Classifying Science: Phenomena, Data, Theory, Method, Practice
Classifying Science: Phenomena, Data, Theory, Method, Practice
Classifying Science
Phenomena, Data, Theory, Method, Practice
By
Rick Szostak
CLASSIFYING SCIENCE
Information Science and Knowledge Management
Volume 7
Editor-in-Chief:
J. Mackenzie Owen, University of Amsterdam, Amsterdam
Editorial Board:
M. Bates, University of California, Los Angeles
P. Bruza, The University of Queensland, Brisbane
R. Capurro, Hochschule der Medien, Stuttgart University of Applied Sciences, Stuttgart
E. Davenport, Napier University, Edinburgh
R. Day, Wayne State University, Detroit
M. Hedstrom, University of Michigan, Ann Arbor
A.M. Paci, Istituto di Studi Sulla Ricerca e Documentazione Scientifica, Roma
C. Tenopir, University of Tennessee, Knoxville
M. Thelwall, University of Wolverhampton, Wolverhampton
The titles published in this series are listed at the end of this volume.
CLASSIFYING SCIENCE
Phenomena, Data, Theory, Method, Practice
by
RICK SZOSTAK
University of Alberta,
Edmonton, Alberta, Canada
A C.I.P. Catalogue record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.
Published by Springer,
P.O. Box 17, 3300 AA Dordrecht, The Netherlands.
References 269
Index 279
List of Tables vii
LIST OF TABLES
phenomena, the theory(ies) they advocate and/or test, and the steps they have
taken to reduce possibilities of error. Clarity is more carefully pursued in
some scientific fields than others. The classifications developed in this book
both encourage and facilitate the careful specification of these key elements
of a research project. Moreover they allow this to be done in the context of a
common vocabulary. At the moment, scholarly communication, even within
disciplines but especially beyond, is rendered problematic by the fact that
different scholars attach quite different meanings to the same word. A
common vocabulary should encourage interdisciplinary communication, and
also communication to the wider public.
At present, and even moreso with the broader vision of science advocated
in this book, scientists face real difficulties in identifying relevant literature
from outside their own community of scholars. Library catalogues are
organized around disciplines rather than phenomena. Moreover while general
works on particular theories or methods can be found (though even here
there are problems in that these may be known by different names in
different fields), it is virtually impossible to search for works that apply a
particular theory or method. Chapter 7 shows how the classifications
developed in this book could form the basis of a superior system of scientific
document classification. While such a project should not be entertained
lightly, the present efforts to develop classifications more suited to the
electronic age provides an opportunity for re-engineering systems of
classification.
What is interdisciplinarity? I have defined this elsewhere as an openness
to the phenomena, theories, and/or methods of multiple disciplines. In this
book interdisciplinary scholarship is contrasted with specialized scholarship,
where particular communities of scholars employ a subset of scientific
theories and methods to analyze a particular subset of phenomena. It is
argued that both types of research are essential to the scientific enterprise.
Specialized communities of scholars can accomplish much because of their
shared expertise, vocabulary, and sense of purpose. On their own, though,
they will produce only a congeries of insights. Even if specialized
researchers become more theoretically and methodologically open, as they
should, interdisciplinary scholars are necessary to tie these pieces into a
coherent whole. Moreover, major advances in scientific understanding
generally come from the combination of insights from different fields.
Interdisciplinary scholars also have an important role to play in pointing out
when specialized scholars would benefit from a wider theoretical or
methodological compass. While much of this book will be couched in
general terms applicable to all scientists, there will be numerous points at
which specific advice is given to specialized or interdisciplinary researchers;
this advice is summarized in chapter 8.
xii Preface
now, it is sufficient to note that all of these distinctions are problematic: the
boundaries between classes are disputed, cases which seem to combine
elements of each class are legion, and some scholars are not as clear as they
should be about what they are attempting to classify, and along what
dimension(s). This book will develop classifications that are at once more
detailed and less problematic than these distinctions.
Questions of whether some types of science are better than others, or
whether different types of science are best suited to different purposes, can
hardly be asked intelligibly without first classifying types of science. Less
obviously, enquiries about the very possibility and limitations of scientific
enquiry would benefit from such a classification, just as the periodic table
aids those who wonder what chemicals can do. Moreover, without some
classification of science, scholars of science will communicate poorly.
“Communication between researchers is impossible unless they can identify
to one another the entities that they are talking about” (Ziman, 2000, 119).
Finally, we shall see that these classifications aid the performance of science
in a variety of ways.
A classification of science should ideally possess two qualities. First, it
should identify an exhaustive set of types of science, as the periodic table
identifies an exhaustive set of possible chemical elements. This would
provide insight into the possibilities and limits of the scientific enterprise.3
Such a classification might, in particular, encourage practicing scientists to
be open to types of science different from those they pursue. Second, the
classification should reflect some theoretical order. This would aid efforts to
identify the strengths and weaknesses of different types of science, and also
the potential for integrating across different types of science – as the periodic
table guides chemists as to the properties of particular elements, both alone
and in combination. Note that a theoretical grounding has the additional
important advantage of allowing the classification of new types of science (or
elements) even before these have been found or created. Both goals could
potentially be achieved either with a unidimensional classification or with a
multidimensional typology; both will be utilized in what follows.
While some elements had been identified before the development of the
periodical table, gaps in the table were then filled in by the search for or
creation of missing elements. This process betrays a mixture of induction
(various particulars are identified, and organized into a larger structure) and
major differences between, say, physics and chemistry in the twentieth century, let alone
the biological sciences.”
3
“Every program of social inquiry, every theoretical vision, I suggest, implies some model
of closure, some sense of how individual bits of insight fit, or fail to fit, into some larger
project of enlightenment” (Rule, 1997, 26). Scientific research programs should instead
proceed from an understanding of the full range of possibilities.
1. Classifying Science 3
4
Whitley argues that the natural sciences can only be understood in
comparison with the social sciences and humanities, Dupré (2001, 4)
notes that (natural) science cannot answer some of humanity’s most
profound questions. He advocates “an approach that draws both on the
empirical knowledge derivable from the (various) sciences, and on the
wisdom and insight into human nature that can be derived from more
humanistic studies.” Rather than speaking of the “limits of science”
(Dupré, 2001, 17), this book includes humanistic study within science.
4 Chapter 1
about science. Given the tendency of both practicing journalists and scientists
to be guided by the five Ws, this result is perhaps not surprising.
Scientific research reports are generally more logical in format than the
research enterprise that they summarize. This project was not begun with the
five Ws in mind. This project was inspired by a sense of the desirability of
classifying science; a feasible means of doing so followed. Familiarity with
the use of the five Ws in the research of Marion Brady on interdisciplinary
teaching encouraged the investigation of the possibility of classifying science
in this way, after a fair bit of inductive contemplation had already been
performed.5 Once the approach seemed useful in a couple of contexts, its
wider applicability was naturally explored.
In addition to the 5W questions, scientists and journalists often ask
‘How?’ Indeed, this is a particularly important scientific question.
Philosophers, though, often distinguish scientific approaches as to whether
they are focussed on ‘Why?’ Or ‘How?’ This suggests that ‘How?’ is
actually a combination of (some of) the other four Ws. It has been noted that
when interviewers ask people a ‘How?’ question, they are generally
rewarded with a chronology of When and Where a process occurred
(Goldenberg, 1992, 118). ‘How?’ will thus be treated in what follows as
primarily a substitute for When/Where questions. When answers to ‘When?’
and ‘Where?’ are not obvious, asking ‘How?’ will prove a useful device.
‘How?’ can also serve as a check on the analysis: do the answers to that
question find a place in the 5W analysis?
It might be argued that if the ‘How?’ question were formulated as “How
does science proceed?” rather than “How do scientists do science?,” a
stronger distinction might be drawn: the 5W questions would interrogate the
inputs into science, and ‘How?’ would inquire about outputs.6 This book,
though, will link inputs and outputs throughout. It will argue that science
should proceed through the careful specification of phenomena, data, theory,
and method. It is hoped that classifications of these elements of science will
greatly facilitate communication across scientific communities, and thus the
cumulative development of scientific insight.
5
Brady notes that the 5W questions are interrelated. He proposes a superior educational
system whereby students are guided to explore the 5W questions as applied to pairs of
phenomena from a lengthy list. Some relationships will prove obvious, while others are
subtle or silly. Students are thus forced to think in a complex manner, appreciate the
importance of exploring causal links, and realize that all phenomena have diverse
influences. Crucially, they gain both an organizing system on which to hang diverse bits
of understanding, and an appreciation of those links and questions they have not explored.
See his website, http://digital.net/~mbrady/
6
I thank Bill Newell for drawing this possibility to my attention.
1. Classifying Science 5
7
Common practice (in North America) is followed here in defining “human science” as the
social and behavioral sciences, plus the humanities. Caws (1993) defines human science
as the study of processes involving human agency. The list of human science phenomena
in Table 2.1 provides a more precise definition of what human science encompasses.
8
Hempel and Oppenheim argued that the purpose of science was explanation, because
scientists were concerned with answering ‘Why?’ questions. Scriven (1988) notes, though,
that scientists engage each of the 5W questions with regard to the phenomena they study,
and answers to each of these questions can be termed explanation.
9
Boylan and O’Gorman render this judgment despite disagreeing with this view. They note
that Quine equated “theory” with “description”, although he said little about “explanation”.
Van Frassen emphasized that “explanation” requires a narrative approach; he, and Boylan
and O’Gorman in turn, nevertheless appreciate that such a narrative will be grounded in
theory.
1. Classifying Science 7
10
Hall and Hall (1996), following Gilbert, argue that there are three major ingredients in
social research: theory, method, and data. The analysis so far has only added reference to
the phenomena that data are supposed to represent.
8 Chapter 1
3. SOME PRELIMINARIES
Bailey (1994) can profitably be followed here. He notes that the main
goal of a classification system is to maximize both cross-group heterogeneity
and within-group homogeneity, but that in general there is a tradeoff between
these criteria. If, for example, that which we wish to classify is distributed
evenly along some dimension, dividing it into small groups will ensure
substantial homogeneity within groups, but also that neighbouring groups are
quite similar as well. The periodic table is thus a misleading guideline, for
many of the things one would wish to categorize are not so discretely
differentiable. While heterogeneity across and homogeneity within types of
science are goals to be pursued in this work, and generally with great
success, it is noteworthy that most categorization schemes have difficulties in
ascertaining where group boundaries are best situated and where particular
cases should be classified.
Bailey argues that the basic secret to categorization is the “ability to
ascertain the key or fundamental characteristics on which the classification is
to be based,” which in turn can only come from a mix of prior knowledge
10 Chapter 1
and theoretical guidance (1994,2). This advice accords well with the premise
above that both induction and deduction should be used to derive
classifications of science.
Bailey defines a typology as a classification that is multidimensional and
conceptual. That is, it is organized in terms of at least two theoretical
criteria. (While some scholars use taxonomy as a synonym for typology,
Bailey reserves taxonomy for multidimensional classifications based on
empirical criteria).11 Bailey notes that if there are many dimensions, it may
be advisable to group nearbly cells of a multidimensional table in order to
obtain a manageable number of classes (a process which is necessarily a bit
arbitrary,12 but often aided by the fact that various cells have no observed
cases). One advantage of the 5W approach to typology is that it generates a
manageable number of dimensions, and thus eliminates the need for
artificially grouping disparate cells into classes. Bailey warns scholars not to
sacrifice dimensions that identify important differences merely to achieve
manageability; the 5W approach will provide insight as well as
manageability. Nevertheless, it is important to show in what follows that 5W
typologies subsume diverse distinctions noted by previous scholars.
There are two broad types of classification. The first, “classification”
proper, involves a unidimensional rendering. For example, a unidimensional
list of scientific methods will be provided in chapter 4. The second type of
classification, typology, involves a multidimensional rendering. The 5W
questions will be used throughout this book to develop such typologies. Both
unidimensional and multidimensional classifications have advantages, and
thus the possibilities for both types of classification will be explored in each
of the next four chapters. Note that both types of classification can
potentially achieve the dual goals of identifying an exhaustive set of classes
and identifying some rationale for the existence of these classes.
Bailey (1994, 12) discusses several advantages of a typology. Scholars
can see where a particular class falls along each dimension. Scholars can
then see which classes are most similar (very important in modern
medical analysis) and most different. Scholars can also ensure that their
11
Bailey (1994, 32-4) is naturally enthusiastic about a third possibility of operational
taxonomy, in which conceptual typologies are found to have empirical validity. This
encourages a mixture of qualitative and quantitative approaches. Ragin (2000, 76-7)
criticizes the common tendency of sociologists to use exclusively the quantitative
technique of cluster analysis to identify clusters which share many but not all
characteristics; he worries that this detracts attention from the importance which
differences along any one dimension may have.
12
It may be explicitly arbitrary, as when index numbers are used, or pragmatic, as when the
goals of a particular research project determine how cells are clustered. Less arbitrarily,
cells may be eliminated if judged theoretically or practically impossible.
1. Classifying Science 11
13
“Categories and their boundaries are centrally important in science, and sciences are
especially good at documenting and publicly arguing about the boundaries of categories”
(Bowker and Star, 1999, 296). This book will hopefully stimulate scientific attention to
the task of classifying science itself.
14
Some would minimize the dangers of reification. Newton, it is noted, started theorizing
from concepts of effort and movement, before developing a theory in terms of force, mass,
and acceleration. Since classification is an essential component of research, even a
misguided system may be better than none in guiding inquiry toward better systems.
12 Chapter 1
15
He surely exaggerates, for prostitution must at least have been recognized as an
occupation. But his point is that prostitutes could more easily move across occupations
and marital status before they became branded for life.
16
Root (1997, 166) worries that if a class such as “homosexual” is created for purposes of
social control, scientific analysis of that class must reflect that bias. But if Root is right
that before the invention of homosexuality bisexuality was the norm, then scientific
investigation of the genetic causes of homosexuality would find that there is no difference.
Root then worries that analysis of marital status must support the legal preferences
afforded heterosexual couples; but surely analysis of the effects of such preferences might
yield the opposite conclusion?
1. Classifying Science 13
17
Ziman (2000, 120) follows Kant in arguing that humans have an inherent capacity for
pattern recognition (and thus classification). Considerable scientific evidence supports this
conjecture.
18
This creates problems for systems of document classification. For a system of
classification to be mutually exclusive, each step in disaggregation must occur in terms of
only one characteristic. This is generally impractical (Langridge, 1992, 15). The logical
structure of the classifications in this book should minimize this problem (see chapter 7).
19
Fabian (1975) also urges scholars to reduce bias by classifying with respect to the real
world rather than just with respect to other classes.
20
Bailey (1994, 8)also distinguishes a synchronic classification based on analysis at one
point in time from diachronic analysis of classes of phenomena that evolve over time.
14 Chapter 1
21
“Prominent among the targets of my criticism are certain radical views: holism (or
collectivism) and individualism (or atomism), spiritualism (idealism) and physicalism,
irrationalism and hyperrationalism (apriorism), positivism and obscurantist anti-positivism,
zealotry and insensitivity to the moral aspect of social issues, bogus rigour and the cult of
data, grand theory and ideology, moralizing ignorant of social science, and the
compartmentalization of social studies” (Bunge, 1998, xi-xii).
22
Of course, no philosophical argument is perfect, and thus one can always question whether
any particular piece of theory takes us closer to a true understanding of the world. But the
vast majority of scholars and casual observers would accept that there is evidence of
advanced understanding in both natural and social science. With respect to the former,
Gower (1997, 4) gloats that, “The facts that keep aircraft aloft are, fortunately for
passengers, not socially determined but ascertained on the basis of evidence by logical
reasoning.”
18 Chapter 1
argue that humans can know everything or nothing, but most accept that
humans have an imperfect capacity to enhance understanding.23
Polkinghorne (1996) notes that from the perspective of a practicing
physicist, the strong program in the sociology of knowledge, which contends
that developments in scientific theory reflect only sociocultural influences, is
nonsense. The behavior of the natural world, as revealed through
experiments and other methods, places severe constraints on the range of
theorizing possible. Yet Polkinghorne appreciates that social and cultural
influences matter. It would be a mistake, then, for practicing scientists to
completely reject all insights of the strong program. By advocating a Golden
Mean approach to this and other questions, this book hopes to speak to both
those who practice and those who study science (who are, notably, scientists
themselves within the definition of science used in this book).
3.4 Interdisciplinarity
23
Epistemologists ask questions such as “What does knowledge consist of?”, “How do
individuals acquire it?”, “How can it be distinguished from opinion?”, “How much should
one rely on other people?”, and “What is the role of scepticism?” (Moser et al., 1998).
With respect to science, this book will build toward answers to the first three questions in
chapter 5, when science is defined and distinguished from non-science. The question of
authority will be discussed briefly in chapters 2 and 3. Various types of scepticism will be
classified, and their insights discussed, in chapter 5. Some will worry that the consensus
identified by Moser et al. applies only to the English-speaking world. Norris (2000)
suggests that there is a greater degree of consensus between Anglophone and Continental
philosophers than is often appreciated. He also suggests that extreme scepticism is often
grounded in a misperception of certain problems in quantum physics.
20 Chapter 1
from consideration. The benefits of unity can thus be gained without the
costs. Only by developing the classifications in this book can both
specialized and interdisciplinary scholars see how each scientific community
fits within the broader scientific enterprise. Bechtel (1986) has described
interdisciplinarity as an ongoing process of discovery, not an attempt to
systematize. Klein (1996a, 21) and many others counter that it can be both:
the classifications in this book encourage both scientific discovery and the
integration of diverse insights into a broader whole.
Weingart (2000) explores the apparent paradox of constant pleas for
interdisciplinarity, but the continuing strength of disciplines. He concludes
that scientific specialization within disciplines and interdisciplinarity “both
are crucially important; they are complementary rather than contradictory”24
He notes in particular that interdisciplinarity aids discovery by juxtaposing
different perspectives, theories, methods, and so on. He draws upon
Hubenthal (1994), who had in turn cited various famous scientists on how
their major discoveries had reflected such juxtaposition (see also Palmer,
1996, and Bromne, 2000; the latter argues that cognitive development of any
type requires the confrontation of different perspectives). Yet Weingart
appreciates the advantages of specialized research too, in allowing the
rigorous study of narrowly defined questions within a community of scholars
with a shared understanding, vocabulary, expertise, and purpose. Dogan and
Pahre (1990) coined the term “hybridisation” to reflect the fact that both
increased specialization and the joining of specializations to form new fields
are essential processes in the evolution of science. By identifying the place
of every scientific specialization within the scientific enterprise, the
classifications developed in this book should aid the essential process of
developing links across specializations.25 As Dogan (1996, 296) notes, “the
process of hybridisation consists, first of all, of borrowing and lending
concepts, methods, theories, and praxis”
Vague or implicit classifications are a poor basis for science of any
sort, but especially for interdisciplinary science. The specialist can learn
to appreciate what is studied in their field, albeit slowly, no matter how
poorly articulated this might be. The interdisciplinary scholar, trying to draw
connections across fields, will struggle to understand what scholars are
24
Newell (1998) reaches a similar conclusion. He notes that while all interdisciplinarians
recognize that disciplines are imperfect, most also feel that disciplines have important
contributions to make to interdisciplinary analysis. He urges those with a more critical
stance to appreciate that interdisciplinary analysis can and does transform disciplines
themselves.
25
Stanley Fish had criticized interdisciplinary maps of some or all of the scientific enterprise
for ignoring what goes on within disciplines (Moran, 2002, 146). The classifications
developed in this book embrace both what happens within and across disciplines.
22 Chapter 1
1. CLASSIFYING PHENOMENA
The value of classifying the phenomena that scientists study may seem
particularly obvious. If scientists do not comprehend the identity of the
phenomena they study, they are unlikely to proceed very far in understanding
how particular phenomena evolve or influence each other. “In the [natural]
sciences the development of ‘pure’ elements and homogenous, stable
phenomena was a key point in the emergence of modern chemistry and other
natural sciences …” (Whitley, 2000, 122). As Singleton and Strait note
(1999, 19-20), “science makes a great fuss about language; observations
must be precisely and reliably reported; terms must be carefully defined,
with clear referents; and the phenomena to which a scientific discipline
addresses itself must be organized and classified in a meaningful way.”
Sadly, though, while the need for classification may be obvious, the
difficulties inherent in the task have prevented most disciplines from
achieving “meaningful classification.” At the level of the modern scientific
enterprise as a whole, the task has not even been attempted. Among the
unfortunate side effects of this situation is the arbitrary nature of disciplinary
boundaries: without a logical classification of phenomena to guide them it is
hardly surprising that disciplines do not pursue a logical division of the
terrain. In some cases several disciplines may share a phenomenon (often
without paying heed to the efforts of other disciplines to comprehend it); in
other cases a phenomenon may be ignored by all.
The task of classifying all of the phenomena that scientists study must
seem particularly daunting. Surely there are thousands upon thousands of
such phenomena? While this is true, these phenomena can be organized
hierarchically within a small number of larger categories. Krieger (1997, 31-
24 Chapter 2
This list of ten – eleven if health and population are treated separately –
logically distinct categories is also arguably exhaustive, for the ten categories
seem to subsume all human activities and characteristics. As Table 2.1
illustrates, it is straightforward to place all subsidiary phenomena within
these categories. In several cases, care must be taken to establish the
boundaries between categories: as noted above, art can be distinguished
from culture by defining art as that which has an aesthetic appeal not limited
to members of particular groups. These precise boundaries become clearer
as the categories are further disaggregated.
Table 2.1 reflects an extensive exercise in disaggeregation undertaken in
Szostak (2000, 2003). Both deduction and induction were used to develop
lists of second and then third-order phenomena (Note that these titles refer
only to the level of aggregation and imply no value judgment): induction in
the sense of finding a place in the classification for all phenomena discussed
in a wide variety of works consulted, and deduction in the sense of thinking
about how phenomena could logically be broken into their constituent parts.
The result should be nearly exhaustive, though some phenomena may have
been missed.1 It seems a reasonable conjecture that all phenomena that affect
human lives will have been noticed by someone sometime: the scholarly
community can thus aspire to an exhaustive list, at least at higher levels of
aggregation: sub-atomic particles are an obvious example of important
lower-level phenomena only observable with advanced scientific
1
One entry has, indeed, been added to the table. Though it was noted above that culture
will include attitudes toward most other categories, an entry for “attitudes toward healing”
was missing from previous versions of Table 2.1. This oversight (which was pointed out
to me) was especially egregious since Wissler, in his efforts decades ago to classify
phenomena, had grouped healing with religion.
26 Chapter 2
Individual (Abilities:)
Differences
Physical Abilities Speed, strength, endurance
Physical Appearance Height, weight, symmetry
Energy Level Physical, mental
Intelligences Musical, spatial, mathematical,
verbal, kinesthetic, interpersonal
(Personality:)
Sexual Orientation
Pahre (1990) argue that the discovery of new phenomena has been a key
component of advance in natural science in recent decades: they refer to
quarks, quasars, and DNA (and the greenhouse effect, which is a causal
link); for the most part, these new phenomena result from the unpacking of
previously recognized phenomena. It is thus still quite useful to classify
known phenomena, and add new phenomena as these are discovered.
30 Chapter 2
Alfred Kuhn’s (1974) definition of the elements of his system could serve
as a definition of phenomena as used here: any identifiable entities, concrete
or abstract, individual or collective.3 Kuhn speaks, though, of events.
Individual events would not be considered as phenomena here, for
phenomena are defined as ongoing, indeed timeless, characteristics of human
society. Individuals may differ in terms of personality, but a set of
personality dimensions are always with us. Genetic evolution may change
human aggressiveness, but attitude to aggression remains a phenomenon
worthy of study. Economic and political institutions evolve, and differ
across societies, but the classification of possible types of institution need not
change to capture this diversity (societies lacking a particular institution fit as
comfortably within the classification as those who differ in the details of
institutional structure).4 “The classes that are important in science are
2
Dogan (1996, 296) hypothesizes that if one developed a 12 by 12 grid of social science
disciplines, virtually every cell would contain some hybrid field. Certainly, if one were to
develop a grid of categories, or even second-level phenomena, one would find it
straightforward to identify causal linkages in most/all cells that deserved sustained
scholarly investigation.
3
The word phenomena has been given precise and conflicting definitions by philosophers
over the years. For Husserl, it referred to the essence of things, or “things in themselves”
which humans with limited sensual apparatus could only approach understanding of (see
below). Conversely, philosophers both before and after him have used the word to refer
instead to sensory perceptions of things. McKeon (1994) notes in this regard that the
Greek base of the word phenomenon is the same as the Latin base of the word appearance.
In this book, individual phenomena will be defined as precisely as possible, but it is
appreciated that human understanding is everywhere imperfect; the use of the word
phenomena here is thus distinct from either of these philosophical usages.
4
As society becomes more complex, scientists may become aware of new phenomena that
deserve to be classified. Note, though, that logically the classification is designed so that it
encompasses societies at all yet-realized levels of complexity. McKeon (1994, 330)
suggests that in science, as in philosophy, definitions of the phenomena being studied
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 31
change in X does so. Yet one key result of Szostak (2003) is that all
phenomena are influenced by many others. As the word influence captures
this idea of multiple causal links better than the word cause, it is generally
used here, though causation will from time to time be spoken of. This is
never meant to imply that only one phenomenon influences any other. The
phrase causal link has been retained because there is no obvious alternative,
and it is poor practice to create jargon unnecessarily. Both cause or
influence, then, refer merely to the various ways in which a realization of one
phenomenon induces a change in the realization of another.
Some scholars feel that it is inappropriate for human scientists to study
causation; they should instead deal only with interpretation of the meaning
individuals attach to situations. In both chapters 3 and 4 it will be shown that
such a distinction is both unnecessary and inadvisable. Interpretation can be
embraced without rejecting causation. Moreover interpretivists in practice
make causal arguments. We can thus join Singleton and Strait (1999, 24-6)
and many others in claiming that scientific understanding necessarily
involves the study of causal links.8
Embracing the study of causal links does not imply a lack of appreciation
of the multiple causation and feedback effects that characterize the world.
That is, phenomena often exert influence in combination with others, and the
phenomena affected by a causal link often exert some reactive influence.
These types of causation can be captured readily: imagine arrows joining and
moving in multiple directions among sets of phenomena in Table 2.1.9
The many advantages for both research and teaching in human science of
a classification of phenomena such as that outlined in Table 2.1 were
discussed at length in Szostak (2000, 2003). They are summarized here:
x It can change the “gestalt” of teachers and researchers such that they
more fully appreciate that the questions they concentrate upon are parts of
a much more complex “big picture”. It is all too easy for scholars to
8
Potter (2000, ch.8) celebrates realist philosophy. If one were to ask what the world would
have to look like for science to be successful, it would have to consist of things
[phenomena] that exert influences on each other.
9
Stump (1996, 449) is critical of science studies for looking only at socio-cultural
influences on science, and ignoring feedbacks. Dupr- (2001) is critical of both
evolutionary psychology and neoclassical economics for tending to assume that the
phenomena they emphasize exert exclusive influence on many others (and notes that
simplistic policy prescriptions follow in both cases). Similar critiques can be made of
other fields.
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 33
denigrate through ignorance links other than those they study, even when
these are closely related to their own research. Note in this regard
Bunge’s (1998, 17) feeling that perhaps the major failing of human
science theory is that it tends to involve too few relevant variables: he
appreciates that it is important not only to identify those phenomena
which exert an important influence, but those which must be held
constant for a posited causal link to operate (see chapter 3).10
x It should encourage a more balanced approach to research and teaching,
and also to public policy advice. At present some causal links are
virtually ignored by scholars, despite being of considerable intrinsic
importance. In particular, policy advice tends to reflect disciplinary
biases: economists focus on economic phenomena when judging trade
deals, and political scientists on political phenomena. Scholars providing
policy advice all too often ignore relevant links with respect to which
they lack expertise. Decision-makers are thus led to believe that they are
being given a more complete analysis than is the case.
x It provides a powerful illustration of the interconnected nature of human
science, and thus of the danger of barriers to interdisciplinary
communication. Take crime as an example: a moment’s reflection
indicates that a host of factors – genetic, individual differences, political,
social, cultural, and more – will influence crime, and thus that a
comprehensive analysis of crime must span many disciplines. The
classification points to (at least) the redefinition of the scope of existing
disciplines.
x By identifying which links researchers are investigating, it can allow
teachers and researchers to recognize when research in other disciplines
deals with the same link. The research performed for Szostak (2003)
uncovered many examples of scholars being completely unaware of
related research in other disciplines. Yet there are also times when
10
Kincaid (1996, 64-9) notes that scientists commonly make ceteris parabis assumptions:
they assume that all relevant variables outside those being studied do not change. In the
real world, especially in human science, this assumption is almost always violated. So
what kind of explanation do scientists provide? They explain certain causal links [Kincaid
speaks of “tendencies”] in isolation from those they regularly interact with. Can
confirmation be provided for a posited causal link that exists within a complex web of such
links? Yes. There may be times when the ceteris parabis world is approximated (naturally
or experimentally), the effect may be visible anyway (especially as the ceteris parabis
world is approached), it may be possible to identify other key influences and jointly
establish their relative importance, indirect evidence may be gained if the posited link
complements others that evidence exists for, and it may be possible to identify
intermediate variables. Blalock (1969), noting that it is infeasible to examine large
numbers of links simultaneously, recommended a block-recursive approach where sets of
links were analyzed. The danger here would be that scientists exaggerate the importance
of links within such blocks and downplay the importance of links between blocks.
34 Chapter 2
scholars engage in a debate without realizing that they are in fact talking
about different links. Economists may thus be befuddled by opposition
by political scientists to a trade deal that enhances economic outcomes;
an appreciation that political scientists stress links to, say, nationalism,
would encourage a more constructive exchange.
x The table can also provide a superior cataloguing system for human
science insights, and thus reduce the scholarly tendency to reinvent the
wheel (see chapter 7).
x It provides very precise definitions of phenomena in terms of the
phenomena into which they are unpacked. For example, culture equals
precisely the phenomena listed under “culture” in Table 2.1. It can thus
provide a solution to one of the greatest barriers to (especially
interdisciplinary) communication: the fact that different groups of
scholars tend to define the same word differently (and are often vague
about these definitions as well). At present, any reference to “culture” by
a scholar is necessarily ambiguous, given literally hundreds of competing
definitions. Scholars will be encouraged to specify which cultural
phenomena are particularly germane to their studies, rather than
appealing to the vague aggregate of culture.
x It provides a positive response to postmodern concerns with complexity,
while avoiding postmodern despair that enhanced understanding is
unattainable. A glance at Table 2.1 brings home powerfully the simple
point that human science must engage thousands of links among
thousands of phenomena. Yet it also suggests that the number of links is
finite and that understanding can be accumulated link by link.
x Grand theories can be mapped onto the list of phenomena, to show that
each is better suited to some links than others (see chapter 3). Scientists
should not leap from a conclusion that Marxian theory provides insight
into one link to an assumption that it provides insight into all; nor should
its failure to illuminate a particular link be taken as cause to reject the
theory for all links. The classification serves as a powerful antidote to the
siren song of grand theory: these are attractive because humans yearn for
a means of simplifying complexity. The classification of phenomena
allows scientists to cope with complexity while embracing theoretical
(and methodological) flexibility.
11
Table 2.1, like the alphabet, can seem daunting on one’s first acquaintance with it. But it
soon proves to be an extremely handy device for categorizing human science
understanding. Like a phone book, one need not memorize every entry in order to be able
to utilize it. Students should not be asked or expected to memorize the hundreds of entries,
but should over time gain an appreciation of the ten major categories and some familiarity
with at least second-level phenomena. If instructors, when introducing new topics, remind
students of where these fit schematically, the student should fairly effortlessly master the
table along with other material.
36 Chapter 2
phenomena within both the Social Structure (see Szostak, 2001) and
Culture (see Szostak, 2003) categories are causally related (in both
directions) to phenomena in all other categories. It thus simultaneously
provides responses to critiques from the “right” and “left” (see chapter 8,
Gaff, 1997). The classification also provides a response to those who
worry that universities and colleges do not adequately facilitate lifelong
learning (see above).
Table 2.1 is useful for the study of any subject in human science. Szostak
(2003) took culture as its focus. That work hopefully established both the
validity and value of the classification, by showing that it can easily organize
a complex literature into discussions of particular links (and indeed can
easily cope with multiple causation and feedback effects). Six broad lessons
emerged for the study of culture, which apply by extension to other
categories:
x Analysis is best performed in terms of subsidiary phenomena, rather than
at the vague level of culture itself. To understand the role of culture in
human societies, hundreds (thousands) of causal links must be
investigated.
x Attempts to unify this diverse literature in terms of a single theory or
method must necessarily severely oversimplify the complexity of culture.
x There are strong links both to and from cultural phenomena. It is thus a
mistake to view culture as either simply the cause or result of phenomena
in other categories (This means, among other things, that it is a mistake to
see either individuals or societal aggregates as uniquely cause or effect;
see Bunge, 1998, 64).
x The siren song of grand theory (or method) is hard to resist in the absence
of some other mechanism for integrating insights into diverse linkages.
Prus (1996), for example, argues that culture can only be understood
through the single lens of his favored theory and method. The
classification of phenomena serves as an antidote to grand theory by
providing a means of organizing diverse causal analyses into a coherent
whole.
x The classification serves an invaluable pedagogical role. The student can
be exposed to a wide range of links (The book treated those generally
considered most important plus many that receive less or sometimes no
attention). Instructors will naturally focus on a subset of these, without
giving students a misleading sense of completeness. Students can be
encouraged to make presentations, write short papers, and so on, on links
not covered by the instructor.
x Notably the classification guides scholars to avoid three problems
identified by Cornwell and Stoddard (1999) as commonly afflicting
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 37
12
That, at least, was the intention. In some cases, such as the unpacking of occupations, it
was particularly difficult to identify universals. But generally this was not problematic.
38 Chapter 2
doubt the very existence of reality,13 however, and would suggest that any
phenomenon is merely a social construct (or perhaps a scientific construct).
That is, there was no such thing as “attitude toward ambition” or “income
distribution” or “personality dimensions” or even “climate” out there until
humans thought of such things. Some who hold to this view doubt the very
possibility of science: they suspect that every individual creates their own
reality and thus that there is no truth for scientists to attempt to uncover (see
chapter 5). Others are less pessimistic, still embrace the study of phenomena
and causal links, and ask only that scientists be particularly careful to avoid
scientific bias (again, see chapter 5). This book relies on a Golden Mean
perspective that there is an external reality, but limits to human abilities to
perceive and comprehend this.14
Seale (1999, 88) notes that those who deny the existence of an external
reality could argue that distinctions between data, theory, and research [or
method or phenomena] are just elements of a language game;15 “I would
argue that at the very least it is a game that we must choose whether or not to
play.” Seale goes on to stress that if an external reality is accepted, these
distinctions are both valid and important.
A list of phenomena such as that in Table 2.1 inevitably raises the
question of reductionism. However, Szostak (2003) found that explanation
should not, and cannot, always be reduced to the lowest possible level of
aggregation, for higher-level phenomena exhibit emergent properties.
Bhushan and Rosenfeld (2000, 5) make a similar argument that chemistry
cannot be reduced to physics, as do Mahner and Bunge (1997, 197) with
respect to biology and physics.
What do phenomena do? Wherever possible, phenomena in Table 2.1
have been defined in terms of the role they play in human societies. Thus,
each phenomenon is functionally unique. This in turn is why subsidiary
13
“It is one of my premises that most people operate as though reality does exist. It is only
academics who make a living arguing the opposite” (Oakley, 2000, 20): Oakley goes on to
suggest that even these academic sceptics generally treat the world as real as they perform
their research.
14
Weingart (2000) suggests that most interdisciplinarians assume an external reality that
interdisciplinary analysis can enhance understanding of. He worries, though, that any
organization of knowledge is inherently arbitrary: environmental studies may be shaped
more by opportunities for funding than any external reality. While the boundaries of
disciplines and interdisciplinary fields are arbitrary, this book is based on the premise that
objective classifications of phenomena, data, theory, and method are possible.
15
Woolgar (1988) argues that there are no objects before our representation of them; this
argument would seem to fly in the face of everyday experience. Prus (1996) does not
doubt that there are real phenomena “out there,” but argues that these resist efforts to
comprehend them. Understanding is thus subjective, and each individual’s perceptions are
shaped by their cultural environment. Nevertheless, a considerable degree of consensus
can be achieved on a list of phenomena such as that in Table 2.1.
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 39
16
Baird (2000) notes that instruments are often hailed for “objectivity” because they produce
quantitative readouts. Judgment is still required as to whether readouts reflect reality.
This narrower sense of objectivity should not be confused with the broader and ubiquitous
need for scientific judgment. Baird worries that the advent of sophisticated instruments
has contributed to the devaluation of the importance of scientific judgment.
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 41
impact?; and under what circumstances does this effect occur? These are the sorts of
questions to be answered in identifying causal links. His other two questions deal with
whether X is related to, and/or similar to Y; as noted with respect to Halperin, such
questions could be asked of both phenomena and links.
18
A handful of scholars were invited to address “Disciplinary keywords and their evolved
meanings” in The Chronicle of Higher Education 49:26. The term “Identity” is used by
scholars to speak to at least two distinct phenomena: visions of self within individual
schemas, and identification with groups; in uses such as “identity politics” it refers to a
causal link between such groups and political phenomena. “Postmodernism” is most often
a critique of scientific practice, but in some hands a theoretical position or even a statement
about realizations of phenomena. Various words such as “art”, “tradition”, and “text” have
come to encompass a wider range of phenomena over time. These examples highlight both
the possibility of and advantages of defining concepts more precisely.
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 43
19
To be sure, Bal is at times quite skeptical of the possibility of firm definitions, and even
celebrates the fact that different scholars will necessarily interpret concepts differently.
Nevertheless, she urges scholars to attempt to agree on what particular concepts mean.
44 Chapter 2
20
The term “meaning” itself is often equated with “authorial/artist intent”, but not always
(Bal, 2002, 23). So authors need to be careful in defining “meaning” itself. Bal (p.27)
suggests that students are required to choose a definition of “meaning”; why, though,
should students not be urged to embrace all possible definitions (and the causal links they
imply): artist intent, audience reaction, and so on? – they could still choose to specialize
with respect to one of these (or not) without needing to assume the others away.
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 45
2. CLASSIFYING DATA
Data are by definition that which can be observed.21 Data might thus be
classified in terms of humanity’s five perceptual senses: sight, hearing, taste,
touch, and smell. In actuality, science relies heavily on the first two of these.
Since none of these senses are perfect, greater use might perhaps be made of
the latter three senses: it could be that errors in these are poorly correlated
with errors in sight or hearing (this is an argument that will be made with
respect to different methods in chapter 4). Bhushan and Rosenfeld (2000,
11-12) note, for example, that while scientists are aware of visual illusions,
there may be no such thing as smell illusion, since the sense of smell is
triggered by direct contact with molecules. More generally, they note that
chemists, like other scientists, have emphasized the visual; thus in the area of
odor research there has been a tendency to borrow inappropriate research
techniques from visual research. While classifications of visual stimuli
(color, shape, size) have long existed, classification of odors has hardly
begun. In any case, scientists should certainly be aware of the limitations of
the human perceptual apparatus (see Jackendoff, 1992).
Nevertheless, it seems more useful to classify data in terms of their nature
than in terms of perceptual apparatus. Three broad categories of data can be
observed:
x inanimate objects
x living things, including people
x events (interactions among beings and objects)
21
Mahner and Bunge (1997, 74) would define a datum as a statement about a fact, such as
“W exists” or “X is in state Y”. Such statements can be more or less true. The approach
taken here equates data with the facts themselves. The perceptual and cognitive errors that
can affect a scientist’s perception of the data will be treated in chapter 5.
46 Chapter 2
22
Tashakkori and Teddlie (1998, ch.6) distinguish between quantitative and qualitative data.
They note, though, that one can quantify qualitative data (by for example measuring what
proportion of people display a particular emotion in a particular situation) and alternatively
treat quantitative data in a qualitative way (using words like “very” for example).
48 Chapter 2
chapter, recognition of the possibility of some overlap among types need not
destroy the utility of a classification.
23
Pahre (1996, 206) notes that data can cross disciplinary boundaries easily, whereas a
lengthy conversation is generally required with respect to transmission of theory and
method. If data need interpretation, interdisciplinary transmission becomes more difficult.
2. Classifying Phenomena and Data 49
Palys (1997, ch.4) notes that scientists cannot avoid the question of
operationalizing the phenomena they wish to study. This is as true for
qualitative as for quantitative research. It is also true for inductive research,
though in this case the process works in reverse: data is first gathered and in
the process of theorizing it is associated with the phenomena that is theorized
about. Since operationalization is essential but necessarily imperfect,
scientists should be open both about the precise nature of the
operationalization that they choose and the justification that they can provide
for this (which may hinge largely on data availability), and alert to potential
50 Chapter 2
biases and errors.24 Scientific communities may agree on best practices with
respect to operationalization; this reduces opportunities for individual
researcher bias but increases the risk of reification.
The scientific community as a whole is guided to seek multiple sources of
data that might shed light on a particular phenomenon or link (Tashakkori
and Teddlie, 1998, ch. 6). In later chapters similar arguments will be made
with respect to theory and method, and 5W typologies used as guides to what
sorts of theories and methods are best suited to particular research
questions.25 The 5W approach is less helpful here, though it is likely true
that if similar results are achieved using different types of data great
confidence can be placed in these results. If different data do not agree, the
temptation to simply ignore inconvenient results needs to be avoided. Note
also that the choice of method – and to a lesser extent theory – constrains the
type of data utilized, and thus later chapters will provide more precise, albeit
indirect, advice on what types of data to embrace.
Who is analyzing the data? This, as with the ‘Who?’ question in chapter
one, raises questions of scientific bias that will be addressed in chapter 5.
24
“All terms used in descriptions or explanations must be specifically and realistically
defined. This makes it possible for someone else to understand explicitly what the facts
are, and perhaps carry out further tests of the facts or explanations. Operational definitions
make ideas testable” (Valiela, 2001, 6).
25
When evaluating methods in chapter 4, the criteria of reliability and validity will be
discussed. Palys (1997) applies these criteria to operationalization. Operationalization is
reliable if similar studies using this operationalization, especially with different
researchers, provide similar results. With respect to validity, a researcher must show that
the operationalization is associated with the phenomenon in question (this is termed
convergent validity) and not with others (divergent validity).
Chapter 3
CLASSIFYING THEORY
1
Moran (2002, 87) suggests that much recent theory in the humanities has been about how
scholarship should proceed. He discusses queer theory, and notes that this is as much a
critique of whether “homosexual” is a meaningful category as an investigation of causal
relationships. As noted in chapter 1, scientific analysis of links can inform questions of the
legitimacy of certain phenomena. Moran notes that queer theory has difficulty coping with
arguments that there may be a genetic basis for homosexuality.
2
Bruce Hunter, in private correspondence, has encouraged careful use of the word “should”
here. A scientist might reasonably wonder how an institution “should” work if official
rules were followed to the letter (or how an organism should function in the environment it
was selected for); an ethicist would instead wonder how institutional rules should be
constructed ideally.
52 Chapter 3
3
Care should be taken that a theory crafted to explain certain empirical regularities is not
tested only with respect to these. Karl Popper thus emphasized the importance of “novel
facts.” While he meant these in a temporal sense, Imre Lakatos argued that it was
important only that some supporting evidence not have guided the original development of
the theory (Motterlini, 1999). This insight supports indirectly the conjectures of this book
that evidence from multiple methods and data types is desirable.
4
Merton is generally credited with coining the phrase “middle-range theory.” Goldenberg
(1992) discusses how Merton and Mills wished to avoid the extremes of grand theory and
empiricism, by developing theories whose scope encouraged the interplay between theory
and empirics essential to scientific advance. Our usage of the term is a bit looser than
theirs.
3. Classifying Theory 53
One fairly clumsy way by which one might classify narrow theories is in
terms of the phenomenon or link to which they apply. Middle-range theories
would be a yet trickier subject, though one could hope to map the extent of
such theories onto a list of phenomena such as that provided in Table 2.1
(that is, draw arrows between phenomena to reflect the direction(s) of
causality implied by the theory). Such a mapping can be useful in providing
a quick and memorable guide to what a particular theory is about. Given the
number, and tendency to overlap, of middle-range theories, such mapping
would provide a messy device for remembering the place of all such theories.
It might, though, provide a useful means for cataloguing such theories so that
researchers interested in a particular set of phenomena could readily access
theories old and new which dealt with similar sets of phenomena (see chapter
7). In developing a typology later in this chapter, the subject matter of a
theory will naturally be a key concern.
In the case of grand theory, a list can be attempted of at least those
theories that have received significant scholarly attention. Yet scholarly
attention itself can be a problem, for theories evolve through time, and may
well split or coalesce: it may thus be far from clear where one theory ends
and another begins. Collins (1998) argues persuasively that a community of
scholars can only cope with a handful of competing theories at any point in
time. There is thus a constant pressure for some theoretical perspectives to
be merged, as others are split. While his focus was on philosophical
argumentation, a similar logic likely applies in science. Specialization
allows the scientific community as a whole to embrace an almost infinite
number of more narrowly focussed theories, but at the level of grand theory
there can be room for only a few. Even here, though, there is clearly room
for more than the handful posited by Collins. Different grand theories
emphasize different causal forces (and often thus different subsets of
phenomena), and thus encourage quite different research agendas. While
some grand theories do compete with others, in other cases scholars
interested in a particular grand theory may find that various other grand
theories deal with an entirely different set of questions. There is thus room
for different groups of scholars to focus on different sets of grand theory.
It might be thought that zoologists can hope to provide systems of
classification that do not require constant revision due to the sluggish pace of
genetic evolution. However, as only some 10% of the world’s biota is
classified, discovery of new species is a regular occurrence. These provide
little difficulty for zoologists if there is a logical place for them in existing
classifications. The emergence of new theories is more problematic for
classifications of theory, precisely because existing classifications are ad
hoc. Moreover, care must be taken in examining the work of past
generations of scientists: they likely saw the theoretical possibilities before
54 Chapter 3
them quite differently from what we do: Durkheim was thus viewed as
having been a social theorist in the 1920s but was categorized as a
functionalist in the 1970s (Freidheim, 1982, 4). Until a typology of theory,
defined in terms of an exhaustive set of criteria, is developed, it is impossible
to develop a timeless list of theories; only a snapshot of the theories in vogue
at a particular point in time is possible. The development of such a typology
will be the primary focus of this chapter.
With this important caveat in mind, a list of “grand theories in human
science that are currently embraced by large numbers of researchers” can be
attempted. The chapter headings in The Blackwell Companion to Social
Theory (B. Turner, 2000), provides a useful starting point:
x Action theory
x Systems theory, and functionalism
x Psychoanalysis
x Structuralism
x Symbolic Interactionism
x Rational Choice theory
x Phenomenology
x Feminism
x Cultural Studies
x Postmodernism
Not all of these, to be sure, are theories in the sense the word is used in
this chapter. Postmodernism, for example, is more a critique of the
possibilities of knowledge, and an advocacy of a turn away from grand
theory, than a grand theory in its own right. Likewise, feminism
encompasses a dizzying array of perspectives on scientific practice. Note,
though, that most of the rest do indeed serve the role of grand theory. And
they generally do this by guiding scientists to look for the same thing across
a wide range of links. Rational choice theory guides scientists to ask what
rational calculating individuals would do in the circumstance in question.
Functionalism guides scientists to ask what purpose an institution or attitude
serves. Psychoanalysis guides scientists to look at the conflicts raging within
subconscious minds.
Narrower theories are often a combination of aspects of grand theories,
applied to a particular research question. A scientist may posit that the link
between two phenomena reflects a particular interaction among rational
calculation, symbolism, and the role that one phenomenon plays in
supporting the other. Categorizing grand theory, then, can provide insight
into the nature of at least some narrower theories as well.
Is the above list exhaustive? The absence of Marxian theory or theories
(which is discussed briefly in several of the chapters), which still motivates a
3. Classifying Theory 55
range of scholars, suggests that it is not. Nor does the list mention
evolutionary psychology, which motivates large numbers of researchers. But
it nevertheless likely captures the majority of grand theories in widespread
use today. Without any objective criteria for judging what qualifies as a
distinct grand theory, an exhaustive list would be controversial. The
scholarly community as a whole might nevertheless be able to achieve a fair
degree of consensus.
1. TYPOLOGY OF THEORY
5
Scholars such as Wallace, Ritzer, and Freidheim have bemoaned the tendency to classify
theories only in terms of their philosophical or sociological origins, rather than in terms of
their internal properties. Moreover, when internal properties are discussed, there is
disagreement as to whether this should be in terms of philosophical principles, some model
of science, some view of the world, or the subject content of a theory (Freidheim, 1982, 4-
7). Freidheim (1982) herself proposed that theories could be distinguished in terms of
whether their goal was explanation or prediction; however scientists should not classify
theories in terms of the goals of the theorist, and should only trust a theory’s predictions if
it has explanatory capability (see below).
56 Chapter 3
problem: theories tend to evolve through time, and thus typing these in terms
of the intentions of the original theorist is quite problematic.
1.1 Who?
Most theories deal with how one or more phenomena influence one or
more others. Less commonly, but importantly, theories discuss the nature of
or internally generated transformations in one phenomenon. In either case
scientists investigate how changes, perhaps just relative to some
hypothesized alternative, in realizations of one (set of) phenomenon will
affect either itself or other phenomena. In asking ‘Who?’, then, scientists are
asking “Who is effecting change?” Any theory must grapple with agency at
this level. If it is said that “racist attitudes cause X,” it will be a vague theory
indeed unless the type of agent that holds such attitudes is specified. If
scholars speak of the effects of aggressive behavior they should specify
whose behavior. In most instances, the type of agent that responds to the
initiating change must also be specified.
Two important distinctions must be made here. The first involves
whether the agent is capable of intentional behavior. Non-Intentional Agents
provide most of the subject matter of the natural sciences. Atoms and
chemicals and even tornados cannot have intentions. Biologists, at least,
often investigate intentionality. Social scientists most often deal with
intentional agents, but far from always. Note in particular that institutions
and organizations, though created through human intentionality, can then
exert influences non-intentionally. Table 2.1 lists several other non-
intentional agents, such as level of income, population distribution, and
gender divisions.6 Within both intentionality and non-intentionality, it is
useful to distinguish three different types of agent:
x Individual Agents. Intentional theories here commonly focus on a typical
individual. They may also explore how different types of individual will
act in a particular situation. Theories may emphasize the effects of
individual acts, though these theories should engage the possibility of
feedback effects, such that the individual’s actions or beliefs are
|themselves conditioned by the effects these are deemed likely to have.
To understand why an individual behaved or believed as they did, it is
necessary to look within the individual at genetic predispositions,
abilities, or personality dimensions. Theories of individual agency can
embrace both subconscious motives of which the agent is consciously
6
Pahre (1996, 206) finds it useful to stress that natural science and social science cannot be
distinguished on the basis of intentionality.
3. Classifying Theory 57
unaware and also “accidents” in which neither the agent’s conscious nor
subconscious minds imagined the outcome.
Newtonian mechanics provides an example of a non-intentional theory
focused upon individual agency. Here the scholar analyses the behavior
of individual particles or bodies that are presumed to act as a single unit.
x Groups of Individuals: Talcott Parsons hypothesized four types of social
group worthy of scientific analysis (see Freidheim, 1982). The first is the
primary group or family. This has deservedly been the focus of a great
deal of scientific analysis. While some theories may reduce familial
behavior to some weighted sum of the actions and wishes of individual
family members, many theories posit that families are not just the sum of
their parts. Parsons’ second type is the organization. As hinted above, an
understanding of organizations may require a mix of non-intentional and
intentional theorizing; again, organizations are not just the sum of their
parts. Parsons also spoke of community and society. The first of these
refers to groups operating in a non-formal fashion, as in developing
cultural guidelines. The study of society, which operates through formal
institutions, requires a mix of intentional and non-intentional insights.
Statistical mechanics deals with distributions of velocities among
groups of particles. The magnitudes that are important are group
averages. Natural scientists have long distinguished these sorts of
theories from the individual-agent analysis discussed above. A perennial
question in physics is how these two types of theories might be tied
together, and whether analysis at the group level reflects either a physical
reality or ignorance about how individual particles interact. Krieger
(1997, 20, 57) notes that sometimes the behavior of a group of particles is
the average or sum of individual particle behavior, and sometimes not;
there are emergent properties of families of particles that are not apparent
at the level of individual particles.
x Relationships. Some “interactionist” scholars argue that what happens
between people is more important than what happens within them:
individuals are reconstituted through their interaction with others
(Barnes, 1995).7 Interactionists thus theorize about the effects that
various types of human relationship have. While there are obvious
7
Unfortunately, Barnes argues that only relational theory is valid. He suggests that
individual-level theory is wrong because tastes are not fixed, and functional theory is
wrong because norms are not fixed (they are manipulated rather than taken). As with all
who argue for one type of causal agent, he ignores the simple fact that the world is a
complex web of causal links: the fact that an agent is acted upon does not preclude them
from exercising causal influence. His suggestion that individuals always try to maximize
pride and minimize shame in relationships (which would allow him to ignore how
individuals shape relationships) is a dangerous oversimplification of human motivation.
58 Chapter 3
8
Ritzer had hypothesized three different types of social theory centred on social facts
(structures and institutions), social behaviors (how individuals respond to situations), and
social definitions (which at least in part dealt with group processes). He noted that writers
of all three types spoke as if their view embraced all, but argued that different data (for
which I would read “phenomena”) required different approaches (in Freidheim, 1982). I
have argued that even individual phenomena will benefit from different approaches.
60 Chapter 3
approaches”; if Jones (1985, 1) were right in this, and note that he wrote
before rational choice theory (see below) gained widespread popularity in
sociology, it could still be hoped that sociologists would be open to insights
from other disciplines which provided a complementary individual-agency
analysis. However, Jones continues that sociologists should look at such
approaches and discover (only) “what is wrong or incomplete about them”.
He then criticizes arguments from genetic tendencies on the grounds that
there are exceptions to many commonly posited links, and arguments from
personality on the grounds that personality is influenced by environment.
But these are not arguments against individual-level explanation but only for
enhancing scientific understanding of the nature of individuals and the
influences upon them. Little (1998, viii) argues in turn that the types of
theory which Jones favors require “at least a stylized conception of how
individuals within social contexts bring about these relationships,” because
there are “no supra-individual actors in social causation.” But Little cannot
have it both ways: claiming some limited possibility for theory at the
aggregate level while denying any form of non-individual agency. Either
everything can be understood in terms only of individual behavior, or the
causal power of social aggregates must be recognized.9 As Bunge (1998)
emphasizes, social aggregates have emergent properties not inherent in the
individuals that comprise them.
To recapitulate: the most common argument against the conclusion that
multiple theories are necessary is an argument that only one type of agency
exists, and this argument fails on several grounds. First, it fails the Golden
Mean test in that legions of scientists over the years have found analysis of
different types of agency valuable. Second, it requires that many of the
phenomena identified in chapter 2 be ignored; yet scientists have found all of
these phenomena useful for analytical purposes. Third, arguments in
defence of the position are faulty: humans live in a complex world of
multiple causation wherein all phenomena are both causes and effects of
others; arguing that X causes Y does not preclude the possibility that Y also
exerts influences upon other phenomena; indeed the existence of Y implies
this.
9
Little nevertheless accepts that multiple theories are necessary, at least in human science.
“Instead, the social sciences inherently consist of a messy, cross-cutting, overlapping set of
theories, hypotheses, causal models, idealized facts, interpretive principles, and bodies of
empirical findings that eliminate but do not reduce.” He likely exaggerates the orderly
nature of natural science.
3. Classifying Theory 61
1.2 What?
Having identified the agents of change, a theory must then cope with the
question of “What do change agents do?” In the case of non-intentional
agency, agents usually cannot actively do anything (tornados providing an
obvious exception). They are thus restricted to a passive form of action
wherein they provide constraints and/or incentives. It should be emphasized
that these effects can be of huge importance despite their passive nature.
Intentional individuals and especially groups can also act passively. They
also share with natural phenomena such as tornados the capacity to act
actively: to do something in common parlance. They also have the ability to
act in a way that by their nature non-intentional agents cannot: they can form
beliefs or attitudes or intentions. That is, they can have causal effects
through thoughts as well as deeds. And these thoughts can be analysed at the
level of individuals and at the level of groups; in the latter case, one can
speak of culture or public opinion or ideology or nationalism.
There are, then, three types of “what” which map imperfectly onto the six
types of “who” identified above. Most non-intentional agents are only
capable of passive causation. Some are also capable of active causation
(note that the existence of tornados places constraints and incentives on
human activity, quite apart from the active behavior of any particular
tornado). Intentional individuals are capable of all three types of causation.
Intentional groups likely have greater powers at passive causation than
individuals, and can also act and form collective beliefs. Intentional
relationships are often posited to affect mostly attitudes, but can also induce
actions and provide constraints.
One might also make a distinction between whether agents are “acting”
or “reacting”. It has been argued, though, that the world is a complex web of
multiple causation. Every phenomenon influences and is influenced by
hundreds of others. Every act, whether passive or active, action or attitude,
is necessarily conditioned by the numerous influences upon the phenomenon
in question. A scientist studying reaction is explicitly taking these into
account. A scientist studying action is treating these as exogenous for the
moment and focussing upon effects. A scientist who imagines that there are
no antecedent causes commits a metaphysical as well as scientific error.
More commonly such scientists are merely pursuing scientific specialization.
Depending on the nature of feedback effects, their investigations may yield
valuable insights. As was argued in chapter 2, scientists should study
individual causal links, but understand that any one link must be placed
within the broader context of related links.
As with agency, it is possible to disaggregate the types of action
described above. Table 2.1 provides much less guidance here: it suggests
62 Chapter 3
10
Seale (1999, 22) can be joined in decrying the oversimplification involved in terms like
“positivist,” which tend to lump together scholars with diverse perspectives on many
issues. Nevertheless, certain common or average tendencies can be identified in what
follows.
3. Classifying Theory 63
11
The economist Milton Friedman famously argued in the 1950s that the test of economic
theory should be its ability to predict: scientists should not mind if assumptions are
unrealistic as long as the results are accurate. But this argument is rarely voiced
(consciously) today; it is widely recognized that people can have little faith in predictions
if they do not really believe the model that generates them. A theory’s ability to predict
thus depends on the theory’s ability to explain, as well as the degree of stochasticity (see
below) in the theory.
64 Chapter 3
people buy less coffee when the price rises, can they not aspire to explain
this result?12
Bunge (1998) provides numerous examples of the productive mixing of
positivist and interpretive approaches. Most branches of psychology blend
analysis of thought and action. Bunge emphasizes in particular how
neuroscience – the analysis of physical changes in the brain – has and will
aid scientific understanding of how people think and act. He notes that some
aspects of thought clearly require positivist explanations, as when brain
injuries interfere with the language faculty. Moreover, human fallibility
means that scientists cannot attribute the results of intentional actions
entirely to intentions, but must pay heed to unforeseen consequences. Nor
can scientists ignore those intentions, and treat actions as the unmediated
responses to certain stimuli. Even in cases such as the rising price of coffee,
there will be scope for interpretation (for example, of whether one’s social
standing depends on coffee consumption), and in other cases this may
swamp other considerations.13 Like Potter, Bunge appreciates that a
compromise is desirable in terms of both method and theory.
It was noted in the preceding section that scientists should be open to
combinations of theories embracing different types of agency. The same
result has now emerged with respect to “what”: scientists should embrace
positivist (action-based), interpretivist (attitude-based) and passive
(constraint and incentive based) theories. Similar results will emerge in the
next three sections as well (and will be italicized each time).
12
Peter Winch and other interpretivists have claimed that human motives are distinct from
causes, and thus interpretation must be different from explanation (B. Turner, 2000). But
surely it makes sense to speak of a person’s anger causing them to strike out. Kincaid
(1996, ch.6) argues that interpretive science is difficult but possible, provides examples of
good and bad interpretive practice (notably a tendency toward tautological arguments, as
when a norm is imagined that would generate observed behavior), argues that
interpretivism does not preclude other types of human science inquiry, and suggests that
interpretivism does not need special methods or evidence. We will see, though, that
interpretivists can have access to different methods and data.
13
Bunge then argues that in accepting an extreme criticism of objectivity and scientism,
interpretivists have accomplished little and done much damage. Likewise, B. Turner
(2000) bemoans the cultural turn in modern sociology which he credits with being
speculative rather than empirical, idealist rather than realist, concerned with images rather
than causal links, focussed on particularities rather than generalities, and thus engaged in
“the narcissistic study of its own textual traditions” (xv); he too urges a combination of
approaches. Similar arguments were made about positivist narrowmindedness in Szostak
(1999).
66 Chapter 3
1.3 Why?
“Why did the agent(s) act (react) as they did?” Whether scientists are
primarily concerned with causes or effects, they must engage this question.
In the case of a non-intentional agent, analysis must proceed in terms of the
constraints and incentives inherent in its nature. In the case of intentional
agents the decision-making process involved must be investigated. There are
five ways in which agents might make any decision. As will be discussed in
chapter 5, this list was first derived inductively, and underpins the five types
of ethical analysis. It can also be derived deductively, by asking what
possible alternatives there are to these processes.
x Rational/Consequentialist. Agents focus on desirable consequences, and
try to rationally calculate the best way to achieve those goals. An agent
deciding whether to continue in school would thus try to carefully
evaluate the costs and benefits of doing so in terms of the goals they hope
to achieve. Their ability to do so depends on their ability to accurately
perceive how the world works, and thus on their schemas (see Table 2.1).
Agents may be selfish or altruistic, and focussed on a diverse set of
genetic drives or personal desires, and these latter may reflect
sociocultural influences to varying degrees.
x Intuitive: Agents act on what their “gut” tells them, without much
conscious thought. An agent might thus drop out of school because it
feels good. An agent’s intuition may guide them toward satisfying
various genetic drives. It may act upon various subconscious schemas
about how the world works, the accuracy of which depends on the agent’s
lifetime experience, and particularly of traumatic events. It may thus
guide agents toward acts they would not rationally (consciously)
countenance.
x Traditional/Cultural. Agents are guided to do “what is done around
here.” For example, if everyone in their peer group is staying in school
they will too. This sort of decision-making at times occur intuitively, if
agents have internalized their group’s attitudes and will feel guilt for
breaking them. However, it generally has some conscious element,
where an agent’s desire to fit in overwhelms any other consequences.
x Rules. Agents follow a set of rules, which they have previously
determined to be socially desirable. These may or not accord with
cultural guidelines. Agents have devoted some thought to them (which in
turn may be influenced by any of the five decision-making processes).
Common examples are the Golden Rule, Kantian Imperative, or a belief
in Rights. But a host of more specific rules are also possible: agents may
for example believe that premarital sex is either a wonderful idea or a
3. Classifying Theory 67
14
Dupré (2001, 117) suggests that philosophers believe that an action can only be explained
in terms of goals and reasons to believe that actions further those goals. He then
recognizes culture as an alternative, and later refers to “principles” that might guide action.
His discussion suggests that greater scholarly familiarity with the five types of decision-
making is advisable.
68 Chapter 3
1.4 Where?
“Where does whatever the agent does (and the reactions to this) occur?”
This question can be interpreted both literally and figuratively. Literally, one
can wonder where in the real world “it” happens. There are two broad
possibilities: that “it” can happen anywhere, or that “it” can only happen in
certain specified situations. Figuratively, one can think of Table 2.1, and a
similar construct for natural science, as a map of the potential set of causal
links, and ask where on that map “it” occurs (one could, that is, draw arrows
connecting the phenomena embraced by the theory). Again, a theory that
speaks to a very small set of causal links can be distinguished from one that
implies that the same effect is felt along a wide array of causal links. Since
different sorts of phenomena exhibit different sorts of agency, no theory
could posit that any one sort of agency was directly reflected along all links;
other links might nevertheless encompass reactions to the particular type of
agency being studied.
Both in the literal and figurative cases, a search for general regularities
can be distinguished from a search for particularities. Philosophers have
since the turn of the last century used the words “nomothetic” and
“idiographic” to refer to these two types of analysis. As noted in the first
chapter, there has been a fair bit of confusion about what exactly these words
mean, what it is that they refer to, and where the boundary between the two
might lie. The apparent answer to the second query is that they represent
different sorts of answer to the question of “Where?” the causal relationship
under question occurs.
As for the first query, the literal and figurative readings of the question
provide different interpretations. The literal interpretation refers to
realizations of phenomena other than those specified within the causal
relationship itself. That is, if it is said that “it” can only happen in the
mountains, a particular realization of the phenomenon “topography” is being
specified. And if a scientist specifies that it can only happen in home or
office, the scientist needs to carefully specify what aspects of relationships,
family structure, occupation, technology, or several other phenomena are in
fact crucial. Nomothetic theory can be defined as that which posits a general
relationship among two or more phenomena, and idiographic theory as that
which posits a relationship only under specified conditions.
The figurative reading refers instead to causal links. A nomothetic theory
is one that suggests a relationship that operates along many causal links: a
perfectly nomothetic theory would apply directly or indirectly to all links. It
is thus a theory that applies over different sets of phenomena. Idiographic
theory refers instead to a causal relationship that affects a small number of
causal links: a perfectly idiographic theory would embrace only one causal
3. Classifying Theory 69
link. Idiographic theory would thus in the extreme apply to only one set of
phenomena.
Defining a boundary between nomothetic and idiographic theory is
problematic in both cases. There is instead a continuum: in the first case
running from specifying no external conditions to specifying these in terms
of all other phenomena,15 in the second case running from application to one
set of phenomena to application to all sets. The only way to avoid a random
cutoff is to define one of these terms with respect to an extreme position. To
do that with nomothetic theory would be ridiculous, for some set of
phenomena or external conditions for which a posited relationship fails to
hold can always be found.16 Nor can idiographic theory be held to the
impossible standard of always identifying realizations of every phenomenon
whether these are inside or outside the causal relationship in question.
As noted in the introductory chapter, well-defined boundaries are not
essential for a classification to be useful. Nomothetic and idiographic can be
helpful classes, even if every theory cannot flawlessly be placed into one
class or another. Not only is there no obvious cutoff, but a given theory may
seem to be nomothetic along one continuum and idiographic along the other.
Scientists should be aware that there is a role for both types of theory within
the scientific enterprise. Schaffner (2000), for example, suggests that
biology would benefit from theories at different levels of generality.
Theorists should struggle to be as explicit as possible about what can be
termed the “range of applicability” of theories: over what particular links
does the theory apply, and under what precise conditions (thus while
generalizability is measured along two continua, range of applicability is
defined precisely in terms of particular links and phenomena; empirical
research should strive to identify how strong the theory is in each of its uses
as well). Indeed, this is one of the primary goals of science, and one area in
which natural science excels over human science.
Scientists often employ the ceteris parabis (all other things remaining the
same) assumption. This can be a useful nomothetic tool. When an
economist theorizes that the increased price of a good will cause decreases in
consumption, ceteris parabis, they are positing a general relationship that
may fail to be observed empirically if overwhelmed by other changes (such
as an increase in income). But even here ideally the theorist (or at least the
community of scientists as a whole) would identify the widest range of
15
Freidheim (1982, 19) distinguishes between interactive types of theory, which describe the
effects of all possible combinations of variables, and ideal types, in which certain
combinations are stressed. While ideal types can be valuable, their limits must carefully be
identified, and what happens outside of this range of applicability investigated.
16
Bunge (1998, 26) notes that social regularities usually hold only for particular times and
places, and that chemical regularities only hold for a range of temperature and pressure.
70 Chapter 3
possible countervailing factors. And the general use of ceteris parabis often
clouds the nomothetic/idiographic distinction: scientists not only ignore the
possible changes in other phenomena (including sometimes feedback effects
from the changes they analyze) that would overturn their results, but even
static realizations of other phenomena that would do so (such as a belief that
price signals quality).17
The careful specification of ceteris parabis assumptions is just one area
in which nomothetic and idiographic theory can usefully be blended.
Economists tend to apply rational choice theory (see below), but are open to
a recognition that certain factors – particularly imperfect access to
information – can interfere with rational behavior. Their response to
arguments that rationality is generally “bounded” can be characterized as “So
what; we’ll just specify the relevant constraints.” This is a compelling
viewpoint, except when it is appreciated how often these constraints simply
overwhelm rational decision-making (see Fuller, 1993, 180). The upshot is
that rational choice analysis often generates the wrong result, and that it can
only be constructively applied in conjunction with a careful consideration of
the factors impeding rational behavior in a particular circumstance (Szostak,
1999). This is an example of a wider truth: scientists should seek a mixture
of nomothetic and idiographic theory.
Previous sections have discussed how answers to the “what” and “why”
questions were related to answers to the “who” question. Are nomothetic
and idiographic theory of different relative importance depending on who
the change agent is? Within the original formulation by Rickert, with its
emphasis on covering laws, the answer would surely be yes. For as Little
(1998) forcefully argues, covering laws are best suited to non-intentional
causation. A covering law stipulates a necessary relationship: if X then Y.
This can be observed in the natural world, as in the Laws of
Thermodynamics. However, as noted above, if human agency is involved
any where in the causal process, there will almost certainly be exceptions to
any rule, and thus it can only be said that “X usually or almost always results
in Y.”18 Such a regularity would still qualify as nomothetic under any but
17
“Laws with wide scope are likely to pick out only very partial causes” (Kincaid, 1996, 97).
Idiographic theory is generally needed to explain complex causal interactions.
18
Bunge (1998, 21-33) argues that some relationships are universal, such as that between
anomie and (increased) crime (or technological innovation and social mobility). Note,
though, that this relationship does not hold for all individuals, and thus an argument that it
always holds at the level of societies is questionable: it depends on individual
idiosyncrasies not overwhelming a general tendency. With enough observations, a case
might be observed where the result did not hold. Bunge recognizes that there are few
lawlike regularities in human science, and that this allowed philosophers such as Dilthey
to associate nomothetic with natural science and idiographic with human science. He
emphasizes, though, that both types of science mix the two: they look for patterns, and
3. Classifying Theory 71
the most narrow of definitions. Alternatively, Bunge (1998) notes that there
are idiosyncrasies even among atoms, though much less than among complex
organisms. There is thus a place for both types of theory across types of
agent, though admittedly the scope for idiographic analysis will tend to
increase with the role of intentional agency.
Little notes a further difference: while nomothetic analysis involving only
non-intentional agents can refer to the nature of the cause agent(s) (as when
explaining the reaction of sodium and chlorine), “Social regularities emerge
rather than govern” (1998, 242). For example common property institutions
do not cause overuse of the resource because of their intrinsic nature but
because of how people respond to this particular incentive structure: an
explanation then must involve a discussion of how people respond. But this
simply means, as has been argued above, that explanations involving
intentionality must describe what agents do.
The Golden Mean ideal can be employed again to appreciate that science
should encompass both nomothetic and idiographic theory. Almost nobody
claims that science should deal only with the general. As Aristotle said,
“Practical wisdom is not concerned with universals only; it must also
recognize particulars, for it is practical, and practice concerns particulars”
(he referred to ethics, but the principle can be extended; Hawthorn, 1991,
34). Some would argue that human science at least is inherently idiographic,
but it has been seen that nomothetic theory has a place there as well.
1.5 When?
“When does ‘it’ happen?” Interpreted literally, this question can yield the
same answer as the ‘where’ question, for it would guide scientists to look at
what conjunction of realizations of other phenomena must be in place for a
given relationship to hold.19 Instead, the “time path” of the process needs to
be investigated. How, in other words, does the causal relationship in
question work itself out through time? There are four broad possibilities:
x There are negative feedback effects such that the original impulse is
exactly negated and the system as a whole is unchanged.
also exceptions, and thus any difference is merely of degree. Potter (2000, 207-8) urges
human scientists to look for tendencies rather than laws; one advantage is that they will
then be more careful in making predictions.
19
If a causal relationship only holds during certain seasons, or at a certain time of day, these
constraints too can be defined in terms of realizations of natural phenomena (time of day).
While it may seem counterintuitive that ‘where’ and ‘when’ questions yield the same
answer, in fact scientists and philosophers generally tend to address questions of time and
space in concert (e.g. Urry, 2000).
72 Chapter 3
role that theories of the fourth type may play. He is, though, correct in
suggesting that those who posit a theory of the first three types should seek
sufficiency. The next chapter will explore how this can and should be done.
1.6 How?
2. WHAT IS A THEORY?
20
Kantorovich (1993, 24-5) concurs that theories necessarily embrace causal relationships.
He also stresses that each theory must have some element of novelty. Unfortunately, he
suggests that each theory invents new phenomena, when it is causal mechanisms that
display novelty.
21
As Roy Bhaskar, the realist philosopher, has noted, events are the conjunction of many
causal links, and thus unpredictable. Scientists can, though, attempt to understand each of
the (replicable) causal links involved. With respect to these, prediction may be possible,
but only if all possible conditioning influences of other phenomena are known (Freidheim,
1982). Bunge makes a similar argument about individuals and societies: these too are
3. Classifying Theory 75
combinations of properties, and scientists can only hope to comprehend these through
analysis of their properties and the influences these exercise (1998, 24-5).
76 Chapter 3
22
Ragin (2000, ch.4) suggests that democracies arise in different ways and that this affects
how they operate. This implies that scientists need to understand how a particular
democracy emerged in order to understand how it operates. Strictly speaking, this is
wrong. The way in which a democracy emerges will influence its precise institutional
form, the attitudes of citizens, and diverse other phenomena. Scientists can thus
potentially understand why a particular democracy functions as it does with reference only
to the modern realizations of phenomena. Given our ignorance, though, we can be guided
by considerations of history to look for the outcomes of historical processes and ask how
these in turn might operate.
23
There are those who would argue that concepts like “culture” are inherently indivisible into
their constituent parts. I have argued strenuously against this point of view in Szostak
(2003). I do recognize, of course, some important kernels of truth: there are indeed strong
causal links among various elements of culture. But if these were as strong as holists
suggest than it is hard to see how cultures could evolve gradually, as they clearly do, nor
why neighbouring cultures are often similar with respect to many characteristics but quite
different with respect to others. If holists wish to maintain that some realizations of
cultural phenomena are always sufficient to generate certain realizations in other cultural
phenomena, such conjectures need to be stated precisely and bolstered empirically, not
casually assumed.
3. Classifying Theory 77
change agent above. Holistic theorists thus have no answer to give to the
‘who’ question. Nor would it seem that they would find the ‘what’ question
terribly easy to engage, for without knowing what sort of change agent is
involved one will be hard pressed to specify what it does. The same logic
applies to the decision-making processes outlined under ‘why’. The theory
of the unrepentant holist is thus no scientific theory at all, for it fails to
answer at least three of the five questions that any scientific theory should
engage.24 It could be called “bad theory” rather than “no theory”: such an
appellation may be deservedly applied to theories in which answers to one or
two questions were simply omitted through ignorance – a practice that will
be found to be all too common below. But “theories” which cannot by their
nature answer these questions do not deserve to be called scientific, whether
they exist in the natural sciences, social sciences, or humanities.
There is a long and troubled philosophical literature, at least in the
English-speaking world, which attempts to differentiate science from non-
science. The popularity of this discourse suggests that many scientists and
philosophers wish to distinguish what scientists do from what non-scientists
do. It is thus no bad thing that this definition of a scientific theory is
exclusive. Indeed, in general a definition that embraces everything is
useless. For a definition of scientific theory to be meaningful, in other
words, it must reject some forms of argument as unscientific. Some
scientists and philosophers may wish that a somewhat different line had been
drawn in the sand. However, this definition did not flow from a desire to
establish a particular boundary, but rather emerges as a logical outcome of
the 5W typology. Analysis of causal links in chapter 2 and in Szostak (2003)
led to the conclusion that holistic theories and concepts needed to be
disaggregated. The analysis here has reinforced that view.25
Having spoken of lines in the sand above, the longstanding philosophical
tradition of defining theories in terms of covering laws (especially popular
among positivists) should be noted. A theory, it was maintained, consisted
of one or more generalizable laws, as well as correspondences between
theoretical and observational terms. Such definitions have an inherent
nomothetic bias and thus exclude theories toward the idiographic end of the
continuum. Not surprisingly, the covering law approach has been repeatedly
24
Bunge (1998, 26) attributes the predictive failure of holistic Marxian analysis to its
reliance on laws of historical transformation, and failure to encompass the particular
constraints and circumstances that affect causal outcomes.
25
I have, to be sure, never liked vagueness, and thus am suspicious of any theory that uses
words that seem to lack a reasonable range of definition (see the discussion of concepts in
chapter 2). Of course, those who question the very possibility of science (and thus
celebrate vagueness, and style over substance) can likely imagine a range of personality
defects that drive me toward the ridiculous goal of organizing human understanding.
78 Chapter 3
attacked on exactly this point: that scientists can reasonably posit theories
that lack a generalizable law. The definition of theory posited here, in
contrast, does not arbitrarily exclude legitimate sorts of scientific theorizing.
3. EVALUATING THEORIES
26
Ziman (2000, 257) notes that there is less theoretical consensus in human science. He
attributes this to the subjectivity inherent in the study of meaning. A greater appreciation
of the strengths and weaknesses of theories and methods, and recognition that every theory
has a range of applicability in terms of phenomena, would help human science recognize
the complementarity of competing theories. Szostak (2003) argued against those (e.g.
Prus) who would maintain that positivist, interpretivist, and postmodern theories cannot be
integrated.
3. Classifying Theory 79
Szostak (2003) argued that all causal links could be understood in terms
of five types of causation:
x Strict causation, as when sodium and chlorine react.
x Intentional causation, as when a person or group acts purposefully.
27
Szostak (1999) and Szostak (2003) argue in favor of various philosophical orientations –
pancritical rationalism, web of belief, and so on – which maintain that people should be
sceptical of all beliefs, but act in accord with those they have reason to believe unless/until
they compile evidence in opposition to these. See chapter 6.
3. Classifying Theory 81
The list had been developed inductively: these are the five types of
causation that philosophers engage, and encompass the scientific analyses
addressed in Szostak (2003). It was noted in Szostak (2003) that the
relationship between these was unclear: some but not all scholars treat
intentional as a subset of strict causation, or hermeneutic as a subset of
intentional, and some question whether functional explanations are not
entirely reducible to intentional arguments.
The 5W typology of theory allows these five types of causation to be
identified much more precisely. Strict causation applies to non-intentional
agents. Intentional and hermeneutic causation apply to intentional agents:
the former deals with their actions, and the latter with their thoughts. The
first three types of causation, then, can be defined in terms of answers to the
‘who’ and ‘what’ questions. It would, in this formulation, clearly be a
mistake to view any one of these as a subset of the others.
An example of functional causation is the argument that “centralized
states need some sort of army or police force to maintain order.” As Elster
(1989) and others have noted, it is all too easy to assume such relationships.
The theorist must go a step further, and ask how the functional relationship
emerges: how, for example, do agents of the state establish an army? This
must necessarily engage scientists in intentional analysis. The question is
thus raised as to whether the only sensible part of a functional relationship is
the intentional part. But why is an army necessary for the maintenance of a
state? This can only be so if an army is the only way in which attitudes and
actions supportive (or at least non-destructive) of the state can be
encouraged.28 This must mean that the army creates appropriate constraints
and incentives. Functional arguments, then, must combine the passive action
of a non-intentional agent with the intentional acts of intentional agents (note
28
Note that arguments for necessity work in the opposite direction from those for
sufficiency. In this case, the posited result (the state) must be identified, and the question
asked whether this has/can ever exist (for long) without the posited necessary conditions
(an army). Ragin (2000) suggests that scientists are as ignorant of the implications of
necessity as they are of sufficiency. Since necessity need not imply sufficiency, scientists
might wish to identify why the necessary factors do not always guarantee the posited
result. Kincaid (1996) notes that evidence for the functional relationship is often easier to
find than evidence regarding the emergence of the necessary conditions.
82 Chapter 3
that there is also scope for intentional analysis of why the constraints
inherent in an army work).
What sorts of agents evolve? The 5W typology suggests this unusual
question. And the answer is that only non-intentional agents evolve.
Intentional individuals and groups do not evolve, though elements of these,
such as genes and beliefs, may evolve. But note that evolutionary theories
focus not on what particular nonintentional agents do but on how they
become what they are. The analysis proceeds in terms of the inherent nature
of the individual agent itself (the possibilities for mutation) and the effects of
a selection environment that comprises other agents. Theories of group
selection exist, and thus some analysis at the level of groups is possible,
though it is generally appreciated that these must explain how group
processes interact with individual-level selection. Selection criteria may be
non-intentional (as when genetic mutations are selected by the physical
environment) or intentional (as when technologies are selected by individuals
or groups). Since a theory of evolution should specify the relevant selection
environment, evolutionary causation may involve intentional as well as non-
intentional arguments.
Of any theory five questions can be asked: Who are the agents? What sort
of action is involved? What decision-making process is employed? Where
does the causal relationship occur, both in reality and in terms of causal
links? (That is, how generalizable is the theory?) What sort of time path
does the causal process follow? Diverse theories will be placed within the
typology in this section; the results are summarized in Table 3.1 below.
Most theories in natural science, outside of biological science, involve
non-intentional agents, and passive reaction, and thus no active decision-
making process. As discussed above, these theories can be distinguished in
terms of individual, group, or relationship agency. They can also be
distinguished in terms of where they occur (in both senses of where) and
what sort of time path is involved.
Evolutionary theory in biology, as discussed above, also involves
nonintentional – generally individual – agency and no active decision-
making. Here, though, there is non-passive action, for mutation is an
inherent quality of the organisms under study. Evolution applies to all
organisms. While nominally nomothetic, evolutionary theory has
idiographic elements in that every mutation and selection environment is
necessarily unique. Evolution is a dynamic process, with organisms
changing through time (though in unpredictable directions); change likely
3. Classifying Theory 83
section engages those theories surveyed in B. Turner (2000) and the analyses
of those theories contained therein.29
It would be desirable to begin the discussion of each of these theories
with a brief definition and/or some typical examples. Generally, though, a
wide variety of analyses are embraced by these theories. One advantage of
the typology is that it identifies key areas of agreement and disagreement
within theories. Brief examples are provided to illustrate analyses that
particular theories embrace.
29
The selection was not entirely random. Chapters were chosen that seemed focussed on one
type of theory (or at least a closely related family of theories). Chapters on anthropology,
feminism, and postmodernism were ignored, as these covered too wide a range of
theorizing. The chapter on structuralism overlapped significantly with that on
functionalism. I note that Plummer (2000) stresses the similarity between symbolic
interactionism and much postmodern theory. The theories surveyed represent two of the
three types of social theory identified by Jones (1985): theories of consensus (such as
functionalism) and theories of interaction; the main example of theories of conflict
provided by Jones is Marxian theory, which is treated only in passing in Turner.
3. Classifying Theory 85
30
Yet later Cohen expresses doubt that theories of action and praxis can be linked. Why not
view these as complements with different ranges of applicability?
86 Chapter 3
When?: Talcott Parsons posited that social order results from individuals
pursuing integrated ends. That is, there is some process through which
individuals choose largely complementary goals (he, like Weber, emphasized
the pursuit of values); they then act to achieve these. This is clearly an
equilibrium process. Giddens too implies some sort of equilibrium process
in maintaining that practices must be more than locally situated because they
support structural patterns. But Giddens like Dewey celebrates those times
at which individuals break free from habit and recognizes that in doing so
they may encourage cultural change. Giddens and Dewey thus envisage a
more dynamic process than Parsons: pursuit of habit may maintain social
stability, but individuals making conscious decisions will cause societal
change. If these acts are rare, societies may move between equilibria;
otherwise they may be constantly evolving.
Comments: While ‘who?’ and ‘what?’ are fairly well specified, action
theories embrace a very wide range of answers to the other three questions.
It is perhaps not surprising that many action theorists believe that it is the
emphasis on praxis or meaning that is central to their theory, but many –
especially those who emphasize relationships – instead argue that the ‘what?’
is quite secondary to the ‘who?’ (see Cohen, 2000; those who emphasize
relationships thus borrow pragmatically from theories of action and praxis).
This very flexibility has made it difficult to define action theory or provide
typical examples: the typology suggests that the broad title captures several
theory types. Sadly, the flexibility with respect to ‘where?’ has not led
theorists to identify complementary ranges of applicability for different
theories within this family. Nor have action theorists signalled a general
appreciation for theories outside the family.31 The juxtaposition of Table 2.1
and the typology developed here could usefully guide theorists both to
identify where particular versions of action theory are particularly strong,
and also where no version of action theory provides powerful insight.
Judging from Cohen (2000), action theorists have spoken at length of
what in Table 2.1 are called schemas, motivations, and emotions (though
Cohen bemoans the lack of empirical investigation of emotions). Much less
attention appears to have been paid to personality and abilities: the table
might usefully guide action theorists to flesh out their views in these
respects. Likewise it seems that only a subset of the possible influences of
the wider society have been engaged. Cohen (2000) criticizes most action
theorists for abstracting away from power relations, for example.
The 5W typology proved very useful in comparing the detailed
discussions of diverse action theorists in Cohen (2000). And it suggests
ways in which action theory could be improved. The typology illustrates
31
Cohen (2000) notes that network theorists tend to ignore the obvious fact that individuals
spend much time alone not worrying about relationships.
3. Classifying Theory 87
32
According to Boyne (2000), the essence of structuralism is similar: a belief in “structures”
like the periodic table in which every element is necessarily related to others in a similar
way. Saussure, for example, had stressed how words only exist in relationship to each
other within the structure of a particular language.
88 Chapter 3
33
He identified four key functions: sustaining the system with respect to the wider
environment; achieving collective goals; fostering internal integration; and pattern-
maintenance and tension-management. Others have doubted that these are either necessary
or sufficient.
3. Classifying Theory 89
34
There is also a question of whether systems are real or just a scholarly way to make sense
of the world. Similar questions could be asked of most/all theories.
90 Chapter 3
that have occurred in American society since Parsons wrote, and the
continued viability of capitalism, it seems likely that the answer is yes.
35
Strauss and Corbin (1998) discuss grounded theory. They see it as an approach to using
qualitative data to generate theories. Within a research project there should be an iterative
process of theorizing inductively and testing hypotheses against new information. They
urge a dense textual description of patterns of relationships.
36
Some symbolic interactionists are thus open to structure, while others are opposed.
Likewise some identify themselves as scientists and others as humanists.
92 Chapter 3
case study approaches. It will be suggested in the next chapter that particular
methods lead to a bias toward particular theoretical results.
Why?: There is little explicit discussion of how meaning is negotiated.
The stress seems to be on the intuitive: humans have inherent abilities to
create and interpret symbols.
Comments: Symbolic interactionism (or perhaps Plummer) does a better
job of identifying answers to each 5W question than was the case with
previous theories. Still, there is much room for disagreement among
theorists with respect to both ‘Where’ and ‘Why’.
Plummer (2000, 196) suggests in passing that since symbolic
interactionism holds that meaning is constantly being negotiated, scholars
cannot hope to pin down precisely what symbolic interactionism itself
means. He is, of course, correct in noting that any theory will evolve in
subtle ways through time. But Plummer nevertheless manages to identify
fairly precise answers to the 5W questions. A general lesson can be drawn
here: scholarly communities can and should essay to identify the
characteristics of any theory at any point in time.
Plummer also remarks that symbolic interactionism, though a minority
view in modern human science, nevertheless has wide but generally
unrecognized influences on writers as diverse as Bourdieu, Giddens, and
Habermas. An effort to identify theories typologically should make it easier
to recognize when elements of particular theory types are being applied
elsewhere.
Plummer applauds efforts to codify and draw generalizations from
detailed research: “This is certainly not to argue for an exclusive insistence
upon cumulative classifying work ... But some move in this direction could
help to prevent each new generation of interactionists from having to repeat
history” (2000, 210-1). The project Plummer envisages would be greatly
facilitated by the development of a typology of scientific possibilities (as in
chapters 2 through 5), and efforts to classify scientific documents in more
detail (see chapter 7). It would also benefit from researchers being more
explicit about their theoretical arguments. Interdisciplinary researchers in
particular would benefit from an enhanced ability to recognize when similar
theories are applied in different fields, and then seek commonalities and
contrasts among these.
5.6 Phenomenology
37
This approach is similar to Freidheim’s advice that scientists take existing works, analyze
the theories therein along appropriate dimensions, see what is missing, and work toward a
comprehensive theory (more properly, theory cluster). Note that this process involves both
deduction and induction. As Freidheim (1982, 80) notes, “Mine is not a neat system.” But
the world can hardly be comprehended without a complex research program.
38
While many biologists hold to the view that adaptation is the only possible biological
process, others have urged greater flexibility, noting for example that some observed traits
may be side-effects of selection processes (Hull and Ruse, 1998, part I).
96 Chapter 3
39
Rule (1997, 32) warns scholars against glorying in the simple application of a theory to a
new domain, and calling this progress. It must instead be established that this application
has some empirical validity. Dupré (2001, 16) suggests that theories become less effective
the farther from their home they travel; this is a useful warning, but scientists should be
open to theories that inform their understanding even a little. Dogan and Pahre (1990, 148)
warn scholars to be wary of theories only used in one discipline. While thus dismissive of
idiographic theory, they do a valuable service in pointing to the value of applying a theory
widely.
3. Classifying Theory 97
40
B. Turner lists four problems with social theory: there is no obvious progress (and much
re-inventing the wheel), it is not clear if the goal is explanation or interpretation, there is no
consensus on what a theory is, and theorists still disagree about various (false)
dichotomies. The typology provides partial or complete solutions to all of these. Turner
later (2000, 16) raises a fifth concern, that the relationship between social theory and ethics
needs to be clarified. This issue will be addressed in chapter 5.
41
The same judgment holds for other definitions the author has encountered. Theories
contain a set of assumptions, but must build upon these in a particular way. A theory may
be a proposition yet to be verified; not only must the nature of the proposition be specified,
but scientists must embrace theories for which there is supporting evidence. Mahner and
Bunge (1997, 87) deal harshly with definitions of theories as the opposite of facts,
equivalent to hypotheses, or generalizations of observed facts.
Chapter 4
CLASSIFYING METHOD
“Of all the courses we teach, none is more important than research
methods” (Singleton and Strait, 1999, xv). Scientific theories were identified
in the last chapter with scientific explanation. It was also noted that scholars
can only have confidence in theories to the extent that these are logical,
coherent, clear, and have been supported by evidence gathered using
scientific methods.1 To be sure, philosophers of science, if not practicing
scientists, now accept that scientific methods can neither prove nor disprove
any theory (nor even any narrow hypothesis). Nevertheless, the application
of scientific methods provides scientists with invaluable if imperfect
evidence with which they can judge whether a theory seems to accord with
reality. The key to science is the imperfect testing of theories against
external reality (Polkinghorne, 1996, 18-19). Scientific theories guide
scientists to ask certain research questions; 2scientific investigations in turn
suggest changes to theories or perhaps even the development of new
theories.
1
Faced with difficulties in defining “scientific explanation” (that is, defining “theory”),
many philosophers of science focused instead on “scientific confirmation.” Hempel
posited that confirmation occurred any time a suggested relationship was observed. The
Bayesian approach speaks of any evidence that raises the probability that the hypothesized
relationship is correct (this unfortunately excludes evidence obtained before the theory was
formulated). The bootstrap hypothesis speaks of confirmation in terms of a wide variety of
empirical tests that approach variables differently (it also applauds the revision of theory in
light of new evidence) (Lambert and Brittan, 1992).
2
Socrates, Aristotle, and Gadamer are among those who emphasized that asking questions
was the key to knowledge. Bacon and Kant were part of a minority of philosophers who
described scientific methods as asking questions of nature. Scientific advance depends on
asking new questions, but also on getting at least partial answers to these to guide further
questioning (Hintikka, 2000, 402-4; he notes that the alternative view, that science
advances through the accumulation of incontrovertible truths, is untenable)
100 Chapter 4
Scarcely any scientific work is published that does not include appeals to
authority in the form of citations of the work of other scientists. At the level
of individual pieces of research, then, appeals to authority loom large as a
method for justifying one’s results. This reflects the simple fact that science
is a complex and cumulative endeavor, in which no piece of research stands
alone. Scientists, though, should only cite those who they believe to have
valid scientific justifications for the conclusions that they draw. And thus in
citing other scientists they are implicitly citing the methods they (and those
they in turn cite) have employed to achieve their results. And thus authority
does not deserve mention in its own right among a list of methods.
1. CLASSIFYING METHODS
This chapter, unlike the previous chapter on theory, thus starts with an
exhaustive and manageable set of scientific methods.4 It is quite possible,
then, that both scholars and students could be acquainted with the basic pros
and cons of every method, should this prove desirable. It will prove possible,
indeed, to evaluate the strengths and weaknesses of all methods in terms of
the 5W questions.
Some scholars would attempt to aggregate some of these methods into
broader categories. “Theoretical” methods, designed to look at the
foundations of a theory, are sometimes distinguished from “Empirical”
methods. Yet most methods can serve to establish both the general adequacy
of a theory and the quantitative strength of posited relationships.
Mathematical modelling is often viewed as theoretical, and statistical testing
as empirical; yet the two are often used in combination. Some scholars
would include the logical analysis of theory structure as a theoretical
method; it is best to distinguish various means of internal evaluation of
3
Hall and Hall (1996) note that the feminist critique entails no unique method but rather
concerns about why particular questions are asked and problems addressed, and respect for
the subjects (people) being studied. Feminists have tended to favor qualitative research
(see below).
4
Singleton and Strait (1999) suggest that it is methods that distinguish science from
journalism (but also distinguish natural from social science and each from the humanities).
These views will be critiqued below. Notably, Singleton and Strait suggest that familiarity
with methods can help citizens understand and evaluate scientific results, and also sharpen
individual powers of critical thinking. They thus suggest that everyone can do research.
4. Classifying Method 103
theories (see chapter 3) from scientific methods, which must at least support
the exposure of theories to real world evidence. “Quantitative” methods are
sometimes distinguished from “qualitative” methods. In terms of the
methods that were listed above, quantitative researchers favour experiments,
surveys, statistical analysis, content analysis, and structured observations
(where particular acts are counted), while qualitative researchers favor
participant observation, in-depth interviewing, case studies in general,
biography, and focus groups (Oakley, 2000, 26). Yet exceptions abound in
which advocates of one approach have nevertheless used the methods of the
other. This overdrawn dichotomy will be revisited below.
Works that survey several methods not surprisingly take the point of view
that diverse methods have a place in science (Ellis, 1994, Hartman and
Hedblom, 1988, Singleton and Strait, 1999). For some, the argument is that
certain methods are best suited to the study of certain phenomena. More
commonly, it is suggested that a particular research problem is best
approached with multiple methods. The 5W typology will allow this
conjecture to be evaluated in some detail.
It was argued in chapter 3 that science should embrace theories that deal
with each of the distinctions identified in the typology of theory.
Necessarily, then, scientists should want methods that would cope with each
of the cells in the typology of theory. Obviously, there will not be distinct
methods to place in each cell. Instead, every method should be investigated
to ascertain how well it copes with the different types of agency, action,
decision-making process, and time path enumerated in the typology of
theory, as well as how generalizable it is. In developing a typology of
strengths and weaknesses of methods, then, the 5W questions should be
asked of method as well. It might be found that one method is clearly
superior for a particular cell in the typology, all methods have some
applicability, or a subset of methods is useful to differing degrees.
Ironically, while a much smaller list of methods has been identified than
was the case with theory types, the typology of strengths and weaknesses of
methods will comprise all of the distinctions relevant to theory, plus several
additional dimensions. That is, in asking the 5W questions of method, a
handful of additional criteria by which to judge methods will be identified.
These additional dimensions refer to potential limitations of methods, rather
than their range of applicability.
104 Chapter 4
2.1 Who?
As in the case of theory, the concern here is with “Who is being studied?”
Again intentional agents can be distinguished from non-intentional agents,
and individuals from groups and relationships. These distinctions can have
important implications for method. Freidheim (1982), for example,
hypothesizes that it is easier to precisely measure individual-level
characteristics. If so, there is a danger that scientists will pay more heed to
individuals than they deserve relative to groups and relationships. In any
case, a key question to ask of any method is how well it copes with each of
the six types of agency.
A further type of distinction also looms large here. Does the method
examine one of these agents, several of these, lots of these, or perhaps all
(relevant cases) of these? McNeill (1990, 121-2) argues that in general
surveys deal with lots of people, interviews with fewer, and observation
(especially participant observation) with yet fewer. And Ragin (2000)
devotes his whole book to discussing the advantages and disadvantages of
studying one versus many. His analysis provides a further argument for the
use of multiple methods.
Note that if any subset (from one to many) of the relevant population is
examined, scientists will face questions of sampling. Is the sample biased, or
does it represent the average of the larger population, or perhaps the most
common attributes of the larger population (which can be quite different
from the average)?
2.2 What?
was appreciated. It should hardly be surprising that this debate has had a
methodological side to it, and that this too should be – and to some extent is
being – guided toward compromise. A strict interprevist would argue most
obviously that scholars should study only attitudes and not actions. If it is
accepted that scholars should study both, and passive reaction as well,
methods that can cope with each of these are critical. The interpretivist point
of view has also been associated with a strong preference for idiographic as
opposed to nomothetic analysis; this in turn flows from a belief that there are
huge differences across individuals in how they perceive apparently similar
situations.5 Interpretivists also tend to argue that people can only be studied
in their natural environment. And interpretivists emphasize qualitative versus
quantitative analysis. Strict positivists take the opposing view on all three
issues. The first two of these distinctions will fall out of discussions of
‘why’ and ‘where’ below; this should encourage a suspicion that there is no
necessary correlation among answers to the three questions. The qualitative
versus quantitative distinction does not emerge from any of the 5W
questions: scholars might be especially doubtful that this distinction is
important in distinguishing good from bad research (see below).6
Regardless of what sort of causal process is investigated, there are four
criteria for establishing a causal argument. The first involves showing
correlation. Observations of the causal agent(s) should be associated with
observations of the posited result(s). Second, the direction of effect should
be established. The change agents should appear before the results (as a
general rule: there are some relations in physics where reverse temporal
causation is posited). Third, alternative explanations of the observed
correlation should be ruled out. For example, the possibility that both the
alleged causes and results are in fact the results of some other causal agent
should be investigated. [The first three of these criteria were identified by
John Stuart Mill; Palys, 1997, 274.] Fourth, intermediate (often called
5
Goldenberg (1992, 180-5) notes that scientists might expect the degree of variation to itself
vary across societies, depending on the degree of cultural conformity. He also notes that
there should be a potential for integration: positivists could establish a link between social
class and school attendance, while interpretivists investigated why some poor students stay
in school.
6
The PO method favored by interpretivists was developed by Robert Park and associates in
the 1920s, “though they knew full well that all methods had something to contribute to
sociological understanding” (McNeill, 1990, 4). By the 1960s there was a debate between
those favoring the “objective” approach of positivism, and others emphasizing the need to
understand what social life means to people. Since then it has become acceptable for a
researcher to use both methods in one project, or different methods for different projects
(McNeill, 1990, 6-7).
106 Chapter 4
7
Palys (1997, 43) notes in turn that qualitative analysis tends to be associated with
induction, and quantitative with deduction.
8
John Stuart Mill urged scientists to deplore any method that would “bestow a
disproportionate attention upon [facts] which our theory takes into account, while we
misestimate the rest, and probably underrate their importance” (in Gower, 1997, 254).
4. Classifying Method 107
2.3 Why?
In the case of theory, the ‘why’ question pointed toward the decision-
making process at work, including the passive decision-making of non-
intentional agents. Individual scientists might wish to investigate the nature
of the decision-making process itself, and/or the results of the decision-
making process. Note that a theory may be largely correct with regard to
either one of these, and yet mistaken with regard to the other. Not only will
particular methods prove to be best suited to answering one type of question,
but methods are differentially applicable to different types of decision-
making process.
“Why do scientists study what they do?” This broad question subsumes
all of the analysis in this chapter, as well as that in chapter 5. The purpose of
this chapter is to type methods in terms of what they do, rather than in terms
108 Chapter 4
2.4 Where?
As with theory, the ‘where’ question can be asked both literally and
figuratively. In literal terms, two key distinctions can be identified. First,
phenomena can be analyzed in one place or as they move through space.
Second, either of these types of analysis can be performed in a natural setting
or in an artificial setting (though only limited movement through space is
generally possible in an artificial setting). With respect to the first distinction,
the advantages of each largely hinge on whether the theory refers to
movement (or should do so). With respect to the second, artificial settings
allow the researcher to control extraneous variables and thus isolate a
particular cause-effect relationship; the danger is that agents may behave
differently in an artificial setting. There is also a null possibility, wherein the
research is not spatially dependent at all. Mathematical modelling is
arguably unaffected by the spatial location or movement of the researcher.
Figuratively, the ‘where’ question echoes the nomothetic versus
idiographic distinction drawn in chapter 3. The obvious distinction here is
that the idiographic investigator wishes to establish the relevance of a
theoretical proposition in a constrained set of circumstances, while the
nomothetic researcher is concerned with showing a broad applicability.
Note, though, that the nomothetic researcher could have recourse to
idiographic methods, illustrating the relevance of a certain proposition in
quite different sets of circumstances. The idiographic researcher may wish
to employ nomothetic methods to establish the limited range of applicability
of a theory. Palys (1997) suggests that the two approaches are inherently
complementary: examination of particular cases should bear out (or not)
general rules, while the analysis of generalities should suggest where
idiosyncrasies lie. “Particulars will suggest, circumscribe, and test
generalizations, and in turn the latter will help find and shed light on the
former” (Bunge, 1998, 25).
2.5 When?
2.6 How?
In the previous chapter, it was found that, with respect to theory, answers
to the ‘How?’ question had been covered within the answers to the 5W
questions. The same result, not coincidentally, holds here. To ask “how
does a scientist investigate?,” is to ask the questions above. The potential
biases in scientific practice will, of course, be investigated in chapter 5.
Hall and Hall (1996,35) argue that the furore over the quantitative versus
qualitative distinction is dying down: “...nowadays most writers on
methodology avoid such a distinction and stress instead the strategy of
mixing methods.” Tashakkori and Teddlie (1998, 5) ground their book in a
belief that these paradigm wars are effectively over. However, for decades
defenders of one approach to research savagely attacked the alternative, and
there are still many scientists (but fewer philosophers) who staunchly believe
that there is only one right way to do research. Moreover, some have
stressed the inherent incompatability of the two approaches, arguing that they
could or should never be combined. This has not prevented an increased
pragmatic interest in compromise. Tashakkori and Teddlie (1998, 11) echo
the Golden Mean approach outlined in chapter 1, arguing that scientists
should accept both quantitative and qualitative approaches because each has
been long used, accepted, urged, and useful. The relative importance of the
two may nevertheless vary by research question. Interdisciplinary scholars
are likely to be especially open to both, though specialized scholars should
be as well.
The quantitative approach emphasizes evidence that can be quantified:
the number of molecules, people, or widgets. The alternative is to focus on
110 Chapter 4
9
Abbott (2001, 6-12) applies the concept of fractals, and argues that distinctions such as that
between quantitative and qualitative are repeated at lower levels: quantitative versus
qualitative kinds of quantitative research could be identified, for example. Rare will be the
extremists who make the same choice at each level. The self-definition of scientists will
depend on the approach of those to whom they compare themselves. Attitudes of quite
different scholars will on certain issues appear quite similar.
10
Should scientists ask research subjects what they think, and involve them in research
design? Qualitative researchers often say that it is unethical not to tell subjects what is
happening; Oakley (2000) responds that it is quite ethical to, for example, have control
groups who are not told they are getting the placebo. Consulting research subjects can
often be valuable in suggesting arguments the researcher might otherwise miss. But there
is the danger of seeing things only as subjects do. Oakley (54) also notes that scientists
may not wish to hurt subjects’ feelings with their conclusions.
4. Classifying Method 111
11
Many, but far from all, feminist researchers have embraced the qualitative cause. Oakley
(2000) bemoans, much better than I could, the limitations this places on feminist research,
and the not-so-subtle pressures to conform. She notes, in particular, that one can hardly
convince others of gender discrimination without some quantitative evidence. Oakley
herself had begun her career as an advocate of qualitative research but came to appreciate
the advantages of combining the two. She thus also came to realize that the longstanding
emphasis on quantitative research was not simply a relic of male-dominated science.
112 Chapter 4
statistical analysis, for example, scientists should ask the qualitative question
of how important the results are.12
Seale (1999) speaks of a tendency of interpretivists to be wary [explicitly]
of causality, for fear that it compromises free will. Tashakkori and Teddlie
(1998) attribute a similar attitude to qualitative researchers. In both cases,
the correlation is far from perfect, with many qualitative and/or interpretivist
researchers openly embracing causality. Even those who do not explicitly do
so end up describing how some phenomena influence others. Interpretivists
tend to prefer the word “process” to the word “causal”, feeling that this
better signals the interrelationship among diverse causal links, but they must
still deal with causation. While it is true that (almost) every phenomenon
influences and is influenced by every other, this hardly prevents scientists
from identifying each causal link, nor making causal arguments (as was seen
in chapter 2).
Quantitative analysis especially is undertaken in both natural and
artificial settings. And we shall see that there are advantages and
disadvantages associated with each of these. In psychology especially there
was nevertheless a heated debate along these lines (Tashakkori and Teddlie,
1998).
Is there a real world out there, or is reality constructed by individuals?
Positivists think that fairly stable causal relationships exist out there to be
uncovered by research. Constructivists think that humans collectively create
reality: there is no “cheating” or “single parenthood” out there, but rather the
definition and implications of these depend on social and cultural
circumstances. But note that these are causal arguments, and scientists could
hope to understand how various cultural attitudes affect single parents. And
thus scientists can investigate the degree to which a certain causal
relationship is conditioned by realizations of other phenomena. Hammersley
and Gomm (2000, 157) note that the claim that there is no one reality is itself
a universalistic claim; there is a long-recognized inconsistency involved in
asserting absolutely that all knowledge is relative. Palys (1997) celebrates
critical realist philosophy, which bridges the gap between the two, and urges
the investigation of diverse causal links (while Tashakkori and Teddlie,
conversely, urge a common acceptance of multiple constructed realities).
In terms of the methods that will be discussed below, quantitative
researchers favor experiments, surveys, statistical analysis of secondary data,
12
Various authors in Pole and Burgess (2000) suggest that researchers from differing cultural
backgrounds are more likely to reach different conclusions using qualitative than
quantitative analysis. Moreover researchers studying the words or actions of those from
different backgrounds can easily misunderstand these (and often ask questions that make
sense only to them). There is also a difference in the popularity of qualitative research
across cultures.
4. Classifying Method 113
4. EVALUATING METHODS
13
Together they urge authors to be clear about the questions addressed, the methods used, the
definitions of key concepts, the context of research, the relationship between researchers
and subjects, the extent of interaction with subjects, the relationship of the evidence
compiled to alternative hypotheses, and the generalizability of results (among
114 Chapter 4
perform a similar exercise to that of Oakley and conclude that there are
greater similarities than differences in how quantitative and qualitative
research are evaluated.
Reliability: Does the method yield similar results when applied to
identical situations? With respect to individual pieces of research, questions
can be asked such as “could/has another researcher duplicated the results?,”
or even “can the same researcher reproduce the results?” At the level of a
particular method itself the concern is with the degree to which replication is
possible. Is the research closely tied to the idiosyncrasies of an individual
researcher, or to the idiosyncrasies of a particular research situation, or can it
reasonably be expected/observed that another researcher can do very similar
research and gain very similar results?
Seale (1999, ch.10) notes that qualitative studies are hard to replicate.14
Nevertheless, reliability is still an important criterion, and this can be greatly
enhanced by various practices developed by qualitative researchers.
Reflective methodological accounting requires the researcher to carefully
report what evidence was collected and how, and how this was interpreted
(Seale emphasizes the importance of distinguishing the recording of
information from the drawing of inferences). Peer auditing involves having
other researchers review the research and comment on issues of reliability.
Seale discusses the heated debates over early ethnographic studies – such as
Margaret Mead’s study of adolescence in Samoa – and notes that these early
researchers did not leave detailed notes from which the reliability of their
studies might be judged.
The importance of reliability should be obvious. If a method or particular
piece of research is not reliable, scientists will and should lack confidence
that the results obtained would be obtained again, and can thus hardly be
confident that they reflect reality. Note, though, that several examples of
research which reach similar results, even if the research is not strictly
replicable, may still help scientists to increase their confidence in reliability,
and perhaps also guide them toward appreciating the range of applicability of
a theory.
Reliability has of necessity been discussed at the level of both methods
and particular pieces of research. While some general range of reliability can
be attributed to a particular method, it is important to appreciate that
particular applications of that method will differ in terms of reliability.
other criteria). Silverman (2000, 178-85) stresses in turn the importance of seeing if any
posited relationship applies over the entire data set, and striving to explain deviant cases.
14
Strict constructivists argue that replication is both impossible and undesirable (because
there are multiple realities). Seale retorts that to abandon replicability leaves no special
place for science relative to fiction.
4. Classifying Method 115
Singleton and Strait (1999), for example, suggest that reliability can be
enhanced by pretesting one’s research instrument, adding items to the
research project which seem important, and dropping items which the pretest
suggests have no impact on the outcome.
Validity: While reliability asks whether there is consensus across
applications of a method, validity deals with the more central question of
whether the results of research reflect an external reality. Note, though, that
if research is not reliable it will almost always be invalid as well. Since by
definition scientists can only approach understanding of external reality
through research, there is necessarily more room for subjective judgment in
evaluation of validity (with some scholars doubting the very existence of an
external reality). Some communities of scholars may thus be tempted to
revel in the reliability of their methods, while ignoring questions of validity.
There are some key questions that can and should be asked. First, does
the research actually investigate the links posited by theory – or, in the case
of induction, those that could be posited by theory? If the results of research
do not accord with such links, as might occur, for example, if the data do not
accurately represent the phenomena in question, scientists should be
sceptical that the results reflect an external reality. For qualitative research it
can be asked whether the explanation provided is grounded in the
observations, or perhaps only consistent with these. Second, it can be asked
whether the research deals with alternative hypotheses. If not, scientists
should worry that the results can be explained in diverse other ways, and thus
that external reality does not accord with the particular theory favored by
researchers.
Goldenberg (1992) treats the two previous questions as tests of internal
validity, for they focus upon the relationship between research design and
theory, and the following questions as tests of external validity. Third, it can
be asked if the results are robust. Note that when concerned with reliability
scientists should aspire to getting similar results from similar studies; here
they should aspire to getting similar results from different studies. This can
be an argument both for using one method across many situations, and for
using many methods. Scientists should not, though, look only for situations
where the theory predicts similar results from different situations, but also
look for where it predicts different results, and ensure that these indeed
follow (Singleton and Strait, 1999). Fourth, it can be asked if the results
allow scientists to predict. Fifth, if a scientific community considers other
theories or measures to be valid, they can look for consistency with these.
Different questions may be more appropriate for different types of
investigation. Nevertheless, a community of scientists should be careful of
focussing on only a subset of these: economists long cherished the predictive
power of their theories, even when results were loosely connected to theory,
116 Chapter 4
only to find that predictions became poor due to changes in un-specified but
relevant phenomena in the 1970s.
Representativeness: Virtually all methods require some sampling of a
larger population, and thus raise questions of the representativeness of the
sample. One problem with Mead’s study of adolescence in Samoa was that
her sample was small and potentially biased (Seale, 1999). Techniques of
achieving representative samples for surveys are well developed; problems
loom larger for other methods. It is noteworthy that most books on method
have an introductory chapter on sampling that precedes discussion of
particular methods. Meltzoff (1998, ch. 4) lists several common types of
unrepresentative sample, and notes that for methods like interviews and
experiments that require a significant time commitment from subjects,
representativeness is particularly difficult to achieve.
5.2 Experiments
15
Bowker and Star (1999, 10) note that ideally a classification should exhibit exhaustiveness,
mutual exclusivity, and a consistent and unique organizing principle. None of the
classifications they studied met this ideal.
4. Classifying Method 119
16
“...in education and the social sciences generally, large groups are needed if the many
variations and ambiguities involved in human behavior are to be controlled” (Bell, 1999,
15).
17
Singleton and Strait (1999) stress that quasi-experiments violate the experimental rule of
changing one variable at a time. Oakley (2000, 309-12) gives examples in medicine, social
work, and income support where uncontrolled quasi-experiments yielded the results
desired by researchers (that the programs worked), while later controlled experiments
yielded the surprising result that the programs in question were much less successful. She
concludes that in general studies without control groups show much higher success rates.
120 Chapter 4
and results measured. Krieger (1997, ch. 3) worries that rare events may be
missed by exclusive reliance on experiments, and thus advocates that
experiments be supplemented by real world analysis of natural processes.
With respect to phenomena, the experiment can only disclose the importance
of phenomena unexpected by the researcher if some sort of mistake is made
in experimental design, either through the introduction of some unplanned
element, or through failure to appreciate how the experimental environment
would influence results. Such serendipity is surprisingly common in the
history of natural science. Sir Alexander Fleming, for example, discovered
penicillin by observing a bacteria-free circle surrounding a mold growth that
had contaminated a culture of staphylococci. As experimental controls are
enhanced by technology, induction may rely increasingly on other methods.
Nomothetic versus idiographic relationships: Both are quite possible, for
experimental design can be manipulated to see how a particular cause-effect
relationship is affected by any number of circumstances. Experiments in
human science are usually conducted by those confident of general patterns
of cause and effect (McNeill, 1990, ch.3).18 Scientists must be careful of
generalizing from a small number of subjects studied in an artificial setting.
Spatiality (studies through space?): Experiments are usually constrained
to operate in an artificial and small laboratory setting. There is thus a huge
validity problem: do agents behave the same in their natural setting? This is
usually not a great concern with non-intentional agents, though some
biologists have doubted that experimental results concerning the effect of
UV radiation on amphibian reproduction support valid explanations of
decreased reproduction in the wild (Longino, 2000, 267-8), and Rothbart
(2000, 83) argues that chemists often seek observational verification of
experimental results. The problem looms much larger for intentional agents.
Other methods, such as participant observation, can then provide a useful
check on the validity of experimental results. Moreover, scientists cannot
follow spatial behavior requiring more space than the laboratory. Note,
though, that some experiments occur in fairly natural settings. A drug trial is
an experiment in which some people are given a drug and some a placebo:
beyond visits to the clinic they live their normal lives. An experiment on
spatial movement could be imagined in which researchers give people
misleading directions and see how they cope. But even in natural settings,
the mere knowledge that one is being observed can cause a change in
behavior: the “Hawthorne effect” refers to studies at GE’s Hawthorne plant
18
Advocates of qualitative research, including feminists, have often been hostile to
experiments (partially due to ethical concerns; because experiments involve control and
manipulation they seem an abuse of power, but Oakley argues that ethical experiments are
possible). Oakley (2000) notes that we all experiment in our daily lives – when cooking or
gardening for example – and should thus be willing to experiment in science as well.
4. Classifying Method 121
in the 1930s that found that workers increased effort whenever they were
being observed.
Change through time (continuous or static coverage?): Experiments
occur at a point in time. They are thus limited in their ability to analyze
changes that occur over lengthy periods. The experimental efforts of
geneticists have nevertheless informed the study of evolutionary processes,
by identifying what sorts of change are possible. Natural experiments are a
bit different, allowing scientists some scope for analyzing revolutions or
planetary formation.
Various time-paths: Experiments are best at identifying simple cause-
effect relationships. They can identify equilibria in very simple systems,
such as setting up a pricing game and seeing how a market-clearing price is
established, but in general are poor at identifying complex interactions.
Reliability: With intentional agents researchers must worry about
signalling the desired result to subjects. As well, subjects sometimes leave
during an experiment, biasing the results in perhaps unknown directions.
Careful design (for example distancing researcher from subject) and
replication (with the same and different research protocols) can help. Even
with non-intentional agents scientists should appreciate that there are a wide
variety of experimental set-ups possible, and thus experimentation cannot be
reduced to a routine process (Gower, 1997, 11).
General Comments: As Gower (1997, 10) notes, with citations from texts
in chemistry and physics, experiments are often treated as “the” method in
natural science. Obviously, experiments have many strengths, especially for
the analysis of non-intentional agents. Researchers may be oblivious to the
role played by various elements of experimental design in generating a
particular result. Thus the results of experiments are “rarely decisive,” and
“often ambiguous and sometimes opaque” because experimental results must
be transformed into broader theoretical arguments, and can generally be
interpreted in multiple ways (Gower, 11).19 It is generally useful, then, to
seek corroborating evidence from other methods. While biologists have had
much success in this regard, psychologists often find that experiments
produce different results from observation (Fuller, 1997, 13-14).
19
Gower goes on to maintain that philosophers of science have come to appreciate “the
practical difficulties in obtaining ‘good’ data from experiments...” (1997, 18). Yet
elsewhere Gower himself seems to treat experiment as “the” scientific method. Collins and
Pinch (1993, 3) are much more critical: “The problem with experiments is that they tell
you nothing unless they are competently done, but in controversial science no-one can
agree on a criterion of competence. Thus, in controversies it is invariably the case that
scientists disagree not only about results, but also about the quality of each other’s work.”
Valiela (2001, 13) counters that “The issue of experimental artifacts is real but something
of a red herring”; scientific advance suggests that problems can be overcome with
appropriate experimental design.
122 Chapter 4
5.3 Interviews
20
Oakley (2000) argues that when women interview women, the principle of respecting
one’s subject may introduce an even greater degree of bias toward identifying with the
subject’s point of view. Nevertheless, interviewers may forget the power relationship
inherent in interviews.
4. Classifying Method 123
5.4 Intuition/Experience
21
Goldenberg (1992) notes that humans are in general not reliable witnesses (though trained
observers may be much better). He suggests that there will be biases both in what is
observed and in how this is reported.
128 Chapter 4
22
Margaret Mead famously argued that Samoan adolescents were immune to feelings of
sexual jealousy. This result is now viewed with great scepticism. Still, Goldenberg asserts
that PO is very good at “theory-building”.
4. Classifying Method 129
23
Atkinson and Hammersley (1998) recognize that ethnographic reports necessarily absract
from reality; they nevertheless disdain the “linguistic turn” which stresses style over
substance in such reports, and celebrates their fictional quality. They suggest that
ethnographic studies should be judged in terms of validity and relevance to theory and
policy.
130 Chapter 4
(skeletons). Agents may also leave traces of what they touched: pottery, or
the plains scoured by glaciers. The traces left by relationships and groups
might be considered indirect traces of the individuals that comprised them.
Type of causation: Physical traces speak to passive causation (as when a
mountain pass facilitates movement) and intentional action (like making
pottery). Scientists can often infer attitudes (with a bit less confidence in
validity) from burial mounds and decorations.
The four criteria for identifying a causal relationship: Physical traces can
at times establish correlations – as when fossils are found in a particular
geological stratum – and (less often) temporality. They may point scientists
to intermediate variables, and may serve to discredit alternative hypotheses.
Decision-making processes?: Physical traces by their nature tell scientists
about the results of decisions, though they may thus provide indirect
evidence of decision-making processes.
Phenomena and processes outside of a particular theory?: This is quite
possible, and often occurs. Biologists have wondered about punctuated
equilibria because of gaps in the fossil record, and archaeologists have
posited links between groups on the basis of similarities in pottery. Still the
favored theory may guide scientists to look in places that are likely to contain
physical traces in accord with that theory.
Nomothetic versus idiographic relationships: Individual physical traces
are situation-specific, but generalizations can be drawn from many.
Spatiality (studies through space?): Physical traces can be collected from
different locales, and thus inferences drawn about spatiality.
Change through time (continuous or static coverage?): Physical traces
can be collected from different points in time, to identify what seems to have
changed, and perhaps evidence on why.
Various time-paths: Physical traces are best at highlighting changes in
particular phenomena over time, but can allow much insight into interactions
among these. Equilibria might be posited if the physical record exhibits little
change over some period of time.
24
Economists have in recent decades embraced a critique of macroeconomic models which
argues that changes in government policies will change attitudes and thus the strength of
causal relationships: economists can thus not use these models to predict how people will
respond to changes in policy. It has not been appreciated that the same critique
undermines all types of statistical analysis. Unless scientists understand why observed
correlations exist, they can have little confidence that a correlation observed in one time
and place will hold in another.
132 Chapter 4
sample of papers from a leading economic journal, and found that the vast
majority had failed to evaluate the real world importance of correlations.
Alternative hypotheses can potentially be tested, though in many important
cases these cannot be distinguished statistically. Intermediate variables can
be identified if they are recorded, and if the researcher includes them in the
analysis. Ragin (2000) devotes much of his book to arguing that standard
statistical procedures do not properly engage questions of sufficiency or
necessity: they instead establish potentially misleading correlations that may
ignore important ways in which causal factors interact. He is particularly
critical of casual assumptions that causal phenomena are independent, and
notes that the statistical techniques for dealing with interdependent variables
yield ambiguous results unless the number of variables is small relative to
the size of the data set; there is thus a tendency to only investigate
interactions preordained by theory (2000, 311-5). Statistical techniques can
also not distinguish between a variable which makes an outcome possible
and one that actively causes the outcome (Meltzoff, 1998). While statistical
procedures exist to distinguish causal influences in opposing directions, in
practice these can easily be conflated.
In the mid-nineteenth century, during a cholera outbreak in London,
William Farr found a strong negative correlation between incidence of
cholera and elevation; this supported the reigning theory of the time, that
cholera was transmitted through the air. John Snow argued forcefully that
cholera was transmitted through water. Unlike statistical analysis, case
studies and natural experiments did provide support for this alternative
theory. Only then was it recognized that the cholera flux was heavier than
water, and the pumping technology of the time caused less of it to be
transmitted to neighborhoods at higher elevation. S. Turner (1997) takes this
cautionary tale as evidence of the danger of relying on statistical analysis
alone, especially when unknown causal processes may be at work.
Decision-making processes?: By their nature, secondary data speak to
results rather than decision-making processes. As with respect to
mathematical modelling, there may be a bias toward assuming rational
decision-making, for this is easier to model.
Phenomena and processes outside of a particular theory?: There are
statistical techniques that allow the identification of correlations across
disparate bits of data: there is thus some inductive potential (though Valiela,
2001, 16-7, doubts that the search for correlations unguided by theory is
generally worth the effort). And even when a theorist has an idea of which
variables to include, statistical analysis can give surprising insights into their
relative importance. In general, though, secondary data are used
deductively. And note that researchers are guided to look at only those
phenomena that are quantifiable and for which data exists. Data rarely exists
4. Classifying Method 133
25
“Once we have a data set, it is a good idea to really try to understand the data before
plunging them into statistical tests now temptingly easy to do using statistical packages”
(Valiela, 2001, 44). Valiela guides researchers to examine outliers, see whether there are
obvious differences across samples, and see whether the data obeys common statistical
assumptions. Sloppy statistical analysis will lessen the potential for induction, and also
reduce the reliability and validity of the analysis.
26
Dale and Davies (1994) discuss various problems in analyzing change through time with
data from one point in time: “age” and “cohort” effects are conflated, respondent reports of
previous experiences are especially likely to error with regard to previous attitudes, and
duration effects may thus be underappreciated (the longer one is married the more likely
one will stay married). They thus encourage various forms of longitudinal research, where
data on the same or very similar subjects is collected at several points in time.
134 Chapter 4
new or old equilibria. There is a great danger that scientists will find
equilibria more often than these exist, simply because techniques for
identifying chaotic or disequilibrium systems are much less well developed.
Techniques of partial analysis, which measure how a change in one
phenomenon tends to cause (how much) change in others, are also available,
and often used. Analysis at the level of particular causal links can serve as
some antidote to a tendency to exaggerate system-level equilibriating
tendencies. Even here there has historically been a problem in that it has
been much easier to estimate relationships that are linear than to estimate
exponential relationships; the latest statistical packages are alleviating this
difficulty. Newell (2001) has hypothesized that interdisciplinarians will
often/always be interested in non-linear relationships, for causal links that
can be comprehended linearly will have been been embraced by disciplinary
researchers.
General considerations re reliability and validity: There is “a common
tendency to treat the validity of numerical data as given despite their
constructed character and the sources of potential error built into them”
(Hammersley and Gomm, 2000, 155). Scientists must look at how data are
recorded, and ask whether either those reporting or those recording had
likely biases. Government bureaucrats may define variables for convenience
in ways that differ from scientific definitions (and recall the discussion above
that definitions of crime or mental illness may reflect a desire for social
control). And they may exaggerate the reliability of statistics (such as crime
figures); researchers may be unable to check this.27 Moreover, neither those
collecting nor using statistics are as careful with respect to changing
definitions as they should be. Note that all of these problems tend to increase
as the researcher moves backward in time. Researchers may also be
selective in which data were included in the analysis. While statistical
analyses should be replicable, there are few professional rewards, at least in
human science, for attempting to replicate results. There is evidence that
mistakes in data entry or use of statistical techniques are common, though
there are only a few key studies here, again reflecting the limited rewards for
that type of research. In any case, the possibility of using different data sets
and different statistical techniques means in practice that quite different
results are derived from quite similar data. Perhaps most importantly,
scientists – and particularly interdisciplinary scientists – must worry that
phenomena that cannot or have not been measured quantitatively will simply
be ignored.
27
“Any data series is partly descriptive and partly interpretive; the thoughtful researcher pays
heed to both aspects”; those collecting data must necessarily have recourse to much
“qualitative” decision-making (Palys, 1997, 239).
4. Classifying Method 135
5.9 Surveys
questions are less flexible and the potential for removing bias less. In some
cases, though, people may be more honest in an anonymous survey (unless
they are misleading themselves) than in a face-to-face interview. And if
individual surveyee biases are likely to extend in opposing directions, the
larger sample available with surveys will be particularly advantageous. Still,
researchers must be careful in inferring causation from correlation; evidence
from other methods can be invaluable.
Decision-making processes?: Surveys will in general be less successful
than interviews at identifying decision-making processes.
Phenomena and processes outside of a particular theory?: Surveys,
unless they allow for open-ended responses (in which case they blend into
interviews; they also become much harder to administer, and create both
practical difficulties and questions of bias in evaluation), are very poor at
identifying these. Those surveyed may find that they cannot respond in the
way that they would wish to. Note that in drawing causal conclusions from
survey data alone those items not included in the survey will inevitably be
excluded. Critics of survey analysis worry that researchers impose their own
analytical concepts on the questions asked.
Nomothetic versus idiographic relationships: Surveys, with their
potential to ask a range of questions of a very large number of individuals,
may be able to identify general relationships or very specific ones.
Spatiality (studies through space?): Surveys can usually only ask people
about movements through space, and are thus subject here to the various
biases noted previously. Surveys can investigate how people in differing
spatial situations respond to survey questions. Longitudinal studies can
provide some measures of migration.
Change through time (continuous or static coverage?): Surveys take
place at a point in time. Longitudinal studies catch the same people at
different points in time, and can thus measure more accurately than a single
survey how people’s attitudes and behaviors change over time: scientists no
longer have to worry about errors of memory. Large-scale surveys, like the
census, can provide similar insights, to the extent that researchers can assume
that the “sample” is the same at different points in time.
Various time-paths: Surveys on their own will have great difficulty in
identifying these.
28
Goldenberg (1992) worries, though, that quantitative techniques of textual analysis will
miss that which is implicit in the text.
138 Chapter 4
Criteria for Aids each, Potentially Might pro- Some insight All; limited
identifying a but limited all four vide insight on with respect
causal on each correlation, to
relationship temporality intermediate,
alternatives
Time Path No insight Little insight Little insight Little insight Emphasize
equilibrium
4. Classifying Method 139
Criteria for All, but Some insight Correlation Some insight Some insight
identifying a rarely done to all four and on on all
causal temporality correlation
relationship well; others
maybe
Time Path Some insight Some insight Emphasize Little insight Some insight
equilibrium
Reliability and Validity: As with many other methods, there are obvious
advantages to replication. Yet there is virtually no explicit replication, either
in historical studies or in the evaluation of fictional texts. When the same
text is revisited, it is generally to show how a different interpretation can be
brought out by a different theoretical perspective. As noted before, one
interpretation is that it is possible to find anything in a text. In general,
though, one can identify the main messages.29
The literary theorist Roland Barthes argued that interdisciplinarity must
involve a focus on a subject such as “the text” that belongs to no discipline
(Moran, 2002, 83). The analysis of this book would suggest that theories of
textual interpretation and methods of textual analysis should be
distinguished, and that neither should be the monopoly of any one
community of scholars. Interdisciplinarians should be open to the use of
multiple theories and methods. While an expertise in literary theory or
method may be invaluable, interdisciplinary scholarship should not be
limited to these.
29
“Most philosophers and critics would be quite willing to admit that slippage of meaning
occurs (poetry works on just such a principle), but would draw the line at saying that
nothing but slippage occurs: it is hard to see how, if that were the case, we could even
communicate such a state of affairs.” (Sin 1992, 109).
4. Classifying Method 141
(McNeill, 1990, 88) Case studies are very useful for idiographic purposes.30
Ragin (2000, 68) suggests that case studies usually turn up evidence that
does not fit any theory perfectly.
Note, though, that a causal sequence cannot be distinguished from an
accidental sequence by relying on any one case study (Little, 1998, 213).
However, general rules may be built up or supported by comparing a number
of case studies (a point made with respect to each of the case study methods
above).31 Some of the detail of individual cases is inevitably lost in
generalizations (Stake, 1998). Scientists could usefully strive both to derive
generalizations and to explain deviations from these. One disadvantage of
statistical analysis is that outliers – data points that fit the estimated
relationship poorly – are rarely subjected to special analysis; a case study
approach could complement statistical analysis here.
McNeill (1990) emphasizes the value of case studies for induction.
Researchers should be careful not just to report those observations that seem
to lend themselves to generalizations; other information may encourage the
development of alternative theories or the recognition of limits to existing
theories. Note that cases are often chosen for their intrinsic interest (but also
to provide insight into a particular issue or theory; Stake, 1998), and thus
may not be representative. This potential bias could be combated through
random sampling, or through choosing quite different cases. While there
seems a danger that a researcher could draw any lesson from the multiplicity
of data contained in any one case study, in practice this danger is limited, and
researchers are often surprised by their results (Ragin, 2000, 68).
Note: Community studies represent one type of case study. A particular
community is analysed with the use of a variety of methods, including PO,
surveys, interviews, and textual analysis (McNeill, 1990, 93).
30
One major criticism of area studies programs has been their case study approach. Geertz
in 1973 responded in favor of the “thick description” inherent in case studies, “without
which the complex interrelationships among social processes and events cannot be
meaningfully unravelled.” As proponents of case studies have suggested criteria by which
these can be evaluated, opposition to case studies has fallen away (all in Tessler, 1999).
31
McNeill (1990) speaks of a ubiquitous comparative method. With case studies,
comparison is made across studies. With experiments, there is internal comparison with
the control group.
142 Chapter 4
5.13 Hermeneutics
32
Note, though, that some interpretivist researchers use the phrase “action research” in order
to distinguish their research from the causal emphasis of positivists.
4. Classifying Method 143
5.14 Mapmaking
33
“It is difficult to describe network analysis methodologically, since it seems to be more of
a perspective or even a theory than a method” (Goldenberg, 262). I suspect that the answer
to this quandary (which causes most writers on method to ignore network analysis) is that
mapping is inherently a method used in conjunction with other methods.
34
Pounds (2001) criticizes historians for not more often thinking cartographically. They use
verbal cartography when maps would be both more precise and objective (without maps,
researchers choose which spatial movements to report). He recognizes the costs involved
in drawing maps, but suspects that the problem is rooted in a lack of cartographic training.
144 Chapter 4
It has hopefully been shown that the typology provides a means for
evaluating the strengths and weaknesses, and especially the range of
applicability, of each method. And it yields a most interesting result: each
method has strengths and limitations. The legions of scientists and
philosophers who have argued otherwise can be thanked for making this
Golden Mean conclusion so important.
It was noted in the previous chapter that the 5W typology of theory
provided an answer to the vexed question of “what is a theory?” Gower
(1997, 249) bemoans the fact that the failure of philosophers to provide an
“account of scientific method” to which no exception can be found, has, as
with respect to theory, opened the door to those who would deny the very
existence of “scientific method,” or any standard by which this might be
preferred to other forms of investigation.35 As with theory, the provision of a
list of scientific methods provides a more compelling (Wittgensteinian)
definition of scientific method than has existed heretofore. Moreover, the
5W questions show that all of these methods can be evaluated in a similar
fashion, and the important result derived that each has strengths and
weaknesses. Given that each proves to have different attributes, it is hardly
35
Sceptics point to the fact that the dominant method in science has changed over time. But
this merely shows that there is more than one scientific method, and none is perfect.
Advances in technology (such as improved telescopes) have influenced the popularity of
particular methods at particular points in time.
4. Classifying Method 145
36
They also suggest that all social research involves five questions: what do we want to
know and why?, what is to be observed? (time and place, units of analysis, relevant
characteristics, process in which units embedded), which and how many objects are to be
examined?, how are they to be observed, and what degree of certainty can be applied to the
results? The 5W typology has dealt with all of these questions and more.
146 Chapter 4
mastery of the material by both students and scholars. Second, and crucially,
it would facilitate comparison by providing a hopefully exhaustive set of
questions. The same can be said with respect to methods. The number of
dimensions has doubled, but is still quite manageable. As with respect to
theoretical flexibility, the typology provides a sound base from which to urge
methodological flexibility, both in general and with respect to particular
research questions.
Specialized researchers can use the typology to ask whether methods
eschewed by their community might have something important to say.
Interdisciplinary scholars with expertise in a particular method could use the
typology to gauge where that method might usefully be applied
“[S]ystematic explorations of new domains have played a large role in the
history of many sciences,” as when scientists explored how magnets operate
on different metals. “Existing knowledge – a taxonomy of substances and
their properties and components – is the major prerequisite for the generation
of such programs” (Langley et al., 1987, 306). If this strategy works for
magnets, why not for (theories or) methods?
One further advantage of the typology is that it suggests that the scientific
community does not take full advantage of the potential of particular
methods. It was often noted that a particular method is not used within its
full range of applicability. The inductive potential of secondary data analysis
is not fully appreciated. PO researchers could try harder to identify causal
relationships.
The advantages of replicating various types of research were also
highlighted. In the case of PO and interviews, comparing results across
different studies can greatly enhance both reliability and validity. In the case
of statistical analysis, replicability is often assumed, but scholars should
make greater efforts to illustrate this. Validity is also problematic; multiple
studies using different data and techniques are highly advisable. These
points are perhaps well understood, but are rarely reflected in especially
human science research.
More generally, the analysis above points to common flaws in the
application of methods. Better scientific practice can and should be
encouraged with respect to all methods. Palys (1997, 186) notes that while
researchers often criticize the practices of other researchers, they are
generally critical not of particular methods per se but of how these are
applied. They also tend to gloss over problems with the application of their
favored method. A greater appreciation of the problems, and best strategies
for overcoming these, within each method, should thus act to encourage a
greater appreciation of methodological diversity.
The 5W approach provides a means by which both scholars and students
could be introduced to the possibilities inherent in all methods. Mastering
4. Classifying Method 147
37
Given the difficulty of mastering different methods, there are advantages to academic
specialization by method. The problem with disciplines is that this methodological
mastery is thus artificially conflated with a set of theories and phenomena, when all
methods should be applied to all relevant theories and phenomena. “[Research methods]
are not the private domain of any particular discipline, but rather are an abstract set of rules
or contingencies that may be applied to both physical science and social science problems”
(Hartman and Hedblom, 1988, 5). It is thus of some interest that some economists,
geographers, and cultural anthropologists would wish to define their disciplines in terms of
method alone.
148 Chapter 4
rather than physics had been the focus of philosophical attention, the value of
methodological plurality would be more widely appreciated; yet even in
biology many urge the exclusive reliance on experiments (Magnum, 2000).
A superior assumption can be proposed: given that no method is perfect,
scientists should always seek justification for any theoretical proposition in
terms of different methods. There may well be exceptions to this guideline,
but these should be established, not assumed. In the words of the Pragmatic
philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce, truth [or at least what is thought to be
likely true] is the confluence of independent streams of good evidence. One
of the costs of disciplinarity is that this common sense notion is not more
widely appreciated.38 Given the imperfections in every scientific method this
yields two types of unfortunate result. In the first case, a hypothesis receives
strong support from analysis using the favored method, but would be
questioned by analysis using other methods. Fuller (1993, 194-5), referring
to the study of science itself, notes that interviews, ethnography, and textual
analysis each have different biases that support different interpretations of
how science operates. In the second case, a hypothesis receives ambiguous
support from the favored method, but would be resoundingly supported by
research using other methods.39 The discussion of cholera and statistical
analysis above is an example.
The 5W questions allow this argument to be fleshed out in detail. Are
there particular types of agent, causal process, decision-making process, and
so on, for which one method far outperforms the others? The clearest
positive answer to this question lies in the applicability of the experimental
method to the study of the interactions among non-intentional agents. Here,
the main limitations of the experimental method, such as the danger that
agents act differently in artificial settings, difficulties in penetrating
decision-making processes, and spatial or temporal boundaries, often do not
come into play (but not always; some natural processes occur on a large
physical or temporal scale such that experimentation is infeasible). The
many strengths of the experimental method thus operate unimpeded. It
38
There are some exceptions. Fraser and Gaskell (1990, 13) celebrate the range of methods
used by social psychologists – interviews, observations, group discussions, content
analysis, and statistical analysis (though Himmelweit in the same volume worries that
some methods are still used less than they should be). And Pervin (1990) concludes his
handbook on personality theory thus: “At least for the present, however (and, we may
hope, for the future) the time of dismissal of some phenomena as not legitimate for
investigation and of hegemony of some research methods over others has passed.”
39
Oakley (2000) notes that as early as 1957 Trow had urged scientists and philosophers to
move away from asserting the general superiority of one method, discuss their relative
usefulness for different questions, and use the widest array of methods suited to the
problem at hand. Campbell and Fiske argued in 1959 that psychological traits in particular
had to be identified with multiple methods (Tashakkori and Teddlie, 1998, 41).
4. Classifying Method 149
should hardly be a surprise, then, that the experimental method dominates the
study of chemicals and atomic particles, for these are well suited to the
laboratory (and vulcanologists try to duplicate this method with natural
experiments). Note, though, that experiments are still fallible: researchers
may be oblivious to the role played by various elements of experimental
design in generating a particular result.40 Even here, then, scholars should
not entirely dismiss other methods. While those methods which involve
asking questions of subjects are obviously unsuited to non-intentional agents
(though chapter 5 will discuss the benefits of querying those scientists who
study these), classification, intuition (chemical reactions are regularly
observed in our daily lives), mathematical modelling (to identify possibilities
and exclude impossibilities), physical traces (of interactions in a natural
setting), and even mapmaking (the Periodic Table can be seen as a map) can
usefully be applied.
Other cases in which a particular method outshines others can be
identified. Mapmaking can give unique insight into spatial and temporal
aspects of causal systems (among other things). Intuition likely gives unique
insight into how and why, for example, art moves humans. Surveys are
advantageous for gauging attitudes of large numbers of individuals. PO may
be the only way to comprehend how others make meaning of their lives. But
again all methods are problematic and scientists would wish to supplement
these wherever possible.
Human science is often viewed as a weak relation to natural science,
precisely because it is not dominated to the same extent by one method. The
5W approach shows that the difference is one of degree rather than kind
(albeit an important difference of degree). Not all natural scientists can avail
themselves of the experimental method. Even those that can use experiments
should nevertheless seek insights from other methods. Human scientists
generally, but not always, focus upon intentional causation. Since all
methods are applicable to intentional agents, but not all are applicable to
non-intentional agents, human scientists must then have recourse to a wider
range of methods than those utilized in natural science. They should neither
idealize nor condemn the methods of natural science, but draw from the full
range. Interpretivists who claim that only attitudes matter neglect the twin
facts that actions result from a mixture of external (to the individual) and
internal causes, and that internal causes can be evaluated in terms of (non-
intentional) personality characteristics, schemas, and so on; they are thus
mistaken in suggesting that human science can have no recourse to the
40
This realization is of critical importance in modern philosophy of science. It was the
mistaken idea that (at least) experiments could be infallible that had supported positivist
arguments earlier in this century that scientific statements could be proved or at least
disproved.
150 Chapter 4
methods of natural science, but correct in asserting that human science must
do more than ape natural science (Singleton and Strait, 1999).
The 5W analysis can guide the research process in many ways. First a
theorist should be guided (by the analysis in chapter 3) to specify answers to
the 5W questions. They can then ask what sorts of method are best suited to
each of the elements of a particular theory. While it may be impossible for
an individual researcher to use all implicated methods, they might strive to
use those underemployed by previous researchers. Note that for any non-
trivial scientific question in human science it will likely be possible to
identify some application of all methods. Most questions in natural science
will likewise lend themselves to a handful of methods. Scholars writing
survey articles should thus strive to report research using all methods, or at
least urge scientists to broaden their approach so that this can be done.
“Unfortunately, social researchers rely altogether too frequently on a
single method or measure when a number of approaches could be brought to
bear on the research question” (Singleton and Strait, 1999, 394).41 Where a
particular research enterprise has been dominated by one method, the
researcher can use the typology to identify the most serious limitations of
that method, and their relevance to the particular research questions being
addressed. If, for example, statistical analysis of secondary data has
dominated, one would be concerned about the possible exclusion of
relationships from the analysis, the role of attitudes and decision-making
processes, the possibility of exclusion of non-equilibrium processes,
trivialization of the spatial dimension, omission of variables not implicated
by theory (or for which data could not be found), interactions among causal
factors more complex than could be handled by standard statistical
techniques (at least before the latest generation of statistical packages),
and/or failure to properly identify causal relationships. One could then turn
to methods that are better in each of these respects. Not surprisingly, various
case study methods loom large here. But again all methods will likely have
something to contribute.
Since particular methods are best suited to the investigation of certain
theory types, the complete reliance of any scientific community on one
method – except in those cases where one method is ideally suited to the
phenomena in question – will almost certainly bias results in favor of the
preferred theory (for surely the community will have chosen a theory and
method that deal with the same type of agent, action, and so on). In other
41
Pressures to conform are felt early in one’s career. “Every student whether writing an
essay or completing a doctoral thesis has felt this pressure. The methods used may satisfy
examiners but they are not suitable for capturing the topic. The brave may abandon the
study and their careers. Most adjust to conform to the standards required for qualification”
(Shipman, 1988, 166).
4. Classifying Method 151
words, scholars are supposed to test theories against alternatives, and if this
is done only in the context of a method best suited to one of the competing
theories, the community will be more confident than it should be in the
validity of that theory. Economists, for example, should be aware that
statistical testing is best suited to rational individual actions and equilibrium
outcomes, just as is the rational choice theory that dominates the discipline.
It is not enough that a community uses multiple methods: they must apply
these correctly, There is a danger that methods will be mis-applied such that
they generate desired responses (Fuller, 1998, 130). Familiarity with the
typology above would be invaluable in spotting such errors; this might be
coupled with a sense of the disciplinary perspective or worldview of the
scholarly community in question (see chapter 5, Szostak, 2003a).
6.2 Triangulation
42
This can be seen as a special case of the problem of induction: just because all existing
cases point in a particular direction does not mean this will hold in future (Seale, 1999, 57-
61).
43
Tashakkori and Teddlie also urge researchers to explicitly draw from both of what they see
as broader quantitative and qualitative paradigms. The analysis above suggests that it is a
mistake to reify qualitative and quantitative paradigms. Seale (1999) argues that research
should not be guided by a paradigm; he urges researchers to eclectically do what works
best. Hammersley (1996, 168) suggests that viewing qualitative and quantitative
approaches as distinct paradigms implies that researchers first choose a philosophic
orientation; in practice researchers develop their philosophical and methodological
orientations pragmatically through interaction with others.
4. Classifying Method 153
6.3 Meta-analysis
44
Stake (1998) suggests a different interpretation of triangulation. It “has been generally
considered a process of using multiple perceptions to clarify meaning, verifying the
repeatability of an observation or interpretation. But acknowledging that no observations
or interpretations are perfectly repeatable, triangulation serves also to clarify meaning by
identifying different ways the phenomenon is being seen.”
154 Chapter 4
1
Kuhn showed that “’the’ paradigm or ‘the’ methods characteristic of a particular science
are a gross simplification; their real content comes in their application ... This means that
we must look at the actual practice of science rather than just its textbook formulations”
(Kincaid, 1996, 36-7). Kincaid refers specifically to problem-solving strategies, skills, and
implicit knowledge.
156 Chapter 5
like.2 The Golden Mean was invoked at the time. Freeman (1994) guides
scholars to expose the influence of power and envy on the scientific
enterprise, “and still recognize that the laws of nature cannot be bent and
cannot be broken by power and money;” he concludes that “the history of
science is most illuminating when the frailties of human actors are put into
juxtaposition with the transcendence of natural laws.” Collins and Pinch
(1993, 1) suggest that, rather than seeing science as all good or all bad, it be
viewed as a “bumbling giant” that possesses some imperfect ability to move
in the desired direction. Later (142) they suggest that scientists should be
more humble; pretending that science is perfect encourages those who are
sceptical of science. In the context of the evolution/creation debate, Kitcher
(1982) argues that false claims that science rests on infallible proofs makes it
too easy for those who disagree with certain scientific conclusions to
discredit these: neither evolutionary theory, nor the evidence in support of it,
is flawless. An understanding that science is inherently imperfect would,
ironically, have the effect of enhancing the authority of science.3 The
reverse argument can also be made: critiques of science that deny any
connection between scientific theories and reality are too readily dismissed
by the scientific community. Scientists can thus be blissfully unaware of the
biases and errors that might afflict their work.4 Moreover, the public,
exposed primarily to extreme views, is left unsure of how to evaluate
particular scientific arguments: “To raise the level of scientific literacy [in
the public], we need to better explain what science does ... [in particular] that
science works in imperfect ways” (Valiela, 2001, 268). A public that
understood the variety of biases that might afflict scientific research, but also
2
Ward (1996, 95) identifies a third extreme: postmodernists who argue that understanding
of reality cannot be separated from the symbols used to represent it. While there is
inevitably some ambiguity even in scientific texts, central messages can still be identified,
at least if the text is clearly written (Szostak , 2003, ch.2). Ward favors a focus on the
process by which scientific discoveries are first made and then spread through the
community of scientists.
3
A further irony comes from the fact that it was from the church that seventeenth century
science borrowed the idea of proof: Copernicus was told that one needed proof to disagree
with Scripture (Motterlini, 1999, 35). Other anti-science arguments reflect jealousy of the
status of science, frustration at inability to understand it, suspicion of any powerful group,
or celebration of the mysterious (Holton, 1993, esp. 154-6, 173-5). The Golden Mean
approach allows arguments to be discredited that can clearly be traced to such motives.
4
This is regrettable, for “A mind-set of critical skepticism is essential for scientists”
(Valiela, 2001, 268). While the social study of science has established that science is not a
uniquely rational activity, even the broader community of sociologists behaves as if it were
(Cole, 1992, ix). Sociologists of science may exaggerate their case out of fear that if they
recognize any role for reality scientists will just assume that this dominates (Cole, 1992, x).
Scientists do, of course, search for errors when judging the works of others; the danger
here is that they look for only a subset of possible errors, perhaps only some commonly
recognized difficulties with the preferred method and data of their field.
5. Classifying Practice 157
the fact that these do not render science impossible, would be much better
prepared to evaluate the barrage of scientific information in the daily news.5
Where does the Golden Mean lie? This is inherently an empirical
question: potential influences of both reality and society [including
individual psychology] in generating scientific results can be identified
theoretically, but there are no simple theoretical grounds on which to
determine the relative importance of these (Cole, 1992, x).6 While some
vague idea of the relative importance of these two types of influence on
average can be gained by looking across several case studies of scientific
practice, common sense suggests that the balance will likely differ across
types of science. “I think that most people working in science studies would
agree that one encounters scientists that one admires more than others,
findings that seem more compelling than others, and uses to which the
sciences are put that seem more enlightened than others” (Cussins, 2000,
331).7 In other words, the types of biases and errors that might afflict science
must first be identified. Then these can be investigated across the types of
theory, method, and phenomena/data identified in previous chapters, to
establish under what conditions particular errors and biases are most likely to
exert a key influence on scientific outcomes.8 This chapter will develop a
typology of critiques of scientific practice. The next chapter discusses how
these are likely correlated with previous classifications.
“For all their labors, the philosophers have failed to come up with any
simple, generally agreed principle on which belief in science might be safely
5
Carl Sagan warned that a public that does not understand the essence of science can
embrace magic as equally valid (Valiela, 2001, 256). Much public angst arises from
exaggerated reports of weak results (Valiela, 259). The public should be informed that
science is imperfect, and scientists encouraged not to exaggerate (Shipman, 1988). Katzer,
Cook, and Crouch (1998, vi) appreciate that “Most consumers of research will need to
evaluate various types of research.” Nevertheless, they seek a common set of criteria to be
applied in each case. They recommend an error approach, where common errors are
looked for; if scientists do not find these they can have confidence in the result.
6
Cole (1992, 234) worries that social constructivists have failed to identify empirical results
that they would accept as evidence that reality also matters. Many scientists in turn reject
evidence that social influences play some role.
7
As Cussins details, the field of science studies is characterized by different schools of
thought. Some schools evince extreme skepticism while others celebrate science; the
majority fall somewhere in between. Not surprisingly these schools of thought tend to
favor theories and methods that support these starting premises (see also Fuller, 1993).
8
Already in 1973, Stoner (xvii), reprising the pioneering work in sociology of science of
Robert Merton, appreciated that the nature and growth of science could not be understood
“without dealing specifically with the contents of science: its concepts, data, theories,
paradigms, and methods.” Yet scholars must also “distinguish the behavior of scientists as
scientists from the details of their ‘output’,” and thus need to identify the social influences
on scientific practice.
158 Chapter 5
Critics of scientific practice often use the words “error” and “bias”
without defining their meaning. Hammersley and Gomm (2000, 151-3)
suggest three main definitions of the word “bias”. While they recognize that
this list may not be exhaustive, it suits this chapter’s purposes nicely; all of
the biases to be identified here fit within one of these meanings of the word.
Notably, at least within their definitions, it only makes sense to speak of
biases or errors if it is thought that there is an objective truth to deviate from;
nevertheless constructivists often accuse others of bias or error (156-7).
A first definition of bias involves the pursuit of a particular point of
view. Scientists will then inevitably emphasize certain aspects of a question.
The most powerful antidote for this sort of bias lies in synthesizing different
viewpoints, as recommended in previous chapters; scientists thus reduce the
risk of ignoring important aspects of the question at hand. Many relativists,
though, recognizing that some bias of this sort is inevitable (at least in human
science), urge scientists to choose a bias that is socially responsible. If
scientists thus miss important insights, though, they may be unable to give
accurate guidance to those they wish to help. 9 Hammersley (2000) notes
9
Some partisans imply that any social change is good; history suggests that misguided
efforts to help the disadvantaged could leave them worse off. An alternative justification is
that different social groups bring different perspectives and values to research. But if all
knowledge is relative scientists have no way of determining which perspectives are best.
To leap from recognition that bias cannot be eliminated to a conclusion that scientists
5. Classifying Practice 159
that such relativist arguments are often assumed rather than justified; he
identifies a handful of possible justifications and finds each wanting.
A second definition of bias would involve any systematic deviation from
reality. Hammersley and Gomm speak of sampling bias or measurement
bias as important examples. If a sample is not random, or a method of
measurement consistently under- (or over-) estimates the true value, results
will likely be erroneous. This is the sort of bias that was dealt with in
chapter 4. No method is perfect, and particular applications of particular
methods introduce scope for further imperfections. At times, such
imperfections are random and should cancel each other out over large
enough samples. Hammersley and Gomm are concerned with imperfections
that are biased in a particular direction. Note, though, that even random
imperfections are problematic, for they introduce noise into results.
The third definition is the most specific: it speaks of a tendency of
researchers to collect, interpret, and present data in a way that supports
preconceptions. This might lead them – and those who accept their results –
to a false conclusion, or away from the correct conclusion. Such a bias
might reflect religious, political, or other attitudes of the researcher. Or it
might represent the desire of all researchers to provide further support for
positions they [or perhaps those they hope to impress] have previously
advanced. Note that such a predilection might be conscious or subconscious.
Hammersley and Gomm emphasize that this bias [like the others] can affect
all methods: they speak in particular of the design of experiments, phrasing
of survey or interview questions, and interpretation of ethnographic data.
Hammersley and Gomm treat biases as a subset of errors. Other errors
include any non-systematic imperfection in the research process. That is, for
them a bias must mean errors in one direction. Note that biases then
necessarily detract from the validity of results. These random errors may
reflect researcher negligence or the inevitable imperfections in methods. In
the latter case Hammersley and Gomm speak of non-culpability.
Hammersley and Gomm emphasize the fact that in any research enterprise
scientists must start from a set of unprovable assumptions (see chapter 6); if
these are wrong the results will likely reflect this. Both negligence and non-
culpability can lead to systematic error as well.
Such definitions of bias and error can provide only a starting point from
which to identify the potential sources of bias and error. As noted above, a
fairly exhaustive list of these should be possible. As with respect to
scientific theory in chapter 3, though, there appear to be a diversity of
should abandon the pursuit of objective understanding is “to assume that an ideal that is
not, or never can be, fully realised is of no value. This is true of some ideals but not of all”
(Hammersley, 2000, 33). This is, of course, a classic Golden Mean argument.
160 Chapter 5
critiques, and there is some sense that new questions arise as science evolves.
This chapter will develop a typology of critiques of scientific practice, and
show where major biases and errors fit, but cannot pretend to engage every
critique that has or could be made. It is thus useful to begin with a fairly but
not completely exhaustive list of the types of questions that might be asked
about scientific practice.10 The following list reflects a reading of diverse
studies of scientific practice; it is much less concrete than the list of methods
in chapter 4, but much more useful than the list of grand theories at the start
of chapter 3:
x What is science, and (how) can it be distinguished from non-science?
x Who possesses scientific understanding?; What are its warrants; How is it
acquired? What does it do? (see Cussins, 2000, 330).
x Is science objective in practice? How objective can it be? What can be
done to make it more objective? Is there an external reality to be
understood?
x In particular, to what degree can evidence support (or not) a theory?; how
much scope for human judgment is there in science?
x To what extent do the perceptual and psychological limitations of all
humans limit the scope for scientific understanding?
x Are scientists biased? Can the directions of bias be identified? (How) can
bias be combatted?
x Is the institutional structure of science conducive to its practice (that is,
does it serve to combat subjectivity, bias, etc,)?
x In particular, how are scientists trained, and is this training appropriate?
x Is science too specialized? What is the role of interdisciplinarity?
x Are the values held by the scientific community appropriate? (How) are
they inculcated, and are they widely held?
x In particular, are scientists likely to exaggerate the evidence in support of
their conjectures, or even obscure evidence that contradicts these?
x Are scientists biased toward producing results that support the economic,
social, and political status quo?
10
Madden (1989, vii) provides a list of persistently recurring questions in the philosophy of
science. These involve theory construction, hypotheses, causality (especially the
universality thereof), lawfulness [that is generalizability], probability, experimental
methods, the problem of induction, and the problem of distinguishing evidence from
assertion. Most of these have been discussed in previous chapters. The last issue deals
most directly with the questions of bias to be engaged in this chapter.
5. Classifying Practice 161
The 5W questions are a useful guide yet again, but will prove somewhat
less exclusive here than in earlier chapters: for example, the incentives faced
by scholars (Why?) reflect the institutional structure in which they operate
(Where?) Recall from chapter 1 that some fuzziness in boundaries is
acceptable if undesirable for a classification. It will still be possible to
identify distinct subsidiary questions under each heading. The classifications
developed in previous chapters will prove useful in pursuing deduction:
when investigating ‘who?’, it will prove useful to examine individual, group,
and relationship agency among scientists. The classification of phenomena is
particularly noteworthy: each element in the typology of critiques can be
understood in terms of causal links toward the phenomenon ‘science’ (or a
definition of science, in the case of ‘what?’). The diversity of analysis in the
field of science studies suggests that a fairly exhaustive classification is
possible by combining as in previous chapters a deductive approach with an
inductive reading of the science studies literature.
2.1 Who?
Are scientists objective? No. Scientists are not computers but complex
organisms with competing genetic drives and quite imperfect perceptual
capabilities. They will often see what they want to see, or what they think it
is important to see, and can be expected to miss much that either conflicts
with or seems entirely extraneous to their view of the world. Are scientists
completely subjective, then? No. While some methods are open to a greater
exercise of subjectivity than others, all require some confrontation with
reality in a manner that limits the researcher’s ability to ignore evidence that
is uncongenial. This fact will form a key element of the very definition of
science to be proffered below.
“Philosophical theories of science are generally theories of scientific
rationality. The scientist of philosophical theory is an ideal type, the ideally
rational scientist” (Giere, 1988, 2). Social constructivist views go to the
other extreme, and deny any influence of reality upon scientific thought.
Giere (1988) argues for an “in-between view” – that is, a Golden Mean – that
speaks of scientists using their imperfect perceptual apparatus to interact
with reality. Scientists strive for explanations that fit both reality and “their
own emotional longings among the alternative world views” (Feuer, 1995,
ix). Writers such as Bunge (1998) and Ziman (2000) bemoan the amount of
ink that has been spilled, notably but not exclusively in recent decades, in
defending one or the other of these untenable extremes while glorying in
162 Chapter 5
the impossibility of the alternative. This book can proceed to the less
sensational but more useful task of identifying the degree and sources of
bias. To ask “who is the scientist?” is to query the degree to which any
human(s) can shake off both limitations in ability and selfish motives in
order to pursue scientific understanding.
One insight of sociology of science is that scientists are not superhuman
but “merely” humans with a particular expertise (Fuller, 1997, 8-9). It is
useful to start, then, with a sense of basic human capabilities. Humans have
likely been selected genetically for certain sorts of scientific inquiry
(Kantorovich, 1993, 201-2). Humanity’s hunter-gatherer ancestors needed to
make judgments in their pursuit of food, clothing, shelter, and other basic
needs, and were likely selected for an ability to reach accurate perceptions of
at least some elements of their environment. Since they dealt with changing
environments they would have been selected not for particular attitudes
appropriate to one environment but an ability to evaluate various sorts of
evidence. Since hunter-gatherers cooperated, they should have been selected
for an understanding of some elements of human as well as natural science.
Along with a selection for certain sorts of inquiry humans have also been
selected for general cognitive abilities, and thus likely have some ability to
tackle any question. Nevertheless, human ability to tackle some questions –
due both to limitations in ability and biases – may be very limited.
Fuller (1997, 28) urges the identification of human cognitive
imperfections, and then of the degree to which these affect scientific practice.
He notes that certain human failings – such as a tendency to deviate from
rules – can at times yield good scientific outcomes, though this is likely not
the general case. Halperin (1997, 21) lists 21 common “fallacies” in how
humans make and evaluate any argument: these include logical problems
such as circular reasoning or assuming that correlation implies causation,
emotional problems such as succumbing to appeals to pity, pride, ignorance,
or tradition, and errors in judgment such as accepting appeals to authorities
with no particular expertise, or accepting evidence that is inherently
unknowable (such as reports that unreported crime is increasing). Later
(1997, 215-6) Halperin lists several biases in decision-making: humans
exaggerate easily recalled information, are excessively optimistic, and allow
emotional states and preferences to overwhelm reason. Scientists are
hopefully less subject to these various biases – scientific training urges
scepticism of authority, for example – but are not entirely immune (see
Kruglanski, 1989). Valiela (2001, 268), notably, worries, as does Halperin,
that scientists all too often criticize fellow scientists rather than the
arguments that these put forth. This human tendency to personalize
arguments is not conducive to scientific advance.
5. Classifying Practice 163
Giere (1988, ch.6) argues that scientists are satisficers: they seek theories
that fit reality, but are not overly concerned that there is likely another theory
that will fit reality even better [especially if this may fit less well with their
worldview]. Valiela (2001, 269) also suggests that scientists are too prone to
inertia in this regard. This is not entirely a bad thing: scientists plagued by
extreme doubt would be unable to proceed. But if Giere is right then
scientists may show too little openness to novel theories and also to evidence
that the existing theory does not flawlessly reflect reality.
Table 2.1 suggests that it is generally useful to look not only at general
human characteristics but also individual differences. Particular scientists
may have qualities that encourage certain sorts of discoveries or certain sorts
of bias. Ralph Waldo Emerson in 1837 observed that “character is higher
than intellect” for a scholar (in Glassick et al., 1997, 62). What personality
characteristics seem broadly conducive to scientific advance?11 Emerson
stressed patience, courage, and self-trust, to which Glassick et al. add
integrity and perseverance. Beveridge (1957) lists curiosity, honesty,
openmindedness, imagination, tenacity, and humility.12 Einstein suggested
that there were three types of scientists, those who worked to exercise their
talents, those who viewed science as a career and could just as easily have
pursued other careers, and those who viewed science as a vocation; he
argued that the last group had an impact much greater than their numbers
(Beveridge 1957, 143).
Beveridge (ch. 5) expands on the role of imagination. Solutions to
problems tend to come from the subconscious when the scientist has
temporarily diverted their attention from the problem: when they are in the
park or the bath. Such moments of inspiration, however, occur only after
lengthy periods of conscious focus on the problem. Beveridge recommends
that scientists read widely and talk with a diversity of others about the
problem, in order to give their subconscious the widest range of information
to synthesize. After a moment of inspiration, they must be able to recognize
that this was imperfect. Beveridge suggests, indeed, that the best scientists
are those best able to recognize errors. He quotes Planck, Einstein, and
Helmholtz; each speaks of many errors on their road to discovery, and how
they were guided by a vague vision of the direction to go. It may be that the
present structure of science (see below) limits the exercise of imagination.
Specialization and the pressure to publish combine to discourage reading
11
In investigating this question, scholars should be wary of spurious correlation: the
psychological attributes, discoveries, and biases of a community may reflect its historical
evolution and/or institutional structure (‘where’ and ‘when’ below; see Bromne, 2000).
12
Amabile (1996) suggests that independence, sensitivity, and a preference for complexity
are also conducive to creativity of various types. An ability to concentrate may also be
crucial, but one must also be able to let go.
164 Chapter 5
13
Getman (1992) argues that (especially leading) scientists like to see arrogance in their
colleagues, for this serves to reinforce their own inflated view of their importance [and
people like to hire people like themselves anyway]. A humble colleague, by their very
existence as well as their research efforts, questions the pretenses of the elite. There may
thus be selection away from humility – which may foster gender and ethnic discrimination.
This tendency will be exacerbated by the training of the next generation of scientists:
rather than telling them of our collective ignorance, their teachers celebrate even trivial
accomplishments, and thus signal that arrogance is not just acceptable but de rigeur.
5. Classifying Practice 165
though, may not let their brains rest in order to achieve inspiration. Certain
sorts of discovery may thus be more likely from the moderately motivated.
Likewise, since extroversion is conducive to interaction with others and
introversion to independent thought, shy people may provide insights that
extroverts cannot. Both holistic and analytical thinkers should be heard, as
should both the calm and emotional. Mood swings may encourage certain
sorts of discovery: Storr (1996) treats Newton and Einstein as examples.
Conscientiousness has obvious advantages for any complex endeavor, but
untidy thinkers may be able to draw connections between elements the
conscientious would never juxtapose. Organizational theorists suggest that
creative firms must draw together people with both diverse talents and
personalities. Scientists, and especially elite scientists, may tend to hire
those who resemble themselves, at least in terms of some personality
dimensions (Getman, 1992, 260). What is lost if the shy or holistic are thus
selected out? Very little research has been performed along these lines.
In addition to biases inherent in genes and individual personalities, a host
of societal influences can generate further biases. Table 2.1 again proves
useful, as all of the major categories could generate some sort of bias:
scientists threatened by volcanoes or earthquakes may have different
attitudes toward nature, as may those in a disease-ridden environment. The
art of a society may influence its scientists, and its economic well-being will
almost certainly have an influence on the amount if not direction of scientific
research. Scholars of science have, though, tended to emphasize cultural,
political, and social considerations.
Scientists are part of a wider society and, even if they consider themselves
rebels or outsiders, will have internalized some of the values of that wider
society. They will thus wish to uncover scientific understanding that is in
accord with these values. This may seem of little import in natural science,
but recall the religious furore occasioned in the past over heliocentric views
of the solar system or theories of biological evolution, and which may well
be occasioned in the future with respect to genetic engineering. Even less
controversial elements of science may reflect cultural values. Newton saw
himself as illuminating the order of Godly creation: who can guess to what
extent scientists exercise a bias toward order in their investigations for
similar cultural reasons? Fuller (1997, 56-7 suggests that scientists generally
believe in progress so powerfully that it is impossible to convince them
otherwise. With respect to human science, cultural values generally play an
even greater role: if a society believes that art is ineffable or market
outcomes fair or gender distinctions normal, then scientists may be biased
toward finding these same results.
Michel Foucault is justly famous for emphasizing the political element in
all of this. Those with power in a society will encourage cultural attitudes
166 Chapter 5
that serve to maintain their power. The values that scientists embrace will
thus often not reflect the will of the people but of the elite. And thus
scientific biases may serve to support the status quo. Elites, moreover, act to
directly influence scientific outcomes through their financing of research (see
below). Foucault spoke in particular of how scientific analyses of
criminality and insanity served as mechanisms of social control, but intended
his analysis to apply much more broadly.
Scholars have also written at length of late about the social element in
values. Society has different expectations of people depending on their
gender, ethnicity, and class/occupation (and also sexual orientation, age,
marital status, and so on). White men can be expected to be more favourably
disposed toward attitudes that support their social status than are women or
minorities or the poor. Since the scientific enterprise has long been
dominated by white men, it likely reflects such biases.14 Again, this problem
might be expected to loom larger in human science, but the priorities chosen
by natural scientists are also affected (as in choosing to investigate prostate
versus breast cancer).
Sadly, much of the relevant literature starts from the assumption that such
biases are pervasive. The work of Foucault and many others can leave little
doubt that such biases do influence scientific outcomes. But innumerable
counter-examples can also be pointed to of white male scientists arguing
against cultural attitudes that serve the elite and/or discriminate against
women or minorities. These can be attributed to two sources. First, culture
is not as monolithic as some scholars of culture presume (Szostak, 2003),
and thus all humans have some capacity to disagree with their society’s
values. Scientists do this in their everyday lives, and are even more likely to
do it in their lives as scientists. Secondly, scientific methods themselves, as
noted above, force scientists to face up to reality and ask questions and reach
conclusions that they might have preferred to avoid.
The preceding analysis has proceeded largely at the individual level. The
typology of theory in chapter 3 would suggest that analysis of groups and
relationships might also be important. As has already been suggested, these
might shape individual personalities and behaviors. Indeed, Fuller (1993, 5)
notes that his analysis of science bears a strong similarity to that of Giere,
except that Giere emphasizes individuals and Fuller groups; elsewhere Fuller
14
Cussins (2000, 350-1) also reviews various arguments that there are inherent masculine
and feminine ways of doing science – say because notions of sexuality influence by
analogy perceptions of the world, or because women are inherently less likely to see nature
as a separate entity. The idea of a distinct feminine perspective has been attacked for
ignoring both personality and ethnic/class differences among women.
5. Classifying Practice 167
applauds Latour and others for stressing the role of scientific relationships
(see Galison, 1996).
A belief in science cannot depend on the virtues of individual scientists,
but must instead hang on the ability of communities of science to more often
than not choose good ideas over bad (Ziman, 2000, 160). Can group
processes overcome (some) individual-level biases? Recall that individual
scientists are influenced by biases, but are often able to rise above these
biases in order to achieve insights that challenge widely held beliefs and/or
offend the powerful. At the level of communities of scholars, if scientists
can be relied upon to take conflicting results seriously, and attempt to test
these against each other by exposure to real world evidence, it can be hoped
that any tendency toward overcoming biases in research will in the long run
be reflected in scientific understanding. That is, no matter how strong the
tendency toward bias, if there is some conflicting tendency, and if
contradictory results are evaluated seriously by the scientific community,
bias will be overcome in the long run. Note, though, the two big “ifs” in the
preceding sentence. As noted above, scientific evidence is never perfect, and
no scientific method infallible. Real world evidence may thus not always be
powerful enough to overwhelm bias. Social constructivists argue that
empirical evidence is often incapable of solving scientific disputes (Cole,
1992, 5). Collins and Pinch (1993) provide several examples for which they
claim that certain theories were accepted or rejected by a scientific
community despite ambiguous evidence. Moreover, the long run can be
very long, and in human science especially the world may have changed long
before scientists arrive at the correct interpretation of how it works. The
point to emphasize here is that the question of bias is essentially an empirical
question, not solvable by theoretical speculation alone, and one that has been
addressed to a very limited extent.
A naive view of science would hold that scientific debates are decided on
the basis of which side marshals the most persuasive evidence and logical
argument. To be sure, these are important; otherwise one could have little
confidence that science would lead to enhanced understanding. But humans
are not (entirely) rational calculating machines. Students of rhetoric show
that metaphor and story are important in making a compelling argument, and
that this is as true in science as in everyday life. Thus scientists buttress
their arguments with detailed (often hypothetical) examples, and strive to
show how the relationship they posit is similar to another already widely
accepted by the scientific community. McCloskey (1990) stresses the
advantages of this: it is harder for a scientist to tell a “big lie” if their
arguments are judged in terms of four criteria rather than two. To be sure,
scientists in evaluating the evidence and theoretical arguments of another
scientist can beneficially ask themselves if they can imagine compelling
168 Chapter 5
examples of the theory at work, and also whether the theory accords well
with other elements of their scientific view (schema) of the world. However,
a flashy story and facile analogy may too easily compensate for faulty logic
and limited or misleading evidence. The antidote, again, is the conscious
application of multiple methods to different types of data, and the clear
statement of how well the evidence accords with the theory. Being aware of
the rhetorical approaches that humans use and heed would also be helpful.15
Not surprisingly, some rhetoricians suggest that rhetoric trumps validity in
determining scientific outcomes (see Brown, 1992); Montgomery (1996)
explores language use in science, and recognizes its importance, but reaches
the Golden Mean conclusion that while rhetorical practices have an
influence, scientists can still aspire to considerable accuracy in their
description of the world.
In the case of social biases, much can be achieved by the entry of large
numbers of women and ethnic minorities into the world of science (though
some ethnic groups, notably Aboriginals, are still hugely underrepresented,
and so is the working class and especially the underclass). Scientific
communities can also benefit from an expanded understanding of cultural
processes, and especially the political element in these (see Szostak, 2003,
for a discussion of these linkages). Scientists can thus become more aware
of potential biases. More generally, Palys (1997, 399) stresses the
importance of not privileging any particular point of view; if scientists do so,
they will then place alternatives at an unfair disadvantage by judging these in
terms of the standards of their favored view. Scientists should strive for
mutual respect and understanding. But most centrally perhaps, scientists can
strive to ensure that the scientific enterprise is open and empirical: that it
takes conflicting views seriously, and subjects these to analysis through the
use of (generally more than one) scientific methods.
Disciplinary biases may be of even greater import than cultural, political,
or social biases. Moreover, disciplinary biases can reinforce the other types
of bias (see Szostak, 1999). Scientists face much greater pressure to accord
with disciplinary values than with wider societal values: their ability to be
hired, promoted, published, heard, and cited are all influenced by their
willingness to act in accord with disciplinary preferences with respect to
theory, method, data, and phenomena of study. Those who insist on using
unusual theories or methods, or examining unusual topics, may find
themselves ignored and even unemployed. It would be an unusual human
being who would be completely impervious to such pressures. Scientific
curiosity may drive research, but is itself shaped by the community in which
15
Halperin (1997, ch.3) warns scholars to beware of, and defend against, emotional
language, name-calling, vagueness, labelling, ambiguity, arguments from etymology,
reification, bureaucratese, misuse of definitions, euphemisms, and misuse of analogy.
5. Classifying Practice 169
2.2 What?
16
Ziman (2000, 12) argues that scholars should not aspire to a simple definition of science,
precisely because science is inherently multidimensional and diverse. But that should not
stop us from knowing what it is (Ziman refers to science as a natural kind).
170 Chapter 5
17
Postmodernists often note that regular people have “theories” too (Seale, 1999); these are
often poorly specified and almost never tested with a scientific method. Early in this
century positivists strove to define science in terms of falsifiability – philosophy and
astrology could be viewed as non-science if they could not identify empirical tests that
could falsify their arguments. As philosophers came to appreciate that no statement could
be proven false empirically, this definition collapsed. Many philosophers, including
Feyerabend, Foucault, and Derrida, thus concluded that there was no such thing as science.
18
Is science rational? We could ask, first, if its means further its goals (of enhanced
understanding). Or we could ask if it pursues a method(s) such that its theories are tested
in the real world, for it is inherently rational to support beliefs with evidence. Lambert and
Brittan (1992) conclude that science cannot be distinguished in either way from non-
science in terms of rationality. This suggests the value of a procedural distinction.
5. Classifying Practice 171
asking the 5W questions of any problem, and not arbitrarily limiting the
range of phenomena, theory, and method to be studied.
Philosophers have uncovered no simple definition of science that serves
to include what is generally thought of as science and exclude that which is
not. The definition above, derived as it is from observations of scientific
practice, serves this goal very well. Note that the inclusion of mathematical
modelling among methods allows some elements of mathematics to qualify
as science: this discipline is often a challenge for those who would define
science. However, while some applied mathematics is thus science, much
mathematical theory is not scientific but philosophical (see chapter 3); as
with philosophy more generally this sort of analysis can provide important
inputs into science, but is not itself science. By including experience and
intuition among methods, the study of art is also included within science.
Philosophers have long attempted to define science in terms of “the
scientific method” rather than twelve scientific methods. The identification
of diverse but equally valid scientific methods suggests that this must always
have been a difficult enterprise. Gower (1997, preface, 7) suggests that
“People do not now believe in scientific method” and thus they doubt that
philosophy has much to say about science. Hopefully the classification of
method solves this particular philosophical muddle. Can some commonality
across all these methods be identified that might serve as a more precise
definition of science? It might be posited that all reflect a desire to confront
scientific theories with evidence from the real world. But does intuition
really engage the real world? While the general principle of confronting
reality is important, a Wittgensteinian conclusion seems warranted: the list of
a dozen methods is more concrete than any brief statement of overarching
principle could aspire to be.
While no phenomenon lies outside the purview of science, good science
requires the careful specification of the phenomena involved in any research
project. Too much research in human science either does not identify which
phenomena or links are being studied, or does so only in terms of vaguely
defined terms (such as culture, which is defined in hundreds of different
ways). Since the list of phenomena of interest to human scientists is both of
manageable length and susceptible to hierarchical organization, there is no
valid reason for such sloppiness. In chapter 2 it was argued that scientific
concepts should either be carefully specified in terms of phenomena, theory,
or method, or jettisoned from the scientific lexicon. Research that involves
well-specified theory and at least one scientific method, but fails to carefully
identify the phenomena or causal links under investigation, must be viewed
as either non-science or bad science.
As noted in chapter 2, scientists can usefully identify patterns in the data
for which they have no theoretical justification. As long as these patterns are
5. Classifying Practice 173
not just imagined, but result from the proper use of scientific methods, and
are inputs into the process of developing theory, they are part of science.
Scientists should be careful in their use of such regularities until they
understand why these occur.
Early in the last century, many scholars tried to establish the “unity of
science” (see Neurath et al., 1970). Positivists often imagined a unity of
science grounded in method (Potter, 2000, 69), though they tended to an
unnecessarily narrow view of acceptable scientific methods. The idea is no
longer popular (Lenoir and Gombrecht, 1996). It is now appreciated that
there are huge differences in theory and method across disciplines (Fuller,
1997, 13-14). Ian Hacking has argued that scholars of science should
emphasize harmony rather than singularity: science involves quite different
types of endeavor, but these are interconnected (Galison, 1996). The
definition of science developed above, and indeed the entire approach of this
book, is consonant with such a view of science. It was argued in chapter 2
that causal links exist between most pairs of phenomena; science is thus a
huge complex enterprise that should strive for a mutually consistent
understanding of every link. In doing so, scientists should be open to the full
range of theory and method, and wary of every possible type of bias.
Scholars of science have long been curious about “boundary work”: when
individuals operate between different types of intellectual enterprise.
Necessarily, such boundaries must be identified before boundary work can
be analysed. Much of this book has served to identify boundaries between
different types of science. Here a way of defining the most central boundary
of all, between science and non-science, has been developed.
Pseudosciences such as astrology might be excluded from this definition of
science on two grounds: astrologers do not in general specify causal agents
or relationships very well, nor do they test their conjectures against reality in
terms of any of the dozen methods. Astrologers may make a case that they
rely on intuition or experience, but it was argued in chapter 4 that relying on
these exclusively is bad scientific practice: the scientist must strive to ensure
that their intuition is not biased. That is, the very method of intuitive
analysis requires that scientists analyse their intuition, not just blindly accept
it. Astrologers that can point to a carefully articulated theory and the careful
use of at least one method other than intuition, could be deemed scientific:
again the purpose here was not to exclude certain groups a priori but to
establish objective principles by which to judge how scientific an enterprise
is. Everyday experience is also excluded from the definition of science
because it is rarely formulated in detailed theoretical terms, and rarely
verified by other methods. As Fuller (1997, 25-30) notes, some definitions
of science have suggested that science could be performed by anyone; the
definition here suggests that people in their daily lives could, but generally
174 Chapter 5
19
I thank Barry Blesser for drawing this issue to my attention.
5. Classifying Practice 175
would have been difficult to rectify the shortcoming, the research may have a
place within the scientific enterprise.
This definition of science not only provides a response to those who
doubt the existence of science, but also to those who would define it so
narrowly as to exclude much university research. Philosophers and scientists
through the ages have spent a great deal of time arguing for the priority of
certain phenomena, types of agency, theories, and methods, and often for the
complete exclusion of others from the domain of science (just as
philosophers have generally done with respect to ethical theory; Szostak,
2004). A simple answer can be provided to questions of which phenomena,
theories, and methods qualify as scientific: all of them. Every theory that
answers the 5W questions qualifies. Every one of the methods listed in
chapter 4 qualifies. And every phenomenon deserves scientific attention.
The various classifications developed in this book have shown that all
deserve a place in science.
Much of the criticism of science comes from humanists. It is perhaps no
coincidence that natural scientists often exclude the humanities from their
view of science. This both reflects and encourages humanist suspicions. Yet
the classifications developed in previous chapters suggest that the subject
matter (art, various aspects of culture), methods (primarily textual analysis,
but also intuitive appreciation), and theories of the humanities deserve a
place in science (though some sorts of philosophy, as noted above, likely
deserve special treatment). This analysis supports Ziman’s (2000, 26)
suggestion that the portrayal of humanists and scientists as two distinct
cultures is – or at least should be – hugely overdrawn.
The defining characteristics of the humanities have changed over time. In
the nineteenth century, the humanities were commonly distinguished from
objective science in terms of their emphasis on the meaning and purpose of
phenomena. As was argued in chapter 3 with respect to interpretivism, this
perspective should be incorporated into the scientific enterprise. Early in the
last century, humanists often stressed the idiographic nature of their analysis;
again this hardly renders them unscientific (and note that humanists often
draw broader lessons from their idiographic research). Texts have always
been important: “The humanities might almost be said traditionally to have
been elaborate exercises in various kinds of reading and writing … ”
(Kervin, 1997, 9). Some have nevertheless emphasized the intuitive
perception of images and ideas. Both methods are important far beyond the
humanities. The point to emphasize here is that both the favored method and
subject matter of the humanities are suitably scientific. A minority would
define the humanities in terms of a holistic approach to everyday life; it has
been seen that science requires a synthesis of specialized knowledge and can
thus encourage greater interaction between humanists and other scientists.
176 Chapter 5
2.3 Why?
Why does the scientist do what they are doing? The question can be
asked on two levels. The first deals with the goals of humans in general.
Why do people do anything? How do individuals judge whether any
behavior is good? Do individuals judge an act’s goodness in terms of their
own selfish desires, or do they take into account the concerns of others? And
by what standards would they judge in either case? This important set of
(philosophical) questions will be deferred until later in this chapter, when the
five broad types of ethical analysis will be discussed.
20
As was seen in chapter 3, human science is also somewhat less able to establish precise
causal relationships, due to the nature of individual thought processes. This point is often
emphasized by philosophers of human science (see Fox, 1997, 126). Nevertheless, “the
obstacles to a science of society are ordinary practical obstacles that can be and sometimes
are overcome” (Kincaid, 1996, 2).
5. Classifying Practice 177
Why do scientists do the sort of research that they do? Scientists are
guided by both the selfless desire to enhance human understanding and the
more selfish desire to have a successful career as a scientist. Valiela (2001,
268-72) suggests that scientists may pursue excitement, self-promotion, a
sense of duty, or profit. Ziman (2000, 158) refers to a principle of
disinterested scientific investigation such that scientists are guided by a
search for truth rather than personal gain; since scientists are human it is
doubtful that this principle is ever perfectly achieved. Hull (1989), though,
suggests that selfishness serves science well. Scientists’ inherent curiosity
and competitiveness drives them to make important discoveries. Their
concern with reputation guides them to identify errors in the works of others,
while limiting these in their own work. In science the penalties for outright
deception may be large enough to keep its incidence small (but growing?).
There does seem to be a strong predisposition toward honesty among
scientists. The fact that scientific works are made available to all causes
scientists to be wary of being fraudulent (Rota and Crants, 2000, 475). This
does not prevent scientists from exaggerating the strength of their argument,
or from ignoring contradictory evidence, but does guide them away from
outright lies. However, scientists driven by a desire to aid humanity, and
inclined to cooperate, may serve science better. If the institutions of science
do not flawlessly channel selfish behavior toward beneficial acts, there is
scope for encouragement of ethical behavior.
It is a simple fact of scientific life that the most brilliant of insights are of
no social benefit if they are not published or read or cited by others. They
may as well not have happened. Thus even a selfless scientist willing to
sacrifice career ambitions must pay heed to the standards by which research
is judged in their discipline or field. One of these standards has been
mentioned above: the tendency of each discipline to favor certain
phenomena, data, theories, and methods. No message emerges more clearly
from the classifications developed in this book than that each theory and
method has strengths and weaknesses, and thus that there are always
advantages to theoretical and methodological flexibility. Disciplinary
preferences must then place arbitrary limits on scientific investigation, and
this must slow the rate of advance in scientific understanding. The problem
is admittedly much smaller in those natural science disciplines that can lean
heavily on the experimental method, but exists even there. Against the
obvious cost of these arbitrary limitations, defenders of disciplines would
point to a huge benefit in terms of the maintenance of scientific standards.
By approving only statistical analysis and mathematical modelling,
economists thus ensure that they are capable of judging each other’s works.
To allow different methods would diminish their ability to judge. It is
doubtful that the benefits outweigh the costs (Szostak, 1999). But more
178 Chapter 5
21
Glassick et al. (1997, 19) discuss how legal developments and a tightening job market
encouraged universities to develop more formal evaluation procedures in the 1970s, at a
time when research was gaining prominence relative to teaching and service. While
resulting standards likely reduced the incidence of discrimination, they encouraged an
emphasis on that which could be quantified. This meant that teaching was either ignored
or treated only in terms of student questionnaires. As for service, “virtually no institution
has yet figured out how to quantify such work” (1997, 20).
5. Classifying Practice 179
22
Economic theory would guide scholarly communities to aim for a world in which the
marginal benefit gained from the last minute expended by a scientific community on each
method is equalized (assuming, as seems likely, that the marginal benefit falls as the
method is used more and more). Economists do not apply this analysis to their own
discipline – in part because these benefits are hard to measure.
180 Chapter 5
23
Lisl Klein and Eason (1991, xii) make a similar point about applying social science in
industry: “One way of looking at and summarizing this situation is to say that in the social
sciences the ‘Development’ part of the ‘Research and Development’ continuum has been
substantially neglected and there is a serious gap between the world of research and the
world of practice.” Theories are often found to be inappropriate or too general when
applied to a specific circumstance..
24
Scientists should, though, not view public policy as a playground for developing theory.
Nor should they disdain the insights of those public policy is supposed to serve. Herda
(1999, 12, 20), echoing the discussion of action research in chapter 4, urges a cooperative
enterprise in which scientists help citizens develop solutions to their problems.
5. Classifying Practice 181
2.4 Where?
Where does the scientist do science? The spatial location of the actual
research project was explored in the discussion of method in chapter 4. Here
the concern is with the institutional location of the scientist. Where does the
scientist exist institutionally? And how does this affect the quantity and
quality of scientific work? Scholars know very little about how differences
in institutions and cultures of science affect rates of scientific advance (Cole,
1992, 227). A necessary first step is to identify possible influences.
In the modern world, academic science is the basic form of science
(Ziman, 2000). This has the important benefit that science is largely
pursued, at least officially, in the public interest. Scientists intend for their
research to be freely available to all, and indeed to be revised by others.25
Universities receive much of their (especially research) funding from the
public, and seek to hire and reward professors who advance scientific
understanding. The results of university research are generally introduced
quickly into the public domain, rather than being kept secret for private
profit. Ziman is justifiably concerned that private funding of university
research is increasing in relative importance, and that this not only interferes
with the scientific pursuit of the problems of the greatest public interest but
that it also encourages secrecy. The very fact of this common complaint
serves as a symbol of the advantages of public research.
To be sure, it has already been seen that various subconscious biases
divert scientists from fully exploiting the potential for selflessly advancing
scientific understanding. And the tendency of most universities to evaluate
professors in terms of quantity of output rather than quality or impact serves
only to reinforce these potential biases. Other elements of the institutional
structure create additional problems. The reliance on individual professorial
curiosity has huge advantages, but there should be a greater place for large
coordinated research efforts: these could harness the efforts of those who
publish little while answering important questions that do not lend
themselves to individualized research.
Not surprisingly, philosophers debate the need for disciplines, and
whether disciplines tend to make good decisions (Fuller, 1993, 49-54).
Since scholars within a discipline emphasize what that discipline thinks
important, and tend to ignore what other disciplines think is important
25
In addition to being disinterested in rewards and desiring to share their discoveries with all,
Merton (1973) suggested two other scientific norms: universalism, whereby scientists do
not judge an idea by who voices it (he emphasized a distaste for ethnic discrimination), and
skepticism. Many scholars have suggested that Merton exaggerated the degree of
adherence to these values. The emerging field og value epistemology explores how
scholars should behave.
5. Classifying Practice 183
26
Valiela (2001, 139) reports that those at more prestigious institutions are more likely to
reject articles written by those at less prestigious institutions. Cole (1992) notes, though,
that biases in judging grant proposals due to either gender or affiliation are slight. He
suggests that the bias operates in terms of ideas; elite scientists can determine which ideas
are approved. Haack (1998, 13) notes that in science, unlike in trials, the jurors have a
184 Chapter 5
vested interest in the outcome. Collins (1998) does not discuss in detail the factors that
determine elite status, but recognizes more than once that chance plays a role.
5. Classifying Practice 185
2.5 When?
27
Stocklmayer et al. (2001) suggest that there are five reasons to communicate science to the
public: the economic (because science is intellectual property, whether public or private),
the utilitarian (because science is useful to know), the democratic (because citizens must
make decisions about, say, global warming), the cultural (because there is something
beautiful about science at its best), and the social (because if the public trusts and embraces
science this will enhance social cohesion).
28
Science has only become exclusive in the modern era: only scientists make contributions to
scientific journals. Yet scientists, unlike other public authorities, are not required to justify
their special status (Fuller, 1997, 36).
5. Classifying Practice 187
29
Some critics of science have treated Kuhnian paradigms as simply social constructs. But
Gower (1997, 245-6) notes that paradigms are by their nature an attempt to grapple with
reality, and thus necessarily influenced by reality. He notes that Kuhn himself was quite
hostile to the relativist viewpoint of such critics. He certainly did not see paradigms as an
entirely arbitrary construction.
188 Chapter 5
by another that seems to have the potential for better explanation, then
opportunities for better explanation through recourse to a wider set of theory
will be eschewed even during times of revolution. In other words, scholarly
advance in at least some fields depends on overcoming the ideal of the
paradigm, which pretends that one or a handful of related and highly
generalizable theories can explain all that needs to be explained.
Previous sections have respectively explored, albeit briefly, the analogies
that could be drawn to the answers to the 5W questions in chapter 3: the
three types of intentional agent, attitudes and actions, the five types of
decision-making, and idiographic versus nomothetic outlooks. What can be
said here about time-path? The behavior of particular scientists will be
conditioned by whether their field is static, moving smoothly between
equilibria (making new discoveries, and incorporating these smoothly into
the corpus of theory), moving in a particular direction, or behaving in an
unpredictable manner. These four scientific time paths create different
opportunities, incentives, and constraints. The analysis of Whitley (2000),
discussed above, touches on some of these issues.
In asking ‘when?’ it is important to look not only at the state of science
itself but at the broader society. Scientists are human, after all, and can
hardly be immune to the cultural influences (and time path of societal
evolution) that affect others. Feuer (1995) describes how oscillations
between optimism and pessimism in the wider society have over the last
couple of centuries influenced the way scientists viewed the world. Krieger
(1997, ix) describes physics as a subculture whose theories reflect the
autonomy, alienation, and exchange that characterize the wider society.
Szostak (1999) discussed various cultural influences on the evolution of
economic theory and method in the twentieth century: economists developed
theories (and supportive methods) that provided comforting answers to a
range of cultural concerns. This does not mean that all of that theorizing and
empirical work was misguided; it does suggest that the scientific community
may have embraced certain results and procedures for reasons beyond their
scientific merits. It is thus a useful exercise for scientists to ask what cultural
biases might influence their evaluation of scientific research, and how the
theories and methods of their field may reflect past cultural pressures. In
addition to cultural influences, it should be noted that the institutions
discussed in the previous section also evolve over time (Stump, 1996, 450).
Cole (1992, xii, 30) suggests that societal factors are important on the
frontiers of science, but that core theories tend to reflect reality. He argues, in
effect, that for a theory to be accepted by an entire scientific community it
5. Classifying Practice 191
2.6 How?
30
Collins and Pinch (1993, 143) make a similar argument about “sciences”: the same degree
of certainty should not be expected in a new science as has (seemingly) been achieved in
physics.
31
In some cases, frontier work is quickly accepted by the scientific community. Cole (231)
suggests that this happens when the evidence is very strong or when the contribution both
answers and creates important questions within the research trajectory. Alternatively,
“Most new scientific contributions never have a chance to enter the core because they fail
to meet the latter criterion [of being important]” (1992, 15).
192 Chapter 5
At the start of this chapter, a brief list of some of the more common
questions asked of scientific practice was provided. This list in turn reflected
a reading of a variety of works on the practice of science. While there is no
pretence that the list was exhaustive, it is still worthy of note that each of
these questions was addressed as the 5W questions were answered. In some
cases it was possible to go some way toward answering these; in others it
was only possible to clarify questions for empirical investigation. These 5W
questions do seem, then, to once again provide a categorization that is both
exhaustive and convenient.
In chapter 3, it was argued that all scientific theories should provide clear
answers to each of the 5W questions. A somewhat less strong argument can
be made here: the enterprises of history, philosophy, and social study of
science must grapple with each of the 5W questions, but not every research
project within these enterprises must do so. Even at the level of individual
research projects, researchers should at least be aware of the other possible
critiques, lest they ignore evidence of these at work.
Any comprehensive attempt to comprehend any particular innovative
process, whether individual or collective, should ask how the perceptual
limitations of all humans affected the process, how the personal
idiosyncrasies of the researcher(s) involved influenced research agendas, and
what the social influences on researchers were. How strong was the
evidence in favor of the theory(ies) that emerged from the innovative
process? (That is, how well did reality overwhelm these various biases?)
What rhetorical devices did researchers utilize to convince the broader
community? What incentives did researchers face (specialization, emphasis
on quantity of publications, profit, and so on), and how did these affect their
behavior? What institutional constraints did they operate under, and how
might these have constrained their inquiries? Did disciplinary boundaries
limit the investigation? Did the research enterprise benefit from interaction
with those working in technology or public policy? How did this research fit
within the broader history of science (what assumptions and preferences and
questions did the researchers start from)? In particular what paradigms did
scientists operate within or supersede? Did they accept the theories and
methods favored by others pursuing similar questions, or not? How did the
training of researchers (mis-) prepare them? What role did serendipity play?
And finally what type of science did the researchers do – what theories,
methods, and causal links did they engage – and how might a broader
perspective have changed the results?
5. Classifying Practice 193
The last question, and many of the others, will be difficult to answer
unless one can refer to other actual research agendas. That is, it is always
hard to know what has been lost due to any bias or constraint unless one can
point to other groups of scientists who operated in a different manner. The
classifications of earlier chapters at least allow room for some educated
speculation. If a research enterprise eschewed certain sorts of theories or
methods, scholars can know what the strengths of these are and can guess as
to the insights they might have provided.32 In this way, research in the study
of science might encourage research in the neglected directions. This in turn
should both advance the cause of scientific discovery while also testing the
accuracy of the original speculation.
The 5W questions were somewhat less mutually exclusive here than was
the case in chapter 3. Overlap is clearest with respect to the ‘Why?’ and
‘Where?’ questions, for the incentives faced by scholars largely reflect the
institutional environment in which they operate. As noted in chapter 1,
overlapping classes are a common problem in classification. Despite some
overlap, it has nevertheless been possible to identify distinct subsidiary
questions under each heading.
The 5W questions have also not so clearly guided an exhaustive
classification of possible critiques as they did of possible types of theory. Yet
the classifications of earlier chapters are quite useful in this regard. With
respect to ‘who’ recourse to the three types of intentional agency, and then
the use of Table 2.1 to identify all possible types of both individual bias and
societal influence, promises a fairly exhaustive classification. With respect
to ‘why’ the five types of decision-making are a valuable guide. With
respect to ‘when’ the investigation of different time paths may prove a good
way of evaluating the historical circumstances of any field of inquiry at a
point in time. Finally, with respect to ‘where’ considerations of
generalizability lead to an appreciation of the necessity of both specialized
and interdisciplinary research.
32
Szostak (2005) argues that economists, in studying the Great Depression, have relied on
only one type of theory. Ten turning points in the historiography of the Great Depression
are described, and it is shown that at each point alternative theories provided potential
solutions to puzzles thrown up by the dominant macroeconomic approach. The emphasis
by economists on mathematical models and regressions has encouraged them to ignore the
clear evidence that the timepath of technological innovation was highly unusual in the
interwar period. Technological explanations of the Depression can be viewed as
complementary to macroeconomic explanations, but require a much greater openness to
disequilibrium processes and one-off events (and interdisciplinary causal linkages).
194 Chapter 5
One of the moments of epiphany that the author enjoyed while writing
this book occurred when discussing decision-making processes in chapter 3.
In striving to outline the various ways in which an individual might make
any decision, it was realized that there were precisely five types of decision-
making process. These five types of decision-making process were, in turn,
identical to the five types of ethical analysis identified in Szostak (2002b,
2004); these five types of decision-making could thus be justified both
deductively and as inductively. At first surprising, this result now seems
obvious: in making ethical evaluations individuals are making decisions, and
thus it follows that each broad type of ethical analysis accords with a
particular decision-making process. This one-to-one correspondence has a
particular appeal, for the list of decision-making processes had been derived
in a fairly deductive manner (at least until it became clear that the two lists
were similar), but the list of types of ethical analysis inductively: by reading
widely in philosophy and attempting to classify. As noted in chapter 3 there
has been scholarly discussion of each type of decision-making, but of no
other type of decision-making. With respect to ethical analysis, philosophers
tend to emphasize the three “formal” types of ethical analysis:
consequentialism (where an act’s goodness is judged in terms of whether its
consequences are good), deontology (interpreted here as implying a reliance
on rules, and thus embracing, for example, the Golden Rule, Kantian
categorical imperative, and arguments from rights), and virtues (where
individuals are urged to live in accord with one or more virtues, such as
honesty; see Baron, Pettit, and Slote, 1997). In addition, individuals should
be aware of the frequent use of both intuition and tradition in everyday lives.
Examples of philosophers lauding these as bases for ethical behavior can be
found across all philosophical traditions. It proved straightforward to place
various philosophical arguments within one of the five broad types, with the
singular exception of the eclectic philosophy of existentialism, which urges
individuals to choose their own path (that is, “decision-making process”;
Szostak, 2004). There is thus good and varied evidence to support the belief
that these five types of decision-making process are mutually exclusive and
exhaustive. Notably, this discussion provides a powerful example of one
role for interdisciplinary analysis: only when one scholar casts their gaze
upon quite different questions can such convergence in understanding occur.
The fact that there are precisely five ways to make decisions raises the
question of whether these flow from the 5W questions. The questions “Why
is an act ethical?”, “When is an act ethical?”, and “What is an ethical act?”
are too similar to distinguish among types of ethical analysis, though one
could imagine that the best answer to “Where is an act ethical?” involves an
5. Classifying Practice 195
one type of ethical analysis, they often have recourse to others. For example,
rights theorists refer variously to intuition, tradition, consequences, and
virtues (Almond, 1998). The five types of ethical analysis can be seen then
as equally valid and complementary. Recognition of this fact should guide
individuals to have greater understanding of those who reach different ethical
conclusions from their own. They can appreciate that ethical dilemmas
reflect disagreements among different ways of deciding what is right.33
While diversity can thus be embraced, individuals need not also embrace an
“anything goes” attitude. The selfish can be distinguished from those who
can provide reasoned justifications for their acts in terms of at least one type
of ethical analysis.
Moreover, individuals can strive where possible to act in ways that can be
justified in terms of all five types of ethical analysis. Such opportunities are
more common than is generally realized. Szostak (2004) evaluated some
150 ethical statements, each associated with a particular phenomenon from
Table 2.1. In roughly half of these cases all five types of ethical analysis
pointed in the same direction. To be sure, no ethical argument is
impregnable, and thus reasonable people could reasonably disagree with one
or more of these statements. This group of statements could nevertheless be
seen as an “ethical core” that people should not deviate from without reason,
though some may reasonably do precisely that from time to time.
Just as the classifications in previous chapters facilitate the exchange of
understanding across scientific fields, the identification of five independent,
complementary, and universally valid (since examples of each can be found
across diverse philosophical traditions) types of ethical analysis facilitates
the performance of a comprehensive and coherent ethical survey (Szostak,
2004). Since the five types of ethical analysis have applicability across all
phenomena, then they must necessarily apply to science in particular.
Scientists were urged above to emphasize the pursuit of understanding rather
than career goals.34 It can now be argued that such an attitude accords with
all five types of ethical analysis. In terms of consequences, the most obvious
counter-argument would be that scientific advance need not have beneficial
societal consequences; some might wish that nuclear physics or certain sorts
33
Polkinghorne (1996, 124) appreciates that scientists cannot disregard ethical analysis. He
bemoans the fact that “the absence in contemporary society of an agreed moral basis for
decisions has reduced ethical debate to the strident assertion of individual opinions.” Just
as society needs to be able to judge conflicting scientific arguments, it needs a means of
evaluating conflicting ethical arguments.
34
Hammersley and Gomm (2000, 164-6) urge researchers to pursue the production of
knowledge above all other goals. They stress that exaggeration has no place in scientific
inquiry. Max Weber had argued that scientists must pursue “truth” wherever it leads, even
if results are unpalatable (Hammersley, 2000, 33).
5. Classifying Practice 197
of biotechnology had never been imagined. But the fact that society devotes
billions of dollars to science is evidence of a profound belief that science
does more good than harm. And a scientific community dedicated to the
public good might tip the balance even moreso in that direction. Eschewing
personal gain to pursue understanding for society’s sake is almost
transparently virtuous. As well, such behavior easily accords with such
ethical rules as the Golden Rule or Kant’s categorical imperative: if
individuals would want other scientists to behave in a socially responsible
fashion they should do so themselves. And most/all traditions celebrate
scientists who generate useful ideas, rather than those who successfully
achieve promotion (at least for the most part).
Finally, selfish careerism should make a scientist feel (intuitively) guilty.
Few scientists are likely self-consciously selfish. Many, though, are able to
rationalize careerist behavior, and thus minimize their guilt. A host of
excuses are possible: “Science is impossible”, “Everybody does it”, “I’ll
change once I get tenure/promoted/retire”, “I am obeying the incentives of
my field and trust others to ensure their consonance with the social good”, “It
does not matter what any one scientist does”. Hopefully this book will have
exposed at least some of these excuses as false. Science is indeed possible.
But it is all too easy to perform bad science. Each scientist has a
responsibility of self-reflection, in order to ensure that they are not being
guided by baser motives. Science could be more successful than it is if there
was greater recognition of the strengths and weaknesses of different types of
science. Scientists who act upon this potential not only advance science in
their own right, but set an example for others. In sum, this book serves to
align the intuition of scientists with the other four ethical guidelines, and thus
urges them toward a more selfless approach to scientific investigation.
It was noted at the outset of this chapter that its subject matter has often
been neglected by scholars of science. This is true even today of ethics:
while institutional changes are (laudably) forcing scientists to reflect on the
ethics of using intentional agents in research, and of accepting funding from
external bodies that expect a particular outcome, scientists rarely engage
more general ethical questions concerning scientific practice, and even
philosophers tend to skirt the issue. Philosophy of science engages
epistemological questions (what can we know?), not ethical questions (what
should we do?). Yet the answers to the sorts of question posed here are
straightforward, and thus a greater attention by scientists to ethics would
yield great dividends.
Human scientists have even shied away from ethical evaluation in their
research. That is, they not only neglect ethical analysis of themselves but of
others. Wolfe (1999) outlines – and debunks – several reasons for this state
of affairs. Scientists were hostile to tradition, feeling that it hindered
198 Chapter 5
1
Freidheim (1982, 5) notes how the use of quantitative methods guides researchers to
develop and apply theories that focus upon variables that can be quantified. Elsewhere,
she finds that paradigms (see below), or clusters of theory/method that guide large groups
of researchers, are most easily identified by method: this suggests that the methodological
preference of the group guides their theoretical choices. Freidheim hopes that these
paradigms will evolve to become focussed instead on certain sets of phenomena.
Emphasis on one method is ill-suited to such a transformation.
6. Drawing Connections Across these Classifications 201
2
Szostak (2003) suggested that the complementarity of theory in natural science could be
attributed to the fact that natural science disciplinary boundaries were more logical,
reflecting for the most part a division in terms of degree of aggregation. That analysis
provides a much more benign view.
202 Chapter 6
3
“An openness to new ideas, a willingness to try out unpopular techniques, and a spirit of
passionate searching after the unfamiliar, Feyerabend argues, contribute more to the
progress of science than commitment to cool reason and accepted methods” (Klee, 1999,
201). This book embraces the flexibility inherent in Feyerabend’s philosophy of science,
while avoiding his scepticism about the very existence of a separate realm called science.
6. Drawing Connections Across these Classifications 203
It was argued in the previous section that scientists should use multiple
methods with respect to any theory. A similar argument can be made with
respect to method and phenomena: multiple methods should be used in
analyzing any phenomenon or causal link.4 This is especially the case given
4
Potter (2000, 69) suggests that methods are specific to particular subject matter. While it is
true that the strengths and weaknesses of methods vary by subject matter, students of
science should be wary of casually dismissing methods in any investigation. Goldenberg
(1992) argues that a researcher should not know what variables are relevant at the outset of
an investigation, and thus cannot know which method is best (note that even he seems to
underestimate the advantages of multiple methods here).
204 Chapter 6
5
Ziman (2000, 127) maintains that natural scientists are increasingly moving away from an
emphasis on laws toward recognition of the context in which these operate.
6
Ragin (2000, ch.6) suggests analysis in terms of fuzzy sets such as “fully democratic”,
“mostly democratic”, and “not democratic.” Unpacking of phenomena (in this case state
decision-making systems) provides a better strategy. As well, Ragin argues that the length
of time a state has existed has important causal implications. But this is only important
because it affects various attitudes toward the state, the maturity of institutions, and other
phenomena: the best strategy is thus to examine the realizations of these phenomena.
206 Chapter 6
7
Philosophers are coming to appreciate that theories are much like maps: they represent a
more complex reality, are social institutions, are abstractions that classify and simplify, are
functional, and require skilled interpretation (Ziman, 2000, 126-7). While perhaps not
always possible, Ziman suggests that mapping theories is generally desirable.
8
Seale (1999, ch.7) hails grounded theory (which grounds theory in empirical observation)
for stressing the link between theory and empirical research; he argues that this should be
the hallmark of all good research. He urges theorists to provide real-world examples of
6. Drawing Connections Across these Classifications 207
their theoretical arguments. He notes, though, that grounded theory cannot help scientists
with unobservables.
208 Chapter 6
3. BETTER PARADIGMS
9
Seale (1999, 19, 30) appreciates that scientists dislike facing up to the uncertainties of
science. He urges them, however, to embrace fallibility, appreciate that there is no perfect
theory or method, and strive for a consciously self-critical research community.
10
Dogan and Pahre (1990, ch.3) suggest that small academic communities are more
productive than large. In part, this reflects the law of diminishing returns: as more
scientists enter a field the average contribution falls. Large groups often also become
focussed on jargon and theoretical hair-splitting. The authors could have noted the
countervailing advantages of largeness. If science advances through synthesis of ideas,
larger communities should generate more ideas to be combined. Of course,
interdisciplinary scholarship provides another source of combinations.
11
An example of this tendency is Silverman (2000, 99), who is sceptical of triangulation
because he feels that a scientific community needs to start from one theoretical perspective
and choose only methods and data that give structure and meaning within that perspective.
210 Chapter 6
12
The “wide reflective equilibrium” of Winkler and Coombs (1993) and “pancritical
rationalism” of Bartley (see Szostak, 1999) provide similar guidelines. Morton (1997), in
summing up the basics of the theory of knowledge, emphasizes human fallibility, and
urges individuals to assess the risk of a belief being wrong versus the risk of mistakenly
thinking it to be wrong.
212 Chapter 6
belief” approach provides the only solution to the problem of infinite regress
identified by Wittgenstein: if a scientist claims that the double helix of DNA
contains cytosine, they can be asked how they know; the response would
involve laboratory techniques for isolating and identifying components of
biological samples; questioning of these could be answered in terms of other
theories that implicate these techniques; and so on (see Moser et al., 1998,
ch.5). At some point, scientists must accept some statements as true, even
though these cannot be proven, or the scientific enterprise becomes
impossible (see Cussins, 2000, 336).13 The sort of flexible paradigms
suggested above accord much better with a “web of belief” approach than do
existing narrowly-defined paradigms.
Scientists should not err in the opposite direction and cast away theories
or methods at the first sign that they do not work. Science being a fallible
process, there may be problems with the evidence gathered rather than the
theory or method in question. Moreover, recall that scientists should be
striving to identify the range of applicability of both theories and methods.
A finding that a particular theory or method does not work in a particular
situation need not and should not imply that it is useless everywhere.14
In other words, scientists need to be more self-conscious and self-aware
about their paradigms. They need to remember that they are a convenience,
not a gift of God. They need to appreciate that all research requires a set of
assumptions, but that these in turn should not go unquestioned. They need to
appreciate the value to scholarly communication of shared assumptions, and
also the danger of these becoming articles of faith rather than questions for
further investigation. If scientists find paradigms to be psychologically
comforting, they need to force themselves from time to time to question
these. They should, in particular, investigate the possibility that a more
flexible paradigm would advance understanding more quickly. They should
be as explicit as possible about the core elements of their paradigm, and what
sorts of evidence would and should cause them to question it. And they
should gaze at alternative paradigms from time to time to see what they have
to offer.
13
Of course, the very statement that “science is possible” is itself unprovable. When
Feyerabend made this point, Lakatos responded that it was possible for scientists to
proceed on the assumption that science was possible, but be ready to critique this position
(see Motterlini, 1999, 13).
14
“Most new and contradictory ideas prove to be of little value;” it is better to reject some
good ideas than casually destroy consensus (Cole, 1992, 199). Many scientists likely share
this view, and there is obviously a kernel of truth to it. Given the danger that scientists
thus too readily dismiss novelty – it is all too easy to rationalize narrow-mindedness within
this perspective – it would be useful to seek to establish the empirical validity of this point
of view.
6. Drawing Connections Across these Classifications 213
Throughout this book, and especially in chapter 5, it has been argued that
science is imperfect yet possible. It is thus important that scientists know the
potential biases that can afflict scientific practice, in order to combat these.
While all scientists should be aware of all potential imperfections, particular
scientists likely need to be more aware of some than others. This section
explores whether the particular problems discussed in chapter 5 are of greater
importance with respect to certain phenomena, data, theories, or methods.
Since the typology of critiques is quite different from the other classifications
in this book, the analysis here must be more detailed than that in previous
sections of this chapter. Note that the very question of “how are certain
biases or errors distributed across different types of science?” has hardly
been asked heretofore. While many correlations seem obvious there is much
scope for further research:
We can proceed through the various biases and errors identified in
chapter 5, asking of each how they might be associated with different
phenomena, data, theories, and methods. The various human perceptual
limitations will afflict all of science. As noted in chapter 2, however, some
phenomena are more observable than others, and thus on average less subject
to perceptual difficulties.
As noted in chapter 4, some methods (such as PO) are inherently more
subjective than others (such as statistical analysis), though researcher biases
can affect the results from the application of any method. Awareness of
potential biases, and efforts at replication, are particularly though not
exclusively important when more subjective methods are used. It is likely
also true that some theories invite greater subjectivity than others:
psychoanalysis invites reflection on unseen mental processes, and
phenomenology is deliberately vague.
Researchers may be influenced by the social structure or power relations
of their society, and guided to results that support the status quo. This type
of bias will obviously only matter for research topics that have implications
for the status quo. Broadly speaking, human science is in greater danger here
than natural science. However, there are exceptions: scientists studying
either the environment or human genes will not be immune from such
influences. And history shows that even studies of the earthly orbit can
offend the powers that be.
A similar point can be made with respect to the possibility that scientists
will pursue answers that reflect their ethical predisposition. Such a bias is
likelier to operate in the study of intentional agents. However, as argued in
214 Chapter 6
method. While textual analysis and introspection may be the only access
scholars have to certain questions in this area, there is clearly scope for the
application of a wide range of methods to questions concerning the social,
cultural, or political causes and effects of changes in art, literature, or
philosophy. The prominence of experiments in natural science may also in
part reflect ease of use, though there are clearly other good reasons for this.
Scientific debates are not won anywhere by the facts alone: rhetoric is
everywhere important. Scholarly communities that exalt style over substance
are most likely to be swayed by rhetorical flair. Clarity of expression in
theorizing was urged in chapter 3: the assumptions – that is, realizations of
all relevant phenomena necessary for a result to hold – and causal
argument(s) should be clearly articulated. Even – perhaps especially –
assumptions taken for granted by a particular community should be stated.
Some scientific disciplines encourage clarity more than others. Scientists
must nevertheless everywhere be on guard for unstated assumptions. In
some areas, such as the analysis of how art moves individuals, there may be
great scope for rhetorical flair in the provision of supporting evidence, but
the theory itself should still be expressed clearly.
All sciences benefit from interaction with the real world. Natural
scientists benefit enormously from interaction with technologists. Much
interchange of this sort occurs, though there are concerns that certain
institutional arrangements limit the free flow of scientific understanding.
Human scientists, however, have more limited contact with policymakers,
and this likely limits the effectiveness of both social science and social
policy.
Research requires money. Those who fund research can thus introduce
biases into the sorts of questions investigated, and the answers found.
Governments in developed countries have – laudably – established arms-
length granting agencies to reduce this bias. Various government agencies,
private firms, and non-profit foundations also provide research funding.
These naturally fund endeavors that interest them. These need not be the
research questions that society as a whole would wish to see studied (though
in the case of government agencies, it could be hoped that they are indirectly
expressing the public will). Even more dangerous is the possibility that
funding agencies will make it clear that they will reward researchers who
find the right answers. This danger is perhaps most obvious in the case of
drug trials financed by drug companies. But the natural sciences more
generally are at greater risk than human science: research in natural science
tends to be more expensive, and is more likely to have implications for the
profitability of private firms. Finally, note that cost affects the type of
research performed: scientists with limited funds may not be able to pursue
the research strategies they think best; conversely as universities increasingly
216 Chapter 6
reward researchers for the amount of research funding they bring in,
researchers are given a perverse incentive to favor expensive research
projects.
Problems associated with the hierarchical nature of science are ubiquitous
(though Whitley, 2000, argues that fields differ in the type of hierarchy).
Scholarly specialization provides at best a partial solution, and carries its
own costs. All scholarly communities are wasteful (see Hull, 1989), and all
discourage certain sorts of innovation. A partial solution to this problem will
be suggested in the next chapter.
Paradigms are important in most disciplines. Some disciplines are viewed
as pre-paradigmatic: these may embrace an attractive array of theories and
methods, but at the cost of there being no core of ideas around which debate
can concentrate. For disciplines that have paradigms, the question to be
asked is whether the disciplinary preferences for theory, method, and subject
matter are strong, and if so to what degree they limit access to evidence that
would threaten the paradigm. This in turn will depend on many of the
questions asked above, especially that of how well suited a particular theory
or method is to a particular area of inquiry. Interdisciplinary scholars may
have a clear role to play in showing what a discipline loses by closely
adhering to a particular paradigm.
Finally, what is science? (this was the ‘what?’ question in chapter 5).
While different biases are of different relative importance for different
research questions, all of natural and human science deserves to be called
“science”. Four points should be emphasized here:
x No type of science is perfect.
x Some types of science are subject to fewer sources of error and bias than
others.
x No type of science is impossible. There are strategies for coping, albeit
imperfectly, with all biases. There are likely, nevertheless, limits to how
far understanding can progress.
x While natural science is less subject to most biases than human science,
this is far from always being the case.
These points have been made with respect to “types of science”. They
could be reworded such that they spoke instead of theory types, methods, or
phenomena.
Chapter 7
CLASSIFYING SCIENTIFIC DOCUMENTS
1
Marcella and Newton (1994,3) identify the purpose of classification with being able to find
things. While classifications have other uses, this use is undoubtedly of great import.
Journal articles rarely receive the classificatory treatment allocated to books, being judged
to be “component parts of larger documents” (Svenonius, 2000, 24); this severely limits
the ability of scholars to locate relevant research in other fields.
218 Chapter 7
generally say little about the ideas contained in a work. Researchers looking
for documents that contain applications of a particular theory or method, or
studies of a particular causal link, thus rely on bibliographies and
recommendations from other scholars, while realizing that they thus likely
miss important works relevant to their research interests. Weinberg (1988)
recognizes that the theory employed in a work is a key piece of information
rarely noted in subject catalogues. She also mentions method, and cites
favorably Swift et al. (1978), who had argued for classifying works with
respect to both theory and method (Palmer, 1996, also advocates
classification with respect to methods). Yet Weinberg makes no
recommendations for change, feeling that any effort to classify documents by
theory and method would necessarily be too complicated.2
Weinberg details some of the costs she had incurred in her own research
due to deficiencies in subject catalogues. It took her much longer to track
down ideas that she had encountered elsewhere, though she could not
remember exactly where; sometimes, this would prove impossible, and
incomplete citation would result. She could not be entirely sure that a
particular idea she was writing about had not been treated previously. If she
could find some works on similar topics, by asking colleagues for
suggestions, she could not be confident that she was not missing important
works, particularly if these appeared in different fields.
Limitations in systems of document classification do not just hinder the
individual researcher, but hobble the scientific enterprise. “Progress [in
scientific understanding] depends on cumulative scholarship, which in turn
depends on scholars’ ability to access all that has been created by the human
intellect” (Svenonius, 2000, 29). Researchers frequently “re-invent the
wheel” by duplicating research that they were unaware of. The loss of
valuable research, which is not retrieved because it is not classified in terms
of its novel elements, is a significant cost. Moreover, science advances by
carefully establishing the range of applicability of its theories and methods.
If classification systems make it difficult to retrieve and thus compare works
that apply a particular theory or method to quite different questions, then this
key form of scientific progress is rendered exceedingly difficult. Finally, the
scientific community is often accused of amassing many bits of information,
but making little attempt to tie these together. While scientific incentives,
which favor new research over integrative research, are partly to blame for
this state of affairs (see Glassick et al., 1997), difficulties in searching for
relevant literature are also at fault. “As research and knowledge become
2
Weinberg notes that full-text searching is often of limited utility in searching for theories,
as theoretical ideas can often be paraphrased in numerous ways. As full text searching
becomes increasingly possible, a common vocabulary of theory, method, and phenomena
becomes increasingly valuable.
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 219
1. FACETED OR ENUMERATIVE?
3
Call numbers also contain author and/or title specific notation to distinguish works that
would otherwise receive the same call number, and also generally note edition and year of
publication. While the concern of this chapter is with classifying works so that subject
catalogues are more useful, the addition of new dimensions of classification will reduce the
size of classes and thus the need of cataloguers to distinguish works by author or title .
220 Chapter 7
such a list. Searches by phenomenon will thus uncover all relevant works
regardless of discipline. Moreover, each phenomenon has a precise
definition. Culture, for example, comprises the hundred or so subsidiary
phenomena listed, and no other phenomena. Scientists are often frustratingly
vague or contradictory in defining terms. See, for example, the hundreds of
definitions of “culture” or “religion” encountered in Szostak (2003). The
hierarchical list of phenomena would encourage greater clarity, and thus ease
the task of classification. It is noteworthy in this regard that one task that
interdisciplinary researchers want information scientists to perform is the
translation of jargon across disciplinary boundaries (Palmer, 2001, 131).
While information scientists commonly compile thesauri to this end, it would
be even better to strive for common usage of key terms.
As scientific understanding advances phenomena once viewed as similar
may be found to be different in important ways, and vice versa (Hjorland,
1994). It is thus advisable that documents be defined in terms of phenomena
defined functionally (that is, in terms of the role they play), so that
classification systems not need continual revision. This is, of course, the
guiding principle pursued in chapter 2. Ironically, Hjorland goes on to argue
that since different disciplines treat the same phenomenon from different
perspectives, it is best to classify documents by discipline. If documents are
classified by phenomena, however, these differences can be readily
compared and contrasted, rather than pursued in isolation.
A simple notational scheme whereby causal links are denoted by the first
letter of the category name was employed in Szostak (2001) and (2003): a
link wherein some cultural phenomenon influences some element of social
structure is thus denoted by an arrow from ‘C’ to ‘S’. A more complex
system would be needed for document classification, in which either letter or
number codes were attached to second and third level phenomena: a
particular occupation might be designated SO97, where O stands for
occupation, and 97 represents the place of the particular occupation on some
list of occupations. Note that notation serves to indicate where in the
hierarchical structure of phenomena a work fits; Marcella and Newton (1994,
48-54) urge notations that reflect hierarchy. The use as notation of the first
letter of categories, and where possible phenomena lower in the hierarchy,
also makes the classification evocative and thus facilitates recall.
As noted with respect to occupations, the list of phenomena in Table 2.1
would have to be fleshed out by developing lengthy lists of subsidiary
phenomena. Fortunately, lengthy lists of such phenomena already exist
within existing classification schemes. The classification of phenomena
would simply determine where such elements fit.
While existing document classification schemes could be drawn upon in
fleshing out lists of phenomena, the result would nevertheless be much less
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 223
complicated than these. One benefit has already been discussed: there will
no longer be multiple entries for a single phenomenon. Existing schemes
also presently treat many causal links between phenomena as subjects. By
listing hundreds of phenomena, and providing appropriate notation for these,
it becomes possible to identify thousands of causal links by joining the
notation of appropriate phenomena. For example an arrow from IPE to SO97
could indicate how the personality dimension of extroversion-introversion
(within the category of Individual Differences) affects performance within a
particular occupation. Note that in so doing a technique from faceted
schemes (linked notation) is borrowed and applied to an enumerative
scheme. Marcella and Newton (1994, 60) applaud systems that allow “the
expression of compound subjects via notational synthesis.” And Rowley
(1992, 240) argues that “... any tool for the organization of knowledge must
[among other things] take into account the relations between subjects.”
Most scientific research investigates how one or more phenomena exert an
influence on one or more others. Researchers interested in the link between
IPE and SO97 will want to be able to find all such works without necessarily
being overwhelmed by every scholarly reference to either IPE or SO97. The
proposed scheme allows the researcher to readily distinguish works focused
on the causal link from those describing one of the phenomena involved. In
other words, it identifies the subject matter of a work much more precisely
for the researcher than do existing schemes. Note that while existing
schemes often classify causal links as subjects, there is no notational signal
of the difference between a work that studies one phenomenon and a work
that investigates relationships among two or more phenomena. The system
proposed here clearly differentiates these quite different types of work.4
The proposed scheme would be grounded in a logical structure focused
upon the subjects scholars study. These, unlike disciplinary boundaries, do
not change, or at least not much: in human science all relevant phenomena
have likely been identified, while in natural science any new phenomena
discovered are generally components of long recognized phenomena (chapter
2). Thus, interdisciplinary fields such as biochemistry pose no problem for
classification: the information scientist simply asks what it is that
biochemists study and classifies their works accordingly. If an
interdisciplinary area asks how one phenomenon affects another it is
classified around that causal link.5
4
If works were also classified in terms of the data employed, researchers could readily
ascertain which data have been used to investigate which phenomena or causal links.
5
Since flexibility is hailed as one of the key advantages of faceted schemes (e.g. Rowley,
1992, 179), it is worth noting that this classification of phenomena allows the development
of a flexible enumerative scheme (see below).
224 Chapter 7
6
Experts refer to “literary warrant” to justify developing classifications around existing
works. Nevertheless, some 80% of books tend to fall within some 20% of existing classes
(Marcella and Newton, 1994,34).
7
Langridge (1992, 18) notes that scientists classify what they study, not what they produce.
This last task is performed by bibliographers, whose duty is not to produce knowledge but
“to organize the knowledge produced by specialists so that it may be available for
whosoever requires it”. The system outlined here would provide bibliographers with a
scientific basis from which to proceed.
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 225
8
Fiscella (1996) thus advocates the publication of interdisciplinary bibliographies. In some
areas of inquiry these do provide a very inclusive guide to the relevant literature. Yet these
are time-consuming to produce due to the problems with classification systems noted here.
Even these bibliographies may miss key works as a result. And huge numbers of
bibliographies (regularly updated) would be needed. Likewise, Palmer’s (2001) suggestion
that information scientists be included on interdisciplinary research teams is both more
costly and less effective, especially for individual researchers, than having more
comprehensive classification systems in the first place.
226 Chapter 7
9
Dogan and Pahre (1990, 151-2) warn researchers borrowing a theory from another field to
keep abreast of changes within that field, and note that researchers can cling to a theory
that has been rejected in its home field. They should at least know why this was the case.
228 Chapter 7
applying a method. Moreover, methods (and even moreso theory types) are
not classified in an exhaustive and coherent manner in any existing system of
classification. Researchers can be blissfully unaware of insights from the
application of a particular method to other phenomena. Scholarly efforts to
comprehend the strengths and weaknesses of methods are thus blunted.
As with theory, it would be useful to distinguish works about methods
from works applying methods. Again, the fact that works about method
would be classified under categories or generalia rather than particular
phenomena or causal links provides an imperfect solution to this problem.
With such a system of classification in place, a scholar interested in applying
a particular method to a particular phenomenon or causal link would be able
to quickly identify any work that had previously applied that method to that
phenomenon or link. If desirable, the researcher could readily expand the
search to embrace closely related or similar phenomena or causal links.
Alternatively it would be straightforward for the researcher to ascertain what
methods had been applied to the particular causal link in question. Likewise,
a researcher could easily ascertain what methods had been used to evaluate a
particular theory type, both in general and with respect to particular causal
links. A researcher with a more general interest in a method could instead
find out to what range of phenomena or causal links that method had been
applied. This alone would tell them something useful about the range of
applicability of the method (and they could learn more by studying the
difficulties encountered by researchers in these varied applications of the
method).10 The value of all of these types of search should be obvious. So
too should be the fact that they are presently impossible.
10
This is as true of classification as any other method. Bowker and Star (1999) note that
those classifying in different realms face similar problems but do not interact; the result is
“pluralistic ignorance.”
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 229
Having identified subject matter, theory type, and method, the proposed
scheme could then proceed to code for type of work (encyclopaedia etc.),
language, time period, and geographical area (as necessary) in a manner
similar to that of other classification schemes. [An additional notation will be
suggested for survey articles and meta-analyses below.] Classificatory
notation for different editions/versions of the same work could also be
considered (Smiraglia, 2001). The introduction of novel classifications of
theory and method above will of course further disperse documents covering
common times and places. But this is a small price to pay to allow scholars
and students to locate documents by theory and method. Marcella and
Newton (1994, 56-8) note the huge advantages of developing a common
coding for such characteristics as time and place (a practice that has been
followed to some extent by all large systems of classification); the proposed
scheme extends these advantages into the realm of theory and method.
230 Chapter 7
Some works are critiques of scientific practice. They point to what are
believed to be inherent limitations or biases in the scientific enterprise (see
chapter 5). While scientists are infamous for being unaware of a variety of
such critiques, many practising researchers will (or at least should) have
interest from time to time in particular types of such critique. Students and
the general public will also have an interest in pursuing certain critiques of
scientific practice.
Existing discipline-based systems of classification tend naturally to
disperse such critiques widely. Some will be housed with general works on
(natural) science. Some will be classified as sociology of knowledge. Some
will be treated as history of science. Some might be viewed as epistemology
or philosophy of science. And those that apply a particular critique to a
particular subject will likely be shelved with that subject. Interdisciplinary
scholars may carry certain critiques across disciplinary boundaries, but even
they will likely only be familiar with a subset of the applications of a
particular critique. This dispersal would not be so problematic if a common
classification of such critiques had been developed, so that the subject
catalogue could guide users to appropriate documents wherever these might
be housed. But, as with theory and method, such a common system has yet
to be employed.
Of course, a typology of such critiques was developed in chapter 5. As
with the typology of theory types, this provides a very useful mechanism for
classifying critique-based documents. However, as was noted in chapter 5,
each element in this typology represents a causal link toward the
phenomenon ‘science’. While general critiques might readily be classified in
terms of such causal links, some special coding would be necessary for
documents applying critiques to a particular theory, method, phenomenon, or
causal link. Such documents should be housed with the primary theory,
method, phenomenon, or link discussed, but these (and general critiques)
should be readily discovered by searches by critique. In all cases the coding
of scientific critiques would follow the other relevant notation. It might be
useful to put this notation in parentheses both to avoid confusion and to
signal that the work is a work of critique.11
At present, if a researcher becomes aware of a particular type of critique,
and wonders if it has been applied to their area of expertise, they have no
good means of proceeding. Those interested in pursuing critical analyses of
a particular field are likewise hobbled. Those with a vague unease about a
particular scientific theory or method cannot now easily check what sorts of
11
The Universal Decimal Classification attempts to classify some works according to “point
of view”. A theoretically derived typology of critical points of view is provided here.
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 231
8. CLASSIFYING PHILOSOPHY
12
One downside here is that main categories may not be ordered in terms of similarity: It
might be desirable for Culture and Social Structure to be adjacent, but C and S are
separated by E for Economy, P for Politics, and several others. While the Dewey system
has been criticized for separating Language (400) and Literature (800), there is a general
feeling that order within main classes is much more important than order across main
classes (Hunter, 1988, 76-7, Marcella and Newton, 1994, 35-6). There also seems to be a
sense that there are or should be some forty main classes; the proposed system, even with
the addition of natural science classes, would have perhaps half as many.
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 233
or method as notation, together suggest that this system could excel in terms
of expressiveness.
Information scientists devote considerable attention to the development of
thesauri, or guides to the terms used in a classification system. They thus
hope to aid users who might search under a synonym for a word used in the
particular classification system. One beauty of the proposed system is that
an overview can be provided in a handful of tables: of phenomena, methods,
theory types etc. Note that these classifications in turn can be derived from
the 5W questions asked in chapter 1. The organizing structure is transparent
enough that any user should be able to find what to search for without having
to guess what precise term to search under. Nevertheless, thesauri should
still be provided, especially with respect to individual theories and critiques
of scientific practice.
Rowley (1992) discusses two ratios by which the effectiveness of a
subject index can be judged. The first, the recall ratio, compares the number
of relevant documents retrieved relative to the number of relevant documents
in the system. The second (and easier to measure), the precision ratio,
compares the number of relevant documents retrieved with the total number
of documents retrieved. By identifying all of the phenomena, links, methods,
theories, and types of critique in a document, the proposed scheme should
aid recall enormously. Likewise, by avoiding ad hocery and a discipline
basis, while aiding recall, it should greatly enhance precision. Researchers
will be able to quickly identify a search that will produce all relevant
documents, regardless of whether these documents were produced within
diverse disciplines or by interdisciplinary scholars. Rowley proceeds to
considerations of the time and effort expended by the user, and ease of use.
Again, by coding in terms of what people wish to look for in a work, ease of
use should be greatly enhanced. Rowley closes by mentioning specificity,
exhaustivity, and degree of error. By basing the system in hopefully
exhaustive classifications, each of which has a specific place for each
element, the system should excel in these respects as well.
than getting too few, it should not be ignored. This problem will arise in any
large library; it will be overwhelming in the emerging set of Internet web
sites which attempt to gather all published work in some area of study (and
even more so in some likely future web site(s) which attempt universal
coverage).13 Note that some 100,000 scholarly papers and 30,000 books or
book chapters are produced annually in the United States alone.
This problem of information overload can only be solved by scholarly
efforts to summarize research. These take two forms. Survey articles
summarize scholarly research on particular phenomena, links, theories, or
(less often) methods. Meta-analyses (chapter 4) look at similar types of
research, such as experiments involving a similar treatment, and attempt to
discern why results may have differed. At present, both types of research are
less valued within the academy than original research. The result is a huge
mass of research with only sporadic and incomplete efforts to synthesize it.
Yet a good survey article spares later scholars from a very difficult
information gathering process (Palmer, 2001; she particularly advocates on-
line surveys with links to works cited). Palmer (1996, 184) suggests that the
main implication of her examination of interdisciplinary research practices is
the key importance of general works such as survey articles, textbooks, and
generalist journals. Willinsky (1999, 165-7) argues that it would be sensible
to devote some fraction of government research funding to such studies.
Palmer (2001) feels that information scientists should participate in the
writing of survey articles, partly because they face greater professional
incentives to do so, but mostly because they will ensure a greater breadth of
coverage. The proposed classification system, especially once adopted by
websites or libraries with reasonably exhaustive collections, could solve the
problem of imperfect coverage: scholars wishing to perform a survey or
meta-analysis could easily locate all relevant documents. They would simply
need the incentive to do so. Greater appreciation within the academy of the
value of such work is one possible source of such an incentive. Greater
appreciation outside the academy of the value of such guides to the wider
literature (and both non-profit and for-profit websites14 might be a powerful
13
Examples include the Educational Resources Information Centre (ERIC) which presently
contains almost a million document abstracts, and hopes to soon have whole articles (note
that a fee is charged for downloading by document), a physics website which receives
35000 hits per day, and various medicine sites which attempt to provide doctors with
access to all research on particular diseases or treatments (see Willinsky, 1999).
14
Willinsky (1999), though somewhat tongue-in-cheek, describes a potential non-profit
organization that would provide a vast storehouse of scientific documents, as well as
commissioning surveys (and more focused research where a particular problem was
identified). Willinsky notes that there is a crying need for especially social science
research to be presented to the public in such a fashion. This would enhance democratic
decision-making, and thus public support for science.
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 235
influence here) is perhaps a more likely force. In both cases, the use of a
classification system which can identify the huge mass of research performed
on (or with) particular phenomena, causal links, theories, or methods, should
highlight the advantages of, and indeed crying need for, works which survey
the literature.
Having recognized the need for scholarly works that synthesize, a
notation for survey articles and meta-analyses should be included within the
classification of “types of work”. Both researchers and the general public
will generally find it useful to read such works first.
The public is often frustrated by conflicting scientific results. Even those
who appreciate that science advances through debate wonder why scientists
do not seem to try very hard to settle disputes (Willinsky, 1999, 31). They
will hardly be heartened to find that scientists need not even be aware of
conflicting results achieved by other scholars. While a better classification
system can alleviate such ignorance, survey articles and meta-analyses can
take researchers an important step toward appreciating the implications of
the research of others. The goal of meta-analyses and review essays is not to
establish a winner among competing interpretations, but rather to outline the
strengths and weaknesses of different pieces of research. It can be hoped
that the scientific community will strive to answer questions raised in survey
articles. Writers of surveys need to overcome the tendency to stress their
favored view and point out only the weaknesses of alternatives. For
questions with public policy implications, the public could be left to judge.
Both writers and readers of surveys of research on particular causal links will
be better able to critique alternatives if they first have an understanding of
the inherent strengths and weaknesses of different theory types and methods.
The typologies developed in chapters 3 and 4 – and document classification
by theory and method – are important here; survey articles on particular
theories and methods would also be of great use.
Both Collins and Pinch (1993, 144-8) and Meltzoff (1998, xv) bemoan
the fact that media reports generally provide only the results of competing
studies. The public, they note, can hardly hope to distinguish among
competing results unless acquainted with some idea of the methods [and
theories] employed by researchers. And as noted above the public must
appreciate that no method is perfect, but neither is any method useless. If the
public had ready access to (regularly updated) survey works that would
compare different studies, both they and the media would likely delve deeper
into scientific controversies.
Oakley (2000, 312-24) celebrates one example of meta-analysis. The
Cochrane collaboration is an international effort to draw together for
purposes of comparison controlled experimental research studies in the area
of obstetrics. The collaboration was motivated by a realization that neither
236 Chapter 7
researchers nor physicians had an easy way of judging the mass of research,
and especially the contradictory results that different studies might generate.
The managers of the collaboration then went on to provide a guidebook for
expectant mothers that described interventions that seemed beneficial, those
requiring further investigation, those with unknown effects, and those with
documented ill effects. These (regularly updated) results have been used
both by health care decision-making bodies and by activist groups. The
collaboration now operates across diverse fields of health science, and
maintains an updated library of research studies. Oakley documents the
emergence of a similar effort in the area of social work, and demands for
these across science (especially in education). Criticisms of the Cochrane
collaboration seem to focus on the unofficial nature of the collaboration, its
exclusive focus on controlled experiment,15 and the questionable value of
some of the research summarized. It would seem that there is little objection
to the principle of such summaries, and widespread appreciation of the value
of such efforts. Note in particular the use made of this endeavor by both
physicians and expectant mothers. As argued above, improvements in
scientific practice can be directly beneficial to the wider public.
Drawing on the experience of the Cochrane Collaboration, the Campbell
Collaboration strives to survey experimental results across human science. It
judges the reliability and validity of studies on particular questions, and then
attempts to combine the results of the better studies. It has unearthed some
11,000 examples of controlled experiments in human science. Early projects
of the collaboration treated the value of driver education programs and
“scared straight” programs for crime deterrence. In both cases, experiments
suggest that these programs are less wonderful – indeed likely harmful – than
have studies using other methods. The analysis in this book would guide
both scholars and the public to take such results seriously, but not eschew
insights to be gleaned from other methods.
The large-scale efforts to survey literature that were documented by
Oakley (2000) and Willinsky (1999) have tended to be organized on a
disciplinary basis. The classifications above would encourage and allow
these and other efforts to span disciplinary boundaries. The surveys would
thus be more comprehensive, and therefore would likely encompass studies
reflecting a wider range of perspectives.
15
Though Oakley herself takes pains to emphasize the many advantages of experiments (and
provides many examples where these provided more accurate answers than casual
qualitative evaluation), she is a believer in methodological flexibility and would likely
approve of efforts both to summarize (at least some) other types of research and to contrast
results across different types of research.
7. Classifying Scientific Documents 237
1. THE CLASSIFICATIONS
theories that may speak to a particular link. In doing so, they will often need
to contend with disagreements across communities of scholars. They also
can expose specialized researchers to the benefits of extending their gaze
over a wider range of phenomena, theory, and/or method (informing them of
related research undertaken by other communities), and remind them of the
various biases and errors that might afflict their work. In particular they can
note that communities of scholars often choose methods that support their
theories, and more generally a worldview of mutually supportive elements.
Interdisciplinary scholars can also identify and investigate combinations of
phenomena, theory, and method that have been ignored by specialized
researchers. Systems of document classification that were not grounded in
disciplines would further encourage interdisciplinary interaction. If
communities of specialized researchers were to become more theoretically
and methodologically pluralistic, the role of interdisciplinarity would shrink,
but would remain essential to the scientific enterprise.
The classifications have huge pedagogical value (see below). Students
can be provided with an overview of the entire scientific enterprise. They
will be able to place any topic covered in their coursework within this
broader structure. They will also be aware of the gaps in their education, and
have an idea of where to look to fill those gaps. A curriculum grounded in
these classifications would facilitate the acquisition of critical thinking skills
as well. Note in particular that students would come to appreciate the
strengths and weaknesses of all theory types and methods. In terms of both
skills and perspectives, students would be better prepared for lifelong
learning. And the academy itself would be better placed to respond to
numerous criticisms of a liberal education.
The classifications underpin a definition of “science” itself, which
escapes most of the problems that have plagued previous efforts to define
science (chapter 5). The definition involves the study of phenomena or
causal links through the use of theories that answer each of the 5W questions
and at least one of the dozen scientific methods.
Turning now to advantages of particular classifications, the classification
of phenomena (chapter 2) serves some important purposes in its own right.
It will encourage scholars to display a greater balance in their coverage of
causal links in their research, teaching, and policy advice; at present it is
often too tempting for scientists to focus on the links that they understand
best. The recognition of the number of causal links should extinguish any
sense that one grand theory can explain all; mapping grand theories onto the
list of phenomena should show that all grand theories have more to say about
some causal links than others. Attempting to organize diverse material in
terms of one grand theory or method must necessarily oversimplify; the list
of phenomena serves as an antidote. It shows the value of unpacking
244 Chapter 8
It has been argued above that science is neither perfect nor impossible.
Moreover, science has been distinguished from non-science: science involves
clarity with respect to theoretical formulation in the specific sense of
answering each of the 5W questions, careful specification of which
phenomena or causal links are being investigated, and exposure of theoretical
propositions to real world evidence in terms of at least one of the dozen
methods. While biases and errors can still affect scientists, the facts that
scientists are clear about theoretical propositions and seek evidence to bolster
these provides limitations to the degree to which scientific conclusions
reflect bias or error. This is especially the case at the level of scientific
communities: if these regularly confront evidence from a variety of sources,
and are careful in their statement and evaluation of theories, scientific
understanding in the long run should be largely shaped by the external reality
it aspires to represent.
Importantly, trust should not be placed in all who would call themselves
scientists. Those who bury their arguments in incomprehensible prose
immunize these arguments against controversion by the evidence. Those who
state theories such that these can be interpreted in multiple ways achieve the
same end. Those who eschew or misuse scientific methods, or rely
exclusively on an unexamined intuition, likewise shield their ideas from
reality. Only in identifying the boundaries of science, and recognizing the
limitations of certain allegedly scientific practices, can a justification be
maintained for belief in the scientific enterprise more broadly. Scientists
cannot command trust simply because they are employed in a university or
laboratory; both they and the communities to which they belong must act in
accord with the definition of science in order to deserve the public’s trust.
This does not, of course, guarantee that they will be right. Even scientists
and scientific communities pursuing the best of scientific practices will often
be wrong. This book has urged scientists to a “web of belief” approach
(chapter 6) in which confidence is placed in statements that seem reliable,
but where scientists are always ready to question all statements in light of
new evidence. Humans are not omniscient, and must make their best
judgments on the basis of inherently imperfect evidence. Only by seeking a
variety of evidence can confidence be increased in a particular proposition.
The public should neither abandon trust in science nor accept every scientific
pronouncement as fact. Scientists should be careful of claiming a greater
confidence than the evidence justifies. And the scientific community should
strive to evaluate all relevant information in reaching conclusions. Ideally,
the public will have access to such evaluations, so that they can make their
250 Chapter 8
The efficiency of scientific practice, the rate of scientific advance, and the
public’s faith in science can all be enhanced by a variety of reforms to
scientific practice. As stressed above, scientists should carefully delineate
the phenomena, data, theory, and method employed in their investigation,
and ideally do so in a manner that is easily comprehended beyond their
community: the classifications both aid and encourage this practice. In
particular, scientists are urged to carefully define “concepts” in terms of
phenomena, theory, or method. Scientific communities should employ a
wider range of theories and methods, analyze a wider range of types of data,
and perhaps draw on multiple ethical perspectives in their approach to the
analysis of any phenomenon or causal link. By recognizing that all
phenomena are causally interrelated, they should be guided to widen their
gaze and include a broader set of phenomena in their analysis. They might
in particular choose to investigate links that have been relatively ignored by
the scientific enterprise. The scientific enterprise as a whole should seek to
understand every causal link. Scientists should seek the range of
applicability of all theories, and recognize that multiple theories may have
1
Cussins (2000, 354) reviews the advantages and disadvantages of public scrutiny of
science. Scientific curiosity should not be constrained to pursue only those topics
suggested by governments or public opinion. Yet given the authority that at least western
societies cede to science, it is desirable that the public has some oversight capability to
ensure that scientists do not pursue self-interest or other biases unhindered.
2
It is noteworthy that postmodernists, who tend to advocate the pursuit of idiographic
research, nevertheless tend also to state their critiques of scientific practice at a general
level. They thus risk erroneously extrapolating from areas in which science is particularly
difficult. This may in part explain the popularity of postmodernism in the Humanities.
Note also that the approach outlined in this book allows the sort of detailed research
preferred by postmodernists to be tied into a big picture, without reliance on the grand
theories that they are justifiably suspicious of.
8. Concluding Remarks 251
3
Longino (2000) surveys many cases in biology where several partial explanations of the
same result exist: “the variety of causal pathways to a similar end forces an emphasis on
one aspect of a causal process …” Scientists should indeed try to understand particular
causal mechanisms both in isolation and in concert. Longino notes, though, that many
biologists use “methodologies that of necessity show only what they are designed to show”
[a danger noted in chapter 4], and then evaluate results by criteria that are also biased [a
danger addressed in chapter 5].
4
“Transdisciplinarity” is a term favored in Europe. It has diverse interpretations, some of
them quite close to North American concepts of interdisciplinarity. For some it implies
doing away with the very idea of expertise, in recognizing that any individual at best
knows only a piece of a larger puzzle. It would seem that it would be more accurate,
though less controversial, to speak of rethinking the definition of expertise. The tendency
of transdisciplinarians to favor integration in terms of themes is also troubling; this can
look too much like the all-too-frequent attempts to unify science via the route of grand
theory.
252 Chapter 8
5
Bunge (1998, 45-6) lodges several complaints against scientific practice in the area of
social psychology: the study of individuals is not integrated with the study of societies,
replication is rare, standards for judging research are poorly articulated, hypotheses are
often unclear, and important questions [causal links] are often eschewed for less important
and often vague questions, certain methods with obvious applicability are ignored,
contradictory evidence is suppressed, jargon is excessive, and questions of the validity and
generalizability of results are ignored. This book has argued against all of these practices.
Likewise, Kincaid (1996, 261-2) proposes several improvements to social science practice:
social scientists should seek complementarity across theories, use experiments more,
8. Concluding Remarks 253
words, using long words when shorter words would suffice, imprecise
phrasing, and poor paragraph structure. Some of the time these practices will
reflect sloppiness on the part of the researchers. Other times, they reflect a
desire – whether subconscious or conscious – for obfuscation. “It is a far
more difficult task to express complex thoughts in simple language than to
express simple thoughts in complex language” (Halperin, 1997, 51).
Scientists and scientific communities can strive to do better.
Finally, what of disciplines? The word has not often been uttered in these
pages (which may itself be symbolic of the fact that disciplines are not an
essential characteristic of the scientific enterprise). By suggesting that
scientific communities be open to multiple theories, methods, causal links,
data, and ethical perspectives, it has nevertheless been argued, at the very
least, that disciplines should be much less insular than at present. In
suggesting that the scientific enterprise needs more, and more flexible,
paradigms in chapter 6, a further argument was made for the redesign of
disciplines. And at various points in this book, many advantages that would
flow from increased communication across communities of scholars have
been noted. The scientific enterprise requires the exercise of multiple forms
of expertise – by phenomenon, theory, method, data, and perhaps ethical
perspective – and needs to operate through communities of scholars that
share a certain basis of understanding. The ideal form of such communities
would seem to be much more flexible than is the case with present
disciplines. And they should be much more open to the exchange of ideas
with other scientific communities than is presently the case, especially in
human science.6
6.1 Interdisciplinarity
6
“A second cultural function of disciplines is that of preventing knowledge from becoming
too abstract or overwhelming. Disciplines legitimate our necessarily partial knowledge.
They define what it is permissible not to know...” (Abbott, 2000, 130). But scholars can
have the advantages of specialization without ignoring the big picture. And scholars should
not mislead themselves about their ignorance. Szostak (2003) discussed how human
science disciplines might be better organized: each could focus on links to and from a
particular category of phenomena but remain open to diverse theories and methods.
7
Many disciplines are at present fragmented into subfields with limited communication
between them. “Interdisciplinary” scholarship as discussed here may thus at times be
necessary even within disciplines (see Dogan and Pahre, 1990).
8. Concluding Remarks 255
8
Salter and Hearn (1996) identify three key problems faced by interdisciplinary research
[and teaching]: a translation problem as different disciplines develop their own
terminology, a language problem as different disciplines attach different meanings to the
same word, and a reception problem as discipline-based journals eschew work which
8. Concluding Remarks 257
borrows heavily from other disciplines. The acceptance of a common list of phenomena
would go some way toward solving the first two problems (and suggestions of better
scientific standards in chapter 5 addresses the third). There are literally thousands of
definitions of the word “culture” in the literature; not one is as precise as that provided by
Table 2.1 (see Szostak, 2003).
9
The interdisciplinary researcher should nevertheless be open to the possibility, stressed by
Newell (2001), that there may be emergent properties not obvious in any of the earlier
theories.
258 Chapter 8
10
Glassick et al. (1997, ix) note that the emphasis on research in modern universities
encourages excessive specialization. Those focused on teaching students are more likely
to see the need to tie diverse bits of understanding into a coherent whole.
8. Concluding Remarks 259
should address how the strengths and weaknesses of these come into play for
the question at hand. Note that instructors could do this by making only
minor changes to existing course content (though the classifications may
encourage them to engage a wider range of phenomena, theory, and method
in their teaching). The students could thus master the classifications in the
course of applying them throughout their college career. At the same time,
they would be able to draw connections within and across courses, for they
would be able to see where each topic covered fits within the broader
scientific enterprise. Along with the classifications developed in earlier
chapters, students could usefully be exposed to the twelve-step process for
interdisciplinary research outlined above, for this process provides guidance
to any individual or group on how to approach complex issues. A capstone
course could draw students from diverse areas of specialization together: a
focus on public policy issues such as environmental protection would be
particularly useful here. Students could each provide insight from their
individual areas of expertise; other students could use their understanding of
the strengths and weaknesses of different theories and methods to analyze the
views of others, and work toward synthesis.11 The curriculum in general, and
capstone in particular, would prepare students for lifelong learning: they
would be able to place any piece of information within a complex organizing
structure, they would be aware of those elements of the scientific enterprise
that they had not engaged (it is all too easy at present for students to
exaggerate the comprehensiveness of their education), they would know the
full set of theories, methods, and so on that they might wish to apply to any
novel problem, they would have a firm basis from which to critically
evaluate the arguments of others, and they would appreciate that no
argument is perfect but that some are better than others.
It might be thought that exposing students to the full range of method,
phenomena, types of theory, and ethical perspectives would be either
impossible or inordinately time-consuming. However, these important
elements – hereafter referred to as comprehensive elements, for they provide
students with a comprehensive overview – can be integrated readily into
existing curricula. Those who design general education curricula often
complain of a tension between a desire to cover many topics, and a wish to
cover certain topics in depth. The comprehensive material contained in the
classifications allows curricula to achieve maximum breadth – students are
11
One oft-stated goal of General Education is for students to gain an appreciation of different
disciplinary perspectives. As noted above, it is often difficult to define what this means.
Most of what is meant can be captured with respect to differences in theories and methods
used, phenomena studied, and ethical approaches applied. Note that this approach would
serve to highlight the advantages and disadvantages inherent in disciplinary specialization.
8. Concluding Remarks 261
12
Kervin (1997) bemoans several problems in Humanities education: the tendency of modern
critics to read texts only to expose “villains”, not to excite the imagination; the tendency to
argue that knowledge is inherently subjective and ambiguous; and the emphasis of many
humanists on political advocacy. The first problem reflects a failure to teach all relevant
links, and particularly to appreciate the aesthetic influence of literature. The second
reflects the absence of a Golden Mean understanding. The third involves a failure to
confront bias. Shattuck (2000) suggests that there are but four ways to organize a
Humanities core curriculum: around Great Books, historical periods, overarching themes
(such as “truth” or “the other”), or ways of knowing. The comprehensive material suggests
a superior fifth approach, which would focus on the pros and cons of textual analysis and
the applicability of other methods to the subject matter of the Humanities, the various
relationships between Humanities phenomena and diverse other phenomena, the five
ethical perspectives (with perhaps an emphasis on how each can be found across diverse
philosophical traditions), and an appreciation of the strengths and weaknesses of theories
commonly employed by Humanists. Note that this approach facilitates the reasoned
comparison of works from Western and non-Western traditions.
262 Chapter 8
could be invaluable, though note that methods are best appreciated when
applied to something. An introductory course structured around diverse
causal links among the list of phenomena in Table 2.1 (and a similar list of
natural science phenomena) could help students choose the area in which
they wished to concentrate, as well as provide a base from which to integrate
later material. An ethical survey course might be especially valuable, given
the limited philosophical content of most other courses. Such a course would
provide students with some valuable guidelines on how to live their lives,
while also preparing them to appreciate the ethical issues relevant to their
other courses. Courses could also be structured around a typology of theory,
and a typology of criticisms of scholarly practice. In all cases, though, it is
critical that the comprehensive material is not isolated in one course, but that
continued reference is made to it in later courses.
The manageable scope of the comprehensive material deserves emphasis.
While human scientists care about hundreds of phenomena, these can be
organized in a handy table. This may seem overwhelming at first, but can
easily be mastered during a college education. The list of methods used by
scholars is even less difficult: colleges can reasonably hope to acquaint
students with the major strengths and weaknesses of each. Likewise, it is
certainly quite feasible to discuss each of the five broad types of ethical
analysis. The typology of theory may be the most difficult element in this
package, but since each of the five broad dimensions of the typology yields a
handful of possibilities, it too is certainly manageable in scope.
Experts on curricular reform emphasize the importance of integration of
general education with the major. “Campus leaders must attend not merely
to the coherence of the general education program but also to the
interrelation of general education and the majors” (Gaff, 1999, 4). As noted
above, if general education courses provided an introduction to the various
sorts of comprehensive material outlined above, it would be both
straightforward and advantageous for courses in the major thereafter to
constantly reference what theory type, method, phenomena, and ethical
approach were being discussed. Such a practice would make both instructors
and students more aware of potential limitations and biases, while permitting
students to place their major in a wider perspective. Ideally, it would
encourage instructors to “teach the conflicts” (Graff, 1992), rather than
pretending that only one theory or method or ethical perspective or subset of
phenomena is appropriate to the question at hand. Students, if informed of
the theories, methods, and so on being covered in each of their courses, in
terms of a shared vocabulary, would be able to recognize conflicts even if
instructors were not explicit about these; at present students often
compartmentalize their knowledge and can thus be blissfully unaware that
8. Concluding Remarks 263
different instructors disagreed (again, see Graff, 1992).13 Thus, not only can
comprehensive material be introduced without requiring any diminution in
attention devoted to the major, but this material will in fact enhance teaching
within the major. Furthermore, the comprehensive material will even help
students to choose their major (and options).
One further advantage of the comprehensive curriculum is that it
enhances the ability of a student to choose a problem-oriented rather than
discipline-determined area of specialization. While a handful of smallish
curricular changes have been entertained above, further changes could be
imagined which would see upper level coursework explicitly focussed on
particular links among specified sets of phenomena, rather than being
constrained by disciplinary boundaries. Degree programs themselves could
more readily be organized around interdisciplinary problems. A student
interested in inner city poverty or environmental degradation will struggle at
present to stitch together the appropriate courses from several disciplines; a
question-driven curriculum would greatly facilitate such a task. Given the
great diversity of complex issues that might attract the interest of a particular
student, institutions may struggle to offer a satisfactory range of upper year
courses. Several solutions are possible: directed reading courses, seminar
courses which draw together students working in related areas (perhaps with
some sort of community outreach component), openness to courses offered
by other institutions, and so on.
New technology will encourage and support this new curricular structure.
CD-Roms and the Internet both excel in allowing students to explore links
between diverse subjects; however, students need an overarching structure in
order to avoid getting lost following hypertext links. New technology also
facilitates the constant editing of both text and graphics. A world that
recognizes that knowledge is expanding gradually in all directions should
appreciate a curriculum that gives students a framework for readily
integrating new information. Adoption of these curricular reforms would
encourage technological developments in particular directions. Scholars
could, for example, work toward an electronic archive wherein academic
literature could be summarized and regularly updated in terms of causal links
and phenomena (see chapter 7). This would make it much easier for both
students and scholars to identify relevant literature.
13
Clarke and Agne (1997, 2-3), drawing on Piaget, argue that learners need to be actively
involved in their learning. They need to develop a structure of schemas, and build new
information onto these. Learning thus involves overcoming conflicts between previously
contradictory elements. They suggest that instructors would reach many more students if
they appealed to innate learning mechanisms. Later, they stress the advantages of asking
the 5W and How questions.
264 Chapter 8
Gaff (1999, 10) argues that all programs of curricular reform should have
an assessment component. While there is no one ideal method of assessment,
experts in the area often advocate methods which can be employed in-class
during a student’s final year. If the exposure of students to comprehensive
material were taken as a primary goal of curricula, it would be relatively
straightforward to test, using a variety of assignments, student mastery of this
material during their final year. Such an assessment technique would both
measure and encourage students’ preparation for lifelong learning. Note that
institutions would want to see how well the students could draw upon – not
just memorize – the comprehensive material, and thus could jointly assess
their mastery of the comprehensive material and particular coursework.
Student familiarity with how to perform interdisciplinary research could
likewise be measured in terms of both familiarity with and application of the
twelve-step process outlined above.
14
Klein (1999) lists twelve broad types of interdisciplinary curricula. Five are organized
around themes or issues, and one around a grand theory or method. Four involve
pedagogies that tend to be associated with interdisciplinarity: team teaching, learning
communities, student portfolios, and residential learning. Two involve developing models
of interdisciplinarity or reflecting on integration. All of these program types are laudable,
but on their own need not provide students with much-needed guidance on how to
integrate beyond their coursework. Comprehensive material could easily be integrated into
these approaches (though less easily into those that stress one grand theory).
15
Singleton and Strait (1999, 2-3) give a couple of examples of misleading media reports –
“More pedestrians are hurt in marked crosswalks” and “X% of doctors prescribe drug Y” –
and argue that students should be guided to ask the right questions: Do most pedestrians
cross streets at crosswalks, and are these where traffic is heaviest?; How many doctors
were involved, how often do they prescribe the drug; and who asked/selected them?
266 Chapter 8
thus individuals should not ignore but rather seek to analyze their intuition.
Finally, recognition of the true complexity of human societies should
encourage everyone to seek out the views of people with diverse
perspectives.16
16
Fish (1998) argued that reform of the academy can and should directly inform attempts to
reform the wider world. A curriculum that embraces complexity through
comprehensiveness enhances both societal ability and will to cope with the complexity of
our times.
17
As with the discovery of radio, a research quest not designed (primarily) to respond to such
criticisms may yield answers that direct attempts to respond might not.
268 Chapter 8
Denzin, N.K., and Lincoln, Y.S., 1998, Introduction to this volume, in: Strategies of
Qualitative Inquiry, N.K. Denzin and Y.S. Lincoln, eds., Sage, Thousand Oaks CA.
Dogan, M., 1996, The hybridization of social science knowledge, Library Trends 45(2): 296-
314.
Dogan, M., and Pahre, R., 1990, Creative Marginality: innovation at the intersections of
social science, Westview Press, Boulder CO.
Dupré, J., 2001, Human Nature and the Limits of Science, Clarendon, Oxford.
Elliott, A., 2000, Psychoanalysis and social theory, in: The Blackwell Companion to Social
Theory, B.S. Turner, ed., Blackwell, Oxford.
Ellis, L., 1994, Research Methods in the Social Sciences, Brown and Benchmark, Madison.
Elster, J., 1989, Nuts and Bolts For the Social Sciences, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Fabian, J., 1975, Taxonomy and Ideology: on the boundaries of concept classification, Peter
de Redder Press, Lisse.
Feuer, L., 1995, Varieties of Scientific Experience. Transactions Publishers, New Brunswick
NJ.
Fiscella, J., 1996, Bibliography as an interdisciplinary service, Library Trends 45(2): 280-95.
Fish, S., 1998, Being interdisciplinary is so very hard to do, in: Interdisciplinarity: essays
from the literature, W.H. Newell, ed., College Board, New York.
Fox, G., 1997, Reason and Reality in the Methodology of Economics, Edward Elgar,
Cheltenham UK.
Fraser, C., and Gaskell, G., eds., 1990, The Social Psychological Study of Widespread Beliefs,
Clarendon, Oxford.
Freeman, D., 1994, Nature’s Imagination: the frontiers of scientific vision, Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Freidheim, E.A., 1982, From Types to Theory: a natural method for an unnatural science,
University Press of America, Washington.
Fuller, S., 1993, Philosophy of Science and its Discontents, Guilford Press, New York.
Fuller, S., 1997, Science, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis.
Fuller, S., 1998, The position: interdisciplinarity as interpretation, in: Interdisciplinarity:
essays from the literature, W.H. Newell, ed., College Board, New York.
Gaff, J.G., 1991, New Life For the College Curriculum, Jossey-Bass, San Francisco.
Gaff, J.G., 1997, Tensions between tradition and innovation, in: Handbook of the
Undergraduate Curriculum, J.G. Gaff, J. Ratcliff, and associates, eds., Jossey Bass, San
Francisco.
Gaff, J.G., 1999, General Education: the changing agenda, Association of American Colleges
and Universities, Washington.
Gaff, J.G., Ratcliff, J., and Associates, eds., 1997, Handbook of the Undergraduate
Curriculum, Jossey-Bass, San Francisco.
Galison, P., 1996, Introduction: the content of disunity, in P. Galison and D. J. Stump, eds.,
The Disunity of Science: boundaries, contexts, and power. Stanford University Press,
Stanford, pp. 1-36.
Getman, J., 1992, In the Company of Scholars, University of Texas Press, Austin.
Giere, R., 1988, Explaining Science: a cognitive approach, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
Glassick, C.E., Huber, M.T., and Maeroff, G.I., 1997, Scholarship Assessed: evaluation of the
professoriate, Jossey-Bass, San Francisco.
Goldenberg, S., 1992, Thinking Methodologically, Harper Collins, New York.
272 References
Gower, B., 1997, Scientific Method: an historical and philosophical introduction, Routledge,
London.
Graff, G., 1992, Beyond the Culture Wars: how teaching the conflicts can revitalize American
education, Norton, New York.
Haack, S., 1998, Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Hall, D.J., and Hall, I., 1996, Practical Social Research: Project Work in the Community,
Macmillan, Basingstoke UK.
Hall, P.A., 2003, Aligning ontology and methodology in comparative research, in:
Comparative Historical Analysis in the Social Sciences, J. Mahoney and D. Reuschmeyer,
eds., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 373-404.
Halperin, D.F., 1997, Critical Thinking Across the Curriculum, Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Mahwah NJ.
Hammersley, M., 1996, The relationship between qualitative and quantitative research:
paradigmatic loyalty versus methodological eclecticism, in: Handbook of Qualitative
Research Methods, J.T.E. Richardson, ed., British Psychological Association, Leicester.
Hammersley, M., 2000, Taking Sides in Social Research, Routledge, London.
Hammersley, M., and Gomm, R., 2000, Biases in social research, in: Taking Sides in Social
Research, by M. Hammersley, Routledge, London.
Hartman, J.J., and Hedblom, J.H., 1988, Methods for the Social Sciences: a handbook for
students and non-specialists, 3rd ed., Greenwood Press, Westport CT.
Hawthorn, G., 1991, Plausible Worlds, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Hedstrom, P., and Swedberg, R., eds., 1998, Social Mechanisms: An Analytical Approach to
Social Theory, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Herda, E.A., 1999, Research Conversations and Narrative: a critical hermeneutics orientation
in participatory inquiry, Praeger, Westport CT.
Hintikka, J., 2000, Introduction: epistemology, in: S. Rosen, ed., The Examined Life: readings
from Western philosophy from Plato to Kant, Random House, New York.
Hjorland, B., 1994, Subject representation and information seeking: survey of a doctoral
thesis, Knowledge Organization 21(2): 94-8.
Holton, G.J., 1993, Science and anti-science, Harvard University Press, Cambridge MA.
Horn, R.E., 2003, Infrastructure for navigating interdisciplinary debates, in: Visualizing
Argumentation: software tools for collaborative and educational sense-making, P.
Kirschner, S.J. Buckingham Shum, and C.S. Carr, eds., .Springer, London.
Hough, G.A., 1984, News Writing 3rd ed., Houghton-Mifflin, Boston.
Hubenthal, U., 1994, Interdisciplinary thought, Issues in Integrative Studies 12: 55-75.
Hull, D.L., 1989, Science as a Process, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Hull, D.L., 1998, Introduction to part V, in: The Philosophy of Biology, D.L. Hull and M.
Ruse, eds., Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Hull, D.L., and Ruse, M., eds., 1998, The Philosophy of Biology, Oxford University Press,
Oxford.
Hunt, M., 1997, How Science Takes Stock: the story of meta-analysis, Russell Sage
Foundation, New York.
Hunter, E.J., 1988, Classification Made Simple, Gower, Aldershot UK.
Jackendoff, R., 1992, Languages of the Mind, MIT Press, Cambridge MA.
Jones, P., 1985, Theory and Method in Sociology: a guide for the beginner, University
Tutorial Press, Slough UK.
Kantorovich, A., 1993, Scientific Discovery, SUNY Press, Albany.
Katzer, J., Cook, K.H., and Crouch, W.W., 1998, Evaluating Information: a guide for users of
social science research, McGraw-Hill, Boston.
References 273
Kent, B., 1987, Charles S. Peirce: logic and classification of the sciences, McGill-Queen’s
University Press, Montreal.
Kervin, A., 1997, Changes in the humanities, in: What’s Happened to the Humanities?, A.
Kervin, ed., Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Kincaid, H., 1996, Philosophical Foundations of the Social Sciences, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Kirschner, P., Buckingham Shum, S.J., and Carr, C.S., eds., Visualizing Argumentation:
software tools for collaborative and educational sense-making, Springer, London.
Kitcher, P., 1982, Abusing Science, MIT Press, Cambridge MA.
Klee, R., 1999, Scientific Inquiry: readings in the philosophy of science, Oxford University
Press, New York.
Klein, E., 1998, Economic Theories and Their Relational Structure, St. Martin’s, New York.
Klein, J.T., 1990, Interdisciplinarity, Wayne State University Press, Detroit.
Klein, J.T., 1996, Crossing Boundaries: knowledge, disciplinarities, and interdisciplinarities,
University Press of Virginia, Charlottesville.
Klein, J.T., 1996a, Interdisciplinary trends: the current context, Library Trends 45(2): 34-54.
Klein, J.T., 1999, Mapping Interdisciplinary Studies, Association of American Colleges and
Universities, Washington.
Klein, J.T., 2000, A conceptual vocabulary of interdisciplinary science, in: Practising
Interdisciplinarity, P. Weingart and N. Stehr, eds., University of Toronto Press, Toronto.
Klein, L., and Eason, K., 1991, Putting Social Science to Work, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Kontopolous, K., 1993, The Logics of Social Structure, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Krieger, M.H., 1997, Doing Physics: how physicists take hold of the world, University of
Indiana Press, Bloomington.
Kruglanski, A., 1989, Lay Epistemics and Human Knowledge, Plenum, New York.
Kuhn, A., 1974, The Logic of Social Systems, Jossey-Bass, San Francisco.
Kuhn, T.S., 1962, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
Lambert, K., and Brittan, G.G. Jr., 1992, An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science 4th ed.,
Ridgeview Publishing Company, Alascedero CA.
Langley, P., Simon, H.A., Bradshaw, G.L., and Zytkow, J.M., 1987, Scientific Discovery:
computational explorations of the scientific process, MIT Press, Cambridge MA.
Langridge, D.W., 1992, Classification: its kinds, elements, systems, and applications, Bowker,
London.
Lechner, F.J., 2000, Systems theory and functionalism, in: The Blackwell Companion to
Social Theory, B.S. Turner, ed., Blackwell, Oxford.
Lenoir, T., and Gumbrecht, H.U., eds., 1996, Writing Science, Stanford University Press,
Stanford.
Little, D., 1998, Microfoundations, Method, and Causation, Transactions Publishers, New
Brunswick NJ.
Longino, H.E., 2000, Toward an epistemology for biological pluralism, in: Biology and
Epistemology, R. Creath and J. Maienschein, eds., Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 261-86.
Madden, E.H., ed., 1989, Theories of Scientific Method: the Renaissance through the
nineteenth century, Gordon and Breach, New York.
274 References
Magnum, D., 2000, Down the primrose path: competing epistemologies in early twentieth
century biology, in: Biology and Epistemology, R. Creath and J. Maienschein, eds.,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 91-121.
Mahner, M., and Bunge, M., 1997, Foundations of Biophilosophy, Springer-Verlag, New
York.
Mann, T., 1993, Library Research Models: a guide to classification, cataloguing, and
computers. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Marcella, R., and Newton, R., 1994, A New Manual of Classification, Gower, Aldershot.
May, T., 1997, Social Research: issues, methods, and process, 2nd. ed., Open University
Press, Buckingham.
Mayer, T., 1993, Truth Versus Precision, Edward Elgar, London.
McCloskey, D.N., 1990, If You’re So Smart... University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
McCloskey, D.N., and Ziliak, S.T., 1996, The standard error of regressions, Journal of
Economic Literature 34(1): 97-114.
McKeon, R., 1994, On Knowing – The Natural Sciences, University of Chicago Press,
Chicago.
McKim, V.R., 1997, Introduction, in: Causality in Crisis: statistical methods and the search
for causal knowledge in the social sciences, V.R. McKim and S.P. Turner, eds., University
of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame IN.
McNeill, P., 1990, Research Methods, 2nd ed., Routledge, London.
Meltzoff, J., 1998, Critical Thinking About Research, American Psychological Association,
Washington.
Merton, R.K., 1973, The Sociology of Science: theoretical and empirical investigations,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Messer-Davidow, E., Shumway, D.R., and Sylvan, D.J., 1993, Knowledges: historical and
critical studies in interdisciplinarity, University of Virginia Press, Charlottesville.
Mokyr, J., 2002, The gifts of Athena : historical origins of the knowledge economy,
Princeton University Press, Princeton.
Montgomery, S.L., 1996, The Scientific Voice, The Guilford Press, New York.
Moran, J., 2002, Interdisciplinarity, Routledge, New York.
Morton, A., 1997, A Guide Through the Theory of Knowledge, Blackwell, Oxford.
Moser, P.K., Mulder, D.H., and Trout, J.D., 1998, The Theory of Knowledge: a thematic
introduction, Oxford University Press, New York.
Motterlini, M., 1999, For and Against Method, University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Mowery, D.C., and Rosenberg, N., 1989, Technology and the Pursuit of Economic Growth,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Mukherjee, R., 1983, Classification in Social Research, SUNY Press, Albany.
Neurath, O., Carnap, R., and Morris, C.W., eds., 1970, Foundations of the Unity of Science,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Newell, W.H., 1998, The case for interdisciplinary study: response to professor Benson’s five
arguments, in W.H. Newell, ed., Interdisciplinarity: essays from the literature, College
Board, New York.
Newell, W.H., 2001, A theory of interdisciplinary studies, Issues in Integrative Studies 19:1-
26.
Nicolescu, B., 2002, Manifesto of Transdisciplinarity [trans Karen-Claire Voss], SUNY Press,
Albany.
Norris, C., 2000, Minding the Gap: epistemology and the philosophy of science in the two
traditions, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst.
References 275
Oakley, A., 2000, Experiments in Knowing: gender and method in social science, The New
Press, New York.
Pahre, R., 1996, Knowledge communication in the social sciences, Library Trends 45(2): 204-
225.
Palmer, C.L., 1996, Information work at the boundaries of science: linking library services to
research practices, Library Trends 45(2): 165-191.
Palmer, C.L., 2001, Work at the Boundaries of Science: information and the interdisciplinary
research process, Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Palys, T., 1997, Research Decisions: quantitative and qualitative perspectives, Harcourt
Brace, Toronto.
Perry, W.G. Jr., 1970, Forms of Ethical and Intellectual Development in the College Years: a
scheme, Holt, Rinehart, and Winston., New York.
Pervin, L.A., ed., 1990, Handbook of Personality Theory and Research, Guilford Press, New
York.
Plummer, K., 2000, Symbolic interactionism in the twentieth century, in: The Blackwell
Companion to Social Theory, B.S. Turner, ed., Blackwell, Oxford.
Pole, C.J., and Burgess, R.G., eds., 2000, Cross-Cultural Case Study, JAI Press, Amsterdam.
Polkinghorne, J., 1996, Beyond Science: the wider human context, Cambridge University
Press, Cambridge.
Potter, G., 2000, The Philosophy of Social Science, Prentice-Hall, Harlow UK.
Pounds, N.J.G., 2001, What economic history means to me, in: Living Economic and Social
History, P. Hudson ed., Economic History Society, Glasgow, 288-92.
Prus, R., 1996, Symbolic Interaction and Ethnographic Research, SUNY Press, Albany.
Rachels, J., 1993, Moral philosophy as a subversive activity, in: Applied Ethics, E.R. Winkler
and J.R. Coombs, eds., Blackwell, Oxford.
Ragin, C.C., 2000, Fuzzy Set Social Science, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Reason, P., 1998, Three approaches to participative inquiry, in: Strategies of Qualitative
Inquiry, N.K. Denzin and Y.S. Lincoln, eds., Sage, Thousand Oaks CA.
Root, M., 1993, Philosophy of Social Science, Blackwell, Oxford.
Rosser, J.B., 1999, On the complexities of complex economic dynamics, Journal of Economic
Perspectives 13(4): 169-92.
Rota, G., and Crants, J.T., 2000, Introduction: ten philosophical and contradictory predictions,
in: The Examined Life: readings from Western philosophy from Plato to Kant, S. Rosen,
ed., Random House, New York.
Rothbart, D., 2000, Substance and function in chemical research, in: Of minds and molecules:
new philosophical perspectives on chemistry, N. Bhushan and S. Rosenfeld, eds., Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Rowley, J.E., 1992, Organizing Knowledge 2nd ed., Ashgate, Aldershot.
Rule, J.B., 1997, Theory and Progress in Social Science, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Salter, L., and Hearn, A., 1996, Outside the Lines: issues in interdisciplinary research,
McGill-Queen’s University Press, Montreal.
Sandler, T., 2001, Economic Concepts for the Social Sciences, Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Sartori, G., ed., 1984, Social Science Concepts: a systematic analysis, Sage, Beverly Hills.
Schaffner, K.F., 2000, Afterword, in: Biology and Epistemology, R. Creath and J.
Maienschein, eds., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 287-95.
Scriven, M., 1988, Explanations, predictions, and laws, in: Theories of Explanation, J.C. Pitt,
ed., Oxford University Press, Oxford.
276 References
Szostak, R., 2005, Evaluating the historiography of the Great Depression: explanation or
single-theory driven, Journal of Economic Methodology, Forthcoming.
Tashakkori, A., and Teddlie, C., 1998, Mixed Methodology: combining quantitative and
qualitative approaches, Sage, Thousand Oaks CA.
Taylor, C.A., 1996, Defining Science, University of Wisconsin Press, Madison.
Tessler, M., ed., with Nachtwey, J., and Banda, A., 1999, Area Studies and Social Science:
strategies for understanding Middle East politics, Indiana University Press, Bloomington.
Turner, B.S., 2000, Preface, Introduction, in: The Blackwell Companion to Social Theory, B.S.
Turner, ed., Blackwell, Oxford.
Turner, S.P., 1996, Introduction: social theory and sociology, in: Social Theory and Sociology,
S.P. Turner, ed., Blackwell, Cambridge MA.
Turner, S.P., 2002, Brains/Practices/Relativism: social theory after cognitive science,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Urry, J., 2000, Sociology of time and space, in: The Blackwell Companion to Social Theory,
B.S. Turner, ed., Blackwell, Oxford.
Vaitkus, S., 2000, Phenomenology and sociology, in: The Blackwell Companion to Social
Theory, B.S. Turner, ed., Blackwell, Oxford.
Valiela, I., 2001, Doing Science: design, analysis, and communication of scientific research,
Oxford University Press, New York.
Vaughan, R.J., and Buss, T., 1998, Communicating Social Science Research to Policy-makers,
Sage, Thousand Oaks CA.
Velkley, R., 2000, Introduction: metaphysics, in: The Examined Life: readings from Western
philosophy from Plato to Kant, S. Rosen, ed., Random House, New York.
Vicedo, M., 2000, Experimentation in early genetics: the implications of the historical
character of science for scientific realism, in: Biology and Epistemology, R. Creath and J.
Maienschein, eds., Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 215-43.
Ward, S.C., 1996, Reconfiguring Truth, Rowman and Littlefield, Lanham MD.
Weinberg, B.H., 1988, Why indexing fails the researcher, The Indexer 16(1): 3-6.
Weingart, P., 2000, Interdisciplinarity: the paradoxical discourse, in: Practising
interdisciplinarity, P. Weingart and N. Stehr, eds., University of Toronto Press, Toronto.
Wellman, B., 1998, On Norman H. Die, Dale H. Bent, and C. Hadlai Hull, SPSS, doing it
ourselves, in: Required Reading: Sociology’s most influential books, D. Clawson, ed.,
University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst.
White, H.D., 1996, Library retrieval for interdisciplinary synthesis, Library Trends 45(2):
239-64.
Whitley, R., 2000, The Intellectual and Social Organization of the Sciences, Oxford
University Press, Oxford.
Williams, R., 1985, Keywords: a vocabulary of culture and society 2nd ed., Oxford University
Press, Oxford.
Willinsky, J., 1999, Technologies of Knowledge: a proposal for the human sciences, Beacon,
Boston.
Winkler, E.R., and Coombs, J.R., 1993 From Kantianism to contextualism, in: Applied Ethics,
E.R. Winkler and J.R. Coombs, eds., Blackwell, Oxford.
Wolfe, A., 1999 Moral inquiry in social science, in: The Nature of Moral Inquiry in the Social
Sciences, C. Cochran, D. Hollenbach, A.Wolfe, and R. Wuthnow, Erasmus Institute,
Rotterdam.
Woolgar, S., 1988, Science: the very idea, Ellis Horwood, Chichester UK.
Ziman, J., 2000, Real Science: What it is and what it means, Cambridge University Press,
New York.
INDEX
causation, types of, 31-2, 72, 80-2, 244, senses and, 45, 47; operationalization
246 and, 40, 48-50, 52, 63, 75-6, 78-80,
Caws, P., 6 115, 119, 131, 206-7, 244, 246, 248;
chaos theory; See complexity quantification of, 47-9
chemistry, 1-2, 5, 9, 12-3, 26, 38, 40, 69, decision-making, five types of, 66-7, 83-
73, 118, 120-1, 143, 149, 220 5, 96, 107, 181, 186, 193-8, 214, 231,
cholera, 132, 148 245, 248, 253, 266
Clarke, J., 263 deduction; See induction
classification; as a method, 102, 117-8, definitions, 7, 30-2, 34, 38, 41, 43-4, 50,
138, 149, 228; desirable qualities, 2-3, 77, 87, 113, 134, 137, 170-2, 188, 222,
5, 15-6; exhaustiveness, 2, 5, 7, 24, 31, 243-5, 256-7
41, 54-5, 97, 102, 118, 144-6, 158-61, Denzin, N.K., 110
192-4, 196, 232-3, 241-2, 253; Dewey, J., 1, 85-6
guidelines for, 9-14, 107, 117-8, 161; disciplinary worldview, 41, 151, 153-4,
importance of, 1-2, 8, 14-6, 18, 23, 31- 183, 200, 204, 243, 256, 260
6, 50, 95-8, 144-54, ch. 7, 241-68; disciplines, 26, 30, 63, 96-7, 100-1, 173,
reification and, 11-3, 48, 50, 118; 177, 236, 246, 251-2, 254, 256;
summary of efforts at, 239-40; characteristics of, 8, 41, 177, 185, 187;
unidimensional versus multidimen- classifying, 14-6, 23, 33, 38; problems
sional, 2, 10, 37 inherent in, 19-21, 33, 59, 104, 147-8,
Cohen, I.J., 84-7 168-9, 177, 179, 181-4, 187, 189, 192,
Cole, S., 156-7, 167, 182, 184, 188, 190- 201, 205, 208-12, 214, 216, 221-2,
1, 212 226, 263. See also human science;
Collins, H., 121, 156, 167, 191, 235 humanities; interdisciplinarity; natural
Collins, R., 54, 155, 183-4, 210, 220, 232 science; social science; various discip-
common ground theory, 22 lines
community studies, 141 diversity, concerns with, 35-6, 111, 137,
comparative method, 141 166, 168, 198, 253, 267; See also
complexity theory, 72, 83, 94 postmodernism
Comte, A., 42, 76 Dogan, M., 21, 26, 30, 41-2, 80, 96, 180,
concepts, scientific, 7, 21, 41-5, 76-7, 184, 208-10, 220, 227, 232, 254
113, 157, 172, 241, 250 Dupré, J., 3, 32, 39, 67, 96, 174
Cornwell, G., 36, 267 Durkheim, E., 54
Courage, 16, 164, 252
Creath, R., 147 economics, 32-4, 39-40, 42, 49, 55-6, 63-
culture, 24-6, 28, 30-1, 33-4, 36-8, 43, 46, 4, 69-70, 96, 115, 121, 130-2, 147,
54, 58, 66, 76, 84-7, 93, 95, 105, 112, 151, 177, 179-80, 184, 190, 193, 200,
166, 172, 175, 267; influences on 205, 214, 229
science, 165-9, 182, 190 economy, 24, 28, 30-1, 38, 58, 117-8,
Cussins, C.M., 157-8, 160, 166, 187, 212, 144, 165, 268; influences on science,
250 160, 165
Einstein, A., 22, 163, 165
Dahlberg, I., 44, 229 Elliott, A., 90
Dale, A., 133 Ellis, L., 103, 145
data, 4, 6, 38-41, 45-50, 63, 133-4, 152, Elster, J., 31, 81
157, 183, 206-7, 210, 223, 244-6; empiricism versus rationalism, 79, 107
defined, 45-7; desirability of using engineering; See technology
different types of, 19, 46, 50, 106, environment, non-human, 25, 29, 38, 46,
108, 200, 207, 244; empirical 58, 165, 213
regularities in, 47, 52, 78, 172-3; five errors and biases, defined, 158-60
Index 281
ethics, 98, 127, 129, 174-7, 181, 183, 186, Getman, J., 164
194-8, 213-4, 231, 245, 248, 262, 266- Giddens, A., 85-6, 92
8 Giere, R., 161, 163, 166, 211
ethnography; See observation Glassick, C.E., 163, 178, 180, 183, 218,
evaluation research, 102, 141-2 258-9
evolution, 44, 59, 81-3, 87, 89, 94, 117-8, golden mean, 8; applied, 38, 40, 59-60,
121, 156, 162, 165, 183, 186, 188, 62, 71, 79, 107, 109, 137, 144, 156-7,
198, 210 159, 161, 168, 259, 261; described,
experience, 102, 107, 124-5, 138 16-9; summary of arguments, 247-8
experiments, 101, 104, 112-3, 116, 118- Goldenberg, S., 4, 52, 105, 113, 115-6,
21, 130, 132, 138, 142, 148-9, 152, 122, 127, 129, 137, 143, 203
154, 159-60, 201-4, 215, 235-6 Gomm, R., 112, 134, 158-60, 196
Gower, B., 17, 40, 106, 121, 144, 172,
Fabian, J., 13 187
feminist theory and method, 51, 54, 84, Graff, G., 35, 262-3
90, 102, 111, 120, 122, 166 grounded theory, 91, 206-7
Feuer, L., 161, 190
Feyerabend, P., 170, 202, 212 Haack, S., 183
field theory, 58 Habermas, G., 88, 90, 92
financing of research, 155, 166, 180-2, Hall, D.J., 7, 102, 109, 142, 151
185-6, 197, 215-6, 234, 247 Hall, P.A., 200
Fiscella, J., 225 Halperin, D.F., 41, 106, 162, 168, 254
Fish, S., 21, 267 Hammersley, M., 112, 134, 152, 158-60,
5W questions; advantages of, 3-4, 10-1, 196
14, 37, 102-3, 109, 144-51, 192-3, Hartman, J.J., 103, 145, 147
195, 197, 205-6, 220, 226, 232-3, 241- Hawthorn, G., 71
5, 253; and hypotheses, 78-9; applied, Hawthorne effect, 120
5-7, 37-40, 48-50, 55-75, 77, 79-82, health, 25, 29, 58, 165
98, 104-9, 116-44, 161-92, 195, 220; Hedstrom, P., 126
described, 3-5 Herda, E.A., 129, 180
Fleming, A., 120 hermeneutics, 81, 102, 142-3
Foucault, M., 165-6, 170 Hintikka, J., 99
Fox, G., 176 history, 63
Fraser, C., 148 Hjorland, B., 222
Free will, 85-6, 88, 90, 112 Holton, G.J., 156
Freeman, D., 156 honesty, 176, 181, 196
Freidheim, E.A., 54-5, 57, 59, 69, 72, 74, Horn, R.E., 237
76, 95, 104, 200 Hough, G.A., 5
Fuller, S., 1, 70, 100, 121-2, 148, 151, Hubenthal, U., 21
157, 162, 166, 173, 182-3, 186, 208 Hull, D.L., 26, 31, 87, 95, 177, 183, 216
functionalism, 54, 81-2, 84, 87-90, 93-4 human science, 14, 33, 59, 73, 80, 83,
134, 140, 142, 146, 158, 167, 172,
Gaff, J.G., 36, 262, 264, 267-8 197-8, 205, 236; defined 6; See also
Galison, P., 1, 20, 22, 167, 173 humanities; natural science; social
game theory, 92-3, 126 science; various disciplines
genetic predisposition, 24, 27, 30, 33, 56, humanities, 3, 42-3, 51, 101-2, 175, 214,
58, 60, 66, 86, 93, 165, 213; See also 250, 261
perception and cognition Hume, D., 4
geography, 147 humility, 156, 163-4, 186
geology, 26, 140, 201, 207 Hunt, M., 153
282 Index
Hunter, B., 51 Kincaid, H., 18, 33, 59, 65, 70, 81, 155,
Hunter, E.J., 221, 224, 232 171, 176, 188, 207, 252
hypotheses, defined, 78-80 Kirschner, P., 237
Kitcher, P., 18, 78, 156, 174
idiographic; See nomothetic Klee, R., 48, 63, 79, 202
incentives facing scientists, 177-81, 189, Klein, E., 55
192-3, 197, 214, 218, 234-5, 258-9 Klein, J.T., 14, 20-1, 35, 41, 204, 255,
induction; problem of, 5, 152, 160; versus 265, 268
deduction, 2-3, 5, 10, 15-6, 25, 41, 44, Klein, L., 180
49, 62, 66, 81, 95, 101, 106-7, 110, Kontopolous, K., 72
115, 119-20, 124-5, 127-8, 132, 140-1, Krieger, M.H., 23, 46, 57-8, 75, 104, 120,
143, 161, 192, 194, 201-3, 224, 255 190
institutional structure of science, 160, Kruglanski, A., 162
163-4, 174, 177-86, 189-93, 245, 252, Kuhn, A., 30
258-9 Kuhn, T.S., 106, 155, 187, 208, 210
institutions, 28, 30, 57-8, 71, 74, 87, 89-
90, 214 Lakatos, I., 52, 106, 174, 212
interdisciplinarity, 9, 19-22, 38, 80, 83, Lambert, K., 99, 170
90, 92, 96, 130, 134, 184, 189, 191, Langley, P., 49, 52, 111, 146, 171, 189
204, 214, 221-3, 225, 229-30, 234, Langridge, D.W., 13, 224
238, 244, 263, 268; benefits of, 14, 20- Lechner, F.J., 87-9
1, 107, 182-3, 194, 200-1, 203, 209, Lenoir, T., 173
214, 216, 242-3, 254-5, 258; boundary life history, 123
work, 30, 173; complement-ary to Little, D., 60, 70-1, 141
specialized research, 21-2, 30, 193, Longino, H.E., 95, 120, 251
210, 242-3, 251, 254-5; defined, 20, longitudinal analysis, 133, 135-6
155; guidelines for, 19-21, 45, 100,
109, 140, 146, 153, 179, 183, 210-1, Madden, E.H., 160
214, 255-7, 260, 264; teaching, 34-5, Magnum, D., 148
101, 268; value of classifications for, Mahner, M., 26, 38, 40, 45-6, 79, 98, 170,
20-2, 30, 34-5, 45, 92, 169, 188-9, 174
219, 255-7. See also disciplines Mann, T., 225
interpretivism, 6, 32, 37, 62-5, 78, 104-6, mapmaking, 102, 143-4, 149, 237; See
110-3, 149, 153, 175, 198, 201, 248 also causal links, mapping
interviews, 101, 104, 113, 116, 119, 122- Marcella, R.,217, 219-24, 228-9, 232, 238
3, 127, 129, 135-6, 138, 140-2, 146, Marxism, 34, 52, 54-5, 76-7, 84
148, 152, 159, 179 May, T., 122-3
intuition, 66, 84, 90, 92, 102, 124-5, 138, Mayer, T., 175
149, 152, 163-4, 172-3, 175, 181, 186, McCloskey, D.N., 131, 155, 167
194, 197, 249, 267 McKeon, R., 3, 30
McKim, V.R., 39, 131
Jackendoff, R., 45 McNeill, P., 104-5, 120, 123, 127, 133,
Jones, P., 60, 84, 201 141, 201, 204
journalism, 4-5, 102 Mead, M., 114, 116, 128
mechanics, 22, 57, 64, 208
Kant, I., 13, 99, 164, 194, 197 medicine, 152-3, 166, 181, 215, 234
Kantorovich, A., 74, 162, 183, 188-9 Meltzoff, J., 41, 49, 116, 119, 132, 235
Katzer, J., 157 Merton, R.K., 52, 157, 182
Kent, B., 1, 15, 169 Messer-Davidow, E., 14
Kervin, A., 175, 261 meta-analysis, 153-4, 229, 234-6, 242
Index 283
method, 4, 6, 8, 11, 19-22, 41, 43, ch. 4, nomothetic versus idiographic analysis, 1,
158-9, 161, 166-9, 173, 178-9, 183-5, 68-71, 77, 82-3, 85, 96, 98, 105, 108,
189, 213-6, 218-9, 225, 227-8, 235, 110, 116, 118, 120, 123, 126, 128,
261-2, 265; bias toward supporting 133, 136, 138-9, 141, 175, 200, 248,
particular theory types, 104, 109, 150- 250, 257
1, 189, 200, 242-3, 246; defined, 100, Norris, C., 19
144-5, 172, 245; desirability of
flexibility in, 19, 34, 36, 50, 90-2, 100, Oakley, A., 38, 103, 110, 113, 119-20,
103-4, 108-9, 115-7, 132, 144-54, 122, 148, 151-2, 170, 235-6
177-9, 181, 185, 188-9, 201-6, 208, observation (participant), 91, 104-5, 107,
210, 214, 236, 241-2, 245-70, 250, 113-4, 120, 127-9, 138-42, 146, 148-9,
252; evaluating, 113-6; existence of 152, 159, 179, 213
more than one, 100, 121, 144, 147, openmindedness, 18, 164, 171, 181, 187,
153, 171-2; range of applicability, 208-9, 211-2
103, 144, 212, 218, 228; reliability, organizations, 28, 57
50, 113-9, 121, 123, 125, 129, 134,
140, 142, 146, 152-3; role in Pahre, R., 48, 56, 96, 183; See also
definition of science, 170-2, 175; Dogan
validity, 50, 113, 115-8, 120, 123, 125, Palmer, C.L., 21, 84, 217-8, 222, 225,
129-30, 134, 140, 142, 146, 151-3, 234, 238
168; See also theory; various Palys, T., 49-50, 105-6, 108, 110-2, 122,
methods 128-9, 134, 146, 168
Mill, J., 105-6 paradigms, 8, 96, 152, 157, 187-90, 192,
models (mathematical), 102, 107, 125-6, 208-12, 216, 247, 252, 254
138, 149, 172, 200 Parsons, T., 57, 84, 86-90, 93
Mokyr, J., 47 Pasteur, L., 164, 202
Montgomery, S.L., 168 patriarchy, 42
Moran, J., 20-1, 51-2, 140 Peirce, C.S., 1, 15, 148, 169, 178
Morton, A., 211 periodic table, 2, 5, 9, 13-4, 26, 87, 118
Moser, P.K., 18, 212 Perry, W.G. Jr., 265
Motterlini, M., 52, 63, 156, 174, 212 Pervin, L.A., 148
Mowery, D.C., 180 perception and cognition, limits of, 45,
Mukherjee, R., 1 160-2, 170, 192, 207, 213, 230-1, 246-
7
narrative analysis, 123 personality, 1, 5, 24, 26-7, 30, 33, 38, 46,
natural science, 6, 56-7, 59, 82, 94, 140, 56, 58, 60, 64, 77, 86, 149; influences
184, 205, 215; compared with human on science, 163-6, 192
science, 1, 3, 59-60, 62-4, 69-71, 78, phenomena, 4-8, 14, ch. 2, 143, 169, 177,
102, 147-50, 154, 165-6, 186, 198- 196, 203-7, 213-6, 222-3, 232, 241-6,
202, 213-6, 221, 244-6, 248, 261; See 255, 264-6; classifying theory with
also biology; chemistry; geology; respect to, 53, 58-9; defined, 30-1, 34,
physics 38-9; induction and, 106-7, 120, 124-
necessity, 81, 88, 100, 132 6, 132-3; realizations of, 31-2, 37, 40,
network analysis, 135, 143 42, 56, 205-6, 215; role in definition
Neurath, O., 15, 173 of science, 170-2, 175; second and
neuroscience, 65, 95 third level defined, 25; triangulation
Newell, W.H., 4, 21, 83, 134, 255, 257 and, 152-3; unpacked, 24-7, 29, 31;
Newton, I., 11, 22, 57, 64, 96, 164-5, 188, versus events, 31; See also causal
208 links; various phenomena
Nicolescu, B., 31 phenomenology, 54, 94-5, 213
284 Index
philosophy, 4, 13-4, 16, 30, 39, 51, 53, Ragin, C.C., 10, 40, 73, 76, 81, 104, 132-
67, 152, 172, 174-5, 214, 231, 247-8; 3, 140-1, 152, 169, 205
of science, 1, 3, 6-7, 16-9, 26, 63, 68, Ranganathan, S., 219-20, 228-9
77, 79, 81, 95, 99-100, 107, 109, 121, rational choice theory, 54, 60, 70, 92-4,
149, 155, 157-8, 160-1, 171-2, 176, 151, 200, 229
192, 197, 206-8, 230; realist, 5, 32, 37- reality, existence of, 37-8, 111-3, 115,
8, 62, 74, 112 153, 247
physical traces, 102, 129-30, 139-40, 149 Reason, P., 142
physics, 1-2, 5, 17, 19, 26, 38, 40, 47, 57- refereeing, 178, 183-4
8, 72, 75, 104-5, 121, 149, 190-1, 196, relationships, 27, 57-8, 67, 84, 86-7, 89-
201, 208 91, 93, 95, 104, 118, 122, 135, 137,
Plummer, K., 84, 91-2 150, 166-7
Polanyi, M., 100 relativity, 22, 64, 188, 208
Pole, C.J., 112 religion, 28; and science, 156, 159, 165,
politics, 24, 28, 30-1, 33, 58, 86; influ- 198
ences on science, 118, 159-60, 165-9, representativeness; See sampling
186, 213, 246 rhetoric, 167-8, 192, 215, 245, 247, 253
political science, 33-4, 200, 205, 229 Root, M., 12, 198
Polkinghorne, J., 19, 79, 99, 100, 119, Rosser, J.B., 83
191, 196 Rota, G., 177
Popper, K., 52 Rothbart, D., 40, 120
population, 25, 29, 58 Rowley, J.E., 223-4, 233
positivism, 62-5, 77-8, 104-6, 110, 113, Rule, J.B., 2, 96-7, 202, 208
149, 170, 173, 201, 248
postmodernism, 34, 37-8, 42, 54, 62, 78, Salter, L., 20, 22, 41, 256
84, 97, 170, 241, 250 sampling, 104, 116-9, 123, 140-1, 159
Potter, G., 32, 62, 65, 71, 173, 203 Sandler, T.,42
Pounds, N.J.G., 143 Sartori, G., 42
practice, scientific, 4, 7-8, 11, 18-9, 21-2, Schaffner, K.F., 69, 147
32-3, 51-2, 63-4, 79, 100, 106-8, 111, schemas, 27, 66, 86, 93, 149, 164, 168,
115, 122, 142, ch.5, 213-6, 245-7, 211, 263
251-2; See also triangulation; various science; as phenomenon, 25, 29, 58;
biases and errors boundedness of, 97, 241; cumulative
protocol analysis, 129 development of, 4, 17-9, 21, 52, 80,
Prus, R., 36, 38, 78 96-8, 101, 106, 156, 158, 186-9, 191,
psychoanalysis, 54, 90, 94, 213 202, 218, 241, 244, 248-9; defined, 3,
psychology, 32, 40, 56-7, 65, 90, 112, 7, 39, 74, 77, 161, 169-76, 243, 249;
121, 148, 207, 252 existence of, 7, 16, 77-8, 160, 170-1,
public policy, 32-4, 55, 142, 156-7, 164, 173-5, 248; improving, 7-9, 15, 18,
166, 180, 186, 192, 201, 215, 235, 32-4, 39, 42, 50-1, 146, 160, 162, 168,
237, 252, 260, 266-8 171, 174, 177-8, 180, 183, 193, 197,
209, 218-9, 241-5, 249-59; normal
qualitative versus quantitative analysis, 1, versus revolutionary, 208-10; unity of,
40, 47, 63, 102-3, 105-6, 109-15, 120, 3, 14-6, 20-1, 23, 173,205, 241;
128-9, 131-2, 134, 140, 152, 154, 178, unpacked, 5-7, 41, 78, 155, 161, 171
200-1, 248 scientific communication, 2, 4, 21-2, 34,
Quine, W., 6, 79 42-5, 48, 97, 140, 183-4, 186, 188,
210, 212, 222, 227, 247; clarity and,
Rachels, J., 211 80, 129, 154, 171, 185, 241, 250, 253-
Index 285
4, 256-7; to public, 156-7, 186, 211, 197, 230; See also philosophy of
214, 234-6, 242, 249-50 science
scientific documents, classification of, 8, Stump, D.J., 32, 100, 190
13, 44, 53, 62, ch. 7; faceted versus sufficiency, 73-4, 76, 81, 88, 132
enumerative, 219-20, 223, 229, 232; survey articles, 150, 229, 234-5, 237, 242,
thesauri and, 222, 226-7, 233; value 263
of, 8, 34, 92, 98, 184, 205, ch. 7, 242- survey method, 101, 104, 112, 116, 129-
3, 255 30, 135-6, 139, 141-3, 149, 152, 159
scientific values, 160, 164-5, 168, 170-1, Svenonius, E., 217, 238
182, 196-8 Swift, D.F., 218
Scriven, M., 6 symbolic interactionism, 54, 85, 91-2, 94
Seale, C., 18, 38, 62, 110, 112-4, 116, systems theory, 54, 87-90, 94
152-3, 170, 181, 206, 209 Szostak, R., 5, 7, 12, 16, 22, 25-6, 32-3,
selfish motives of scientists, 161-3, 177, 36, 41, 46, 59, 65, 72-3, 75-8, 80-1,
196-7 83, 88, 93, 144, 151, 164, 166, 168,
sexual orientation, 12, 27, 51, 166 174-5, 177, 179, 184, 187-8, 190, 193-
Shattuck, R., 261 4, 196, 201-2, 211, 214, 222, 231,
Shipman, M., 150, 157, 253 254-5, 259, 266
Silverman, D., 114, 129, 131, 209
Simonton, D., 188, 207 Tashakkori, A., 46-7, 50, 109-13, 148,
simulation, 126 151-2
Sin, S., 140 Taylor, C.A., 169
Singleton, R.A. Jr., 23, 32, 80, 99, 102-3, teaching, 9, 32-6, 97, 99, 101-2, 146-7,
106, 115, 119, 130, 142, 145, 150-2, 178, 181, 183, 234, 236-7, 243, 252,
265 258-68; lifelong learning, 35-6, 243,
Sklar, L., 47, 72 260, 264-5
Smiraglia, R.P., 229 technology, 25, 29, 58, 144, 174, 180,
social influences on science, 118, 165-6, 192, 263
168, 213, 246 Tessler, M., 141
social science, 40, 42, 56, 60, 97, 130, textual analysis, 102, 113, 129, 136-43,
151, 180; See also human science; 148, 175, 214-5
various disciplines theory, 4-6, 11, 19-22, 33, 37-41, 43, 45,
social structure, 24, 26, 29, 33, 36-7, 57- 47, ch. 3, 158, 163, 166-9, 173, 183-5,
8, 90, 267 187, 189-90, 195, 213-6, 218-9, 225-8,
sociology, 59-60, 80, 101, 105, 156, 162, 235, 262, 265; cluster, 72, 75-6, 89,
214, 229-30 98, 202, 244; defined, 51, 74-8, 98,
stability versus change, 72, 88-9, 128 244; desirability of flexibility in, 19,
statistical analysis, 102, 112, 130-4, 139- 34, 36, 58-60, 65, 67, 70-2, 78, 95-7,
43, 146, 148, 150-4, 179, 200-1, 203, 177-9, 181, 189, 204-8, 210, 214, 246-
213, 227, 229 7, 250; evaluating, 78-80, 97, 244;
Stake, R.E., 141, 153 generalizability, 40-1, 50, 68-71, 79,
Stanley, T.D., 154 91; grand, 34-6, 52-4, 75, 160, 243,
Stocklmayer, S.M., 186 250-1; interaction with method, 8, 64-
Stoner, N.W., 157 5, 78, 80, 100, 102-3, 106, 108, 115,
Storr, A., 165 117, 141, 148, 150, 178-9, 192, 199-
Strauss, A., 91 203, 208-12, 246; range of
structuralism, 54, 81-2, 84, 87, 89 applicability, 69, 75, 78-80, 85-6, 96,
study of science, 1-3, 8, 19, 32, 148, 156- 98, 100, 106-8, 114, 202, 205-6, 209,
8, 161-2, 167, 173, 181, 188, 191-3, 212, 218, 226, 242-4, 257; role in
definition of science, 170-2, 175;
286 Index
springeronline.com