ADA168207
ADA168207
IIEEEEEEEEEEEE
IIflflfllflflflf
EEEEEEEEE
mini
LI M
1 2 4 01.
1160''*~ -
-i - -" -
p I 'II'
p ~. ~. .
pt
CHA.
MICRCOPYRESOUTIN TFSI
. .. . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . . ... . ,Ji', t, .
-Lo
" "
-- .- -- .
i*.j
... 44
BETWEEN HOPE AND FEAR:
0 THE PSYCHOLOGY OF RISK
00
LOLA L. LOPES
READ INSTRUCTIONS
REPORT DOCMENTATION PAGE BEFORE COMPLETING FORM
. REPORT NUMBER 2. VT ACC No N
. CATALOG NUMBER
WHIFF 24 .y40!s
4. TITLE (ad Subtitle) S. TYPE OF REPORT G PERIOD COVERED
Arlington, VA 22217 61
14. MONITORING AGENCY NAME • AODRESS(If different from Controlling Office) IS. SECURITY CLASS. (of thle report)
Unclassified
ISa. DECLASSIFICATION/DOWNGRADING
SCHEDULE ,,-.**
17. DISTRIBUTION STATEMENT (of the abstirac ntered in Block 20. It different tram Report)
IS. KEY WORDS (Continue on reverse sde If necessar and Identify by block number)
risk.
decision making_,
motivation,
20. ABSTRACT (Continue on reverse side If neceesary and Identify by block number)
%, .''
%-7 " PI"
6 _Unclassified
Wcumyrv cLAmnCATMW oF T pAeC CMW D", -ih4
44
Sr I.
.1.
Lola L. Lopes
Department of Psychology
University of Wisconsin
Madison, Wisconsin
"-....
In press:
Advances in Experimental Social PsycholQyv
Aceeson Fo.
NT I.
D)TIC TA~
. . -- - "
Justl'["'
Dislri '
,°- .
OIALITY
NSPECTILOj
30
a ~% .****. ~ ' -U
Psychology of Risk / 2
(Contents)
I. Introduction
A. The Experimentalist's View
B. The Personologist's View
II. Psychophysical Versus Motivational Theories of Risk
A. The Role of Cognition
B. Risk-Taking Reconsidered
OleI
".°.
,'"""'- - '..
","%
.'.v"".."..
.v .' . . . ."-".. . .,, "v, -" ,-".
. -'.v.v. .. ..,... ..,." ,. ."-
.,,&,[. -, ..,..,,, , ", "U'-'
_ _,'...x,"
Psychology of Risk / 3
Most things begin to look a little funny if you stare at them long
enough. So too the psychology of risk. What is most disconcerting is that
there is so much theory for so little substance. Countless hours have been
spent by psychologists and economists alike in trying to explain theoretically
why people buy both lottery tickets and insurance. Lottery tickets cost a
dollar. One. We buy insurance (when we can afford it) so that we can sleep
better. Is it really so strange that we should want to buy both?
This article is about risk: what risk is (if it is any thing at all);
how people think about it; what they feel about it; and what they do about it.
The article is also about how psycholoqists think about risk: how they study
it; what tasks they use; what factors they vary; and what models they build
(or borrow) to describe people's behavior.
L.
Psychology of Risk / 4
potential return with "risk," a construct that is most often identified with
variability in the outcome distribution. For example, Coombs's (1975)
"portfolio theory" is based on the premise that choices among risks reflect a
compromise between maximizing expected value and achieving an individually
determined ideal level of risk. Thus, investors who prefer low risk must
accept the lower but safer returns associated with bonds whereas investors who
prefer more risk can opt for the higher but less safe returns of stocks and
commodities.
The first use of the utility concept was made by Daniel Bernoulli in
1738. He argued that the value of money is not absolute, but depends on how
much one has already: "Any increase in wealth, no matter how insignificant,
will always result in an increase in utility which is inversely proportionate
to the quantity of goods already possessed" (Bernoulli 1967, p. 25). This
view implies that a constant gain, say $1000, will be worth more subjectively
to a poor person than a rich person. It also implies that subjective
differences between amounts of money that differ by a constant get smaller as
the absolute magnitudes of the amounts get larger. In other words, there's
more difference psychologically between $1,000 and $2,000, say, than betweeen
$10,000 and $11,000. In Bernoullian terms, money has marqinally decreasing
utility (which is short for saying that the subjective value of constant
increments gets smaller and smaller). In mathematical terms, the utility
function (which relates the objective value of money to its subjective value)
is negatively accelerated. An example of a negatively accelerated utility
function is shown in the upper left quadrant of Figure 1.
(Markowitz, 1959; Williams, 1966; Kahneman & Tversky, 1979). For example,
many people would prefer to face an 80% chance of losing $4,000 than to lose
$3,000 for sure even though the expected value of the risky loss ($3,200) is
greater than the sure loss.
This is a task in risky choice (even though the probabilities are only
roughly known) because subjects are choosing among alternative actions that
have the character of gambles. One can choose (and some do) to stand near the
peg in which case the probability is high, but the personal satisfaction in
getting the ring over the peg is small. Alternatively, one can stand further
back in which case the probability is smaller but the satisfaction is greater.
One can even choose a long shot (literally) in which the probability is
virtually nil, but the potential satisfaction is enormous. (Consider the
People who are low in Ms, however, especially if they are also high in
M , more often stand either very near or very far from the peg. Either way,
tAse people reduce their performance anxiety by virtually guaranteeing that
they will experience either the tepid success of a trivial accomplishment or
the denatured failure of not doing something that can't be done anyway except
by sheer good luck.
The gamble task and the ring toss task appear to have little in common,
but they are alike structurally. In each case the subject chooses among
alternative options, each of which can be characterized by the probabilities
and values that are attached to uncertain outcomes. In fact, one can with
some justice interpret subjects' choices in the ring toss task as maximizing
expected utility (cf. J. Atkinson, 1958). But there are profound differences
in the theoretical mechanisms that have been used to explain subjects' choices
in these two tasks.
-- ~ * S.,
+, ,. -++ jl.+ll.
, i ***-*_ *-* -- 9 * * ), * * * "
Psychology of Risk / 7
The same can be said for theories in which objective probabilities are
replaced by subjective probabilities or by probability weights. In fact,
Kahneman and Tversky (1984) have referred to their decision weight function as
reflecting the "psychophysics of chances" (p. 344). Their decision weights
are assumed to differ from objective probabilities due to factors that are
like those found in perception. For example, category-boundary effects make a
change from impossibility to possibility (or from possibility to certainty)
seem larger than a comparable change in the middle of the scale. This is the
same sort of thing that happens in the "categorical perception" of human
speech. Sounds that actually change in equal acoustic increments from an
ideal "ba" to an ideal "da" are perceived to shift abruptly from sounding like
clear ba's to sounding like clear da's (Liberman, Harris, Hoffman, & Griffith,
1957).
If they stand too close to the peg, they are much more likely to
throw the ring on.. .but they are less likely to get any feelings of
achievement satisfaction from doing so. If they stand too far away,
they are both much less likely to succeed and more likely to regard
success as "luck," than if they stand a moderate distance from the
peg. In fact, they are behaving like the businessman who acts
neither traditionally (no risk) nor like a gambler (extreme risk),
but who chooses to operate in a way in which he is most likely to
get achievement satisfaction (moderate risk, in this case about one
chance in three of succeeding) (p. 212).
There are many places in McClelland's account where one could evoke
psychophysical mechanisms to explain why children make different choices:
they might attach different subjective values to success at different
distances; or they might assign different probabilities to succeeding at a
given distance; they might even differ in the way they perceive distances.
But this is not how achievement theorists explain things. McClelland is
careful to rule out such factors. For example, he acknowledges that children
who are high in achievement motivation tend to perceive their probability of
success more favorably than children with low achievement motivation,
particularly when there is no evidence one way or the other. However, when
they have reasonable knowledge based on past performance, they use that
knowledge appropriately and do not display a greater perceived probability of
success than children who are low in achievement motivation. In his words,
achievement motivated children "are not impractical 'dreamers' overestimating
their success at everything; instead they rely on facts so far as they are
available, and then fall back on generalized self-confidence" (McClelland,
1961, p. 223).
One can also examine the possibility that achievement motivated children
simply place higher subjective value on success by looking at their
preferences in games of pure chance. In this situation they clearly prefer
V -- * . ~ . . . - .. . . . . . . . . . . .
Psychology of Risk / 8
the shortest odds they can get (the safest bets) followed by intermediate
values. Children with low achievement motivation, on the other hand, tend to
like long shots that offer large prizes, but at small probability (McClelland,
1961).
A. 7 e Role of Cognition
We have, then, two different approaches to explaining risky choice, one
primarily psychophysical and the other primarily motivational. The theories
differ also in the degree to which they are coQnitive. The motivational
theories have strong cognitive components. In order to choose appropriately,
task difficulty must be analyzed for the relative contributions of skill and
chance, past experience must be marshalled and used to assess probabilities,
goals must be set and future feelings predicted about what will be satisfying
and what not. Thus, it is motivation that incites action and gives it
direction (i.e., approach or avoidance), but it is cognition that guides
action to its intended goal.
Psychophysical theories, on the other hand, have not been couched in
cognitive terms, although they certainly might be. One could, for example,
justify a Bernoullian utility function in terms of Maslow's (1954) notion of a
need hierarchy. On this view, $1,000 really is worth more to a poor person
than a rich person because the poor person will spend the money to satisfy
more basic needs (food, shelter) whereas the rich person will spend it on more
transcendent needs (operas, electronic running shoes). Likewise, people's
tendency to treat small probabilities as zero might be justified cognitively
in terms of th, degree to which small probabilities can be expected to produce
discernable impacts on how we choose to live our daily lives. This was done,
in fact, by the early probabilist, Buffon, who urged that all probabilities
less than .0001 be treated as "morally" (which is to say, psychologically)
equal to zero (Daston, 1980).
7
-~ -7 -7 - LITlK w-Tx winu TV WV NV-- -7 . 4. -. 7. W -7
Psychology of Risk / 9
B. Risk-Taking Recnsidered
S %~
.. ~ ig . . ~ .. . * * *-.. -..- * . . . . . •. •j.. . .-.- o|
Psychology of Risk / 11
All the lotteries in the figure are "gain" lotteries which means that
their prizes are all > 0. Loss lotteries were also used in some of the
experiments. Loss lotteries are just like gain lotteries except that their
outcomes are negative. Thus, for example, the long shot for losses has 31
tickets that each lose zero, 22 tickets that each lose $49, and so forth down
to 1 ticket that loses $439. Likewise, the riskless loss lottery guarantees a
riskless (sure) loss of at least $70.
Three kinds of task have been used. In the most common task subjects
were shown pairs of lotteries in all possible combinations and asked which
they would prefer if they were allowed a free draw from either (Lopes, 1984,
Experiments 1 and 2; Schneider & Lopes, in press). Pair-preference data can
be used to infer preference orders over the entire set of stimuli. The second
kind of task involved judgments of riskiness also expressed in pair-choices
(Lopes, 1984, Experiments 3 through 6). These can be used to infer risk
orders (which are not the same as preference orders except for risk averse
people). The third kind of task (Lopes, 1986) was embedded in a standard
pair-preference task. Subjects were shown pairs of lotteries and asked to
express their preferences for each. For a subset, however, they were also
asked to explain their preferences in writing. These written protocols were
collected for a group of 14 graduate students from a variety of departments.
In order to avoid the known pitfalls of retrospective reports (Ericsson &
Simon, 1980), the protocols were obtained directly at the point of choice.
'
." " . t . . * . *. . .
..-- . . .. . . . . . ." - f. ..
Psychology of Risk / 12
The idea that risk is a function of shape has been proposed both for
theories of risk perception (Luce, 1980; Pollatsek & Tversky, 1970) and for
theories of risk preference (Allais, 1979; Coombs, 1975; Hagen, 1969;
Markowitz, 1959). In these theories, shape is identified with the statistical
moments of the distributions, particularly mean, variance, and skewness
Variance is generally considered to be bad (i.e., risky) whereas positive
skewness (a predominance of low outcomes with a few high outcomes) has been
identified with hope and negative skewness (a predominance of high outcomes
with a few low outcomes) has been identified with fear (Hagen, 1969). In this
view preference for the short shot over the long shot would be interpreted as
.. due to the short shot's much lower variance. Likewise, preference for the
riskless lottery over the short shot would be interpreted as a preference for
positive skewness since these lotteries have equal variance.
Moments models have several virtues, not the least of which is that any
distribution can be described, in principle, to any desired level of precision ,
by a sufficiently large set of its moments. But they also have major
difficulties. Some of these are technical as, for instance, 5 the fact that,
subjectively speaking, risk doesn't really act like variance . More serious,
however, is that such theories implicitly assume that moments have independent
psychological reality. That seems doubtful except for the simplest
comparisons. It is not all that easy to intuit the relative variance of
.. lotteries that differ in skewness (e.g, the peaked lottery versus the short
shot) except when the differences are very great (e.g., the peaked lottery
versus the long shot).
In the present theory, lotteries are represented by cumulative graphs
called Lorenz curves that are used in economics to show how wealth is
distributed among people. Welfare economists find them useful for saying
things like "The poorest 20% of the population in Country X have less of their
country's wealth than the poorest 20% in Country Y." What is relevant for us
is that subjects tend to talk as though they also view lotteries in cumulative
terms. Here, for example, are reasons given by three typically risk averse
subjects for why, in a forced choice between the short shot and the long shot,
they prefer the short shot (Lopes, 1986):
I'd rather have greater chances of winning a little something than
greater chances for nothing. The triple jackpot [in the long shot]
doesn't make me want to go for it cuz the odds are too great.
(Subject #10)
losing and the best odds indicate a good chance of winning $71 or
more. The [long shot] has too many opportunities to lose -- it is
too risky. (Subject #7)
In the [long shot], 32% do better than the best in the [short shot],
but 31% get nothing at all. The [short shot] is the better risk.
(Subject #14)
The chance for winning nothing is small with the [short shot] but
since the dollar amount in the [long shot] is attractive I run the
risk of losing and go for the [long shot]. (Subject #12)
The top prize money of the [long shot] is better. You still have a
good chance of winning some money in the [long shot] as well as
having a shot at the top prize money. The in between prize money in
the [long shot] is not all that bad, and is greater than the top
prize money of the [short shot]. (Subject #9)
I'll take the added risks of losing it all or getting a lower number
for the chance of the higher prizes. Therefore I'll pick the [long
shot]. (Subject #11)
,.o
"V
Psychology of Risk / 14
The Lorenz curve is plotted at the right. The abscissa gives the
cumulative probability (column 3) and the ordinate gives the cumulative
proportion of prize money (column 7). Notice that the Lorenz curve runs from
the lower left (the low or "bad" end of the curve representing tickets with
small prizes) to the upper right (the high or "good" end of the curve
representing tickets with big prizes). If every ticket in the lottery were a
$100 sure thing, the Lorenz curve would fall on the diagonal. To the extent
that the tickets have unequal prizes, the Lorenz curve bows away from the
diagonal.
Figure 4 gives the Lorenz curves for the long shot and the short shot.
Notice that the curve for the long shot lies everywhere below the curve for
the short shot. This is the sign of large relative dispersion. The long
shot's several large outcomes (indicated by the steepness of the curve at the
upper end) must be paid for by its many zero and small outcomes (indicated by
the flatness of the curve at the lower end). The Lorenz curve for the short
shot, on the other hand, lies nearer the diagonal since it has no really large
outcomes and only a few small outcomes. These considerations lead directly to
a simple rule for choosing between lotteries: people who want to avoid the
wors outcomes should prefer lotteries whose Lorenz curves lie near the
diagonal at the low end (stippled area at lower left), and people who want to
have a go at the best outcomes (at least as good a go as can be gotten) should
prefer lotteries whose Lorenz curves lie far from the diagonal at the high end
(striped area).
Figure 5 shows the Lorenz curves for the short shot and the riskless
lottery. These make an interesting comparison because their Lorenz curves
cross one another: the curve for the riskless lottery is nearer the diagonal
at the low end (stippled area lower left), but further away at the high end
(striped area upper right). Thus, the riskless lottery offers both higher
minima and higher maxima. Not surprisingly, it appeals to both kinds of
subjects. Here are subject #10 (risk averse) and subject #11 (risk seeking)
from Lopes (1986) explaining why they chose the riskless lottery:
The [riskless lottery] has (1) a higher jackpot (2) greater chance
of winning a larger amount under $100. I look at the highest amount
I could lose rather than the highest amount I could win. (Subject
#10)
I picked the [riskless lottery] because both the minimum and the
". maximum amounts are more, and because for both there's a good chance
of getting around $100. (Subject #11)
.1"
r.wJ1 wt . ' . ,. . ' . %_ ' % :q. j. __ 1.I J I . . .. . . . ..... . p [
Psychology of Risk / 15
Figure 6 gives Lorenz curves for the bimodal lottery and the long shot.
These lotteries (which look very different superficially) are similar at their
low ends (lots of small outcomes) but differ markedly at their high ends (lots
of moderately large outcomes versus a few really large outcomes). People who
want to avoid low outcomes should have a mild preference for the bimodal
lottery since it lies a little nearer to the diagonal at the low end. People
who want to win large outcomes, however, should have a relatively strong
preference for the long shot since its Lorenz curve lies quite a bit further
from the diagonal at the high end. This is exactly what happens (Lopes, 1984;
Schneider & Lopes, in press). The pattern is illustrated by the following two
protocols from Lopes (1986), the former expressing a mild preference for the
bimodal lottery and the latter expressing a stronger preference for the long
shot:
Lorenz curves can also be used to describe loss lotteries. The only
thing that needs to be remembered is that for losses, the best (biggest)
outcome is zero. (Not hard to remember when real losses are being
considered!) Figure 7 gives the Lorenz curves for the bimodal loss lottery
and the long shot loss lottery. Although they look a little different than
Lorenz curves for gain lotteries (the curves now being above the diagonal),
they are read in exactly the same way. Cumulative probability still runs from
0 at the left to 1 at the right and cumulative proportion of value still runs
from the smallest value at the bottom (minus 1) to the largest value at the
top (zero). The worst outcomes are still in the lower left corner and the
best outcomes are still in the upper right corner. If all the tickets were
for a $100 loss, the Lorenz curve would fall on the diagonal.
The rule for choosing also stays the same: people who want to avoid the
worst outcomes (big losses) should prefer lotteries whose Lorenz curves lie
near the diagonal at the low (bad) end (stippled area); people who want to
obtain the best outcomes (small losses) should prefer lotteries whose Lorenz
curves lie far from the diagonal at the high (good) end (striped area).
~ ~
.b . . .. . .q ~. .4 A . . . .. .. . . . . . . . .. .. . . . . . . . . . . .. --
Psychology of Risk / 16
loss lottery:
With the [bimodal lottery], the most that I can lose is $200. With
the [long shot], I could lose $439. (Subject #2)
I would not risk losing $439, or even $292 and up. (Subject #3)
In contrast, here is a subject who chooses the long shot:
I choose the [long shot] because there is a preponderance of tickets
that can incur no loss, and a fair number of other tickets that
could lose less than $98. In the [bimodal lottery] 50% of the
tickets do stand to lose $93 or less but there are fewer that can
promise to cause no financial loss. I notice that there are large
amounts to be lost if one is unlucky, but the chances of being
unlucky are somewhat slimer in the [long shot]. (Subject #1)
- --..- "~
" .,.,";b
--i'-i': . .'" ":" -," .""-* . "........ v ....... ; ...2'> ...... > .' .i.;,....;.i . ..... .
Psychology of Risk / 17
I pick the [short shot] because the maximum loss is less and because
you may be able to hit as low as zero loss. No matter what, you
lose $70 and possibly $200 in the [riskless lottery] -- too much
risk. (Subject #11)
To sum up, Lorenz curves have at least four virtues for representing
lotteries. First, being cumulative, they reflect the fact that subjects tend
to evaluate lotteries in terms of inequalities. Second, they facilitate
comparison of the particular regions in lotteries that appear to be salient to
people with different goals. Third, they suggest similarities and differences
among lotteries that, although they may seem obvious in retrospect, do not
easily come to mind from inspection of the lotteries themselves. Fourth, they
predict when people having different goals will agree (or disagree) about
lotteries and when differences will be relatively large (or small). These are
no small virtues for a stimulus representation. But that is all that Lorenz
curves are: a way of representing lotteries. It is not to be supposed that
people convert risks into "mental Lorenz curves". Clearly, they do not. The
purpose of the Lorenz curve representation is to deepen understanding of the
functional stimulus and to help us psychologists see (literally) what it is
that people focus on when they compare lotteries.
and risk seeking choices exist side by side in the same individual's behavior.
In an earlier article (Lopes, 1984), I argued that risk averse and risk
seeking individuals differ in whether they pay most attention to the worst
outcomes in a distribution or the best outcomes. Risk averse people appear to
be motivated by a desire for security whereas risk seeking people appear to be
motivated by a desire for potential. The former motive values safety and the
latter, opportunity.
There are, however, two general points that should be made about
weighting. First, weights in the theory are joint functions of the magnitudes
of probabilities and the magnitudes of the outcomes to which they are
attached. This is a fundamental departure from the family of weighted value
models since in those models, probability and value are independent. Second,
weights reflect individuals' Qoals and not their perception of probabilities
or values. Thus, the fact that a person chooses, for example, to minimize the
likelihood of a bad outcome does not imply either that (subjectively) he
underestimates the value of good outcomes or that he overestimates the
probability of bad outcomes. Although psychophysical effects may occur in
either the money or the probability domain, these are considered to be of
secondary importance in determining risky choice.
The security/potential factor is conceived to be a dispositional
variable, reflecting the way individuals typically respond to risks. Not
surprisingly, security motivation (risk aversion) is the far more connon
pattern (see Lopes, 1984; Schneider & Lopes, in press), so cormon, in fact,
that economists have considered it to be the pattern for Everyman (Arrow,
1971; Pratt, 1964). This is probably not due to chance. Standards of
prudence are passed from parent to child in the normal course of growing up.
If that is not enough, hard experience informs us in no uncertain terms that,
as Damon Runyan said, "the race is not always to the swift nor the battle to
the strong, but that's the way to bet" (cited in Ellsberg, 1961, p. 644).
Risk seekers, on the other hand, may dog the long shots, waiting (as a famous
risk seeker once said) for "that one streak of luck, properly ridden and
encouraged," to compensate them for all the bad times (Thackrey, 1968, p. 67,
quoting Nick the Greek).
It should also be noted that the fact that someone is primarily motivated
by one of the poles of the security/potential dimension does not imply that
they are unaware of the other pole. It is better to think of these opposing
tendencies as existing in some strength in everyone (as do M s and Maf in
7W
Psychology of Risk / 19
Atkinson's, 1983, theory), but with potential much less important than
security and aspiration for risk averse people and security much less
important than potential and aspiration for risk seeking people. Such weak
motives would tend to come into play primarily when the stronger motives were
insufficient to determine choice.
The aspiration level that functions in any given situation (including the
present task situation) can reflect at least three different sources. The
first is the direct assessment of what is reasonable or safe to hope for. For
illustration, here is a subject from Lopes (1986) who has rejected the short
shot in favor of the peaked lottery:
The chances are in the [peaked] lottery that I will get something
close to $100, and I might get much more. I don't know why [I
should] let $130 be the top limit when there's a reasonable chance
of nearing $100 and a possibility for more. (Subject #3)
The next subject has chosen the riskless lottery in preference to a $100 sure
thing:
In both these cases, the subjects have taken the riskier option, but not
before assuring themselves that it's prudent to shoot for its somewhat higher
prizes.
I chose the [sure thing] because I would rather take the $100 as a
sure thing than risk winning less. The other lottery also offers a
sure thing ($70 at the least), however, the chances of winning less
than $100 are about 50-50 in that lottery, so I opt for the safe bet
of $100, a sure thing. (Subject #7)
The same shifting of aspiration level also occurs for losses. Here are
two more protocols from the previous subject. In the first she rejects the
long shot loss lottery in favor of the short shot. In the second she accepts
the long shot in favor of a sure $100 loss:
I chose the [short shot] because the most I could lose would be $130
and that seems safer than the [long shot]. Also the odds in both
lotteries seem to favor a loss of between $50-$150, so I figure the
lottery which has the lowest ceiling on a possible loss is the
safest risk. (Subject #7)
Notice that the subject seems to switch from considering a $130 loss to be
acceptable to considering a $100 loss to be unacceptable. Statements like
these make it clear that sure things have a powerful influence in organizing
choice, and the same seems to be true of values that are highly likely, though
not certain.
',°% '
Psychology of Risk / 21
A simple truth: you can't have it all. Corollary: you want more than i%
you can have. Conflict is in the nature of things. All resources are limited
(wealth, youth, even free lottery tickets), so people get plenty of practice
juggling inconsistent desires and jury-rigging tolerable compromises.
The second form of conflict is both more interesting and less obvious.
These are the conflicts that can be created as different situations induce
different patterns of agreement and disagreement between dispositional motives
toward security or potential and the immediate needs and opportunities
affecting aspiration level.
4.]
Psychology of Risk / 22
be true for almost any pair of loss lotteries: the ordering on security runs
essentially opposite to the ordering on aspiration level.
Let's begin with the risk averse person. Column 1 lists the six
lotteries from Figure 1 plus a $100 sure thing. Columns 2 and 6 (AL) give the
probabilities that the lotteries will yield the aspiration level: $50 or more
for gains and $50 or less for losses. Columns 3 and 7 (SEC) give hypothetical
values on security. (Keep in mind that the riskless lottery and the short
shot change places as one goes from gains to losses.) These values range
evenly between 1 for the sure thing and 0 for the long shot except for a tie
in each ordering. (For gains, the worst outcomes in the short shot and the
peaked lottery are almost identical in probability and value. Their Lorenz
curves would be essentially superimposed at the low end. In the same way, for
losses, the worst outcomes for the riskless lottery and the peaked lottery are
almost identical. Their Lorenz curves would also be superimposed at the low
end.)
Columns 4 and 8 (SEC x AL) show how security and aspiration are
integrated. A multiplying rule is used because the choice is conjunctive. A
lottery lacking good values on either security or aspiration will be rejected.
The final two columns (REL PREF) simply normalize the products to a cormon
base (by dividing by the sum of products) in order to allow an easier
comparison of relative preference.
A similar analysis is given in the bottom of the table for the risk
seeking person. Values for potential (POT) have replaced values for security,
and the aspiration levels are now $80 or more for gains and $20 or less for
losses. Note here that the ties in potential are now between the riskless
lottery and the peaked lottery for gains and the short shot and the peaked
lo"tery for losses.
Starting first with the risk averse person, note that relative
preferences for gain lotteries tend to decrease from the sure thing to the
long shot. This reflects the strong positive correlation between SEC and AL
for gains (r = .97). For losses, however, there is an inverse-U pattern:
preferences are low at the extremes but higher in the middle. This reflects
. .. . . . . .. . . . . . . . . . . . . .
Psychology of Risk / 23
the strong negative correlation between AL and SEC for losses Lr = -.91).
For the risk seeker, the simple pattern occurs for losses: preferences
tend to increase from the sure thing to the long shot reflecting the strong
positive correlation between POT and AL for losses (r = .92). For gains,
however, the pattern is complex. The least preferred lotteries are the sure
thing and the short shot and the most preferred are the bimodal, rectangular,
and the long shot. This complexity reflects the negative correlation between
POT and AL for gains Lr = -.97).
I"
The first bit of support for the two factor theory comes from judgments
of riskiness. In Experiments 3 and 4 of Lopes (1984), subjects were shown
pairs of gain lotteries and were asked to say which was the riskier. In
virtually every case, the lottery judged to be the riskier was the one whose
Lorenz curve lay further from the diagonal at the low end. The only
exceptions involved the relative riskiness of riskless lotteries and short
shots. (There were three examples of each). About half the subjects judged
the riskless lotteries to be the riskier (contrary to the original
expectation) and about half judged the opposite.
Experiments 5 and 6 of the same study suggested why this was so. in the
former experiments, the term "risk" was left vague so that subjects could
supply their own meanings. In the latter experiments, however, subjects were
asked to select the lottery for which it would be riskier to pay $100. Under
this condition, judgments for the other lotteries were virtually unchanged,
but subjects were now nearly unanimous that the riskless lotteries were the
riskier, a judgment that makes objective sense because there is a good chance
that riskless lotteries will yield substantially less than $100 (e.g., $70).
Apparently in the original experiment subjects adopted different aspiration
levels. For most lotteries, riskiness does not depend on whether the
aspiration level is low ($50) or high ($100), but for the riskless lotteries,
the shift in aspiration is crucial.
i
The ability of the two factor theory to account for judgments of
riskiness is a point in its favor, particularly as contrasted with
..................... ...........
Psychology of Risk / 24
The second bit of support for the theory is that it can predict the
preferences of both risk averse and risk seeking people. In experiments 1 and
2 of Lopes (1984), subjects were shown various pairs of lotteries and asked to
say which they would prefer to play. The subjects were then divided according
to whether or not they tended to take the sure thing when it was offered.
Risk averse subjects (i.e., those subjects who took the sure thing 8 or more
times out of 10) had preferences that were essentially perfectly predicted by
security motivation (i.e., they preferred lotteries whose Lorenz curves lay
near the diagonal at the low end.) Risk seeking subjects (i.e., those who
took the sure thing 3 or fewer times out of 10) had preferences that were for
the most part predicted by potential motivation (i.e., they preferred
lotteries whose Lorenz curves lay far from the diagonal at the high end).
The ability to account for people whose choices are primarily risk
seeking is another benefit of the two factor theory. Psychophysical theories
and moments theories are theories of Everyman because they are based
mechanistically on principles that should hold for us all: "our perceptual
apparatus is attuned to the evaluation of changes or differences" (Kahneman &
Tversky, 1979, p. 278); "uncertainty ... has a disutility growing worse with
increasing speed when [the] standard deviation [of utilities] increases"
(Hagen, 1979, p. 274). But-Everyman is risk averse for gains even though
every man (or woman) is noty. Two factor theory puts risk seekers and risk
averse people on equal footing. Although their choices may differ profoundly,
their choice processes have more similarities than differences. They
understand risks in the same way (cumulatively) and they trade off the same
factors. Their goals may differ, but they have the same conceptual equipment.
The best evidence for the two factor theory comes from a recent study of
the preferences of preselected risk averse and risk seeking subjects for gain
and loss lotteries (Schneider & Lopes, in press). Subjects were selected from
a large group of undergraduates who had filled out a brief questionaire asking
for their preferences in five choice pairs. Each pair contained a positive
two-outcome gamble and a sure thing of equal expected value. In accord with
conventional usage, risk averse subjects were defined as those who selected
the sure thing every time, and risk seeking subjects were defined as those who
selected the gamble at least four times. Thirty subjects were selected from
each group.
Psychology of Risk / 25
,S
The risk seeking subjects also follow the pattern predicted by the two
factor theory. Their preferences are essentially monotonically increasing
from the sure thing to the long shot for losses, but vary complexly for gains.
Worst liked are the sure thing, the short shots, and the peaked lotteries;
long shots and riskless lotteries are better liked. These patterns were also
highly reliable statistically.
-i ~ ~ ~ ~ ~ - - '*
Psychology of Risk / 26
theories (Coombs, 1975; Coombs & Lehner, 1981; Luce, 1980; Pollatsek &
Tversky, 1970) have shied away from using such language. Queasiness about the
ordinary language of emotion and intention goes back in psychology at least to
Watson's behaviorist manifesto, and in the area of risky choice has been
amplified by exposure to a similar movement in economics termed positive
economics (Friedman, 1953). In fact, modern economic expected utility theory
(von Neumann and Morgenstern, 1947) has relegated even the classical
psychophysical concept of utility to the status of an epiphenomenon. In the
modern view, utility does not precede and cause preferences; it is, instead,
merely a convenient fiction that can be used by the practitioner to summarize
the preferences of those who, by choice or chance, follow the dictates of the
von Neumann and Morgenstern axiom system.
If however, hope and fear and plans are necessary ingredients in risky
choice, then it is not unscientific to talk about them. Many social
scientists working outside the narrow confines of the laboratory or the
mathematical proof treat these terms casually, like old friends. In the
remainder of this paper I draw on these broader approaches to risk and show
their relation to the two factor theory.
It should also be noted that although fear feeds risk aversion, risk-
taking can be fed either by hope or by necessity (see Section IV.B).
Conventional economic theory treats risk-taking as a luxury. Neither
individuals nor firms are supposed to indulge in it unless they can afford it.
Kunreuther and Wright (1979), however, have pointed out that sometimes the
poorest farmers devote as large a proportion of their land to cash crops as
the richest farmers. Likewise, Bowman (1982) has demonstrated that
Lt'
. •. . .L . . ,, . . , . %: . ,. ,. l.-i , 6;L , ,-v-- ,T _ ,VT :_-V.rV :,:. VT _
Psychology of Risk / 27
A lot has been written about control in recent years. Langer (1977) has
synthesized an impressive body of experimental evidence documenting the fact
that people behave as though they believe that chance events can be
controlled. In her view, the illusion of control comes about for several good
reasons: (1) people are motivated to master their environment, (2) it is
unpleasant to believe that one has no control, (3) chance and skill elements
coexist in many situations, and (4) the illusion can help us emotionally more
than it can harm us practically.
One might suppose (as Langer has not) that risk-taking behavior is caused
by the optimistic illusion that outcomes are more controllable than they
really are. McClelland (1961), however, has argued that entrepreneurship is
independent of optimism. He presents evidence from four different countries
that school boys who are high in optimism are "conscientious, efficient,
forward-looking, manaQerial types [who work] hard and efficiently at
everything more or less indiscriminately" (p. 227-228), but they are not
necessarily high in achievement motivation. A student who is high in
achievement motivation works hard only on those things that can give a sense
of personal responsibility. "If there is no challenge, he doesn't work so
*,9
- 1 w...ILI
Psychology of Risk / 28
I
hard: in this sense he would make a poor bureaucrat" (p. 228).
The belief that one can control one's fate appears to be necessary to
good mental health (Abramson, Seligman, & Teasdale, 1978). When highly
desired outcomes are believed to be unlikely or when highly undesirable
outcomes are believed to be likely, and when the individual believes that
nothing can be done to change these likelihoods, depression results causing
attendant motivational and affective deficits.
Beliefs about control and motivation feed back on one another. When
aversive events occur despite one's efforts to prevent them, motivation to
control events is reduced both in animals (Maier & Seligman, 1966) and in
humans (Hiroto, 1974; Hiroto & Seligman, 1975). When control is later made
possible, the motivational deficit prevents learning from occurring.
Responses that are not made cannot be reinforced. A vicious cycle results.
C. and
Uncertainty is embedded in time. There is a now in wh. 2h some tn.:ngs are ,"
true, a future in which other things may be true, and a still farther future
in which we may reflect on the past. At the point of choice we look forward
along this track, and we also anticipate looking back. T7he temporal element
is what gives risk both savor and sting.
Pope (1983) has criticized expected utility theory for having i'ncred the
time between the decision and the resolution of the uncer-tainty, what she
calls the pre-outcome period during which fear and hope operate. She points
out that the period can be long not only for long-term decisions such as
individuals choosing careers, governments embarking on social programs, and
businesses making major capital investments, but also for repeat short-term.
decisions: "after deciding to devote a fraction of the housekeeping funds to
i ',
Psychology of Risk / 29
a weekly lottery ticket, housekeepers can dream from age nineteen to ninety-
nine that they will become millionaires after the next drawing" (p. 156).
The importance of having safe fallback positions in real life may account
for the fact that the perceived riskiness of technological hazards is not
solely related to estimates of annual fatalities but also reflects dread of
outcomes that are perceived to be uncontrollable, catastrophic, not easily
reversed, and of high risk to future generations. Thus, intelligent but
technically unsophisticated raters (students and members of the League of
Women Voters) estimate fewer annual deaths from nuclear power than from home
appliances but nevertheless consider nuclear power to be much more risky
(Slovic, Fischhoff, & Lichtenstein, 1980, Tables 2 and 3).
" -
-. " , ,. ,' b-
Psychology of Risk / 30
But the Sherpas who carry the loads also share in the risks. Why do the
Sherpas climb? The conventional view is that they climb out of economic
necessity. Michael Thompson (1980), however, himself an Everest climber,
disputes this distinction between Sherpa and non-Sherpa. In Thompson's view,
risks that are pursued for practical purposes become tame in the process as
has commercial air travel. But risks that are pursued for themselves do not
become tame. Thus, for aesthetic purposes a proposed Everest route "is only
felt to be worthwhile if there is considerable uncertainty as to its outcome"
(p. 278). Sherpas also take this view and refer scornfully to the route that
Hillary and Tenzing followed, the easiest of the routes for obvious reasons,
as "the Yak route." A small joke among those who share a common aesthetic.
Nor should custom and duty be forgotten in their effects on risk taking.
Consider the story of the Reindeer and the Montcalm (Mowat, 1982). In March
of 1932 the salvage tug Reindeer set to sea carrying 28 men in a furious storm
to rescue a damaged freighter. Reindeer was not designed for such work and
she was old and ill-equipped. Within hours she was foundering 60 miles from
land. The vessel Montcalm, meanwhile, had been damaged herself by the storm
and was running for harbor. When it became clear that no other ship could
reach Reindeer in time, the master of Montcalm, Captain Rothwell, turned her
back to sea. "It had been no easy decision. Montcalm carried sixty
passengers and a crew of fifty, and their lives were all in Rothwell's care.
The risk to them was real enough, but the death of Reindeer's men was sure
unless that risk was taken" (Mowat, 1982, p. 46). Although Reindeer sank, all
N.-
+ U+
.,+ML-,...- . . . '- .- I:-,.i. ,+. ++ : + . " , ,,. . ,,., -
V.I
Psychology of Risk / 31
i
I°
S"
P' 5
Psychology of Risk / 32
References
. . ....
..-..... .., ....- .... . ..•...-.. .-. . . .., . ° .. .. . . . .. . .. . .. ... . .. .. - .. . .. - . .. - .
I. W."i"
k- 07 2F~ 2 ' ~ ~ .i% 19IVATV
Psychology of Risk / 33
7,
Psychology of Risk / 34
• 7
" 1
Psychology of Risk / 35
.9 .~ 9,
7
Psychology of Risk / 36
Footnotes S
The writing of this article and the research reported in it were
N00014-84-K-0065. I am
grateful to by
facilitated Office
Leonard Berkowitz, Patricia contract
of Naval Research Devine, Mary Douglas, Robin Keller,
David Messick, Gregg Oden, Sandra Schneider, and Alex Wearing for their
helpful criticism and coffnts and (again) to Gregg Oden for his MacWonderful
help with the graphics.
6. The graphical analyses that are used in this paper apply only to
lotteries having equal expected value. Although Lorenz curves can be drawn
for lotteries that differ in expected value (by omitting the normalization
step in column 7), comparisons of such Lorenz curves would need to take this
into account. In such cases, comparison by means of a mathematical index of
security or potential would probably be preferable (see Section IV.A).
Psychology of Risk / 37
expected utility theory and has been considered to be irrational for that
reason (see, e.g., Samuelson, 1977, p. 48).
ix
C.
..
o...
. :<........,
... ..... ...
,....
. .....
.......
. ..< .-¢ . .. . . .........
..
< .. ...
Psychology of Risk / 38
Table 1
Hypothetical Preferences for Risk Averse and Risk Seeking Individuals
for Gain and Loss Lotteries
~ * ~ ~ b *
Psychology of Risk / 39
Figure Captions
5. Comparison of the Lorenz curves for the riskless lottery (RL) and the
short shot (SS). The fact that the curves cross one another indicates that RL
is good both for avoiding small outcomes (stippled area) and for approaching
large outcomes (striped area).
6. Comparison of Lorenz curves for the bimodal lottery (BM) and the long
shot (LS). These lotteries are very similar at their low ends (stippled area)
but very different at their high ends (striped area).
7. Comparison of Lorenz curves for the bimodal (BM) and long shot (LS)
loss lotteries. These lotteries are very different at their low ends
(stippled area) but very similar at their high ends (striped area).
8. Comparison of Lorenz curves for the riskless (RL) and the short shot
(SS) loss lotteries. The fact that the curves cross one another indicates
that SS is good both for avoiding large losses (stippled area) and for
approaching small or zero losses (striped area).
9. Mean preference data for risk averse subjects for gain lotteries
(open symbols) and loss lotteries (filled symbols). Data are the number of
times a subject chose a lottery out of the total number of times the lottery
was available for choice. (From "Reflection in preferences under risk: Who
and when may suggest why" by S. L.& Schneider and L. L. Lopes, Journal of
Experimental Psycholoc1 : Human Perception and Performance, in press.
Copyright 1986 by The American Psychological Association. Reprinted by
Psychology of Risk / 40
permission.)
10. Mean preference data for risk seeking subjects for gain lotteries
(open symbols) and loss lotteries (filled symbols). Data are the number of
tines a subject chose a lottery out of the total number of times the lottery
was available for choice. (From "Reflection in preferences under risk: Who
and when may suggest why" by S. L.& Schneider and L. L. Lopes, Journal of
Experimental Psycholoiy: Human Perception and Performance, in press.
Copyright 1986 by The American Psychological Association. Reprinted by
permission.)
.I.o
I.
I.
.4.
DOLLARS
DOLLARS
customary
position'**
LOSSES GAINS
DOLLARS
,°
Figure 1[
$200 I
$186 I
$172 III
$159 11111
$146 1111111
$200 I $130 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII $132
$119 111111111
IlIlIIIII
$187 II $115 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII $106 I IIII
$172 I1! $101 IIIIIIIIIIIII $ 93 IIIII
$157 Ilii $ 86 IlIIIII $ 80 IlIIIIII
$143 1IIII $ 71 1111111 $ 66 Ill9ll3ll
$129 IIIIIII $ 57 11111 $ 53 1111111
$114 $ 43
$IIIIIIIII 5III 11111
$ 40
$ 99 IIIIIIIIIIIIIII $ 28 III $26 III
$ 85 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII $ 13 II $13
$ 70 IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIII ZERO I ZERO I
$200 11111
$189 i11
$178 JIIII
$168 11111
$158 11111 $200 IIIIIIIIII
$147 11111 $186 IIIIIIII
$136 11111 $172 111111111
$126 11111 $159 1111111
$116 11111 $146 11111
$105 11111 $132 Ill
$ 94 11111 $119 I $439 I
$ 84 11111 $106 I $390 II
$ 74 11111 $ 93 I $341 III
$ 63 1IIII $ 80 I $292 1I11
$ 52 11111 $ 66 III $244 11111
S 42 11111 S 53 11111 $195 1111111
$ 32 11111 $ 40 1111111 $146 II
$ 21 11111 $ 26 111111111 $ 98 IIIIIIIIIIIIII
$ 10 11111 $ 13 IIIIIIIIS 49 IIIIIIIIIIIII
ZERO 11111 ZERO IIIIII ZERO IIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIIi '
RECTANGULAR BIMODAL LONG SHOT
Figure 2
:.:: . .- ..-.
.-. .- ."--, ". .."- ."- v -." •" -. '- -. - .--. . -".
-" ,' "- -, " ". - - -" "- . -" "
CUMULATIVE VALUE
cc:J
x x
a_ Q-w Lnr- L N W M M C> )
~~O~O~viO
oo>
)C~-oc'(DLnC)'Joa q como
0Q .0 . . . . . . . . .
a.
Cd)
LJ
0 0 CLeJ'o
RT w--aMq ---- n
1%*
7677
.14.
.........
..
.Q.
. . ..
.. .. . . . . . . .
0
. .. .. . . . .
*. . . . .. .~ . .. . .. .
.5** 5*...........5
.5* /* at........./.
.. . . .. . .
./.. .. ..
CUMULATIVE VALUE
/...............
... S..........
.
... . . . .
......
...
.... 0.
~ ~ K.....................
.
. / ./
/.'/* //o/
.. . . .....
..... .. . . .. . .
-.
0 ~~ flVA ALLv'1hNflo
de,
do P. op / /
" /cr
//0
............
.........
A. . .......
... ......... 5
........
.
. .. .......-
........ w ..
.. ....
......
...
......
...
D..
.
...
D.....
0..... ...........
0 BflVABAiivflV\JfO. ...
....
....
....
....
1p 4
~~~~V~~F
... Vw 1 r I1WVI LIU L.W 7V. UU-VV"W rw %- yw- Im VYV ~ 1'y~
coo
Clz)
w 0
Cof
CQ
CO'
c-J
C'))
CO
OSD
CAPT Paul R. Chatelier J. Randy Simpson
Office of the Deputy Under Secretary Statistics Program Code 1111SP
of Defense Office of Naval Research
OUSDRE (E&LS) 800 North Quincy Street
Pentagon, Room 3D129 Arlington, VA 22217-5000
Washington, D. C. 20301 Dr. Lyle 0. Broemeling
Department of the Navy Code 1111SP
Engineering Psychology Program Office of Naval Research
Office of Naval Research 800 N. Quincy Street
Code 1142EP Arlington, VA 22217-5000
800 North Quincy Street
Arlington, VA 22217-5000 (3 copies) Information Sciences Division
Code 1133
Aviation & Aerospace Technology Office of Naval Research
Programs 800 North Quincy Street
Code 121 Arlington, VA 22217-5000
Office of Naval Research
800 North Quincy Street CAPT William M. Houk
Arlington, VA 22217-5000 Commanding Officer
Naval Medical R&D Command
Physiology and Neurobiology Program Bethesda, MD 20814-5055
Office of Naval Research
Code 1141NP Dr. Randall P. Schumaker
800 North Quincy Street NRL A. I. Center
Arlington, VA 22217-5000 Code 7510
Naval Research Laboratory
CAPT. P. M. Curran Washington, D.C. 20375-5000
Code 125
Office of Naval Research
800 North Quincy Street
Arlington, VA 22217-5000
2
JANUARY 1986
3
JANUARY 1986
r %
4
v w
JANUARY 1986
p
" S
JANUARY 1986
6 .- .
JANUARY 1986
Other Organizations
7
JANUARY 1986
Other Organizations
8
. . . . . . 9 . . .. . . . . ... .. . .. - . ... -p
JANUARY 1986
Other Organizations
: 9
p _______________________