Integrating Music Into Intellectual History
Integrating Music Into Intellectual History
http://journals.cambridge.org/MIH
JOHN E. TOEWS
1
Lydia Goehr, The Imaginary Museum of Musical Works: An Essay in the Philosophy of Music
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992).
309
310 john e. toews
2
Jacques Barzun, Berlioz and the Romantic Century, 2 vols. (Boston: Little Brown, 1950,
3rd edn 1969); Paul Robinson, Opera and Ideas: From Mozart to Strauss (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1985).
3
See especially the chapter on Schoenberg and Kokoschka in Carl Schorske, Fin-de-Siècle
Vienna: Politics and Culture (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1980); and the lecture on
Mahler published in idem, Thinking with History: Explorations in the Passage to Modernism
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998).
4
Michael Steinberg, The Meaning of the Salzburg Festival: Austria as Theater and Ideology,
1890–1938 (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1990). The book includes a discussion of
musical works by Strauss, Schoenberg and Mahler.
5
William McGrath, Dionysian Art and Populist Politics in Austria (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1974), esp. chap. 5 (on Mahler).
6
See, for example, Martin Clayton, Trevor Herbert and Richard Middleton, eds., The
Cultural Study of Music: A Critical Introduction (New York: Routledge, 2003).
7
Subotnik’s influential essays of the 1970s and 1980s are collected in Rose Rosengard
Subotnik, Developing Variations: Style and Ideology in Western Music (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1991). Kramer’s books include Music as Cultural Practice,
1800–1900 (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1990); Classical Music and Postmodern
Knowledge (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995); and Musical Meaning: Toward
integrating music into intellectual history 311
ignorance, does not really engage the scholarly tradition of “new historicism”
in musicology (with which he shares many assumptions and concerns) in his
own work, preferring to relate his analyses to the older generation of venerated
historicizing musicologists and cultural critics—like Carl Dahlhaus and especially
Theodor Adorno8 —rather than to scholars of his own generation.
Why have historians been so cautious in embracing, appropriating and
participating in the project to integrate the history of music into the history
of culture?
Two obvious answers to this question emerge from the reviewed materials.
One is the abstract formalism that has been so prevalent in the analysis of
musical works by musicologists in university music departments during the last
half century. The amount of technical expertise and sheer stubborn patience
required to comprehend analyses of the internal structures of classical music is
formidable. Yet historians are rightly cautious about writing about music in its
various historical contexts without the benefits of some non-hermetic language
for verbalizing what is actually going on within the music itself. The widely chosen
alternative is to write not so much about the music itself as about institutions that
support the composition, performance and general consumption of music; about
the individuals who compose, perform and consume; and especially about the
aesthetic and philosophical commentary that tried to provide a framework for
listening to music and construing its meaning at different times and in different
places. Even those historians who probably could cite scores and analyze the
internal dynamics of formal musical structures in a sophisticated fashion tend
to fall back on external descriptions and analyses to escape the confined space
of formal musicology and to communicate with their intended audiences. It is
noteworthy that none of the historians in the books under review actually cite
or analyze musical scores, and that, when they are not talking about the various
external factors impinging on the music, they tend to speak about musical works
that have texts (operas, lieder, cantatas, oratorios and other choral works) so
a Critical History (Berkeley: University of California Press, 2002). Leppert and McClary’s
anthology, Music and Society: The Politics of Composition, Performance and Reception
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1987) played a critical role in promoting the
development of the new historical musicology, as did their subsequent efforts to infuse
musicological analysis with conceptions of subjectivity drawn from critical theory and
post-structuralism.
8
References to Adorno are omnipresent in the new musicology. He is clearly the primary
intellectual mentor of recent attempts both to historicize musical forms and to analyze
these forms in terms of the dialectical dynamics of subjectivity. For a good summary
of the impact of Adorno on Anglo-American musicology see the introduction and
commentaries by Richard Leppert in Theodor W. Adorno, Essays on Music, selected and
with an introduction and commentary and notes by Richard Leppert (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 2002).
312 john e. toews
that the music can be talked about largely through interpretive analysis of the
structure and dynamics of the texts and of the perspectives and interactions of
the characters who sing the texts.
Another possible approach, perhaps modeled on Adorno’s supreme
confidence in his ability to say what the music was saying, is to replace discussable
descriptions or arguable citations with direct assertions about what the tones must
mean. The latter tactic probably connects to a second source of trepidation for
historians who want to include music in their analysis of the history of culture—
the widespread belief that musical experience is an experience of the ineffable,
that what music does cannot be adequately redescribed or represented in words
or images, but transcends the representational stances of speaker and observer in
other artistic media and merges subjective and objective dimensions in ways that
always elude any specific reference to, or representation of, a content beyond its
own internal structural components. From this perspective, writing about music
can quickly begin to look like, and be judged as, a series of empirically unverifiable
subjective responses to a transcendent reality that cannot be rationally described
or verbally communicated.
Both the hermetically autonomous structures of musical forms and the
ineffable, transcendent, non-referential nature of musical experience constitute
cultural constructions of the nature of music that work to isolate music from
other cultural phenomena and erect barriers against the specific contextualizing
and temporalizing methods of historical analysis and narrative mediation. At the
same time however, these ascribed characteristics of musical reality and musical
experience are historical residuals of the cultural construction of the tradition of
European classical music in the nineteenth century. They are connected to the
historical emergence of a particular kind of music at a particular time and place
and are thus themselves primary objects for historical analysis. Many historical
musicologists and cultural critics have taken note of the paradoxical nature
and ideological uses of definitions of music as a self-referential autonomous
structure of tones that somehow transcends the conditions of meaningful speech
and communication.9 The emergence of the concept of “pure” or “autonomous”
art music after 1800 was accompanied by a flood of commentary and criticism
(some of it by composers themselves, like Hector Berlioz, Robert Schumann or
Richard Wagner) that mediated between the ineffable work and its particular
historical audiences, as well as by a systematic aesthetics that provided it with
9
The classical modern account is Carl Dahlhaus, Die Idee der absoluten Musik (Kassel:
Baerenreioter Verlag, 1978); but see the more recent Daniel K. L. Chua, Absolute Music
and the Construction of Meaning (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999); and
Berthold Hoeckner, Programming the Absolute: Nineteenth-Century German Music and
the Hermeneutics of the Moment (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2002).
integrating music into intellectual history 313
10
The beginnings of the aesthetic theory of autonomous, abstract art is connected to the
emergence of the classical instrumental forms of symphony, sonata and chamber music in
the late eighteenth century in John Neubauer, The Emancipation of Music from Language:
Departure from Mimesis in Eighteenth-Century Aesthetics (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1986).
11
Michael P. Steinberg, Listening to Reason: Culture, Subjectivity and Nineteenth-Century
Music (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2004); Ian Bent, ed., Music Theory in the
Age of Romanticism (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Celia Applegate, Bach
in Berlin: Nation and Culture in Mendelssohn’s Revival of the St Matthew Passion (Ithaca:
Cornell University Press, 2005); Daniel Beller-McKenna, Brahms and the German Spirit
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2004); Mark Evan Bonds, Music as Thought:
Listening to the Symphony in the Age of Beethoven (Princeton and Oxford: Princeton
University Press, 2006); and Karen Painter, ed., Mahler and His World (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2002).
314 john e. toews
12
Steinberg, Listening to Reason, 5 ff.
13
The conference anthology edited by Jost Hermand and Gerhard Richter, Sound Figures of
Modernity: German Music and Philosophy (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 2006),
represents a sustained effort to reconstruct this tradition and, more, to sustain its viability
in the post-Adorno era.
14
Lydia Goehr, The Quest for Voice: On Music, Politics and the Limits of Philosophy (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1998), 1; original emphasis.
integrating music into intellectual history 315
15
For Mark Evan Bonds, this construction of music as an imagined narrative of the thinking
subject, as a discourse of subjectivity, a way of knowing rather than a rhetoric of speaking,
is clearly a fiction of the listener. In his view the “revolution” in music c. 1800 was really a
revolution in the aesthetic discourse about music, a change in the framework of listening
created by the critical and pedagogical activity of aesthetic theorists and music critics
rather than by composers and compositions. Beethoven’s symphonies did not create a
new way of listening—a new way of listening was created by a transformation of ideas
about subjective agency that was subsequently attached to Beethoven’s compositions. See
his Music as Thought, 5–29 and passim.
16
Steinberg, Listening to Reason, 9–11.
316 john e. toews
analysis of the nineteenth century allow historians to relate their own present
experience of the music to the ways music was experienced in the past? What is
the relationship between the history of writing about music and the history of
music? Certainly the historical description and analysis of writing about music is
easier to connect to other textually articulated forms of intellectual history than
the performance of historical subjectivity within the music itself. Music Theory
in the Age of Romanticism, a collection of essays by a dozen Anglo-American
musicologists whose education has been informed by various post-structuralist
conceptions of subjectivity, and the monograph by the music historian Mark
Evan Bonds, Music as Thought: Listening to the Symphony in the Age of Beethoven,
provide some suggestions about what might be learned from close readings of
writing about music.
Four essays in the first section of the edited collection address the ways in
which theoretical constructions of musical experience in the nineteenth century
were framed by general assumptions concerning the nature of sense experience,
intellectual cognition, the metaphysical foundations of structural relations, and
the dynamics of structural transformations in time. What comes across in
these essays first of all is the variety of philosophical frameworks informing
musical theorizing. An essay by Leslie David Blasius explores the theoretical
literature on piano pedagogy and finds it shaped by a robust survival of late
eighteenth-century sensationalist and associational psychology. His sources, as
one might guess, tend to come from French and English culture, and the study
of the piano exercises might perhaps be classified under educational theory
as much as musical theory, but it is important to remember that all musical
theory in the nineteenth century did not stem from German idealist and
Romantic philosophy, and that, as in other cultural dimensions, the conflict
and interaction of Enlightenment and Romantic traditions, utilitarian and
idealist philosophies, continued through the so-called “Romantic” period. The
three essays that follow, by Ian Biddle (on Schelling), Thomas Christensen (on
the Hegelian historicism of François-Joseph Fétis), and Sanna Pederson (on
the conflicts between Romantic and Hegelian constructions of music at mid-
century), moreover, complicate the whole issue of the idealist framework of
Romantic theory, and the Romantic theoretical framework of nineteenth-century
music. According to Biddle, Schelling’s philosophy of art articulates a model of
musical structure as organic structure in which immanent meaning emerges from
the relations between corporeal realities and the organizing totality of the absolute
subject. Biddle claims that Schelling’s ideas grounded the theory of autonomous
music and the internal structural analysis that emerged from it. But his analysis
also makes obvious that the description of autonomous, organic musical structure
was originally conceived as the embodiment of a deeper reality, that music,
like the other fine arts, was imagined as depicting, or giving corporeal shape
integrating music into intellectual history 317
to, the dynamic self-fashioning of the Absolute, that the immanent structures
of musical form gave voice to a transcendent subjectivity. If Schelling’s views
implicitly or explicitly informed the ways in which early nineteenth-century
listeners constructed musical experience then the subjectivity they enacted in
that experience was experienced as an expression of a deeper identification,
as a discovery of essence rather than as an emancipation from identity and
representation. Musical experience revealed absolute subjectivity as the ground of
individual subjectivity. This tendency is made very clear in Bonds’s reconstruction
of idealist and Romantic aesthetic philosophies—including that of Schelling.
Listening to music was presented as participation in a privileged movement
of knowing that reached toward and fleetingly embodied philosophical truth,
the truth of totalizing synthesis This truth was intimated in experiences of the
sublime that the conceptual and representational structures of empirical and
rational philosophies could never encompass.17
The essays by Christensen and Pederson, however, also indicate that Schelling’s
aesthetic philosophy and its particular way of construing musical form as the
articulation of subjectivity was in conflict throughout the first half of the century
with the Hegelian theory that subordinated musical experience to the progressive
articulation of organic totality and subjective autonomy in the self-conscious
structures of rational speech. For Hegelians like Fétis, the structures of musical
form represented particular organizations of subjectivity in historical cultures,
ordered in a progressive sequence moving toward more rational and thus more
universal articulation. As Pederson reminds us, and as Bonds tends to forget, it
is important to recognize that the so-called “Romantic” theory of autonomous
self-relating musical structure had a discontinuous history grounded in shifting
historical contexts. It was marked by conflicts with opposing perspectives.
Constructions of musical experience were historically contingent and demand
contextual analysis. At the same time, these essays on the philosophical framing
of theories of musical form reveal that, for most of the nineteenth century,
theories of self-structuring dynamic subjectivity as the appropriate form of the
arts remained theories of representation of a reality that these arts embodied and
performed, but did not constitute. In performing subjectivity, music performed
a script written elsewhere. Nineteenth-century theorists may have argued over
whether or not music performed this script better than the other arts or other
cultural forms, but they never, or rarely, doubted that music derived its power
to enact subjectivity from its function as the representation of an infinite subject
or absolute existential ground of some sort. The construction of music as the life
of a subject structuring and restructuring itself in a series of temporal “presents”
may be a useful fiction from our perspective, but the evidence provided in
17
Bonds, Music as Thought, 29–62.
318 john e. toews
these essays indicates that musical experience of subjectivity was certainly more
like a revelatory encounter with the immanent essence of existence for most
nineteenth-century European intellectuals.
The second group of essays engages in a close reading of accounts of musical
structure in exemplary classical works (symphonies of Beethoven and Berlioz)
by contemporary reviewers like E. T. A Hoffmann, Robert Schumann and
the influential contributors to the first important journal of public musical
criticism—the Allgemeine musikalische Zeitung. What is revealed in each of these
cases is that contemporary critics structured their analysis of the musical work
according to a specific mode of communicative and historical hermeneutics,
best exemplified by the theories of the Romantic theologian and cultural critic
Friedrich Schleiermacher. The music was imagined as shaped by the motives and
genius of the composer. What was experienced in the act of listening was an
interaction with Beethoven’s or Berlioz’s subjectivity, not an identification with
the musical subject per se. Or rather the musical subject was interpreted in terms
of the composer’s intentions and creative power in expressing and communi-
cating a personal conception of the underlying infinite ground of subjective
life.
Brian Heyr’s analysis of a contemporary review of Beethoven’s Eroica is
especially interesting, because he reverses the direction of the nineteenth-century
hermeneutic method he has historically reconstructed in order to develop his own
theory of constructive interpretation, in which the listener creates the meaning
of the musical structure in the process of listening and relistening. The meaning
of a piece, he claims, is constituted by a constantly shifting reinterpretation of
the narrative pattern between memory and the future as we learn to connect
our expectations to the moving musical horizons that define our experience of
being in the music. The listener in this model does not simply project subjective
meanings into the dynamics of the musical experience. What happens instead is
a type of dialogue or interaction with the increasingly familiar and predictable
narrative flow of the notes. It is this dialogic experience that turns an arbitrary
subjective construction into an experimental life shaped in a certain way by the
musical structure. But contemporaries of Beethoven or Berlioz did not construct
their musical experience in this fashion. They claimed to experience an encounter
with another subjectivity, not just an interaction with a constructed framework
(a fictional universe) for experimenting with possible identities (fictional “I’s”)
within themselves. It is this disjuncture between the construction of music as
thinking by the idealist and Romantic theorists and poststructuralist theories
of the movement of subjective agency beyond identity and representation that
is missing in Bonds’s work. One consequence is that Bonds seems hapless in
producing some understanding of how the actual musical compositions may
integrating music into intellectual history 319
18
Applegate, Bach in Berlin, 2; original emphasis.
19
This part of Applegate’s work should be read alongside David Gramit, Cultivating Music:
The Aspirations, Interests and Limits of German Musical Culture, 1770–1848 (Berkeley:
integrating music into intellectual history 321
players, teachers and publicists. The 1829 performance took place in the concert
hall of a musical academy and was performed not by a church choir or an
ensemble of court musicians but by a mix of devoted amateurs and professionals
who had emerged as a significant social component of civil society after the
reforms of the revolutionary and Napoleonic decades. The performance of
1829 and its public impact was made possible in part by the fact that both
performers and audience were prepared to imagine themselves involved in a
process of self-cultivation through artistic means. The meaning of the work
performed was mediated to an audience of educated listeners and readers through
both a well-developed musical pedagogy and ongoing public discussion in the
burgeoning print culture of journals and published writings. Applegate traces
the multiple, interacting developments through which musical performers were
gradually transformed from artisans into self-conscious artist–professionals, how
the context of performance shifted from church, court and town square to
public concert venues or the intimate settings of family life, how amateur music
associations emerged as voluntary forms of communal self-education within the
freedoms of an emerging civil society after 1800, and how journals and journalists
used the moralizing power of the fine arts as a major component of their
program of public cultivation. In all of these areas Applegate tends to emphasize
the conditions of imagining individual cultivation as an identification with the
community of the cultural “nation,” vaguely defined by overlapping linguistic,
ethnic, religious boundaries. Less forcefully presented are the attempts to ground
this identification specifically in a construction of a self-conscious relation to
a past that was not only “discovered” as different, but also rediscovered as an
expression of an essential continuity that transformed difference into identity.
The chapters where this issue is more closely addressed and which zero in more
specifically on how musical subjectivity was organized through a dialogue with
the past are the chapters that focus with more analytic and interpretive intensity
on the questions of “why Mendelssohn?”, “why Bach?” and “why the St Matthew
Passion?” In fact all three questions really merge into one. What were the reasons
for Mendelssohn’s conviction that the music of Bach was the historical foundation
of his own generation’s attempt to organize and perform their individual and
collective subjectivity through music and how did his choice, interpretation and
performance of the St Matthew Passion articulate that conviction?
University of California Press, 2002), which provides a more general, systematic and
theoretically informed analysis of the same phenomena, and critically examines the
tension between, on the one hand, the claims that musical experience was essential to the
cultivation of human subjectivity per se and, on the other, the interest in directing musical
experience toward the construction of exclusionary identities, not only of nationality, but
of class and gender as well.
322 john e. toews
relation to the past, into the conventional judgment that Mendelssohn’s music
is not that interesting, somewhat glib, and perhaps even shallow. Mendelssohn,
he says at one point, was too much a historian as a musician. He had worked
through the most important issues regarding agency and identity in relation to
the past by the time he sat down to compose his works, with the paradoxical result
that compositions that officially eschew “representation,” and transform extra-
musical realities and identities into aesthetic possibilities, ultimately turn out to
be, or are experienced as, representations of an already achieved resolution.20
My own view is that Steinberg is wrong about this and that more careful
musical analysis of what goes on in Mendelssohn’s compositions would have
made this clear. What Steinberg experiences as the presentation of already
achieved resolution is in fact a complex position of how lack of resolution,
or a tense balancing of multiple, dynamic possibilities, can be sustained by
the musical subject. In Mendelssohn’s compositions the relativity and constant
transformation of subject positions and communal identifications is sustained
by a faith in a transcendent will that both grounds subjectivity and sustains it
as subjectivity through its various transformations. In Mendelssohn’s musical
world this transcendent ground is the will of the father that must be illuminated
and discovered through an interpretation of the words of revelation. In his
claim that this “resolution” is already there when the music begins Steinberg is
right. But it is there only as an item of faith, and needs to be performed in the
music to become real. The drama of the music lies in the battle to discover and
experientially affirm the knowledge that grounds both autonomy and integration,
and to sustain that knowledge against the constant temptation to fall under the
spell of particular historical, cultural identifications that claim exclusivity and
fail to recognize the historical relativity of all specific religious and communal
identities. This is a musical historicism that differs from those of Beethoven or
Wagner, but it is a historicism that comes into being in the music, and can only
be illuminated through an analysis of the dynamic structures of Mendelssohn’s
musical compositions. This does not mean that one cannot talk or write about
it anymore than one must surrender the right to talk about the construction of a
particular historical self-consciousness in the aesthetic forms of the “I” shaping
itself in the dynamics of a novel like Madame Bovary or Bleak House. As an
aesthetic construct, the work has its own voice, as Steinberg constantly reminds
us, and that voice is usually (inevitably?) more subtle and multidimensional
than the voice of its author as we might come to know it through other textual
evidence.
20
Steinberg, Listening to Reason, 95, 122.
integrating music into intellectual history 325
interesting insights. The passages Brahms collected and used were usually stripped
of their theological content, and selected for their expression of earthly moods,
desires and hopes. In fact it would seem that according to Beller-McKenna’s
own analysis it was Brahms’s music that framed the meaning of these selections
rather than the other way around. At the same time the connections drawn
between historical contexts and musical forms, although sometimes suggestive,
often seem to fall into very broad analogies open to conflicting interpretation.
What is powerful in the book is Beller-McKenna’s ability to tease out complex
narrative patterns of structural relations through the detailed analysis of musical
form.
At the core of the book are two chapters that dissect Brahms’s well-known Ein
deutsches Requiem (Opus 45, completed in 1868) and his now virtually unknown
Triumphlied (Opus 55, 1871) as musicalizations of an apocalyptic paradigm of
historical development, first as expectation and hope and then as triumphant
fulfillment. The Requiem is conventionally related to Brahms’s personal attempts
to come to terms with and seek consolation for the personal losses of his mentor
and musical father Robert Schumann,who died in 1856, and his biological mother,
who died in 1865. From this perspective the biblical passages are appropriated and
musically framed to express the human psychology of loss, grief, commemoration
and consolation. Steinberg tends to hear the Requiem and interpret the paradigm
of transformation it performs in this way. The representation of personal grief and
the hope for external consolation through either conquest of the world or loving
acceptance by the world are “resolved” through a revelatory experience of music
itself as the site where militancy and consolation, masculine control and maternal
love, are reconciled. Beller-Mckenna, however, reads the patterns of temporal
and structural relations in the piece within a paradigm of apocalyptic cultural
transformation. Inconsolable grief and irresolvable conflict find their resolution
in the hope for a radical change within social and cultural structures of immanent
community that will create a New Jerusalem or second Paradise where the
divisions of temporal life will be dissolved in a timeless eternity. His analysis of the
music does suggest a cessation or at least partial suspension of normal temporal
order in the outer movements and an experience of alienation and longing
accompanied by intimations of promised fulfillment in the five inner movements
of the Requiem. The key to the interpretation of this apocalyptic pattern of
subjective longing and articulated hope for a home in which that longing will
finally be stilled is seen in the political context of Brahms’s composition—
the movement toward German national unification under Prussian Protestant
leadership during the 1860s.
Beller-Mckenna wants to argue that the Requiem represented Brahms’s
powerful personal identification with the German nation (as shaped by the
linguistic foundations and Protestant perspectives of the Lutheran Bible). The
integrating music into intellectual history 327
21
Beller-McKenna, Brahms and the German Spirit, 126.
328 john e. toews
this particular interpretation of how the cultural content of the formal dynamics
in Mahler’s music might be construed. Talia Becker Berio’s “Mahler’s Jewish
Parable” examines Mahler’s insider–outside status as an assimilating Jew at a
moment of increasing anti-Semitic exclusion as the foundation of his musical
performance of a subjectivity both longing for integration and resistant to the
ideological integrations that were offered. Essays by Charles Maier and Karen
Painter reveal a possible political framework for Mahler’s musical performance
of subjectivity. Maier describes how Mahler’s public roles as musical director
and conductor involved an engagement with audiences that aimed not only
to deconstruct nostalgic ideologies of reconciliation and identity, but also to
construct, in an activist, recognizably progressive manner, the listening public as
a new form of cultural community. Like Freud’s apparently paradoxical role as
the charismatic creator and director of the psychoanalytic movement and thus
fashioner of new identities for the analyzed, Mahler’s focus on the individual
psychic process of identity-formation and identity-unraveling implied the hope
for a new kind of affirmative community of the ideologically disabused. His
massive musical structures with their often simplified appeal to the psychic
conflicts of Everyman, rather than to the expert knowledge of the musical
cognescendi, thus suggested a desire to involve mass audiences in the historical
experience of subjectivity enacted in his art. Finally, an essay by Peter Franklin
on gender implications in Mahler’s musical discourse suggests that, like Freud,
Mahler imagined the organization of subjectivity as a constant exploration of
both feminine and masculine identities in the never completely resolved or fixed
gendering of subjectivity.
The four essays devoted to structural and formal analysis of specific musical
works and/or passages tend to confirm the suggestions of the contextual essays.
In this case at least, historical analysis of the extra-musical context of the worlds
in which Mahler composed, performed and was performed, and formal analysis
of the autonomous musical universes within which he explored the interaction
between subjectivity and identity, cooperate, or at least interact, in ways that open
up convincing interpretations of the meaning of the works. Essays by Camilla
Bork and Peter Revers on Mahler’s settings for Friedrich Rueckert’s lyrical poetry
suggest that Mahler’s contextually defined personal crisis and transformation
in 1901 produced a shift in musical form that is consistent with Steinberg’s
claim of a turn toward a disillusioned, self-reflective, ironic stance in relation
to possibilities of identity and resolution as well as toward the construction
of aesthetic affirmations of inconclusive, interminable subjectivity. A study of
Mahler’s late style by Stephen Helfling confirms this pattern. The overall effect
on the reader is that Mahler’s musical works, like the novels of Musil, Mann or
Proust, are an integral part of the history of subjectivity as it evolves from the
emancipation of the modern subject, through the transformations and crises
integrating music into intellectual history 331
22
There is an insightful comparative analysis of the role of modernist irony in Mann and
Mahler in Walter Frisch, German Modernism: Music and the Arts (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 2005), 186–213.