Micro Economics
Micro Economics
Prepared by:
Fernando Quijano, Illustrator
If I believe that my competitors are rational and act to maximize their own
payoffs, how should I take their behavior into account when making my
decisions?
Now Firm A has no dominant strategy. Its optimal decision depends on what
Firm B does. If Firm B advertises, Firm A does best by advertising; but if Firm B
does not advertise, Firm A also does best by not advertising.
Dominant Strategies: I’m doing the best I can no matter what you do.
You’re doing the best you can no matter what I do.
Nash Equilibrium: I’m doing the best I can given what you are doing.
You’re doing the best you can given what I am doing.
In this game, each firm is indifferent about which product it produces—so long as it does
not introduce the same product as its competitor. The strategy set given by the bottom left-
hand corner of the payoff matrix is stable and constitutes a Nash equilibrium: Given the
strategy of its opponent, each firm is doing the best it can and has no incentive to deviate.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 7 of 47
THE BEACH LOCATION GAME
FIGURE 13.1
BEACH LOCATION GAME
You (Y) and a competitor (C) plan to sell soft drinks on a beach.
If sunbathers are spread evenly across the beach and will walk to the closest vendor, the
two of you will locate next to each other at the center of the beach. This is the only Nash
equilibrium.
If your competitor located at point A, you would want to move until you were just to the
left, where you could capture three-fourths of all sales.
But your competitor would then want to move back to the center, and you would do the
same.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 8 of 47
Maximin Strategies
Prisoner B
Confess Don’t confess
Dominant strategies are also maximin strategies. The outcome in which both
prisoners confess is both a Nash equilibrium and a maximin solution. Thus, in a
very strong sense, it is rational for each prisoner to confess.
MATCHING PENNIES
In this game, each player chooses heads or tails and the two players reveal
their coins at the same time. If the coins match Player A wins and receives a
dollar from Player B. If the coins do not match, Player B wins and receives a
dollar from Player A.
Note that there is no Nash equilibrium in pure strategies for this game. No
combination of heads or tails leaves both players satisfied—one player or the
other will always want to change strategies.
Jim
Wrestling Opera
Wrestling 2, 1 0, 0
Prisoner A
Opera 0, 0 1, 2
There are two Nash equilibria in pure strategies for this game—the one in
which Jim and Joan both watch mud wrestling, and the one in which they both
go to the opera. This game also has an equilibrium in mixed strategies: Joan
chooses wrestling with probability 2/3 and opera with probability 1/3, and Jim
chooses wrestling with probability 1/3 and opera with probability 2/3.
Should we expect Jim and Joan to use these mixed strategies? Unless they’re
very risk loving or in some other way a strange couple, probably not. By
agreeing to either form of entertainment, each will have a payoff of at least 1,
which exceeds the expected payoff of 2/3 from randomizing.
Suppose this game is repeated over and over again—for example, you and
your competitor simultaneously announce your prices on the first day of every
month. Should you then play the game differently?
TIT-FOR-TAT STRATEGY
In the pricing problem above, the repeated game strategy that works best is the
tit-for-tat strategy.
Was it really to “help reduce fare confusion”? No, the aim was to reduce price
competition and achieve a collusive pricing arrangement. Prices had been driven
down by competitive undercutting, as airlines competed for market share. The
plan failed, a victim of the prisoners’ dilemma.
Suppose that both firms, in ignorance of each other’s intentions, must announce
their decisions independently and simultaneously. In that case, both will probably
introduce the sweet cereal—and both will lose money. In a sequential game, Firm
1 introduces a new cereal, and then Firm 2 introduces one.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 19 of 47
The Extensive Form of a Game
FIGURE 13.2
PRODUCE CHOICE GAME IN EXTENSIVE FORM
Although this outcome can be deduced from the payoff matrix in Table 13.9,
sequential games are sometimes easier to visualize if we represent the
possible moves in the form of a decision tree.
To find the solution to the extensive form game, work backward from the end.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 20 of 47
The Advantage of Moving First
As in Chapter 12, we will use the example in which two duopolists face
the market demand curve 𝑃 = 30 − 𝑄.
If both firms move simultaneously, the only solution to the game is that both
produce 10 and earn 100. In this Cournot equilibrium each firm is doing the
best it can given what its competitor is doing.
Compared to the Cournot outcome, when Firm 1 moves first, it does better—
and Firm 2 does much worse.
In this section, we’ll consider what determines which firm goes first. We will
focus on the following question: What actions can a firm take to gain advantage
in the marketplace?
Recall that in the Stackelberg model, the firm that moved first gained an
advantage by committing itself to a large output. Making a commitment—
constraining its future behavior—is crucial.
If Firm 2 knows that Firm 1 will respond by reducing the output that it first
announced, Firm 2 would produce a large output. . The only way that Firm 1
can gain a first-mover advantage is by committing itself. In effect, Firm 1
constrains Firm 2’s behavior by constraining its own behavior.
Firm 1 must constrain its own behavior in some way that convinces Firm 2 that
Firm 1 has no choice but to produce the sweet cereal. Firm 1 might launch an
expensive advertising campaign, or contract for the forward delivery of a large
quantity of sugar (and make the contract public).
Firm 1 can’t simply threaten Firm 2 because Firm 2 has little reason to believe
the threat—and can make the same threat itself. A threat is useful only if it is
credible.
As long as Firm 1 charges a high price for its computers, both firms can make a
good deal of money. Firm 1 would prefer the outcome in the upper left-hand
corner of the matrix. For Firm 2, however, charging a low price is clearly a
dominant strategy. Thus the outcome in the upper right-hand corner will prevail
(no matter which firm sets its price first).
Can Firm 1 induce Firm 2 to charge a high price by threatening to charge a low
price if Firm 2 charges a low price? No. Whatever Firm 2 does, Firm 1 will be
much worse off if it charges a low price. As a result, its threat is not credible.
Here we have a sequential game in which Race Car is the “leader.” Race Car
will do best by deciding to produce small cars. It knows that in response to this
decision, Far Out will produce small engines, most of which Race Car will then
buy. Can Far Out induce Race Car to produce big cars instead of small ones?
Suppose Far Out threatens to produce big engines. If Race Car believed Far
Out’s threat, it would produce big cars. But the threat is not credible. Far Out
can make its threat credible by visibly and irreversibly reducing some of its own
payoffs in the matrix, thereby constraining its own choices. It might do this by
shutting down or destroying some of its small engine production capacity. This
would result in the payoff matrix shown in Table 13.12(b).
Now Race Car knows that whatever kind of car it produces, Far Out will
produce big engines. Now it is clearly in Race Car’s interest to produce large
cars. By taking an action that seemingly puts itself at a disadvantage, Far Out
has improved its outcome in the game.
Although strategic commitments of this kind can be effective, they are risky and
depend heavily on having accurate knowledge of the payoff matrix and the
industry. Suppose, for example, that Far Out commits itself to producing big
engines but is surprised to find that another firm can produce small engines at
a low cost. The commitment may then lead Far Out to bankruptcy rather than
continued high profits.
Developing the right kind of reputation can also give one a strategic advantage.
In gaming situations, the party that is known (or thought) to be a little crazy can
have a significant advantage. Developing a reputation can be an especially
important strategy in a repeated game.
A firm might find it advantageous to behave irrationally for several plays of the
game. This might give it a reputation that will allow it to increase its long-run
profits substantially.
Through the 1960s, the conventional wisdom held that a discount store could
succeed only in a city with a population of 100,000 or more. Sam Walton
disagreed and decided to open his stores in small Southwestern towns.
This game has two Nash equilibria—the lower left-hand corner and the upper
right-hand corner. Which equilibrium results depends on who moves first.
The trick, therefore, is to preempt—to set up stores in other small towns quickly,
before Company X (or Company Y or Z) can do so. That is exactly what Wal-Mart
did. By 1986, it had 1009 stores in operation and was earning an annual profit of
$450 million. And while other discount chains were going under, Wal-Mart
continued to grow. By 1999, Wal-Mart had become the world’s largest retailer,
with 2454 stores in the United States and another 729 stores in the rest of the
world, and had annual sales of $138 billion.
In recent years, Wal-Mart has continued to preempt other retailers by opening
new discount stores, warehouse stores (such as Sam’s Club), and combination
discount and grocery stores (Wal-Mart Supercenters) all over the world.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 30 of 47
13.7 Entry Deterrence
To deter entry, the incumbent firm must convince any potential
competitor that entry will be unprofitable.
TABLE 13.16 (a) ENTRY POSSIBILITIES
Potential Entrant
Enter Stay out
If Firm X thinks you will be accommodating and maintain a high price after it
has entered, it will find it profitable to enter and will do so.
Suppose you threaten to expand output and wage a price war in order to keep
X out. If X takes the threat seriously, it will not enter the market because it can
expect to lose $10 million. The threat, however, is not credible. As Table
13.16(a) shows, once entry has occurred, it will be in your best interest to
accommodate and maintain a high price. Firm X’s rational move is to enter the
market; the outcome will be the upper left-hand corner of the matrix.
If Boeing has a head start in the development process, the outcome of the game
is the upper right-hand corner of the payoff matrix.
European governments, of course, would prefer that Airbus produce the new
aircraft. Can they change the outcome of this game? Suppose they commit to
subsidizing Airbus and make this commitment before Boeing has committed itself
to produce. If the European governments commit to a subsidy of 20 to Airbus if it
produces the plane regardless of what Boeing does, the payoff matrix would
change to the one in Table 13.17(b).
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 34 of 47
TABLE 13.17(b) DEVELOPMENT OF AIRCRAFT AFTER
EUROPEAN SUBSIDY
Airbus
Produce Don’t produce
Boeing knows that even if it commits to producing, Airbus will produce as well,
and Boeing will lose money. Thus Boeing will decide not to produce, and the
outcome will be the one in the lower left-hand corner.
A subsidy of 20, then, changes the outcome from one in which Airbus does not
produce and earns 0, to one in which it does produce and earns 120. Of this, 100
is a transfer of profit from the United States to Europe. From the European point
of view, subsidizing Airbus yields a high return. European governments did
commit to subsidizing Airbus, and during the 1980s, Airbus successfully
introduced several new airplanes.
As commercial air travel grew, it became clear that both companies could
profitably develop and sell new airplanes. Nonetheless, Boeing’s market share
would have been much larger without the European subsidies to Airbus.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 35 of 47
EXAMPLE 13.5 DUPONT DETERS ENTRY IN THE TITANIUM DIOXIDE
INDUSTRY
In the early 1970s, DuPont and National Lead each accounted for about a third of
U.S. titanium dioxide sales. In 1972, DuPont was considering whether to expand
capacity. New regulations and higher expected input prices would give DuPont a
cost advantage. Because of these cost changes, DuPont anticipated that National
Lead and some other producers would have to shut down part of their capacity.
DuPont’s competitors would in effect have to “reenter” the market by building new
plants. Could DuPont deter them from taking this step?
DuPont considered the following strategy: invest nearly $400 million in increased
production capacity—much more than what was actually needed. The idea was to
deter competitors from investing.
Scale economies and movement down the learning curve would not only make it
hard for other firms to compete, but would make credible the implicit threat that in
the future, DuPont would fight rather than accommodate.
By 1975, however, things began to go awry. Demand grew by much less than
expected, and environmental regulations were only weakly enforced, so
competitors did not have to shut down capacity as expected. Finally, DuPont’s
strategy led to antitrust action by the Federal Trade Commission in 1978. The
FTC claimed that DuPont was attempting to monopolize the market. DuPont won
the case, but the decline in demand made its victory moot.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 36 of 47
EXAMPLE 13.6 DIAPER WARS
Auctions are used for differentiated products, especially unique items that don’t
have established market values, such as art, antiques, sports memorabilia and
the rights to extract oil from a piece of land.
Auctions create large savings in transaction costs and thereby increases the
efficiency of the market.
The design of an auction, which involves choosing the rules under which it
operates, greatly affects its outcome. A seller will usually want an auction
format that maximizes the revenue from the sale of the product. On the other
hand, a buyer collecting bids from a group of potential sellers will want an
auction that minimizes the expected cost of the product.
● first-price auction Auction in which the sales price is equal to the highest
bid.
● second-price auction Auction in which the sales price is equal to the
second-highest bid.
● common-value auction Auction in which the item has the same value to
all bidders, but bidders do not know that value precisely and their estimates of it
vary.
To avoid the winner’s curse, you must reduce your maximum bid below your
value estimate by an amount equal to the expected error of the winning bidder.
The more precise your estimate, the less you need to reduce your bid. The
winner’s curse is more likely to be a problem in a sealed-bid auction than in a
traditional English auction.
Copyright © 2013 Pearson Education, Inc. • Microeconomics • Pindyck/Rubinfeld, 8e. 42 of 47
Maximizing Auction Revenue
Here are some useful tips for choosing the best auction format.
1. In a private-value auction, you should encourage as many bidders as
possible.
2. In a common-value auction, you should (a) use an open rather than a sealed-
bid auction because, as a general rule, an English (open) common-value auction
will generate greater expected revenue than a sealed-bid auction; and (b) reveal
information about the true value of the object being auctioned.
3. In a private-value auction, set a minimum bid equal to or even somewhat
higher than the value to you of keeping the good for future sale.
In a common-value auction, the greater the uncertainty about the true value of
the object, the greater the likelihood of an overbid, and therefore the greater the
incentive for the bidder to reduce his bid.
In the United States, plaintiff attorneys often bring cases in which they represent
classes of individuals who were allegedly harmed by defendants’ actions that
adversely affect human health or well-being. The attorneys are typically paid on a
contingent fee basis, which means they are paid nothing if they lose the case, or a
percentage of the amount recovered, typically around 30%.
In some cases, the percentage fee awards have been seen as unreasonably large
relative to the efforts made by the attorneys. What could be done about this? A
number of federal judges had a solution: hold auctions in which attorneys bid for
the right to represent the class of potential plaintiffs.
In a typical such auction, attorneys would offer a percentage fee as part of a
sealed-bid process.
In one unusual auction following on a criminal verdict against auction houses
Sotheby’s and Christie’s, Judge Lewis Kaplan of the Southern District of New York
allowed law firms to offer a broader range of payment terms as part of their bids. It
turned out that the winning bidder was the law firm of Boies, Schiller & Flexner.
Months after taking the case, David Boies settled with defendants for $512 million,
earning the attorneys a $26.75 million fee (25 percent of the $107 million excess
over the minimum of $425 million) and generating just over $475 million for
members of the class.
Internet auctions are subject to very strong network externalities. Both sellers and
buyers gravitate to the auction site with the largest market share. In China, eBay
had to compete with Taobao, whose managers decided not to charge sellers any
commissions, so that most of its revenue was from advertising. While its revenue
was limited by this strategy, Taobao quickly became the dominant Internet auction
site in China. And eBay likewise lost out in Japan, this time to Yahoo! Japan
Auctions, which aggressively obtained an early market share lead. The strong
network effect then made it nearly impossible for eBay (or anyone else) to
challenge Yahoo!’s dominance in Japan.