Fabb Nigel Compounding
Fabb Nigel Compounding
3 Compounding
NIGEL FABB
1 Overview
A compound is a word which consists of two or more words. For example, the
Malay compound mata-hari ‘sun’ is a word which consists of two words: mata
‘eye’ and hari ‘day’. Compounds are subject to phonological and morpholo-
gical processes, which may be specific to compounds or may be shared with
other structures, whether derived words or phrases; we explore some of these,
and their implications, in this chapter. The words in a compound retain a
meaning similar to their meaning as isolated words, but with certain restric-
tions; for example, a noun in a compound will have a generic rather than a
referential function: as Downing (1977) puts it, not every man who takes out
the garbage is a garbage man.
aigre-doux (sour-sweet)
1.1.3 The semantic relations between the parts The semantic relations
between the parts of a compound can often be understood in terms of modifica-
tion; this is true even for some exocentric compounds like redhead. Modifier–
modifiee relations are often found in compounds which resemble equivalent
phrases; this is true, for example, of English AN%N1 compounds and many
Mandarin compounds (see Anderson 1985b). It is not always the case, though;
the French compound est-allemand (East German) corresponds to a phrase
allemand de l’est (German from the East). In addition, many compounds mani-
fest relations which can be interpreted as predicator–argument relations, as in
68 Nigel Fabb
expert-test-ed
checker-play-ing (as an adjective: a checker-playing king)
window-clean-ing (as a noun)
meat-eat-er
right-hand member. We discuss this in section 3.2. There have been many
accounts of synthetic compounds, including Roeper and Siegel 1978, Selkirk
1982, Lieber 1983, Fabb 1984, Botha 1981 on Afrikaans, and Brousseau 1988 on
Fon; see also section 2.1.2. Many of the relevant arguments are summarized in
Spencer 1991.
The part which is not attested as an isolated word is sometimes found in other
words as well; in some cases it may become an attested word: for example, telly
70 Nigel Fabb
(= television). These parts fail to resemble affixes morphologically (they are relat-
ively unproductive compared to most affixes), and there is no good evidence
on phonological grounds for considering them to be affixes. They are also
unlike affixes semantically; judging by their contribution to the word’s mean-
ing, they have lexical rather than grammatical meanings. A similar example
from standard Tamil (Steever 1988) is the form nA[ ‘goodness’, which is not
independently attested, but can be found in compound nouns such as nalla-nA[
‘good-day’.
One thing that is reasonably clear about the structure of compounds is that
they contain two words, and the distinctness of these two components is vis-
ible to various rules. Other aspects of structure are not so obvious, however:
in the order of the parts regulated by rules 2.1, are their word classes visible
to any rules 2.2, and are three-word compounds hierarchically structured (2.3)?
2.1 Directionality
A compound can be ‘directional’ in two senses. One sense involves the posi-
tion of the head: whether on the right or the left. The other sense involves the
direction of the relation between the parts of the compound: the direction of
modification in a noun–noun compound (e.g. in log cabin modification is right-
wards) or the direction of complementation in a verb-based compound (e.g. in
push-bike complementation is rightwards). Notice that the two senses of direc-
tionality can be independent, because a compound can have internal modifica-
tion or complementation without having a head: killjoy has no head, but it does
have a predicator–complement order. This is an important descriptive issue;
some accounts assume that a modifier–modifee or predicator–argument rela-
tion inside a compound is itself evidence that part of the compound is a head.
To the extent that there are any useful claims about directionality of the head
to be made, it is probably best to focus on the narrowest definition of head
(which involves a semantic link between head and whole); see Brousseau 1988
for arguments to this effect.
2.1.1 The location of the head In English, the head of an endocentric word
is on the right. In French, the head is on the left (as in bal masqué, ‘masked
ball’). It has been argued (e.g. by DiSciullo and Williams 1987) that all true
endocentric compounds are right-headed, and that any left-headed compounds
should be considered as exceptions – for example, as phrases which have been
reanalysed as words. This is not a widely accepted account (it is based on the
controversial Right-Hand Head rule of Williams 1981b).
Compounding 71
—modifies→
meat-eater
←takes as complement—
(a)
It is not obvious that the interpretive facts alone demonstrate the presence
of a complex structure. The interpretive rules might simply pick any pair of
adjacent units and make them into a unit, taking a ‘syntactic’ structure like (a)
and building a ‘semantic’ structure like (b) or (c). Compare hierarchical phrase
structure, which pre-exists any interpretive strategy, as can be shown by the
sensitivity of syntactic processes (such as binding theory) to constituent struc-
ture. But compounds are relatively inert compared to syntactic constituents
(no movement, anaphoric coindexing, etc.), so it is harder to find supporting
evidence for complex constituent structure.
As we will see (section 5.1.1), there is some evidence in English from the
stressing of four-word compounds that the compound-specific stress rules are
sensitive to a subconstituent structure, and hence that such structure exists
outside the interpretive component. Turkish also presents evidence for sub-
constituent structure in hierarchically interpreted compounds (Spencer 1991).
The ‘indefinite izafet compound’ has the structure Noun + Noun-poss. when
it consists of two words. The three-part compound has one of two types of
structure, each corresponding to a different interpretation of its hierarchical
structure (as bracketed):
Baoyu qu-lei-le ma
Baoyu ride-tired-asp horse
‘Baoyu rode a horse (and as a result it/Baoyu got) tired’
The resultative verb compound here is qu-lei. The first verb describes an action
‘ride’; the second verb characterizes the result of that action as a state, ‘tired’,
of the compound verb’s subject (Baoyu) or object (that horse). The compound
verb thus inherits theta-role-assigning properties from the component verbs.
This is one reason for thinking that the internal structure of the compound
may be visible in the syntax. Another reason comes from the fact that the first
verb can be duplicated and followed by the object, so that the above sentence
has this as an alternative form:
Baoyu qu ma qu-lei-le
and compounds:
The two kinds of word can be seen as two kinds of compound. Both kinds of
compound have word-like phonology (e.g. both have a single primary stress)
and morphology (e.g. both are pluralized in the same way). Neither com-
pound can be extracted from. The difference between them is that construct
state nominals are more transparent interpretively and syntactically than other
compounds; for example, definiteness and plurality on the components of
a construct state nominal are taken into account by sentence-interpretation
rules. Borer argues that the distinction should be achieved by having word-
formation rules in the lexicon (to build ordinary compounds) or in the syntax
(to build construct state nominals). A word built in the syntax will have its
components visible to syntactic processes.
zikken-syuuryoo-go
experiment-finish-after = ‘after the experiment was completed’
with phrases; and others isolate compounds as a distinct class. Most recent
discussions of these groupings have been in a Lexical Morphology/Phonology
framework, and have been used to argue for a level-ordering of morphological
and phonological processes (see section 5.2 for an illustration).
5.4.2 Inflectional morphology There have been two lines of research focus-
ing on whether an inflectional morpheme (e.g. marking plurality, case or tense)
can be found on a component word inside a compound.
One approach (e.g. Kiparsky 1982b) focusing on the question of level-
ordering of morphological processes, looks at the distinction between regular
and irregular inflectional morphology, and asks whether irregular morphology
is more likely to appear on a compound-internal word (because it precedes the
compounding process) than regular morphology (which comes later than the
compounding process). The evidence from English is not particularly clear. As
82 Nigel Fabb
5.4.4 Clitics and compounds Dakota postverbal clitics are attached in the
lexicon (Shaw 1985). They attach to the first member of syntactic compounds,
but not to the first member of lexical compounds.
6 Conclusion
(a) If there are compound-building rules, what form do they take? Are
they recursive (i.e. building hierarchical structure), and do they take
word class into account? Are compound-building rules based on a
universally available rule type (i.e. is ‘compound’ a universal?).
Compounding 83
NOTE