Hegels Metaphysics Changing The Debate
Hegels Metaphysics Changing The Debate
J am es Kreines
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6): 466-480 .
And it is safe to say that recent work on Hegel’s theoretical philosophy lacks
philosophical issues they are m eant to address. There can be no question here of
com plete and even-handed coverage of the m any interpretive subvarieties and
debates between them all. There are, however, two general approaches broadly
approach and those favoring a newer “non-m etaphysical” approach. But I argue
that the m ost im portant and com pelling points m ade by both sides are actually
itself sim ply unconvincing. The m ost prom ising directions for future research, for
those on both sides of recent debates, will require recognizing that Hegel’s
The first general approach popular in recent work is the m ore traditional of
the two; I will call it traditionalism , following Redding (20 0 2). I think this
general view is best introduced in term s of the idea that Hegel aim s to revive and
to what Spinoza calls “substance” or “God.” Spinoza claim s that “from God’s
suprem e power, or infinite nature … all things, have necessarily flowed” (Ethics
IP17S1). And Hegel sim ilarly holds that “the absolute” determ ines, grounds, or
substance with the em phasis on freedom in Kant and later idealists.1 But at this
straightforward and vivid story is that Hegel sees substance itself as a m ind or
1For an excellent English-language version of the this version of the history of the developm ent of
post-Kantian idealism , see “Part II” of Henrich’s 1973 lectures at Harvard (20 0 3).
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 3
encom passing “cosm ic spirit” (1975, 87ff.). This idea certainly provides a natural
3:28/ 14).
sum m arize clearly. The basic idea is that everything real is determ ined by a
fundam ental organizing principle of the whole, which interpreters often call a
basic “structure.” This is supposed to be what Hegel him self refers to as “the
natural and m ental phenom ena. But this “structure” is best or m ost com pletely
freedom . Rolf Horstm ann and Frederick Beiser are two, of m any, advocates of
Robert Pippin’s Hegel’s Idealism (1989); Robert Brandom and Terry Pinkard
have long been working along broadly sim ilar lines. The basic view is best
project is sim ilar to Kant's attem pt to account for the conditions of the possibility
2 I follow here especially the version proposed by Horstm ann; see especially his discussion of a
“prim ary structure” (1991, 177-82) and the sim ilar form ulation at (1998/ 20 0 4; Part 4). And see
Beiser (1993 and 20 0 5). See also Stern (1990 , especially pp. 110 -119) and Wartenberg (1993).
Kreines, Changing the Debate 4
the source of the legitim acy or norm ative authority of these form s of thought; for
exam ple, Hegel follows what Brandom describes as a Kantian “shift in attention
idealists about Kant’s sharp distinction between concept and intuition. Hegel
determ inate cognition or thought about objects, without assum ing that
supposed to send Hegel in two m ain new directions. First, he defends a form of
holism according to which the “form s of thought” depend for their determ inate
identity on their places within a larger whole or network. And, second, Hegel
argues that the conditions of the possibility of determ inate cognition of objects
“Geist” is fundam ental in Hegel’s theoretical philosophy, but this term does not
social life.7
sim ply be whether Hegel is m ore sim ilar to Kant or to Spinoza, as he will likely be
sim ilar to each in different respects. The question is, what specific respect is at
issue? The answer can seem to be this: one approach sees Hegel as offering an
account of what really or even absolutely exists; the other sees Hegel as
schem es. Insofar as they see the debate in this way, friend and foe alike tend to
The term “m etaphysics” can, of course, be used in m any different ways, but
the idea of a “non-m etaphysical” reading of Hegel gains m uch of its substance
from the work of Klaus Hartm ann, whose term s are adopted by m ore recent
to the determ inant of others” (1972, 124 and 110 ). These form ulations suggest a
natural way for us to use the term “m etaphysics,” which I will adopt here:
My own view is that this general idea of a “non-m etaphysical” Hegel is only
interpretations; be that as it m ay, however, this specific idea has attracted a great
deal of criticism .8 And it is easy to see why. After all, if anything com es through
8 More recent interpreters som etim es say that they seek new interpretations which differ but
rem ain “non-m etaphysical” (Pippin 1989, 6). Brandom em ploys different but sim ilar term s: Hegel
follows a Kantian “shift in attention from ontological questions … to deontological ones” (1999,
Kreines, Changing the Debate 6
clearly in Hegel’s texts it is the great extent of his philosophical am bitions. Surely
these include the am bition to defend an account of what truly or really exists. If
that point is not already clear enough in the Phenom enology , then it is even
“what … the thing in itself is in truth” or “what is truly in itself” (WL 5:130 / 121).
Furtherm ore, Hegel does address different kinds of existences and the relations
between them . He does so, for exam ple, in his discussions of “Mechanism ,”
“Teleology,” and “Life” at a crucial point at the conclusion of the Logic.9 Finally, it
is sim ply hard to believe that Hegel’s attem pt to account for som ething called
non-m etaphysical term s, setting aside those Hegelian aspirations which do not fit
schem es to an account of what truly or really exists? Perhaps at one tim e this
orthodoxy.10 To seek to defend such views is fair enough. But it is hard to see why
we should view Hegel through the lens of this particular contem porary am bition,
165-6). For som e persuasive criticism s see Horstm ann (1984, 47) on Hartm ann; Siep (1991) on
Pippin (1989); and Beiser (1995) on the approach of Hartm ann and his followers.
9 One indication that these sections are crucial is that they are found im m ediately before and
im m ediately after “The Idea”; these sections help to explain Hegel’s claim s about that central
term , and provide arguments for his claim s. I say m ore about Hegel on the priority of teleology
over m echanism in Kreines (20 0 4).
10See Am eriks’ (20 0 0 , 11) sim ilar point about non-m etaphysical approaches to Kant and post-
Kantians.
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 7
Sim ilarly, we should be wary of the idea that a fault-line between m etaphysical
rather than an artifact created by viewing Hegel through the lens of com m itm ents
by renouncing the term “non-m etaphysical” and stressing instead the idea of a
m etaphysical Hegel? I think we can, and that doing so is the best way to
appreciate the m ost prom ising avenues open for further advancing and defending
nontraditional approaches.
What then are the other, m ore im portant and pressing, issues raised in
recent debates about Hegel’s theoretical philosophy? These can best be brought
into focus by considering Hegel’s relation ship to Kant. In short, Kant fam ously
things as they are “in them selves.” All should agree that Hegel seeks to overturn
this restriction, or to establish knowledge which is not lim ited in this way—to
establish knowledge of “what is truly in itself” (WL 5:130 / 121). But there are two
While I will return to consider traditionalism in m ore detail below, the basic
11See the first footnote in Pinkard (1999). Also, Pinkard’s com pelling (1996) defense of Hartmann
and “non-m etaphysical” approaches, for exam ple, offers no defense of the idea that Hegel offers a
m etaphysically-neutral analysis of concepts; Pinkard instead refocuses attention on the core idea
that Hegel aim s to com plete Kant’s critical project, rather than to revive specifically pre-critical
form s of m etaphysics.
Kreines, Changing the Debate 8
Kant’s lim its. For exam ple, Kant argues that we cannot have theoretical
Hegel asserts knowledge, beyond Kant’s lim its, that there is such a highest being:
elim inate Kant’s lim its, or to erase those lim its from within. That is, Kant denies
critical m etaphysics, and Hegel agrees. But Hegel takes Kant’s denial farther:
Hegel aim s to justify the conditions of the possibility of thought about objects in a
m anner which will deny or undercut the idea that these conditions m ight block
knowledge, though it is conditioned, is not lim ited or restricted. And the “form s
of thought” which condition our knowledge do not m erely articulate the way
objects appear to us; they are supposed to articulate the way things really or
absolutely are. For exam ple, Pippin portrays Hegel as aim ing to elim inate Kant’s
lim itation of our knowledge by arguing that “‘thought determ inations of the real’
… are what it is to be real.” Or, Hegel tries to argue that “what initially can only
be our way of taking up, discrim inating, categorizing the world” can “som ehow
12 Pippin (1989, 83) and (1993, 287) respectively. On the later form ulation, see Stern’s
(forthcoming) response. McDowell, though not focused specifically on Hegel interpretation, offers
an interesting form ulation of the general point: “it is central to Absolute Idealism to reject the
idea that the conceptual realm has an outer boundary” (1994, 44). Redding is another
nontraditionalist who advances broadly sim ilar claims in a com pelling m anner. See Redding
(20 0 2, 3.2).
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 9
ground absolute form s of thought, it will itself be the absolute. Or, perhaps Hegel
thinks that this form of subjectivity m ust be accounted for in term s of a yet m ore
basic “structure” of historically developing form s of social life (or “Geist”); if so,
then knowledge of the absolute would be achieved by, as Brandom says, “m aking
Note what m akes this strand of nontraditionalism m ore com pelling than the
not that Hegel rejects m etaphysical questions about the real or absolute nature of
and the source of their legitim acy, norm ativity, etc. The com pelling idea is rather
that Hegel pursues som e kind of consideration concepts and legitim acy which is
But what specifically are Hegel’s “thought determ inations of the real”? And,
m ore generally, what distinctive conclusions does Hegel advocate concerning the
way things really or absolutely are? The m ost prom ising ways to further develop
would be im plausible to say that Hegel seeks to justify certain “form s of thought”
13Both Pippin (1989, 18) and Brandom (1999, 168) stress Hegel’s praise of Kant’s “original
synthetic unity of apperception” at WL 6:254/ 584.
14So this strand of nontraditionalism can recognize and m ake sense of Hegel’s ambition to
em ploy som e new form of logic to resolve old questions about m etaphy sics. See e.g. EL §9An.
Kreines, Changing the Debate 10
as them selves “determ inations of the real,” but has nothing further to say about
w hich form s or determ inations—or about what reality, so-determ ined, is like.
And on this specific terrain nontraditionalists cannot lean on a com parison with
Kant. For the content of Hegel’s “determ inations of the real” is supposed to differ
com plains, for exam ple, about Kant’s claim “that cognition has no other form s of
thought than finite categories.”15 And Hegel does not seek a new justification for
Kant’s account of the extent of our knowledge, adding only the negative point
that it is illegitim ate to even conceive of anything beyond that extent. Nor does
Hegel sim ply borrow Kant’s account of a causally-determ ined realm of spatio-
tem poral appearances and argue that this is all there is to reality itself.
departure from Kant: they em phasize, as noted above, Hegel’s holism and his
account of Geist. Both will lead nontraditionalists into debates about the specific
character of Hegel’s m etaphysics. Consider holism first. Som e form s of sem antic
exam ple, the form er m ight hold, without saying anything about reality itself, that
our concepts depend for their m eanings on their places within a larger whole,
that Hegel’s “form s of thought” are “determ inations of the real” or “what it is to
be real” (Pippin 1989, 83). So if Hegel has a holistic account of the “form s of
thought,” then this would have to include a m etaphysical dim ension; it would
have to involve som e form of the idea that, for real things them selves, “what it is
15 WL 6:261/ 589; Also e.g. EL §62An. See also Hegel’s responses to Kant’s Antinom ies. For
exam ple: it is wrong for Kant and post-Kantians to assum e “that cognition has no other form s of
thought than finite categories” (WL 5:216/ 191 and also WL 5:270 ff.234ff.; VGP
20 :351ff./ 3:448ff). On the im portance of this Hegelian am bition to extend our knowledge beyond
Kant’s lim its, see Stern (1999, section V).
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 11
to be real” depends on their place within som e larger whole or network. That
would certainly be a substantial claim about the way things really or absolute are,
and it certainly could be argued that this claim is Hegel’s. But this raises a further
holism differ from the m onism traditionally attributed to Hegel? That is, how
sem antics and conceptual schem es, epistem ology and webs of belief, etc. The
concerning the specific content of Hegel’s m etaphy sics. In what specific sense are
real things them selves dependent? What is the specific nature of the w hole or
philosophically crucial respects from Spinoza’s answers, and from the answers
Som e nontraditionalists m ight wish to resist the dem and for answers to
pointing out that Hegel rejects som e pre-critical form ulations of m etaphysical
questions. For exam ple, Hegel dism isses the questions of pre-critical rational
psychology, which are supposed to illegitim ately treat Geist (m ind or spirit) “as a
thing.”16 But Hegel’s ultim ate goal here clearly is not Kantian in spirit: Hegel does
not aim to establish a lim itation of our knowledge; he aim s to overcom e such
lim itations and to establish knowledge of reality and the absolute. So he certainly
16See §389, §389Zu, §379Zu, §34Zu; VGP 19:199/ 2:181. On this point see especially DeVries
(1988) and Wolff (1991).
Kreines, Changing the Debate 12
does not hold that all m etaphysical questions in all form ulations are
unanswerable. For exam ple, if Hegel is a holist, then he m ust have answers to
questions about the nature of the whole, its parts, and their real relations. And,
m ore generally, the defense of any com pelling nontraditional approach cannot
rest without specifying which m etaphysical questions Hegel does engage, how
Hegel’s answ ers differ from traditional portrayals. Perhaps in this way Hegel’s
m etaphysics, such as Spinoza’s m onism . But, again, m aking that case would
to differentiate it.
The point applies sim ilarly to nontraditionalists’ stress on the idea that
Geist—in the sense of our own historically developing form s of social life—is
pragm atism .17 But surely not to any non-m etaphy sical form of antirealism or
pragm atism , lim ited to claim s about (e.g.) epistem ology or sem antics. For
exam ple, Hegel’s view cannot be just that the “form s of thought” inherent in our
concepts, language, standards or form s of social life determ ine what can
m eaningfully count as real for us—without involving any m etaphysical claim , any
claim about reality itself, or (as som e critics of realism put it) any claim about an
17 On antirealism see Pippin (1989; 99, 262, and 267); on pragm atism see Brandom (1999).
18 Citations from Putnam (1982, 147); see also the concluding claim that m etaphysics is
“overwhelm ingly unlikely” to be revived (165). Granted, there are nearly endless varieties of
antirealism and realism debated today, and perhaps m ore than one way to understand Putnam ’s
claim s here. But I see the controversies concerning what antirealism and realism are, and what
issues are at stake there, as excellent reason to cut out the contem porary m iddleman and focus
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 13
them selves, at least in their m ore com pelling form ulations, hold that Hegel’s
Geist and the “form s of thought” m akes Geist so fundam ental for Hegel, then
they need an account of the m etaphysical dim ension of this relation—an account
of a real relationship between Geist (som ething real, even if not “a thing” in som e
sense) and reality generally (or “what it is to be real”). And they need to explain
how this relationship differs from traditional portrayals, such as those on which
In sum , nontraditionalists have prom ising avenues open to them for the
further developm ent and defense of their approach to Hegel, whether they stress
Hegel’s holism , his account of Geist, or som e com bination. But what these
avenues will require m ost of all are defenses of nontraditional accounts of Hegel’s
m etaphy sics. My own view is that especially prom ising indications of the
directions in which nontraditionalists can advance their case in this way can be
m ore directly at Hegel. See also Pippin on how Hegel’s antirealism itself am ounts to a kind of
realism involving claim s about reality “as it is in itself” (1989, 99).
19Nontraditionalists tend to worry that a m etaphysical dependence claim would result in an
unappealing form of m etaphysical idealism , suggesting their could be no reality without us; they
seek to differentiate Hegel’s views; see Pippin (1993, 65 and 20 0 1) and Brandom (20 0 1, 82). For
an interesting com bination of a traditional account of the dependence or positing relation with a
nontraditional account of Geist as our historically developing form s of social life, see Forster’s
interpretation: Hegel thinks that truth itself depends on enduring com m unal consensus, and that
we consequently have a “radical freedom , or power to determ ine what is the case quite generally”
(1998, 242).
20 Brandom 20 0 1, 69. See also Westphal on Hegel’s “ontological holism ” (1989, Ch. 10 ). And see
Redding’s suggestive rem ark about a respect in which Hegel is “at variance with the Spinozistic
form of holism on which Schelling had drawn” (1996, 10 8-9).
Kreines, Changing the Debate 14
beyond Kant’s lim its, rather than elim inating or erasing those lim its from the
content provided by sensible intuition.21 This lim its us to knowledge within the
bounds of sensibility or experience, or the bounds delim ited by the form s of our
sensible intuition—space and tim e. Kant will argue that this allows knowledge of
appearances but not of things as they are in them selves. Such knowledge would
require a higher kind of intellect. It would require a non-sensible intuition
Kant som etim es further suggests that this sort of im m ediacy would be possible
only for a divine intellect, specifically in the sense of an intellect whose own
cognitions were “archetypes,” the very ground or source of the reality of the
objects known.23 Kant denies that we can have any knowledge of the existence of
such a divine intellect (e.g. A277-8/ B333-4). But he stresses the im portance of its
conceivability: for exam ple, “in the Critique of Pure Reason we had to have in
m ind another possible intuition if we were to hold our own to be a special kind,
nam ely one that is valid of objects m erely as appearances” (KU 5:40 6).
Traditionalists tend to see Hegel as arguing that (i) there really is such a
higher non-discursive form of intellect; (ii) there really is som e highest thing or
21Our understanding “can only think and m ust seek the intuition in the senses” (B135). To extend
m y knowledge, “I m ust have besides the concept of the subject something else (X) upon which the
understanding m ay rely” (B12), and m y source for this “som ething else” m ust be sensible
intuition.
22In the first Critique, see for exam ple A49/ B72, A252/ B30 9, A279/ B335. For a broader
sum m ary of the different senses of “intellectual intuition” in Kant, see Gram (1981).
23 See e.g. B68 and Gram (1981, 291).
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 15
aspect of reality which can be known only thereby; and (iii) we ourselves can
What does this have to do with m onism ? Kant argues that our discursive
synthesis could never be com pleted.24 Here too we can conceive of an intellect not
lim ited in this way, capable of cognition grasping together im m ediately the parts,
no m atter how com plex, of a larger whole; Kant’s m ost direct and extended
found in an infinite and unified whole of everything, and that we can gain
knowledge of this absolute by achieving som ething sim ilar to Kant’s “intuitive
understanding.”25
This general approach raises com plex issues concerning the developm ent of
Hegel’s philosophy and his relationships to his contem poraries. To m ake a long
story very short, the clearest supporting evidence is found in Hegel’s earliest
publications, from 180 1 and 180 2. Here Hegel certainly does seem to claim that
defending the philosophy of his friend and collaborator Schelling. But Hegel and
Schelling fall out shortly thereafter. And in later publications, beginning with the
180 7 Phenom enology of Spirit, Hegel consistently em phasizes extrem ely sharp
then should we still see him as aspiring to knowledge of a highest being accessible
Traditionalists answer in the affirm ative. They portray the changes in Hegel’s
writings as a reflection of his developm ent of a new way of m eeting m ore or less
Schelling, and perhaps owing m uch to the influence of Germ an rom anticism .
More specifically, the changes involve a new term inology for stating, and a new
way of justifying, the basic claim that there is a higher form of intellect and an all-
grasping reality im m ediately ; but such claim s always beg the question, because
m ature Hegel com es to think, as Harris puts it, that “‘intuition’ m ust be resolved
into a truly speculative m ethod of discursive reasoning” (1993, 44). If so, then
26PhG 3:23/ 10 . Hegel does not nam e Schelling here, and there is room for dispute about whether
Schelling’s account of “intellectual intuition” is his target. But Hegel will later apply the basic
com plaint here to Schelling specifically (VGP 20 :421 ff.). For m ore on Hegel’s developm ent and
his developing relationship to Schelling, see Baum (1986), especially his basic gloss at (32-3) and
on the “disappearance of intuition” (225 ff.). On this disappearance of intuition, see also Harris
(1993, 44) and Beiser (1993, 18).
27 Beiser (20 0 5) stresses an approach to Hegel via Schelling (59 f.) and Germ an rom anticism (34
f.), though he also em phasizes Hegel’s later rejection of intuition (14 and 169 f.). See also the
recent accounts of the continuity of Hegel’s basic goals in Longuenesse (20 0 0 ) and Franks (20 0 5,
6.4).
28 Citations from PhG 15/ 4. For the clearest presentations of the criticism here, see especially
Hegel’s criticism s of Schelling at VGP 20 :434-5/ 3:525 and the extended discussion of Hegel’s
contem poraries at EL §61 ff. On this criticism see especially Westphal (20 0 0 ).
Philosophy Com pass 1:5 (20 0 6) 17
seeks to lim it him self to claim s which can be justified by entirely discursive
m eans; so how could he seek to conclude that there is a highest being which is
the lim its of the discursive understanding? Traditionalists need to show that a
m ore com plex view of the m atter resolves this apparent tension. Or they need to
shift toward a portrayal on which Hegel argues that the absolute can be known
discursively; but the latter approach would be a huge step toward the central
claim of recent nontraditionalists: Hegel does not seek to surpass Kant’s lim its,
or the lim its of the discursive understanding, but rather to elim inate the idea that
som e m ost fundam ental thing or aspect of reality m ight exceed these lim its.29
Traditionalists often see Hegel as always assum ing the possibility of the very
sort of m etaphysics which Kant criticizes.30 So they could say that Hegel’s
discursive reasoning begins from this assum ption, proceeding to the conclusions
that a highest being of interest in such m etaphysics m ust really exist, and that we
m ust have the capacities required to know this absolute. But to dispute Kant’s
views by first assum ing the contrary of the conclusion for which Kant actually
argues would be to beg the question, and m anifestly so. How could that be m eant
which Hegel him self com plains about in his contem poraries? This worry has
29See especially Pippin on Hegel’s developm ent an d relation to Schelling (1989, ch. 4). Also
Redding: “the very opposition that Kant has between finite hum an thought and infinite godly
thought is suspect” (20 0 2, section 3.2; also 1996, 23-4).
30 See e.g. Düsing: “the possibility of scientific m etaphysics, which Kant examines critically, is
accepted without question” (1983, 421) and also (Düsing 1976, 119). And Guyer (1993, 171-2 and
20 4-5). And Siep (20 0 0 , 18-21).
Kreines, Changing the Debate 18
argum ents are supposed to m eet the standards Hegel him self em ploys in
and his relation to Schelling (1989, ch. 4)—one which dovetails with a
traditional understanding of Hegel’s views and their developm ent with new
prom ising recent approach can be found in Longuenesse’s (20 0 0 ) account of how
try to justify his claim s. Another can be found in Paul Franks’ (20 0 5) new
account of how Schelling’s argum ents function, and of how Hegel follows
Schelling (371 ff.). And yet another can be found in Horstm ann’s (20 0 6) account
m etaphysical m onism .
5. Co n clu s io n
In sum , interpreters of all persuasions should look beyond debates about the
Hegel’s m etaphysics. For exam ple, are traditionalists right to see Hegel’s
Spinoza, or akin to those objects which (Kant argues) could be known only by a
And there is one final advantage to be gained by this shift in focus. The old
respects. If so, then the very best future interpretations m ight turn out to be those
which can recognize and integrate the advantages of both traditional and
31 I would like to acknowledge the helpful suggestions of an anonymous reader for this journal.
Kreines, Changing the Debate 20
Oth e r W o rks
Baum , M. 1990 . “Kants Prinzip der Zweckm äßigkeit und Hegels Realisierung des
Begriffs”, in Hegel und die Kritik der Urteilskraft. Ed. H. F. Fulda and R.
P. Horstm ann. Stuttgart: Friedrich From m ann Verlag.
Beiser, F.C. 1993. “Introduction: Hegel and the Problem of Metaphysics”, in The
Cam bridge Com panion to Hegel. Cam bridge: Cam bridge University Press.
Beiser, F.C. 1995. “Hegel, a non-m etaphysician? A Polem ic”, Bulletin of the Hegel
Society of Great Britain 32: 1-13.
Düsing, K. 1976. Das Problem der Subjektiv ität in Hegels Logik. Hegel-Studien.
Beiheft 15. Bonn: Felix Meiner.
Horstm ann, R. P. 1984. Ontologie Und Relationen : Hegel, Bradley , Russell Und
Die Kontroverse Uber Interne Und Externe Beziehungen. Konigstein/ Ts.:
Athenaum : Hain.
Horstm ann, R. P. 1991. Die Grenzen der Vernunft. Eine Untersuchung zu Zielen
und Motiven des Deutschen Idealism us, Frankfurt am Main: Anton Hain.
Pippin, R. 1989. Hegel’s Idealism . Cam bridge: Cam bridge University Press.
Putnam , H. 1982. “Why There Isn't A Ready-Made World”, Sy nthese 51: 141-167.
Spinoza, B. 1994. A Spinoza Reader, ed. and trans. Edwin Curley. Princeton.
Stern, R. 1990 . Hegel, Kant and the Structure of the Object. London: Routledge.
Stern, R. Forthcom ing. “Hegel’s Idealism ”, in Cam bridge Com panion to Hegel,
2nd Edition. Frederick Beiser (ed). Cam bridge: Cam bridge University
Press.