This document discusses scalar implicatures and their relationship to syntactic phenomena like intervention effects. It argues that scalar implicatures are computed simultaneously with syntactic computations. This allows implicatures to influence grammaticality judgments. Specifically, it explains how implicatures derived from negation under factive verbs like "because" can account for intervention effects in sentences with those verbs, resolving an issue for the proposal.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
8 views
2004 - Scalar Implicaturen Pi - 25
This document discusses scalar implicatures and their relationship to syntactic phenomena like intervention effects. It argues that scalar implicatures are computed simultaneously with syntactic computations. This allows implicatures to influence grammaticality judgments. Specifically, it explains how implicatures derived from negation under factive verbs like "because" can account for intervention effects in sentences with those verbs, resolving an issue for the proposal.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 1
S C A L A RI M P L I C A T U R E SP/O L A R I T YP H E N O M E N A /A N D T H E S Y N T A X / P R A C M A T I CI S
NTERFACE 6/ 86 S T R U C T U R EASN D B E Y O N D
causeof ungrammaticality in intervention cases.However, I think that the specific
This raises,however,a generalissuefor our proposal.Let me try to lay it out as form in which factivity getsrealizedinbecaaseclausesis indeedresponsiblefor their clearly as I can. Implicatures are, in general,cancellable.Shouldn't we expect, there- peculiarbehavior vis-d-vis intervention. Let me try to illustrate this idea. Consider a fore, ihat when they are removed, intervention effects should disappearor be weak- sentencelike (137a) on the LF schemaricallyindicaredin (137b): ened with any kindof intervener?Shouldn't we, in other words, expect that if we remove the relevant implicafixe, every should behave like many? For that matter, (I37) a. Johndidn't complainbecause Mary wasin a badmood. how can we possibly reiy on implicatures, generally held to be an extragrammatical b. not [JohncomplainedBEcAUsEMary wasin a bad mood] phenomenon,to account for the degradedgrammatical status of certain sentences? The point is that, for independentreasorls,the claim that implicatures are exffa- The problem is the following. If, assumingan LF-isomorphic to (137b), we ernbed grammatical is probably wrong. Or rather, whether we like to think of them as extra- anNPI in the main clause,we get intervention (whereasif we embedit in the subor- grammatical or not, scalar implicatures are computed in parallel to the syntactic dinateclause,we do not). Now supposethat the factive natureof becauseclausesis computation, and (at appropriate stages)the results of the two computational pro- due to the circumstancethat they actually involve a double assertion.Suppose,in ..rr., are accessibleto each other. Look in particular at the present setup. For any other terms, that a sentencesuch as "John complained becauseMary was in a bad expressiono, we have a well-defined characterizationof its plain meaning lloll and mood" is literally interpretedas "John complainedand that was causedby Mary's oflts strong one llslls. This enablesus to directly state a condition in NPl-licensing beingin a bad mood." Accordingly, the logical form of a plain (nonnegated)because in terms of strong meanings. Strengtheningmust be checked with respectto strong clauselike (138a)is as shownin (138b): meanings.The fact that implicatures can be cancelled (i.e., that in certain contexts *. *unt to useplain meanings)does not and cannot affect this fact. If sentenceswith (138) a. Johncomplained because Mary wasin a badmood any failto be stronger than the strong version of the corresponding sentenceswith b. lJohncomplained]i md cAUsE(Mary wasin a badmood,xi) some,the condition on any licensing cannotbe met. And that's the end of it. To clarify further, Suppose,for example, I try to say, "I doubt that every student So,becauseclausesare covert conjunctive statementswhere the first conjunct is the has any background." Grammar gives me two meanings,the plain one ll I doubt that mainclause(which is actuallyasserted)and the secondconjunct is formedby the cAUSE every student has any backgroundll and the strong one lll doubt that every student operator;the secondargumentof the latter [x1in (l3Sb)] is a covert pronominal ele- has any backgroundlls.It doesnot matter which one I choose.Whichever one I choose, mentbound by the main clause.This reflects the intuition that "p becauseq" does two I am required to check whether it entails the relevant competitor, which is lll doubt things:assertsp and adds to it a specification of what causesit. Now consider what that every studenthas some backgroundlls.Since that fails, the sentencein question wouldhappenif we embeda structurelike (138b)under negation,as in (139): is ruled out. The disappearanceof intervention with numeralsor a quantifier like many is an all togetherdifferent matter. In that case,by simply choosinga suitable scale (139) not [[Johncomplained]; andcAUsE(Marywasin a badmood,x1)l (which we independentlyknow that we must be able to do), we can get a strong meaninglll doubt that many studentshave any backgroundlls,which is equivalentto Formula(139) is of the form - (p ^ q); such formulas, as we saw above,generally its plain meaning; with respect to such an interpretation, strengthening is met and implicate(p v q). That is, the strong meaningof (139) would be ony itgrammatical. Independentlymotivated axioms on scalespreventme from doing the same with every (and other operators) (140) - [[Johncomplained]1 n causn(Mary wasin a badmood,x1)l Let us now turn to other types of sentential operators-t/ and becauseclauses. n [[Johncomplained],v causr (Mary wasin a badmood,x1)l A puzzling aspectof intervention noted above was the fact that r/clauses, although involving u uniu"tral quantifier over worlds, show no intervention effect. The an- Given the factivity of cAUsE(i.e., the fact that CAUSE (p, q) entailsp ^ q), formula swer to that, frorn the presentpoint of view, is straightforward. It is not the inherent (if (la0) is provably equivalentto feature of an operator that causesintervention. It is, rather, its position on a scale any). ffclauses are not part of a lexicalized scale.Hence, under negation they don't (141) Uohncomplainedli n - cAUsE(Marywasin a badmood,x;) trau" a positive implicature of the sort that could get in the way of NPl-licensing. This leads us to the issue of becauseclauses.They do show intervention effects. In otherwords, the strongmeaningof (139) would be (141). This would explain why However, just like fclauses, becauseclausesdo not seemto belong to a scale.Hence, wide scopenegation of a becauseclause is generally construed as negatingjust the it is not obvious what my approachmight have to say about them. Although this might cause,not what gets caused.A further consequenceof this approachis that when- well turn out to be a problr*, thrr" area few preliminary considerationsthat are worth evernegationis construedas having wide scope,an NPI in the main clausecan never pointing out. The obvious observation is that becauseclausesare strongly factive. be licensed.Consider,for example,(121d'), whose logical form (under the current ihir, pi, ,., is not enough to conclude much. We know that NPIs may be licensed hypothesis)is given in what follows: by cenain factives, llke be surprised,2eandthus factivity by itself can hardly be the