Good Design and Aesthetic - Lives Jeffrey Petts
Good Design and Aesthetic - Lives Jeffrey Petts
Source: The Journal of Aesthetic Education , Vol. 53, No. 2 (Summer 2019), pp. 1-18
Published by: University of Illinois Press
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
University of Illinois Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to The Journal of Aesthetic Education
Jeffrey Petts
1
Monroe Beardsley wrote that there would be no aesthetics if everyone was
silent about works of art.1 Similarly, there would be no philosophical aes-
thetics of design if no one ever talked critically about, but instead quietly
enjoyed or put up with, our built environment and things of everyday use.
But whereas Beardsley could draw on an established and distinct body of art,
music, and literary criticism to set the aims and scope of aesthetics, a similar
metacritical approach to the aesthetics of design has no directly equivalent
body of critical work. That’s not to say designed things aren’t objects of criti-
cal appraisal raising judgments of a distinctively aesthetic character. Charles
Rennie Mackintosh’s ladder-back chair was “designed to enhance the white
walls of the Hill House bedroom,” a house Mackintosh designed too, and
its “poise and elegance” suitably “contrasted with the spatial proportions of
the room.”2 A sampling of nominations for the UK Design Museum awards
reveals a range of products where “beauty” is part of the rationale for nomi-
nations, from a phone offering “an elegant and thoughtful aesthetic” to the
beauty of a vase, “the facets of which beautifully absorb and reflect ambient
light,” or a new “elegant but minimalist lounge chair, which reveals its com-
position and joinery.”3
But such aesthetic attributes and evaluations of furniture, interior design,
products, and buildings sit alongside other distinct judgments of them. So
a chair might be elegant but also meet demands that it be durable and easy
to stack, like Robin Day’s 1960s polypropylene chair.4 Design awards usu-
ally refer also to aesthetic considerations as one among several evaluative
criteria. So while the UK Design Museum’s annual award typically refers
to beauty or related aesthetic concepts, it always lists a range of criteria that
also include consideration of materials, functions, and cost. Similarly, the
Jeffrey Petts is an independent scholar based in London. His research centers on the
concept of work and its relations to art, design, workmanship, and everyday aesthetic
interests. He was awarded a PhD in philosophy from the University of York in 2013.
offer or support any overtly moral or political claims (even when seemingly
moral-political terms are being used, like “designing for freedom”).14 To reit-
erate: a metacritical approach to design takes what designers say about good
design in general seriously but also aims to understand what they mean by
the terms they typically use. The main claim I shall make is that, using terms
like “improvement,” “fit,” and “well-being,” they mean experiences of felt
rightness in our relationships with everyday things and experiences that are
explicable and open to public discussion, that is, ones of real value. In short,
their collective endeavor at good design is one aimed at aesthetic quality in
our everyday experiences of things and the built environment. Design edu-
cation, insofar as it concerns itself with the principles and practices of good
design, then, is properly also a de facto part of aesthetic education.
* * *
This aesthetic quality of good design is not to be conceived as a claim for
design’s “artistic” status, though, as an “art” apology for design, in other
words. Nor does it support some kind of formal “artistic” training for
designers.
It is as well at this stage to clear the philosophical ground of the supposed
artistic elements and aspirations of design work. Such a set of claims is a
common aestheticist prephilosophic intuition about design work, oppos-
ing a functionalist view. They are views too that occasionally find resonance
within the broad community of designers, marking a supposed fault line in
design practice between engineering and styling.15 The broadly functional
intuition understands design work as making things that fulfill their basic
function, requiring the appropriate problem-solving and engineering or
technical skills for that type of thing. The broadly aesthetic intuition under-
stands design work as a discrete activity concerned with giving functional
things a stylish “look and feel” or form and requiring broadly creative and
artistic skills. In other words, the functionalist intuition sees design as solv-
ing problems about how something will work, and its exemplary worker
is an engineer-designer; the aestheticist intuition sets any design problem
as one about a functional thing’s form and supposed aesthetic appeal and
designers are essentially thought of as creatives.
Critical thinking about the issue suggests that design’s artistry qua cre-
ativity is not intrinsic to design work or at best has a meaning that is unique
in the context of design. So Kees Dorst associates a certain kind of design
creativity with artistry, arguing that, where designers develop their own
goals and build these into projects, they “are something of artists.”16 Dorst
thus suggests that design’s supposed art status resides in the artfulness of
self-generated goals, rather than in some shared, transferable practical skills
or professional standards between designers and artists. For Dorst, the point
at which designers are artists is that at which they develop an individual
style, albeit one that is only enacted through the possibilities for creativity
set by design problems. But this means there is a key difference with art too:
while a designer’s goals are essentially set by others, because stakehold-
ers in the end product require a practical need to be met, artists set their
own goals. Norman Potter similarly argues that the key difference between
art and design work is in the freedom artists have to generate works.17 He
notes that a designer’s output, like models and drawings, are neither ends
in themselves nor the sole output of the designer’s vision but rather the out-
come of many discussions with clients and other stakeholders. These might
be procedures familiar to artists—especially those working on public or
other commissions, of course—but, still, the origins of artistic work are more
inward, so that “a painter’s first responsibility [unlike a designer’s] is to the
truth of his own vision.”18 Again in a similar vein to Dorst, Potter character-
izes design’s artistry in a “shared visual sensibility” or a designer’s having
a sense of style.19 But that does not direct us to any necessarily common
skills, procedures, or general aims for art and design. Creativity in design
may be evidenced by style, but that is not evidence of art. It marks imagi-
native, practical problem-solving. This becomes clearer when examples of
thinking about design work and its aims are examined (in the next section).
Still, design has its general freedom issue like art, but it typically centers on
its proper relation to advertising and marketing rather than to ideas about
artistic “true-to-self” authenticity. So, for example, Olga Gueft, a leading fig-
ure in twentieth-century American design and editor of Interiors for twenty
years, warned that “Madison Avenue pressures can oppress as tyrannically
as law,” referring to that area’s cluster of advertising agencies and their no-
holds-barred commercialism.20
* * *
As a final preliminary, it is worth noting that the metacritical approach
is distinct from recent interest in the concept of design in that it changes
philosophical focus to questions about good design.21 I do not seek to define
design or provide an ontology of design. But in seeking to establish good
design’s philosophical foundations, design’s distinctive contribution to aes-
thetic value is revealed.
This has broadly educative consequences too. First, the contribution of
metacriticism to design education is not to verify design principles and their
various applications, as expressed in statements about design in general by
practitioners. Rather, it explains how these statements represent overarch-
ing design ideas of fitness and related terms that are essentially aesthetic
in character. Second, metacriticism of design statements thus contributes to
thinking about aesthetic education more generally by revealing the meaning
of good design’s key ideas and explaining how design works for improved,
flourishing aesthetic lives at personal, household, working, and social levels.
2
In the examples and analyses that follow, I aim to show that designers think
good designs culminate and are evidenced by a final aesthetic moment
when a design solution is tested and experienced as just right and being fit
for purpose. Designers reflecting on design give this aesthetic characteriza-
tion central importance in their apologies for it, whether explicitly or not.
But they do so in different ways.
The statements examined here are categorized and chosen to show varia-
tions in the way in which aesthetic fit as an overarching design value or
apology is envisaged. I suggest three broad, distinct categories. The first
category covers the way designers think about the personal experience of
using particular things; the second examines how designers conceive the
individual’s experience of the aesthetic value or beauty of their everyday
domestic lives; and the third covers claims designers make about designing
communities that support the good life. Each category supports the gen-
eral thesis that apologies for design are essentially about improving human
experiential life in explicably aesthetic terms.
all are “about how people have attempted to shape their environments.”63
Such doubts are assuaged further if other statements about good design are
in mind, like those examined here, which relate aesthetic quality in the built
environment to the good life generally.
3
We can conclude from this, albeit introductory, metacriticism that apologies
for design are variations of a broad aesthetic functionalism about design’s
general value. In summary, aesthetic functionalism about design amounts
to a cluster of criteria about its value as an activity around meeting needs
in fitting ways that improve practical life, adding things of beauty, of aes-
thetic value, to everyday lives, and creating built environments that aid the
good life.
I conclude with some thoughts on how aesthetic functionalism about
design’s value as an activity might support existing developmental views
of the nature of the aesthetic and, in turn, contribute to the concept of aes-
thetic education. Paul Guyer notes that a general developmental view of
the aesthetic argues that aesthetic experience has a value beyond discrete
moments of felt pleasure and aesthetic evaluation. In short, aesthetic inter-
est and experience have an educative role in life more generally. So he notes
theorists who acknowledge that aesthetic interest allows us to develop our
imaginative and cognitive capacities but who additionally value it “because
of the benefits the development of these capacities can bring to the rest of
our lives.”64
This general developmental view of the aesthetic—arguing for its impact
on the “rest of our lives” or its educational value—is evident in different
theoretical idioms. I will briefly note three and how design’s aesthetic func-
tionalism accords with each. They are John Dewey’s pragmatic account of
human adaptation, the expansive view of the aesthetic field argued by the
everyday aesthetics movement, and the broadly social view of the signifi-
cance of the aesthetic in the tradition of Friedrich Schiller.
design, then, has an aesthetic quality that is, in Deweyan terms, “internal”
to its work, properly done. It is not an “external and partial” producer–
consumer relation or a commercial exercise.68 Rather, good design, by its
aesthetic quality, is not determined by such externals but is indicated as a
consummatory human experience of things. We experience things as “hav-
ing their own internal functional adaptations” that “fit in a way that yields
aesthetic results.”69 In the round, good design is part of the everyday inte-
gration of the live human creature with her environment. As such, designers
contribute in unique ways, by their focus on everyday things, to the stock
of aesthetic value in the world. It is worth noting too that Dewey sees this
threatened, and not just by external commercial factors, by what he calls
“mechanical production,” which he regards as anathema to aesthetic qual-
ity. Yet industrial conditions of production can, he thinks, be manipulated
to aesthetic ends by thinking about products’ “efficient use,” for example,
by removing “silly encumbering ornamentations.”70 So, ultimately, Dewey’s
developmental aesthetics sits four-square with aesthetic functionalism about
design, especially fundamental ideas about needs and aesthetic fit, summed
up by his general contention, albeit in the context of industrial design, that
“aesthetic revolution [is] brought about by better adaptation to need.”71
Dewey goes on to suggest that this “revolution” extends from products
themselves to how production, including, of course, design work, generally
is organized: “No permanent solution [to the absence of aesthetic quality
in artifacts] is possible save in a radical social alteration, which effects the
degree and kind of participation the worker has in the production and social
disposition of the wares he produces.”72
Everyday Aesthetics
The everyday aesthetics movement is developmental in its commitment to
ideas about the extensive range of opportunities for aesthetic interest and
experience and their value.73 It challenges what it perceives as the Western
art-centered bias of philosophical aesthetics and also disputes the idea of
aesthetic experience as essentially a disinterested encounter with artworks,
arguing for accounts of aesthetic experience that acknowledge its active and
practical nature. Yuriko Saito, for example, argues for a divided aesthetics
between that of art and of the everyday, between disinterested aesthetic
experience of artworks and active aesthetic involvement with the everyday,
with design in the “everyday” camp. She argues that a significant part of
that active everyday experience should be a “green aesthetics” in design-
ing artifacts.74 The general point, however, remains that something about
design work as an activity enriches our aesthetics lives and is also signifi-
cant because “engagements with everyday objects and environments far
exceeds interaction with art.”75 So, in Saito’s everyday aesthetics, we see an
aesthetics-society nexus suggested: “Everyday aesthetic tastes and attitudes
* * *
In summary, aesthetic functionalism about design endorses and deepens
the developmental understanding, in its various idioms, of the role of the
aesthetic in our everyday lives. It shows how good design is an integral
part of the concept of aesthetic education. And placing statements about
design work in general in the context of developmental aesthetics deepens
our understanding of them.
Notes