Article On Zizoulos Theology of Personhood
Article On Zizoulos Theology of Personhood
2014
Tingcui Jiang
Hong Kong Baptist University
Recommended Citation
Jiang, Tingcui, "A critical study on Zizioulas' ontology of personhood" (2014). Open Access Theses and Dissertations. 108.
https://repository.hkbu.edu.hk/etd_oa/108
This Thesis is brought to you for free and open access by the Electronic Theses and Dissertations at HKBU Institutional Repository. It has been
accepted for inclusion in Open Access Theses and Dissertations by an authorized administrator of HKBU Institutional Repository. For more
information, please contact [email protected].
A Critical Study on Zizioulas’
Ontology of Personhood
JIANG Tingcui
Doctor of Philosophy
I hereby declare that this thesis represents my own work which has been done
after registration for the degree of PhD at Hong Kong Baptist University, and has not
been previously included in a thesis, dissertation submitted to this or other institution
for a degree, diploma or other qualification.
Signature:_________________
i
ABSTRACT
In Part II, I will explore the being of man as personhood. The Father as personal
cause bequeaths us an ontology of personhood which also provides the metaphysical
ground for the being of human persons. Personhood rather than human nature is the
centre of anthropology. The mode of existence of the Trinity is the foundation for the
transformation of human existence from a biological hypostasis to an ecclesial
hypostasis. Personal otherness is constitutive of human person. Otherness as an
ontological existence transforms the relationship between human beings in
communion. The coexistence of otherness and communion in a Trinitarian model
provides a foundation for the criticisms of Levinas’ concept of otherness without
communion.
In Part III, I will criticize the Western views of God and person, but also analyze
and criticize Zizioulas’ ontology of personhood. The significance of the ontology of
personhood is shown by its providing an insightful and radical critique of the
substantialist Trinitarian theology which understands One God as substance foremost.
At the same time, it provides strong criticisms of individualist understanding of the
concept of personhood.
ii
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
Above all, I would like to thank my family, the pastor, sisters and brothers from
church for their encouragement and support which are the sources of my strength and
confidence to sustain my study and research in the past few years especially when my
health was not in good condition. Without their prayers and care I would not have
survived those tough days.
iii
TABLE OF CONTENTS
Declaration i
Abstract ii
Acknowledgments iii
Table of Contents iv
Introduction 1
iv
Chapter Two Analysis of Zizioulas’ ontology of personhood 51
v
Part II From God’s Person to Human Person 89
Chapter Three The person of the Father as the ontological ground for
the personhood of human beings 90
3.2 The being of God as the ontological ground for the being of man 95
vi
4.2 Personal communion in otherness 117
vii
5.2.4 Zizioulas’ reiteration of the Cappadocian notion of the Son’s
mediation in the procession of the Spirit 157
5.2.5 Substantialism dictates that unity precedes diversity logically or
ontologically in God 160
viii
7.2 Criticisms and defenses of Zizioulas’ ontology of personhood 207
Conclusion 225
Bibliography 229
ix
Introduction
John Zizioulas (1931-) is a famous contemporary theologian from the Eastern
from the traditional Western substantialist approach. I will call this approach in this
into the details, I will first introduce the overall shape of my research in the
following sections.
our era. The Christian gospel consists of an account of how God saved man, and
before that gospel can be understood something must be known about God and
about man. What kind of God would the Christian God be? How can we understand
the being of God and the being of His creature man or the individual human
Each research also has its presuppositions, its basic concepts and its direction. It
means that there can be different preliminary understandings of the being of the
entities into which the inquiry is being made. Therefore, there is a necessity for an
1
Zizioulas calls his theology a personalist approach which is contrasted with a substantialist
approach: “this may explain why theology in the West, with the help of St Augustine’s decisive
influence, has developed a substantialist rather than a personalist approach to Trinitarian theology.”
See John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness: Further Studies in Personhood and the Church, ed.
Paul McPartlan (London: T&T Clark, 2006), 124.
2
In this thesis, I often use “man” to denote the human species for convenience’s sake. It, of course,
does not mean that I accept the superiority of males over females.
1
Macquarrie writes: “Is the being of man, for instance, already conceived as
theology, traditional Western theology formed the knowledge of the being of God
and human. For example, from Justin Martyr to Augustine, the early theologians
drew freely on Greek sources, especially Plato, for their theological work.4 Thomas
Aquinas made use of the philosophy of Aristotle in his exposition of the Christian
faith. His scholastic theology took theological speculation to a whole new level.
The knowledge of God and the knowledge of man he thus arrived at became the
by a philosophy of being, and an inquiry into the idea of being becomes his
theological assumption, from which his theology sets out to make inquiries. With a
3
John Macquarrie, An Existentialist Theology (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1973), 6.
4
For example, Justin Martyr, Dialogue with trypho. See http://earlychristianwritings.
Com/text/justinmartyr-dialoguetrypho.html. Augustine, The Trinity, trans. Edmund Hill, O. P.
(Brookly, N. Y.: New City Press, 1991).
5
Scholastic thought is known for rigorous conceptual analysis and the careful drawing of
distinctions. Scholasticism was the movement based on Aristotle but developed beyond Aristotle. It
is incorporated into Christianity and throughout Christendom. Scholasticism places a strong
emphasis on dialectical reasoning to extend knowledge by inference, and to resolve contradictions.
For example, Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica.
6
Rudolf K. Bultmann, New Testament and Mythology and Other Basic Writings, ed. and trans. S. M.
Ogden (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1984).
2
develops a theological hermeneutic on the basis of this new understanding.
of God and the being of human are not conceived as substances but in an alternative
the person. He uses the term ‘person’ in an uncustomary sense in accordance with
ontology, Zizioulas’ human being mainly focuses on his personal mode of being in
communion with God. The most important result is that the theological concept of
person is drawn from the Person of the Father who is the cause of the personal
divine existence. The concept is quite different from that of philosophy. I will
perspective.
7
Zizioulas writes: “It is a presence that seems to come to us from outside this world—which makes
the notion of person, if properly understood, perhaps the only notion that can be applied to God
without the danger of anthropomorphism…Personhood thus proves to be in this world—through
man—but not of this world.” See John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 141, footnote 84.
3
interchangeable in Zizioulas’ Trinitarian theology. 8 In my thesis, I distinguish
the relational character of personhood over and against the reduction of personhood
terms of two terms: ekstasis and hypostasis. The term ekstasis means a movement
that in and through his communion a personhood affirms his own identity and his
particularity. Hypostasis ‘supports his own nature’ in a particular and unique way.
The notion of hypostasis is identical with personhood rather than substance since it
Communion and otherness are two aspects of the concept of person. The Father
approach. The Eucharistic experience implies that life is imparted and actualized
of being and life with communion to the ultimate origin of existence, God himself.
8
For example, Zizioulas writes: “There is no ousia in the nude, that is, without hypostasis, to refer to
God’s substance without referring simultaneously to this personhood.” See John Zizioulas,
Communion and Otherness, 125.
9
Ibid., 101.
4
Otherness implies personal uniqueness. For Zizioulas, otherness is primary and
constitutive of the very idea of being. The human being is defined through
absolute Other. It is not an ethical concept but an ontological concept. It means that
the Other can truly exist as Other only if it is ultimately regarded as person or
hypostasis and not as self or nature, and every being should be treated as an
Zizioulas often uses ‘man’ to refer to all human beings. In accordance with his
usage, I also use this word in this way which does not imply a sexist understanding.
theologians regard that the Cappadoican Fathers in the East and Augustine in the
West have said the final words on the Trinity. In the Augustinian tradition, God is
one because of the one ousia which is equally shared by the three persons. It
involves the ontological primacy of the ‘one God’ over the ‘Triune God’.10 The
understands the three persons of the Holy Trinity as relations within one substance.
The priority of one substance over the three persons, as well as the identification of
the One God with the one substance, and not with the Father is quite clear in this
case. If we give priority to the ‘One God’, we make the Trinity logically secondary
from an ontological point of view.11 Boethius (d. 525) and Thomas Aquinas (d.
10
Augustine divides between economic and immanent trinity with his psychological model of trinity,
which described the inner life of God as being like a human’s memory, intellect, and will. It is
Thomas Aquinas’ scholastic theology which applies this kind of theological speculation to a summit.
11
See John Zizioulas, The One and the Many: Studies on God, Man, the Church, and the World
Today, ed. Fr. Gregory Edwards (California: Sebastian Press, 2010), 10, footnote, 22.
5
1247) provide the philosophical-theological treatises on the doctrines of the Trinity.
They assumed the authority of the early church’s council regarding the Trinity
(three persons sharing one substance). However, they may also have made the
doctrine of the Trinity irrelevant to the everyday life of Christians by making the
During the sixteenth century some new reflection on the Trinity begins with the
theologians and their heirs. In the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, the rise of
doctrine of the Trinity. They teach about ‘reasonable Christianity’. At the same era
the rise of Pietism and Revivalism called ‘enthusiastic religion’ counters the Deism
in Western Christianity.14
looks for the ‘essence of Christianity’ apart from the dogma of the Trinity which is
12
For example, Anabaptists like Menno Simons and Balthasar Hubmaier reject the classical,
orthodox doctrine of the Trinity; Michael Servetus and Faustus Socinus, the two best-known
heretics during the sixteenth century which was constituted by a relatively diverse group of
unorthodox protestants—rejected from Protestantism by other protestants, were known as the
anti-trinitarians or anti-Nicenes. See Roger E. Olson and Christopher A. Hall, The Trinity
(Michigan/ Cambridge: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2002), 75.
13
The most influential deists are John Locke (1632-1704), John Toland (1670-1722), and Matthew
Tindal (1656-1733). The deists or rationalists tended toward an implicit anti-Nicene attitude. The
representative book of Locke is The Reasonableness of Christianity (1695) which has an influence
on the rise of Deism; Toland, Christianity Not Mysterious (1696); Matthew Tindal, Christianity as
Old as the Creation (1730). The English philosopher John Locke is often considered one of the
fathers of modern, Enlightenment philosophy and Deism. They influence the educated, intellectual
elite of Great Britain and North America and spread to the European continent.
14
Such as Philipp Jakob Spener (1635-1705), Nikolaus Ludwig Count Von Zinzendorf (1700-1760),
John Wesley (1703-1791), and Jonathan Edwards (1703-1758). They tend to accept Nicene
orthodoxy as a given and focus on experience of God and Christ. Zinzendorf is the leader of the
pietistic Moravians. His contribution to the doctrine of the Trinity is an analogy of the Trinity as ‘the
holy family’ and the Holy Spirit as ‘our dear Mother’. Jonathan Edwards is a leader in the revival
known as the Great Awakening of the 1740s and also a passionate Calvinist. He has little new to
contribute to the doctrine of the Trinity. His theological work focuses on questions of human
depravity, divine sovereignty, original sin, and salvation. See Roger E. Olson and Christopher A.
Hall, The Trinity, 80-88.
6
Albrecht Ritschl (1822-1889) and Adolf Harnack (1851-1930) greatly influence
the North American Protestant movement known as the ‘social gospel’. Walter
Rauschenbusch (1861-1918), a leader of social gospel, has little use for the doctrine
of the Trinity. Reinhold Niebuhr (1892-1971) questions the social gospel’s idea of
social ethics for its inability to respond to the injustices of the Industrial
Revolution.
inadequate expression of the Christian faith, because they lack a personal truth.
During the twentieth century a new reflection on the Trinity becomes a tide. A
personal or a living God rather than a substantialist God becomes necessary for the
era. A study of the doctrine of the Trinity should relate to the deeper existential
needs of the human person. Zizioulas points out: “the faith in the Holy Trinity is not
one’s existence to this faith; Baptism in the Trinity means entering into a certain
way of being which is that of the Trinitarian God. Trinitarian theology has profound
15
See David M. Whitford ed. Reformation and Early Modern Europe: A Guide to Rresearch
(Missouri: Truman State University Press, 2007), 137. In 1958, the Catholic historian Ernst Walter
Zeeden suggested a new approach: confession-building or confessional formation.
16
John Zizioulas, “The Doctrine of God the Trinity Today: Suggestions for an Ecumenical Study”,
in Alasdair I. C. Heron ed., The Forgotten Trinity (London: BBC/CCBI Inter-Church House, 1991),
7
living God: “By ‘word’ we do not mean the single word. This word, as a unit of
mind, but the reality which gave meaning to their lives.”18 Theology should relate
theology and revives the doctrine of Trinity. It was extended by the Austrian
revived Richard of St. Victor’s and the Cappadocian Fathers’ social analogy of the
Trinity from the suffering of God on the cross, in dialogue with the traditional
depersonalized God. Latin American Liberation theologian Leonardo Boff (b. 1938)
LaCugna (1952-1997) wrote a massive book on the Trinity entitled God for Us: The
Trinity and Christian Life in the last decade of the century, which also supports a
personalist turn.
The doctrine of the Trinity is the source of the renewal at once of Christianity
19.
17
G. Ebeling, The Nature of Faith (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1961), 185.
18
John Hick, Philosophy of Religion (Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice-Hall, 1963), 61.
8
itself and its influence on culture. Eastern Orthodox theologian John Zizioulas
linked the doctrine of the Trinity with the ontology of person in communion. The
book Being as Communion by Zizioulas was called a landmark book for the
century. We can see the importance of John Zizioulas’ ontology of person through a
For Barth, the Trinitarian formula una substantia--tres personae means one
divine subject in three different modes of being. 19 To avoid the use of words
connoting consciousness as a modern concept, Barth uses his own term ‘mode’ to
replace the term ‘person’. 20 Then the concept of ‘person’ is not a clear concept of
concept of person in the theology of Barth: “It is rather that it fails to reclaim the
the modern age.22 Karl Rahner questions the traditional Western view of the Trinity
and calls for a return to the Biblical view and the Greek Patristic position which
identifies God with Father, rather than with the divine substance, as the Augustinian
and medieval scholastic traditions do. He proposes a personal God which is called
19
Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, vol. I, eds. G. W. Bromiley and T. F. Torrance (Edinburgh: T & T
Clark, 1963), 363.
20
Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, vol. I, 355. Barth writes: “We have avoided the term ‘person’ in
the thesis at the head of the present section. It was never adequately clarified when first introduced
into the Church’s vocabulary, nor did the interpretation with it was later given and which prevailed
in mediaeval and post-Reformation Scholasticism as a whole really brings this clarification, nor has
the injection of the modern concept of personality into the debate achieved anything but fresh
confusion.”
21
Colin E. Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian theology (Edingburgh: T & T Clark, 1997), 195.
22
Karl Rahner was a leader at the Second Vatican Council (Vatican II) in the early 1960s and
continued to work for change of the church’s thought and life after the Council until his death in the
early 1980s. His best-known and most influential monograph on the doctrine is entitled The Trinity.
Rahner’s main target throughout his life was to oppose widespread secularism, especially in the
West. See Karl Rahner, Foundations of Christian Faith: An Introduction to the Idea of Christianity
(New York: Crossroad, 1982), 46.
9
God the Father.23 Like Barth, Rahner does not treat the concept of person clearly as
to the doctrine of Trinity.24 In order to avoid the modern concept of person, Rahner
Trinity; he prefers to use the description ‘the threefold God’ instead of the ‘triune
God’ and “transforms the classical doctrine of the Trinity into the reflection Trinity
of the absolute subject.” 25 Therefore, some problems arise. For example, the
relation between the Father, the Son and the Spirit is difficult to describe: “Because
the modes of subsistence within the Trinity do not represent distinct centers of
consciousness and action, there cannot be any mutual ‘Thou’ between them
either.”26 Jürgen Moltmann criticized Rahner because he did not apply the concept
of person to the three persons of the Trinity but applies the concept of person for the
unique essence and consciousness of God: “And in his way he introduced this
individualistic idea into the nature of God himself. The ‘one unique essence’ of God
exclusive sense.” 27 Through the brief survey above, it seems that despite the
linger on.
23
Ibid., 84. Rahner considers this one of the fundamental assertions about God. Karl Rahner starts
from the assumption that God is one self-communication of God, that is: “each one of the three
divine persons communicates himself to man in gratuitous grace in his own personal particularity
and diversity…since it implies a free personal act, since it occurs from person to person, as a
communication of ‘persons’.” See Karl Rahner, The Trinity, trans. J. Donceel (London: Burns &
Oates, 1986), 35.
24
See Karl Rahner, The Trinity, 43.
25
Ibid., 147.
26
Jürgen Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom: The Doctrine of God, trans. Margaret Kohl
(Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1993), 146.
27
Ibid.
10
3.2 A change of the view of the human person
At the same time, during the past century, from a perspective of anthropology,
there has been an increasing interest in the study of the concept of personhood,
because it is connected with issues like personal identity, the rights of the person or
Western tradition has its roots in Augustine and Boethius. Since Descartes
discovers the cogito, the external world and other people have always been a source
being the Other. The other has been ignored. Therefore, it not only involves an issue
relationship leads to indifference and alienation which may cause mental illness and
social problems.
Fathers’ Trinitarian theology. Therefore, this research includes two parts: one
involves the view of God, and the other involves the view of human person. In
28
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion (Crestwood, N. Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1985);
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality (Crestwood, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press,
1984); Christos Yannaras, Orthodoxy and the West (Brookline, Massachusetts: Holy Cross Orthodox
Press, 2006); Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us: The Trinity and Christian Life (San Francisco:
HarperSanFrancisco, 1991); Colin E. Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian Theology (Edinburgh:
T&T Clark, 1997); Leonardo Boff, Trinity and Society (Maryknoll, N.Y.: Orbis, 1988).
29
Bo-Myung Seo, A Critique of Western Theological Anthropology: Understanding Human Beings
in a Third World Context (Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press, 2005), 88.
11
contrast with Western traditional concepts of person, divine persons will be
Visiting Professor at Geneva, King’s College London, and the Gregorian University,
committees for dialogue with the Roman Catholic Church, and with the Anglican
Church, and has been Secretary of Faith and Order at the World Council of
Studies in Personhood and the Church constitutes the single most significant
Orthodox academic theological work of the last half-century. In 2006, the book
Communion and Otherness was edited and published. It includes many articles
which explain the notion of personhood further. In 2010, Gregory Edwards edits
Zizioulas’ articles into a book The One and the Many: Studies on God, Man, and the
Church and the World Today. Up to now, his works include seven books. Most of
30
Douglas H. Knight, ‘Introduction’, in Douglas Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas:
Personhood and the Church (Aldershot, Hants/Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2007), 3.
31
John Zizioulas, Ellenismos Kai Christianismos: H Synatese ton duo Kosmon (Athens:
ApostolikeDiakonia, 2003). This would be rendered in English as Hellenism and Christianity: The
Meeting of Two Worlds. This work is not published in English. Being as Communion: Studies in
Personhood and the Church (Crestwood, NY: St Vladimirs Seminary Press, 1997); Eucharist,
Bishop, Church: The Unity of the Church in the Divine Eucharist and the Bishop During the First
Three Centuries (Brookline, MA: Holy Cross, 2001); Communion and Otherness: Further Studies
in Personhood and the Church (London: T&T Clark, 2007); Lectures in Christian Dogmatics
(London: T&T Clark, 2009); The One and the Many: Studies on God, Man, the Church, and the
World Today (California: Sebastian Press, 2010). Remembering the Future: An Eschatological
Ontology (London: T&T Clark, 2012).
12
with ousia but with personhood,32 and One God is the personhood of the Father
rather than the ousia of God. It means that the personhood of the Father is the
initiator of personal being. What the Father ‘causes’ is a transmission not of ousia
but of personal otherness.33 Therefore, ‘One’ and ‘Many’ are constitutive of being
theology. His lectures have been edited in a book Lectures in Christian Dogmatics
in 2008. Although Zizioulas’ treatise Being as Communion was not at first greeted
1985, in the early 1990s it began to influence the reflection on Trinitarian theology
and represents in some ways the culmination of Trinitarian thought in the twentieth
theology.34 For example, Yves Congar considers Zizioulas to be “ ‘one of the most
original and profound theologians of our epoch’ and that he presents ‘a penetrating
Barth’s mode of being and Rahner’s mode of subsistence, Zizioulas retains the use
of the word persons in relation to the three persons of the Trinity and he reinterprets
32
All three of the great Cappadocian fathers, Basil the Great (330-370), Gregory of Nazianzus
(329-390), and Gregory of Nyssa (335-394), were key contributors to the Trinitarian reflection in the
fourth century.
33
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 130.
34
See Roger E. Olson & Christopher A. Hall, The Trinity, 112-113.
35
On the cover of the book John Zizioulas, Being as Communion.
36
He considers that the modern dilemma of personhood is that by emphasizing self-existence in
freedom as the true essence of personhood, and regarding suicide as the ultimate expression of
freedom, the question of self-actualization cannot be truly answered.
13
also emphasizes a notion of a living God, a personal God. A personal God provides
a ground for the being of the human person. The notion of ontological otherness
also preserves the dignity of the individual. Theology and anthropology are in the
end inseparable. It is the purpose of this research to investigate how Zizioulas deals
the first is the Father as cause which has been questioned by many Western
T. F. Torrance particularly cites from Cyril and Athanasius to oppose the primacy of
the Son and the Spirit at least appearing to be less truly God than the Father. Alan
Torrance also regards that the Cappadocian projection of causal notions into the
being with communion. Gunton insists that all three persons are together the cause
The second issue concerns the ontological concept of person: is the concept of
person really from the Cappadocian Fathers? Some Orthodox scholars such as
Lucian Turcescu, Andrew Louth and John Behr have claimed that Zizioulas’
Turcescu questions the legitimacy of Zizioulas’ use of materials taken from the
Cappadocian Fathers. John Behr’ objection is that Zizioulas’ theology is “an odd
37
John Behr, ‘The Trinitarian Being of the Chruch’, St Vladimir’s Theological Quarterly 48.1/2004:
67-68.
14
At the same time, Zizioulas’ theology gains support by many theologians. Alan
objection to Zizioulas’ theology, Alan Brown criticizes that the meaning of Behr’s
objection is not entirely clear, and argues that concepts such as ‘being’, ‘logos’,
‘truth’ and ‘life’ are all Scriptural. 38 Colin Gunton, in his thesis on “Person and
traces the roots of Western culture back to the thought of Augustine and Boethius
which provides an argument for the individualistic tendency in which the other is
regarded as a threat. Douglas Farrow, in his thesis, ‘Person and Nature: The
There are some articles in the book The Theology of John Zizioulas edited by
Douglas Knight which explore Zizioulas’ thought especially. There are some other
books which discuss Zizioulas’ concepts of communion and person. For example,
Patricia Fox’s book, God as Communion: John Zizioulas, Elizabeth Johnson, and
the Retrieval of the Symbol of the Triune God, investigates Zizioulas’ central
which contrasts Karl Rahner and John Zizioulas on triunity. Alan Torrance highly
between truth and communion—‘the essential thing about a person lies precisely in
38
Alan Brown, ‘On the Criticism of Being as Communion in Anglophone Orthodox Theology’, in
Douglas H. Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 71.
39
Colin Gunton, ‘Person and Particularity’, in Douglas Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas:
Personhood and the Church, 97-108.
40
Douglas Farrow, ‘Person and Nature: The Necessity-Freedom Dialectic in John Zizioulas’, in
Douglas Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 109-124.
15
his being a revelation of truth, not as ‘substance’ or ‘nature’ but as a ‘mode of
existence’”.41
John Zizioulas, over how to adequately conceive the doctrine of the Trinity as an
expression of the realism of divine-human communion, and hence, of the God who
is both transcendent and immanent. 42 In part three of Paul Collins’ book Trinitarian
Theology: West and East— Karl Barth, the Capppdocian Fathers, and John
Zizioulas, he discusses the concept of personhood, the category of being and the
category of communion.
focus on the level of relation and particularity which is contrasted with the
ontology of relationality.
41
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation—with Special Reference to Volume One of Karl Barth’s Church Dogmatics
(Edingurgh: T&T Clark, 1996), 304.
42
Aristotle Papanikolaou, Being with God: Trinity, Apophaticism, and Divine-Human Communion
(Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006).
16
Firstly, although personalist ontology is an assertion of the metaphysics of the
the concept of personhood, we will find that the emphasis of Zizioulas’ theology is
the other. Therefore, it is not sufficient for us to explain person only in terms of
of God and human beings from the traditional solipsism. For a long time, whether
Secondly, some critics recognize that there is no dimension of sin in the theology
of Zizioulas, but do not explore why Zizioulas puts the sin on a moral level rather
than an ontological level. They have no analysis from the concept of personhood
itself. I will point out the distinction between the Cappadocian and Zizioulas’
overlooking sin and justice because Zizioulas regards them as substantial concepts.
How to solve this problem? I will explain sin and justice and as relational or
existential concepts. Thus, it will not conflict with the relational concept of
personhood and personhood can include the concepts of sin and justice itself.
17
Therefore, sin and justice are both substantial and relational or existential. I think
that it is a more complete understanding of the being of God and the human person
Thirdly, between the self and the Other, Zizioulas only emphasizes an
ontological principle: the Other prior to the self. Because of the lack of the notion of
7. Summary of thesis
The thesis includes three parts. Part one mainly explores the source of ontology
Chapter one traces the background and source of the ontology of personhood. There
the identification of hypostasis not with ousia but with personhood; and an
identification of God’s ultimate being with a person rather than ousia. A new idea of
one God comes into being. It influences the Council of Constantinople in 381 CE
the Father as personal cause. Zizioulas’ Trinitarian formula is not completely same
and philosophical contexts. I also discuss some theological criticisms of the Father
ontology of relationality.
consists of two chapters. Chapter three shows the person of God as the existential
ground for the personhood of human. This chapter clarifies the basic meaning and
three characteristics of personhood; the doctrine of the Trinity gives us the truth of
18
our own existence: the Father as personal cause for personal existence and
personhood in the light of Christology. At the same time I will introduce two modes
of existence and the transformation from one type to the other: from biological
Chapter four explores personal otherness and communion and clarifies the basic
being. It raises a criticism of the self prior to the Other. ‘Otherness’ as a primary
same time, because otherness can only exist in communion, it can be applied to
Part three includes three chapters. Chapter five attempts to explain why the
Western idea of One God causes at least three problems in Trinitarian theology
from the perspective of ontology of personhood: the first is the separation of the
oikonomia and theologia in the doctrine of God; the second is the problem of
Filioque; the third is that unity precedes diversity logically or ontologically in God.
Western substantialist anthropology, criticize this concept which does not include
otherness and communion, criticize the relationship between God and human as
Chapter seven analyzes the contributions and criticizes the flaws of Zizioulas’
ethical categories alone and his theology is detached from the injustice of the
20
Part I
Persons-in-Communion
21
Chapter One
ontology of personhood
In Greek ontology, Ousia as a single reality is more real than individual beings.
person. Death dissolves the concrete individual or person completely but not his
impossible too. However, for Jewish and Christian theology, the situation is
different. Firstly as Christ says, God is not “the God of the dead, but the God of the
living” as witnessed in the book of Moses, “I am the God of Abraham, and the God
of Isaac, and the God of Jacob.”(Mark 12:26-27) The individual can attain eternal
found in the Bible, whereas hypostasis appears in Wisdom, Paul, and Hebrews.44
43
Person and personhood in this thesis should not be understood in terms of ‘personality’, i.e., a
complex of natural, psychological or moral qualities; or in terms of self-consciousness. Person
cannot be conceived in itself as a static entity, but only as it relates to other persons. Person as a
relational category has a marked contrast with the Boethian individualistic tradition. See John
Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 212.
44
Christopher Stead, Divine Substance (Oxford: At the Clarendon Press, 1977), 161.
22
This chapter will analyze the influence of substantialism on the idea of God, its
the ontology of personhood. In this way, new ideas of God and ultimate reality have
developed by Christian writers of the first four centuries A.D., and especially the
Trinitarian concept of one God in three persons. Ousia is a Greek word. From the
standpoint of etymology, ousia means being; it is the abstract noun connected with
the verb ‘to be’. Ousia means ‘thing-of-a-kind’ in Plato and the thing in question is
real. It corresponds to the question ‘What is x?” Ousia is more real than any
unchanging Forms which lend to the world of appearances some measure of order
and consistency. In the Timaeus, Plato shows how the unchanging Forms come to
Metaphysics Book XII, Aristotle bases his doctrine of God on his cosmology. He
45
Aristotle, Categories, 2a 31; 3b 10.
23
Divinity is conceived as a perfect mind, and divinity must be absolutely one. On the
other hand, Platonic use of ousia as a collective term denotes ‘unchanging (genuine,
and therefore immaterial) reality. When Christian theologians applied these terms
Irenaeus takes over the word from his Gnostic opponents, and he applies this word
At the end of the third century, homoousios has been used to formulate the
upon the phrase una substantia to express the unity manifested in the three Persons
of the Godhead. The una substantia represents the stuff or reality, called spiritus,
which the Second and Third Persons derive from the First.48 Origen was the first
writer to use the term homoousios to indicate the Son’s relationship to the Father.
The terms ousia and homoousios were drawn into the Arian controversy: the Arians
claim that the Father is necessarily superior to the Son in status and the Son is
derived from the will of the Father; The Son is not ‘consubstantial with him’.
Therefore, ousia and homoousios had become the focus of Nicene controversy.
The Nicene Fathers have interpreted homoousios along the line which suggests
that Father and Son are identical in the strictest sense, i.e., ‘a single reality’. ‘A
46
Christopher Stead, Divine Substance (Oxford: At the Clarendon Press, 1977), 190.
47
Ibid., 201.
48
Ibid., 202.
49
Ibid., 248.
24
easily leads to an understanding which regards Father and Son as aspects of a single
Christopher Stead points out that the usage of ousia in the early Christian
problems in his book Divine Substance. I will choose two main themes from Stead
Because hypostasis and ousia are used as synonyms, the Son will not be another
hypostasis. As Christopher Stead points out: “We do not find clear references to a
system in which Father, Son, and Holy Spirit are described as constituting one
50
Ibid., 131.
51
Ibid., 169-170.
52
Ibid., 249.
25
At the end of the second century, Tertullian (c. 160-225AD) is the first to employ
the word ‘Trinity’ (una substantia, tres personae). He indicates the unity of God
with ‘substance’, and the other word ‘persons’ means plurality. While `substance’
persona has proved that the word involves a combination of individuality and
never defines it in either way but he does use it in both legal and philosophical
senses. In Tertullian’s Trinitarian theology, the words persona and substantia have
not dissolved the tension between the three and the one. The history of the concept
Marius Victorinus does not use it in his account of the Trinity. Hilary and Ambrose
tell us little. Even Augustine is less than lucid on Trinitarian usage. The chief
problem is Christological not Trinitarian: how can Jesus, God and man, be one
person? ...It is claimed that only in Boethius, who imports the meaning of
The Western Greek writer, Hippolytus, translated the formula for the Christians
of the East. Prosopon has been used in Greek with reference to the Trinity first by
God. The word ‘personae’ has been expressed in Greek as ‘prosopon’ which meant
53
Eric Osborn, Tertullian, First Theologian of the West (UK: Cambridge University Press, 1997),
132-133.
54
Ibid., 138.
55
Ibid.
56
G. L. Prestige, God in Patristic Thought (London, S.P.C.K., 1952), 159.
26
being. The Greek term ‘prosopon’ replacing the Tertullian Latin term ‘personae’
risks denoting that “persons would be fronts for the essence of God behind or
Sabellius (fl.ca. 215) taught in Rome and his teachings became widespread in the
West. At the beginning of the third century, this approach to deal with the Christian
doctrine of God in terms of the Logos took the form of modalism, for which the
persons of the Trinity are roles that God takes for the sake of creation. God played
the role of Father in the Old Testament, the Son in the New Testament, and Holy
Spirit in our own time, adopting these three identities to perform particular
Sabellius uses the term ‘person’ not in an ontological sense but roles assumed by
the One God. Thus `person’ has been used in the singular, denoting only “One
Person” in God.
In the East, Origen (c. 185-254AD) used the term “hypostases” for the Trinity.
Origen affirms that each of the Three is a distinct hypostasis from all eternity, not
just manifested in the economy as for Tertullian. It stems directly from the idea of
will and action. The ultimate ground of His being is the Father, who alone is ‘the
57
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, ed. Douglas Knight (London: T & T Clark,
2008), 50.
58
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 38, see footnote 30.
59
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 48.
27
fountain-head of deity’. As Kelly said, “one must be careful, however, not to
From Origen onwards the East continually replaces the term ‘person’ with
‘hypostasis’, which means God had three unchanging beings, ‘tres substantiae’. It
risked collapsing into tritheism and it contradicted the Latin expression ‘una
Trinitarian formulation.61
The Logos approach has originated with the Greek apologists, particularly Justin
and above all Origen. The concept of Logos for Philo is an instrument for
harmonizing Greek cosmology with the Old Testament. On the basis of the Fourth
Gospel, Justin applies this idea to Christ, and establishes a foundation for
communication with the Greeks. This offered the possibility of converting Greek
thought to Christianity, but there is a danger for the Christian gospel. According to
the Logos approach, God projected the Logos in order to create the cosmos. It has
not changed the Greek concepts of God and cosmology, and could lead to a wrong
Christology: “For many generations after Justin the Logos could be thought of as a
projection of God always somehow connected with the existence of the world.”62
The question is whether the Logos was uncreated or a part of the creation. For the
second-century apologists there was little clarity on whether the Logos and Spirit
60
J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines (San Francisco: Harper & Row Publishers, 1978), 130.
61
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 37.
62
John Ziziouals, Communion and Otherness, 180.
28
are divine or mere parts of creation.63 Arius pushes this question to the extreme
ending up in heresy.
In about 318, Arius, a priest of Alexandria, began to teach a doctrine that God is
ingenerate and eternal. Since the Son is generated he is not eternal, but created by
the will of the Father. The fundamental premise of Arius’ system is the affirmation
of the absolute uniqueness and transcendence of God, the unoriginate source of all
reality. Arius said, “We acknowledge one God, who is alone ingenerate, alone
eternal, alone without beginning, alone true, alone possessing immortality, alone
wise, alone good, alone sovereign, alone judge of all, etc.”64 The being and essence
of the Godhead cannot be shared or communicated. The Arians asserted that the
Logos should be related to creation rather than to God’s being. According to Kelly,
the view of Arius and his colleagues on the Son can be summarized in four aspects.
compared with the rest of creation; he comes from the Father’s will. “To suggest
Secondly, the Son as a creature must have had a beginning. Prior to His
Thirdly, the Son can have no communion with, and indeed no direct knowledge
of, His Father. Although He is God’s Word and Wisdom, He is distinct from that
Word and that Wisdom which belong to God’s very essence; He is a creature pure
and simple, and only bears these titles because He participates in the essential Word
and Wisdom. In Himself He is, like all other creatures, “alien from and utterly
63
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 46.
64
J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines (New York: Harper & Row, Publisher, 1978), 227.
65
Ibid., 228.
29
dissimilar to the Father’s essence and individual being”.66 Being finite, therefore,
Fourthly, to the question whether the Son can be called God or is indeed Son of
God, the answer is that these are in fact courtesy titles. Arius wrote: ‘He is not God
Arius speaks of three persons of the holy triad in the sense of Origenistic
language. The Arians seek an array of Scriptural texts in support of their theses,
such as Proverbs 8. 22 (‘The Lord created me’), Acts 2. 36 (‘God has made Him
Lord and Christ’), Romans 8.29 (‘The first-born among many’), Corinthians I, 15
(‘The first-born of all creation), etc. Arius regards that there are a host of passages
Eunomius was by birth a Cappadocian, and slightly older than Gregory. He was
one of the most interesting heretics of the fourth century. He and his teacher Aetius
developed the Arian heresy to its extreme. He completed and formulated his
teacher’s heretical tenets. They asserted the absolute unlikeness of the being of the
Father and that of the Son. Starting with the conception of God as absolute being,
inconceivable, and the generation of the Son of God must have had a beginning.
The Arian conclusion is that the Son did not exist before the generation. They are
against the equality and similarity of essence from the mere fact that the Father’s
essence is unbegotten, and that of the Son is begotten. The Son is the first creation
66
Athanasius, C. Ar. I, 6. See J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines, 228.
67
J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines, 229.
68
Ibid., 227-230.
69
Ibid., 230.
30
of the Divine Energy, and is the instrument by whom God created the world. In this
sense, the Son is the expressed image and likeness of the Energy of the Father as the
origin of creative power.70 They viewed the Holy Spirit as sharing the Divine nature
in an even remoter degree, as being only the production of the only-begotten Son.
Father, Son and Spirit in the uniqueness of each hypostasis, described in terms of its
in theology to make a sharp distinction between substance and person. While the
concept of nature expresses the equality of the hypostases, persons express the
Arius’ conception of God is in the end Greek. The Christology has been
understood through the Logos approach. It can be summed up in the question of the
relationship between God and the world. For the ancient Greek, there is an
ontological affinity between the world and God: from the early Pre-Socratic
tendency to unite being and thinking as to form a unity. “This affinity was expressed
either through the mind (nous), which is common between God and Man, or
70
“Image’ and ‘Energy’ borrowed from Holy Scripture (Heb. I. 3). But borrowed with a
difference— not ‘the Image of His Substance,’ which they would not admit, but of His ‘Energy,’
which is a very different conception. Cf. Philip Schaff ed., Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers
(Massachusetts: Hendrickson Publishers, 1995), second series, Vol. 7, 281.
71
Cf. Philip Schaff ed., Nicene and Post-Nicene Fathers, second series, Vol. 7, 282.
31
through the Reason (Logos), which came to be understood especially by Stoicism,
as the link, at once cosmic and divine, that unites God and the world.”72 Arianism
highlighted the philosophical issue of the ontological relation between God and the
world.73
I will analyze the reasons from two aspects: one involves the idea of truth; the
For Greek thought, truth is the unity existing between the intelligible world, the
thinking mind and being. The way to seek truth transcends history. For Christianity,
Christology is the sole starting point to understand truth because Christ claims
himself to be the truth (John 14:6). For Jews, truth may be considered as God’s
promises and the manifestations of God’s presence and His activity in history
towards an ultimate end. When Christ as the truth encounters with Greek thought
and the Jewish mentality, Zizioulas states that the Greek Fathers face a problem:
Can truth be considered simultaneously from the point of view of the ‘nature’ of being (Greek
preoccupation), from the view of the goal or end of history (preoccupation of the Jews), and
from the viewpoint of Christ, who is both a historical person and the permanent ground (the
Logos of being—the Christian claim)—and all while preserving God’s “otherness” in
relation to creation?74
During the patristic period, the existence of God was a ‘given’ for nearly all
Christians or pagans alike. The question that preoccupied the Fathers was not
whether God existed or not, but the question which tormented entire generations:
how He existed. To answer the question about the being of God was not easy. The
greatest difficulty stemmed from ancient Greek ontology: the being of God75 and
72
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 180.
73
See John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 181.
74
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 72.
75
In the thought of ancient Greeks, their God was a rational, connective force, that holds the world
32
the being of world formed an unbreakable unity.76
The Logos approach is one of the most dramatic attempts to reconcile the Greek
idea of truth with the Christian truth. Because of Christ’s claim to be the truth (John
14:6), Christology is the sole starting point for a Christian understanding of truth.
interpret. How should one understand Christ to be the truth? ‘What is truth?’(John
18:38). Christ left Pontius Pilate’s question unanswered, and throughout the ages
the Church has not answered it with one voice. Our problems today concerning
truth appear to stem directly from these different understandings of truth in the
course of the Church’s history.”77 There are some issues in the Logos approach
according to Zizioulas.
The first issue is about epistemology. Justin developed an idea of truth similar if
not identical to that of Platonism: God, who is known ‘only through the mind’,78 as
the ultimate truth, is understood to be ‘he who is always the same in himself and in
relation to all things.’79 This mind was given, according to Justin, simply ‘in order
to contemplate that same being who is the cause of all intelligent beings.’80 Justin’s
view has not rejected the ontologically necessary link between God and the world.
knowing God (for ancient Greeks, the cosmos gives us knowledge of God). Nous is
the medium between God and Man which leads us to the idea of Logos. Christ, as
the Logos of God, establishes a link between God and the world, between the truth
and the mind. Thus, Christ is not truth itself. But Jesus said, “I am the truth” (John
together in harmony (cosmos means order and beauty), or a reason that allowed them to explain the
cosmos. For the Greeks the cosmos shows us something of the nature of God. Cf. Lectures in
Christian Dogmatics, 41.
76
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 16.
77
Ibid., 67.
78
Justin, Dial. 3, 7. C.f. John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 73, footnote, 17.
79
Justin, Dial. 3. 5. C.f. John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 73, footnote, 16.
80
Justin, Dial. 4. 1. C.f. John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 73, footnote, 18.
33
14:6).
The second issue is about ontology. The danger of a monistic ontology was not
apparently problematic for the Church until the time of Clement of Alexandria, who
The application of the Logos concept in this sense led to the crisis of Arianism.
Clement’s way of understanding truth develops along the direction of Justin. The
Greek view of truth influences the way of understanding the idea of God: truth as
the ‘nature’ of being. This view has a decisive significance for later theology in the
West. Origen connected the idea of God so closely with that of creation that he
came to speak of eternal creation. Since God is eternally a creator, the link between
the Logos of God and the logoi of creation comes to be an organic and unbreakable
unity, as in the Greek idea between God and the world. Origen interpreted the
The third issue is about Christianity. Christ is ‘truth itself’ not in his humanity,
but in his relation to truth. It is ‘true’ only in so far as it participates in the truth. The
Logos of God seems to indicate that “the incarnation does not realize the truth in a
fundamental way, but merely reveals a pre-existing truth”.81 The prototype of truth
is found in spiritual souls, this truth as a kind of image has been imprinted in those
who think according to the truth.82 Thus it essentially does away with the need of an
authentic revelation.
The fourth issue is about salvation. By developing the Logos as the link between
the world and God, Justin gave the principle of knowledge a key role in salvation to
the point of arguing that even before Christ and among the pagans true knowledge
as salvation was possible, for example, among the ancient Greek philosophers. This
81
John Ziziouals, Being as Communion, 77.
82
See John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 75-77.
34
in fact provides a fertile ground for Gnosticism.
The fifth issue is about spirituality. A Christian Gnosticism emerges, i.e., the
Justin was developed further in the catechetical school of Alexandria, where Greek
philosophy was influential. Two great names stand out in this respect: Clement of
Alexandria (d. 215) and Origen (d. 253). Their thought could be described as
the early church in the Patristic age. On the one hand, it tends to undermine the
value of the material world and to attribute creation not to God but to a demiurge,
which is to be held responsible also for the evil that humanity experiences and this
escape from matter in time, which would involve asceticism or its opposite. On the
other hand, it concerns the understanding that salvation and spiritual life consist of
knowledge.
Both Clement and Origen operated with the idea of the Logos and used
revelation is not the revelation of Jesus Christ. As Zizioulas comments, “This idea
of revelation seems to lie at the very heart of the problem, since revelation always
and knowledge that the Logos of God grants to the human soul. The essence of
spirituality is the contemplation of the divine Logos or of God in and through the
83
John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 162.
84
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 77.
35
Logos.85 He undermined the historical Christ. His influence accounts for many
The term ‘person’ entered theological terminology since Tertullian in the West
and introduced in the East probably through Hippolytus. The history of the terms
development with regard to the use of these terms in the Trinitarian theology of the
Greek Fathers is very obscure. Here I will analyze its meaning briefly according to
the part of the head that is ‘below the cranium’, or from the usage in the theater as
actor’s mask. Zizioulas considers that it includes two aspects from the actor’s mask.
One is that man strives to fight against the harmonious unity which oppresses him
as rational and moral necessity, the necessity of the cosmological order we call fate.
So he has to suffer the consequences and he can never escape this fate ultimately.
The other is that the same man who becomes a person in the mask acquires the
bitter taste of a brief freedom as a unique and unrepeatable entity. The ‘person’ is
tragically related to the mask; the “person” is not his true “hypostasis” which means
persona is probably to be traced back to the Etruscan word phersu, which would
connect it with the ritual or theatrical mask. At the same time, declares Zizioulas,
85
Ibid., 162.
86
See John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 163.
36
the anthropological connotation did not differ essentially from the use of the Greek
in the beginning, but the Roman persona leaned more towards the idea of
concrete individual. Besides the theatrical mask, persona as a category has a more
sociological content: “persona is the role which one plays in one’s social or legal
has nothing to do with the ontology of the person”. 87 The Roman persona
subordinates his freedom to the organized whole, and the individual is a means, a
possibility, of tasting freedom or affirming one’s identity. This identity marks one
man different from another which is guaranteed by the social whole. Zizioulas
regards that the politicization and sociology in the Western mentality cannot be
to be grounded. The term “hypostasis” was linked with the term “ousia” or
substance (the Latin term subsantia would literally translate into Greek as
hypostasis), and even identified with it in Greek philosophy. It was accepted in the
first Christian centuries. Zizioulas cites Athanasius’ Letter to the Bishops of Egypt
and Libya about the identification of the two terms: “hypostasis is ousia and has no
other meaning apart from being itself…for hypostasis and ousia are existence.”89
The other argument is the Synodical letter of Alexandria 362 AD which refers to
Nicaea as having anathematized those who profess that the son is “of another
hypostasis or ousia.”90 The problem with hypostasis by itself is that it does not
express the relational dimension of God or the communion between the Three. (see
1.4.2 below)
87
Ibid., 34.
88
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 27-49.
89
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 36. See footnote 23.
90
Ibid. 36.
37
In conclusion, we can see that ‘person’ and ‘hypostasis’ are not related in ancient
substance with hypostasis, diffused so widely in the Greek thought of the first
Christian centuries, that created all the difficulties and disputes concerning the
ontological revolution.
ontological otherness within one substance has been proposed by the Cappadocian
Fathers through an ontological revolution. In Zizioulas’ view all of these have been
realized by the transformation of the idea of truth from the Logos approach to the
Eucharistic approach.
1.4.1 A new idea of truth: the identification of truth with life in worship
The Eucharist, also called Holy Communion, the Sacrament of the Altar, the
Blessed Sacrament, the Lord’s Supper, or other names, is one of the most important
experience of the triune God is communion with the living God, the source of
epistemology. Such a priority for Zizioulas is consistent with the Eastern patristic
In his work Being as Communion the Eucharistic approach was introduced as the
Greek patristic synthesis concerning truth. The Logos theologians of the first three
91
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion 36.
38
i.e., the Eucharistic approach, to the idea of truth has been provided by the Greek
Fathers to answer the question of truth. The representatives are Ignatius of Antioch
(c.35-50AD) and St Irenaeus (c.130-202AD). Zizioulas tells us that this was not an
intellectual movement. Through studying the works of Irenaeus and that of Ignatius,
he found that the Eucharist is the center in their theology and its role is decisive for
the identification of being or existence with life. The identification of being with
life has been developed in the Greek patristic thought in the second century.
The word ‘life’ in western minds means the idea of something ‘practical’ as
Zizioulas searches the cause of why life had been put in opposition to being. For
Aristotle, life is a quality added to being, and not being itself since the individual
life cannot be eternal. The truth of being is not found in life, but precedes it. “With
being we use the verb to be while with life we use the verb to have: life is possessed
precisely because life is something possessed, and cannot precede being, that truth
as the meaning of being relates ultimately to being as such, not to life.”92 Thus the
Greek mind was unable to say at the same time ‘being and life’. But the Christian
had to say both at once. This identification of being with life affected the idea of
of Athanasius and the Cappadocian Fathers—they provide the foundation for the
Zizioulas gives both historical and theological reasons for this identification.
There are three reasons to explain why the theology of the Eucharist leads to an
Firstly, the Bible sets the roots of the relationship between the Eucharist and
92
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 79.
39
life. Ignatius of Antioch speaks of truth in connection with life. This view is the
or ‘true life.’ (John 3: 15, 16; 14: 6; 17:3). Ignatius’ way of combining knowledge
with life points towards an ontological rather than an ethical approach to truth
which leads to an understanding of truth as practice. For Ignatius, life signifies not
only practice but being forever: i.e., that which does not die. Truth is identical with
Secondly, the Eucharist as the true Christ in the historical and material sense
of ‘truth’ has been applied to the fight against Docetism and Gnosticism: Ignatius
in combating Docetism and Irenaeus in combating Gnosticism. For both men the
ontological.
Finally, the Eucharist was understood as community: “The life of the Eucharist is
the life of God Himself, but this is not life in the sense of an Aristotlelian movement
which flows out mechanically from the interior of existence.”94 There is an analogy
between the existence within the Trinity and the existence within the members of
communion are identical”, 95 i.e., Man knows God and himself in this
93
Ibid., 79-80.
94
Ibid., 81.
95
See Irenaeus, Adv. Haer. IV, 20:5. See also John D. Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 81;
40
because He is life and all beings find their meaning in their incorruptible existence
which are imparted and actualized in the event of communion rather than lying in
Justin’s Logos approach. But Irenaeus seems to stop here, because his primary
concern is that created being ultimately depends upon the Trinity. The question of
the being of God or Trinitarian theology has not been answered until the fourth
century. Zizioulas emphasizes: “But it must be strongly underlined that without this
and Irenaeus, the Trinitarian theology of the fourth century would remain a
problem.”96 It means that persons can experience this living God of communion in
the Eucharist and this leads directly to the Trinitarian theological developments of
the fourth century: the identification of being and life with communion.
Facing the challenge of the heresy, the Church was compelled to search for
greater clarity for the identity of the Son and Spirit: whether Logos and Spirit are
divine or part of creation. The Arian crisis forced the Fathers to revise Origen’s
revision of the doctrine of the Logos. Athanasius proposes that the doctrine of the
Logos can be maintained only if the Logos becomes identical with the Son as part
and ‘will’. The Son’s being belongs to the substance of God, while the being of the
world belongs to the will of God. It “makes it plain that the being of the Son in his
relation to God was not of the same kind as the being of the world”. 98 This
96
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 82.
97
Cf. John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 83.
98
Ibid., 85.
41
distinction has been used to argue against the Arians, through breaking out of an
ontological affinity between God and the world in Greek philosophy. Zizioulas
comments:
He thus avoided the trap into which Justin and Origen has fallen, not by abandoning ontological
thought but, on the contrary, by raising it up to the ultimate character which its nature requires.
To be is not the same as to will or, hence, as to act. This assertion, apparently Greek and not
Hebrew, presented itself as the means for protecting the biblical roots of the Gospel from the
dangers of Greek ontology. God’s being, in an ultimate sense, remained free in relation to the
world, in such a way that the Greek mind could identify it as ‘being’ without having to link it
with the world out of an ontological necessity.99
the idea of substance. “To say that the Son belongs to God’s substance implies that
obvious that Athanasius makes the use of ‘substance’ un-Greek and leads to a new
the level of will and action but to that of substance. When communion becomes an
based on a Greek rational starting point, but comes from the Eucharistic experience:
Communion, freedom and otherness of God and the world. In order to understand
the relationship between communion and substance, we should review briefly two
philosophy there are four categories. The first is substance or substrate, which
corresponds to matter. Second, there is the quality (poion) that differentiates matter.
99
Ibid., 84.
100
Ibid., 84.
101
Ibid., 85.
42
Thirdly, there is ‘being in a certain state’ or disposition. This is the category of
one thing possessed in relation to something else. In Stoic category, the relation is
individual things that are associated with it in the world, but on which its
For Aristotle, in Book I of the Categories, Aristotle lists ten categories of being.
The first category is divided into primary and secondary substances. Primary
or species and genera respectively. The two meanings of the word substance would
also prove decisive in both Latin and Greek medieval theology. The remaining nine
categories of being are accidents, that is, characteristics that may reside in a
substance but are not essential to it. These include quantity, quality, relation,
place, time, posture, having, acting, and being acted on. With respect to the
category of relation, a term is said to be relative to another if one implies the other,
In Stoic and Aristotelian philosophies, relation does not indicate what something
means that the ultimate character of God’s being as substance can be conceived
102
J. M. Rist, Stoic Philosophy (Cambridge: University Press, 1969), 169.
103
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 84.
104
Ibid., 86.
43
rather than Stoic philosophy, relation would be identified with substance: relation
shows what something is. In the Greek Trinitarian tradition, relation will show only
But this relational divine substance had not been further conceptualized. In the
concerns the being of God. The use of the idea of substance by Athanasius means
that the Son has always belonged to God’s being. “Athanasius demonstrated that
nature, but he does not show to what extent ‘interior’ communion within one
that a thing’s concrete individuality (hypostasis) means simply that it is (i.e. its
ousia). A category must express the distinctiveness while emphasizing both the
relations between the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit and their transcendence to the
world within the immanent Trinity. Ousia was clearly not the answer to express the
threeness of God, since three ousiai would be equivalent to three gods. On the
other hand, the problem with hypostasis by itself is that it does not express the
to be found which would give theology the ability to avoid Sabellianism, that is,
which would give an ontological content to each person of the Holy Trinity, without
105
Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1991), 58-59.
106
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 87.
44
endangering its biblical principles: monotheism and the absolute ontological
independence of God in relation to the world. From this endeavour came the
Greek philosophy”.108
distinction between substance and person in God: “By being a person the Father
conclude that the Son is not God or homoousios with the Father. When God is
but to personhood.”109
In the fourth century the Cappadocian Fathers sort out problems of the
Trinitarian theology concerning the persons and unity of God, through the
concept’s revolution.
substance and it does not express the relational dimension of God or the
between these two meanings so that essence and hypostasis could no longer be
regarded as synonyms, but they identify ‘substance’ with ‘nature’.110 The Latin
term ‘substantia’ was expressed in Greek not by ‘hypostasis’, but by ‘ousia’. The
‘hypostasis’ meant the same as ‘person’. From then on, the ‘person’ is no longer an
adjunct to a being and becomes the being itself and is simultaneously, as a most
107
Ibid., 37.
108
Ibid., 36.
109
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 160.
110
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 50.
45
significant point, the constitutive element (the “principle” or “cause”) of beings.111
be combined with the ontological character of hypostasis and this is precisely the
genius of Basil,” 112 argues Zizioulas. This identification was to Basil the most
adequate way to express both the distinctiveness of the Father, Son, and Holy Spirit,
and their inseparable unity or koinonia and hypostasis in the new sense are
related to one another. This was a revolutionary move: “the term ‘hypostasis’
which had referred to what was most fundamental and unchanging, was now a
category; person no longer denoted just a relationship that an entity could take on
or the role that an actor would play”113. But it has received almost no mentioning in
The Cappadocian Fathers defended the ontological integrity of each person and
and person allows the concept of person to emerge more clearly as a distinct
category in ontology.115 However, the Cappadocian Fathers would face the other
problem: how to avoid tritheism or how to deal with the unity or oneness of God.
According to Zizioulas, the Cappadocian Fathers solve the problem through two
steps. The first step is to suggest the ousia (substance) or physis (nature) is a general
111
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 39.
112
Aristotle Papanikolaou, Being with God: Trinity, Apophaticism, and Divine-Human Communion
(Notre Dame, Ind.: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006), 83.
113
John D. Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 51.
114
Ibid., 50.
115
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 160.
46
category, while hypostases (plural) refer to concrete individuals. In this way it is
logically possible to speak of one substance and three hypostases (or persons)
through the analogy of the three men. But the other theological difficulty arises,
The second step is to distinguish the being of person and the being of God. In
human existence, nature precedes the person and each human person can be
each of the persons of God’s existence transcends space and time, so God has not
had a beginning, and the three persons do not exist prior to their divine nature and
vice versa, but coincide with it. At the same time, the three persons of the Trinity
are united in an unbreakable communion (Koinonia) and each person exists by the
‘one’. Then the ‘one’ does not precede the ‘many’ but the ‘one’ and the ‘many’
coexist. Logically, the Cappadocian Fathers solve the tension between ‘tritheism’
Substance indicates divine oneness, but the ground of unity remains the
Zizioulas provides the historical testimony about the influence of this ontological
revolution on the Council of Constantinople of 381 CE. The Creed of Nicaea at the
116
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 51.
117
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 118.
47
point where it referred to the Son as being ‘from the substance of the Father’ (ek tes
ousias tou patros) had been changed into ‘from the Father’ (ek tou patros). The
theses:
Zizioulas asserts that it is a victory for Basil’s way of speaking of God. First,
there is no mention of the word homoousios (Basil avoids this term on his
with strictly scriptural language. “It describes him as Lord (kyrion), a reference to 2
Cor. 3.17, as Life-giving (Zoopoion), which is taken from Jn 6.63, and as ‘having
spoken through the prophets’ (2 Pet. 1.21).”118 Zizioulas concludes that it is based
metaphysical thought.
Secondly, the only non-scriptural language used to describe the divinity of the
Spirit is ‘worshipped and glorified together with the Father and the Son’. Zizioulas
argues that it is another Basilian victory, “for it was he who argued for the divinity
Zizioulas argues that because Basilian theology had affected the pneumatology
of Constantinople much, then the Creed about the procession of the Spirit from
the Father should be explained by Basilian terms. First, ‘the Holy Spirit
proceeds from the Father’ means that the ultimate ontological ground of the Holy
118
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 191.
119
Ibid., 191.
48
Spirit is a person, and not substance. Zizioulas asserts that it safeguards the faith
that the person ‘causes’ God to be.120 Second, the Spirit, by proceeding from the
Father, and not from divine substance, is a person too. Zizioulas points out that a
question raised is whether the Spirit proceeds also from the Son. In other word, the
question concerns the Filioque. We will discuss this issue in Chapter Five.
Constantinople, Zizioulas claims that the reference of the Creed to the procession of
the Spirit from the Father should be placed in the light of this theology. The
importance of this idea has been expressed through two aspects: on the one hand,
the utmost implication of the phrase ‘from the Father’ should be interpreted through
the ‘person’ in the true sense. “In asserting that the Spirit proceeds from the Father
we must understand, in strictly Basilian terms that the ultimate ontological ground
of the Holy Spirit is a person, and not substance.”121 The Spirit is not simply a
power issuing from divine substance; He is a product of love and freedom and not
of substantial necessity.
The Creed of Chalcedon, as the Doctrine of the Hypostatic Union was adopted at
the Council of Chalcedon in 451 in Asia Minor.122 The definition is that Christ is
“acknowledged in two natures”, which “come together into one person and
hypostasis”.
120
Ibid., 192.
121
Ibid., 192.
122
That Council of Chalcedon is that fourth of the first seven Ecumenical Councils accepted by the
following Christian denominations: Eastern Orthodox, Catholic, Catholic and many Protestant
Christian churches. It is the first Council not recognised by any of the oriental Orthodox churches
who may be classfied as non-Chalcedonian.
49
meaning of Trinitarian terms and to distinguish among them. The sixth chapter of The Doctrine
of the Fathers consisted of a group of quotations intended to show “that nature and hypostasis
are not the same, but that ousia and nature are the same, likewise that hypostasis and person are
the same.” All these terms had been employed in the discussions of the doctrine of the person
of Christ…in the Trinity, nature or ousia referred to that which was one, hypostasis or person
to that which was more than one; in the person of Christ nature or ousia referred to that which
was one. A further complication was the history of previous usage even within the orthodox
tradition, where ousia and hypostasis had sometimes been equated. Both the Nestorian and the
Jacobite traditions had their own distinctive usages: the former distinguished between
hypostasis and person, assigning to Christ one person but two hypostases; the latter tied nature
to hypostasis, ascribing to Christ not only a composite hypostasis, as did the Chalcedonians,
but a composite nature. ‘What causes the error of the heretics,’ according to John of
Damascus, ‘is their saying that nature and hypostasis are the same’.123
The Chalcedonian formulation owes a lot to this neat identification from the
Cappadocian Fathers onward between hypostasis and persona, so much so that the
Chalcedonian Fathers can tackle the complicated problem of Christ’s identity and
123
Jaroslav Pelikan, The Christian Tradition: A History of the Development of Doctrine, II (Chicago
and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1974), 81-82.
50
Chapter Two
ontological being as fundamental as ousia, and personhood, i.e. the state of the
ontological categories. At the same time, it means the identification of God with the
Father, i.e., the Father as the cause of the existence of Trinity. Some theologians
accept the conceptual revolution, but they oppose the Father as cause. I will explore
the importance of ‘the Father as cause’ in the later part of this chapter.
Moreover, some Orthodox scholars such as Lucian Turcescu, Andrew Louth and
John Behr have claimed that Zizioulas’ view of personhood is in fact different from
the views of the Cappadocian Fathers. This chapter will explain the meaning of the
concept of personhood, and discuss the issue of the Father as personal cause in the
being of God. Some criticisms of and defenses for Zizioulas will be advanced,
For the Cappadocian Fathers, the Trinitarian formula is: one ousia, three
hypostases that is identified as the Latin personae. The Father is the ground of unity
or oneness. In Zizioulas’ Trinitarian theology, the Trinitarian formula is: God the
Father, three persons. Though Zizioulas does not entirely oppose the concept of
51
essence, Zizioulas’ emphasis is on the person of the Father. This ontology of
For Zizioulas, there are three ways to describe the being of God in terms of
Cappadocian theology: (a) that God exists, (b) what God is, and (c) how God is who
he is.
For (a) to say that God exists, is merely to indicate his existence rather than
non-existence.124 The question of God’s existence was not one that patristic writers
For (b) the question is ‘what God is’. The ‘what’ question relates to the essence of
a thing. Saint Gregory Nazianzus makes this distinction between ‘what’ and ‘that’
questions in his Second Theological Oration. Because the essence of God is simply
beyond our conception, Gregory claims that we cannot give an answer to this ‘what’
question. It is the first principle introduced by the Fathers that we cannot know the
‘what’, i.e., the essence of God. Zizioulas contrasts it with a Greek principle: “a
basic principle of Greek thought is that we can come to know the essence of beings
and that the mind can achieve this, by conceiving the idea and then being led to the
essence itself.”125 According to Plato, our minds reach beyond the material world to
that truth. The more the mind is purified of all materiality, the more it is able to
reach the reality, which is what the form is. For Aristotle, the essence of things is in
the material hypostasis. There are certain natural laws operating in them. The
Eastern Fathers are different from the Greek philosophers: they believe that the
124
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 54.
125
Ibid., 58.
52
For (c) the question ‘how God is’ represents a third way to refer to the being of
God. It concerns the question of ‘how’ something is, i.e., in what way God is who
of the view of the Cappadocian Fathers: “God is God as Father, Son and Holy
Spirit—these persons indicate how God is”.126 Here Zizioulas sees the issue of
fundamental as the ‘what’ question: they both refer to what we call ‘being’.” In
Communion and Otherness, Zizioulas directly describes that the Father as cause is
to answer how God is: “Giving existence or being to the Son by the Father is a
matter not of nature, of the what God is, but of how God is.”127 In this book he
discusses the issue of causality and he distinguishes between ousia and person or
hypostasis in the divine being. The person of the Father has been discussed as an
ontological principle in the doctrine of God. Thus, we can see that Zizioulas
describes this ‘how’ question from different angles and both angles form a whole to
2.1.2 The being of God as person giving rise to otherness and communion
The consequence of the Father as cause is that the personal Father generates
communion are two aspects of the concept of the person. Zizioulas proposes the
person rests in the facts that he represents two things simultaneously which are at
126
Ibid., 57.
127
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 129.
53
cannot be imagined in himself but only with his relationships.”128 In short, the
Father as cause is the origin of the Trinitarian personhood. Here, two points are to
be noted.
when the concept of ‘person’ is identified with ‘hypostasis’, the concept of ‘person’
in the case of God’s three persons. In the Cappadocian view, these three persons are
indeed three complete entities. Three complete persons have a common substance
otherness.130 “This implies that the idea of causation is used in order to describe the
how of divine being and avoid making the emergence of the Trinity a matter of
transmission of ousia. What the Father ‘causes’ is a transmission not of ousia but of
being.”131
an idea of relational entity through all of this: each is found entirety within the other;
each person has his own ontological integrity, and yet they are one. In other words,
each person is distinct from another but each exists within the other persons. The
(a) They are constituted in relationship. Even the Father as a relational entity is
128
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 106.
129
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 103-104.
130
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 130.
131
Ibid., 129-130.
54
inconceivable without the Son and the Spirit.
relational ontology may dissolve the sexism in religion and society. “His freedom in
bringing them forth into being does not impose itself upon them, since they are not
already there, and their own freedom does not require that their consent be asked,
since they are not established as entities before their relationship with the
Father.”132 Zizioulas sets up this idea through contrasting the Fatherhood of God
with human Fatherhood. He points out that the context of human Fatherhood is
entity of the human Father is already established prior to that of his son.”133 So the
by individualism in time.
Zizioulas raises two related issues to explain relational entity: “How is it possible
for one person to be the bearer of the entire being of God? How is it possible for a
person to exist within another person, without losing their identity?” 134 He
discusses these questions from the contrast between creation and the uncreated:
created nature is different from uncreated nature concerning time and space:
person cannot be the bearer of the entire human essence because of his mortality.
For God, there is no beginning and no mortality, no limitation of space, and each
person of God is the entire being, not a portion of the being of God.
(b) “In God, the existence of the one person within the others actually creates a
132
Ibid., 122.
133
Ibid., 122.
134
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 63.
55
particularity, and ‘individuality’ and an otherness.”135
‘perichoresis’, which refers to the unity and distinction of each person. Zizioulas
interprets this concept in terms of Saint Basil’s letter: “whatever the Father is, is
also found in the Son and whatever the Son is, is also found in the Father. The Son is
found in his entirety within the Father and he has the Father in his entirety within
him. Thus, the hypostasis of the Son is the image and the likeness by which the
Father can be known and the hypostasis of the Father is known in the image of the
Son.”136 The argument comes from the Fourth Gospel; the three persons inhere in
one another. “Whomsoever has seen me, has seen the Father, for I am in the Father
Some Orthodox scholars such as Lucian Turcescu, Andrew Louth and John Behr,
personhood, the Holy Trinity and the Church is not really traditional, and is
different from the view of the Early Church Fathers. More specifically, they have
claimed that it differs from the views of the Cappadocian Fathers, namely, St.
Gregory of Nyssa, St. Basil the Great and St. Gregory of Nazianzus.
Turcescu questions the legitimacy of Zizioulas’ use of material taken from the
135
Ibid., 64.
136
Basil, Letter 38, see John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 62-63.
56
century insights to foist on the Cappadocian Fathers. This methodology leads him
the individual. 138 “To explain the distinction between God’s substance and the
divine persons, the Cappadocian Fathers used the analogy of the common and the
particular, as detailed in Aristotle and the Stoics”. 139 It means that Turcescu
individual. “It now becomes evident that for Gregory hypostasis means ‘individual’
and is opposed to species. In the human and divine cases, hypostasis can also be
Gregory, one can think of Peter, James, and John as many, yet the human in them is
one.”141
Secondly, there are limitations and deficiencies of the analogy between human
and divine being in a logical sense. Zizioulas points to Gregory of Nyssa’s claim
137
Lucian Turcescu, “Person versus Individual and Other Modern Misreading of Nyssa”, Modern
theology 18. 4/ 2002: 527-539.
138
Lucian Turcescu, Gregory of Nyssa and the Concept of Divine Persons, (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2005), the whole chapter two.
139
Ibid., 48.
140
Ibid., 53.
141
Ibid., 67.
142
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 171.
57
that it is a misuse of language and not accurately, in using the example of Peter, Paul,
illustrate the three persons of the Holy Trinity. The deficiencies are as follows:
persons; the derivation of human persons from different personal causes. These
factors apply purely to human personhood. The Cappadocian Fathers must exclude
these factors when applying this analogy. No natural or moral quality would be used
by any of the Fathers to distinguish a divine person, simply because such qualities
are common to all three divine persons. All natural and moral qualities, such as
energy, goodness, will, and so on, are qualities commonly possessed by the divine
persons and they have nothing to do with the concept of divine personhood.
Prestige supports this view: “the differences that distinguish different human
beings are manifold, but the differences that distinguish the divine persons consist
being defined solely and exclusively in terms of a relational ‘mode of being’, admits
143
G. L. Prestige, God in Patristic Thought (London: SPCK, 1952), 244.
144
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 176.
58
theologians to draw our concept of human personhood from the study of the human
of natural and moral qualities, and so on.146 If we derive personhood from Trinity,
mentioned by Turcescu is arguably the one whose thought is most significant for
Nazianzus”149
145
Ibid., 176.
146
Ibid., 176.
147
Ibid., 176-177.
148
Aristotle Papanikolaou, “Is John Zizioulas as Existentialist in Disguise? Response to Lucian
Tucescu,” in Modern Theology 20.4, October 2004, 601-607.
149
Aristotle Papanikolaou, “Is John Ziziouals as Existentialist in Disguise? Response to Lucian
Turcescu,” in Modern Theology, Vol. 20 no. 4 (October 2004), 602.
59
Cappadocian Fathers
Cappadocian Fathers, and his understanding of the rich connotation of the concept
quest for otherness and communion. For Zizioulas, the personal Father generates
personal otherness and communion in divine being. Otherness and communion are
two aspects in the concept of person. “The significance of the person rests in the
facts that he represents two things simultaneously which are at first sight in
Fathers.
For Gregory of Nazianzus, the concept of ‘person’ not only includes the meaning
of ‘otherness’ and ‘communion’, but also the common substance, essence or ousia
of God which has been hypostasized in each person of the Trinity. Kelly highlights
The essence of their doctrine is that the one Godhead exists simultaneously in
three modes of being, or hypostases. So Basil remarks, “Everything that the Father
is seen in the Son, and everything that the Son is belongs to the Father. The Son in
His entirety abides in the Father, and in return possesses the Father in entirety in
Himself. Thus the hypostasis of the Son is, so to speak, the form and presentation by
which the Father is known, and the Father’s hypostasis is recognized in the form of
the Son.” Here we have the doctrine of the co-inherence, or as it was later called
150
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 106.
60
‘undivided…in divided Persons’,151 and there is an ‘identity of nature’ in the three
hypostases.152
To explain how the one substance can be simultaneously present in three Persons
they appeal to the analogy of a universal and its particulars. Basil writes:
‘Ousia and hupostasis’ are differentiated exactly as universal and particular are, e.g. animal
and particular man. From this point of view each of the divine hypostases is the ousia or
essence of Godhead determined by its appropriate particularizing characteristic, or identifying
peculiarity…Gregory of Nazianzus has to confess…the distinction of the Persons is grounded
in Their origin and mutual relation. They are, we should observe, so many ways in which the
one indivisible divine substance distributes and presents itself, and hence They come to be
153
termed ‘modes of coming to be.
Prestige also summarizes the Cappadocian thought: “Yet the whole unvaried
common substance, being incomposite, is identical with the whole unvaried being
of each person; there is no question of accidents attaching to it; the entire substance
of the Son is the same as the entire substance of the Father: the individuality is only
the manner in which the identical substance is objectively presented in each several
However, for Zizioulas, he only takes on the perspective of the otherness of three
defined, a hypostasis was an ousia together with its properties; but Christ, being a
properties. Another simple definition was to say that hypostasis was the particular,
nature the general.”155 A hypostasis bearing two natures is the creed of Chalcedon.
Therefore, when we describe the meaning of hypostasis, we cannot put aside the
151
Gregory Nazianzen, or. 31. 14.
152
Didymus, De. Trin. I, 16 (PG 39, 336). See J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines, 264.
153
J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines, 264-265.
154
G. L. Prestige, God in Patristic Thought, 244.
155
Jaroslav Pelikan, The Christian Tradition: A History of the Development of Doctrine, II (Chicago
and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1974), 82.
61
element of ousia.
catholic person is inclusive, and such person expressed the totality of a nature. The
source is that “Jesus is the communion of divine and human, ‘hypostatically’ uniting
(Chalcedon).”156
denotes (a) the what he is of God’s being, and this the Cappadocian Fathers call the
ousia or substance or nature of God; and (b) it refers to the how he is, which they
identify with this personhood.”157 Therefore, there are two kinds of ontological
for Zizioulas’ theological ontology. Zizioulas describes these two ways to denote
being: “both denote being, but the former refers to the what and the latter to the
how of being. Giving existence or being to the Son by the Father is a matter not of
nature, of the what God is, but of how God is.”158 According to the theology of
Gregory Nazianzen, ‘substance’ means divine oneness or unity, but person of the
Father is the ground of unity of the three persons: “the three have one nature…the
ground of unity being the Father, out of whom and towards whom the subsequent
156
Cathrine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 296.
157
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 125.
158
Ibid., 129.
62
persons are reckoned.”159
distinction between ousia and hypostasis and the divine ousia exists hypostatically.
It means that ousia and person are used together in the Trinitarian theology of the
Cappadocian Fathers. In fact, the ousia and person are not contradictory in their
Trinitarian theology. Logically speaking, when ouisa denotes the general, and
person denotes the particular in Trinitarian theology, they are not two elements in
opposition. In fact from the perspective of existence, they express unity in Trinity.
There is a balance when the Cappadocian Fathers uses ousia and person
accept it from the angle of nominalism rather than realism, i.e., the essence of God
as an concept conceived by the abstract intellect as existing in each person, the view
no ousia in his formula of Trinity or Trinitarian theology. It is not exactly the same
principle, namely, the ‘personal’ principle. In other words, he only considers the
question of how God is. He gives up the question of what God is. For him, “the
Father as ‘cause’ is God, or the God in an ultimate sense, not because he holds the
ontological otherness and communion in the divine being, while substance means
159
Gregory Nazianzus, Or. 42.15. See Communion and Otherness, 118.
160
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 130.
63
divine oneness. Substance is outside persons. Zizioulas only concentrates on the
one way to denote being in terms of personhood. It directly avoids the emergence of
concerning heresies. They had to protect the equal identity of the Son and the Spirit
with the Father, or their full deity. They used the term homoousios to affirm that the
Son shares one and the same divine nature as the Father. But in the modern
the doctrine of God and preserves the ontological notion of otherness. Zizioulas
uses God the Father to express One God instead of substance or ousia which
denotes divine oneness. Thus substance is outside persons, and it is not necessary
for Zizioulas to apply the concept of substance or ousia in his Trinitarian formula.
Zizioulas only takes one route to denote the oneness of being in terms of
Cappadocians reversed the Greek situation, for the Trinitarian theology of the
secondary to being or nature, thus it can be free in an ultimate sense. The absolute
otherness of God’s existence dictates that the approach to God contrasts acutely
with that of the Greeks. Based on it, Zizioulas opposes Western substantialist
theology which is in parallel with Greek substantialism. His formula for Trinity
64
prefers ‘God the Father, three persons’ to ‘one substance, three persons.’ It
leads to great implications for theological anthropology and ecclesiology for our
modern times.
Monarchia means one arche. It was first employed by theologians to indicate that
there is only one rule in God, amounting to one will, one power, and so on.161
Because the concept was applied not only to God’s economy in the world but to
God in his immanent eternal life, thus the question involves the being of God. Arche
is attached exclusively to the Father in Basil’s theology: “For Father is the one who
has given the beginning of being to the others…Son is the one who has had the
beginning of his being by birth from the other’.162 In Basil’ context, the meaning of
being does not denote ousia but rather hypostasis (person). Gregory Nazianzen
refers to all three persons of the Trinity when he uses the term monarchia in the
early sense of one rule, will and power: “It is, however, a monarchia that is not
limited to one person, for it is possible for unity if at variance with itself to come
when he thinks that Gregory Nazianzus’ does not want the monarchy to be limited
to the Father.164 But Gregory refers to the Father when he expresses ontologically
161
Justin, Dial. 1; Tatian, Or. Ad Gr. 14, etc.; see also John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness,
131.
162
Basil, C. Eun. 2.22; see also John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 131-132.
163
Gregory Naz., Theol. Or. 3.2; see also John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 132.
164
See T. F. Torrance, The Trinitarian Faith (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1996), 239. “While Gregory
65
with the term monas. This is the text that immediately follows the one just quoted:
“For this reason, the One having moved from the beginning (from all eternity) to a
Dyad, stopped (or rested) in Triad. And this is for us the Father and the Son and the
Holy Spirit. The one as the Begetter and the Emitter, without passion of course and
without reference to time, and not in a corporeal manner, of whom the others are
monas referred to the Father rather than the ousia ontologically in this passage of
Gregory, “If the monas referred to something other than the Father, that is to ousia
or something common to the three persons, we would have to exegete the text in the
following way: ‘The one ousia (monas) moved to a Dyad and finally stopped at the
Triad’. This would mean that from the one ousia came first the two persons together
to which a third one was added finally to make the Trinity.”166 If the monas refers to
the Father, it explains itself: “the one as the Begetter and Emitter, of whom the
others are the one begotten and the other the emission.”167 It is consistent with
Zizioulas concludes that there is a distinction between the moral sense and the
ontological sense when Gregory uses monarchia: “In the moral sense of unity of
mind, will, and so on, he refers it to the three persons taken together (how could it
Nazianzen offered much the same teaching as his fellow Cappadocians, he exercised more flexibility
in the use of theological terms…while Gregory nevertheless spoke of the Father as the arche [origin]
and the aitia [cause] in order to secure the unity of the Godhead.”
165
Gregory Naz., Theol. Or. 3.2; see also John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 133.
166
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 133.
167
Ibid., 133.
168
Ibid., 133-134.
66
2.3.2 Stressing person to the extent of excluding ousia
Zizioulas tends to oppose the concepts of person and ousia, and he excludes the
notion of ousia from his ontology of personhood, because he insists that we cannot
know the ousia of God and the Christian truth is identified with life.169 At the same
something that Greek philosophy had never done before, when he introduces
substantialist approach as the revelation of God. In other words, only the particular
is real, and no universal principle as the essence of God can be grasped: goodness,
Christian doctrines, there is only one kind of knowledge, i.e., personal knowledge.
His theology cannot escape from the influences of traditional Eastern traditional
Secondly, because of the lack of the perspective of ousia, it is easy for some
Gregory of Nazianzus, ousia exists in each person which guarantees equality for
each Triune person. When Gregory of Nazianzus discusses the person of the Son,
he refers to ousia simultaneously: “He is called the Son of God, because he and the
Father have the same nature, not only for this reason, he is eternally begotten of the
169
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 56.
170
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 130. See also Aristotle Papanikolaou, Being with
God: Trinity, Apophaticism, and Divine-Human Communion, 82-85.
171
We can find the concept of ousia in Zizioulas’s works, but he does not apply this term from an
ontological perspective.
67
Father.”172 Zizioulas consents to this view, but in his ontology of personhood, he
does not apply the notion of ousia to his theological system. Therefore, we may
suspect that it is difficult for Zizioulas’ model of Trinity to serve as a model for
social order as the social Trinity would do.173 In chapter seven, I will discuss this
issue.
Zizioulas has responded to criticism that causality in Trinity entails the danger of
theology.’174 Zizioulas traces the notion of cause back to the Fathers. The idea of
causality comes from Greek philosophy, and it influenced the Greek Fathers. It is
about the question of how and why something is caused, that is, has come into being.
When the Cappadocian Fathers employed this notion in theology, there are some
Firstly, the concept of cause was removed from its necessary involvement with
time. The argument is from Oration of Gregory Nazianzen: “The name of the
unoriginate is Father; of that who has had a beginning (arche), Son; and of that
who is together with the beginning, Holy Spirit. And the union of them is the Father,
172
Gregory of Nazianzus, Or., 30.20.
173
Social models of the Trinity, with their very strong emphasis on the personal, relational, and
social aspects of being, they focus on the distinctly practical significance of Trinitarian faith for
Christian life in the world. For example: Leonardo Boff,Trinity and Society, London: Burns &
Oates, 1988.
174
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion, 289.
68
from whom and to whom are referred those who follow…with neither time nor will
nor power instigating”.175 In the same Oration, Gregory Nazianzen says: “Those
who exist from the first cause without time”.176 When causation has been applied
beyond time, Zizioulas claims that cosmological implications need not be read
that the Greek idea of causality from its inception was tied up with the dynamic
movement of ousia.177 Though the Cappadocian Fathers used the term physis
(nature) with regard to God, they refused to attach causality to it. Zizioulas
the how, not to the what of God. Causality is used by these Fathers as a strictly
the Trinity
175
Gregory Naz., Or. 42. 15.
176
Gregory Naz., Or. 31. 10; 5. 14.
177
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 128.
178
Ibid., 128.
69
actualized in an event of communion.”179 Person as relational entity in Trinitarian
beyond the self, to seeking communion with the Other.”180 It brings about a change
of the idea of truth, as I state in chapter one section 1.4.1. It identifies truth with life
rather than an objective idea like that of the Greek idea of truth. Thus, communion,
relationality and person are all ontological categories. For Zizioulas, the person of
the Father as the ultimate cause renders each person a relational or communal entity
in Trinity, each person has his own ontological integrity because of the person of
Zizioulas also pinpoints that besides taking the Father as ultimate reality, there
are two alternative views of ultimate reality. One is the Augustinian view that the
three are one because they are relations within the one divine substance; the other is
“what makes the three one, accounting for or expressing their unity, is their
relationship or communion with each other”.181 The latter implies that relationality
or communion is the ultimate ontological category. Later we shall see that the
Torrance and Colin Gunton effectively take the second alternative understanding of
ontology. And it is this second kind of relational ontology that Zizioulas basically
debates with.
179
Ibid., 82.
180
John Zizioulas, “Relational Ontology: Insights from Patristic Thought.” In John Polkinghoren ed.,
The Trinity and an Entangled World: Relationality in Physical Science and Theology (Grand Rapids,
Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub., 2010), 155.
181
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 136.
70
ultimacy of the Father
Facing the criticism that “if a particular person [within the Trinity] is regarded
Zizioulas’ logic is that the person is a relational term. This means that person’s
when we utter the word ‘Father’ we indicate automatically a relationship, that is, a
subordinationism
Zizioulas argues that there is an ordering in the Trinity: the Father comes first, the
Son second, and the Spirit third in biblical and patristic references to the Holy
Trinity, and the order cannot be reversed –we cannot place any of the other persons
before the Father. Zizioulas quotes Gregory Nazianzen’s words to indicate the
ordering in the immanent Trinity: “[t]he union is the Father from whom and to
whom the ordering of persons runs its course.”185 Zizioulas lists the example of
182
Ibid., 126.
183
Ibid., 127.
184
Ibid., 126.
185
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 138, footnote, 76. Gregory Naz., Or. 42.15; cf. Basil,
C. Eun. 1:20; 3:1: the Son is second to the Father ‘because he came from him’, i.e., not in the
economy but in the immanent Trinity. Gregory of Nyssa insists on this order, too, with regard to the
third place, that he Spirit occupies in the immanent Trinity. See also Zizioulas, Communion and
71
Jesus in Gethsemane or in the desert to indicate an ordering in both the economic
and the immanent Trinity: “the Son’s filial ‘Yes’ to the Father…can only make sense
if it points to the eternal filial relationship between the two persons. It is mainly this
unbroken eternal filial relationship that accounts for the fact that Christ’s humanity;
or rather Christ in his humanity, never sinned, that is, contradicted the will of the
Father, although he was tempted to do so in the desert and before going to the
stated above, “When all things are subjected to him, then the Son himself will also
be subjected to the one who put all things in subjection under him, so that God may
be all in all.” (1 Corinthians 15.28) Zizioulas claims that every movement in God
begins with the Father and ends with him. Therefore it inevitably established an
ordering in both the economic and the immanent Trinity. 187 Furthermore, the
temporal, moral and functional terms or phrase such as ‘the Father is greater than I’
(John 14.28) must be understood through the ordering in the immanent Trinity
claims that ‘a hierarchy of value’ would be anthropomorphic and cannot be used for
uncreated existence.
Zizioulas claims that causality does not necessarily endanger equality or lead to
subordinationism. Rather, only when divine nature is confused with the divine
person, and the ‘begotten or emission’ has been read as transmission of ousia by the
Father to the other two persons, then the equality of the Trinitarian persons as fully
by any person would imply the existence of this nature prior to personhood, and
to indicate the relation of order and equality: “why is it necessary, if the Spirit is
third in rank, for him to be also third in nature?...Just as the Son is second to the
Father in rank because he derives from him…but not second in nature, for the deity
is one in each of them, so also is the Spirit.”189 In terms of the Cappadocian view
that divine nature does not exist prior to the divine persons, Zizioulas posits that the
Father is greater than the Son not in nature, but in the way (the how) that nature
emergence of persons, and equality refers to the one divine substance. Therefore,
Zizioulas concludes that Trinitarian ordering and causation protect rather than
threaten the equality and fullness of each person’s deity, once that ordering and
For some critics, they have different Trinitarian theologies. Zizioulas argues that
and C. Gunton193 dissociate the economic Trinity from God’s eternal being. They
make this ordering refer to the economic Trinity and to soteriology. Then they can
divest the economic properties in relation to the persons of the Trinity.194 Cyril
insists that the Father is said to be greater than the Son only economically, and thus
left no room for subordinationism in the case of Holy Trinity. 195 However,
189
Basil, C. Eun 3.1; see also in John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 140.
190
Ibid., 140.
191
See Vladimir. Lossky, In the Image and Likeness of God (Crestwook, N.Y.: St. Vladimir’s
Seminary Press, 1974), 92.
192
See T. F. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives, 1994, 32.
193
See C. Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian Theology, 196.
194
Vladimir Lossky, The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church (Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s
Seminary Press, 1976), 83.
195
See T. F. Torrance, The Trinitarian Faith (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1988), 338.
73
Zizioulas distinguishes between the economical Trinity and immanent Trinity but
he does not separate them. So his critics charge that there is subordinationism in
some sense in Zizioulas’ Trinitarian theology. But there are problems for the critics
themselves when they separate the economic Trinity from the immanent Trinity. I
suggests that three persons of God are mutually constitutive and there exists mutual
By extending the notion of causality to the three persons, it might seem that
Papanikolaou preserves the notion of freedom within the Trinity and avoids
personal otherness were symmetrical, or the Father, the Son and the Spirit are
freedom
‘how God is’, the divine modes of existence. Essence expresses “what God is”.
Zizioulas’ ontological principle is the priority of person over nature. For Ziziouals,
ontological freedom of God and man. It means that the ontological freedom of God
and man are not limited by the necessity of the substance in Zizioulas’ thoughts. He
writes: “The manner [person] in which God exercises His ontological freedom, that
precisely which makes Him ontologically free, is the way in which He transcends
and abolishes the ontological necessity of the substance by being God as Father,
that is, as He who ‘begets’ the Son and ‘brings forth’ the Spirit.” 197 In his
ontological principle, the relation between person and nature is antithetical. But the
and time they enhance it.” 198 This means that the person-nature relationship is
conceptual revolution, but they oppose the Father as cause. However, the most
theologians of substantialist ontology, but from theologians who equally stress the
197
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 44.
198
Douglas Farrow, ‘Person and Nature: The Necessity-Freedom Dialectic in John Zizioulas’, in
Douglas H. Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 121.
75
ontology of relationality.
The monarchy (monarchia) of the Father indicating the one arche in divine
existence has been criticized by many theologians.199 The main criticism is that
giving preeminence to the Father would threaten the equality of Trinitarian persons;
the second criticism is whether taking Father as cause of the Trinity would endanger
Zizioulas’ identification of being and communion. The third one is that causality as
the Father, Zizioulas has to face these criticisms. The following section will discuss
these.
Many theologians offer criticisms involving the Father as personal cause. For
example, T. F. Torrance opposes the view of the monarchy of the Father on different
theological grounds: “In the Cappadocian framework this meant that procession is
which is hardly satisfactory for it falls short of affirming the homoousion of the
Spirit.” 200 Torrance thinks that Gregory Nazianzen’ view of causality was not
limited to the Father: “Gregory Nazianzen felt strongly that to subordinate any of
the three divine Persons to another was to overthrow the doctrine of the Trinity. He
was thus returning to the more unified conception of the divine arche advocated by
Athanasius, who had also rejected any idea of degrees of Deity in the Trinity.”201
199
According to Gregory Nazianzen, in the ontological sense, monarchia means unity of personal
derivation. The monas is identified with the Father. In the moral sense, monarchia signifies unity of
rule. It is shared equally by the three persons. See his Theol. Or. 3.2 or John Zizioulas, Communion
and Otherness, 119, footnote 21.
200
Thomas. F. Torrance, The Christian Doctrine of God, One Being Three Persons (Edinburgh:
T&T Clark, 1996), 186.
201
T. F. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives: Toward Doctrinal Agreement (Edinburgh: T&T Clark,
76
Torrance particularly cites from Cyril and Athanasius to oppose the primacy of the
Father, since there is a danger of an ontological subordinationism, with the Son and
the Spirit at least appearing to be less truly God than the Father. In fact, the two
heretical context. Their views are the main arguments for Torrance to criticize the
For Alan Torrance, there are some problems with Zizioulas’ concept of causality:
The first problem is that there is a contradiction between ‘the Father as cause’ and
‘Holy Trinity’ as ontologically primordial: “If the Trinity derives from a causal act
of the Father, is the ‘concept’ of the ‘Holy Trinity’ really being conceived as
The second problem is that causality threatens personal equality of the Trinity:
to the Father’ – even though he might not be ‘obliged to downgrade the Logos into
something created.”203
The third problem is that Alan Torrance regards that the Cappadocian projection
of causal notions into the internal life of God would seem to be potentially
itself’.”204
integrated with the Eucharistic experience that Zizioulas perceives as the context of
1994), 30.
202
See T. F. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives: Toward Doctrinal Agreement, 30-35.
203
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1996), 293.
204
Ibid.
77
Trinitarian articulation.205 This means that ‘causality’ is not a proper category in
Trinitarian theology.
I will discuss the question of T. F. Torrance and the first question of Alan
Torrance which involve the ontology of relationality in the coming sections. The
answer can be found in 2.3.6 “Personal ordering in the immanent Trinity not a
person and communion. The reply can be acquired in part 2.3.5 “Rendering
communion primordial not in conflict with the ontological ultimacy of the Father”.
The fourth asks whether ‘causality’ is a proper notion for Trinitarian theology. In
Cappadocian notion of the Father as cause; now we turn to more ontological issues
Torrance’s famous book The Christian Doctrine of God, One Being Three
Fathers:
205
Ibid., 290-292.
78
We recall that the conflation of these two senses by the Cappadocian Fathers gave rise to
serious difficulties, not least in connection with their conception of the Unity of God as
deriving ‘from the Person of the Father, thereby replacing the Nicene formula ‘from the
Being of the Father.’ In the Cappadocian framework this meant that procession is regarded
as taking place between different modes of existence or relations of origin, which is hardly
satisfactory for it falls short of affirming the homoousion of the Spirit.206
As we have pointed out above Torrance writes: “Gregory Nazianzen felt strongly
that to subordinate any of the three divine Persons to another was to overthrow the
doctrine of the Trinity. He was thus returning to the more unified conception of the
divine arche advocated by Athanasius, who had also rejected any idea of degrees of
Alan Torrance queries Zizioulas: “it seems to us that he fails to offer sufficiently
do not conceive of the intra-divine communion of the Triunity as the ground of all
that is, that is, as sufficient in itself and as indeed ‘capable’ of existing ‘by
206
Thomas. F. Torrance, The Christian Doctrine of God, One Being Three Persons, 186.
207
T. F. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspective: Toward Doctrinal Agreement (Edinburgh: T&T Clark,
1994), 30.
208
Thomas. F. Torrance, The Christian Doctrine of God, One Being Three Persons, 185. Torrance
argues that the formulation of the doctrine of the Trinity at the Council of Constantinople’s
development did not follow the line advocated by the Cappadocians in grounding the unity of the
Godhead in the Person of the Father as the unique and exclusive Principle of the Godhead, but
reverted to the doctrine of the Son as begotten of the Being of the Father and made a similar
affirmation of the Holy Spirit. It is reaffirmation of Nicene theology which operated on the basis laid
down by Athanasius. See 182.
79
itself’.”209 Alan Torrance is consistent with T. F. Torrance when they cite Cyril’s
conceptions.
indwelling and containing of one another, in which they are inconfusedly united and
inseparably distinguished, was very different, for it carried within it the combined
Gunton also criticizes that while causality preserves the due priority of the Father
in the Godhead, it is not an adequate theology for the mutual constitution of Father,
communion’ as the ultimate reality in God, Zizioulas points out that though the
view “appears to be different from that of making substance the ultimate reality, yet
the difference is actually very little and the difficulties it presents are exactly the
same”.212. It means that they all create the ‘fourth’ reality behind the three persons.
Firstly, Zizioulas claims that it will violate the biblical monotheism of ‘God the
209
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation, 293.
210
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation, 294. The quotation is taken from T. F. Torrance, The Trinitarian Faith, 340.
211
Colin E. Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian Theology (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1997), 196.
212
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness. 134.
80
Father’ if anything beyond the Father is regarded as ultimate reality. He quotes Karl
Secondly, Zizioulas questions the ‘oneness’ or ‘unity’ of the three divine persons
(in the co-emergence and co-existence of the three persons) as the ultimate reality
in God. The one God is not the Father but the unity of Father, Son and Spirit in
the creedal and biblical expression ‘from the Father’, because ‘from the Father’
means an ontological derivation. In this case, otherness of the persons in Trinity “is
not derived from a particular Other but is itself the ultimate explanation of
itself.”215
because “if the one God is not a particular hypostasis, our prayer cannot be
addressed to the one God but only to the Trinity or to the ‘Triunity.’ ”216. Logically,
the one God is left out of our prayer. Zizioulas points out that according to the Bible,
in praying to the Trinity, we are ultimately praying to the one God, the Father. And
he provides two biblical verses as argument, “then comes the end, when he hands
over the kingdom to God the Father, after he has destroyed every ruler and every
213
see also John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 134.
214
Karl Rahner, The Trinity (London: Burns & Oates, 1986), 17.
215
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness. 135.
216
Ibid., 136.
81
authority and power” (1 Corinthians 15.24); and “for through him both of us have
In response to Gunton’s ‘three persons are together the cause of mutual and
reciprocal constitution’, Zizioulas thinks that it will threaten the coincidence of the
It seems that Zizioulas has provided plausible replies to his critics, and the
Cappadocian Fathers, and Zizioulas responds to their criticisms, they ignore two
Firstly, Gregory Nazianzen’s person as cause does not deny the homousion of
three persons. I think both T. F. Torrance and John Zizioulas overlook this issue.
relationship between the Council of Nicea (325) and the Council of Constantinople
(381): whether or not the Cappadocian Fathers safeguard the homoousios when
they posit the Father as the ultimate ontological principle. Zizioulas gives priority
217
Ibid., 35
82
being a matter of transmission of substance, causality involves freedom in personal
being and makes God the Trinity not a necessary but a free being.”218
However, Zizioulas does not highlight the real purpose of Gregory Nazianzen,
namely, his intention to affirm the Nicene faith. In order to preserve the idea of
homoousios of the first Ecumenical Council and oppose the attack of Arianism,
Gregory distinguishes the concept of hypostasis (person) from ousia and insists
that the Father and Son are relational entities. The difference between them is the
origin and the relation. Therefore, the difference is in ‘person’ or hypostasis and the
ousia of the three persons is one and the same. Thus, he insists on the view of
said by Kelly:
The climax of the developments we have been studying was the affirmation of the Nicene
faith at the council of Constantinople in 381. At this the consubstantiality of the Spirit as well
as of the Son was formally endorsed. The theology which prevailed, as exemplified by the
great Cappadocians themselves and by teachers like Didymus the Blind and Evagrius
Ponticus, may be fairly described as in substance that of Athanasius. It is true that their angle
of approach was somewhat different from his. Emerging from the Homoousian tradition, it
was natural that they should make the three hypostases, rather than the one divine substance,
their starting-point.219
away from his historical context. Athanasius’ homoousion could not deal with the
5th century, and he was primarily concerned with Christology, dealing with a series
218
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 130.
219
J. N. D. Kelly, Early Christian Doctrines, 263-264.
83
Gregory Nazianzen in his theological orations discussed the question of Arians
and Eunomians: whether the Son is the essence of God or the energy of God. This is
a dilemma: if the Church replied that the Son is the essence of God, it would not
have been possible to distinguish between the Son and the Father; if the answer is
the energy, they would have reduced the Son to a creature. Gregory proposes a third
way to answer Eunomians’ question: the Son is neither essence nor energy, but an
identity that can be described only in terms of his relationships. The ‘Father’ and
‘Son’ are categories of relationship and persons. The concept of person is not an
On the other hand, the importance of the above view was a response to the
procession from one to another is a natural evolution outwards from the One, in a
with love, for “this analogy makes the Father’s begetting of the Son involuntary,
which would suggest that the entire Trinity exists as a natural and necessary
consequence of the essence that God is.”220 Gregory Nazianzen’s argument is: “for
we shall not venture to speak of ‘an overflow of goodness,’ as one of the Greek
like some natural overflow, hard to be retained, and by no means befitting our
conception of Deity.”221
Nazianzen, ignores some important theological and philosophical problems that the
220
Ibid., 61.
221
Gregory Naz., Theol. Or. 3.2.
84
Cappadocian Fathers have treated with their ontology of personhood. On the other
hand, although Zizioulas is right in expounding the Cappadocian view of the Father
Fathers with Athanasius’ theology. The overall effect of the Cappadocian Fathers’
although they affirmed Athanasius’ concept of homoousion they did not allow it to
strengthen a substantialist understanding of the Triune God, but uses the concept of
must bear in mind that this ontology of personhood has to repudiate the
In fact, Zizioulas is fully aware that in the East, since Origen, there is
Son to the Father without being obliged to downgrade Logos into something
created. But this was possible only because the Son’s otherness was founded on the
same substance”.222 It is obvious that the Cappadocian Fathers and John Zizioulas
continue the Eastern traditional Monarchianism of the Father which was criticized
separate hypostases from ousia, and identify hypostases with person. That means
Nazianzen writes: “When we admit that, in respect of being the Cause, the Father is
222
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 89.
85
greater than the Son, they (Arianism) should assume the premise that He is the
Cause by Nature, and then deduce the conclusion that He is greater by Nature
also.”223
beneficial to consider the famous Reformed theologian Calvin, for Calvin supports
the monarchy of the Father. Many theologians argue that the main theological
influence on Calvin was Augustine, but it is evident that Calvin appeals to the
more attention to each personhood in Trinity. 224 Calvin rejects the theological
method of the Latin schoolmen that begin with the abstract question ‘what God is’.
Instead he begins with that of ‘what kind of God is he’.225 For Calvin, the relation
Calvin gives primacy to the biblical revelation of God as Father, Son and Holy
Spirit. At the same time he believes the orthodox expression of the Trinity: One
God in Three persons and Three persons in One God.227 Calvin used the words of
Gregory of Nazianzen to express the relation between one and three: “I cannot think
of the one without quickly being encircled by the splendor of the three; nor can I
223
Gregory Naz., Or. Theol. 29.15.
224
For example, T. F. Torrance. J. Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion, I, 13. 17.
225
Calvin, Institute I. 2. 2.
226
J. Calvin, Institutes of the Christian Religion, I. 13.20.
227
Ibid., I 554, 6, 21.
86
discern the three without being straightway carried back to the one.”228
Calvin begins with the distinction of persons in God, because to know God is to
know him precisely as three persons, 229 and it was only the person of Christ
revealed by the Son of the Father distinguishing him from the Father and the
Spirit.230 He accepts the Greek term prosopon, and its Latin translation persona, as
equivalent to hypostasis used in this way, and agrees to the use of subsistentia as a
literal translation of hypostasis. 231 It means that Calvin affirms the ontological
otherness among the three persons. He cites the words: “the stamp of the Father’s
the Persons of the Trinity: “from this we also easily ascertain the Son’s hypostasis,
which distinguishes him from the Father. The same reasoning applies to the Holy
Spirit…”232
in relation, but essence refers to being in itself. Calvin argues that this distinction
within the utter unity of God with different persons is not contradictory. It is in this
sense that Calvin speaks of the three divine persons in the one being of God, who
are what they are as Father, Son, and Holy Spirit in their consubstantial relations
In modern theology, there are also some Western theologians who maintain the
monarchy of the Father. For example, Moltmann avers that the monarchy of the
Father does not threaten the equality of persons in Trinity through the concept of
228
Ibid., I, 13, 17.
229
Ibid., I. 13.2
230
Ibid., I. 13.16.
231
Ibid., I.13. 2.
232
Ibid., I. 13. 2
233
T. F. Torrance, Trinitarian Perspectives: Toward Doctrinal Agreement (Edinburgh: T&T Clark,
1994), 28.
87
It is true that the Trinity is constituted with the Father as starting point, inasmuch as he is
understood as being ‘the origin of the Godhead’. But this ‘monarchy of the Father’ only
applies to the constitution of the Trinity. It has no validity within the eternal circulation of the
divine life, and none in the perichoretic unity of the Trinity. Here the three Persons are equal;
234
they live and are manifested in one another and through one another.
The other theologian who supports ‘the monarchy of the Father’ is Catherine
LaCugna. In her book God for Us, she argues that subordination in the economy
does not entail subordination at the level of ‘theologia’. “The Cappadocian solution
subordination, since Son and Spirit in the economy are sent by the Father who
All the above theological voices support Zizioulas’ claim that acceptance of the
monarchy of the Father does not necessarily commit one to an objectionable form
of subordinationism.
234
Jürgen Moltmann, The Trinity and the Kingdom: The Doctrine of God (Minneapolis, Fortress
Press, 1993), 175-176.
235
Karl Rahner, The Trinity, 17.
236
Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us (San Francisco: HarperSanFrancisco, 1991), 70.
88
Part II
89
Chapter Three
beings to be? In Greek philosophy, the particular is caused by the general. “In other
words, particular human beings are in so far as they participate either in the ideal
‘human being’ or in the ‘nature’ of humanity, its species.”237 In contrast with the
Greek view, Zizioulas thinks that the cause of being is the particular, not the general.
being is caused not by divine substance but by the Father. Similarly, when a human
being exists as God himself exists, he takes on God’s ‘ways of being’. The reason is
that “God created humankind in his image”. (Genesis 1. 27) Therefore, the
simultaneously: the Father is the ultimate giver of personhood, and each single
person acquires personal otherness, i.e., absolute particularity in Christ, i.e., the
ground for the being of man, and our transformation from biological to ecclesial
237
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 104.
90
Based on the Cappadocian fathers, the concept of person (and therefore
personhood) is a relational and ontological category and does not refer primarily to
being-by-itself.
terms of two terms: ekstasis and hypostasis. Ekstasis was used in the mystical
of oneself: “The person in its ecstatic character reveals its being in a catholic, that
is, integral and undivided, way, and thus in its being ecstatic it becomes hypostatic,
that is, the bearer of its nature in its totality.”239 Hypostasis means the particular
truth by the fact of being in communion, hypostasis signifies that in and through his
communion a person affirms his own identity and his particularity; he ‘supports his
238
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 101.
239
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 213.
240
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 106.
241
Aquinas is the representative proponent of ‘the individualization of ‘nature’’. See Joseph Bobik,
translation and interpretation, Aquinas on Being and Essence (Notre Dame: University of Notre
91
‘personality’ exists in itself, but a person is constituted within his relationships and
personhood is about “hypostasis, that is, the claim to uniqueness in the absolute
sense of the term, and this cannot be guaranteed by reference to sex or function or
experiences, since all of these can be classified, thus representing qualities shared
by more than one being and not pointing to absolute uniqueness.”242 Finally, the
‘person’ cannot exist in fallen existence, but ‘nature’ or ‘personality’ can, because
Before the fourth century, when the notion of hypostasis was identical with that
of ‘substance’, these two words are the same in usage denoting the ultimate
particular being in itself since Aristotle. But when the term hypostasis ceased to
denote ‘substance’ and became synonymous with that of `person’ in theology, the
not with ousia but with personhood means that the ontological question is not
Dame Press, 1965), 59-107. The essence of man is a composite substance. The composite
substances are form and matter. For man, form and matter signify soul and body. It means we cannot
say that either one of them alone is itself the essence. (59) Humanity or essence signifies that by
which man is man: “Humanity, for example, though composed, is not man; it must be received into
something which is designated matter.” (107) Matter is the principle of individuation. It is
designated matter which constitutes the principle of individuation. “The principle of individuation is
not matter taken in just any way whatever, but only designated matter…such matter is not placed in
the definition of man as man, but it would be placed in the definition of Socrates, if Socrates had a
definition. Rather, it is nondesignated matter which is placed in the definition of man; for this bone
and this flesh are not placed in the definition of man, but bone and flesh absolutely.” (75)
242
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 111.
243
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 107.
92
boundaries, but to a being which in its ekstasis breaks through these boundaries in
identity is to be found ultimately not in ‘substance’, but only in a being which is free
from the boundaries of the ‘self’. Because “these boundaries render it subject to
such a being free from these boundaries is free, not in a moral but in an ontological
sense, that is, in the way it is constituted and realized as a being.”245 Furthermore,
since hypostasis is identical with person, not with substance, it exists not in its
communion.
The mystery of being a person lies in the fact that here otherness and communion are not in
contradiction but coincide. Truth as communion does not lead to the dissolving of the diversity
of beings into one vast ocean of being, but to the affirmation of otherness in and through love.
The difference between this truth and that of ‘nature in itself’ lies in the following: while the
latter is subject to fragmentation, individualization, conceptualization, comprehension, etc., the
person is not. So in the context of personhood, otherness is incompatible with division.246
“It is an ‘I’ that can exist only as long as it relates to a ‘thou’ which affirms its
existence and its otherness. If we isolate the ‘I’ from the ‘thou’ we lost not only its
244
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 214.
245
Ibid., 214.
246
John Ziziouilas, Being as Communion, 106-107.
93
otherness but also its very being; it simply cannot be without the other. This is what
(b) Personhood is freedom. Freedom is the basic presupposition for the constitution
of personhood. Furthermore, this freedom is not freedom from the other but
freedom for the other. “In its anthropological significance, as well as in its
freedom of being other.” 248 Zizioulas distinguishes the concept of ‘other’ from
holy, etc.), which is not what the person is about: to be a person implies not simply
the freedom to have different qualities, but mainly the freedom simply to be
yourself. Zizioulas’ purpose is to show that “a person is not subject to norms and
absolute.”249
freedom is not from but for someone or something other than ourselves, thus
freedom makes the person go outside and beyond the boundaries of the ‘self’. It can
of the other. The affirmation of the other is not limited to the ‘other’ that already
exists, but wants to affirm an ‘other’. This is the totally free grace of the person.
This is the creativity which is defined by Zizioulas: “Just as God created the world
totally as free grace, so the person wants to create its own ‘other’.”250 A person as a
creator brings about a totally other identity as an act of freedom and communion.
247
Ibid., 9.
248
Ibid., 9.
249
Ibid.
250
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 10.
94
3.2 The being of God as the ontological ground for the being of
humans
Zizioulas claims the being of God as the ontological ground for the being of
human: “Because we are made in the image of God we can see intimations of this in
our own relationships. Because man is made in the image of God, we can find
analogies between God and man, that are based in the relationships of the persons
of God. The doctrine of the Trinity gives us the truth of our own existence.”251
being. Personal identity is guaranteed by relationship with God, thus the identity
would not be isolated: “Personal identity is totally lost if isolated, for its
the hypo-static and the ek-static have to coincide. The Father as cause, a particular
Because the concept of personhood is related also to the idea of divine causality,
the Father being the cause of personhood in God’s being can throw light on our own
personal existence. Zizioulas argues for the significance of ‘causality’ from three
Firstly, it means that a person is always a gift from someone. It affirms that
251
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 64.
252
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 112.
253
Ibid., 141.
95
notion of self-existence is a substantialist notion. Causality in Trinitarian
persons are the outcome of love and freedom, and they owe their being who they
are, their distinctive otherness as persons, to other person(s). Persons are givers and
ourselves but by someone else, who in this way is ‘higher’, that is, ontologically
‘prior’ to us, the giver of our otherness. There are three important points of view
ontologically free and fully equal. A-symmetry does not exclude equality.
Zizioulas writes: “A-symmetry is not incompatible with equality.”254 (c) All others
owe their being to the person who in his own being generates otherness, that is, the
Father. This makes the Father the ultimate giver for human personhood, because
the Father’s personhood is not given or caused by someone else, but is the
The idea of a-symmetry is important to preclude the logical possibility that the
ultimate giver, the Father, receives his personhood from those who receive it from
254
Ibid., 144.
255
Ibid., 144.
96
The realization of the drive of man towards personal ontology cannot be
provided by created being. Christ is the way to fulfilling the human drive to
(a) Christology is one from above, not from below. It means the nature of Christ
speaking of the hypostasis of the Son as the only personal identity of Christ. Man
acquires personal identity and ontological particularity only by basing his being on
the Father-Son relationship in which nature is not primary to the particular being. It
(b) In Christ, the particular is raised to the level of ontological primacy, and the
general exists only in and through the particular. The ‘who’ of Christ is the Son. The
two natures give their qualities to the personal identity without making the identity
depends on these qualities. In Christ, the aim does not exclude natural qualities
from the identity of ‘I’ –but ‘enhypostasizes’ these qualities. So the cause of being is
the particular, not the general man. It means that our identities do not ultimately
(c) Christ exists in the personal relationship with the Father. The salvation for the
world is the union of the created with the uncreated. This union is not mechanical or
magical synthesis of two natures, but through the communion with the triune God:
the incarnation is a movement from the Father back to the Father, through Christ in
the Holy Spirit. This model of union provides a possibility for the union of the
97
of persons acting in freedom”.256 Zizioulas criticizes the view that Christ gave up
his divinity in suffering for our sake in terms of the self-emptying (kenosis) in the
incarnation. Zizioulas denies this view because Christ’s divinity has been affirmed
by the relationship with the Father, and this relationship is in no way altered by the
incarnation. The nature of Christ is the same with the Father and this nature exists
without interruption. He can suffer because he took human nature. In Christ nothing
human and completely God as the Council of Chalcedon (451) stated that in Christ
either respect.
separated. The Holy Spirit is the ‘life-giver’.257 Zizioulas has not emphasized alone
the function of Spirit as the drive towards the realization of personal ontology,
Christ.”259
256
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 109.
257
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 204.
258
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 126-132.
259
Ibid., 131.
98
means the realization of personhood and this realization is salvation: “The eternal
survival of the person as a unique, unrepeatable and free ‘hypostasis,’ as loving and
being loved, constitutes the quintessence of salvation, the bringing of the Gospel to
man.”260 In this section, I will introduce these two modes of existence. Since it is
existence
In the first part 1.4.2, we have stated that Athanasius develops the idea of
communion has been formed within the Eucharistic theology developed by Ignatius,
Greek patristic thought concerning truth, we can say that the Greek Fathers’ main
success in this area rests in the identification of truth with communion.”262 When
this point of view has been applied to created existence, Zizioulas describes the
fallen existence as the rupture between being and communion.263 Then salvation
means a recovery of the relation between being and communion. It is very different
from the Western soteriological categories like sin, justification and sanctification.
From the perspective of the relationship between God and man, God created the
world so that it would participate in his own glorious life. The responsibility of man
260
Ibid., 49.
261
Ibid., 83.
262
Ibid., 101.
263
Ibid., 102.
99
is to bring the world into a living relationship or communion with him. He was to be
the mediator between the material world and God, and so he was created at the end
of creation, when everything else was ready for him. God gave man God’s own
freedom and the capacity for self-government. But the freedom of man includes a
possibility for the fall of man. “Man has the freedom which every other created
being in the material world lacks, and he exercises it by accepting or rejecting each
given event or situation.”264 When man decided to exercise his freedom by saying
‘no’ to God and makes himself ‘God’, the fall happens. “Adam succumbed to the
temptation to declare himself ‘God’ and set out to redirect creation from the
uncreated God to his own, created self. In deciding that everything should refer to
Zizioulas lists three consequences of the fall or rupture between being and
communion.
The first consequence is idolatry. Zizioulas explains the reason: idolatry is the
realizes how much weaker he is, he regarded nature as a god, or indeed as many
gods. He began to divinize the forces of nature and then to worship them. It is a
tragedy for mankind to deify creation, for it leads to a dissolution: “When man took
God’s place and turned himself to nature, all creation became victim to man’s
delusion. Man and creation have together become confined to a life determined by
the laws of nature. Though biological life seems to point towards life without limit,
The second consequence is that truth has been linked with the nature or
substance of things. The substance or ousia of things becomes the ultimate content
264
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 98.
265
Ibid., 98.
266
Ibid., 99.
100
of truth. The being of things has been recognized before a relationship, and every
single being acquires an ontological status on its own merit. The world consists of
objects, thus the known and the knower exist as two opposite partners. “Since the
being of things is ultimate and prior to communion, and everything that exists
posits its own being as something ‘given’ to man the world ultimately consists of a
fragmented existence in which beings are particular before they can relate to each
The third consequence is a ‘dying being’. One biological fact is that death takes
place at the end of life. We will analyze death as an ontological problem which is
Therefore, for Zizioulas, from the perspective of the ontology of communion, the
lacks communion with God. Only the ecclesial hypostasis as new life is in
communion with God. The ecclesial hypostasis does not exclude the existence of
birth. Every man who comes into the world bears his ‘hypostasis’, which is not
people.”268 This biological hypostasis can be traced back to two ‘passions’. The
first ‘passion’ is tied to the natural instinct which Zizioulas calls ‘ontological
267
Ibid., 103.
268
Ibid., 50.
101
necessity’. Because the natural instinct or impulse is subject to necessity rather than
freedom, thus the person as a being ‘subsists’ not as freedom but as necessity. The
separation of the hypostases; the other is death. The earlier stage means the
which is born as a biological hypostasis, behaves like the fortress of an ego, like a
new ‘mask’ which hinders the hypostasis from becoming a person, that is, from
kinds of death. One is in the sense of biology which belongs to the nature of what is
created; the other is the opposite of real life in our fallen existence.270 This kind of
death entered the world as the punishment for disobedience and the fall.271 It means
that an ethical relationship between God and the world determined the death of man.
It seems that God introduced death to creation and imposed it on man. Salvation has
often been set out in moral and judicial terms. For Zizioulas, biological death has
not been caused by man’s act of disobedience. Zizioulas regards that death has
always been the natural condition of created beings, and death is inevitable for
creation.272 Because the world came from nothingness, death is only a return to
nothingness.
269
Ibid., 51.
270
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 264.
271
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 102.
272
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 51; Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 102.
102
Death is not only a biological phenomenon. For Zizioulas, he also discusses
death as the opposite of the real life and I would call it spiritual death. “Life is
commandment of the Creator is life. (Romans 7.10) Whereas man in his fallen
existence loses his being and runs into death, when he exists according to the
command and intention of the Creator, he gains his being and attains to life in the
fullest sense.”274
spiritual death and the new spiritual life to ‘after the flesh’ or ‘after the Spirit’. It is
consistent with the New Testament: “So that the just requirement of the law might
be fulfilled in us, who walk not according to the flesh but according to the Spirit.”
(Romans 8. 4) The existence of the fall or death is an existence ‘after the flesh’.
Man’s authentic existence is ‘after the Spirit’ which expresses a way of man’s being:
man is oriented to God, to the invisible and eternal rather than to the world, i.e., the
Death is an ontological problem for human beings. Zizioulas claims that the
problem cannot be put right simply by our obedience: “Athanasius pointed out that
if the problem could be solved simply by forgiving Adam his sin, God could have
done so. Adam could have repented, and indeed he did weep and regret what he had
273
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 78.
274
John Macquarrie, An Existentialist Theology: A comparison of Heidegger and Bultmann
(Harmandsworth: Penguin Books, 1973), 129.
103
done. God could have forgiven him, and all would have been well. But Athanasius
shows that the heart of the problem was not obedience or disobedience, because
this was not a moral but an ontological problem.” 275 The ontological problem
The themes of death and life are the main categories in Zizioulas’ theology. For
not discuss the problem of sin. From the above quotation, he also wants to say that
The new mode of existence formed in the Church is called ‘the hypostasis of
life, an eternal life. The ecclesial existence exists truly in unbroken relationship
with God. The true definition of man is the creature who participates freely in the
life of God—not a creature who lives from some resources of his own.277
the new birth of man through baptism. Baptism leads to a new mode of existence, to
275
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 102. Zizioulas did not explain the source of
Athanasius’ opinion.
276
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 261.
277
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 115.
104
ecclesial hypostasis is through baptism. According to the hypostatic communion,
Zizioulas defines the essence of baptism: “This adoption of man by God, the
identification of his hypostasis with the hypostasis of the Son of God, is the essence
of baptism.” 278 The new hypostasis of man is realized through the Church.
Therefore, in early patristic literature the image of the Church as mother is often
employed. Through the Church a birth takes place: man is born as ‘hypostasis,’ as
person.
principle which has been applied from God to man: “As an ecclesial hypostasis man
thus proves that what is valid for God can also be valid for man: the nature does not
determine the person; the person enables the nature to exist; freedom is identified
Firstly, Zizioulas discusses the case of incarnation. What makes Christ a person
is the relationship with the Father through which all his other relationships exist and
by which they are determined. In the incarnation, Christ took on other relationships
such as relationships with his mother, his disciples, and the entire people of Israel.
Zizioulas claims that “all these relationships belong to his personal identity, and
they are all judged by the decisive relationship that Christ has with the Father.”280
It can provide an answer for one question: where does Christ get his consciousness
theological circles, of whether Christ had two kinds of consciousness in two natures.
278
Ibid., 56.
279
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 57.
280
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 112.
105
draws his consciousness of himself from his relationship with the Father and is
determined by this single relationship. Zizioulas claims that only until 20th century
discovery that there is no ‘I’ without a ‘you’.”281 It is important for the practice of
Western portraits of Christ and those in Byzantine. In the West, Christ is portrayed
as a baby alone with his mother, the Virgin Mary, which means that the maternal
relationship gives the identity to the baby. But in Byzantine, the painter shows us
that the child is God, and so the baby is not defined by the Virgin but by his
Secondly, it can be used in the human case. “We are persons because our distinct
parents, natural relationships with our environment, and a vast complex of other
social and political relationships.”283 We receive our personhood from the whole
us and God. This relationship will eventually determine all other relationships. That
means that only one relationship is the most important and ultimate for us. This
them: one is that through the Church man transcends exclusivism. According to
the family has priority in love over ‘strangers’. But the ecclesial hypostasis
281
Ibid., 113.
282
See John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 112-113.
283
Ibid., 111.
106
capacity of the person to love without exclusiveness, and to do this not out of
conformity with a moral commandment (‘Love thy neighbor,’ etc.) but out of his
‘hypostatic constitution,’ out of the fact that his new birth from the womb of the
Church has made him part of a network of relationships which transcends every
into individuality. In the Church two things are realized simultaneously: the world
is presented to man not as mutually exclusive portions but as a single whole. Man is
called upon to unite every concrete being. At the same time this man expresses and
realizes a catholic presence in the world, a hypostasis which is not an individual but
ontological level rather than a moral level: Thus the ecclesial hypostasis is not a
creation.285
experience: “What happens to the biological hypostasis of man when that which I
have called the ecclesial hypostasis is brought into being?” 286 In spite of the
existence of the ecclesial hypostasis, man does not cease at the same time to be born
and to die in accordance with his biological hypostasis. In fact, the encounter
284
Ibid., 58.
285
See John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 58, footnote 53.
286
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 58.
107
determined by his relationship with God. But the ecclesial hypostasis is not entirely
realized in man’s historical existence: “Man appears to exist in his ecclesial identity
not as that which he is but as that which he will be; the ecclesial identity is linked
with eschatology, that is, with the final outcome of his existence.”287 In practice a
manner different from the biological as a member of a body which transcends every
a locus where man experiences the transcendence of the ontological necessity and
historical context of human existence where the terms ‘father,’ ‘brother,’ etc., lose
and universal love.” 290 The Eucharist is the ecclesial identity in its historical
has as its object man’s transcendence of his biological hypostasis and his becoming
an authentic person.” 291 The Eucharist means that man ultimately exists only
287
Ibid., 59.
288
Ibid., 59.
289
Ibid., 60.
290
Ibid., 60.
291
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 61. See footnote 61. Zizioulas takes marriage as example:
“it would be a mistake to regard marriage as a simple confirmation and blessing of a biological fact.
Linked with the Eucharist it becomes a reminder that although the newly married couple have been
108
within Christ.292
Eucharist that expresses the relationship between the ecclesial and the biological
hypostasis. The ecclesial hypostasis is not simply a historical being but points to an
a person, which, however, has its roots in the future and is perpetually inspired, or
rather maintained and nourished, by the future. The truth and the ontology of the
person belong to the future, are images of the future.”293 According to the book of
hoped for, the conviction of things not seen” (Hebrews 11:1) in light of the
the ecclesial hypostasis contains a kind of dialectic of ‘already but not yet.’ This
person to see that his true home is not in this world, but in the future, “The ecclesial
hypostasis, as a transcendence of the biological, draws its beginning from the being
of God and from that which it will itself be at the end of the age.”294
blessed in order to create their own family, nevertheless the ultimate and essential network of
relationships which constitutes their hypostasis is not the family but the Church as expressed in the
Eucharistic assembly. This eschatological transcendence of the biological hypostasis is also
conveyed by the ‘crowning’ of the bride and groom, but is lost essentially and existentially from the
moment the rite of marriage is separate from the eucharist.”
292
See John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 116.
293
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 62.
294
Ibid.
109
Chapter Four
Communion and otherness are two aspects of the concept of person. This kind of
For Zizioulas, otherness is primary and constitutive of the very idea of being. It
not of ethics but of ontology: if otherness disappears beings simply cease to be.”296
has been formed in the unique relationship in which a certain other is singled out as
the unique Other. Uniqueness is not understood in terms of nature, but is rooted in
295
Emmanuel Levinas (1906-1995) was a French philosopher of Lithuanian Jewish ancestry who is
known for his work related to Jewish philosophy, existentialism, ethics, and ontology.
296
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 11.
110
energy, etc.). The only otherness we can speak of in the case of the Trinity is personal otherness.
It is an otherness that involves uniqueness and radical alterity stemming not from natural or
moral qualities, or from a combination of such qualities, but from unique relations.297
absolute Other. “Only if the ultimate goal of a particular being is the Other, and
only if this Other is a person that can hypostasize the particular and elevate it to the
status of ontological ultimacy, can this particular being survive as particular, and
not be swallowed up by the general.”298 This means that if the existence of a certain
being has the general as its ultimate goal, it will be destined to be absorbed by the
general. Thus, Zizioulas affirms the crucial question for human beings: “is whether
in all truth the ultimate goal in our existence is—to put it in terms borrowed from
patristic theology— the ‘other’ not as λλο but as λλοζ (otherness of being),
The Other must be a person rather than a principle such as morality, a code of
behavior, etc. This point can be used to criticize the tendency to reduce religion into
a kind of ethics. However, it raises some questions: whether the work of the Cross
can be morally described through the absolute priority of the Other, whether
martyrdom and asceticism are part of ethics, and whether we have such an ethic of
logical difficulty, because otherness is generated from unique relations rather than
the self alone or its nature. “The Other can truly exist as Other only if it is ultimately
regarded as person or hypostasis and not as self or nature, it will mean that every
being should be treated as absolutely Other in the above sense.”300 Ethics operates
297
Ibid., 70.
298
Ibid., 68.
299
Gregory Naz., Ep. 101. 4 (PG 37, 180A-B); Maximus, Ep. 15 (PG 91, 552B): λλο=otherness of
nature; λλοζ =otherness of person. See Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 68, footnote 157.
300
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 69.
111
difficult to comprehend otherness by a general category of beings like essence or
nature. Therefore, Zizioulas claims that we cannot regard and treat all ‘others’ as
absolutely and truly Other from the perspective of ethics. In other words, we can
only understand others as absolutely and truly others ‘in Christ’ or ontologically.
freedom and ‘to be the other’. All communion must make otherness a primary and
constitutive ingredient; it makes the other free, not only having the ‘freedom of
will’, but also having the freedom to be the other: “Otherness is necessary for
freedom to exist: if there is no absolute, ontological otherness between God and the
presupposition for the other to be other. The Father as personal cause generates
otherness, namely, God is the source of all otherness. Zizioulas analyzes two facets
of otherness.
(a) The human being is defined through otherness. Human being’s identity
emerges only in relation to other beings: God and the rest of creation. Freedom is
the presupposition: a human being is distinguished from the animals by his or her
otherness with respect to God, animals and other human beings. At the social level,
classes or qualities of any kind lack ontological otherness. The human being who
301
Ibid., 19.
112
(b) The drive of the human being towards otherness is rooted in the divine call to
Adam. The call simultaneously implies three things: relationship, freedom, and
otherness. First, through the call, a relationship has been constituted: Adam as a
human being other than God and the rest of creation in freedom. Through the
granted and is not self-existent, but a particularity which is a gift of the Other.”302
Second, the call means that God is the ground for the existence of human. If there is
no God, there is no man, and there is no freedom for the human being to be the
ultimate other: “Freedom without God would lose its ontological character; it
the subject of the call. His idea can be distinguished from the ontology of
relationship, i.e., the human being does not spring automatically from just any
relationship. Instead, otherness is a unique gift which comes from the Other or God.
Finally, the identity of a human being is constantly formed through the response to
this call of the Other. Because of the human free will, Zizioulas emphasizes that “as
long as there is freedom there is history: the ‘yes’ and ‘no’ to the call, which defines
humanity and makes the human being an historical being…To this call, Adam in his
freedom answered with a ‘no’. It was Christ who fulfilled it, thus revealing and
4.1.3 Otherness beyond the conflict between the particular/person and the
general/nature
302
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 41.
303
Ibid., 42.
304
Ibid., 43.
113
In the thought of the Greek Fathers, hypostasis or person signifies the particular,
while nature or ousia expresses the common or general. For Zizioulas, the
individual ceases to exist after death, but nature or ousia of human beings does not
disappear. There seems to be a conflict between the particular and the general. Of
course, the conflict mentioned here does not mean a formal logical contradiction,
There are two areas in which the ontological level of human existence manifests
itself in a decisive and uncontrollable way: the way a human being is established as
a particular through biological birth, and the way it ceases to be a particular after
death. Both of these facts are ontological and not merely psychological, since they
are constitutive of a particular human being and totally uncontrollable by our minds
or feelings. Both of them involve a conflict between the particular and the general,
This kind of conflict only exists in the created realm. In the case of the human
being, nature precedes the person, whereas in God the two coincide fully. Human
beings are born as a result of pre-existing natural laws, common to all humans. So
the general being in this case is ontologically prior to the particular. In God the
divine persons exist not as a result of given natural laws. Three persons and one
substance exist simultaneously as one and many. So there cannot be any conflict
Zizioulas affirms that the conflict is ontological and not merely psychological.
suffers this conflict. Zizioulas criticizes that ever since Augustine the Western mind
has tended to treat the conflict between nature and person as a psychological
305
Ibid., 56.
114
matter instead.
Zizioulas emphasizes that the conflict can only be resolved in the body because
the body is ontologically constitutive of the human being and so essential for his
identity and particularity. Because the body is absolutely important for a human
conceive human identity without the body. He affirms the Creeds which include the
most important article of the Resurrection of Christ from the very beginning (1
Corinthians 15). The creeds emphasize the resurrection of the ‘flesh’ or the ‘body’
of Christ, and not simply his ‘death’ for our sin. For the human being, the resolution
of the conflict cannot be found outside the body itself. For example, some people
resort to the immortality of the soul, a kind of escape from the body, but this
amounts to the loss of the human being itself. For Zizioulas, the conflict between
event in the person of Christ and as the eschatological destiny for all humanity”.306
the being of the Church: “By being the body of Christ, the Church exists as the
guarantees the ontological truth, the eternal survival…of every being we regard as
unique and indispensable, for he is the only one in whom death, which threatens the
particular with extinction, is overcome.” 307 Since the being of Church is ‘the
306
Ibid., 62.
307
Ibid., 75-76.
115
hypostasization of all particular beings in the unique hypostasis of Christ’, the
Church in every respect serves this purpose. “The Church is the place where God’s
love as the love of a particular and ontologically unique being is freely offered to
his creation in the person of Christ, so that every particular human being may freely
in the Eucharist that the love of God is offered to humanity as the unique hypostasis
in which all human beings can freely obtain otherness and uniqueness. The two
only way for a particular being ontologically to be truly Other is to be born again,
this time not from nature but from the Spirit…What Baptism initiates, therefore, the
same time, there is an ontological relationship between the Church and the world
when Zizioulas understands of the Church through the Euchrist. He argues this
issue in his book The Eucharistic Communion and the World.310 He develops a
issues is the ontology of personhood. Given space limitations, this article can’t fully
explore ecclesiology.
308
Ibid., 79.
309
Ibid., 80.
310
John Zizioulas, The Eucharistic Communion and the World, ed. Luke Ben Tallon (London: T & T
Clark, 2011).
116
Pneumatology, 311 Zizioulas affirms Spirit as the force of hypostasization. “The
Christ will not end up in an absorption of the many into the one, in the loss of
otherness.”312
communion [is] formed within the current of eucharistic theology that connected
knowledge is not a knowledge of the essence or the nature of things, but of how they
are connected within the communion-event.”315 Communion and otherness are not
contrary, communion and otherness are supposed to permeate and pervade our
lives in their entirety. They are to become an attitude, an ethos, rather than an ethic
and a set of principles.”316 Zizioulas applies the ascetic life, say, of the desert
otherness.
The desert Fathers provide an ontological ground for our attitude to the Other.
They insist that the Other should be kept free from moral judgment and
than one entity. By being a person, the Other is by definition unique and therefore
unclassifiable. Only in this way can one remain truly and absolutely, that is,
ontologically, Other.” 317 Zizioulas emphasizes that this kind of attitude of the
ascetic Fathers is not concerned with the inner psychological experience of the
individual. Its ground is relational and ontological: “one is truly oneself in so far as
one is hypostasized in the Other while emptying oneself so that the Other may be
‘it is no longer I who live, but Christ who lives in me.’”318 (Galatians 2.20) For the
This ‘condemnation of the Self’ is the foundation for a positive attitude to the
Other. However, how can desert Fathers deal with evil, which apparently exists in
other people? In this situation, evil is not ignored or overlooked, but is passed from
the Other to the Self. Zizioulas writes: “The stories of such empathy with the
Other’s sin which are retained in the lives of the desert Fathers are indeed striking
and moving. One of the brothers does penance for the other’s sins, as if he had
committed them himself…The personal cost in such cases is very high but it is paid
317
Ibid., 82.
318
Ibid., 85.
319
Ibid., 82-83.
320
Ibid., 82, see footnote 183.
118
issue: Does the ascetic ethos violate truth, when it transfers the evil of the other to
one’s innocent self? Zizioulas gives a twofold answer to this question. First, the
3.13), so that we could become the righteousness of God (II Corinthians 5.21). For
the desert Fathers, the ground of their activity is the Christology of kenosis:
“Behind the ethos of self-condemnation for the sake of the Other lies the
Christology of kenosis.”321 They develop the theology of ascetic kenosis: the entire
giving over of the I to the other and receiving of the other in his or her fullness.
having primacy over the Self.322 Their purpose is not to develop their subjectivity
human beings as either good or evil; the ascetic ethos presented above proceeds
with the assumption that all human beings participate in the fall and are sinful. For
example, Jesus declared the accusers of the adulterous woman incompetent to pass
judgment on her: ‘let him who is without sin among you be the first to throw a stone
at her’ (John 8.7). According to the ethical principles, the Other is so identified with
qualities. When someone commits adultery or murder, we tend to say that he or she
is an adulterer or a murderer. But God in Christ forgives our sin by removing them
(Acts 3. 19; Romans 4. 7-8, 11, 27; etc.). Christ can remove our sin by bearing our
sins in his body on the tree, i.e., he dies and rises for us. This means that evil cannot
be identified with the evil-doer. Ascetic life which bears the evil of the other
321
Ibid., 83.
322
Ibid., 84.
119
Furthermore, this does not mean forgiveness is a merely psychological matter—a
means. 323 Even when it is said that God no longer ‘remembers’ our sins, the
meaning is not psychological but ontological, since whatever God does not
‘remember’ ceases to exist (Hebrews 10.4). Thus, the Christian ethos of otherness
does not allow for the acceptance or the rejection of the Other on the basis of his or
her qualities, natural or moral, but on the simple basis of each person’s ontological
Incarnation, which for him is the mystery of love. Both the negative aspect of
ascetic life, that is the uprooting of self-love, and its positive goal, which consists in
the attainment of virtues and theosis, involve the priority of the Other over the
Self.” 324 This kind of view of communion suggests that otherness implies
the encouragement of immoralities, but means that the worth of human life cannot
be assessed only from the moral perspective. In this way, it preserves one’s personal
While I think the metaphysical principle concerning the priority of the Other over
the Self is insightful, it may not be sufficient for a full understanding of the concept
323
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 86.
324
Ibid., 84.
325
Ibid., 82.
120
4.3 Transformation of the relationship with the Other
As I discuss above, Zizioulas’ understanding of communion with the Other is
operated under a metaphysical principle of the Other as having primacy over the
Self. The Other may be hypostasized in oneself and hypostasization constitutes the
In the last chapter, I criticize the individualist concept of person in the Western
been framed as the question of the self rather than the question of the other. The
other has been ignored. From a perspective of epistemology, the Other has to be
reduced to something for the self to recognize. Since Descartes discovers the cogito,
the external world and other people have always been a source of philosophical
difficulty. It is because the philosophers find that it is not easy to explain how I can
really be certain of the existence of the external world and other minds. The Other
has been brought under the domination and subjugation of the I.326
The ignoring of the Other is also affected by the moralizing of philosophy, which
is heavily criticized by Nietzsche. He blames that since Plato, philosophy has been
decisive role.327 The moral ‘good’ is the highest idea which is also a metaphysical
category:
This means that moral judgments are torn from their conditionality, in which they have grown
326
Bo-Myung Seo, A Critique of Western Theological Anthropology: Understanding Human Beings
in a Third World Context (Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press, 2005), 88.
327
Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Random House,
1968), 222.
121
and alone possess any meaning, from their Greek and Greek-political ground and soil, to be
denaturalized under the pretense of sublimation. The great concepts “good” and “just” are
severed from the presuppositions to which they belong and, as liberated “ideas,” become
objects of dialectic. One looks for truth in them, on takes them for entities or signs of entities:
one invents a world where they are at home, where they originate—In summa: the mischief has
already reached its climax in Plato—And then one had need to invent the abstractly perfect
man as well: good, just, wise, a dialectician.328
Since morality (or the social instinct mentioned by Nietzsche below) is largely a
social thing, this leads to a serious consequence: the individual existence has been
overlooked. Friedrich Nietzsche condemns that every individual was sacrificed and
served as a tool: “As the social instinct resting on the valuation that the single
individual is of little account, but all individuals together are of very great account
conscience…My idea: goals are lacking and these must be individuals’! We observe
how things are everywhere…Go into the street and you encounter lots of ‘slaves’.”
329
To use Levinas’ words, it is to reduce the Other into something of the Same:
“Western philosophy has most often been an ontology: a reduction of the other to
the same by interposition of a middle and neutral term that ensures the
history, the priority of the self over the other is the dominant belief. “When
epistemology became dependent on each other. This led ancient Greek philosophy
328
Ibid., 234-235.
329
Ibid., 154.
330
Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso Lingis
(London: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1979), 43.
122
ontology.”331
Rosenzweig reflects on the problem of German Idealism, and he claims that the
emphasis on essence can be traced from the philosophy of Thales to Hegel: they try
the relationship between men directly. As said by Levinas: “If it claims to integrate
myself and the other within an impersonal spirit this alleged integration is cruelty
and injustice, that is, ignores the other. History as a relationship between men
ignores a position of the I before the other in which the other remains transcendent
with respect to me.”333 This amounts to stripping the Other of his or her otherness or
humanity. Professor Seo points out: “The idea that to be human is to be a subject is
modern Western thought as a whole a history of thinking about the I.”334 While I do
not entirely deny the significance of this “modern achievement,” I also need to
point out that the consequence of this “achievement” is often the impersonal
often afraid of the others and continuously defends himself against the
society are largely functional. Every person is basically identified with his function
in the society, e.g., being a doctor, a teacher, etc. Such relations are not relations of
persons as persons, but only as workers. They are relations of the functions which
331
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 43.
332
Franz Rosenzweg, His Life and Thought, ed. Nahum Glatzer (New York: Schocken Books, 1961),
179-231.
333
Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, 52.
334
Bo-Myung Seo, A Critique of Western Theological Anthropology: Understanding Human Beings
in a Third World Context (Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press, 2005), 82.
123
different persons perform in the cooperative association. The bonds of relation
between individuals which constitute them are impersonal. Each isolated individual
uses all his capacity to secure his own satisfaction and to preserve his own life.
However, these egocentric individuals are still rational beings in terms of the
instrumental reason.
atomic units, inherently isolated or unrelated, and ideally equal. The units are
dynamic; they are units of energy. There is nothing in them to hold them together.
They are united in a whole by an external force which counteracts the tendency of
Professor Seo thinks that the notions of subjectivity have been bound up not only
with the way of thinking about the subject but also with the global project of
subjection such as the West’s project of colonial expansion and domination in the
modern period. This kind of project has been heavily criticized by liberation
theology, which thinks that we need to listen to the voices of the poor and the
and systemic poverty. This means that the understanding of human being conceived
as self and subjectivity should be changed. Min agrees with Gutierrez’s search for
335
John Macmurray, Person in Relation, 137.
124
the ‘creation of a new man’ and says that the self is “not the isolated and
Christian faith and the task of theology to interpret that tradition in view of the
central crisis of the time.”337 According to these criteria, many modern theological
anthropologies are inadequate because they tend to be asocial and ahistorical and
transcendence.338
consciousness and its internal distinctions. Thus, it does not essentially involve an
ontological relationship with others: “The journey of the soul toward God is a
journey inward. The process by which the soul comes to the deepest knowledge of
itself and of its God is introspection and self-reflection. This makes the social,
Because nature is the principle of personhood, Western theology did not develop an
relationship with others is also subsumed under general truths. Yannaras criticizes
clearly: “If we relate the image of God to nature and not to the personal
336
Anselm Min, Dialectic of Salvation: Issues in Theology of Liberation (Albany: SUNY Press,
1989), 93.
337
Ibid., 165.
338
See Bo-Myung Seo, A Critique of Western Theological Anthropology: Understanding Human
Beings in a Third World Context (Lewiston: The Edwin Mellen Press, 2005), 51.
339
Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 247.
340
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality, 26.
125
exacerbated by our tendency to regard truth as objective propositions, something
impersonal.
It can be traced back to Plato’s axiological idealism which identifies being with
the ‘idea of the Good.’341 According to Yannaras, the approaches and systematic
influence the rationalistic synthesis of Roman Catholic scholasticism and the whole
of Western thought. The standard of good or virtue is based on the rules of logic or
has laid the foundation for the rationalism and subjectivist ethics of modern
European culture. But it lacks the truth of the personhood and leads to some misery:
When the truth of the person is undervalued or ignored in the realm of theology, this inevitably
results in the creation of a legalistic, external system of ethics…When intellectual and
conventional categories replace ontological truth and revelation in Christian theology, then in
the historical life of the Church, too, the problem of salvation is obscured by a shadow that
torments mankind, that of a ‘law’ which leads to nowhere.342
relationship with others. Moreover, both Catholic and Protestant churches claim
that they have the ‘right to evangelize’. Sometimes evangelism degenerates into the
‘war for souls,’ both in a metaphorical sense and a literal sense. As a result,
standards become extreme or absolutized, it may even lead to cruel actions in the
341
See, for example, Plato, Republic 7:517 bc.
342
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality, 26-27.
343
Elizabeth H. Prodromou, “International Religious Freedom and the Challenge of Proselytism”, in
Aristotle Papanikolaou and Elizabeth H. Prodromou eds., Thinking through Faith: New Perspective
from Orthodox Christian Scholars (New York: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2008), 271-272.
126
name of the “Good,” such as the famous Donatists, 344 the Crusades, 345 the
persecution of the Anabaptists,346 or even the United States’ attacking Iraq (even if
resulted in negative effects for the image and reputation of the Church, which is
now not infrequently regarded as the enemy of human rights and the pluralistic
society. These events also sow seeds of hostility between different religions and
points out: “Christianity faces a direct challenge in its contribution toward new
existence. As I have described in chapter three (section 3.3.3.), the Eucharist means
with all human persons and other creatures. It transcends the ontological necessity
or biological limitation and treats the other as authentic person and lets the other
free.
344
In 3th century, the Donatists were rigorists, holding that the church must be a church of ‘saints’,
not ‘sinners’, and that sacraments, such as baptism, administered by traditores were invalid. See
http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Donatism
345
In 1096-1291, the Crusades were a series of religious expeditionary wars blessed by the Pope and
the Catholic Church, with the stated goal of restoring Christian access to the holy places in and near
Jerusalem. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Crusades
346
In the 1520’s and 1530’s the Anabaptists were radical, violent revolutionaries in the name of love,
equality and spirituality; and the Reformers persecuted the Anabaptists. See
http://www.frontline.org.za/articles/were_anabaptists_persecuted_for%20_faith.htm
347
On 20 Mar 2003, The United States launched a thundering bomb and missile attack on Baghdad.
This started an all-out war to drive Saddam Hussein from power and disarm Iraq.
348
Elizabeth H. Prodromou, “International Religious Freedom and the Challenge of Proselytism”, in
Aristotle Papanikolaou and Elizabeth H. Prodromou eds., Thinking through Faith: New Perspective
from Orthodox Christian Scholars (New York: St Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2008), 269.
127
sanctification: “God’s purpose in doing everything that He did in the Old Testament
is ultimately our sanctification. His purpose when He ‘sent forth his Son, made of a
woman, made under the law’ (Galatians 4:4) was still our sanctification. When
Christ went to the death of the cross, the object was our perfection, as it was in the
giving of the Holy Spirit. Indeed, everything God has done about us and our
salvation has as its end and object our sanctification.”349 In contrast with the West,
Christos Yannaras explains the emphasis in Orthodox tradition: “Man was created
to become a partaker in the personal mode of existence which is the life of God—to
the concept of sanctification in the sense of ethics. As Charles Hodge says: “All men
instinctively judge a man for what he is. If he is good they so regard him. If he is bad,
judge ourselves, and on which men universally judge each other.”351 A relationship
with the living God is often ignored. A personal relationship with other persons
may be lacking too. Christos Yannaras claims: “When the truth of the person is
underrated or ignored in the realm of theology, this inevitably leads to the creation
of a legal, external ethic. Man’s ethos or morality ceases to relate to the truth of the
person, to the dynamic event of true life and its existential realization.”352 Ethics
alone cannot manifest a relationship with the living God. Only by moving away
from legalistic norms can we encounter the living God. As Grec Ogden writes:
“Starved for an internal reality, the Christian life moved away from being defined in
349
Martyn Lloyd-Jones, God the Holy Spirit (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 2003), 200.
350
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality (New York, St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1984),
19.
351
Charles Hodge, Systemtic Theology, Vol. III, 190.
352
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality, 153.
128
terms of the ethical norms that the institutional church represented and toward an
encounter with the living Christ.”353 The Bible teaches us to live according to the
Holy Spirit, (Romans 8. 4) The Spirit reveals the Lordship of Christ to Christians.
“For to this end Christ died and lived again, so that he might be Lord of both the
When we are not satisfied with the other’s differences, we can have two kinds of
attitude. First, we should receive a sinner in Christ and pray for him or her, and give
a chance for him or her to repent. Second, we will not forgive until the sinner
personal relationship with others, we need to separate the action of sin from the
sinner. The distinction is clear in the Bible: “Let love be genuine; hate what is evil,
hold fast to what is good…bless those who persecute you; bless and do not curse
them.” (Romans 12. 9; 14) If someone does not separate the love for sinner and the
hatred of sin, it is impossible to speak of seeing the sinner from the perspective of
God, and to promote a relationship of love through the work of the Holy Spirit.
353
Greg Ogden, The New Reformation: Returning the Ministry to the People of God (Michigan:
Zondervan Publishing House, 1990), 18.
354
See Westminster Confession of Faith with Scripture Proofs 15:6. It is a Reformed confession of
faith, in the Calvinist theological tradition.
355
See Christos Yannaras, Orthodoxy and the West, 208-209 and passim.
129
The classical example in the Bible is “a sinful woman forgiven” in the Gospel of
Luke. When the sinful woman weeps, and anoints Jesus with the ointment, the
Pharisee who had invited Jesus judges the woman in his heart: “If this man were a
prophet, he would have known who and what kind of woman this is who is touching
him—that she is a sinner.”(Luke 7. 39) Jesus says to him: “Therefore, I tell you, her
sins, which were many, have been forgiven; hence she has shown great love. But
the one to whom little is forgiven, loves little.” (Luke 7. 47) In this scene, we can
see two kinds of attitude to the woman. For the Pharisee, his standard of the moral
law hinders him from seeing the woman from the perspective of God. He cannot
the sinful woman, and treat the sinner from the sight of Jesus.
relationship. It will change the mode of existence of the isolated individual when
ourselves when we accept that our origin, existence and destiny belong not to
ourselves but to God… We were created for the purpose of glorifying God by means
community. Society originates from the family. The family is a basic community in
which the habit of cooperation is learned. The personal life in the family will
beyond its boundaries will change the relationship of the isolated individuals: from
which maintains the society is the personal life rather than the morals or law.
356
John Macmurray, Person in Relation, 347.
130
It does not mean that we need to abolish law or morality. What is required is a
existence.”357 Its implication is that personal life is our ultimate purpose, and our
salvation of God is to restore our communion with God and other people. We live in
relationship with others. LaCugna understands the arche of God as personal life.
She articulates precisely the relationship between ontology and ethics: “From the
God is not the enemy of mutuality, equality, and a nonhierarchical social order, but
its only sure foundation!”358 In other words, a personal life, properly understood,
far from being the enemy of morality, can in fact provide the foundation for
morality.
Zizioulas takes Martin Buber and Emmanuel Levinas as examples of this departure
For Buber, the other and I have equal primordiality: “The I exists only through
the relationship with the Thou.”359 The dialogical situation “is not to be grasped on
357
Christos Yannaras, Persons and Eros, trans. Norman Russell (Massachusetts: Holy Cross
Orthodox Press, 2007), 285.
358
Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 399.
359
See M. Buber, ‘What is Man?’ in Between Man and Man, trans. R.G. Smith (London: Collins,
1954), 205.
131
the basis of the ontic of personal existence, or of that of two personal existences, but
of that which has its being between them and transcends both.”360 Buber claims that
“‘Between’ is not an auxiliary construction, but the real place and bearer of what
ultimate ontological category.362 Furthermore, the I-Thou and I-It relationship have
been decided by an attitude either of the I-Thou or of the I-It kind.363 This implicitly
makes the Other depend on the intention of the I, who can turn it either into an
I-Thou or into an I-It relationship. Zizioulas believes that I does not exist because of
‘the relationship with the Thou’, but because of the ‘Thou’. Therefore, Zizioulas
queries Buber: “in the final analysis, does this not imply recognition of the primacy
of the I over the Other?” 364 It means that for Zizioulas, Buber’s notion of
personhood still cannot provide an ontological ground for otherness in contrast with
than any other philosophers: “For Levinas, the Other is not constituted by the Self
(Husserl, etc.), nor by relationality as such (Buber), but rather is absolute alterity,
than itself.” 365 It affirms the constitutive character of the Other in ontology.366
360
Ibid., 204.
361
Ibid., 203.
362
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 47.
363
M. Buber, I and Thou, trans. Walter Kaufmann (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1970), 53-54.
364
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 47.
365
Ibid., 48.
366
Ibid., 48.
132
367
the Holy Trinity.
communion. But he does not give a more detailed analysis. I will try to integrate
Levinas criticizes the ‘I’ prior to the other in Western traditional philosophy. He
builds his philosophy on the starting point of the other: “Since the Other looks at me,
I am responsible for him, without even having taken on responsibility in his regard;
priority of the other person over being, or essence. The other constitutes a
the face. The face signifies the Infinite.”369 The desire for the invisible is called the
metaphysical desire. For Levinas, the metaphysical desire tends toward the
absolutely other. The absolutely other “is understood as the alterity of the Other
Desire.”370
Not only desire for the alterity or otherness of the Other is emphasized, but also
subjectivity amounts to sameness. When I meet the face of the other in the Infinite,
367
Ibid., 49.
368
Emmanuel Levinas, Ethics and Infinity, trans. Richard A. Cohen (Pittsburgh: Duquesne
University Press, 1982), 96.
369
Ibid., 105.
370
Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority (London: Martinus Nijhoff
Publishers, 1979), 35.
133
a being for myself has been suspended. This means that the Other is prior to me or
the Other has priority over my consciousness. As Pierre Hayat puts in his preface to
Alterity and Transcendence: “The face of the other is the locus of transcendence in
that it calls into question the ‘I’ in its existence as a being for itself.”371 Therefore,
the identity of I has been reformed when I meet others: “The I is not a being that
always remains the same, but is the being whose existing consists in identifying
itself, in recovering its identity throughout all that happens to it. It is the primal
has been terminated through the idea of the Infinite and otherness, because the
metaphysical desire for the Infinite or the other is beyond the capacity of the ‘I’ as
only starting from an I, will be terminated with the surpassing of the subjective.”374
Levinas calls the relation with the Infinite metaphysical. He thinks it is prior to
the no nor the yes is the first word. The description of this relation is the central
issue of the present research.”376 This kind of relation is not the relation which is
formed through the idea of sameness. Levinas regards the relation with the Infinite
as ‘a relation without relation’: “For the relation between the being here below and
371
Emmanuel Levinas, Alterity and Transcendence, trans. Michael B. Smith (London: the Athlone
press, 1999), Xiv.
372
Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, 36.
373
Ibid., 51.
374
Ibid., 51.
375
Ibid., 42.
376
Ibid., 42.
134
relation without relation—we reserve the term religion.”377
The relationship between the Other and ‘I’ cannot be resolved into a higher unity.
alterity, the radical heterogeneity of the other, is possible, only if the Other is other
with respect to a term whose essence is to remain at the point of departure…A term
can remain absolutely at the point of departure of relationship only as I”.378 The
purpose of separation is the breach of totality: “Thus the metaphysician and the
Firstly, the being of the Other is not constituted by relation: “It is necessary that a
being, though it is a part of a whole, derive its being from itself and not from its
frontiers (not from its definition), exist independently, depend neither on relations
that designate its place within Being nor on the recognition that the Other would
bring it.”380
Again the concern is the breach of the totality: “The breach of the totality that is
radical.”381
Life is love of life, a relation with contents that are not my being but more dear than my being:
thinking, eating, sleeping, reading, working, warming oneself in the sun. Distinct from my
substance but constituting it, these contents make up the worth of my life…The reality of life is
already on the level of happiness, and in this sense beyond ontology…happiness is
accomplishment.382
Levinas criticizes both Western philosophy and religion: “Religion subtends this
377
Ibid., 80.
378
Ibid., 36.
379
Ibid., 35.
380
Ibid., 61.
381
Ibid., 119.
382
Ibid., 112-113.
383
Ibid., 81.
135
vision, metaphysics precedes ontology.384 Therefore, for Levinas, the metaphysical
propositions. For Levinas, ontology reduces the other to sameness.385 It means that
transcendence are the themes of his book Totality and Infinity. Only separation
reason seems to be that Levinas wants to reject the kind of communion which
However, Zizioulas does not clearly distinguish two kinds of communion when he
otherness by the same and the general, and a subjection of otherness to unity. But
not all communions will threaten otherness. We can distinguish two kinds of
communion and two kinds of eros in order to reconstruct the concept of otherness in
384
Ibid., 43.
385
Ibid., 42.
386
Ibid., 48.
387
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 70.
136
can be found in nature itself, as the ancient Greeks and modern romanticism have
inherent energies. This kind of eros does not stem from the Other and is not
ultimately destined to the Other. However, there is another kind of eros. Zizioulas
not simply ecstatic but also and above all hypostatic: it must be caused by the free
particular being.”388
Zizioulas contrasts these two kinds of eros in Platonism and in the patristic
constitutive ontological factor, because love is attracted irresistibly by the good and
the beautiful which are ideas. Thus the concrete particular is used as a means to an
end, and finally sacrificed for the sake of the idea. This means that though the erotic
movement appears to be related to one particular being, this being is not unique in
ekstasis, is constantly intensified and does not stop until the loving one “has
become entire in the whole of the beloved one and is embraced by the whole,
eros is described here as a free movement from a free being to another free being.
‘circumscription’, the two beings still retain their ontological integrity. This
movement is driven by a purpose different from a natural one: “The cause and the
ultimate purpose of the erotic movement in this case is nothing else (e.g., nature,
ideal, or even the relationship of love itself) than the concrete Other, in whom the
388
Ibid., 71.
389
See John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 72.
137
erotic movement stops and rests.”390
These two kinds of eros are naturally connected to two kinds of love. The
emphasize that the uniquely loved being is a hypostasis or person rather than an
idea. Therefore, Zizioulas says: “Christ is the unique Other, the one in and through
whom all other beings are loved, not in a psychological but an ontological sense,
since it is in him that everything exists (Colossians 1. 16) and acquires its
particular identity.”392
390
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 72.
391
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 277-278.
392
Ibid., 75.
138
his ally because his personalism should be helpful for overcoming the totality of
(a) Christ does not simply stand vis-à-vis each man, but constitutes the ontological
ground of every man. This means that Christ does not represent an individualized
anthropology if it only offered Christ as the victim for the sins of humanity in a
substitutionary manner. Atonement understood in this way would not really affect
the human person’s being ontologically. Such a Christology may answer man’s
needs for forgiveness (in a legal sense) but does not really touch man’s being. The
key for anthropology is the ‘de-individualized’ Christ and man: “In order that
restored.”394
Spirit is not simply an assistant to the individual in reaching Christ, but he is also
participating in Christ.
offered outside the anthropology of personhood. According to the Bible, the Son is
393
Roger Burggraeve ed., The Awakening to the Other: A Provocative Dialogue with Emmanuel
Levinas (Leuven; Dudley, MA: Peeters, 2008), 142.
394
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 244.
139
the unique hypostasis of the Father (Hebrews 1.3). This uniquely loved being is a
hypostasis which hypostasizes other beings. It does not exclude other particular
beings, and in fact it establishes their otherness in and through communion. It gives
them an identity, a hypostasis of their own. The Son of God is the true Other who
doctrine of the Trinity gives us some revelation concerning our existence. The
Cappadocians locate the real distinctiveness of Father, Son, and Spirit in terms of its
will be built on the ground of totality and crystallized into a system. Therefore, the
individual is not apprehended in its otherness but in its generality. The relation with
the other is accomplished only through some ideas which an I learns from the Bible.
personhood, it means that the ultimate reality is personhood rather than substance.
This is a departure from Greek cosmology, making a personal God who is love and
freedom, rather than some impersonal principles, the Ultimate. Only this new
ontology could save theology from the control of classical Greek philosophy.
According to the Cappadocians, God the Father is the cause of everything and
God the Father is the source of otherness. In terms of the personal originating
principle, God the Father begets the Son and brings forth the Spirit and ultimately
also the world. Every particular exists in communion with others. “Since a person
140
is defined by relation of origin, the divine persons are never thought of as separate
expression and concrete existence of God. It is different from the unity of the divine
Because Levinas’ theory does not depend on the Trinitarian God, but on one
Infinite, it is difficult for him to integrate the notions of communion with otherness.
395
Cathrine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 246.
396
Ibid.
397
See Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, 47.
141
Part III
Ontology of Personhood
142
Chapter Five
the Father or the ousia of three persons. The developmental directions are different
West. The Catholic approach begins with the unity of the divine nature and then
attempts to explain the reality of the three persons. The Greek take the reverse route.
They begin with the three persons, emphatically with the person of the Father, and
benchmark and source for those who followed. Rahner criticizes this typical
Western approach to the doctrine of God in his work, the Trinity, and he proposes a
return to the Greek patristic and biblical identification of God’s being with the
Father rather than the divine ousia.399 The Western idea of God causes at least three
personhood:
the first is the separation of the oikonomia and theologia in the doctrine of God;
opinion on the first question without much discussion,400 and he talks of the third
398
Philip A Rolnick, Person, Grace, and God (Michigan/Cambridge: William B. Eerdmans
Publishing Company, 2007), 36.
399
Karl Rahner, The Trinity (London: Burns & Oates), 58.
400
Zizioulas focuses on the issue of Filioque. When he mentions the relation between ‘ecomonic’
and ‘immanet’, it is a critique of the view of Rahner (the economic Trinity is the same as the
immanent Trinity). He does not discuss the separation of the oikonomia and theologia in the doctrine
143
question in some fragments of his books. This chapter will attempt to evaluate these
through the general concept of the divine substance: una substantia, tres personae,
i.e., one divine substance is constituted as three individual divine persons; the three
persons are different from one another, but they are one in their common divine
substance. For Tertullian, God is from all eternity One, but not alone. Because
Tertullian, like many others, never succeeds in defining his concept of being, it is
Augustine who gave the Western tradition its mature form.401 Thus we will start
the doctrine of God, for him the ontological principle of God is the one divine
important for him to bring up again the theological ontology of the Cappadocians.
In this section we will focus on the major Latin Christian thinkers who contribute to
For Augustine (354-430), God is by his essence pure actuality of being and
of God in Western theology. See John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 201-202.
401
Eric Osborn, Tertullian, First Theologian of the West (Cambridge; New York: Cambridge
University Press), 132-134.
402
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 40.
144
therefore cannot be conceived of as being with potency; he is above all simple and
analogies to the Trinity: the mind (mens), its knowing, and its love; later this gives
way in turn to memory, knowledge, and love of self (memoria sui, intelligentia sui,
voluntas sui).403 In Book 10, Augustine moves to an even higher image: memory,
understanding, and will (memoria sui, intelligentia sui, voluntas sui). In the
psychological triads, memory means more than recall, something more like one’s
perpetual sense of identity and presence to oneself; and self-knowledge is the key to
knowledge of God. Augustine writes, “When [the soul] seeks to know itself, it
already knows that it is seeking itself.”404 Memory, understanding, and will are not
three substances but one substance. And each faculty exhibits the characteristics
both of substance and of relation. He writes: “For not only is each [faculty]
comprehended by each one, but all are also comprehended by each one. For I
remember that I have memory, understanding and will; and I understand that I
understand, will and remember; and I will that I will, remember and understand;
and at the same time I remember my whole memory, understanding and will.”405
“something singular and individual” in contrast with the nature which is held
in common.406 Concerning the distinction of the three persons, Augustine did not
follow the conceptual revolution of the Cappadocians. The direct reason given by
Augustine is the problem of translation: “The Greeks also have another word,
403
See Augustine, The Trinity, trans. Edmund Hill, O.P., ed. John E. Rotelle (Brooklyn, N. Y.: New
City Press, 1991), IX, 4, 273.
404
Ibid., Augustine, The Trinity, X, 5, 291.
405
Augustine, The Trinity, X, 18, 298-299.
406
Augustine, The Trinity VII, 11, 229.
145
hypostasis, but they make a distinction that is rather obscure to me between ousia
and hypostasis, so that most of our people who treat of these matters in Greek are
accustomed to say mia ousia, treis hypostaseis.”407 For the problem is that ousia is
is not having a clear notion of ‘person’: “Yet when you ask ‘three what?’ human
speech labors under a great dearth of words. So we say three persons, not in order
Besides the linguistic usage, Gunton explains the other reason why Augustine
different kind of question from that asked by the Cappadocians: “not, what kind of
being is this, that God is to be found in the relations of Father, Son and Spirit? But,
what kind of sense can be made of the apparent logical oddity of the threeness of the
one God in terms of Aristotelian subject-predicate logic? The one God is the
substance, being single and unchanging. There is no problem there in terms of the
philosophical tradition.”410
relationality is located within the divine essence. As William Hill notes that “the
fullest implications of Augustine’s thought are that God is one ‘person’ within
and its internal differentiations. Therefore, God would in fact be one person rather
407
Augustine, The Trinity V. 10, 196.
408
Augustine, The Trinity VII. 9, 227.
409
Augustine, The Trinity V. 10, 196.
410
Colin E. Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian Theology, 40-41.
411
William Hill, The Three-Personed God: the Trinity as a Mystery of Salvation (Washington:
University Press of America, 1983), 61.
146
than three persons as propounded in the theology of the Cappadocians.
Boethius (480-525) was one of the most influential thinkers of the early medieval
the Trinity and the person of Jesus Christ. He interpreted the Augustinian tradition
Boethius tended to make greater use of speculation than did the early church
Fathers. This is because the medieval mind of the Latin West made little distinction
i.e., one essence or subsistence of the Godhead, but three hypostaseis, that is three
adopted person as a better term than substances, the concept of ‘person’ is almost
declares the predication of God is unique and requires important changes from our
normal way of putting things, his count in De Trinitate IV begins with a listing of
Aristotle’s categories and never gets too far beyond them.”415 Relation is a logical
concept in Boethius’ Trinitarian thought: “it is evident that these terms are relative,
412
See Roger E. Olson and Christopher A. Hall, The Trinity, 51.
413
See Philip A Rolnick, Person, Grace, and God (Michigan/Cambridge: William B. Eerdmans
Publishing Company, 2007), 42.
414
Ibid., 42.
415
Ibid., 43.
147
for the Father is someone’s Father, the Son is someone’s Son, the Spirit is someone’s
Spirit. Hence not even Trinity is predicated substantially of God.”416 It shows that
Boethius did not explicate the diversity of the three persons ontologically.
understood from the relation of person and nature through Christological debates:
“For one thing is clear, namely that nature is a substrate of person, and that person
second substances, Boethius sees primary substances, i.e., the particulars as persons.
regard to the doctrine of the Trinity, Aquinas followed Augustine which makes the
divine essence the starting point. Aquinas affirmed that God is a substance:
temporal thought. God is both intellect and love. An intellectual nature requires
some degree of multiplicity in the same way that love does. The intellectual love of
the Father produces the Son and the Holy Spirit. In Trinity, it is a movement from
416
Boethius, De trinitate, 37; see also Philip A Rolnick, Person, Grace, and God, 43.
417
Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium 83; see also Philip A Rolnick, Person, Grace, and God,
37.
418
See Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, The Doctrine of God: A Global Introduction (Michigan: Baker
Academic, 2007), 96.
148
In the book Summa Theologiae, Aquinas says that a divine person signifies a
relation as subsisting, that is, a hypostasis subsisting in the divine nature. 419
Concerning the relations of the persons to the divine substance, Thomas discusses
in Summa Theologiae I, 39-42. He thinks that pure ‘essence’ is the form of the
persons. According to the form rendering a thing what it is, the persons are decided
divine nature itself, therefore it is something subsisting just as the divine nature is.
Consequently just as Godhead is God, so God’s Fatherhood is God the Father who
That is, as substance which is a hypostasis subsisting in the divine nature, though
what is subsisting in the divine nature is nothing other than the divine nature.”420
proper to particular things or substances. 422 This question which concerns the
concept of personhood.
419
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I. Q. 29, a, 4.
420
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae. Ia.29. 4
421
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I, Q. 29, a.1.
422
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I, Q. 29, a. 1, a.3.
149
essence and person, I will analyze the consequences caused by the Western
approach to Trinity
person. Theologia in the general sense is the doctrine of God considered in Godself.
Oikonomia is used for the action of God in the world in the doctrine of the
or design.423 In New Testament, the word has at least two kinds of meaning. Firstly,
it means a steward (oikonomos) of God. For example, Paul calls himself a servant
of Christ and steward of God (1 Corinthians 4. 1); the bishop is called God’s
1.7) Secondly, it is used to mean the plan of salvation, or how God administers
God’s plan. In Eph. 1:9-10 economy refers to the mystery of God’s benevolent
will or plan of salvation hidden from all eternity: “With all wisdom and insight
God has made known to us the mystery of his will, according to his good pleasure
that he set forth in Christ, as a plan (oikonomia) for the fullness of time, to gather
up all things in Christ, things in heaven and things on earth.” (Ephesians 1.9-10)
The term oikonomia was used broadly in the early church. According to the book
God for Us, there are three basic meanings. Firstly, oikonomia means God’s
423
Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us: The Trinity and Christian Life (San Francisco: Harper
San Francisco, 1991), 24.
150
providential plan, dispensation, or ordering of the cosmos. Secondly, by the end of
priority of theologia over oikonomia or nature over person: “The basic difference
between Greek and Latin theology is often said to be that Greek theology
emphasizes person over nature, Trinity over unity, whereas Latin theology
emphasizes nature over person, unity over Trinity.”425 It will lead to some serious
issues such as its irrelevance for the practice of faith. Zizioulas seldom raises this
theologians who separate the immanent Trinity from the economic Trinity.
First of all, Augustine’s approach leads to the breach between oikonomia and
which follows logically from the starting point in the divine unity instead of the
economy of salvation, tends to blur any real distinctions among the divine persons
and thereby formalizes in Latin theology the breach between oikonomia and
theologia.”426
Along with the separation of theologia and oikonomia, Augustine influences the
relations of God in se, with scarce concerning God’s acts in salvation history. After
424
Ibid., 25-26.
425
Ibid., 96-97.
426
Ibid., 99.
151
Augustine, in the period of scholasticism, ontological relationships among Father,
Son, and Holy Spirit would be viewed independently of the Incarnation and sending
of the Spirit.”427 Karl Rahner criticizes Aquinas and scholasticism in general for
developing a doctrine of the Trinity which excludes the activity of the persons in the
During the sixteenth century some new reflections on the Trinity begun by
Luther and Zwingli created the freedom to challenge Christian traditions. The
anti-Trinitarian movements from Spain and Italy and other parts of Europe
salvation, sacraments and the Trinity. One of the reasons is its irrelevance to the
practice of faith. Martin Luther and John Calvin reoriented theology toward the
5.2.2 Divergence between East and West in dealing with oikonomia and
theologia
between oikonomia and theologia. The Cappadocians connects oikonomia with the
427
Ibid., 81.
428
Karl Rahner, The Trinity (London: Burns & Oates, 1986), 16-17.
429
Cf. Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 144.
152
human nature of Christ,430 while theologia is connected with His divine nature.
Because the doctrine of God could not be separated from salvation history or
economy, the Cappadocians use the concept of person (hypostasis) to express the
being of God. The concept of person can unite two natures. This is a ground for the
Christology of Chalcedon (451 A.D.): the union of two natures took place in the
person of Christ. The person is the ultimate identity. God exists eternally as Father,
Son, Spirit, and this eternal life is what is given in the redemption. The
Christian doctrine of God. For the Cappadocians, ‘Theology’ is not limited on the
divine ousia exists hypostatically and there is no ousia apart from the hypostasis. It
ontology of personhood.
Zizioulas expresses the relation between theologia and oikonomia in the light of
430
Basil, C. Eun. II, 3 (29, 577A); see also Catherine, God for Us, 39.
431
Gregory Nazianzus, Theological Orations, 29. 18.
153
the Cappadocian view: they stressed more than any of the ancient Fathers the
Why Western theology takes a way which is different from that of East? The
the analysis of human consciousness as the method for understanding the Trinity. It
is different from Eastern Greek theology which affirms the ontological distinction
of three persons. Today, a renaissance of the doctrine of the Trinity is taking place.
and immanent Trinity: “The ‘economic’ Trinity is the ‘immanent’ Trinity and the
Augustine or Thomas Aquinas, Rahner takes the economy of salvation as the only
valid starting point for knowledge of God. Rahner develops a model of personal
God as the theological starting point: “We say: ‘of God,’ and we do not presuppose
thereby a ‘Latin’ theology of the Trinity (as contrasted with the Greek one), but the
biblical theology of the Trinity (hence, in a sense, the Greek one). Here God is the
Similarly, Zizioulas puts forward the question: is the economic Trinity the same
432
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 202.
433
Karl Rahner, The Trinity, 22.
434
Ibid., 83-84.
154
as the immanent Trinity? He regards that most Western theologians in our time call
for a positive answer, e.g., K. Barth, J. Moltmann and K. Rahner, but Zizioulas
The doctrine of the Holy Spirit has been one of the thorniest problems in
There are two traditions, Eastern and Western, to understand the relationship
between the Holy Spirit and the Father: “the idea of the monarchy of the Father is
the sole ‘principle’ in God’s Trinitarian being promoted by the Greek Fathers, and
St. Augustine expresses that the Holy Spirit proceeds from the Father ‘principaliter’
the Second Ecumenical Council states that the Holy Spirit proceeds ‘from the
Father’, without additions of any kind, such as ‘and the Son’ or ‘alone’: “Καὶ εἰς τὸ
in the Holy Spirit, the Lord, the giver of life, from the Father proceeding”).
Filioque [‘And (from) the Son’] means that the Latin text now in use in the
Western Church speaks of the Holy Spirit as proceeding ‘from the Father and the
early as the 8th century. It was accepted by the popes only in 1014, and is rejected
435
Y. Congar, I Believe in the Holy Spirit (New York: Seabury Press; London: G. Chapman, 1983) III,
16; see also John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 201.
436
John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 41-42.
155
by the Eastern Church. The Filioque has been an ongoing source of conflict
between the East and the West, contributing in part to the East-West Schism of
accordance with the theology of the Constantinople Council (A.D.381) on the Holy
Spirit. Zizioulas points out what he regards as the main issues lying behind the
Filioque problem. He further discusses this problem in his book The One and the
Many according to the document of the Pontifical Council for the Promotion of
For Zizioulas, the problem of the Filioque involves the view of God: “the real
issue behind the Filioque concerns the question whether the ultimate ontological
category in theology is the person or substance.”438 Zizioulas asserts that the reason
of the Western interpretation lies in the assumption that the ontological principle of
God or the unity of God is not founded on the person but on the divine substance.
Zizioulas, “Among the Greek Fathers the unity of God, the one God, and the
ontological ‘principle’ or ‘cause’ of the being and life of God does not consist in the
one substance of God but in the hypostasis, that is, the person of the Father.”439 If
the ultimate ontological category is not the hypostasis of the Father alone, then if
two hypostases are ultimate ontological categories at the same time this would
result in two gods. The Father is the only cause of the generation of the Son and the
procession of the Spirit. From this view, the East opposes the Filioque which has
been insisted by the West because the West identifies the ontological principle of
God with His substance rather than the person of the Father.
437
See https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Filioque
438
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 196.
439
John Zizioulas, Being As Communion, 40.
156
5.2.4 Zizioulas’ reiteration of the Cappadocian notion of the Son’s mediation
There are some efforts for theologians to solve the question of Filioque.
Zizioulas cites the view of Y. Congar: “the Western interpretation of the Filioque,
based on the theology of St Augustine, does not necessarily reject or exclude the
thesis that the Father is the only cause of divine existence in the holy Trinity.”440
But for Zizioulas, the issue of Filioque cannot be resolved by the term
necessarily preclude making the Son a kind of secondary cause in the ontological
does not necessarily preclude making the Son a kind of secondary cause in the
ontological emergence of the Spirit, for the Filioque means two sources of the
Spirit’s personal existence. The Father may be called the first and original cause
‘principle’. “The term ‘cause’, when applied to the Father, indicates a free, willing,
and personal agent, whereas the language of ‘source’ or ‘principle’ can convey a
more ‘natural’ and thus impersonal imagery. This point acquires crucial
significance in the case of the Filioque issue.” 442 Zizioulas evaluates that the
Cappadocian idea of ‘cause’ was almost absent in Latin theological tradition, and
this for him is the reason which leads to the problem of Filioque.
St. Gregory of Nyssa admits a ‘mediate’ role of the Son in the procession of the
Spirit from the Father. Zizioulas concludes: “The notion of ‘cause’ seems to be of
440
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 197.
441
John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 42.
442
Ibid., 42.
157
special significance and importance in the Greek patristic argument concerning the
Filioque. If Roman Catholic theology would be ready to admit that the Son in no
way constitutes a ‘cause’ in the procession of the Spirit, this would bring the two
traditions much closer to each other with regard to the Filioque.”443 It is done with
the help of the preposition δια (through) and the phrase ‘through the Son’ as St.
Zizioulas regards that the Filioque at the level of the economy of God presents no
difficulty to Eastern Orthodox theology, but the projection of this into the immanent
Trinity creates great difficulties. Besides the understanding that the economy
cannot be identified with immanent Trinity, the other reason for Zizioulas is that the
doctrine of Holy Spirit should be formulated in the light of the theology of the
III. The Holy Spirit is worshipped and glorified together with the Father and
the Son.
These theses are to indicate that Holy Spirit has the same divinity with the Father
and the Son. Zizioulas argues that the pneumatological doctrine of Constantinople
is clear in these respects, and the Filioque is obviously an addition to the original
Creed.
Zizioulas argues that patristic sources show that the Son in some sense ‘mediates’
in the procession of the Spirit. Zizioulas emphasizes that the ‘mediation’ could not
be understood as another ‘cause’ in divine existence. That the Father remains the
only cause is the philosophical and theological presuppositions with which the
443
Ibid., 43.
158
Cappadocians operate in theology, and they influence the Fathers of Constantinople
precisely: “between the Alexandrian (cyrillian) tendency to involve the role of the
tendency to limit the role of the Son in the coming into being of the Spirit to the
Economy, Gregory of Nyssa’s position seems to strike a middle road which does
introduces the notion of ‘cause’ which he clearly reserves to the Father alone and
put the Son and the Spirit on equal footing. Unlike Cyril, Gregory does not take the
ousianic or ‘natural’ relation of the Spirit to God as one of the relationship with the
Alexandrians and the Antichochenes, has not been fully appropriated by the West.
Zizioulas analyzes the possible historical reasons at this point. “These may have to
do with the fact that the Council of Constantinople in 381 was exclusively an
Eastern council, with no participation from the Western Church, although it was
fact that Augustine’s theology dominated the West soon after the Cappadocians.”445
Cappadocian theology will lead to the following conclusion: the phrase ek tou
Patros,
(a) does not exclude a mediating role of the Son in the procession of the Spirit,
(b) does not allow for the Son to acquire the role of aition by being a mediator, and
(c) does not allow any detachment of divine ousia from the Father (or from the other persons of
444
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 193.
445
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 124, see footnote, 39.
159
the Trinity): when we refer to ousia we do not refer in any way to something conceivable
Through this conclusion, Zizioulas excludes any attempt to define the content of
this mediation of the Son by making him some kind of secondary cause or by
distinguishing between personal and ousianic levels of operation, for these are not
Overall speaking, there are four kinds of expression about the procession of the
Spirit:
(b) Father and Son both are the same causes on ousianic level.
indispensable existential truth, namely, the ontological ultimacy of the person of the
Father. So he definitely rejects (a) and (b). However, for him, we can accept (d)
instead of (c) in order to recognize the element of truth in the Filioque phrase.
ontologically in God
Ever since Tertullian, the Christian Trinity has always been depicted through the
general concept of the divine substance: una substantia-tres personae, i.e., one
divine substance is constituted as three individual divine persons; the three persons
are different from one another, but they are one in their common divine substance.
For Augustine and Thomas Aquinas this one, common, divine substance is counted
446
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 194-195.
447
Ibid., 195.
160
as the foundation of the Trinitarian persons, and this substance was ontologically
and logically primary in the formulation. Eastern theology criticizes this view for
making essence or substance of God into a fourth category prior to the threeness of
the Trinity. Furthermore, the psychological model for the Trinity is located ‘inside
the head of the one individual, in the structures of the mind’s intellectual love of
itself’.448 It influences theological anthropology directly, for the imago Dei has also
been located in the human intellect and reason and this leads to an individualistic
forced him into a rather static concept of deity, on the one hand, and an
Since Aquinas, the article of faith on God has been shared in the treatise De Deo
uno and the treatise De Deo trino. This two-fold division means that there is a God
and that God is one, only after that comes the Trinity.
Trinitarian theology involves in its basic structure the problem of the relation between unity and
diversity in the form of the ontological relation between the One and the Many. The faith in
‘one’ God who is at the same time ‘three,’ i.e. ‘many,’ implies that unity and diversity coincide
in God’s very being. The question whether unity precedes diversity logically or ontologically in
God is of crucial importance. Medieval theology succumbed to the logic of essentialism or
substantialism, which inherited from classical Greek thought, and gave priority in dogmatics to
the chapter ‘De Deo uno’, which received precedence over that of ‘De Deo Trino.’ God,
logically speaking, is first ‘one’ and then ‘many.’ This theological monism is the equivalent to
448
Colin Gunton, Promise of Trinitarian Theology, 94; see also Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian
Theology: West and East, 120.
449
C. B. Kaiser, The Doctrine of God: An Historical Survey (London: Crossway Books, 1982), 81;
see also Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 120.
161
the philosophical monism that characterized ancient Greek thought from the Pre-Socratics to
Neoplatonism.450
In Barth’s theology, God is the subject of his own being and his own revelation.
Barth emphasizes one personal God to replace a static concept of God in traditional
still the same as the substantialist approach. As Collins comments: “Thus, while
Barth is rooted in the tradition of the West, he makes significant moves towards the
the particular (hypostasis) in the same way as the Eastern tradition does.” 451
of the human soul or mind, there is an alternative social analogy of the Trinity too.
The representative is Richard of St Victor, Hugh’s student, who shared his teacher’s
approach to emphasize the distinctive works in the Trinity in the eleventh century.
book De Trinitate, he argues that the doctrine of the Trinity could not possibly be
the perfect love between persons. His precondition is that “perfect love is always
directed toward what is distinct from and in some sense outside the self. Self-love is
imperfect love. God’s love must be perfect and not in any way dependent upon the
cited by Collins in his book. For example, O’Donnell affirms that “Richard
450
John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 336.
451
Ibid., 227.
452
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, The Doctrine of God: A Global Introduction (Michigan: Bbaker
Academic, 2007), 98.
453
Ibid., 98
162
preserves the Boethian accent upon substantiality but he complements this idea
the doctrine of the Trinity.”455 Moltmann argues that one’s existence is understood
in the light of another, and this ‘another’ can be explained on two levels: the divine
nature and the other persons: “it is true that in the first place he related this other to
the divine nature. But it can be related to the other Persons too”;456 Collins argues
that Richard’s theology is founded on a social model of the Trinity, but Richard’s
It is not easy to understand Richard’s idea because his book On the Trinity has
never been fully translated into modern English. There are different views about the
began with the persons of the Father, Son, and Spirit and with human persons in
community.”458 But William Hill concludes that Richard’s On the Trinity “begins
with God in the oneness of his nature, but stresses love as the most distinctive and
identifying trait of that nature.”459 Anyway, Richard’s idea of sociality in God has
In the nineteenth century, the social analogy of the Trinity was used by those who
454
O’Donnell, The Mystery of the Triune God (New York: Paulist Press, 1989), 101; See also Paul M.
Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 138.
455
T. F. Torrance, Theological Science (Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1996), 306.
456
Jürgen Moltmann, Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 173.
457
Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 138.
458
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, The Doctrine of God, 98
459
William, J. Hill, The Three-Personed God, 78.
460
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, The Doctrine of God, 99.
461
For an exposition of Hartshorne’s understanding see C. E. Gunton, Becoming and Being: The
Doctrine of God in Charles Hartshorne and Karl Barth (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978),
163
dependence upon the concept of the Absolute Subject of Hegelian thought does not
necessarily sustain the psychological model like Augustine does. Rahner describes
But questions arise in relation to the social analogy too, especially because there
Collins comments that those who have worked with either model had sought to
relate consciousness to both the threeness and the oneness of the Godhead, with
Though Barth and Rahner realized that the psychological model had not expressed
the revealed knowledge of the Godhead, yet as Collins criticizes: “In their
terminology for threefoldness and in their concept of the deity as Subject, both have
in chapter six.
its heirs today, the unity of God lies in the divine substance or the absolute subject
shared by the three persons. Then persons and relations have been formulated in
terms of the attributes such as oneness and simplicity. One God is a divine
substance or the absolute subject. This approach gives priority to ‘unity’ over
75-76.
462
J. Bracken, The Triune Symbol: Persons, Process, and Community (Lanham: University Press of
America, 1985), 48-57.
463
See Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 152-154.
464
Rahner, The Trinity, 106; see also Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 154.
465
Rahner, The Trinity, 117.
466
Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 154.
467
Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 155-156.
164
‘diversity’.468 The key reason is that the concept of otherness is not regarded as an
theology, the person never played the role of an ultimate ontological category, due
to the tendency to place the person of the Father under the ontological priority of
ontological primacy to the person would mean to undo the fundamental principles
with which Greek philosophy had operated since its inception, (i.e., One).”471 Let
Firstly, ‘One God’ is God the Father rather than one substance, “that is, of the
Nazianzus rejects Plato’s notion which speaks of God as a crater: this crater
necessary generation of existence. Gregory departs from the Athanasian idea of the
‘fertile substance of God’ too. He does not see the generation of the Son or the
spiration of the Spirit in such terms as a way of substantial growth. He insists with
the rest of the Cappadocians that the Father is the cause of divine existence and the
468
Cf. Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 248.
469
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 198
470
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 36.
471
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 164.
472
Ibid., 162.
165
three-personed God create the world jointly. Thus, ‘One God’ is not understood in a
Platonic or Aristotelian sense. The one arche (origin or cause) in God came to be
the cause of divine being, generation and spiration are not necessary but free.
God the Father is the ‘willing one’,473 the only cause of divine existence.
state is to be found in God, i.e., the ‘One’ and the ‘Many’ exist simultaneously in
God. The premise is that the person has to be given ontological primacy in
philosophy.474 God in Trinity involves simultaneously the ‘One’ and the ‘Many’.
Neoplatonism tended to give priority to the ‘One’ over the ‘Many’. For example, in
Plato’s Eternal Ideas, all reality is one, with finite beings as manifestations of the
absolute One. The particular person never has an ontological role. Neoplatonism
had identified the ‘One’ with God himself. One emanates Many of a degrading
nature, so that the return to the ‘One’ through the recollection of the soul was
thought to be the purpose and aim of all existence. Philo links classical Platonism
and Neoplatonism and argues that God is the only ‘One’ because he is the only One
who is truly ‘alone’. The Cappadocians explain that the priority of nature over
person, or of the ‘One’ over the ‘Many’ is due to the fact that human existence is a
different existence from that of God, and the way of human existence should not
Thirdly, the Cappadocians “gave to the person ontological priority, and thus
freed existence from the logical necessity of substance.”475 Zizioulas regards that
473
Gregory Naz., Theol. Or. 3.5-7.
474
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 163-164.
475
Ibid., 165.
166
there is an ontological necessity in Greek worldview:
This ontological monism which characterizes Greek philosophy from its inception leads Greek
thought to the concept of the cosmos, that is, of the harmonious relationship of existent things
among themselves. Not even God can escape from this ontological unity and stand freely
before the world, ‘face to face’ in dialogue with it. He too is bound by ontological necessity to
the world and the world to him, either through the creation of Plato’ Timaeus or through the
476
Logos of the Stocis or throuth the ‘emanations’ of Plotinus’ Enneads.
The personal ontology traces the world back to an ontology outside the world,
that is, a personal God who transcends the necessity of Greek cosmology and
substantialism. Zizioulas asserts that the Cappadocians reversed the Greek ways of
philosophy in which the particular was not secondary to being or nature. Thus the
Lastly, the particular person never has an ontological identity in classical Greek
thought: “What mattered ultimately was the unity or totality of being of which man
ontology of personhood, I have discussed them in Chapter three and will discuss its
476
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 29-30.
477
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 164.
167
Chapter Six
Because nature or ousia express the general, personhood usually signifies the
substantialist approach which keeps substance at the forefoot. This kind of view of
personhood. (2) Criticism from the perspective of the ontology of personhood. (3)
shortly after his conversion to Christianity: The Catholic and Manichaean Ways of
Life (composed between 388-390). In his response to the question ‘what is man?’
Augustine stresses that soul and body are essential components of human nature
and emphasizes the superiority of the soul over the body. In one of his initial
sharing in reason, fitted to rule the body.” 478 His Christian anthropology is
478
Augustine, De Quantitate Animae 13, 22. Cf. Joseph Torchia, O.P., Exploring Personhood: An
Introduction to the Philosophy of Human Nature (New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.,
2008), 115, 109-110.
168
developed within the Neoplatonic framework. Human nature presupposes a
“harmonious union” of the inner man of the spirit and the outer man of the flesh.
Augustine focuses on the mind or intellect, the highest part of our rational nature, as
The mature Augustine introduces the term persona into his anthropological
lexicon. He sees that the composite unity of soul and body constitutes not only the
human being but an individual person in his or her own right. It underscores a
transition from talking about the general (what we all share in common) to a
Augustine finds the image of the triune God in the human person. His use of the
knowing and living was fundamentally based on the biblical understanding of the
human person as created in the image of God (Genesis 1:26). As we have stated in
the model for the Trinity. This influences not only the doctrine of the Trinity, but
consciousness that has now become one of the central features of our contemporary
479
See Joseph Torchia, O.P., Exploring Personhood: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Human
Nature (New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc., 2008), 113.
480
Augustine, The Trinity, trans. Edmund Hill, O.P. (Brooklyn, N. Y.: New City Press, 1991), VII. 11,
229.
481
Gunton, Promise of Trinitarian Theology, 102; see also Augustine, The Trinity, XIV. 15, 383.
169
notion of person. In many ways, to ask about human personhood is to ask himself:
“I became for myself a great question.”482 Thus, Augustine utilizes the method of
only the particular substances can qualify as persons: “person cannot anywhere be
individuals are single persons named.”483 Thus, the concept of person focuses on
the individual reality. Boethius’ definition of person is: “The individual substance
distinguishes humans, God, and angel from all other sorts of individual substance.
Therefore, the concept of person has been applied to man, God and angel, but we do
not predicate person of a stone, tree, or horse. This definition has been formed in his
Firstly, for Boethius, substance is prior to person. “For one thing is clear, namely
that nature is a substrate of person, and that person cannot be predicated apart
482
Augustine, Confessions, trans. Henry Chadwick (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991), IV. Iv.
9, 115.
483
Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium, 85; cf. Philip Rolnich, Person, Grace, and God, 38.
484
Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium, 85; cf. Philip Rolnich, Person, Grace, and God, 39.
170
from nature.”485 Indeed, person is properly predicated of substance: “Since person
cannot exist apart from nature and since natures are either substances or accidents
and we see that person cannot consist in accidents, it therefore remains that person
Secondly, the definition of the human person depends upon our understanding of
the person of Christ. For Boethius, an analogy is present between human persons
the existence of two persons in Christ, Boethius insists that the reality of Christ is
the reality of the union, i.e., the person unifies. In human persons, the union
Like Augustine, Aquinas refines the concept of human personhood in the course
of theological discussion on the Trinity and the person of Jesus. As Joseph Torchia
Theologica does not emerge in his Treatise on Human Nature. Rather, it unfolds in
the course of his treatment of the Trinity and his analysis of the relations between
the Persons of the Trinity.”488 For Aquinas, personhood means a unique individual.
what is distinct in that nature: thus in human nature it signifies this flesh, these
bones, and this soul, which are the individuating principles of a man, and which,
485
Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium 83; cf. Philip Rolnich, Person, Grace, and God. 37.
486
Boethius, Contra Eutychen et Nestorium 83; cf. Philip Rolnich, Person, Grace, and God. 38.
487
See Philip Rolnick, Person, Grace, and God, 41.
488
Joseph Torchia, Exploring Personhood: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Human Nature
(New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc. 2008), 140.
171
of a particular human person.”489
of individualized substance with the definition of the person. The term individual is
of this form has the nature of …person. For soul, flesh, and bone belong to the
nature of man; whereas this soul, this flesh, and this bone belong to the nature of
this man.”491 The subsistent reality is the primary sense of the human substance.
the formal principle of the soul and the material substrate of the body. It
the ultimate perfection of a given thing. In this respect, Aquinas moves beyond the
Plato and Aristotle for Aquinas regards existent reality as a dynamic act.
For Aquinas, the human person is a dynamic being that actualizes the potentiality
for certain operations unique to his or her own existence. The person has an
intrinsic value and dignity because the person participates in a hierarchy of being in
which God provides the first cause and final end of everything which exists.
Persons possess a status by virtue of their relation to God as creatures in his image
and likeness. The difference between persons and other creatures is that persons are
able to internalize reality through their intellect and even grasp something of the
489
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica Ia, Q. 29, a. 4.
490
Ibid., Ia, Q. 29, a. 3.
491
Aquinas, Summa Theologica Ia, Q. 29, a. 2, ad.3.
172
infinite majesty of God.
Aquinas stresses the hypostatic union of God and man in Christ. The union is
neither located in the divine or human nature, nor in some accidental attribute of the
sometimes in terms of our individual uniqueness, and at other times in terms of our
terms of its metaphysical foundation. For Aquinas, the body is the individual
principle of a man, and the human soul is the primary metaphysical principle of the
individualist concept.
Zizioulas criticizes the Western view of person with regard to three aspects. I try to
communion
492
Ibid., IIIa, Q. 2, a. 6.
173
tradition. He writes:
With the help of a cross-fertilization between the Boethian and the Augustinian approaches to
man, our Western philosophy and culture have formed a concept of man out of a combination
of two basic components: rational individuality on the one hand and psychological experience
and consciousness on the other. It was on the basis of this combination that Western thought
arrived at the conception of the person as an individual and a personality, that is, a unit
endowed with intellectual, psychological and moral qualities centred on the axis of
consciousness.493
ancient Greeks did not operate in anthropology with the notion of subject, that is, of
the self as thinking its own thoughts and as being conscious of itself and
preoccupied with its own ‘intentions’.”495 Zizioulas claims that the introspective
way in Augustinian tradition has affected the Western mind and modern Orthodox
through the confusion between ontology and psychology in our ordinary way of
understanding and discourse of selfhood, and the human being is ultimately only an
493
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 211.
494
Socrates’ work is an important beginning of the individualistic legacy. Socrates’ individual self-
independence from the community in which he lived set an important precedent for the way in
which a person could conceive of himself or herself as a separate and distinct being. But his
individualism was defined in terms of social roles. Modern philosophy has in fact developed a
concept of the individual that is far more solitary than that created by Socrates and the Antiquity.
The philosopher who first formulated the idea of this solitary self was Rene Descartes (1596-1650).
He has become known as ‘the father of modern philosophy’. See website:
http://faculty.frostburg.edu/phil/forum/Descartes.htm (KKM: but you have already discussed
Descartes before. Sometime the order of your discussions can be more systematic & logical thought
the problem here is not very great.)
495
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 46.
174
communion.496
way of thinking. The human person is generally defined by the ability to think of
incommunicable. The person and mind continues to be identified with each other in
Stanley J. Grenz also regards the idea of ‘self’ as a modern invention and agrees
that it can be traced back to Augustine: “The trajectory that gave rise to the modern
self begins with Augustine. Building from the Greek dictum ‘Know thyself,’
Augustine transposed the focus of the search for self to the realm within.” 497
Augustine’s emphasis on the inward journey, the quest for self-knowledge, also led
to the concept of the self as the stable, abiding reality that constitutes the individual
human being.
From the book of Augustine, we can find that he defines ‘person’ in terms of
‘consciousness’ or ‘mind’: “Any single man, who is not called the image of God
in terms of everything that belongs to his nature but only in terms of his mind is
one person and is the image of the Trinity in his mind. But that Trinity he is the
image of is nothing but wholly and simple Trinity…three persons of one being,
not like any single man, just one person.”498 There is the problem of an improper
496
Ibid., 46.
497
Stanley J. Grenz, ‘The Social God and the Relational Self’, in Richard Lints, Michael S. Horton
and Mark R. Talbot ed., Personal Identity in Theological Perspective (Cambridge: William B.
Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2006), 71-72.
498
Augustine, The Trinity XV, 11, 403.
175
notes that Augustine “did not accept the opportunity of making an analogy
relationships of human persons.” 499 Conversely, the model for the Trinity is
It produces huge influences on the whole Western philosophy and society: the
understanding of personhood. It tends towards a view of the divine persons and the
the old ontological paradigm into a new subject-centered perspective lies at the core
Descartes, the real person is to be identified with thought, and therefore with ‘mind’.
499
A. C. Lloyd, “On Augustine’s Concept of a Person,” in Augustine: A Collection of Critical Essays,
ed. R. A. Markus (Garden City, N. Y.: Anchor Books, 1972), 204.
500
Colin Gunton, The Promise of Trinitarian Theology (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1997), 95.
176
between personhood and subjectivity. Because the noumenal realm can never be the
Because of the analogy of being, this conception has been applied to God. In the
understood as the Absolute Subject in theology. For example, Barth affirms that
God is subject only, never object.502 God is known through an Event, i.e., the event
subject (God reveals), the content (God reveals himself), and the very happening
God is one divine Person with three modes of existing. Barth understands person
in the modern terms of self-consciousness and freedom and he fails to deal with the
Son and the Spirit as persons in the Trinity. Therefore, there exists only one Person
and one subjectivity in Barth’s Trinitarain theology, and Moltmann criticizes that
Barth’s theology is in fact rooted in the idealist tradition of the single self-conscious
501
For example, see Immanuel Kant, Critique of Pure Reason (1781); Critique of Practical Reason
(1788); Critique of Judgment (1790).
502
Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics, II/2, 438.
503
Ibid., 339.
504
Ibid., 413.
505
Paul M. Collins, Trinitarian Theology: West and East, 223.
177
divine subject.506 Gunton claims that Barth’s usage of tropos hyparxeos keeps him
enclosed in the Western tradition of the Trinity and personhood, rather than setting
Similarly, Rahner regards that it is difficult for us to use the modern meaning of
person to understand the Trinity as three divine persons because this would suggest
movement have their common basis the concept of consciousness, on which they
found the concept of the person. Boston’s personalist Brightman defines person as
“a complex unity of consciousness, which identifies itself with its past self in
Overall speaking, it seems correct for Zizioulas to criticize Augustine’s and other
framed as the question of the self rather than the question of the other. This
undesirable consequences in our culture. I will discuss this issue in the next chapter.
506
Moltmann, Trinity and the Kingdom of God, 140.
507
Gunton, The One, the Three and the Many, 191.
508
Karl Rahner, The Trinity, 107.
509
E. S. Brightman, “Personalism,” in V Perm ed., A History of Philosophical Systems, (New York:
The Philosophical Library, 1950), 340.
178
6.2.2 Relationship between God and human as an impersonal union
Confessions.
Zizioulas distinguishes two kinds of relationship between God and man. The
relationship between God and man can be expressed by two kinds of presence: the
presence of the personal and the presence of a-personal beings. The purpose of the
situation: “The first indication that this presence is not a matter of psychology but of
something far more fundamental and primordial is to be found in the fact that it
does not rest upon conscious reflection but precedes it.” 510 The presence of
perception. Zizioulas asserts that if we use this kind of model to understand the
relationship between God and man, the relationship would become an a-personal
reality.
Christos Yannaras explains these two kinds of relation even more clearly.
In other words, the Church does not identify the truth of being with God as an objective and
abstract first cause of existence and life: God is not a vague supreme being, an impersonal
essence which may be approached only through the intellect or the emotions. Nor is He a
‘prime mover’… The God of whom the Church has experience is the God who reveals Himself
in history as personal existence, as distinctiveness and freedom. God is person, and He speaks
with man ‘face to face, as a man speaketh unto his friend’.511 (Exodus 33:11).
The priority of essence entails the priority of conceptual thought and therefore of the
individual intellect over experience. God is not recognized primarily as personal intervention in
history revealing the mode of divine existence, as personal experience of participation in this
mode…God becomes an object of individual understanding, which implies an abstract and
510
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 217.
511
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality, 16-17.
179
impersonal ‘supreme being’ unrelated to experience and history.512
Martin Buber also talks about two kinds of relationship: the I-Thou relationship
and the I-It relationship. The I-It relationship is constantly turning the Other into an
object. “The I of the basic word I-You is different from that of the basic word I-it.
The I of the basic word I-It appears as an ego and becomes consciousness of itself
as a subject (of experience and use). The I of the basic word I-You appears as a
person…Egos appear by setting themselves apart from other egos. Persons appear
appointment in a café with a friend whose existence matters to me. But when I
arrived there I cannot discover that this person is there. For me, the absent person
precisely by not being there occupies the entire space-time context of the café. It is
only after I reflect consciously on the situation that I know who ‘is’ and who ‘is not’
there. A distinction emerges between the presence of the personal and the presence
of a-personal beings. “Those who ‘are’ and those who ‘are not’ there are not
communion and freedom but by their own boundaries or through those imposed by
our own mind. Their presence is compelling for our minds and senses but not for
our freedom; they can be turned into things, they can lose their uniqueness and
of a-personal being would turn God into a natural object but this has nothing to do
with the living God of the Bible and the worshipping Church. The personal
512
Christos Yannaras, Orthodoxy and the West, trans. Peter Chamberas and Norman Russell
(Massachusetts: Holy Cross Orthodox Press, 2006), 34,
513
Martin Buber, I and Thou (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1970), 111-112.
514
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 217.
515
Daniel J. Price, Karl Barth’s Anthropology in Light of Modern Thought (Michigan: William B.
Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2002), 167.
180
A presence of a-personal beings appears to be based on the nature of things, that
is to say, to something one simply has to recognize according to its nature. For
example, according to Aquinas, the mind is conformed to God because it has God
as its object: “The divine image is noted in man according to the word conceived
from the knowledge about God and the love derived from thence.”516 In contrast, the
presence of personal beings is not established on the basis of a given ‘nature’ of the
being but of love and freedom: “in this case, ontology cannot ultimately take for
granted the being of any being; it cannot attribute the ultimacy of being to a
necessity inherent in the nature of a being; it can only attribute it to freedom and
love, which thus become ontological notions par excellence. Being in this case
owed its being to personhood and ultimately becomes identical with it.” 517
Zizioulas describes the presence of God in Eastern Church and theology by two
over of the I to the other, and the receiving of the other in his or her fullness. The
what it really is.”519 Theosis can be understood as the process whereby we become
516
Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae I. 93. 8c.
517
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 218-9.
518
W. Pannenberg, Basic Questions in Theology, vol. III, 1973, 112; see also John Zizioulas,
Communion and Otherness, 218, footnote 18.
519
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 243.
181
‘partakers in Divine nature’. “I say, ‘You are gods’” (Psalms 82:6). This phrase
from the Old Testament, quoted by our Lord Himself (John 10: 34), has deeply
exterior imitation of Christ through moral effort, but direct union with the living
God, the total transformation of the human person by divine grace and glory—what
words of St. Basil the Great, man is nothing less than a creature that has received
the order to become god.”520 The idea of theosis does not involve the absorption of
the creation by the divine nature, that is, the loss of its otherness. Christ as the locus
would cease to be totally other than the creation. Chalcedon safeguards divine and
human otherness by insisting that the two natures in Christ remained always
way.521
While the Lutheran confessions tend to be skeptical of the idea of theosis, the
Lutheran theologian Paul R. Hinlicky recognizes that they have in fact neglected
520
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, One with God: Salvation as Deification and Justification (Minnesota:
Liturgical Press, 2004), 17.
521
See John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 37.
522
Paul R. Hinlicky, “Theological Anthropology: Toward Integrating Theosis and Justificaiton by
182
6.2.3 The problem of man as a moral issue rather than ontological one
a moral issue (often with legalistic understanding as well). He expresses this point
legal understanding of man’s relationship with God: “Starting from such a concrete
and existential concept of sin, the Orthodox tradition has refused to confine the
whole of man’s relationship with God within a juridical, legal framework; it has
Although Zizioulas often criticizes the West for treating the problem of the
human person as a moral issue rather than an ontological one, he does not always
analyze the reasons clearly. From Zizioulas’ books, I can only find one major reason:
explained shortly). On the one hand, I will make use of the historical testimony i.e.,
defend Zizioulas’ opinion. On the other hand, I will criticize Zizioulas’ overly
God and creation is mainly construed in terms of ethics (because person is not an
substantialist ontology and identify being with substance to call God’s relationship
with the world ‘ontological’. Thus, in the West, the gap between God and creation
has been filled mainly not by ontology but by ethics or psychology: communion
between the Creator and creation has been conceived either in terms of obedience to
philosophy and points out that it undermines Incarnation, that is, the hypostatic
ontological and ethical understandings of doctrines. Sin as a moral issue is the most
basic issue for man. However, many doctrines have been explained from an ethical
that if one confesses his or her sins, then this particular list of sins will be
cancelled;528 the atonement means that the Lord Jesus Christ suffered the penalty of
525
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 20.
526
Ibid., 29.
527
Cf. David Martyn Lloyd-Jones, God the Father, God the Son (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books,
2003), 185.
528
Aristotle Papanikolaou and Elizabeth H. Prodromou eds., Thinking through Faith (New York: St
Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2008), 219. According to Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia,
confessionalization is a recent concept employed by reformation historians to describe the parallel
processes of ‘confession-building’ taking place in Europe between the peace of Augsburg (1555)
and the Thirty Years’ War (1618-1649). During this time prior to the Thirty Year’s War, there was a
nominal peace between the Protestant and Catholic confessions as both competed to establish their
faith more firmly with the population of their respective areas. This confession-building occurred
through ‘social-disciplining,’ as there was a stricter enforcement by the churches of their particular
184
the broken law vicariously, as the substitute for His people.529 In this way, salvation
becomes totally objective because this vacarious death can happen regardless of
inadequate to the images of rebirth, regeneration, creation of new man, etc. which
also constitute essential parts of atonement, and these all lie on the level of ontology,
that is, the transformation of human persons and their relationship with God and
In fact, although we cannot say that this is universally the case, it is arguable that
Roman Catholic moral theology and Protestant Christian ethics by and large have
manifested a tendency towards moralism. Moral theology is the name given by the
Roman Catholic tradition to the theological discipline that deals with Christian life
and action.530 An academic and systematic approach to moral theology began in the
teaching of Thomas Aquinas. Aquinas deals with the human response to God’ gift
and the moral life in the second Part of the Summa theologiae. But it is Alan of Lille
(d. 1202) rather than Aquinas who separates out a discipline called ‘moral
We can take moral theology in the United States as an example. Moral theology
was identified with what were called ‘manuals of moral theology’. The manuals of
moral theology owe their origin to the Council of Trent in sixteenth-century. The
rules for all aspects of life in both Protestant and Catholic areas. This had the consequence of
creating distinctive confessional identities. For example, the TULIP of Calvinism: Total Depravity;
Unconditional election; Limited or Definite Atonement; Irresistible of Grace; Perseverance of the
Saints.
See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Confessionalization
529
David Martyn Lloyd-Jones, God the Father, God the Son, 317.
530
Charles E. Curran, Catholic Moral Theology in the United States (Washington: Georgetown
University Press, 2008), xi.
531
Ibid., 1.
185
Council understood the sacrament of penance primarily in juridical terms. The
the legal model of the manuals, conscience is the subjective norm of morality,
whereas law constitutes the objective norm of morality.533 The approach of moral
theology in the United States in the period before the 1960s was based on natural
law. However, it can be seen that there are increasing dissatisfactions with the
model of natural law even within the Catholic tradition. For example, the
moral theology. It brought startling changes. Moral theology was no longer tied to
in this discipline. John Paul II emphasizes that truth is the ultimate foundation for
moral living and moral theology. In this period, some moral theology even turns to
give more emphasis on the person himself rather than the legalistic assessment of
his act. So the understanding of sin has also been changed, and some argue that this
signifies a return to a more Biblical understanding. After all, the concept of sin in
Genesis is more than just an act of disobedience because sin also involves a
532
Ibid., 2. In the same book, we can find some examples: Stephen Badin, an early missionary in
Kentucky, spent most of his days in these pastoral visits hearing confessions. (p.11) In the seminary,
the emphasis was on moral theology. Diocesan seminarians had more instruction in moral theology
than they had in dogmatic theology. (p.12) Aloysius Sabetti (1839-98), author of a manual of moral
theology, sees morality primarily in terms of obedience to law. (p.19)
533
Ibid., 181.
534
Ibid., 184.
186
relation to man is fundamentally to be understood in terms of command and obedience.535
metaphysical ground. For example, justification by faith may suggest that our
righteousness is built only upon the legal transaction between God and Christ:
Christ’s death has paid for us our debt to God, and hence we are deemed righteous
and justified. However, Matti Kärkkäinen reflects: “Yet in order for the
righteousness to be genuine, a new obedience is called for, not just a ‘legal fiction.’
But it is only through ‘the example of Christ and by his gracious gift of the Holy
Spirit [that] this achievement of righteousness has become a new possibility for
believers.”536
Greg Ogden criticizes that American Christian life after World War II had been
reduced to the ethical level: “A generation ago the Christian life was conceived of
the Church…Going to the church was as American as apple pie, since the church
provided the moral glue for the community and national spirit.”537 Will Herberg
describes that in the fifties (after World War II), to be an American meant to identify
with one of these religious traditions. In this period, going to church did not
generally mean that people are having a vital, living encounter with Christ. Even
church people may only have a kind of institutional faith. This kind of Christianity
535
Stanley Hauerwas, Character and the Christian Life: A Study in Theological Ethics (San Antonio:
Trinity University Press, 1984). 2.
536
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, One with God: Salvation as Deification and Justification (Minnesota:
Liturgical Press, 2004), 130. The citing in it belongs to Hinlicky, “Theological Anthropology,” 58.
537
Greg Ogden, The New Reformation (Michigan: Zondervan Publishing House, 1990), 17.
538
Ibid., 18.
187
6.3 Analysis of Zizioulas’ criticisms
We can analyze Zizioulas’ criticisms of Augustine with regard to three aspects,
and evaluate Zizioulas’ criticism of the problem of the world merely as a moral
distinction: “In the Greek idea, ecstasies, the toward-another, is primary; in the
not only a manifestation of the priority of the I; it is always at the same time
object.”540 We have to point out that in our cognition, turning the Other into an
object to some degree is almost inescapable, and this in itself cannot be regarded as
evil. The crucial matter is whether we ONLY treat the Other as an object. If so, this
would turn into an undesirable kind of I-it relationship. Even Buber himself does
corollary from the understanding of the human person as the image of God. In his
The Trinity, Augustine presents more than twenty triadic psychological analogies
539
Catherine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 287.
540
Greg Ogden, The New Reformation, 48.
188
for exploration. The purpose of exploring these analogies is to love God: “Now this
Trinity of the mind is God’s image, not because the mind remembers, understands
and loves itself; but because it has the power also to remember, understand and
love its Maker”541 In his Confessions, the whole person stands in relation to God as
in a contemplative union with their creator. Augustine does put some emphasis on a
personal relationship between the human person and God: “You stood me face to
face with myself,” he prays, “so that I might see how foul I was.” 542 All the
All in all, to know the truth, the mind needs to be enlightened ‘from outside
popular among Christian philosophers for most of the Middle Ages. For example,
541
Augustine, The Trinity, XIV, 15.
542
Augustine, Confessions VIII, 7.16; see also Joseph Torchia, Exploring Personhood: An
Introduction to the Philosophy of Human Nature (New York: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.,
2008) 115.
189
Albert the Great (c.1200–1280) and his student, Thomas Aquinas (c.1225–1274),
led to a belief that human beings might be able to achieve certain knowledge
despite the changeability of mind and matter. It was the Franciscan John Duns
Scotus, more than anyone else, who put an end to the theory of divine illumination.
means of cognition. Therefore, the discussion focuses on whether the human mind
Greek view of truth and it ignores the ontological level of the communion between
God and the human person. It falls into a complete abstractionism. I will criticize
not only a theory of cognition. At the same time, there is an ontological ground in
this kind of cognition: because God is a living God entering into relationship with
human persons, a human person can communicate with Him. In other words,
reflection of his meeting with a living God. Though Augustine does not define
person as a relational concept, in his whole faith, we can find an ontological ground
for this kind of relational understanding. It simply means that there is a gap between
Augustine’s definition of the term of ‘person’ and the full content of his faith
experience. As we have stated in part one, in The Trinity Augustine explores the
again to link person with substance: “But it is ridiculous that substance should be
190
reference to itself”.543
available terminology and concepts at that time rather than to his relationship with
God. Philip A. Rolnick comments: “Standing near the beginning of the great Greek
about how persona, which is being used to translate hypostasis, is not then
Augustine’s terms, Zizioulas concludes that this kind of relationship between God
and man is impersonal. In fact, in both Augustine’s theology and that of Aquinas,
there are personal relationship between God and man. In other words, this is a flaw
These may still have led to undesirable consequences, especially when these
concepts have been increasingly divorced from their original theological contexts
as the Western society becomes more and more secular. However, we can have a
other philosophers.
may have exaggerated his point when he alleges that the whole Catholic and
Protestant traditions have viewed the problem of the world merely as a moral
problem. For example, the views of ‘Original Sin’ and ‘total depravity’ are not
Augustine and Pelagius. There are two elements in Augustine’s doctrine of sin: the
543
Augustine, The Trinity VII. 9, 227.
544
Philip A. Rolnick, Person, Grace, and God (Michigan: William B Eerdmans Publishing
Company, 2007), 32.
191
metaphysical element in Augustine’s doctrine of sin arose from his controversy
with the Manicheans. Manes teaches that sin was a substance. Augustine defines
evil as the privation of good (which is identified with being), and metaphysically it
belongs not to the category of being, but to the category of nothingness. Thus,
although sin in some sense exists, we need not say that God is sin’s author (even if
God is the Creator of everything). The above controversy shows that theologians
In the early part of the fifth Century, Augustine formulates the doctrine of total
depravity when he protests against Pelagius’ views. Augustine strongly held that
fallen man was utterly incapable of any good works and was thus completely
dependent on the divine grace for salvation. The reason was that Augustine
believed that Original Sin was passed down the generations through the very act of
sexual intercourse. Original Sin made it impossible for humans to do good on their
own account, because it degraded both their moral capacity and their willpower.
Only through God’s grace could humans achieve salvation. Pelagius (probably A.
Augustine’s views on grace and determinism. Because he taught that man retained
natural goodness and emphasized free will, he denied original sin and affirmed
unhindered human free will. Again, these debates show that the understanding of
On the other hand, Zizioulas understands the concept of sin merely from a moral
He has also neglected the fact that many Western theologians have in fact realized
192
the problems of moralism and legalism, and have tried to correct it. For Catholic
theology through the doctrine of union with Christ. It presents a challenge to the old
The response from Reformed circles defending the doctrine of justification has,
generally speaking, followed two lines. One response has continued to place greater
emphasis on the priority of justification for the entire structure of salvation and
makes this legal dimension the basis for all other benefits of redemption. However,
the other response does assert the central role of union with Christ as the
In fact, Mannermaa School claims that Luther’s view of justification differs from
theology.548 However, for Luther himself, justification is not a forensic term but
545
Richard Gaffin, “Biblical Theology and the Westminster Standards.” WTJ65 (2003): 165-79. cf.
http://historiasalutis.com/2011/08/20/a-guide-to-recent-discussions-on-justification-and-sanctificat
ion
546
It comes from a site. Many books and articles which discuss ‘union with Christ’ have been
introduced on this website in recent years:
http://historiasalutis.com/2011/08/20/a-guide-to-recent-discussions-on-justification-and-sanctificat
ion
547
In Europe, since the 1970s a ‘new quest for Luther’s theology’ has emerged mainly at the
University of Helsinke, initiated by Tuomo mannermaa and his students. See Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen,
One with God: Salvation as Deification and Justification (Minnesota: Liturgical Press, 2004), 37.
548
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, One with God: Salvation as Deification and Justification (Minnesota:
193
rather a matter of Christ abiding in the heart of the believer in a ‘real-ontic’ way;
theosis (union with Christ) is one of the images Luther used to describe salvation.549
Since this school emphasizes Christ’s person, we can say that the emphasis on the
followers (the Lutherans) have largely forgotten this genuinely “Lutheran” truth.
When the Protestant tradition maintains the indispensability of the ‘union with
Christ’ now, it means that they emphasize an ontological dimension in the Christian
doctrines. It may become a bridge for the dialogues between Eastern theology and
Western theology. However, although Zizioulas may have exaggerated a bit in his
questions for the West: whether they have really sufficiently changed their largely
ontology of personhood
Zizioulas’ personal ontology provides a powerful criticism of substantialist
views of God and the human person. However, there are some flaws in Zizioulas’
personal ontology. For example, the most important concepts of ‘sin’, ‘justice’ or
‘righteousness’ are overlooked by Zizioulas. For Zizioulas, ‘sin’ and ‘justice’ are
ethical categories. Therefore, ‘sin’ has not been regarded as an important concept
Many theologians agree with the ontology of personhood without criticisms, and
others criticize Zizioulas but provide no further analysis. In this chapter, I will
analyze both the contribution and the flaw of Zizioulas’ ontology of personhood.
ontology; building up a personal knowledge for Christianity; the view that salvation
mainly involves that Zizioulas’ ontology of personhood ignores the concepts of sin
and justice. His ontology of personhood also does not have sufficient social
concern.
study
study theology. They tend to leave application in the hands of ministers and pastors.
ontological category which can run through theoretical theology and practical
According to “God is not alone and God exists in communion”,550 and the being of
God as the personhood of Father, Zizioulas reframes his Trinitarian theology which
that personal identity can not be found through nature because nature always points
550
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 166.
196
particularity. Zizioulas insists the ontology of personhood and gives Christian
doctrine a personal interpretation. From this starting point, it will change our
analysis.
experience of the living Church, rather than of intellectual perception or the logical
dogmas, not merely on exterior imitation of Christ’s moral effort, but direct union
with the living God, the total transformation of the human person by divine grace
substantialism. His efforts are to show that true knowledge is not a kind of
knowledge of the essence or the nature of things, but of how they are connected
551
The substantialist approach brings some objective knowledge of God and man. However, only a
personal approach helps us set up a personal knowledge. Zizioulas said that it would be wrong to
present dogmas as unconnected with the essence of our life. “Theology does not have the obligation
only to describe dogmas, presenting the form they took in the past. It also has a duty to interpret
them, so that it becomes apparent how and why our existence depends on them.” See John Zizioulas,
The One and the Many: Studies on God, Man, the Church, and the World Today, ed., Fr. Gregory
Edwards (California: Sebastian Press, 2010), 18.
552
The tendency to approach spirituality is not through the intellect or knowledge but through the
personal union.
553
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 3.
554
Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, One with God: Salvation as Deification and Justification, 46.
555
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 106.
197
introducing a new kind of epistemology. Since Zizioulas’ emphasis is on ontology,
The Greeks saw abstraction as an indispensable and valuable tool in the search for
knowledge. Thales concluded that water was the essence of everything. Therefore,
reached their worldview by abstract reasoning. Therefore, abstraction was the way
various things have something in common in their being. However, when we think
about ‘being-in general’, the features of individual things have been ignored.
Moreover, the rationalists’ chief concern is certainty. They believe that only if
Some theologians are not secular rationalists, and their starting point is the
revelation of the Bible. However, they have the same view of truth as that of the
often defined as ‘justified, true belief.’ For these theologians, the knowledge of God
also involves justified true belief which is grounded in God’s clear revelation of
himself in nature, man, and the Bible. This kind of knowledge always involves a
subject who knows an object according to some standard or criterion. It seems that
the rationalism of non-Christian thinking has also influenced the Christian thought.
Similarly, this kind of religious epistemology does not leave room for personal
198
knowledge.
For example, John frame, a reformed theologian, points out the limitations when
the abstractionist method is applied to theology. John Frame writes: “Theology, too,
means above all to tell us something very specific, not general truths about
being-as-such but about the Lord, the living God, about specific historical events in
which God saved us from sin, about our own character, decisions, actions, attitudes,
and so forth.” 556 John Frame mentions three perspectives of knowledge: the
“Under the normative perspective we asked, is this belief consistent with the laws of
thought? Under the situational perspective the question was, is my belief in accord
with objective reality? Now we come to the existential perspective in which we ask,
can I live with this belief?”557 Frame also points out the intimate connection of
intellectualist tradition quite a lot. However, the core of knowledge, for him, is still
three perspectives include an existential perspective, they still do not ascend to the
ontological level. In short, his framework is still under the spell of ‘substantialism’.
556
John M. Frame, The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God (New Jersey: Presbyterian and Reformed
Publishing, 1987), 175.
557
Ibid., 150.
558
Ibid., 149.
199
Abstractionism has been suspected by the Greek Sophists and skeptics, medieval
experience.
scientific knowledge. He writes: “Two types of knowledge we possess, and may seek
persons as persons: the other our knowledge of persons as objects. The first
depends upon and expresses a personal attitude to the other person, the second an
involving human being. Firstly, the concept ‘man’ is a general class concept. It is
scientific knowledge of man which we can obtain without entering into personal
relations. Secondly, the concept of ‘the personal’ is not about an isolated individual;
relations. However, for Macmurray, these two types of knowledge are not mutually
man, and the work of the anthropological sciences is justified and is, in principle,
correct, though of course it may be mistaken in detail.”560 Both refer to the same
human beings. If the two types of knowledge were apparently in contradiction with
559
John Macmurray, Persons in Relation (London: Faber and Faber Limited, 1970), 37.
560
Ibid., 38.
200
one another, the reason must be that we regard the scientific account as a complete
Unfortunately, we will then commit an error. “The error lies in our failure to
understand the special character of scientific knowledge, and so not in our science
but in our philosophy of the personal. It is, in fact, the result of a false valuation of
the objective attitude, which makes it normative for all possible attitudes.”561
objectivism. Similarly, we find that the same error has happened in our theology
when we regard the objective knowledge of God and man as a complete and
absolute account of reality. In fact, it is doubtful whether there has been a truly
time, objective knowledge was regarded as a complete and absolute account, and
not as a true account of the aspect of realities. This kind of framework will
doctrine’, which are formulated in terms of abstractionism.562 God, for them, could
not be known by way of essence. “Thus we have had an era of ‘theologies of’ this
and that: theologies of hope, liberation, personal encounter, Word of God, crisis,
conception of substance in the 20th century. For example, Carl Henry uses one
564
chapter to describe ‘Divine Revelation as Personal’. For McGrath,
evangelicalism needs to focus on the person and work of Jesus Christ, and to affirm
that all must be based upon Christ, not simply as a source of ideas, but as the
foundation of every aspect of the Christian life: “The evangelical passion for truth
is expressed partly in its focus on the person of Christ, in that Jesus Christ is the
truth.”565
ontology which is quite distinct from the Western substantialist ontology. As Alan
Torrance comments:
Here we see the extent to which Zizioulas breaks with theological approaches operating from a
‘revelation model’ and consistently redefines the theological enterprise from the perspective of
a ‘communion model’—a model which sustains (and presupposes) a commonality of
personhood between God and humanity. In doing this Zizioulas does a great deal to take
theology beyond the obsession with epistemological concerns which has characterized so much
theology since the Enlightenment—even, as Colin Gunton suggests, Karl Barth’s theology.566
The ‘communion model’ will transform our knowledge of God from an objective
ontological scheme which provides support for the concrete individual and
564
Carl F. H. Henry, God, Revelation and Authority, Vol. II (Texas: Word Book, Publisher, 1976),
151.
565
Alister E. McGrath, A Passion for Truth: The Intellectual Coherence of Evangelicalism (England:
Apollos, 1996), 27.
566
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation, 299-300. Gunton writes: “Karl Barth saw himself primarily as standing before the
God made known-revealed –in Scripture, and as is well known, his preoccupation with revelation
gave to his theology a strongly epistemic drive, which at the same time showed him to be working in
some way in the context of, although also against, the Enlightenment.” The Promise of Trinitarain
Theology, 4-5.
202
integrates knowledge into life according to this kind of ontological theology. He
realizes that knowledge and communion are identical. In other words, knowledge
and life are identical. 567 LaCugna claims: “indeed, authentically theological
knowledge is that which comes about as a result of union with God.” 568 Alan
personal life.
knowledge is the primary kind of knowledge we find in the Bible. Thus we can
Zizioulas does not exactly say this. For example, sin can be explained through a
more relational understanding than an ethical one alone. When we introduce sin
from this starting point, it will help us avoid the tendency towards legalism.
At the same time, the personal attitude helps us enter into personal relation with
God and others and treat them as persons. Thus, the relationship between God and
relationship. It also shows that faith transcends ethics.570 Under the objectivist idea
567
John Zizioulas, Being as Communion, 81.
568
Catherine LaCugna, God for Us, 348.
569
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation, 304.
570
Kierkegaard provides a famous argument for why faith transcends ethic in his book Fear and
Trembling. There is a paradox between the ethical expression and the religious expression when
Kierkegaard describes the story of Abraham, who was told by God to ascend Mount Moriah to
sacrifice his only son, Isaac, (Genesis 22: 2-14) for it is impossible that Abraham don’t love his only
son. Here Kierkegaard points out a very important problem about the relationship between faith and
ethics. Kierkkegarrd raises three problems. The first deals with the possibility of a teleological
suspension of the ethical. The second questions the existence of an absolute duty to God. The third
asks whether it is ethically defensible for Abraham to conceal his undertaking from Sarah, from
Eliezer, and from Isaac. In the first problem, Kierkegaard defines ethics as the universal, as applying
to all at all times. The ethical is the telos, of everything outside itself and there is no telos beyond the
203
of truth, it is difficult for Christians to distinguish the ethical from the ontological
relationship between God and man, because Christians only emphasize the
the goal of knowledge is to establish a personal relationship between God and man
both emphasize the personal relationship between God and man. However,
Zizioulas’ starting point is the three persons of the Triune God. He does not focus
only on the person of Christ like evangelicalism often does. Thus there is more
evangelicalism has.
One issue is important: whether Zizioulas abondons the objective Word of the
Bible when he claims that truth is personal or subjetive. Zizioulas does not exclude
the objectivity of the Bible. He distinguishes two terms: Doctrine (Dogma) and
kerygma. In terms of different objects, Zizioulas points out the dogma or the
preaching to all the world. “While kerygma exists in order that it can proclaim the
truth to those outside the Church, which does of course involve arguing with them
about what is true…Dogma is the doctrine that, through its councils, the Church
confesses as the truth that brings salvation for every human being. This truth brings
ethical. Concerning the relationship between ethics and religion, there are two possibilities: either
the ethical is harmonious with the eternal salvation or the ethical clashes with the religious. In most
cases there is no conflict between the two aspects, but not always. When somebody faces a collision
between these two ultimates, the question emerges: which one is higher? That is to say, which is the
ultimate end deserving to be given precedence? Kierkegaard defines faith as the single individual
standing in an absolute relation to the absolute: “Faith is precisely the paradox that the single
individual is higher than the universal, is justified before it, not as inferior to it but as superior... that
it is the single individual who, after being subordinate as the single individual to the universal, now
by means of the universal becomes the single individual who as the single individual is superior, that
the single individual as the single individual stands in an absolute relation to the absolute.” Søren
Kierkegaard, Fear and Trembling, trans. and eds. Howard V. Honand and Edna H Hong (New Jersey:
Princeton University Press, 1983), 54.
204
us into particular relationships with one another, and it brings the Church into a
particular relationship with God and with the world.”571 Thus there are two kinds
logical proposals, but of personal relationships between God, man and the world.
We do not come to know truth simply through intellectual assent to the proposition
that God is triune. It is only when we are drawn into the life of God, which is triune,
and through it receives our entire existence and identity, that we have real
knowledge.”572
ontological and existential, not in the sense that one kind of being becomes another
kind of being (fruit becomes bread), but in the sense that the new person involves a
salvation. Generally speaking, the Western understanding of new life involves the
The substantialists approach man from the viewpoint of his ‘substance’ and try to
understand him by drawing the limits between divine and human nature.573 When
the perfect human nature rather than the personhood is the ultimate ground for the
rational being who represents the Imago Dei before the Fall. He possesses a perfect
571
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 6.
572
Ibid., 7-8.
573
Calvin, Comm. on Rom. 7:14.
205
nature which is the end of man. Eventually, man will receive an entirely new nature
For Calvin, the purpose of Christ is to help us to be men who recover perfect
human nature as Adam does before the Fall. As T. F. Torrance writes: “In some
sense, Calvin thought of Christ as bearing the image of God in virtue of His human
nature in addition to the fact that He was the image of God in the sense of the
eternal Word.”575 Christian new life is identified with a perfect human nature. It
means that the change is from a corrupt human nature to a perfect human nature.
Martyn Lloyd-Jones writes: “Now we are concerned more about the power and the
pollution of sin—‘renews his whole nature in the image of God and enables him to
divinize human nature through the perfect human nature of Jesus. For example: as
For some substantialists, a puzzling question arises: if the nature of man has been
changed, why does man continue to sin after regeneration? Therefore, it is difficult
574
Calvin, Comm. on Gen. 1. 26.
575
T. F. Torrance, Calvin’s Doctrine of Man (Connecticut: Greenwood Press, Publishers, 1977), 60.
576
David Martyn Lloyd-Jones, God the Holy Spirit (Wheaton, IL: Crossway Books, 2003), 195.
577
Ibid., 207.
206
for us to accept the sinful reality of ourselves and others. If we expect an entirely
new nature after believing, we will be very disappointed because we still often find
ourselves sinning. Since it is difficult for us to accept this conflict, we may become
God in Christ through the Holy Spirit as an ontological and existential issue. The
person: “No transformation in nature is possible outside the sphere of its personal
realization, since nature only exists in persons, and once it becomes existentially
It will affect our attitude toward other persons directly. Because the ultimate
ground is personhood rather than human nature, we should not treat persons in
terms of their qualities. We can distinguish one’s personhood from his behavior. It
theological?
The most serious criticism of Zizioulas’ ontology of person is that his theological
ontology is taken from philosophy rather than theology. For example, two Greek
Fathers ideas that he has in reality imported from philosophical personalism and
578
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality, 144.
207
existentialism. 579 Papanikolaou writes: “Criticism of John Zizioulas’ relational
and ‘existential’ attempt ‘to construct a metaphysical system’ which has for its aim
thought.584
579
See Norman Russell, “Modern Greek theologians and Greek Fathers,” Philosophy and Theology,
18 (1):77-92 (2006). See John Panagopoulos, “Ontology of Theology of Person” (in Greek), Synaxis,
Vol. 13-14 (1985), 63-79; 35-47; and Savas Agourides, “Can the Persons of the Trinity form the
Basis for Personalistic Understandings of the Human Being?” (in Greek), Synaxis, Vol. 33 (1990),
67-78.
580
Aristotle Papanikolaou, “Is John Zizioulas an Existentialist in Disguise? Response to Lucian
Turcescu,” Modern Theology 20:4/2004, ISSN 0266-7177 (Print); ISSN 1468-0025 (Online), 601.
581
John Behr, ‘The Trinitarian Being of the Chruch,’ St Vladimir’s Theological Quarterly 48.1/2004:
67-68.
582
John Behr, ‘Faithfulness and Creativity’, in Abba, 159-77, at 176; See Douglas H. Knight ed.,
The Theology of John Zizioulas: Person and the Church, 45.
583
Andrew Louth, John Damascene: Tradition and Originality in Byzantine Theology (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2002), 51.
584
Alan Brown, ‘On the Criticism of Being as Communion in Anglophone Orthodox Theology’, in
Douglas H. Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 40.
208
In chapter two (section 2.2.1), I have introduced that Lucian Turcescu criticizes
Zizioulas for using ninesteenth and twentieth century ideas to understand the
In reply, Zizioulas admits that modern philosophy does influence his thinking but
he claims that it does not determine it. Zizioulas argues that the criticism above
does not really go to the root of things because it remains on the superficial level of
This was the starting point of the whole of Western personalistic thought, through
Descartes and the Enlightenment to the first American personalists in the twentieth
century.”585 For all types of personalism, both in America and in Europe, their
Zizioulas distinguishes his personalism from that of M. Buber, G. Marcel and others
misleads many people into confusing my views with those of that sort of
585
John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 20.
586
Ibid., 21.
209
chapter two (section 2.4.2) when I distinguish the ontology of relationality from the
ontology of personhood.
Many theologians’ articles were collected by Douglas H. Knight in the book The
Theology of Zizioulas. The essays are mainly reflecting on the relationship between
the individual and the community and the very nature of God. They on the whole
Zizioulas’ theological concept of person. He thinks that Zizioulas traces the roots of
Western culture back to the thought of Augustine and Boethius which provides an
threat.
personhood, an ontology which has at its heart what even the most optimistic
existentialism does not, that is, a concept of freedom through love: freedom through
transcended.
587
Colin Gunton, ‘Person and Particularity’, in Douglas Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas:
Personhood and the Church, 97-108.
588
Douglas Farrow, ‘Person and Nature: The Necessity-Freedom Dialectic in John Zizioulas’, in
Douglas Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 109-124.
210
Divine-Human Communion, critically analyzes the implications of Zizioulas’
reworking of the patristic category of hypostasis. His criticism mainly concerns the
communion.589
in her book God as Communion: John Zizioulas, Elizabeth Johnson, and the
Retrieval of the Symbol of the Triune God. She agrees that Zizioulas’ idea: “is a
concept that springs from an ontology of person that has its roots in Greek patristic
However, Zizioulas has some important supporters. For example, Gunton scarely
soteriology:
And yet much Orthodox theology fails adequately to encompass the deep fallenness of the
human condition, attested as that is both by Scripture’s emphasis on the cross as the centre of
the awesome process and the manifest need of fallen man for redemption. In a word, by failing
to take adequate account of the bondage of the will, Eastern theologians, among them John
Zizioulas, can appear to ascribe to the human capacity more than is justified apart from
593
redemption.
It seems that he realizes the defect of Zizoulas’ anthropology but he does not
589
Aristotle Papanikolaou, Being with God: Trinity, Apophaticism, and Divine-Human Communion
(Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press, 2006), 25.
590
Patricia A. Fox, God as Communion: John Zizioulas, Elizabeth Johnson, and the Retrieval of the
Symbol of the Triune God (Minnesota: The Liturgical Press, 2001), 32.
591
Ibid., 48.
592
Gunton, Colin E. “Trinity, Ontology and Anthropology: Towards a Renewal of the Doctrine of
the Imago Dei”, In C. Schwobel and C. Gunton eds., Persons Divine and Human (Edinburgh: T&T.
Clark, 1991), 47-64.
593
Colin Gunton, “Persons and Particularity”, in Douglas H. Knight ed., The Theology of John
Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 104.
211
Farrow points out that Zizioulas does not explain a difficulty: how the personal
existence of God can be applied to the being of humans in view of the different
essences of God and man: “But this distinction between God’s nature or substance
and his ‘personal life’ or ‘personal existence’ is itself problematic; indeed it is not
clear how Zizioulas can make such a distinction, or that we should follow him in
doing so. And it becomes even more problematic if the latter is abstracted in such a
Alan Brown introduces the realization of the new hypostatic mode of existence
through love without criticism. “Thus, so hypostasized, man is able to transcend the
relationships of biological existence through a love which loves ‘not because the
594
Douglas Farrow, ‘Person and Nature: The Necessity-Freedom Dialectic’, in Douglas H. Knight
ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 119.
595
Alan Brown, ‘On the Criticism of Being as Communion in Anglophone Orthodox Theology’, in
Douglas H. Knight ed., The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 64.
596
Zizioulas defends himself when a Greek theologian criticizes him: “I have stressed repeatedly
that the person cannot be conceived of without the essence, and the essence of God cannot be
conceived of ‘in a naked state,’ without the person. In consequence, the charge of being
‘anti-essence’ is not applicable to me, and the statement that ‘the only divine essence of God is His
existence” is a complete distortion of my position.” Zizioulas takes the concept of ‘love’ as an
example: “Love in this sense is common to the three Persons, meaning that it relates to the essence
or nature of God”. See John Zizioulas, The One and the Many, 22.
212
influences Zizioulas’ anthropology directly, i.e., the concepts of ‘justice’ and ‘sin’
are missing in his soteriology. As a result, Zizioulas’ theology seems to ignore some
of the crucial elements of the Bible. In fact, justice and sin can be explained from an
ontological and relational perspective. It means that they are not only concepts of
ethics.
In chapter three (section 3.3), I discuss two modes of existence: biological and
continues to insist upon the Resurrection as the centre of its whole life precisely
because it sees that the problem of the created is not moral but ontological; it is the
problem of the existence (and not the beauty) of the world, the problem of death.”597
Death is a state of life which is caused by the rupture between being and
continue in existence, and overcome his limits and the eventual dissolution that they
bring, the creature has to be in relationship with the uncreated God.” 598 The
process of salvation is how Jesus brings the world back to a living relationship with
God.
human action or activity. Zizioulas applies the view of Bourke: ethics is “the
what types of activity are good, right, and to be done…what the ethicist aims at,
597
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 261.
598
John Zizioulas, Lectures in Christian Dogmatics, 98.
213
then, is a reflective, well-considered, and reasonable set of conclusions concerning
the kinds of voluntary activities that may be judged good or suitable or evil and
unsuitable…”599 Ethics operates on the basis of the polarity between good and evil.
He observes that the “West (Catholic and Protestant) has viewed the problem of
and has made of the Cross of Christ the epicenter of faith and worship.” 600
However, Zizioulas thinks that ‘sin’ is not the reason for the necessity of the
atonement, and sin is not one of the fundamental categories of soteriology. In fact,
the necessity of salvation is not based on the sin of man, but death. The purpose of
salvation is the union between the created and the uncreated rather than the
Zizioulas’ theology manifests the general tendency of Orthodox theology. “The joy
of the resurrection—that is the key-note of the Eastern Church’s whole outlook upon
Naturally Zizioulas avoids the Cross as the center of salvation. Gunton writes:
“Confession of sin does indeed bulk large in Eastern liturgy, but appears to have
little structural effect on Orthodox theology. It may be the case that Western
soteriology sometimes suffers by comparison with that of the East in failing to make
599
V. J. Bourke, ‘Ethics’, New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2nd ed., 2003, vol. 5, p. 388f. Cf. John
Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 81-82, footnote, 180.
600
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 261.
601
Nicholas Arseniev, Mysticism and the Eastern Church (Crestwood, New York: St. Vladimir’s
Seminary Press, 1979), 17.
602
Colin Gunton, ‘Persons and Particularity’, in Douglas H. Knight ed., The Theology of John
Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church, 104.
214
relational or ontological understanding of ‘sin’ among persons too.
In Zizioulas’ writing, he does not distinguish the concept of ‘sin’ in its different
levels. We should affirm that ‘sin’ is not only a moral conception. In Western
theology, the idea of sin or evil is essential for understanding human nature. It is not
concept of sin which I have argued in chapter six (section 6.2.3) through
Augustine’s theology.
concept, but a personalist one: “It thus appears as an illness, as a parasite existing
only by virtue of the nature he lives off. More precisely, it is a state of the will of this
nature; it is a fallen will with regard to God. Evil is revolt against God, that is to say,
a personal attitude. The exact vision of evil is thus not essentialist but
personalist.”603
Kierkegaard also interprets sin from the existential perspective:
The very concept in which Christianity differs most crucially in kind from paganism is: sin, the
doctrine of sin. And so, quite consistently, Christianity also assumes that neither paganism nor
the natural man know what sin is; yes, it assumes there must be a revelation from God to reveal
what sin is. It is not the case, as superficial reflection supposes, that the doctrine of the
atonement is what distinguishes paganism and Christianity qualitatively. No, the beginning has
to be made far deeper, with sin, with the doctrine of sin, which is also what Christianity does.604
existence. It means separation from being and exclusion from life. The restoration
to the fullness of life and existence can take place only if man undergoes an
existential change.605 Therefore, sin is not essential to our nature, because in God’s
creation there is nothing which is hypostatically and naturally evil. “Sin is a failure,
603
Vladimir Lossky, Orthodox Theology: An Introduction, trans. Ian and Ihita Kesarcodi-Watson
(New York: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1989), 80.
604
Søren Kierkegaard, The Sickness unto Death, ed. S. Kierkegaard (New York: Penguin Books,
1989), 122.
605
Christos Yannaras, The Freedom of Morality (New York: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1984),
35-37.
215
a failure as to existence and life: it is the failure of persons to realize their
through love.”606
Bultmann has a wonderful analysis of the human condition under sin: ‘I’ and ‘my
flesh’ can be equated. The true self of a man is thereby dissociating itself from this
self that has fallen victim to flesh. “This inner dividedness means that man himself
destroys his true self. In his self-reliant will to be himself, a will that comes to light
in ‘desire’ at the encounter with the ‘commandment,’ he loses his self, and ‘sin’
becomes the active subject within him (Romans 7:9). ”607 It implies that sin is a loss
of being. Sin manifests an inner relation with self and with God. Therefore,
although Paul emphasizes the moral good or evil, he does not separate moral action
According to the existentialist theologian John Macquarrie, sin involves not only
ethics. He says: “[Sin] implies not only moral evil but alienation from God…Sin in
the New Testament is an ontical conception—it describes not only a possibility for
man but his actual condition.”608 He uses an illustration to clarify this concept.
When Paul says that ‘all have sinned’ (Romans 3:23), he is making an ontical
statement: the entity which we call man has fallen into the condition which we call
sin, and that this is true of all men. This ontical statement can only be properly
All in all, from the existential perspective, sin means rejecting a relationship with
God. Though sin lacks an essence, it manifests itself as a broken relationship with
606
Ibid., 34.
607
Rudolf Bultmann, Theology of the New Testament, trans. Kendrick Grobel (Tübingen: SCM
Press Ltd. 1952), 245.
608
John Macquarrie, An Existentialist Theology, 103.
609
Ibid., 30.
216
dimension. It seems that he has excessively separated ethical problems and
perspective of the individual, human incapability under the power of sin is not
lead us to overlook the responsibility for the serious consequence of sin, because
Zizioulas regards sin as only a moral problem and Christians, according to him,
should focus instead on the relationship with God, i.e., an ontological problem. I
view. For example, Alan Torrance writes: “That opened up the profound
priesthood of Christ.” 610 However, few critics ask Zizioulas: “what kind of
ecclesiology and epistemology. Lossky, Yannaras and Zizioulas share the consensus
that divine-human communion could not be otherwise expressed than through the
but mystical knowledge which goes beyond reason without denying it. 612 The
610
Alan J. Torrance, Persons in Communion: An Essay on Trinitarian Description and Human
Participation, 305.
611
Aristotle Papanikolaou, “Personhood and its exponents in twentieth-century Orthodox theology”,
in Mary B. Cunningham and Elizabeth Theokritoff ed., The Cambridge Companion to Orthodox
Christian Theology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009), 233.
612
Vladimir Lossky, The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church (Crestwood, NY: SVS Press,
1976), 38-39.
217
purpose of theology is to guide the believer towards an experience of divine-human
communion. For Yannaras, in the experience of union with God, the knowledge of
God is an ‘erotic affair’ and the ‘gift of an erotic relationship’.613 For Zizoulas, the
transcends the limitation of finite nature towards an eternal communion with God.
ontological freedom.” 614 ‘Righteousness’ and ‘holy’ are not included in the
these concepts as ethical principles. He even suggests that this ethical principle is in
When Zizioulas says that ‘the idea of justice is absent from Christ’s teaching’, he
understands the concept of justice on the ethical level in terms of the philosophy of
concept of justice, and his examples are incomplete. For example, we can take ‘the
parable of the unforgiving servant’ as an example: “Then his lord summoned him
and said to him, ‘You wicked slave! I forgave you all that debt because you pleaded
with me. Should you not have had mercy on your fellow slave, as I had mercy on
you? And in anger his lord handed him over to be tortured until he would pay his
613
Christos Yannaras, On the Absence and Unknowability of God: Heidegger and the Areopagite, ed.
A. Louth (Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 2005), 86.
614
Ibid., 46.
615
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 86.
218
entire debt. So my heavenly Father will also do to every one of you, if you do not
forgive your brother or sister from your heart.” (Matthew 18.32-35) From this story,
we can find that the justice of God is accompanied by mercy and grace. In other
words, there is a presupposition for Justice: God’s grace. The purpose of God is to
bring us back to him. Therefore, the action of God cannot be judged only by an
ethical principle of justice in the sense of philosophy. However, it does not mean
Other: the Other is prior to the Self. The ascetic life is a good example: “This
theological justification of ascetic self-emptying for the sake of the Other is deeply
Maximus locates the roots of evil in self-love.” 616 This model of communion
ontological ground for the existence of the Other. However, this ontological
principle is not enough for us to understand the existence of a society, because this
In fact, justice is not only an ethical category, but also a relational or ontological
concept, i.e., justice means a right relationship. In other words, justice is manifested
in the Other my master.” 618 Zizioulas’ principle does not involve the issue of
plural relationships, what happens if this principle conflicts with the third party? As
616
Ibid., 84.
617
Ibid., 82.
618
Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority, trans. Alphonso Lingis
(Pittsburgh: Duquesne Univ. Press, 1969), 72.
219
Levinas writes: “If proximity ordered to me only the other alone, there would not
have been any problem.”619 Levinas suggests the necessity of moving from the
principles, because of the notion of the ‘third’. The character of this kind of justice
is equality. All in all, justice as right relationship exists between two persons and
between more than two persons. Dogenes Allen insists: “In Christianity, however,
justice must always be considered, even when you deal with those who are weaker.
You must always take others into account; not as a matter of mercy, but as a matter
of justice, for there is an absolute equality between people. People are not equal in
earthly ways, but our absolute equality is not based on earthly matters.”620
According to the Bible, righteousness and justice have both the ontological
content and the ethical dimension which are grounded in the existence of God:
“Righteousness and justice are the foundation of your throne.” (Psalms 89:14).
“Righteousness art Thou, O Lord, and upright are Thy judgment (Psalms 119: 137)
holiness of the character of God; or in view of its manifestation toward the creature.
As such the righteousness or justice of God consists in giving each his worthy due,
human being. They form an indivisible entity. Christ is accepted by faith, and then
619
Ibid., 32.
620
Diogenes Allen, “Christian Values in a Post-Christian Context,” in Fredric B. Burnham ed.,
Postmodern Theology: Christian Faith in a Pluralist World (Oregon: Wipf and Stock Publishers,
1989), 29.
621
Wilhelmus á Brakel, The Christian’s Reasonable Service, chapter Three. See
http://www.davidcox.com.mx/library/B/Brakel%20-%20Christian's%20Reasonable%20Service%2
0(Systematic%20Theology).pdf
220
the righteousness of Christ is infused into the human heart.622 “But we who live by
the Spirit eagerly wait to receive by faith the righteousness God has promised to
srelationship with God and with others. Even when justification requires individual
purposes for the covenant community and to the coming of the kingdom of God.
Therefore, a communion with God should include the meaning of justice. When
understand society. I will further analyze the problem from the social dimension.
be the ground of ethics. Because ‘justice’ is not on the ontological level, our attitude
towards others can only be ‘love’. His theological ontology limits in the scope of
Church’s involvement. 624 That ‘the Other prior to the self’ as an ontological
principle cannot provide an adequate ground for the social structure, because of the
lack of the notion of ‘justice’. So this kind of theology runs the risk of becoming
622
Martin Luther, Weimarer Ausgabe (Latin original of Luther’s works) 2, 146, 29-30; 36; 12-16,
32-35. See Veli-Matti Kärkkäinen, One with God: Salvation as Deification and Justification, 53-54.
623
Ibid., 122.
624
From the theme of Zizioulas’ book Being as Communion: Studies in Personhood and the Church,
we can know his scope.
221
room for law and order if this attitude to the Other were to become a principle of ethics.
Societies are organized on the assumption that evil can be controlled only if it is somehow
identified with the evil-doer, for it is not evil as such but the person who commits the evil act
that can be the subject of law. Given that justice is a fundamental principle of ethics and law, any
transference of moral responsibility for an evil act from the person who committed it to
someone else would be totally unethical.625
missing from Zizioulas’ thought.”626 For LaCugna, salvation is not only involving
examples: “Both types of theology typically appeal to the Latin doctrine of the
persons.”628
ontological basis for social justice. It manifests a theological ethos of the East: “In
the East, the cross of Christ is envisaged not so much as the punishment of the just
beings’ sin…The point was not to satisfy a legal requirement, but to vanquish
625
John Zizioulas, Communion and Otherness, 87.
626
Cathrine Mowry LaCugna, God for Us, 266.
627
Ibid., 292.
628
Ibid., 266.
222
death.” 629 It also reflects a tendency of Greek theology: “Greek theology is
the end about the pattern of relationships among persons in the oikonomia.”630 This
type of theology which lacks the perspective of righteousness might lead to serious
consequence in the community and society. We may consider the religious situation
There are no emphasis on the concepts of righteousness and social justice in the
existence of the particular and the community. In the 20th century, The Church in
Russia had no ability to resist the Bolshevik Communist party. The government was
controlled by the Bolsheviks which were staunch materialists and atheists. Religion
was to them ‘opiate of the people”. The church remained deaf to the spiritual needs
of the age. “The Church actually stood aside in this struggle for truth and the
welfare of humanity. The upper hierarchs had taken sides with the enemies of the
people.”632 They did not care about social justice and people’s troubles. Father
Gregory Petroff, a priest living at that time, was a remarkable man with a clear
629
Ibid., 22.
630
Ibid., 288.
631
Julius F. Hecker, Religion under the Soviets (New York: Vanguard Press, 1927), 2.
632
Ibid., 85-86.
223
Christian; there exists no Christian government. It is strange to speak of the Christian world.
The mutual relations of the various people are altogether contrary to the spirit of the gospel; the
most Christian states maintain millions of men for mass butcheries, sometimes of their
neighbors and sometimes of their own citizens… God was reasoned about without being
introduced into life itself.633
633
Ibid., 166-167.
224
Conclusion
I have explored Zizioulas’ ontology of personhood in this dissertation.
but also a historical reality. The ontological revolution has influenced the creed of
these creeds, but we have not noticed the ontological meaning. In other words, our
set up a view of the living or personal God to replace a substantial view of God
truth. Theological argument takes root in the view of truth. Therefore, Zizioulas
traced his idea of truth to the Eucharist theology of Ignatius and Irenaeus, which
identify truth with life. Based on this, there is a possibility of the ontological
revolution which identifies hypostasis with personhood for the Cappadocians. The
reasonably criticized.
identified with that of the Cappadocians. Some critics believe that Zizioulas
225
contrast Zizioulas’ ontological concept of personhood with the approach of
but a difference.
Zizioulas sets up his own theological ontology exclusive of the concept of ousia,
realtionality, Zizioulas believes that the ultimate element of decision is Self rather
than the Other. When he compares his ontology with the ontology of relationality,
Western traditional way takes a different approach to understand the human being
by the person of God the Father and Christ is the way to person existence. Therefore,
ponder over that the problem of the poor and the oppressed is not ethical but
ontological. The suffering of the others connects our existence with our
contrast with the Western substantialist view of God and the human person.
Subtantialist view of God and anthropology are not directly related to Christian life
since Augustine brings a huge problem which does not include the otherness and
traced the personas identity to God, this condition started to be changed, for the
particular was raised to the level of ontological primacy. Each particular is affirmed
determines that our attitude to the other cannot depend on the quality of the other. A
explain personal identity through the person of God. Human identity and equality
are not only the categories of the contemporary humanism, but also the theology
which can be found in patristic thought. In the ultimate sense, Christian life can be
anthropology: lack of the consciousness of sin and the notion of justice. Zizioulas
places the concepts of sin and justice on the ethical level. It is his failure not to
explain the concept of sin and justice ontologically. At the same time his
principle of ‘the Other prior to the Self’ can provide an ontological foundation for
human moral action. However, the principle of ‘the Other prior to the Self’ alone is
not an adequate ontological ground or ethical principle for the existence of a society.
Christian community or the socialproblems like injustice. This is one of the weakest
However, despite these defects, the rich reflections of John Zizioulas clearly
break away from the individualism of Western framework. In fact, I argue that from
we can also develop a critical attitude towards our existence in a society, because all
of us have an equal worth which is based on a relationship with God. It means that
well as a foundation for our experience and identity. Along this line, we can have a
theology. Not only that it can be used to critique the concrete shape of the social
order, it can also be used for cultural criticism and the rebuilding of a new
relationship in the community. Of course, this thesis can only hint at all these. This
228
Bibliography
Primary Sources
Books by Zizioulas
Being as Communion: Studies in Personhood and the Church. Crestwood, NY: St.
Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1985.
Eucharist, Bishop, Church: the Unity of the Church in the Divine Eucharist and the
Bishop during the First Three Centuries. Trans. Elizabeth Theokritoff, Brookline.
MA: Holy Cross Orthodox Press, 2001.
Communion and Otherness: Further Studies in Personhood and the Church. Paul
McPartlan (ed.). London: T & T Clark, 2006.
The Lectrures in Christian Dogmatics. Douglas Knight (ed.). London: T & T Clark,
2008.
The One and the Many: Studies on God, Man, the Church, and the World Today. Fr.
Gregory Edwards (ed.). California: Sebastian Press, 2010.
The Eucharistic Communion and the World. Luke Ben Tallon (ed.). London: T & T
Clark, 2011)
Articles by Zizioulas
229
“Relational Ontology: Insights from Patristic Thought.” In John Polkinghoren (ed.),
The Trinity and an Entangled World: Relationality in Physical Science and
Theology (Grand Rapids, Mich.: Wm. B. Eerdmans Pub., 2010), 146- 156.
“The Nature of the Unity We Seek—The Response of the Orthodox Observer.” One
in Christ 24 (1988): 342-48.
“Man the Priest of Creation.” In A. Walker and C. Carras (eds.), Living Orthodoxy
in the Modern World (London: SPCK, 1996), 178-88.
Secondary Sources
Arseniev, Nicholas. Mysticism and the Eastern Church. Crestwood, New York: St.
Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1979.
Augustine. The Trinity. Trans. Edmund Hill, O.P., ed. John E. Rotelle. Brooklyn, N.
Y.: New City Press, 1991.
Balthasar. Hans Urs Von. A Theological Anthropology. New York: Sheed and Ward,
1967.
Basil of Caesarea. On the Holy Siprit. Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary
Press, 1980.
Behr, John. The Nicene Faith. Vol. 2 of The Formation of Christian Theology.
Crestwood, NY: St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 2004.
Bourke, V. J. ‘Ethics’. New Catholic Encyclopedia, 2nd ed., vol. 5, 2003. See
http://www.highbeam.com/doc/1G2-3407703789.html
Bracken, Joseph A. The Triune Symbol: Persons, Process, and Community. Lanham:
University Press of America, 1985.
231
340-352.
Buber, Martin. I and Thou. Trans. Walter Kaufman. Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark. 1970.
Buber, Martin. ‘What is Man?’ in Between Man and Man, trans. R.G. Smith.
London: Collins, 2008.
Bultmann Rudolf. New Testament and Mythology and Other Basic Writings. Trans.
and ed. S. M. Ogden. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1984.
Burggraeve, Roger. (ed.) The Awakening to the Other: A Provocative Dialogue with
Emmanuel Levinas. Leuven; Dudley, MA: Peeters, 2008.
Calvin, John. Institutes of the Christian Religion. Grand Rapids, Mich.: W.B.
Eerdmans, 1983.
Collins, Paul M. Trinitarian Theology, West and East: Karl Barth, the Cappadocian
Fathers and John Zizioulas. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
Congar, Y. I Believe in the Holy Spirit. New York: Seabury Press; London: G.
Chapman, 1983.
Cumin, Paul. ‘Looking for Personal Space in the Theology of John Zizioulas.’
International Journal of Systematic Theology 8.4/2006: 356-370.
Del Colle, Ralph. “‘Person’ and ‘Being’ in John Zizioulas’ Trinitarian Theology:
Conversations with Thomas Torrance and Thomas Aquinas.” Scottish Journal of
Theology 54, no.1, 2001, pp.70-86.
232
Farrow, Douglas. ‘Person and Nature: The Necessity-Freedom Dialectic’, in
Douglas H. Knight (ed.), The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the
Church (Aldershot/Burlington: Ashgate Publishing, 2007), 109-124.
Fox, Patricia A. God as Communion: John Zizioulas, Elizabeth Johnson, and the
Retrieval of the Symbol of the Triune God. Minnesota: The Liturgical Press, 2001.
Frame, John M. The Doctrine of the Knowledge of God. New Jersey: Presbyterian
and reformed Publishing, 1987.
Gilson, Etienne. History of Christian Philosophy in the Middle Ages. New York:
Random House, 1955.
Grenz, Stanley J. ‘The Social God and the Relational Self’, in Richard Lints,
Michael S. Horton and Mark R. Talbot (eds.), Personal Identity in Theological
Perspective (Cambridge: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2006), 70-92.
Gunton, Colin E. Becoming and Being: The Doctrine of God in Charles Hartshome
and Karl Barth. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1978.
Gunton, Colin E. The One, the Three and the Many: God, Creation and the Culture
of Modernity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Gunton, Colin E. Father, Son and Holy Spirit: Toward a Fully Trinitarian Theology.
London: T & T Clark, 2003.
Gunton, Colin E. ‘Person and Particularity’, in Douglas Knight (ed.), The Theology
of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the Church (Aldershot/Burlington: Ashgate
Publishing, 2007), 97-108.
233
Doctrine of the Imago Dei”, in Schwobel, C & Gunton, C (eds.), Persons, Divine
and Human (Edinburgh: T&T. Clark, 1991), 47-64.
Hauerwas, Stanley. Character and the Christian Life: A Study in Theological Ethics.
San Antonio: Trinity University Press, 1984.
Hecker, Julius F. Religion under the Soviets. New York: Vanguard Press, 1927.
Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Trans. Joan Stambaugh. State University of
New York, 2010.
Henry, Carl F. H. God, Revelation and Authority, Vol. II. Texas: Word Book,
Publisher, 1976.
Hill, William J. The Three-Personed God: the Trinity as a Mystery of Salvation. The
Catholic University of America Press, 1982.
234
Baker Academic, 2003.
Kelly, J. N. D. Early Christian Doctrines. San Francisco: Harper & Row Publishers,
1978.
Kierkegaard, Søren. The Sickness unto Death. S. Kierkegaard (ed.). New York:
Penguin Books, 1989.
Knight, Douglas H. (ed). The Theology of John Zizioulas: Personhood and the
Church. Aldershot, Hants/Burlington, VT: Ashgate, 2007.
LaCugna, Catherine Mowry. God for Us: The Trinity and Christian life. Chicago:
Harper Collins Publishers, 1991.
Lloyd-Jones, David Martyn. God the Father, God the Son. Wheaton, IL: Crossway
Books, 2003.
235
Lossky, Vladimir. The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church. London: James
Clarke, 1957.
Lossky, Vladimir. In the Image and Likeness of God. Crestwook, N.Y.: St.
Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1974.
Lossky, Vladimir. The Mystical Theology of the Eastern Church. Crestwood, NY:
St. Vladimir’s Seminary Press, 1976,
Macmurray, John. Persons in Relation. London: Faber and Faber Limited, 1970.
McPartlan, Paul G. The Eucharist Makes the Church: Henri de Lubac and John
Zizioulas in Dialogue. Edinburgh: T&T Clark, 1993.
Moltmann, Jürgen. The Trinity and the Kingdom of God. Trans. Margaret Kohl.
236
Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1993.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Will to Power. Trans. Walter Kaufmann. New York:
Random House, 1968.
O’Donnell, John J. The Mystery of the Triune God. New York: Paulist Press, 1989.
Ogden, Greg. The New Reformation: Returning the Ministry to the People of God.
Michigan: Zondervan Publishing House, 1990.
Osborn, Eric. Tertullian, First Theologian of the West. UK: Cambridge University
Press, 1997.
Pannenberg, Wolfhart. Basic Questions in Theology, vol. III. London: SCM Press,
1973.
Plato. Republic. Roslyn, N. Y.: Published for the Classic Club by Walter L. Black,
1969.
237
Prestige, G. L. God in Patristic Thought. London, S.P.C.K., 1952.
Rahner, Karl. The Trinity. Trans. Joseph Donceel. London: Burns & Oates, 1986.
Rosenzweg, Franz. His Life and Thought. Nahum Glatzer (ed.). New York:
Schocken Books, 1961.
Russell, Norman. “Modern Greek Theologians and Greek Fathers.” Philosophy and
Theology, 2006, 18 (1):77-92.
238
and Act. Edinburg: T&T Clark, 1995.
Stevenson Leslie and David L. Haberman. Ten Theories of Human Nature. 4th ed.,
NY: Oxford University Press, 2004.
Torrance, Thomas. F. The Christian Doctrine of God, One Being Three Persons.
Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 1996.
Turcescu, Lucian. Gregory of Nyssa and the Concept of Divine Persons. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2005.
239
Yannaras, Christos. On the Absence and Unknowability of God: Heidegger and the
Areopagite. A. Louth (ed.). Edinburgh: T & T Clark, 2005.
Yannaras, Christos. Orthodoxy and the West. Trans. Peter Chamberas and Norman
Russell. Massachusetts: Holy Cross Orthodox Press, 2006.
240
CURRICULUM VITAE
October 2014
241