0% found this document useful (0 votes)
13 views

How Seriously Should We Take Minimalist Syntax A C

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
13 views

How Seriously Should We Take Minimalist Syntax A C

Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 4

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/2570018

How seriously should we take Minimalist syntax? A comment on

Article · March 2003


Source: CiteSeer

CITATIONS READS

12 168

2 authors, including:

Morten H Christiansen
Cornell University
284 PUBLICATIONS   15,050 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

the Puzzle of Danish View project

Testing implicit statistical learning implicitly: A novel chunk-based measure of statistical learning View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Morten H Christiansen on 22 May 2013.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


How seriously should we take Minimalist syntax? A comment on
Lasnik
Shimon Edelman and Morten H. Christiansen
Department of Psychology
Uris Hall, Cornell University
Ithaca, NY 14853-7601, USA
{se37,mhc27}@cornell.edu

November 14, 2002

Lasnik’s review of the Minimalist program in syntax [1] offers cognitive scientists help in navigating
some of the arcana of the current theoretical thinking in transformational generative grammar. One may
observe, however, that this journey is more like a taxi ride gone bad than a free tour: it is the driver who
decides on the itinerary, and questioning his choice may get you kicked out. Meanwhile, the meter in the cab
of the generative theory of grammar is running, and has been since the publication of Chomsky’s Syntactic
Structures in 1957. The fare that it ran up is none the less daunting for the detours made in his Aspects of
Theory of Syntax in 1965, Government and Binding in 1981, and now The Minimalist Program, in 1995.
Paraphrasing Winston Churchill, it seems like never in the field of cognitive science was so much owed by
so many of us to so few (the generative linguists).
For most of us in the cognitive sciences this situation will appear quite benign (that is, if we don’t hold a
grudge for having been taken for a longer than necessary ride), if we realize that it is the generative linguists
who should by rights be paying this bill. The reason for that is simple and is well known in the philosophy of
science: putting forward a theory is like taking out a loan, to be repayed by gleaning an empirical basis for it;
theories that fail to do so (or their successors that may have bought their debts) are declared bankrupt. In the
sciences of the mind, this maxim translates into the need to demonstrate the psychological (behavioral), and,
eventually, the neurobiological, reality of the theoretical constructs. Many examples of this process can be
found in the study of human vision, where, as in language, direct observation of the underlying mechanisms
is difficult; for instance, the concept of multiple parallel spatial frequency channels, introduced in the late
1960s, was completely vindicated by purely behavioral means over the following decade; see, e.g., [2].
In linguistics, the nature of the requisite evidence is well described by Townsend and Bever: “What do
we test today if we want to explore the behavioral implications of syntax? . . . the psychological basis for
the two primary and ever-present operations, merge and move.” [3], p.82. Unfortunately, to our knowledge,
no experimental evidence has been offered to date that suggests that Merge and Move are real (in the same

1
sense as the spatial frequency channels in human vision are). Generative linguists typically respond to calls
for evidence for the reality of their theoretical constructs by claiming that no evidence is needed over and
above the theory’s ability to account for patterns of grammaticality judgments elicited from native speakers.
This response is unsatisfactory, on two accounts. First, such judgments are inherently unreliable because of
their unavoidable meta-cognitive overtones, because grammaticality is better described as a graded quantity,
as well as for a host of other reasons [4]. Second, the outcome of a judgment (or the analysis of an elicited
utterance) is invariably brought to bear on some distinction between variants of the current generative the-
ory, never on its foundational assumptions. Of the latter, the reality of Merge and Move is but one example;
the full list include assumptions about language being a “computationally perfect” system, the copy theory
of traces, the existence of Logical Form (LF) structures, and “innate general principles of economy”. Un-
fortunately, these foundational issues have been not been subjected to psychological investigations, in part
because it is not clear how to turn the assumptions into testable hypotheses.
Lasnik is optimistic that Minimalism, which is “as yet still just an ‘approach’, a conjecture about how
human language works (’perfectly’)”, can be developed into an “articulated theory of human linguistic
ability.” Such optimism would seem to require that the foundational issues be thoroughly addressed, but
to our surprise they are not on Lasnik’s list of “Questions for future research”. This may explain why
Minimalism is not even mentioned in recent reviews of and opinions on various aspects of language research
in this journal, ranging from sentence processing and production [5, 6, 7] and syntactic acquisition [8, 9] to
the brain mechanisms of syntactic comprehension [10, 11, 12]. We believe it would be in the best interests
of linguistics and of cognitive science in general if the linguists were to help psychologists like ourselves
to formulate and sharpen the really important foundational questions, and to address them experimentally.
This, we think, would help cognitive scientists take Minimalist syntax more seriously.

References
[1] H. Lasnik. The Minimalist Program in syntax. Trends in Cognitive Science, 6:432–437, 2002.

[2] H. R. Wilson and J. R. Bergen. A four mechanism model for threshold spatial vision. Vision Research,
19:19–32, 1979.

[3] D. J. Townsend and T. G. Bever. Sentence comprehension. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 2001.

[4] C. T. Schütze. The empirical base of linguistics: grammaticality judgments and linguistic methodol-
ogy. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, IL, 1996.

[5] E. Kako and L. Wagner. The semantics of syntactic structures. Trends in Cognitive Science, 5:102–108,
2001.

[6] M. J. Pickering and H. P. Branigan. Syntactic priming in language production. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 3:136–141, 1999.

2
View publication stats
[7] A. J. Sanford and P. Sturt. Depth of processing in language comprehension: not noticing the evidence.
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 6:382–386, 2002.

[8] R. L. Gómez and L. Gerken. Infant artificial language learning and language acquisition. Trends in
Cognitive Science, 6:178–186, 2002.

[9] M. Tomasello. The item-based nature of children’s early syntactic development. Trends in Cognitive
Science, 5:156–163, 2001.

[10] M. Kutas and K. D. Federmeier. Electrophysiology reveals semantic memory use in language compre-
hension. Trends in Cognitive Science, 4:463–470, 2000.

[11] A. D. Friederici. Towards a neural basis of auditory sentence processing. Trends in Cognitive Science,
6:78–84, 2002.

[12] E. Kaan and T. Y. Swaab. The brain circuitry of syntactic comprehension. Trends in Cognitive Science,
6:350–356, 2002.

You might also like