Appendix: Rawls'S Theory of Justice
Appendix: Rawls'S Theory of Justice
extensive liberty compatible with a like liberty for all. And there
seems to be no way at all of defending the thesis that it is a
necessary condition for a social institution to be just that it
satisfies this condition. Suppose you continue to stretch 'liberty'
out of recognition. Then whatever particular criterion you
take for deciding whether two people are equal, you might
still find that if they had the most extensive liberty compatible
with their having equal liberty, they would have an amount of
liberty whose value was unequal to the value of their attributes,
i.e. in the terms of Chapter 2, you could find that my condition
(C) was violated. In particular, you could say that a practice
or a social institution was unjust because it gave equals an
equal amount of liberty, but each person more liberty than he
deserved.
Nor will narrowing down the sense ofliberty be of any help.
For in the first place it will then not necessarily be equal
liberty that equals must have if a situation is to be just; there is
an indefinite number of other criteria for deciding whether
the effects of a situation on people are equally valuable. And
secondly, even if we do choose this particular criterion for the
evaluation of effects, you could again say that a social institu-
tion was unjust because it gave equals an equal amount of
liberty but each person more than he deserved. For instance,
you could claim that a law was unjust because it prescribed a
disproportionately small term of imprisonment for a certain
type of crime.
So in general, and even if we ignore Rawls's insistence that
the liberty which equals enjoy must be not merely equal but
the most extensive compatible with its equal distribution, it
seems impossible to wring more than one necessary condition
for one not very popular sense of 'just' out of his two prin-
ciples.
But in the last resort, the question of what 'just' means is of
course unimportant. What is important is to formulate various
possible moral principles clearly, and ask questions about their
justification or unavoidability, their popularity and their
particular implications. Once this has been done, it doesn't
matter what names these principles are given. The acceptance
of a faulty description of the meaning of 'just' could initially
divert one's attention from that particular range of possible
moral principles in which the concept of justice is employed.
APPENDIX 77
But once a correct description of the concept has revealed these
possibilities, one can afford to recognise that even a faulty
description of the concept can reveal other possible moral
principles, as worthy of investigation as principles of justice
themselves.
Bibliographical Note
Rawls's theory of justice is set out in: 'Justice as Fairness', Philosophical
Review, LXVII (I958) I64-g4; 'The Sense of Justice', Philosophical Review,
LXXII (I963) 28I-305; 'Constitutional Liberty and the Concept of Justice',
Nomos, VI (I963) 98--I25; and 'Distributive Justice', in P. Laslettand W. G.
Runciman (eds), Philosophy, Politics and Society, 3rd series (Oxford, I967).
Rawls's ideas are applied to particular social questions by W. G. Runciman
in Relative Deprivation and Social Justice (I966) and '"Social" Equality',
Philosophical Quarter[y, XVII (I967) 22I-30.
Apart from Rawls's writings, the most influential recent works are Ch.
Perelman, The Idea of Justice and the Problem of Argument (I963), H. L. A.
Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford, I96I), W. K. Frankena, Some Beliefs about
Justice (Lawrence, Kansas, I966) and Nicholas Rescher, Distributive Justice
(Indianapolis, I966). Rescher comes closer to the principal contentions of
Chapter 2 of the present book than the other three authors, and is very
much less vague than they are about the logical relations between various
general or formal necessary conditions for the application of 'just', and
about the degree of Spielraum which these conditions allow in the choice
of specific criteria for deciding such questions as whether people are
relevantly equal. J. G. H. Newfield, 'Equality in Society', Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society, LXVI (I965-6) I93-210 is also recommended.
Since the distinction between senses of 'just' and principles of justice
has been generally neglected, little has been written about differences
between various possible principles of justice themselves. Some writers
have indeed claimed that, even though 'just' has a fixed descriptive meaning
and is no mere general commendatory term, it is necessarily true that just
actions are right. There is a good critique of this view in D. C. Emmons,
'Justice Reassessed', American Philosophical Quarter[y, IV (I967) I44-5I.
Equipment for a more refined proliferation of possible principles of justice
than I have been able to offer can be found in G. H. von Wright, An Essay
in Deontic Logic and the General Theory of Action, Acta Philosophica Fennica,
Fasc. XXI (Amsterdam, I968).
Little has been written on the psychological factors affecting the relative
popularity of principles of justice. J. Rawls, 'The Sense of Justice',
Philosophical Review, LXXII (I963) 28I-305 is ostensibly devoted to this topic.
W. Kaufmann, 'The Origin of Justice', Review of Metaphysics, XXIII {I969)
209-39 contains some material on the views of Nietzsche and Mill. In
'Whatever the Consequences', Ana[ysis, XXVII {I966) 83-102, Jonathan
Bennett tries to show that all principles of the form 'It would always be
wrong to . . . whatever the consequences' are in the last resort on a par
BIBLIOGRAPHICAL NOTE 79
with 'It would always be wrong to leave a bucket in the hallway, etc.',
and can only be accepted by someone who either submits to a moral
authority such as the Church, or misapprehends the nature of the distinction
between actions and consequences. If his arguments were successful, we
could prove some additional conclusions about the potential unpopularity
of certain principles of justice. There is a brief general discussion of difficul-
ties about lack of general consistency in von Wright, An Essay on Deontic
Logic and the General Theory tif Action, pp. 78-81.
The relations between justice and equality are discussed by D. D.
Raphael in 'Equality and Equity', Philosophy, XXI (1946) 118-32, and
Problems tif Political Philosophy (London, 1970) chap. vii. For a careful
account of the various notions of equality which can be employed in
principles of equality, see Felix E. Oppenheim, 'Egalitarianism as a Descrip-
tive Concept', American Philosophical Quarter(;!, vu (1970) 143-52. The
papers by Mortimore and Williams, cited on pp. 59 and 6o above, are
also recommended. Little which is both philosophically sophisticated and
non-Rawlsian has been written in English about justice and socialism.
Leonard Nelson's System der philosophischen Rechtslehre und Politik, in Siimtliche
Werke, Bd. VI (Frankfurt a.M., 1964) is a deeply impressive attempt at a
complete political casuistry based on a principle of justice.