Law As A Social System
Law As A Social System
136
137
I.
There are two innovations that especially lend themselves to use in a
theoretically grounded sociology of law: (1) the theory of system differ-
entiation, inspired by general systems theory, which conceives of differ-
entiation as the establishment of system-environment relationships in
systems; and (2) the assumption that such differentiation is possible only
through the establishment of a self-referential closedness in the systems
becoming differentiated. Without such closure, the systems would have
no way of distinguishing their own operations from those of the environ-
ment. With the aid of these two concepts we can achieve an understand-
ing of the social character of law and, at the same time, the legal system's
own reflective accomplishments. In other words, doctrine or legal theory
can be better understood as one formulation of the legal system's self-
referentiality. This understanding does require, however, a much more
precise mode of presentation than has tended to be customary, a presen-
tation that is consistent with systems theory.
Formulations such as the statement that there are "connections be-
tween" law and society (which presupposes that law is something outside
of society) especially must be avoided. The legal system is a differenti-
ated functional system within society. Thus in its own operations, the
legal system is continually engaged in carrying out the self-reproduction
(autopoiesis) of the overall social system as well as its own. In doing so,
it uses forms of communication that, for all their esoteric quality, can
never be so abstract as to be completely removed from normal, compre-
hensible meaning. This means not only that the legal system fulfills a
function for society—that it "serves" society—but also that the legal sys-
tem participates in society's construction of reality, so that in the law, as
everywhere in society, the ordinary meanings of words (of names, num-
3
See N. Luhmann, SOZIALE SYSTEME: GRUNDRISS EINER ALLGEMEINEN THEORIE (1984)
[Social Systems: Outline of a General Theory].
138
4
See generally 1 E. MORIN, LA METHODE: LA NATURE DE LA NATURE (1977) [Methodol-
ogy: The Nature of Nature]. For a biological perspective see F. VARELA, PRINCIPLES OF BIOLOGI-
CAL AUTONOMY (1979).
139
140
II.
The next sections of this essay will deal with some of the conse-
quences of this theoretical point of departure. Especially important here
are aspects in which this theory leads to views that are new or that differ
from ones previously accepted.
A.
An especially important implication of this theory of the law's auto-
poietic character is that the boundaries of the system must be drawn dif-
ferently than has been customary (even in the way sociologically oriented
systems theory has dealt with law). Up to now the law has been treated
either from the perspective of jurisprudence, as a complex of norms, or as
a system of knowledge, in abstraction from real social behavior. Jurists
saw the legal system as a macro-text. Or, as is customary in sociology,
the focus was shifted to institutions that are concerned with law on a full-
time basis, whether those institutions were organizations (primarily the
courts), or the legal profession. This perspective permitted empirical
treatment of such problems as "access to the law." Yet distinguishing
between the legal system and the state as the basis for organizations and
the source of power was difficult. Political influence on the law was con-
ceived as a kind of input (of the law into the law). Alternatively, the
legal system as a whole was even conceived from the standpoint of the
political system, as an "implementation" of politics. For all its ambiva-
lence, this perspective has left a definite mark on jurists' attitudes toward
the relationship between law and politics.7
Assuming that the system has a self-referential, closed character
leads to completely different notions about the boundaries of the system.
They are defined not at the institutional but at the operative level. And,
as is evident to the sociological observer, the system's boundaries are de-
fined by the legal system itself, with the aid of a recursive referral of
operations to the results of (or the prospects for) operations by the same
system. In these terms, every communication that makes a legal asser-
tion or raises a defense against such an assertion is an internal operation
of the legal system, even if it is occasioned by a dispute among neighbors,
a traffic accident, a police action, or any other event. It is sufficient that
7
One significant consequence is that jurists, more than other professionals, have an understand-
ing of the political context of their own practice. See Lange & Luhmann, Juristen—Berufswahl und
Karrieren, 65 VERWALTUNGSARCHIV 113-62, 157 (1974) [Jurists—Choice of Profession and Ca-
reers. Archives of Administration].
141
the communication be assigned a place within the system, and that has
already occurred with the use of the code lawful/unlawful. Of course,
the law can also be observed from the outside, as in a news report in the
press. And within the educational system there is also a didactic treat-
ment of law that only simulates legal cases and thus does not aim at a
decision. Consequently not every reference to the law is an operation
internal to the legal system. But whenever a communication occurs in
the context of the administration of justice, the context of providing for
conflicts within the law, or the context of an alteration of the law—that
is, in the processing of normative legal expectations—we are dealing with
an operation internal to the legal system, and this operation simultane-
ously defines the boundaries between the legal system and the everyday
life context that occasions the posing of a legal question.
These system boundaries are a good place to study thefilteringeffect
of the legal system. One sees clearly, for example, how difficult it can be
in ongoing life relationships (marriages, work relationships, relationships
between neighbors) to resort to the law to give force to one's own views.
The rigidity of the binary code makes the reasons for this difficulty clear:
asserting one's own legal position is tied to designating opposing views as
unlawful. A look at the legal cultures of the Far East also shows that
recourse to the law can be interpreted as an intention to engage in con-
flict, and consequently it is institutionally discouraged.
Clearly there is a connection between the complexity of the law, its
resulting opaqueness, and how high this threshold of discouragement is.
Corruption, which a look at various civilizations will show to be a nor-
mal phenomenon, has an equally discouraging effect on potential users of
the legal system. Corruption in law is a normal phenomenon: it is only
realistic to assume that the law accommodates dominant interests; it
could not conduct itself otherwise and still be accepted. (This does not
mean, however, that corruption is a part of official legal policy or that it
is consciously cultivated). Rather, what is amazing is the degree to
which the law can be purged of corruption in spite of this. With a de-
crease in corruption, the threshold of discouragement is thereby lowered;
people have confidence in a judge who is impartial. Yet, this relief itself
leads to an increase in the complexity of the law. With less corruption to
filter people out of the legal system, the number and diversity of cases
increases, and as a result there is increased need for regulation. With this
increase in complexity, the threshold of discouragement shifts its location
from corruption to complexity. It thereby acquires a form against which
the legal system itself is powerless and which is the subject of recurrent
complaints throughout the history of law.8
If one adopts a self-referential autopoietic theory, it no longer makes
8
An example is the discourspreliminaire [preliminary discourse] in S. LINGUET, 1 THEORIE
DES Loix civiLES, ou PRINCIPES FONDAMENTAUX DE LA SOCIETE (London 1767) [Theory of Civil
Law, or Fundamental Principles of Society].
142
sense to assume that the structures of the legal system, which themselves
regulate the production of its operations, can be specified as input and
output. The specification of structures always presupposes operations of
the system itself. This does not contradict the assumption of a normal
complicity with dominant interests on the part of the law. Nor does it
exclude the possibility that an outside observer could describe the legal
system with the aid of an input-transformation output model. But such a
description would be compelled to give the transformation function the
form of a "black box," and to take into consideration the fact that the
law adjusts its reactions to its condition at any given time, that it can
change even if external interests do not change, and that it thus does not
function as a "trivial machine." To the degree to which these factors are
taken into consideration, however, it makes sense to move from an input-
output model to the theory of self-referential systems.9 It is better suited
to the existing state of affairs.
B.
The most important advantage of this theory of a closed self-referen-
tial legal system may lie in its close resemblance to the notions of legal
doctrine and legal theory, a closeness which by virtue of its alienation
effect proves surprising and irritating at the same time.10 Sociological
theory attempts to reconstruct not only jurists' actions, but also their
conceptions, or at least the way the legal system generates self-observa-
tions and self-descriptions. We are not concerned here with a "critique
of ideology" or a sociology of knowledge in the classical manner in which
modes of thought are linked to interests or social positions and explained
in those terms.
Our starting point is the thesis that a self-referential system can link
its operations together and reproduce them only through concurrent self-
9
See also the distinction between couplagepar input and couplagepar cloture [coupling through
input; coupling through closure] in Varela, L'auto-organisation: De Vapparence au mecanisme, in
L'AUTO-ORGANISATION: D E LA PHYSIQUE AU POLITIQUE 147-64 (P. Dumouchel & J. Dupuy eds.
1983) [Auto-organization: From Appearance to Mechanism, in Auto-organization: From Physics
to Politics].
10
A parallel problem arises in the relationship of law to theology, and it has been more exten-
sively discussed in the literature. See D. POLLACK, DIE RELIGIONSTHEORIE NIKLAS LUHMANNS
UND IHRE SYSTEMTHEORETISCHEN VORAUSSETZUNGEN, (1984) [Niklas Luhmann's Theory of
Religion and Its Systems-Theoretical Presuppositions]; F. SCHOLZ, FREIHEIT ALS INDIFFERENZ:
ALTEUROPAISCHE PROBLEME MIT DER SYSTEMTHEORIE NIKLAS LUHMANNS (1982) [Freedom as
Neutrality: Old-European Problems with Niklas Luhmann's Systems Theory]; THEOLOGIE UND
FUNKTIONALE SYSTEMTHEORIE: LUHMANNS RELIGIONSSOZIOLOGIE IN DER THEOLOGISCHEN DlS-
KUSSlON (M. Welker ed. 1985) [Theology and Functional Systems Theory: The Reception of Niklas
Luhmann's Systems Theory by Theology]; Moritz, Religion und Gesellschaft in der DDR, 110 THEO-
LOGlSCHE LITERATURZEITUNG 573 (1985) [Religion and Society in the German Democratic Re-
public. Journal of Theological Literature]; Pannenberg, Die Allgemeingultigkeit der Religion, 11
EVANGELISCHE KOMMENTARE 356-57 (1978) [The Universal Validity of Religion. Protestant
Commentary].
143
144
13
See also Y. Barel, Leparadoxe et Ie systeme: essai sur Ie fantastique social (1979) [Paradox and
System: Essay on the Fantastic in Society]; Barel, De la fermeture a I'ouverture en passant par
I'autonomie?, in L'AUTO-ORGANISATION, supra note 9, at 466-75 [From Closure to Openness by
Way of Autonomy?]. As a case study in the history of legal theory see Luhmann, Die Theorie der
Ordnung and die natiirlichen Rechte, 3 RECHTSHISTORISCHES JOURNAL 133 (1984) [Natural Rights
and The Theory of Order. Journal of Legal History].
14
See Lofgren, Some Foundational Views on General Systems and the Hempel Paradox, 4 INT'L
J. GENERAL SYS. 243 (1978).
145
C.
Finally, with the help of a general theory of self-referential auto-
poietic systems it is possible to connect systems theory to a theory of
evolution more adequately than before. What results is a weakening of
the concept of "adaptation" to the environment, a concept that cannot
adequately explain either the high degree of form constancy in natural
evolution nor the accompanying tempo of innovations. This is true for
the theory of the evolution of living systems, but even more true for the
theory of social evolution.
Special evolutionary paths become possible when the differentiation
of particular autopoietic systems is successful; for as soon as this occurs a
system can vary its structures, insofar as this is compatible with its con-
tinued self-reproduction. In constructing and altering structures, auto-
poietic systems can make use of contingent impulses from the
environment that occur and disappear again, as well as of errors in the
reproduction of their own operations. The possibilities are often re-
stricted more by the demands of internal consistency than by problems of
survival in the environment. In other words, very often a system fails to
make full use of the degrees of freedom the environment permits it and
restricts its own evolution to a greater degree than would be ecologically
necessary.15 Even with this modification to the theoretical apparatus of
classical Darwinism, however, it is still correct to characterize evolution
as an unplanned (not coordinated and in this sense making use of "acci-
dents") differentiation in variation, selection, and restabilization.
Accordingly, a theory of the evolution of law has to clarify two pri-
mary questions: (1) what problem leads to the differentiation of a partic-
ular evolution of law within a general social evolution, and (2) what is
the nature of the autopoiesis of law that allows it to be maintained even
when structural alterations take place? The answer to these questions
must start from the principle of variation, for a specific selection mecha-
nism can be formed only if the pertinent variation manifests specific
peculiarities.
The problem that gives rise to a special evolution of the law must lie
in uncertainty about whether expectations, and which expectations, can
be maintained, or at least be proven to be counterfactually justified, in
the case of conflict. This problem becomes relevant, if it was not so from
the outset, because a segmentary social structure establishes who is to be
on what side, who is to confirm claims, to take oaths, and if necessary, to
fight. The evolution of law then begins with the loosening of the struc-
15
On this point, with regard to a broadly conceived concept of organizations, see K. WEICK,
THE SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY OF ORGANIZING (2d ed. 1979).
146
16
For modern perspectives see J. SCOTT, THE MORAL ECONOMY OF THE PEASANT: REBEL-
LION AND SUBSISTENCE IN SOUTHEAST ASIA (1976); Thompson, The Moral Economy ofthe English
Crowd in the 18th Century, 50 PAST AND PRESENT 76 (1971).
147
III.
Legal theory has found it difficult (and perhaps it always will) to
grasp this positive quality of the law in the absence of any conception of
an external (especially a moral) justification. The 19th century's attempt
to understand law as a guarantee of freedom (and that means freedom for
17
To show that the phenomenon is not so new, an example from the 18th century: For the sake
of the button makers, the law ordains that buttons may not be made out of the same fabric as the
clothing. See V. de Riqueti, Marquis de Mirabeau, 1'ami des hommes 90 (Paris 1883) [The Marquis
de Mirabeau, Friend of Man].
18
See Marquand, Religion und Skepsis, in Dm RELIGIOSE DIMENSION DER GESELLSCHAFT:
RELIGION UND IHRE THEORIEN 45 (P. Koslowski ed. 1985) [Religion and Skepticism, in The Reli-
gious Dimension of Society: Religion and Its Theories].
148
149
22
See supra note 11.
23
See supra note 12.
150