2 Visualization 2
2 Visualization 2
a b a a b
a+b
b
b a2 b2 = (a + b)(a b)
Fig. 2.1 A paper-and-scissors activity that models the difference of two squares
Jackie (Cohort 2) was in seventh grade when she joined my Algebra 1 class to
participate in a yearlong teaching experiment involving various aspects of alge-
braic thinking at the middle school level. Her earlier mathematical experiences had
solidified for her the impression that mathematics was something that she merely
followed on the basis of rules that occasionally made sense to her. Her comment
in the opening epigraph came early in the fall semester when our class was explor-
ing factoring simple polynomials initially from a visual perspective. In a follow-up
activity, when I asked the class whether it was possible to factor a sum of squares,
all of them said no and explained that there was no way of reconfiguring the totality
of two squares having two different dimensions into a single rectangle (i.e., with no
overlaps).
Later, when the students learned to use algeblocks (Fig. 2.2), a three-dimensional
version of algebra tiles, the manner in which they explained the process of factoring
simple quadratic trinomial and cubic binomial expressions reflected a firm grasp
of a visual strategy. For example, the responses of two Cohort 1 Grade students,
Cheska and Jamal, in Fig. 2.3 had them associating the task of factoring a simple
polynomial expression in terms of whether it was possible to reconfigure the relevant
algeblocks into a single rectangle whose dimensions represent the factors of the
given expression. Also, when I asked them to factor x3 + 2x2 , their initial approach
had them gathering algeblocks consisting of a cube and two squares and combining
them to form a cuboid with a square base x2 and a height of (x + 2). The visual
action allowed them to conclude the equivalent form x3 + 2x2 = x2 (x + 2).
Cheska:
Jamal:
2005, 2007a; Trouche, 2003, 2005). Researchers who work in an emergent mod-
eling perspective ground initial mathematical activity in real or experientially real
settings, which provide learners with an opportunity to develop a “model of” some
(informal) intended mathematical knowledge that then becomes their basis in pro-
ducing a “model for” more (formal, general) mathematical concepts, processes,
and reasoning (e.g., Gravemeijer, Lehrer, van Oers, & Verschaffel, 2002; Stephan,
Bowers, Cobb, & Gravemeijer, 2003).
The following two related points below are worth noting early at this stage in
this book in light of how I situate the role of visualization in cognition involving
mathematical objects, concepts, and processes. First, cognitive activity is a dynamic
and distributed phenomenon, that is,
[it] is in fact the result of a complex interplay and simultaneous coevolution, in time, of the
states of mind, body, and external environment. Even if, of course, a large portion of the
complex environment of a thinking agent is internal, and consists in the proper software
composed of the knowledge base and of the inferential expertise of the individual, never-
theless a “real” cognitive system is composed by “distributed cognition” among people and
some “external” objects and technical artifacts.
(Magnani, 2004, p. 520)
Thus, the term visualization as it is used in this book should not be viewed as a
thaumaturgical concept or a tool that is isolated and analyzed for the sole purpose of
developing and justifying an alternative mathematical practice distinct from current
institutional practices that continue to favor alphanumeric competence. I see it as
functioning within a distributed system that Magnani (2004) has clearly described
in the above two passages. Further, the dynamic nature of the system is compatible
with, and adaptive to, changes in representational competence or, in Freudenthal’s
(1981) words, progressive schematization.
In his August 1980 plenary address at the Fourth International Congress of
Mathematics Education, Freudenthal explained his idea of progressive schematiz-
ing, which I consider to be an integral element in any psychological account of
visual thinking in mathematics, in the following manner:
1 Nature of Cognitive Activity and Cognitive Action 25
In present history, we are certainly fortunate enough to witness, and benefit from,
theoretical and methodological advances in the cognitive science of visualization
and learning technologies that we now find ourselves in a much better position to
realize Freudenthal’s vision of a mathematical language that could be learned from a
visually oriented progressive formalization perspective. In this context, visualization
is framed within, and pursued as, an epistemological process that lies at the kernel
of a conceptual and developmental account of alphanumeric competence.
Following O’Halloran (2005) and Millar (1994), progressive schematizing
involves a complex conceptual evolution and coordination of, and convergence
among, systems of semiotic resources. Progression at the intra-semiotic level occurs
within mathematical language, mathematical symbols, and visual images, while pro-
gression at the inter-semiotic level occurs between and among the three systems.
Since each type of semiotic resource contains information and several resources
that together convey redundancy of the same information in varying form and con-
tent, progression is a marked indication that some type of convergence is occurring.
To take a case in point, Jackie, Cheska, and Jamal acquired their algebraic compe-
tence in factoring in a progressive manner by drawing on their visual experiences
with the algeblocks that provided them with the necessary “insight, understanding,
and thinking” before they finally transitioned to “rote, routines, drill, memorizing,
and algorithms” (Freudenthal, 1981, p. 140). Factoring on a quadrant mat with the
algeblocks contained sufficient visual structural information that enabled them to
construct an analogous symbolic structure, which they conveyed through a diagram.
Progressively, the diagram emerged as a symbolic (algebraic) process that could
then handle all cases of factoring involving quadratic trinomial squares.
Following Bakker (2007), the use of symbolic forms associated with procedures
basically signifies successful hypostasis and increased “structuring of thought”
(O’Halloran, 2005, p. 2). Further, familiarity with the relevant concepts does not
necessarily imply the absence of visualization. For example, Fig. 2.4a–c shows the
written work of Jackie, Cheska, and Jamal on three assessment tasks that were given
to them toward the end of a teaching experiment on factoring. Clearly, they fully
transitioned to a routinized algebraic strategy they hypostasized as tic-tac-toe that
reflected their structural experiences with the algeblocks. The tic-tac-toe strategy
is a coded symbolic knowledge in algebraic form; it exemplifies a diagram, a type
of visual spatial representation in which the symbols, expressions, and other related
inscriptions are positioned and combined in a particular way that makes sense within
some stipulated rule.
26 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
Fig. 2.4 a Ollie’s algebraic method on a factoring task. b Cheska’s algebraic method on a factoring
task. c Jamal’s algebraic method with no variables on a factoring task
a
For what value or values of n will the linear For what value or values of n will the linear
system have no solution? Explain. system have an infinite number of
solutions? Explain.
b
Fig. 2.5 a An end-of-a-unit Algebra 1 assessment task involving a linear system of equations in
two variables. b Kirk’s visual approach to the Fig. 1.5a task. c Earl’s numerical solution to the
Fig. 1.5a task
increasing by two circles. In reconstructing the pattern on the table with actual chips
and extending it to include two additional stages (Fig. 2.6b), she apparently saw
nothing else (e.g., shape of the pattern) beyond the additive relationship. Her prefer-
ence in dealing with patterns numerically was, in fact, carried through all the 3 years
she was involved in our study. For example, Fig. 2.7 shows her written work on a
Stage 1
Stage 2
Stage 3
Stage 4
Stage 6
Stage 5
Stage 7
Stage 8
Fig. 2.6 a T circle pattern. b Dina’s interpretation of the pattern in Fig. 2.6a in sixth grade
1 Nature of Cognitive Activity and Cognitive Action 29
Fig. 2.7 Dina’s written work on a linear pattern task in eighth grade
linear pattern in Grade 8. Her written response to item 1 in Fig. 2.7 conveys a surface
knowledge of the basic features of the pattern. In explaining her direct formula, C =
3P + 1, which she established numerically, she associated the coefficient 3 with the
constant addition of three circles and the constant, 1, to the “circle in the middle.”
Second, a neural basis for both dual coding in mathematics and visuospatial
processing relevant to various aspects of numerical calculations has now been
established following rigorous methodological protocols. The results provide very
interesting insights that enable us to understand the fundamental, genetic role of
visual thinking in mathematics. For example, a recent brain imaging study by Tang
et al. (2006) has shown that arithmetical processing in the brain appears to be
shaped by cultures. When the thinking processes of 12 adult Western participants
and 12 university Chinese students were compared in relation to a simple visually
30 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
presented arithmetical task that asked them to determine whether a third digit was
greater than the bigger one of the first two in a triplet of Arabic numbers, they actu-
ally found “differences in the brain representation of number processing between”
the two groups (p. 10776). On this particular task, the Chinese participants pro-
cessed visually, while the Western participants processed verbally. Tang et al. (2006)
hypothesized that the visual dominance in number processing among the Chinese
participants could be explained by their reading experiences in school, which
involve repeatedly learning Chinese characters, and their early experiences in using
an Abacus that activated the production of mental images that are all visual in form.
A recent review of research studies on the role of visuospatial processing in
various aspects that matter to arithmetical computing by de Hevia, Vallar, and
Girelli (2008) presents converging evidence that infers a “close relationship between
numerical abilities and visuospatial processes” (p. 1361). For example, individuals
have been documented to be relying on a spatial mental number line when com-
paring and obtaining differences of two numbers. The line, which research shows
appears to be oriented from left to right, assists subjects in dealing with numerical
quantities and their relationships and magnitudes at least in approximate (and not in
exact) terms. Certainly, with more cultural learning, the relevant spatial properties
are expected to further develop and undergo refinement. Beyond studies involving
the mental number line, de Hevia et al. (2008) also underscore the significant role of
visuospatial representations in memory and arithmetical problem solving. Findings
include the following: (1) learners tend to keep numbers in an active state by draw-
ing on some form of visuospatial support; (2) mathematical prodigies develop and
use internal visual calculators that become evident when they solve numerical tasks
that require complex computations; (3) individuals perform arithmetical procedures
(e.g., obtaining the product of multi-digit numbers) by coordinating their stored
arithmetical facts and their spatial image of the process relevant to the operation, a
view that refines earlier interpretations which trace the process to be primarily work-
ing within a language-based semantic network (e.g., verbal rote learning of facts).
Third, in their recent extensive review of research concerning the imagery
and spatial processes of blind and visually impaired individuals, Cattaneo et al.
(2008) clearly articulate what I interpret from research among nonblind learners
of mathematics to be a problematic aspect of the constitutive nature of the “visual
experience.” Cattaneo et al. write:
The perceptual limitations of the congenitally blind are reflected at a higher cognitive level,
probably because their cognitive mechanisms have developed by touch and hearing, which
only allow a sequential processing of information. As a consequence, cognitive function-
ing of blind individuals seems to be essentially organized in a “sequential” fashion. On
the contrary, vision – allowing the simultaneous perception of distinct images – facilitates
simultaneous processing at a higher cognitive level.
(Cattaneo et al., 2008, p. 1360)
1.41421356237309504880168872420969807856967187537694807317667973799073247
846210703885038753432764157273501384623091229702492483605585073721264412
149709993583141322266592750559275579995050115278206057147010955997160. . .
A follow-up activity we used in class involves finding the sum of the harmonic
series
∞
1 1 1 1
=1+ + + + ··· .
n 2 3 4
n=1
Abstract
Visual
Referential Operative
..... .....
A square array of 2m x 2m means 4 square arrays, each consisting of m x m dots. Hence, every
even square number is the sum of 4 square numbers.
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
..... .....
An odd number 2m + 1 means 2 horizontally aligned rows of m dots plus an isolated dot, say,
..... . .....
A square array of (2m+1) x (2m+1) means 4 square arrays, each consisting of m x m dots, plus
4 groups of m dots, plus a central dot. Hence, every odd square number is odd (why?).
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
..... . .....
Hence, even squares are even and odd squares are odd. But every even square is a sum of
four squares. We are now ready to prove that 2 is an irrational number.
Proof:
a a2
If 2 = , (a, b ≠ 0 integers), then 2 = 2 or a2 = 2b2. So, a2 is twice another square number.
b b
Then there would have to be a smallest square number that is twice another square number
since there is no unending sequence of ever smaller square numbers. Let k2 be the smallest. So
k 2 = 2(h2).
Then k2 is an even square. So, there is some number n such thet
k 2 = 4(n2).
Also, h2 = 2(n2).
Since h2 is smaller that k2, it means that a smaller square number than k2 is twice another
square number, but this contradicts the assumption we made about k2 being the smallest.
Thus, there is no square number that is twise another.
b Exploring 2
1. Use a construction paper to outline a unit square. Then draw a diagonal to the square
and cut along the diagonal. What is the length of the diagonal?
2. Obtain a piece of adding-machine tape and draw a number line that is sufficient enough to
construct and label integers from –10 to 10. Then construct and label –9.5, –8.5,–7.5, …, 9.5.
3. Starting from 0, lay out the diagonal whose length is 2 on the number line. Estimate
the numerical value of 2 . Can the value be 1.5? Why or why not? Which number is it closest to?
1 2 3 4
Initially, the students used a centimeter graphing paper and constructed the picture
shown in Fig. 2.10. Then they confirmed that each shaded rectangle had an area
corresponding to a term in the given harmonic series. Next I asked them to imagine
a train of shaded rectangles beyond the picture they drew. I had them estimating
the amount of paint they would need to cover the entire shaded area. With the aid
of a graphing calculator, they started adding the terms one by one. After verifying
on the basis of a sufficient number of terms that the series would yield no finite
sum, they began to realize the difference between everyday and mathematical ways
of seeing.
The above experience allowed my Algebra 1 students to develop the view
that visually drawn constructions of some mathematical objects, concepts, or pro-
cesses despite being incomplete in form could also effectively assist in developing
structural awareness (Mason, Stephens, & Watson, 2009) of the corresponding
abstract knowledge. While their totality (i.e., essence) could not be fully appre-
hended through the sensory modalities alone, what is actually being sought is
intellectual insight drawn from one’s emerging structural awareness as mediated
by the relevant visual representation. Certainly, having structural awareness drawn
from visual forms would allow learners to construct inferences about the corre-
sponding abstract object, concept, or process. This perspective should assist us in
moving beyond dichotomous thinking relative to the symbolic/visual hierarchy in
mathematics. Brown (1999) is certainly correct in pointing out that some math-
ematical knowledge could not be primarily derived from sense experiences, as
follows:
All measurement in the physical world works perfectly well with rational numbers. Letting
the standard meter stick be our unit, we can measure any length with whatever desired
accuracy our technical abilities will allow; but the accuracy will always be to some rational
number (some fraction of a meter). In other words, we could not discover irrational numbers
or incommensurable segments (i.e., lengths which are not ratios of integers) by physical
measurement. It is sometimes said that we learn 2 + 2 = 4 by counting apples and the like.
Perhaps experience plays a role√in grasping the elements of the natural numbers. But the
discovery of the irrationality of 2 was an intellectual achievement, not at all connected to
sense experience.
(Brown, 1999, pp. 5–6)
3 General Notion of Visualization in this Book 35
His basic point is reflected via the dashed side of the operative triangle shown in
Fig. 2.8, which symbolically conveys the treacherous path that characterizes the
movement from the visual to the abstract or, more appropriately, from our everyday
sense of the visual to the mathematically visual.
However, aiming for structural awareness allows us to engage in a more rec-
onciliatory interanimated discussion of the perceived divide between the visual
and the symbolic or, in Brown’s terms, between sense experience and intellectual
achievement. This move toward interanimation is derived from the work of Warren,
Ogonowski, and Pothier (2005), who also saw the need to move past what they
perceive to be dichotomies in modes of thinking in school science. They speak of
interanimation in terms of some creative coordination, that is,
[it] denotes a process whereby a person comes to regard one way of conceptualizing, rep-
resenting, and evaluating the world through the eyes of another, each characterized by its
own objects, meanings, and values. As such, it resists the strong temptation to dichotomize
modes of thinking or being.
(Warren et al., 2005, p. 142)
The move toward structural awareness is, thus, seen as being initially rooted in
visual experience and, yet, serves as a route in gaining a better access of the cor-
responding abstract knowledge as well. Its essence, Mason, Stephens, and Watson
(2009) note, lies in a learner’s “experience of generality, not a reinforcement of par-
ticularities” (p. 17) that enables him or her to find meaning in manipulating both
representational contexts in a simultaneous fashion.
In this book, I share the view that visualization is about “the many ways in which
pictures, visual images, and spatial metaphors influence our thinking1 ” (Reed, 2010,
p. 3). Hence, in its raw form, it could be either internal (mental images) or external
(diagrammatic and spatial representations) (see Lohse, Biolsi, Walker, & Rueler,
1994 for an interesting classification of visual representations). Reed articulates it
clearly when he insists that
[l]anguage is a marvelous tool for communication, but it is greatly overrated as a tool for
thought. . . . Much of comprehending language, for instance, depends on visual simulations
of words or on spatial metaphors that provide a foundation for conceptual understanding.
Sometimes we are conscious of visual thinking. At other times it works unconsciously
behind the scenes.
(Reed, 2010, p. 3)
1 Bees provide a nonhuman example of species that appear capable of distinguishing between
shapes and employing landmarks in tracing their route from some food source to their hive (Frisch,
1967).
36 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
2 SeeNg and Lee (2009), Murata (2008), and van Galen, Feijs, Figueiredo, Gravemeijer, van
Herpen, and Keijzer (2008) for an explanation of the role of rectangular, tape, and strip diagrams in
Singapore, Japanese, and Dutch textbooks, respectively. I should note the interesting similarity in,
and convergence toward, the use of visual approaches in teaching word problems in mathematics
(more generally) in these countries.
3 General Notion of Visualization in this Book 37
A school increased its staff by 35%. If 108 On Labor Day, cell phone prices were
staff members were working after the marked down by 20%. The sale price of an
increase, how many were there originally? item was $300. What was the original price
Solution: of the item before the discount?
Let x be the original number of staff members Solution: Let x be the original price in dollars
108 x y 300
x y
100 80
=
100 = 135 x 300
x 108 80x = 30000
135x = 10800 x = 375
x = 80
35 135 20 80
= =
y 108 y 300
y = 28 y = 75
Check: 80 + 28 = 108
Check: 375 – 75 = 300
There were 80 staff members prior to the The original price of a cell phone was $375
increase. before the 20% decrease.
Fig. 2.12 Examples of Parker’s (2004) unitary diagrams for solving percent increase and percent
decrease problems
Fig. 2.11 a Visual approach to percent problems using unitary diagrams in a US version of a
Singapore mathematics text (Curriculum Planning and Development Division, 2008, pp. 51 &
99; Copyright belongs to the government of the Republic of Singapore, c/o Ministry of Education,
Singapore, and has been reproduced with their permission). b Visual approach to a percent problem
using a bar diagram in a US version of a Netherlands mathematics text (Mathematics in Context,
2006, p. 23). c Visual approach to a percent problem using a tape diagram in a US version of a
Japanese mathematics text (Tokyo Shoseki, 2006, p. 66)
3 General Notion of Visualization in this Book 39
Campos’s Visual Subtraction with Regrouping Involving Two Two-Digit Whole Numbers
Lana’s Visual Addition with Regrouping Involving Two Three-Digit Whole Numbers
Fig. 2.13 Grade 2 students’ visual approaches to adding, subtracting, and multiplying whole
numbers
40 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
The initial stages of mathematical discovery – namely, the intuitive and conjectural work,
like theoretical work in the sciences – involves speculations on the nature of reality beyond
established knowledge. Thus we borrow our name “theoretical” from this use in physics.
There is an older use of the word “theoretical” in mathematics, namely, to identify “pure”
rather than applied mathematics; this is a usage from the past which is no longer common
and which we do not adopt.
(Jaffe & Quinn, 1993, p. 2)
After
42 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
b Before
After
Fig. 2.14 a Jackie’s written work on a free construction task after a teaching experiment on linear
pattern generalization. b Arman’s before and after visuals involving addition of whole numbers
strategy when adding whole numbers. He would initially draw all the required cir-
cles (or sticks) on the basis of the numbers that were presented to him and then
would patiently count all of them together. After the teaching experiment, his com-
bined visual/symbolic strategy reflected his understanding of the central role of
place value and regrouping in the addition process. The solutions offered by Jackie
and Arman exemplify what I consider in this book to be visual (and much later
visuoalphanumeric) representations.
5 Three Fundamental Principles of Visualization 43
on the type of activity that is pursued, which could be imaginal (e.g., appeal to intu-
ition), formational (e.g., concept or process development), or transformational (e.g.,
problem solving). Since all visual representations are conveyed through signs, we
discuss different types of mathematical objects. Also, since all visual representations
operate within rules and structures, we articulate the figural nature of the concepts
that allow the objects to exist. Section 5 in Chapter 3 revisits the meaning of visual
thinking but developed in the context of mathematics.
Principle of acquisition: Individuals abduce the intended meanings of visual
representations involving everyday objects through the use of one strategy or a
combination of two or more strategies. Some documented strategies include learned
pairings; manipulating their corresponding iconic representations; associating with
a relevant experience; and establishing relational structural similarities. Abduction
refers to the logic that “covers all the operations by which theories and conceptions
are engendered” (Peirce, 1957, p. 237). That is, it “consists in studying facts and
devising a theory to explain them” and “its only justification is that if we are ever
to understand things at all, it must be in that way” (Peirce, 1934, p. 90). Abduction,
in fact, plays a central role in the development of mathematical concepts, processes,
and representations since it is primarily concerned with developing and establishing
inferences about rules (Thagard, 1978), rules and their extensions in simultaneity
(Eco, 1983), and structures (Mason, Stephens, & Watson, 2009).
Gattis (2004) was particularly interested in how spatial representations acquire
their meanings, but many of her claims also apply to visual representations in the
general case. The meanings of symbols are oftentimes acquired through learned
pairings, which involves explicitly learning the relationship between script and
sound or between word and picture. Iconic symbols allow a mapping to take place
between the elements of the image and the icon, especially if there is a good fit
or an isomorphism between the icon or the physical model and the correspond-
ing referent. However, no new information could be obtained beyond what icons
represent because they represent an already existing object. Especially in the case
of everyday objects, icons depend on physical resemblance and are not generally
useful in representing abstract concepts such as “goodness.”
Among abstract concepts, associations with a relevant experience significantly
matter more than physical semblance. For example, children associate growth
graphically with a vertical line or express feelings of warm and cold by imag-
ining fire and ice, respectively. But association as a strategy itself could also be
deceiving and limited and could possibly lead to misconceptions especially in
cases when multiple mappings are possible or when counterintuitive concepts are
involved.
Similarities of relational structure involve establishing relationships “between
objects, relations between them, and relations between relations” (Gattis, 2004,
p. 592). For example, interpreting a given spatial representation such as a map
or a graph involves mapping “conceptual elements to spatial elements, conceptual
relations to spatial relations, and higher-order conceptual relations to higher-order
spatial relations” (Gattis, 2004, p. 592). Relational structure activates relevant cog-
nitive processes such as metaphorical and analogical reasoning, which capitalize on
5 Three Fundamental Principles of Visualization 45
similarities observed between and among objects, concepts, and relations. The nov-
elty of Gattis’s (2004) notion of relational structure stems from individuals’ typical
experiences with everyday diagrams in which only general meanings are available
and follow-up work is needed, which involves constructing and reasoning about
particular details. The details include establishing a mapping on three levels, that
is, object to object, relation to relation, and higher order relation to higher order
relation.
In Chapter 4, I discuss the mutually determining role of structured visual
representations and alphanumeric symbolization in the construction of visuoal-
phanumeric symbols. We begin the chapter by considering at least three types of
mathematical symbols – iconic, indexical, and symbolic – that appear to share many
of the same characteristics above that Gattis (2004) inferred in the case of every-
day objects and concepts. In the case of everyday and logic problems, Fig. 2.15 is
a schematic model that situates the use of visual imagery in the beginning phase
that is then carried through and progresses toward more verbal and other symbolic
forms. Certainly, it is easier to state a rule or express a relationship in verbal or
symbolic form. Further, the phenomenon of visual fading seems to occur in prob-
lem situations that are of the sequential reproduction type (i.e., sequential in the
sense that general principles have already been established and reproduced because
of the recognition of a familiar structure). However, the verbal or the symbolic
phase does not necessarily imply the absence of visual images. Such images, in
fact, basically support judgment, reasoning, and decision-making strategies. For
example, among chess masters, their verbal articulations represent “judgments on
more abstract representations of board positions” (Kaufmann, 1985, p. 62) without
needing to repeatedly employ specific visual strategies. Among expert soccer play-
ers (and coaches, in particular, who communicate with their players using slates
Verbal
(Simultaneous – Sequential)
Type of processing
Visual
In this chapter, we focus on patterns such as Fig. 2.6a and address the primary
dilemma of how to develop reasonable abductive inferences (i.e., rules) and, con-
sequently, algebraic generalizations on the basis of limited information (i.e., the
3 Thagard’s (2010) recent theorizing concerning this topic involves understanding the implications
of embodied abduction, which involves “the use of multimodal representations” (p. 1). Embodied
abduction is inferred in many sections of this book.
5 Three Fundamental Principles of Visualization 47
known stages in any pattern) that apply to the unknown stages (i.e., extensions).
Since patterns are structures, in this chapter, we provide a visually drawn empirical
account of progressive evolution of structural thinking and generalization involv-
ing patterns in both figural and numerical forms. We clarify what and how we
mean by patterns and further explore Peirce’s notion of abductive reasoning or,
simply, abduction. We then justify a stronger claim in which accounts of progres-
sive formalization, schematization, symbolization, and mathematization all involve
accounts of progressive abductions. In two sections, we distinguish between entry-
level abductions and later or mature abductions that produce visuoalphanumeric
representations. We also discuss constraints and difficulties in making abductive
transitions, which have implications in the content and quality of structural thinking
and generalization. We close the chapter by considering how visuoalphanumeric
representations in Algebra 1 and structured visual thinking at the elementary
level could support hypostatic abstraction and growth in functional thinking and
understanding.
Principle of reasoning: Many problem solvers employ imagistic reasoning in
organizing their thoughts and as an alternative to purely symbolic or linguistic
forms of reasoning. Imagistic reasoning oftentimes leads to meaningful associa-
tions, analogies, inferences, and relational structures. Yip (1991) observes that
professional engineers, physicists, scientists, and mathematicians sometimes expe-
rience difficulty in verbally articulating their “intuitive grasp” of a problem situation
but then still manage to convey their thoughts through graphs and visual, analogue,
and diagrammatic representations. Nersessian (1994), Buchwald (1989), Kaufmann
and Helstrup (1988), and Miller’s (1997) engaging description of Einstein’s propen-
sity for visual thinking in various aspects of his scientific achievements all provide
us with accounts of great scientists, mathematicians, and inventors who employed
imagery (e.g., visual, nonvisual such as spatial, etc.) and visual analogies primar-
ily in their process of discovery. For example, Hadamard, French mathematician,
frequently employed visual imagery “when matters became too complex” (quoted
in Kaufmann & Helstrup, 1988, p. 114). Einstein employed visual images in
developing a thought experiment that played a central role in his special theory
of relativity (Miller, 1997, p. 61). Buchwald’s (1989) historical account of the
wave theory of light in the 1830s includes a discussion of the significant role
of drawings in Augustin Fresnel’s polarization experiments. Inventors like Edison
employed heuristics that were hinged on a visual process that “manipulate(d) both
a device-like conception (mental model) and a set of physical artifacts (mechanical
representations) in order to create a new object” (Carlson & Gorman, 1990, p. 417).
Even in less dramatic cases, the comprehensive review of Kaufmann and Helstrup
(1988) and the case studies developed by Nersessian (1994) show convergence in
the use of imagery in problem solving among people of various abilities. Pinker
(1990) also notes that in cases involving quantitative information, most people pre-
fer to process them using graphic forms of representation than other nonpictorial
means such as tables of numbers and lists of propositions.
Antonietti, Cerana, and Scafidi (1994) also share the above views on the general
effectiveness of images in various contexts, especially the flexible power of images
48 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
and their ability to assist people avoid the unnecessary use of procedures. However,
they are also quick to point out that
imagery is useful when subjects are aware of the goal, that is, when the free production
of mental images is oriented toward a specific endpoint. Imagery flows produced without
frames of reference . . . can generalize in a wide range of directions so it is probable that
subjects can follow an unproductive line of thinking.
(Antonietti et al., 1994, p. 188)
First, on matters involving nonspatial concepts such as time, age, and rate, Gattis
(2002) observed that the spatial reasoning of young children (ages 6 and 7 years old)
with little to no formal experiences in graphing appears to be “influenced by general
constraints in reasoning” and “these constraints precede the learning of graphing
[and more formal] conventions” (p. 1175).
Second, children’s knowledge acquisition processes involving everyday objects
involve marked transitions in orientation from (within and across) object properties
to object relationships (see, e.g., Gentner, 1983; Markman and Gentner, 2000).
Third, Antonietti’s (1999) investigation into college students’ use of visual rep-
resentations in various tasks (logical, mathematical, geometrical, and practical)
illustrates the view in which usefulness of imagery appears to be task dependent.
That is, an individual’s choice of using a visual representation seems to depend on
how he or she discerns the nature of the task. For example, if a task is perceived
to be involving numbers, like Dina in my study, who consistently approached every
pattern generalization task numerically, then he or she is likely to use a numerical
method without “tak(ing) advantage of possible intuitions suggested by visualiza-
tion” (Antonietti, 1999, p. 409). Antonietti also notes how students tend to perceive
visuals as helpful in dealing with situations that involve concrete situations but not
so in cases of abstract and conceptual problems.
Fourth, even when diagrams or pictures are shown with text, their level of com-
plexity and realism influences the content and quality of knowledge and comprehen-
sion that are acquired by individuals (Butcher, 2006). For example, more detailed,
schematic diagrams (e.g., Venn diagrams or the figural patterns in Chapter 5)
are much harder to deal with than are iconic and simplified diagrams. What is at
issue is the level of abstraction (i.e., transparency of relations) that is involved in
both picture types.
In Chapter 6, I analyze the relationship between visual thinking and diagram-
matic reasoning. Diagrammatic reasoning is viewed as a type of imagistic reasoning
that individual learners employ in establishing necessary mathematical knowledge.
It involves distributed actions of manipulating, discerning, interpreting, and infer-
ring relations on diagrams. A typical example is shown in Fig. 2.17, which shows
two diagrams in a school geometry text curriculum that have all the required infor-
mation needed to establish their deductive proofs. Talking about ancient Greek
mathematics and mathematicians, Netz (1999) refers to diagrams as “the metonym
of [their] mathematics” (p. 12), where diagrams and their corresponding proposi-
tions and proofs all convey the same meaning. In Chapter 6, however, we pursue
purposefully constructed diagrams in school algebra and number sense such as those
shown in Figs. 2.11a-c and 2.12 in order to demonstrate their significant role in pro-
viding students with structured images of symbolic forms and perhaps, more impor-
tantly, in “set(ting) up a world of reference” (Netz, 1999, p. 31) that allows them to
see the necessary conceptual relations. Readers are also referred back to examples
in previous chapters to establish the view that progressive diagrammatization can
support progressions in formalization, schematization, and mathematization of the
corresponding alphanumeric forms. Diagrams are, thus, seen beyond their typical
50 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
1. Let M be the midpoint of the side AB of an equilateral triangle ABC. Let N be a point on BC
such that MN BC. Prove that BC = 4BN.
A M B
2. Let P be a point outside a circle . Let A be a point on such that AP is tangent to . Let
BC be a chord of with C nearer to P than B such that BC || AP. Let the lines BP and CP meet
again at K and L, respectively. Let line KL meet AP at point M. Prove that M is the midpoint
of AP.
A M
P
K
B
C
Fig. 2.17 Two examples of geometric diagrams (Bautista & Garces, 2010)
I suggest that one way to advance the study of the role of visualizations in science involves
looking further at the social formation of communities of collecting and exchanging pic-
tures and understanding the historical (and increasingly institutionalized) mechanisms that
developed for framing some as “scientific” and some as “unscientific” objects. . . . Assessing
the history of scientific enterprises and responses to them compels us to look closely at the
social histories of individual images, including where they survive today and how and why
they came to be there.
(Tucker, 2006, p. 113)
The two complex issues that are pursued in Chapter 7 have much to inform
us about cultural and neurophysiological factors that influence the performance of
visual thinking in mathematical learning. Readers should be forewarned that the
findings discussed in this chapter have been drawn from investigations conducted
by experts in these fields, which certainly influenced various aspects of my own
research study that I have reported in the previous chapters. We begin the chapter
with a very interesting interpretive sociohistorical account that explains subtle dif-
ferences in visual attention and construction of concepts among students in diverse
classrooms. We also discuss the theory-laden and socialized nature of scientific
knowledge construction. Then we talk about accounts of differences in the way
mathematical objects and their images are perceived, captured, and interpreted as
a consequence of sociocultural modes of seeing that influence the nature and type
of mathematical content that is valued and produced. We also present a materialist
view of objects in mathematics, which sees visual forms of mathematical knowl-
edge as evocations of shared social and cultural feelings and practices. We then
give a cultural account of the nature of mathematical proofs in terms of particular
ontological perceptions of objects that influence the manner in which truths and the
empirical world are constructed. The remaining sections limn findings from research
conducted with individuals that have visual impediments at varying levels. We dis-
cuss perspectives drawn from a few studies that describe the nature of their image
construction and processing. The main point that is addressed deals with the need
to broaden our prevailing understanding of the sources and nature of visual rep-
resentations to include all aspects of our sensory modalities (i.e., auditory, haptic,
kinesthetic and, in some cases, olfactory) that provide redundant information and
need to converge and overlap in knowledge acquisition processes (Millar, 1994). We
close the chapter with a discussion on the significant role of multimodality learning
in mathematics.
imagery in neuroscientific terms. Despite the unsettling fact, I take the convergent
view of Chambers (1993), who claims that images are neither propositional nor pic-
torial but both, that is, “images are meaningful representations, that is, descriptive
information must accompany depictive information” (p. 79).
In mathematics, visual representations in the mind are seen as visual simu-
lations of the relevant objects, (numerical) processes, and relationships among
objects. This reminds of a situation in my Algebra 1 class when my students
tried to understand
√ and remember the process of deriving the quadratic formula
x = (−b ± b2 − 4ac)/2a to obtain the roots of the equation ax2 +bx+c=0, where
a, b, and c are real numbers and a = 0. While they could recall the formula by
singing, a mnemonic strategy they acquired from the Internet, some of them ini-
tially understood and eventually remembered the derivation process by visualizing
a reenactment of the process as it is applied on a particular example (see Fig. 3.12).
Hence, the modality of visual images in mathematics could also be seen as being
meaningful in Chambers’s (1993) sense, that is, they are neither figural/geometric
nor numerical/algorithmic in form but could be both. More broadly, visual thinking
in mathematics encompasses the use of all types of symbols from personally con-
structed images and signs to alphanumeric expressions to diagrams that all convey
meanings that are used to reason.
In Chapter 8, I discuss a progressive modeling view on visualization – the travel-
ing theory proposed in this book – in relation to the development and understanding
of mathematical objects, concepts, and processes on the basis of the two-triangular
structure shown in Fig. 2.8. The traveling theory articulates the necessity of pro-
gressions in visualization from the referential to the operative. Consequently, visual
forms evolve as well from personally constructed images to visual representations
to what I refer to as visuoalphanumeric representations. The structures of such rep-
resentations, in fact, should convey the same power as their symbolic counterparts
that are routed in solely alphanumeric terms. As I have noted in the Introduction, an
effective visual process in mathematics enables personal or subjective visual images
to evolve into more structured visual representations (in Goldin’s (2002) sense)
before fully transitioning into visuoalphanumeric representations. The term visuoal-
phanumeric conveys the interanimated symmetric reversal phenomenon of seeing
the visual in the symbolic and the symbolic in the visual, a product of heterogenous
inference drawn from several sources.
Also embedded in the progressive model is the notion of structural awareness that
enables learners to use their visual representations in constructing and experiencing
generality and (hypostasized) abstraction and in connecting intended mathemati-
cal properties in their own mathematical thinking. Figure 2.18 is a diagram of
the progressive model that I extrapolate in further detail in this particular chap-
ter. Briefly, visual thinking in mathematics takes places initially at the referential
phase in which mathematical knowledge is seen as generalizations and (hyposta-
sized) abstractions of arithmetical relationships. Visuals are employed that allow
individuals to easily recognize relationships that are instantiated by and through the
images. With more learning, the circle of individuation, acquisition, and reasoning
7 Forms and Levels of Visual Representations 55
Operative Phase
COMMUNITY
.
.
.
Acquisition
Progressive Schematization
INDIVIDUAL
grows in sophistication, leading to more formal types and specific forms of visual
representations at the operative phase.
The concentric circles in Fig. 2.18 incorporate, and visually convey, progres-
sive schematization in terms of local generalizations and (hypostasized) abstractions
that eventually reach a global state at the operative level. That is, once something
is generalized or abstracted from an object, an event, a process, or a relation,
it then becomes the basis that supports a later generalization or (hypostasized)
abstraction, and then again. Visual thinking is also seen initially as an individual
affair through the construction of subjective images that later evolves as a result of
frequent interactions with the community (in particular, the classroom). The com-
munity imposes its own practices at various levels of the epigenetic cycle, which is
then appropriated and internalized in varying degrees. However, despite the social
influence, individual learners interpretively reproduce4 what they find meaning-
ful to appropriate and internalize and so in some cases manage to retain some of
4 Throughout this book, I emphasize the need to reconcile between individual construction and
sociocultural practices. Corsaro’s (1992) notion of interpretive reproduction is an approach that
“stresses both the innovative and creative aspects of” every individual learner’s “participation in
society and the fact that” he or she “both contribute to and are affected by processes of social
reproduction” (Corsaro, Molinari, & Brown Rosier, 2002, p. 323).
56 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues
8 Instructional Implications
Without a doubt, the hallmark of school mathematics is its symbol system so pre-
cise, economical, and universal that it bears little semblance to ordinary language
systems in whatever cultural context. “The grammar of mathematical symbolism,”
O’Halloran (2005) points out, is “based on a range of condensatory strategies which
facilitate rankshift for the rearrangement of relations” (p. 131). This explains why
9 Overview of Chapter 3 57
9 Overview of Chapter 3
In Chapter 3, I explain the contexts of important terms we use throughout the book.
In doing so, readers obtain a more cohesive account of visual representations in
school mathematics and gain insights into how progressive schematization could be
achieved in a systematic manner. While such representations may initially emerge
as personally constructed images and images-in-the-wild, performing visual actions
within particular structures and customary ways of thinking allow such subjectively
drawn images to transform into more meaningful structured representations. To take
a case in point, Arman (Grade 2, 7 years old) initially added the two numbers sup-
plied in the word problem in Fig. 2.14b visually by drawing circles and counting
all. Later, when he learned to perceive whole numbers in terms of place value,
his pictures transitioned formally that allowed him to visually add more efficiently
using sticks and squares, as shown in Fig. 2.14b. How he developed such images
and the corresponding visuoalphanumeric method is the subject of mathematical
cognitive activity, which is rooted in explicit knowledge that is as much visual as it
is symbolic.
58 2 Visualization and Progressive Schematization: Framing the Issues