘not ordinary Sinsigns,
such as are peculiar occurrences that are regarded as significant’. A replica
is only significant because of a ‘law which renders it so’ (CP 2.246).8 Such
a law, however, is not the ‘general rule of meaning’ by which a symbol is
related to its object. It is, rather, a law of ‘replication’ that regulates how
an abstract type is transformed into an individual token. This ‘law of
replication’ is, so to speak, stored in every replica. In a sense, we could say
that every replica token is self-referential insofar as it indicates the type
of which it is a replica. Peirce argues ‘that the mass of ink on the sheet
by means of which a graph is said to be ‘scribed’ is not _ a symbol, but
only a replica of a symbol of the nature of an index’ (CP 4.500).
42 U. Wirth
Conclusion
Notes
1. According to Koselleck (1999: 105), the term ‘crisis’ designates a state of uncertainty
requiring some decision: ‘The general uncertainty in a critical situation is mingled with
the certainty that the critical state of affairs will have an end sometime — although it
is not determined when this will take place’.
2. Of course, we might also conclude that the ‘determination’ is a vague term in itself, since
it can be used to designate quite different things, such as logical determination, causal
determination, intentional determination, or determination by individuation.
3. Although habit taking needs no repetition, iteration plays an important role in ‘habit-
change’, since ‘repetitions of the actions that produce the changes increase the changes’
(CP 5.477). Iteration has a strengthening power.
4. Searle (1993: 1) criticizes Derrida’s account of representation, especially his position
that ‘meanings are ‘‘undecidable’’ and have ‘‘relative’’ indeterminacy _ . Instead of fully
determinate meanings, there is rather the free play of signifiers and the grafting of texts
onto texts’. Concerning the type-token distinction, Searle writes:
I believe the distinction between linguistic types and linguistic tokens was first
formulated by Charles Sanders Peirce. _ We need this distinction because identity
criteria for types and tokens are quite different. What makes something a case of
‘the same token’ will be different from what makes it ‘the same type’. _ The distinction
between types and tokens, by the way, is a consequence of the fact that language is rule-
governed or conventional, because the notion of a rule or of a convention implies
the possibility of repeated occurrences of the same phenomenon. (Ibid. 8)
5. ‘A Legisign is a law that is a Sign’, and ‘this law is usually established by men. Every
conventional sign is a legisign [but not conversely]’ (CP 2.246). We could add here that all
conventional signs are symbolic legisigns, although not every symbol is conventional.
6. However, an utterance is not just a replica token, it is, rather, a replica token that is
used intentionally. This definition leaves it open as to whether it is the utterer or the
receiver who applies intention to the token. In his essay, ‘Literal meaning’, Searle (1979:
119–120) states, concerning the distinction between ‘type’ and ‘token’, that an utterance
is more than just the replica of a sentence-type. One and the same utterance can
have many replicas, as, for instance, in the case of a book, where one and the same
utterance is distributed in thousands of copies. According to Searle, a token always has
the same meaning as its type. Hence, the difference between the meaning of a sentence
type and an utterance token is due to the speaker intention and not to the type-token
distinction.
7. On the other hand, of course, Peirce argues that ‘the absolute individual _ cannot exist’
and that all ‘that we perceive or think, or that exists, is general’ (CP 3.93). This is
especially true of a replica-token.
44 U. Wirth
8. According to Peirce, ‘a legisign has a definite identity, though usually admitting a great
variety of appearances. _ The qualisign, on the other hand, has no identity. _ Instead
of identity, it has great similarity’ (CP 8.334).
References