Chapter 2
Chapter 2
UTILITARIANISM
Chapter Objectives
INTRODUCTION
On January 25, 2015, the 84th Special Action Force (SAF) conducted a police
operation at Tukanalipao, Mamasapano in Maguindanao. Al so known as Oplan Exodus, it,
· was intended to serve an arrest warrant for Zulkifii bin Hir or Marwan, a Malaysian terrorist
and bomb-maker who had a $5 million bounty on his head. This mission eventually led
to' a clash between the Philippine National Police's (PNP) SAF, on the one hand, and the
Bangsamoro Islamic Freedom Fighters (BIFF) and the Moro Islamic Liberation Front
(MILF) on the other. Although the _police operation was "successful" because of the death
of Marwan, the firefight that ensued claimed sixty-seven lives including forty-four SAF
troopers, eighteen MILF Fighters, and five civilians. However, the relatively high number of
. SAF members killed in this operation caught the attention of many including the Philippine
media and the legislature.
In one of the Congress investigations that followed this tragic mission, then Senate
President Franklin Drilon and Senator Francis Escudero debated the public hearing of an
audio recording of an alleged conversation that attempted to cover up the massacre of the
_PNP-SAF commandos. Drilon questioned the admissibility of these recordings as evidence
under the Anti-Wire Tapping Law whereas Escudero cited the legal brief of the Free Legal
1-. _Assistance Group (FLAG) arguing that the Anti -Wire Tapping Law protects only the recording
'··and interception of private communications. Drilon cited Section 4 of the Anti-Wire Tapping
Act (RA 4200) and explained that · any communication or spoken word, or the existence,
co~tents, substance, purport, or meaning of the same or any part thereof, or any information
This case exposes the aftermath of th e Mamasa pano incident and the Senate
investigations. The Senate inquiry proceeding s rai sed questions on th e possibility of wire-
tapping and the intrusion to one's right t o privacy. While th e 1987 Philippine Constitution
does protect one's right to private communication, it did provide some exemptions to its
inviolability. These exemptions include a lawful order of th e court and/o r issues involving
public safety and order.- ln fact, RA 4200 (or the Anti-Wire Tapping Law) and RA 9372 (or
the Human Security Act of 2007) both provided exemptions to the inviolability of the righl
p privacy in instances of treason, espionage, rebellion, and sedition. Whi le this is certainly
a legal issue, can it also constitute a moral concern? By raising the distinction between
moral and legal issues and concerns, do you think that th ese t wo are different? To simplify
things, let us put aside the question of law and let us assume that you were asked to decide
whether wiretapping is morally permissible or not. On w hat instances is w iretapping morally
permissible and on what instances is it not morally permissible?
In the book An Introduction to the Principles of Morals and Legislation (1789_), Jeremy
Bentha;;, begins by arguing that our actions are governed by two "sqvereign masters"
-which he caffs"pl; as-;,",;, and painl The se "masters" are given to us by nature to help us
determine what isgood or bia a nd what ought to be doneand not; they fasten our choices
to their throne. "-·- - •
The creed which accepts as thefoundaticin of mo'rals, utility or the greatest happiness princlp~
~) h?J.dfthat actiO~s are right in proportion as they'ten~ -toproITl,ote h'appiness; ~rong as they
1:eriito prOduce ihe reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended pleasure and the abs~nce
of ~In; by ~nhappiness; pain and the privation of Pleasure. To give a dear view of the moral
1.~ ·:·i;~t ~~·by .the th_eo1; much_,~ '.ore fe~uires ,to be _sa,i d/in" pilrticular, wh~t thing$ it ,
i;
:,_;}n the idea~ ,~f pain}ndP.lea; ure, .~nd to what e)(t~nt, this /~ft an open questi,o~.
·ese -_ supplementary ~xplanations do -~~t::3ffect:the" theory of life on which this theor,'
' is grounded~namely, that plealtirtand·freedom from pain are the. only thi~gs
-~~nds; and that au desirable,!,h'.n~s·_("".,~:ic~ ar~ _7s numer~us ir1 the utilitarian asin
he_~~) ~re desir~_ble _:eit'h. e-~~or.pJr~:su,,~e i:n_h~ie," t'"Jhemselves or as a ·means to
Clearly, Mill ar.gues that we act and do things because we find them pleasurable
and we avoid doing things because they are painful. If we find our actions pleasurable, Mill
explains, it is because they are inherently pleasurable in th.emselves or they eventually lead
to the promotion of pleasure and the avoidance of pain. Bentham and Mill characterized
I
Mill dissents from Bentham's single scale of pleasure. He thinks that the principle
of utility must distingui sh plea sures qualitatively and not merely quantitatively. For Mill, .
utilitarianism cannot promote th e kind of pleasures appropriate to pigs or to any other
animals. He thinks that there are higher intellectual and lower base pleasures. We, as moral
agents, are capable of searching and desiring higher intellectual pleasures more than pigs
are capable of. We undermine ourselves if we only and primarily desire sensuality; this is
because we are capable of higher intellectual pleasurable goods. For Mill, crude bestial
sures, which are appropriate for animals, are degrading to us because we are by nature
easily satisfied by pleasures only for pigs.' Human pleasures are qualitatively different
m animal pleasures. It is unfair to assume that we merely pursue pleasures appropriate
for beasts even if there are instances when we choose to pursue such base pleasures. To
explain this, Mill recognizes the empirical fact that there are different kinds of pleasures:
It is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognize th,e fact that some kinds
of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others. It would be absurd
that while, in estimating all other things, quallty ls considered as well as quantity, the
estimation of pleasure should be supposed to depend on quantity alone.,
<;ontrary to Bentham, Mill argues that quality is more preferable than quantity. An
excessive quantity of what is otherwise pleasurable might result in pain. We can consider,
for example, our experience of exc_essive eating or exercising. Whereas eating the right
amount of food can be _pleasurable, excessive eating may not be. The same is true when
exercising. If the quality of pleasure is so_'!ietimes more important than quantity, then it is
important to consider the standards whereby differences of pleasures can be judged. Tht
test that Mill suggests is sim_ple. In deciding over two comparable pleasures, it is important
While it is difficult to, understand how Mill was able to compare swinish pleasures
with human o nes, we can presume that it would be better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a
pig satisfied. Simply put, as human beings, we prefer the pleasures that are actually within
our grasp. It is easy to compare extreme types of pleasures as in the case of pigs and humans,
but It Is difficult to compare pleasures deeply integrated in our way of life. The pleasures of
an llonggo eating chicken inasa/ and an lgorot eating pinikpikan is an example. This cannot
be done by simply tasting inasa/ or pinikpikan. In the same way, some people prefer puto to
blbingka or liking for the music of Eraserheads than that of the APO Hiking Society.
Equating happiness with pleasure does not aim to describe the utilitarian moral
agent alone and independently from others. This is not only about our individual pleasures,
regardless of how high, intellectual, or in other ways noble. it is, but it is also about the
pleasure of the greatest number affected by the consequences of our actions. Mill explains:
What is a right? Mill understands justice as a respect for rights directed toward
society's pursuit for the greatest happiness of the greatest number. For him, rights are a valid
claim on society and are justified by utility. He explains:
t have, throughout, treated the idea of a right residing in the injured person, and violated
by the injury, not as a separate element in the composition of the Idea and sentiment, but
as one of the forms in which the other two elements clothe themselves. These elements
are, a hurt to some assignable person or persons on the one hand, and a demand for
punishment, on the other. An examination of our minds, I think, will show that these
two things include all that we mean when we speak of vi~lation of a right. When we call
1 anything a person's right, we mean that he has a v_alid claim on society to protect him
in the possession of it, either by the force of law, or by that of education and opinion.
If he has what we consider a sufficient claim, on whatever account, to have something
guaranteed to him by society, we say that he has a right to it. 13
Mill expounds that the abovementioned rights referred are related to the interests
that serve general happiness. The right to due process, the right to free speech or religion,
and others are justified because they contribute to the general good. Thi s means that
society is made happier if its citizens are able to live th eir lives knowing that their interests
are protected and that society (as a w hole) defends it. Extending this concept to animals,
they have rights because of the effect of such principles on the sum total of happiness that
follows as a consequence of instituting and protecting their interests. It is not accidental,
therefore, that utilitarians are also the staunchest defenders of animal rights. A right is
justifiable on utilitarian principles inasmuch as they produce an overall happiness that is
greater than the unhappiness resulting from their implementation.
Utilitarians argue that issues of justice carry a very strong emotional import because
the category of rights is directly associated with the individual's most vital interests. All of
these rights are predicated on the person's right to life. Mill describes:
To have a -~ight! then is, I conceive, to have something which society ought to defend
me_in the possession of. If the objector goes on to ask why it ought, I can give him no
other reason than general utility. If that expression does not seem to convey a sufficient
feellng of the strength of the obligation, nor to account for the peculiar energy of the
- feeling, it is because there goes to the composition of the sentiment, not a rational only
but also an animal element, the thirst for retaliation; and this thirst derives its intensity,
as well as its moral justification, from the extra ordinarily imPortant and impressive kind
of utility which is concerned. The interest involved is that of security, to everyone's
l ;,fe~lings_,the most vital of all interests. 14
Mill creates a distinction between legal rights and their justifi ca ti on. He point~ Otri.
that when legal rights are not morally justified in accordance to the greatest happiness
principle, then these rights need neither be observed, nor be resp ected: Th,s_ 15 like saying
that there are instances when the law is not morally ju stified and, in th is case, Ev~n
objectionable.
:.. The legal rights of which he is deprived may be rights which ought not to have belonged
to•him; 'in other words, the law which confers on him these rights may be a bad law.
when it is so, or when (which is the same thing for our purpose ) it is suppose d to be so,
opinions will differ as to the justice or injustice of infringi ng it. So me ma intain th at no
,, ,law, however bad, ought to be disobeyed by an individua l citizen; t hat his ~pposition to
.it, if sh~wn at all, should 'only be shown in endeavoring to get it altered by co mpetent
:, auth □-rity. This opinion {whi~h condemns many of the most illustriou s benefactors of
/ 'tnankirld, and would often protect pernicious institutions against t he o nly weapons
t~',~hich, in the st~te of things existing at the time, have any chance of succeed ing against
f ) n'em) is defended, by those who hold it, on grounds of expe diency; principally on that
~ of the importance; to the common interest of mankind, of maintain ing inviolate t he
k,:_'.se~timent of submission to law.:. When, however, a law is thought to be unju st, it seems
i : always to be regarded as being so in the same ways in which a breach of la1.•; is unj ust,
i( namely, by Infringing somebody's right; which, as it ·cannot in this case be a legal right.
f~·receives a different appella~on, and is called a moral right. We may say, therefore, t hat a
( ', sec~nd case on injustic~ for1sists !n taking or withholding from any person th at to which
rz~~e.h~?il !1or:1.~i!~: t ~ _ _ .
Mill seems to be suggesting that it is morally permissible to not foll ow, even violat'
an unjust law. The implication is that those who protest over political policies of a moral\
objectionable government act in a morally obligatory way. While thi s is no t always preferr&
While it can be justified why others violate legal rights, it is an act of injustice to
violate an individual's moral rights. However, Mill seems to provide some extenuating
circumstances in which some moral rights can be overridden for the sake of the greater
general happiness. Going back to the case of wiretapping, it seems that one's right to
privacy can be sacrificed for the sake of the common good. This means that moral rights are
o_nly justifiable by considerations of greater overall happiness. He qualifies moral rights in
this way:
All persons are deemed to have a right to equality of treatment, except when some
recognized social expediency requires the reverse. And hence all social inequalities
which have ceased to be considered expedient, assume the character not of simple
inexpediency, but of injustice, and ~ppear so tyra·nnical, that people are aPt to wonder
how they ever could have been tolerated; forgetful that they thenisel,ves perha~s
tolerate other inequalities under an equally mistaken notio_n of expediency, the
correction of which would make that which they approve seem quit~, as monstrous as
what they have at least leaqlt to condemn. 17
In this sense, the principle of utility can theoretically obligate us to steal, kill, and
the like. We say ' theoretically" because this merely constitutes a thought experiment and
need not be actualized. Since what matters in the assessment of what we do is the resultant
happiness, then anything may be justified for the sake of producing the greatest happiness
of the greatest number of people .
. .... ..,. ...... . , ~ - ~.,.....,.~~~,....---~-·•-')
~
Thus, to save a life, It may-not only ~ allow~ble; ~~t a duty to steal or take by forCe,
the necess.iry food ~r "1edici~·e, or to ki~n,a~, •~n~ co,mpel fo offic!ate, the o~ly qualified
medical practitioner. ll_l such cases, as we do not call justice which is not a virtue, we
usu.illy say, not that justice must give wa'i( to some other inoral principle, but that what is
, just iri ordinary cases is, by reason of that other principle, n~t just in the particular case.
By·thi~ Useful accommodation of language, the character of indefeasibility attributed to
· justice is kept up, and w~ ,are saved_from"the necessity of maintaining that there can be
l~~dable injus,tice.ia
i i,,.£.; '-µ
While there is no such thing as a laudable and praiseworthy injustice, Mill appeals
to the utilitarian understanding of justice as an act justified by the greatest happiness
principle. There is no right to violate where utility is not served by the social protection of
individual interests. While he recognizes how utilitarian principles can sometimes obligate
us to perform acts that would regularly be understood as disregarding individual rights, he
argues that this is only possible if it is judged to produce more happiness than unhappiness.
SUMMARY
Bentham and Mill see moral good as pleasure, not merely self-gratification, bul ,
also the greatest happiness principle or the greatest happiness for the greatest number
of people. We are compelled to do .whatever increases pleasure and decreases pain to the
most number of persons, counting each as one and none as more than one. In determining
the greatest happiness for the greatest number of people, there is no distinction between
Bentham and Mill. Bentham suggests his felicific calculus, a framework for quantifying moral
valuation. Mill provides a criterion for comparative pleasures. He thinks that persons who
experience two different types of pleasures generally prefer higher intellectual pleasures to
base sensual ones.
Mill provides an adequate discourse on rights despite it being mistakenly argued:
to be the weakness of utilitarianism. He argues that rights are socially protected interest5
that are justified by their contribution to _the greatest happiness principle. However, he also
claims that in extreme circumstances, respect for individual rights can be overridden 10
promote the better welfare especially in circumstances of conflict valuation.