Standard Models of Arithmetic
Standard Models of Arithmetic
net/publication/281936805
CITATIONS READS
0 2,101
1 author:
Ali Enayat
University of Gothenburg
58 PUBLICATIONS 210 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
All content following this page was uploaded by Ali Enayat on 17 December 2016.
ALI ENAYAT
Gödel’s incompleteness theorems demonstrated once and for all that our
knowledge of a sufficiently rich structure is highly dependent on the choice
of higher order formal frameworks within which the structure is viewed
through. This Gödelian insight has come to shape a great deal of research
in the foundations of mathematics, particularly in set theory, where the
higher order frameworks are provided by large cardinal axioms. For example,
consider Gödel’s constructible universe L of set theory. It is consistent with
ZF that the class V of all sets coincides with L, and yet it is well-known [J]
that in the presence of sufficiently large cardinals (e.g., a Ramsey cardinal)
0# exists, and in particular the satisfaction-predicate of L is definable in V,
which in light of Tarski’s undefinability of truth theorem is a strong form of
asserting V 6= L.
Date: December 13, 2016.
It is a pleasure to present this paper in a Festschrift volume for Christian Bennet. The
results presented here arose from a question posed by Joel Hamkins and Victoria Gitman
that asked whether there is a characterization of models of arithmetic that arise as the
standard model of arithmetic in some model of ZF; this question was communicated to
the author by Roman Kossak at the Mittag-Leffler Institute, during September of 2009.
Thanks to Roman, Menachem Magidor, and Jouko Väänänen for inspiring conversations,
to Jim Schmerl for reminding me of the relevance of his remarkable paper [Sch-2] to the
questions dealt with here, to Fredrik Engström for a careful reading of the penultimate
draft which resulted in weeding out many infelicities, and to Martin Kaså for his fine efforts
in putting this volume together. NOTE: IN THIS DRAFT THE PROOF OF LEMMA
11.1 IS IMPROVED.
1
2 ALI ENAYAT
PAT := ∩ Th(NM ) : M |= T .
finitely axiomatizable over PA. Also, since for each natural number n there is
an arithmetically definable truth predicate for Σn -arithmetical sentences one
can use the proof strategy of Theorem 4 to show that PAT is also axiomatized
by sentences of the form {ψn : n ∈ ω}, where ψn is the arithmetical sentence
that expresses:
“Con(Tn + ϕN ) holds for all true Σn sentences ϕ”.
6. Proposition. Every ZF-standard model of PA that is nonstandard is
recursively saturated.4
Proof: ZF can define the Tarskian satisfaction predicate for every set struc-
ture; and in particular it can do so for N. In light of this observation,
recursive saturation follows from a routine overspill argument, as in [Ka,
Proposition 15.4].
7. Theorem. Every countable recursively saturated model of PA + ΦT is a
T -standard model of PA.
Proof: The quickest way to prove this theorem is by a “resplendence ar-
gument”, as in the proof of Corollary 9 (since every countable recursively
saturated model is resplendent [Ka, Theorem 15.7]), but we take this oppor-
tunity to present a direct proof (indeed, by a varation of this proof, one can
show the resplendence property of countable recursively saturated models).
Given a countable recursively saturated model A |= PA + ΦT , first use re-
cursive saturation to find c in A that codes Th(A) by realizing the recursive
type Σ(v), where
Σ(v) := {ϕ ↔ pϕq ∈Ack v : ϕ ∈ Sent},
where pϕq is the Gödel number for ϕ, ∈Ack is “Ackermann’s ∈”, i.e., a ∈Ack b
holds iff the a-th bit of the binary expansion of b is 1; and Sent is the (re-
cursive) set of sentences in the usual language of arithmetic. Next, let
hϕn : n ∈ ωi be a recursive enumeration of arithmetical sentences, and con-
sider the arithmetical formula γ(i) defined below:
γ(i) := Con (Ti + {ϕj : j < i ∧ ϕj ∈Ack c})
It is easy to see, using the assumption that ΦT holds in A and our choice of c
that A |= γ(n) for each n < ω, and therefore by overspill A |= γ(d) for some
nonstandard element d of A. By invoking the Hilbert-Bernays arithmetized
completeness theorem [KS, Thm 1.12] within A, we can conclude that there
is a model M of T with the following three properties:
(1) Th(A) = Th(NM ).
(2) NM is recursively saturated.
4This proposition is a descendent of a result of Ehrenfeucht and Kreisel [EK] that
states that no model of PA that is expandable to a model of second order arithmetic is
finitely generated (recall that an infinite recursively saturated model cannot be finitely
generated).
STANDARD MODELS OF ARITHMETIC 5
(iii) Nfn (ω,En ) = N(ω,En+1 ) , i.e., (ω, En+1 ) has no natural numbers other
than the ones in fn (ω, En+1 ) .
By the aforementioned Kotlarski-Schmerl theorem, (d) implies that there
exist E n , g and fn such that for all n < ω :
(e) B, E n , E n+1 , g, f n |= Φn (E n , E n+1 , f n , g).
The desired model M is the direct limit of the models ω, E n via the
embeddings f n : n < ω .
In order to present the next result (Theorem 14) we need a definition.
12. Definition. Suppose M is a model of ZF.
(a) NM is M-rather classless if all the classes of NM are parametrically
definable in M (and therefore each class is coded as a real number of M).
(b) RM is the field R of real numbers in the sense of M.
(c) R(M) the external Scott completion (also known as the Cauchy comple-
tion) of the field of rational QM of M. The Scott completion of an ordered
field F is the largest ordered field that contains F as a dense subfield (by a
theorem of Dana Scott [Sco], every ordered field has a Scott completion).
13. Remark. Generally speaking, RM is a proper subfield of R(M);
and when M is countable, RM is also of course countable, but R(M) is of
cardinality 2ℵ0 . Moreover, one can show, using [Sch-1, Proposition 1.4] that
RM ∼= R(M) iff NM is M-rather classless.
14. Theorem. Let κ be an infinite cardinal, T be an extension of ZFC,
and suppose A0 is a T -standard model of cardinality less than κ.
(a) There is an elementary extension A of A0 such that A is κ-like and
end extends A0 .
(b) Moreover, if cf( κ) > ℵ0 , then A can be required further to be M-rather
classless, where A = NM , for some model M of T .
Proof sketch: Suppose A0 = NM0 , for a model M0 of T . Fix a nonprin-
cipal ultrafilter U in M0 , and let M be the κ-th iterated ultrapower of M0
modulo U. The desired model A is NM . The moreover clause uses the same
argument as in the well-known PA-case [KS, Thm 2.2.14].
15. Remark. The full force of AC is not needed for the above construction.
What is needed is enough choice to have a workable theory of ultrapowers,
i.e., (i) ACω , and (ii) the existence of a nonprincipal ultrafilter on P(ω).
16. Corollary. ZF-standard models need not be resplendent.
Proof: By Friedman’s self-embedding theorem [Ka, Theorem 12.4] every
countable nonstandard model of PA is isomorphic to a proper initial segment
of itself. This shows, by a “reduction to the countable” argument (as in the
proof of Corollary 9), that every resplendent model of PA is isomorphic to a
8 ALI ENAYAT
proper initial segment of itself, a property that cannot be true of any κ-like
model, so thanks to Theorem 14(a) the proof is complete.
17. Remark. Lemma 11.1 and Theorem 14 can also be derived as corol-
laries of general results of Schmerl’s [Sch-2]. Schmerl’s paper deals with
sequential theories (i.e., theories in which a “β-function” that codes finite
sequences is available) and which include the full scheme of induction in the
extended language. It is known that such theories are reflexive [HP, Thm
3.30, Ch.III].
References
[D] R. Dedekind, Essays on the Theory of Numbers, Dover Publications, New
York, 1963
[EF] A. Ehrenfeucht and G. Kreisel, Strong models of arithmetic, Bull. Acad. Polon.
Sci. Sér. Sci. Math. Astronom. Phys. vol. 14 (1966), pp. 107–110.
[F] H. Friedman, Boolean Relation Theory, to appear in the Lecture Notes in
Logic Series of the Association for Symbolic Logic.
[HP] P. Hájek and P. Pudlák, Metamathematics of First-order Arithmetic, Per-
spectives in Mathematical Logic, Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 1998.
[J] T. Jech, Set Theory, Springer Monographs in Mathematics, Springer-Verlag,
Berlin, 2003.
[Ka] R. Kaye, Models of Peano Arithmetic, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1991.
[KY] L. A. Kolodziejczyk and K. Yokoyama, Categorical characterizations of
the natural numbers require primitive recursion, preprint available at
http://www.mimuw.edu.pl/˜lak/publik.html
[KS] R. Kossak and J.H. Schmerl, The Structure of Models of Peano Arithmetic,
Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2006.
[Ko] H. Kotlarski, On cofinal extensions of models of arithmetic, J. Symbolic Logic
vol. 48 (1983), no. 2, pp. 253–262.
[L] A. Lévy, Axiomization of induced theories, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc. 12 (1961)
pp. 251-253.
[Sch-1] J. Schmerl, On a problem of Sikorski, Israel J. Math 50 (1985), pp.145-159.
[Sch-2] , A reflection principle and its applications to nonstandard models, J.
Symbolic Logic vol. 60 (1995), no. 4, 1137–1152.
[Sco] D. Scott, On completing ordered fields, Applications of Model Theory to Al-
gebra, Analysis, and Probability (Internat. Sympos., Pasadena, Calif., 1967)
Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York, pp. 274–278.
[SY] S. Simpson and K. Yokoyama, Reverse mathematics and Peano categoricity, Ann.
Pure Appl. Logic 164 (2013), no. 3, pp. 284-293.
[V] J. von Neumann, On the introduction of transfinite numbers, in Jean van Hei-
jenoort, From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic,
1879-1931 (3rd ed.), Harvard University Press, pp. 346-354 (English translation
of von Neumann’s 1923 work).