Corruption in America by Zephyr Teachout
Corruption in America by Zephyr Teachout
IN AMERICA
C O R RU P T IO N
I N AMER IC A
j
from b enj a min fr ankl in’s snuff b ox
to c i tizens united
ZEPHYR
TEACHO U T
Teachout, Zephyr.
Corruption in America : from Benjamin Franklin’s snuff box
to Citizens United / Zephyr Teachout.
pages cm
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-674-05040-2 (alk. paper)
1. Political corruption—United States—History. 2. Judicial
corruption—United States—History. 3. Political culture—
United States. 4. United States—Politics and government—
Moral and ethical aspects. I. Title.
JK2249.T43 2014
364.1'3230973—dc23 2014010417
To Aly, Waylon, Jed, Celia, Sargent,
Zoe, Dewey, Esme, Garth, Elise, and Elva,
my big-hearted, big-dreaming nieces and nephews
Contents
Introduction 1
1 Four Snuff Boxes and a Horse 17
2 Changing the Frame 32
3 Removing Temptations 56
4 Yazoo 81
5 Is Bribery without a Remedy? 102
6 Railroad Ties 125
7 The Forgotten Law of Lobbying 144
8 The Gilded Age 174
9 Two Kinds of Sticks 183
10 The Jury Decides 195
11 Operation Gemstone 205
12 A West Virginia State of Mind 215
13 Citizens United 227
14 The New Snuff Boxes 246
15 Facts in Exile, Complacency,
and Disdain 258
viii contents
Appendix 1:
Anticorruption Constitutional Provisions 307
Appendix 2:
Major Nineteenth- and Twentieth-Century
Anticorruption Laws 311
Notes 313
Cases Cited 351
Further Reading 357
Ac know ledgments 359
Index 361
Introduction
• • •
• • •
The Citizens United decision was not merely bad law; it was bad
for politics, and displayed an even worse understanding of his-
tory. Americans from James Madison onward have argued that
it is possible for politicians and citizens alike to try to achieve a
kind of public good in the public sphere. The traditional view is
not naive—it does not assume that people are generally public-
regarding. It assumes that the job of government is to create
structures to curb temptations that lead to exagerated self-
interest. It certainly recognizes the power of self-interest; but in-
stead of endorsing it, the traditional American approach makes it
government’s job to temper egocentrism in the public sphere. The
traditional conception implicates difficult questions: What is self-
orientation and public orientation, and what is the public good?
But it does not discard these distinctions because they are dif-
ficult ones to parse. A classical American approach engages the
complexity. Like liberty, speech, or equality, corruption is an
important concept with unclear boundaries. It refers to exces-
sive private interests in the public sphere; an act is corrupt when
private interests trump public ones in the exercise of public
power, and a person is corrupt when they use public power for
their own ends, disregarding others.
10 corruption in america
our legal system. The book challenges four commonly held mis-
conceptions: that corruption law began in the post-Watergate
era, that criminal bribery law is the dominant sphere in which
corruption law plays out, that bribery law is coherent and con-
sistent, and that quid pro quo is the heart of corruption law. A
deeper understanding of the tradition of corruption can enrich
our civic culture and our laws.
If the Supreme Court can better remember our past, it might
overturn dozens of cases that have limited the capacity of elected
legislatures to make their own experiments in democracy. And if
we, as citizens, can remember our past, it could augment the way
we think about our founding principles. What if we could add
“anticorruption” to citizens’ sense of national identity?
• • •
j
Four Snuff Boxes and a Horse
disliked snuff, but liked the form and frequently adorned them
with portraits of himself.11 Deane apparently thought the gift
would help save his reputation: he offered it as proof of the great
work he had done for the new country. According to Arthur Lee’s
account, Deane “expected, from the effect of a French Fleet, of
which he was to claim the sole merit, the brilliancy of a diamond
snuff box, and complimentary letter,” that he would return to the
United States with sufficient proof of his loyalties.12 John Adams
was dismissive of the use of evidence, remarking that “unthinking
men may be amused with a golden snuff box.”13
Deane’s acceptance of the snuff box led to Lee accusing him
of violating one of the core laws of the Confederation. In his
papers on the matter, Lee wrote: “Deane knew that it was one of
the fundamental laws of our Union that no person in the service
of the United States should accept from any king, prince, or
minister any present or gratuity whatsoever . . . yet in the face of
this fundamental law, Mr. Deane accepted of a gold snuff, set
with diamonds, from the King of France.”14 The disloyalty and
accounting accusations against Deane were never proven, as the
French did not disclose their accounting. Deane would eventu-
ally return to France, disgraced but not sentenced. But the ques-
tion of the appropriate relationship to foreign gifts remained.
It turns out it was far easier to criticize the gift acceptance
than to resist it: the next snuff box went to Lee himself. Lee,
along with Franklin, had negotiated the 1778 treaty with France.
When Lee returned to the American states in 1780, he carried
with him a new jeweled snuff box, also given to him by King
Louis XVI, with the king’s portrait set in diamonds. Lee was
understandably concerned about the appearances of accepting
the box—in part because Deane had countercharged him with
24 corruption in america
disloyalty. But Lee was also worried about offending the king.
He wrote to a friend that the snuff box might “excite some mur-
murs” and thought that the Articles of Confederation might
prevent accepting the gift.15 Like most humans, he found the
ethical proscriptions of others easy to understand but when he
was placed in the same situation as Deane, he was less sure about
what to do.
As Lee was then embroiled in accusations that he had given
offense to the French court, the gift also served for him as “proof
of the untruth” of the accusations against him.16 The French li-
aison, Vergennes, “warned his adjutant in Philadelphia that an
unscrupulous politician like Arthur Lee might employ the King’s
portrait . . . to give the impression that he (Lee) held the king’s
confidence and thus could speak freely on matters of French
foreign policy.”17 Lee wrote to his brother, “as you can imagine, I
was embarrassed about receiving or refusing it.” He explained
that he had told the court that receiving such a gift was against
the rules of those he represented, but the court insisted. Lee
ultimately gave the gilded box to Congress to determine what to
do with it. He wrote to the Committee of Foreign Affairs on
January 19, 1780:
Jefferson’s Brilliants
The last Constitutional-era snuff box never made it in front of
Congress. When Thomas Jefferson, after the Constitution was
ratified, took his own turn as a diplomat to France, he thought
at first that he could be free from the custom of receiving gifts,
which he found distasteful. As one of his biographers put it,
“Jefferson thought it mercifully prohibited by the Constitution.”29
Nonetheless, the French court gave him a snuff box at the end of
his tour, embedded with “brilliants” surrounding a portrait of the
king. It was valued slightly less—but only slightly—than the one
given to Franklin. He wrote to his assistant William Short,
asking him to let the appropriate parties know that the gifts
clause meant that he could not accept the customary present
four snuff boxes and a horse 29
from the king. “Explain to them that clause in our new constitu-
tion which [says] ‘no person holding any office of profit or trust
under the U.S. shall accept any present, emolument, office, or
title of any kind whatever from any king, prince or foreign state.’ ”
Jefferson recognized that he could go through Congress for ap-
proval but told Short he did not choose “to be laid on the grid-
iron of debate in Congress for any such paltry purpose,” so he
should not even let the relevant parties know about it. “Be so good
as to explain it in such a manner as to avoid offence.” The difficul-
ties attending the gift caused Jefferson “considerable anguish,”
but he eventually accepted it.
Instead of going through Congress, he asked his secretary to
take the gilded frame, remove the diamonds, catalogue and value
them, sell the most valuable, put the money toward Jefferson’s
own private account, and not report it. Literary historian Mar-
tha Rojas describes his response as “both calculated and tor-
tured,” and argues that it may have been driven by concerns
about money. His letters to Short on the matter were written in
cipher. He asked him to take out the diamonds and sell them,
and then safely return the portrait, doing whatever was neces-
sary to keep attention away.30 Upon Short’s instructions, the
banker extracted the diamonds.31 The money raised from the
sale of the diamonds was put into his own account and used to
pay for the diplomatic presents and embassy debts. When it was
done, Short wrote: “I send you . . . the remains of what I received
for you, agreeably to your desire. The secrecy you requested is
fully observed.”32
Whether Jefferson did not want to offend the French or could
not resist the temptation of a chance to pay off debts, we cannot
know. But his simultaneous disdain for European gifts and his
30 corruption in america
j
Changing the Frame
He, and the other framers, were haunted by the spector of fu-
ture desolation.
But Gibbon was not the only source of the preoccupation
with Rome. The pamphleteers and letters of the time show that
the most important activists and intellectuals read the Roman
writers directly.4 They cited Plutarch, Sallust, and Cicero—each
of whom pointed to corruption as the core reason for political
decline. Jefferson thought Tacitus was the greatest writer of any
generation, and John Adams emotionally embraced the writing,
saying that it was as if he were reading a history of his own po-
litical times.5 The founding fathers’ “scrutiny of the late Roman
republic resembled an autopsy.”6 Throughout the Constitutional
Convention and the ratification debates, the framers refer to
Roman and Greek corruption. The names Brutus, Cassius,
changing the frame 35
tism and corruption were opposites; a patriot was one who puts
the country’s interest “in his care,” whereas a corrupt courtier is
one who puts his own interests in his care when in public ser-
vice.21 Adams had come to reject the king because he saw the
role as leading to nothing but private interests and therefore not
worthy of governing.22
Early American conceptions of what corruption meant flowed
from two related but distinct sources. The first was Aristotelian
and republican, embodied in the thinking of the French politi-
cal philosopher Baron de Montesquieu; the second was Chris-
tian, puritanical, and intertwined with theories of natural law,
embodied in the theories of the English philosopher John Locke.
In both traditions, the core metaphor of corruption was organic
and derived from disease and internal collapse. Corruption was
a rotting of positive ideals of civic virtue and public integrity. It
“most often brought to mind a fuller, more coherent, and more
dreadful image of a spreading rot. A frequent metaphor com-
pared corruption to organic cancer, eating at the vitals of the
body politic and working a progressive dissolution.”23 In the re-
publican tradition, corruption was the cancer of self-love at the
expense of love of country. It existed at a personal and structural
level. The individual was a metaphor for the state, and the state
was the metaphor for the individual; both were complex psy-
chological institutions that could fall prey to weaknesses that
would corrode them from within. In the Christian tradition,
corruption was the loss of personal virtue and expressed itself
through hedonism, sloth, arrogance, and laziness at the ex-
pense of the love of God and the good. In both traditions, sys-
temic corruption occurs in political/ethical structures that create
40 corruption in america
Montesquieu
The framers were well-read and drew on many sources. How-
ever, as historian Bernard Bailyn persuasively argued, the “chief
authority” for the Constitutional framers was the eighteenth-
century French political philosopher Charles-Louis de Secon-
dat, Baron de La Brède et de Montesquieu. The Spirit of the Laws
was written just thirty years before the Constitutional Conven-
tion and was a foundational part of their political education.
Montesqueiu’s name “recurs far more often than that of any
other authority in all of the vast literature on the Constitution.
He was the fountainhead, the ultimate arbiter of belief; his
ideas were the standard by which all others were set. The
framers reverted to his authority at every turn.”24 Therefore,
understanding the way that Montesquieu thought about hu-
man nature, government, and corruption enriches our own un-
derstanding of the meaning of corruption during the Constitu-
tional era.
Montesquieu is most known for his support of different
branches balancing powers against each other. But his advocacy
for mixed government was a direct outgrowth of his beliefs
about human nature. Montesquieu’s approach was Aristotelian.
Aristotle set out six ways a government can constitute itself:
three kinds of governments, and three perversions. The rule of
one is monarchy or tyranny; the rule of a few is either an aris-
tocracy or an oligarchy; and the rule of the public is either a
changing the frame 41
sionate, sensational love of the rule of law, and love of the spirit
of law itself, is the basis on which a country can govern itself.
If Montesquieu established the thesis of government and
citizenship for the framers, the Scottish philosopher Thomas
Hobbes represented the antithesis. Hobbes rejected the idea
that people should or could be virtuous. He dismissed the “bab-
bling philosophy of Aristotle” and argued that there is no dif-
ference between monarchy and tyranny, or between a corrupted
democracy and an uncorrupted one. They are just the same
things, he said, by different names: the word monarchy is used
by those who like a particular leader, and tyranny by those who
hate him. In the seventeenth century, Montesquieu picked a
fight with Hobbes. Hobbes saw entirely self-interested citizens as
inevitable human nature, whereas Montesquieu saw them as the
greatest threat to political society. Montesquieu set out to wrest
realism from Hobbes: in his view, not only was Hobbes’s psycho-
logical portrait inaccurate, but his political science would lead to
more unstable governments. He directly attacked what he saw as
Hobbes’s falsely dark, and possibly naive, description of human
nature. Simone Goyard-Fabre calls him the “anti-Hobbes.”29
Hobbes—like some modern justices—believed that people
are fundamentally egoist. Corruption was an incoherent idea
for Hobbes—a view we find dormant for hundreds of years, but
then recurrent in late-twentieth-century Supreme Court doc-
trine. The founders read Hobbes, but most of them also rejected
him and his view of human nature. Adams thought he treated
men “like cattle” and misunderstood the role of context, reason,
and law.30 Jefferson “lamented” that a contemporary was going to
adopt Hobbes’s view of human nature. Hobbes saw no justice or
injustice, but “only convention.”31 Jefferson believed that systems
44 corruption in america
of his needs, choosing what was good for him as well as for
the whole. He was not expected to surrender his particu-
lar self-interest. Instead, he was thought of as pursuing his
particular desires while still remaining conscious of the
interests of his peers and participating in a collectivity of
equals.40
not always clear. There are no debates about whether a good out-
come derived from a corrupt mental state would be classified as
a corrupt “act” or merely a corrupt actor. It was, however, clear
that the framers believed that corrupt mental states tended to
lead to corrupt actions, and therefore fixing structures to en-
courage certain sympathies was a primary job of Constitutional
design. Again, they perceived a dynamic relationship between
acts and thoughts.
In Federalist No. 55 Madison wrote about how corruption
might “subdu[e] the virtue” of senators.41 Pennsylvania delegate
Gouverneur Morris spoke about how “wealth tends to corrupt
the mind & to nourish its love of power, and to stimulate it to
oppression.”42 Morris was clearly talking about a transforma-
tion in “the mind,” a fundamental corrosion of the interior life
that would then lead to a corrosion of practices (stimulating
it to oppression). When Madison, in Federalist No. 10, puzzles
on the problem of bias in self-government and notes by analogy
that “no man is allowed to be a judge in his own cause, because
his interest would certainly bias his judgment, and not improb-
ably corrupt his integrity,”43 he is making a claim about the inte-
rior life of the mind—the moral attitude taken by an individual.
He is claiming that exterior forces have the power to shape the
moral orientation of a person, just as a powerful flow of water
might shape the soil around it. Money has an alchemical effect—
not just leveraging action, but in so doing, changing the nature of
the agent that it works upon. The language is both technical
and moral.
A set of actions were treated as archetypal corruption, regard-
less of the mental state. The king’s use of his power to bestow
offices to create allegiances among parliamentarians was corrupt.
50 corruption in america
(On this, the outlier was Alexander Hamilton, who argued that
the king’s using offices to create “attachments” was not corrupt,
but merely influence. His belief in the legitimacy of such influ-
ence was entangled in his monarchism. For the rest, the king’s
use of power was treated as implicitly corrupting, whether or
not the parliamentarians would have supported the king with-
out the promised offices.) Bribery and extortion were likewise
considered per se corrupt, but such crimes were rarely punished
criminally, so invocations of bribery were rarely in reference to
criminal law standards and were more often in reference to the
use of a gift, political office, or flattery to persuade someone to
change a course of action.
One thing shines through all the usages: the way corruption
was referred to at the time was rarely in conjunction with viola-
tions of criminal law. There were relatively few criminal laws of
corruption at the time, as I’ll show. Gouverneur Morris explic-
itly said that the corruption concern encompassed lawful abuses
of power, not merely unlawful abuses or usurpations.44 Morris
argued, as an example of predictable legal corruption, that legis-
latures might want to print money in ways that enriched them
personally, using legitimately granted public power for private
gain. Though the word corruption was used hundreds of times
in the convention and the ratification debates, only a handful of
uses referred to what we might now think of as quid pro quo
bribes.45 That constituted less than one-half of 1 percent of the
times corruption was raised. In direct contradiction to the inter-
pretation of corruption in Citizens United, the concept of corrup-
tion encompassed, but was not equated with, explicit exchange
or explicit embezzlement.46
changing the frame 51
Dependency
One of the most dangerous structures, one that was likely to
lead to corruption, was the dependent one. The language of de-
pendence and corruption was so intertwined at the founding
that in some cases, corruption and independence could sound
like opposites. Contemporary theorists sometimes used “corrup-
tion” and “dependence” together, indicating that they saw cor-
ruption as the natural result of dependence. Scottish philoso-
pher David Hume, for example, in discussing the relationship
of the Crown to the kind of public offices that were frequently
given out as rewards for loyalty, wrote that “we may give to this
influence what name we please . . . we may call it by the invidi-
ous appellations of corruption and dependence.”52
The Declaration of Independence was in part a declaration of
freedom from corruption. While modern rhetoric often treats
independence and liberty or freedom as interchangeable, liberty
referred to either a Christian conception of rationally limited
human action or a set of substantive privileges and immunities,
or freedom from enslavement.53 Independence, on the other hand,
was not invoked in the discussions of liberty and was more re-
lated to the rhetoric of corruption. Independence is the absence
of (in) a power relationship (of the pendant). Independence was at
its core a relational word, which symbolized the rejection of a
kind of relationship. Dependence could refer to a kind of struc-
tural dependence (where a person is actually dependent upon
others financially and therefore must do their bidding) or a
54 corruption in america
j
Removing Temptations
But a few days later, Franklin intervened with his own pre-
pared speech, which was read out loud for him.5 Franklin’s big-
gest concern was a version of the modern revolving door be-
tween Congress and well-paying lobbying jobs: the problem of
people going into office not to represent the public but in order
to get a well-paid job. They called this the problem of “placemen.”
Randolph had proposed to pay salaries to members of the execu-
tive branch. Franklin disagreed: he thought officials should work
for free and the expenses be merely defrayed. His speech expressed
a peculiar—and rather wonderfully radical—American contri-
bution to thinking about government and corruption. Just as the
Articles of Confederation had taken “gifts” from the category of
diplomacy and put them in the category of corruption, Franklin
was trying to take “payment for offices” out of the category of
“practices of governing” and put it in the category of “corruption.”
Franklin presented a model of human behavior in which men
are flexible and can be “good” and virtuous in one setting, yet
destructive and corrupt in another. Franklin’s speech was full of
broad claims about human nature and its relationship to power:
delegates ought to watch carefully the powerful influences of
ambition and greed, or what he called “the love of power, and the
love of money.” Power and money can spur action, “but when
united in view of the same object, they have in many minds the
most violent effects.” One cannot “place before the eyes of such
men” jobs that have both honor and money in them. If a “post of
honor” is “at the same time a place of profit,” then men “will move
heaven and earth to obtain it.” He wrote that the disorder and
troubles in Britain had come from the existence of lucrative ex-
ecutive posts. These could lead to factions that then divide the
nation, distract the government, and encourage “fruitless and
removing temptations 61
Elections
Madison described the essence of good government this way:
But the roads were too bad, the distances too great, and the
numbers too formidable to allow for the concerted redirection
removing temptations 71
of the minds of men to private gain and the interests of the state
to private or foreign interests. While traditional republican the-
orists had always argued that only small countries could be re-
publics, Madison and the founders argued that larger countries,
among other attractions, provided better protections against
corruption.
The frequency of elections was also tied up in corruption.
How to use elections to make each branch dependent on the
people instead of on a different branch? The problem, as later
explained by Madison, was that in Britain, members of the House
of Commons were elected for seven years, and only a small num-
ber of people participated in the election.29 The longer terms
strengthened the legislators’ bonds with the executive and weak-
ened them with the people. Two-year periods would not lead to
the same kind of corruption. But if the political terms were too
short, the legislature might be too erratic, as the body itself
would constantly change. If terms were too long, however, legis-
lators would come to entrench themselves and use their offices
for their own advantage. Madison argued that election enabled
“an immediate dependence” and “intimate sympathy” with the
people. Frequent elections were “the only policy” that secured
this kind of psychological tie to the public. A short term would
ensure accountability and make it difficult to run too far on the
public purse. But a long term, Williamson argued, would make it
more likely that men of good character would undertake the
commitment to service—that is, a short term would attract only
weaker men, whose characters were capable of corruption.30
The framers were also vexed about the Senate selection pro-
cess. Pinckney wanted to replace the method of selecting the
Congress, switching its selection from “by the people” to “by the
72 corruption in america
Rotten Boroughs
Above all, the framers didn’t want representatives who did not
work for the public but rather worked for themselves or for a
powerful patron. They saw how rotten boroughs had enabled
that in England. In the New York state convention, Alexander
Hamilton explained that “the true source of the corruption
which has so long excited the severe animadversion of zealous
removing temptations 73
came from elsewhere but that they exploited the system and did
not truly belong to or intend to respond to the residents. The par-
allel nine-year citizenship requirement for senators was also heav-
ily debated—Mason again taking the charge and telling stories of
cabal and adventurers—but they ultimately settled on nine (in-
stead of three, fourteen, or thirteen) as fittingly more than that
for the House “because they would have more power.”
The age requirements for federal office come from an effort
to limit the power of family dynasties. The age limits make it
harder for one to come into power just by being a child of a
wealthy or political family. The provisions were “aimed to prevent
wealthy candidates from gaming the system.”39 Those most af-
fected by age limits would be the wealthy sons of a political
dynasty—not those without means. As Mason said, “If residence
be not required, Rich men of neighboring States may employ with
success the means of corruption in some particular district and
thereby get into the public Councils after having failed in their
own State. This is the practice in the boroughs of England.”40
Accounting
Giving the legislature the power of the purse was supposed to
stop corruption.41 The founders were concerned that an execu-
tive with the power of appropriation would use it to create de-
pendency by giving out money to political leaders.42 The Con-
stitution required that the treasury be accounted to ensure that
money was not stolen from the national treasury.43 All military
appropriations were limited to two years. The appropriations
clause also ensures that this happened by including a require-
ment that funds be appropriated transparently. The transpar-
removing temptations 77
grant. The “limited times” part of the clause showed that the
framers wanted monopolies (which both represented corruption
and led to temptations) to be carefully constrained.
Treaties
While most of these provisions related to internal governance,
the specter of foreign power was always present. In one proposal,
treaties could be approved with half of the Senate’s approval.
Gerry, however, “enlarged on the danger of putting the essential
rights of the Union in the hands of so small a number as a majority
of the Senate, representing, perhaps, not one fifth of the people.
The Senate will be corrupted by foreign influence.”45 The dele-
gates, in turn, enlarged the requirements, demanding two-thirds
of senators to agree to a treaty. As Lawrence Lessig puts it, “The
Framers didn’t want a Congress that was a farm league for the
French Riviera.”46 The executive was given the treaty-making
power after much disturbed debate.
chapter four
j
Yazoo
passed it to the clerk, who read the title of the act and the
other records, and then, committing them to the flames,
cried out in a loud voice, “God save the State and preserve
her rights, and may every attempt to injure them perish as
these wicked and corrupt acts now do!”8
For some individuals, the legal battle ended with the new leg-
islative act. Several people who had purchased Yazoo land from
the initial companies voluntarily gave up their titles and got
their money back. But the corruption controversy didn’t die
in the fire. The Yazoo companies, in defiance of Georgia, con-
tinued to sell claims to the land throughout the country. Ac-
cording to the sellers and buyers, a deal is a deal, even if it is a
bad one, and the land was no longer owned by the State of
Georgia. Through these proliferating land sales, the local issue
quickly became national.
Pro-Yazoo and anti-Yazoo divisions largely—but not
completely—reflected the lines between the early parties: Feder-
alists (who favored strong central governments) and Democratic-
Republicans. Political pamphleteers got in on the act and dis-
tributed screeds about the sale. The Yazoo scandal became a
political litmus test for politicians outside of Georgia.
Yazoo supporters argued that the sale could not be nullified.
From their point of view the state was bound by the contract to
sell the land. It didn’t matter if the motives of all the legislators
were obviously self-interested, and it didn’t matter whether or
not it reflected the will of the people. Their vision of a republic
depended on stable property rights: whether or not the purchas-
ers were exactly disinterested or innocent, purchasers needed as-
surance that what they bought wouldn’t be snatched away from
86 corruption in america
its own tribunal, or, if not acting as a court, “exerting a mere act
of power in which it was controlled only by its own will.” Since
he did not want to give the legislature the authority to act either
as a judge upon itself or as unconstrained mere power, he con-
cluded that the only way to examine the revocation is through
the traditional common-law lens of contracts—with the legisla-
ture (not the public) as the relevant actor. Within the realm of
contracts, then, he turned to the public policy goal of making
sure that titles are secure and the importance of keeping open
“the intercourse between man and man.” It was of utmost im-
portance to protect innocent third parties.24 While initial con-
veyances might be set aside because they were procured by cor-
ruption, once they had passed into an innocent third party’s
hands, they became enforceable.
Marshall reasoned that Georgia was asking for legislatures
to get special treatment in contract law. To treat the legislature
as a special category for purposes of these kinds of conveyances
would lead to the legislature being able to “devest any other in-
dividual of his lands, if it shall be the will of the legislature so to
exert it.” In order to support the right of the legislature to re-
voke its own grants, Fletcher would have to argue this principle:
“That a legislature may, by its own act, devest the vested estate of
any man whatever, for reasons which shall, by itself, be deemed
sufficient.”
In some ways the most radical move was Marshall’s charac-
terization of the land grant as a contract.25 This allowed Mar-
shall to place the case in the context of the contracts clause of
the U.S. Constitution, Article I, Section 10, which says that no
state may “pass any Bill of Attainder, ex post facto Law, or Law
impairing the Obligation of Contracts.” According to Marshall,
yazoo 97
Whatever respect might have been felt for the state sover-
eignties, it is not to be disguised that the framers of the
constitution viewed, with some apprehension, the violent
acts which might grow out of the feelings of the moment;
and that the people of the United States, in adopting that
instrument, have manifested a determination to shield
themselves and their property from the effects of those
sudden and strong passions to which men are exposed.
The restrictions on the legislative power of the states are
obviously founded in this sentiment; and the constitution
of the United States contains what may be deemed a bill
of rights for the people of each state.
j
Is Bribery without a Remedy?
cated that they were within the category of wrongs that dis-
qualified one from office or public service—regardless of the
size of the criminal penalty. Several states kept this tradition.
For example, the original New Hampshire constitution included
this provision: “No person shall ever be admitted to hold . . . any
office of trust or importance under this government, who in the
due course of law, has been convicted of bribery, or corruption,
in obtaining an election or appointment.”21 And of course the
U.S. Constitution retained this feature, making it an impeach-
able offense to commit “high crimes and misdemeanors.” One
might not be jailed for extortion, but it disqualified one from
public office.
Neither corruption nor bribery nor extortion were uniformly
or clearly defined. A 1797 Delaware list of “indictable crimes”
described bribery broadly, as “an offense against public justice,”
constituted by undue reward for one in the administration of
public justice, in an attempt “to influence him against the known
rules of law, honesty, or integrity, or [constituted by] giving or
taking a reward for offices of a public nature. He who accepts
and he who offers the bribe are both liable to punishment.”22
Because extortion cases were more frequently appealed than
bribery cases, we have a better sense of what constituted “cor-
rupt” behavior in the extortion context in the early years of the
country.
Courts were split both on whether some kind of corrupt
intent was required to prove a violation, and on what kind of
evidence was required to show corrupt intent.23 Criminal cor-
ruption law in Maryland was close to an absolute “bright-line”
rule—a rule in which the act is examined without regard to
whether there is corrupt intent—in that no officer was allowed
112 corruption in america
to take more than his statutory salary. The Maryland court held
that intent did not matter—the crime was complete upon the
illegal taking, even though, “No doubt he received the fee under
an entire conviction that he had a right to it.”24 As the Mary-
land judge argued, if you needed to prove corrupt intent, there
would be few convictions. In an 1827 Pennsylvania case, where a
justice of the peace took money from someone charged with as-
sault, the justice of the peace appealed a conviction of extortion
on the grounds that there was no proof he took the money with
corrupt intent. The Supreme Court of Pennsylvania rejected
the appeal because of the danger that “pretexts would never be
wanting.” Therefore, “sound policy” led the court to conclude that
“the absence of a corrupt motive, or the existence of an agreement
by the party injured, furnishes no justification for doing what the
law forbids.”25 In contrast, a Massachusetts court concluded that
corrupt intent was an essential element of the extortion statute.
“Unless the excess [fee was] wilfully and corruptly demanded and
received, it was not within the statute.”26 Some courts held that
corrupt intent could be deducted by circumstance. A 1796 North
Carolina case included the indictment that the defendant “took
eight shillings for a certain service by colour of his office, and for
wicked gain sake.” The defendant said that it was by mistake,
but because the amount taken was above the legal fee, there was
sufficient evidence of a crime and the wicked gains sake require-
ment was presumptively satisfied.27 All of these issues return
in later years to make bribery laws difficult to pin down.
One 1795 Virginia case foreshadowed another interesting
question in bribery law: is it illegal if you bribe someone who
does not have the power to make a difference? A candidate for
county clerk promised one of the justices of the peace that if the
is bribery without a remedy ? 113
justice of the peace would vote for his candidacy, he would share
the profits he earned if elected. A judge puzzled over whether it
was possible to say that corrupting one of a group of electors
constituted bribery. He concluded no: one cannot be convicted
of selling an office when only one of many of the electors is of-
fered a payment, because the electing body is larger than the
individual whose vote might be influenced.28
There is little case law evidence that these laws were broadly
enforced.29 Furthermore, bribery laws were not mentioned in
the Yazoo scandal; they were treated skeptically in Anderson v.
Dunn; and there are less than a dozen reported political corrup-
tion cases in the first fifty years after the ratification of the Con-
stitution. One would have to conduct a study of trial records of
the period to know more precisely how often they were used,
but they were not a significant part of the discourse in the early
republic.
Under this statute, any gift of any kind to any legislator with
intent to influence official activity is illegal. On its face, it would
cover any campaign contribution designed to influence policy
(let alone the wheelbarrows of cash that were reportedly in
fashion). Law, practice, and culture were disconnected, each
from the other.
Perhaps the best example of the the transformation of brib-
ery law from a judicial realm to the legislative realm is a much-
cited 1868 case interpreting the common law of corruption. The
New Jersey Supreme Court concluded that despite the early
association of bribery with the judicial realm, the weight of the
118 corruption in america
j
Railroad Ties
the length of The Great Gatsby.”14 The case deciding these issues
in Tennessee, Lynn v. Polk, was no exception. It became the lon-
gest case ever published by the Tennessee Supreme Court, about
the length of Faulkner’s As I Lay Dying.
All five justices wrote separate opinions. Justice Turney found
the law unconstitutional on the grounds that it fundamentally
violated the legislative sovereignty to bind future iterations of
the government. One legislature should not be allowed to “exceed
the length of its own life in its appropriations of public moneys.”
Instead, each legislature should only be allowed to “provide for
the contingencies of the two years intervening between stated
sessions.” To do otherwise would be to force the state into a po-
sition where, in “prosperity or adversity, in peace or war, in health
or pestilence, in plenty or famine, still nothing can be drawn from
the treasury until the creditor has been paid annually eight-tenths
of a million dollars.” The current legislature was actually taking
sovereignty away from the future, because it in effect put sover-
eignty in the hands of federal jurisdiction, because of the im-
pairments of contracts. The logic, in essence, was that because
of the ban on the impairment of contracts between the state and
private parties (a ban created by the Yazoo case), a contract be-
tween the state and private parties that reached into the future
was unconstitutional. He refused to address the question of
bribery, finding it unnecessary to the case. However, the argu-
ment Turney made was so unusual and novel—and would make
it impossible for states to do almost anything involving promises
to repay—that it is hard to believe that the bribery charges, or
the judge’s own politics, did not influence the case. The opinion
by Justice Freeman is what really makes this case noteworthy. It
is the most thoroughly judicial exploration I have found of the
132 corruption in america
set aside executive pardons, “upon the ground that they were
corruptly granted.” That, in turn, might lead to governors refus-
ing to enforce judicial orders because they would deem them
“corruptly rendered.” From such a state of corruption investiga-
tion would result “collision and conflict, confusion and chaos.”
This might be different if there were a clear standard of cor-
ruption, but, as McFarland saw it, there was no such clarity. The
judiciary could just use the civil standard—that corruption was
more likely than not—but it would lead to the judiciary over-
turning all kinds of bills. Moreover, in many instances there
was some inappropriate influence on both sides of a piece of
legislation. In effect, it would undermine the core democratic
conceit—that representatives make policy.
Lynn v. Polk, unlike Fletcher v. Peck, had no significant impact,
except in the short term in Tennessee. Even in its minor features
it was an outlier. It is interesting as an artifact, as it shows a path
not taken in corruption law in the nineteenth century. But a cen-
tury later, the seeds of Freeman’s concurrence reappear in the
writings of the law and economics scholars in a different form: a
suggestion that all governmental acts should be subject to a po-
litical process review and should be treated skeptically, as likely
products of a corrupt process.
down the middle, north to south.16 Its growth was heavily de-
pendent on public aid: in 1850 it received over 2.5 million acres
of land from the state, land that had been given for that purpose
from President Millard Fillmore. By 1856 it was the longest rail-
road in the world. A spur into Chicago grew into a hub, and the
largest building in Chicago became the Illinois Central’s Grand
Central Station.
As the railroad grew, so did its needs—and, apparently, its
greed. As in Tennessee, railroad projects were particularly prone
to corruption of their great promise, the concentrated capital
available to them, their innovation in purchasing political power,
and confusion around land values. In 1869, Illinois Central hired
Alonzo Mack, a former state senator, to represent its efforts to
get the state to sell its highly coveted lakefront land and the sub-
merged acreage around it. Mack was a powerful lobbyist with
connections in every corner of the statehouse, and he had a rep-
utation for using any mode of persuasion available to him. One
newspaper correspondent described Mack holding court at the
popular Leland Hotel, center of political and social activities for
the statehouse. In the hotel, according to the visitor, there was a
table for ladies, a table for strangers, a table for honest men, and
a table for corruptibles. Mack presided over the table for cor-
ruptibles. “When a person leaves the ‘honest men’s’ table and
goes over to that of the ‘corruptibles,’ it is an intimation that he is
ready to listen to proposals,” the correspondent wrote.17
Whether through bribery or persuasion, Alonzo Mack did his
job well for Illinois Central, pushing a bill through the House
that would force Chicago to sell over 1,000 acres of submerged
property for $800,000. An opponent of the bill immediately cried
foul: “Various reports are in circulation concerning supposed cor-
railroad ties 139
j
The Forgotten Law of Lobbying
ence to take the natural resources of the state to line their own
pockets. Lobbyists cost the state money. Of the $11 million in
debt, one proponent estimated that a million was currently in the
pockets of lobbyists, who had charged money in order to serve
private interests.
liced almost entirely by civil law. Virtually all of the cases deal-
ing with lobbying were contract cases, with courts deciding
whether or not to enforce contracts for “lobbying” services. Typ-
ically, there was no investigation into whether the underlying ac-
tivity was illegal (as a criminal law matter) or not: in many states
it was not. Courts would simply declare lobbying contracts in-
valid. As Supreme Court justice Field wrote, “all agreements for
pecuniary considerations to control the . . . ordinary course of
legislation are void as against public policy.”9 A popular contracts
hornbook with repeated publications in the late nineteenth and
early twentieth century said:
Unscrupulous Agents
The word lobbyist was first used in the beginning of the nine-
teenth century as paid influencers started to hang around the
lobbies of legislative buildings and hotels, using indirect and di-
rect means to serve their clients. Lobbyists included “peddlers
150 corruption in america
passage of a law by the said legislature, having for its object re-
lief to the undersigned.” In exchange, he was promised 10 per-
cent of the amount of money received. The key holding of Rose,
which made it particularly powerful, regarded the legal ele-
ments of the contract. The court held that it was impossible to
sift apart the contract and separate the legal from the illegal ele-
ments. While there was evidence that some of what the lawyer
did in this case was pure professional preparation, work which
could have otherwise been lawfully compensated, the agree-
ment to use influence to pass a law rendered the other parts of
the agreement entirely void.
The scope and meaning of these cases was clarified in Trist v.
Child,17 which made clear that paid personal influence was
against public policy even when a lawyer performed the ser-
vices, when the person purchasing the services might other-
wise be without ability to influence, and even when it was not
done secretly.
Child, made visits to Congress and wrote letters and made ar-
guments proving the claim, Congress appropriated the sum of
$14,559 to Trist. After the lawyer successfully persuaded Con-
gress of the value of his claim, the old man’s son refused to pay
the lawyer. Child sued him for the money owed. Trist’s defense
was based on the logic of Marshall—the lobbying contract was
void as against public policy. The courts, he argued, had no busi-
ness in enforcing something so corrupt.
The case was—and remains—so interesting because at stake
was lobbying itself, not just underhanded lobbying. Unlike in
Marshall or Rose, there was no allegation of secrecy. Instead, it
seemed like a straightforward, aboveboard claim where a lawyer
was hired to do something that an old man could not do. If the
court was going to invalidate this contract, all contracts to lobby
were clearly at risk.
One could hardly imagine a more sympathetic context for
enforcing a lobby contract; this was the constitutional test of
the logic of Harris. Child had been “open, fair, and honorable.”
There was no evidence of anything suspicious: there was no evi-
dence of secret collusion, or payments or promises to members
of Congress. The age and inability to travel of the client made it
seem he could not prosecute his claim without terrible hard-
ship. If there was any right to petition the government, ought it
not extend to the aged, who might need to hire someone on their
behalf? Child argued that Trist had a right to personally petition
Congress, and that this right must mean the right to hire an
agent to petition on his behalf.
The Court sided with Trist. It concluded that the sale of in-
fluence itself, whether or not accompanied by payments or sus-
picious behavior, was a civic wrong. The Court addressed the
156 corruption in america
ship, for a fee. In this sense, agreeing to work for pay on political
issues is more akin to selling the personal right to vote than sell-
ing legal skills. Lobbyists have a separate and distinct obligation
to pursue public ends, and while they may be allowed to express
self-interest in the vote, they have, as citizens, an obligation to
honor and love the equality of the political system.
As in Marshall, the Court treated lobbying in terms of its
general effects—what the Court in Marshall called the poten-
tial for a “compact corps of venal solicitors”—not just its indi-
vidual ones. A general acceptance of lobbying would lead to a
corrupt culture. Lobbying paid by individuals could not be al-
lowed because it would lead to lobbying paid by corporations:
Personal or Professional
Trist was cited for many years for its principles. A few years
later, in an 1880 case to enforce a contract for influencing the
Turkish government’s purchase of arms, the Supreme Court re-
iterated the broad principle, even though the Turkish govern-
ment, not the American government, was at stake.18 The defen-
dant in that case sold over $1 million in arms to the Turkish
government in 1870 and 1871. The choice of arms was directly in-
fluenced by the plaintiff, a consul for the Turkish government,
the forgotten law of lobbying 159
the first step toward bribery. The “law forbids the inchoate step”
in bribery.40 Lobbying leads to bribery through temptation—
private meetings with money and no one watching make it hard
for enough individuals to resist, even if the majority succeed. “If
the tempted agent be corrupt himself, and disposed to corrupt
others, the transition requires but a single step.”41 Legal lobby-
ing allows citizens to tell other citizens that they can take money
and turn it into political power, and once that traffic is legal, they
will figure out ways to skirt the law but in fact engage in offering
value in exchange for influence.
Because lobbying leads to bribery, the job of the courts was to
protect against the temptation. Courts routinely held that it
was not necessary to find that the parties agreed to some “cor-
rupt” or “secret” action. Instead, the question was whether the
“contract tends directly to those results.”42 A contract was prob-
lematic when it “furnishes a temptation to the plaintiff, to re-
sort to corrupt means or improper devices, to influence legisla-
tive action.” Such a temptation leads to bribery, which in turn
leads to destroying the institution and undermining public con-
fidence.43 Much as a later Supreme Court in Buckley v. Valeo44 (a
case I explore in Chapter 13) would describe “appearance of cor-
ruption” as being just as important as corruption itself, the courts
in these contract cases were concerned that the public would
lose trust in institutions with the growth of lobbying.
The role of temptation in lobbying contracts was treated
much like the role of temptation in conflict of interest cases, ex-
cept that with lobbying, the conflict posed was between the role
of citizen or legislator and the role of lobbyist or lobbied. In Mc-
Ghee v. Lindsay, an Alabama case, the court refused to enforce
a public contract in which a state-employed supervisor had an
168 corruption in america
interest. The court talked about how no man can serve two
masters with conflicting interests.45 Doing so creates “a tempta-
tion, perhaps . . . too strong for resistance by men of flexible
morals, or hackneied in the common devices of worldly busi-
ness, . . . which would betray them into gross misconduct, and
even crime.” The court focused on creating structures where
temptations do not exist for men with “flexible morals” or those
who are steeped in the usual run of business behavior. In fact,
even though there was no evidence of bribery or an incorrect
price, the court adopted the policy of not enforcing these con-
tracts as a “preventive check against such temptations and se-
ductions.” The Vermont Supreme Court, for instance, held that
“the sale by an individual of his personal influence and solicita-
tions, to procure the passage of a public or private law by the
legislature, is void as being prejudicial to sound legislation, man-
ifestly injurious to the interests of the state, and in express and
unquestionable contravention of public policy.”46 It is totally ir-
relevant to look at whether the sale was effective or not, and
whether or not anything improper was done. “The principle of
these decisions has no respect to the equities between the par-
ties, but is controlled solely by the tendency of the contract.”47
A person cannot “with propriety be employed to exert his per-
sonal influence, whether it be great or little, with individual
members, or to labor privately in any form with them, out of the
legislative halls, in favor of or against any act or subject of legis-
lation.”48 The court should discourage those practices “if it cor-
rupts or tends to corrupt some, or if it deceives or tends to de-
ceive or mislead some.”49
Many of these cases involved contingency fees. Courts would
routinely declare that contracts for contingent fees to obtain
the forgotten law of lobbying 169
j
The Gilded Age
Isolated Elites
The Pendleton Act and the Australian ballot reforms played an
important role in rethinking the kind of anticorruption law that
was possible. Still, at the end of the nineteenth century, demo-
cratic politics was increasingly dominated by wealth and the
country had no general theory about how money and politics
should interact. Some late-century elites who condemned vote
buying and the spoils system thought the use of money to influ-
ence official behavior was legitimate and simply part of political
practice. Members of the public, on the other hand, condemned
the corporate trusts and their corrupt campaign contributions.
In The Gilded Age, Mark Twain and Charles Dudley Warner’s
wry novel about lobbying and land speculation, the protagonist,
Laura Hawkins, is transformed from an unsophisticated woman
the gilded age 181
railed: “Can Mr. Hanna buy the voters of the Midwest? The
Standard Oil Company, the great railroad corporations, the big
manufacturing trusts, the bond syndicates, Mr. Carnegie, Mr.
Pierpont Morgan, Mr. Huntington, and all the rest of the high-
minded patriots who are furnishing Mr. Hanna with the means
to defend the national honor, think he can.”10 Whether through
purchase or persuasion, or a blend of the two, Hanna’s tactics
worked, and McKinley defeated Bryan in 1896, and again in 1900.
On September 6, 1901, a “medium sized man of ordinary ap-
pearance” approached President McKinley in the Temple of
Music at the Pan-American Exposition in Buffalo, New York,
and shot him in the abdomen. McKinley died a week later. Vice
President Teddy Roosevelt became the president of the United
States. Roosevelt brought an almost religious, prosecutorial zeal
to the office and made fighting corruption, “and above all cor-
ruption in public life,” a centerpiece of his eight years in office.11
Roosevelt was a former New York City police commissioner
who fancied himself capable of rooting out individual vice, an
ambitious politician who dreamed of building his heroic stature
through individual indictments. And, like Franklin, his experi-
ence led him to be particularly drawn to structural reforms that
would change systems. He was in many ways a corrupt old fox
like Franklin and knew how to work his way around a room of
millionaires.
Whether driven by fear of another Bryan challenge—or
something similar—or his own convictions, he came into office
proclaiming a vision of ridding the country of the corruption of
the prior generations. Roosevelt’s approach formed the basis of
twentieth-century anticorruption law.
chapter nine
j
Two Kinds of Sticks
Free and honest elections are the very foundation of our re-
publican form of government. . . . The fact that a particular
192 corruption in america
j
The Jury Decides
and actions. The use of the mail fraud statute exemplified this
permissiveness.
The use of influence by Shushan, the former head of the New
Orleans Levee Board, and Herbert Waguespack, a member of
the finance committee of the same board, was at the heart of the
case. They had successfully persuaded the board to authorize a
New Orleans bond repayment at a lucrative percentage when
they both had a major financial interest in the authorization.
They stood to earn hundreds of thousands of dollars in fees, to
be split between them and their coconspirators.
Shushan’s job had been to persuade the Louisiana governor,
who had influence but lacked formal authority. Waguespack
had argued for the bonds in his official role. An employee of the
board was paid to spy on what competitors in the bond business
were doing. None of the people involved had direct decision-
making authority except Waguespack, and he did not have a
deciding vote. All of these agreements were concealed from the
other decision makers.
The story stank when it came out, but prosecutors had two
problems. First, there was no evidence that the city of New Or-
leans was actually hurt by the decision. Second, the general fed-
eral bribery law did not reach state officials. To solve both of
these problems they turned to a federal law that had been
passed sixty years earlier, the federal mail fraud statute. The
mail fraud provision, enacted in 1872, was designed to combat
abuse of the post office. It criminalized using the mail to ad-
vance “any scheme or artifice to defraud.” In 1909 Congress
amended it to prohibit “any scheme or artifice to defraud, or for
obtaining money or property by means of false or fraudulent
pretenses, representations, or promises.” It was written in a
the jury decides 197
Permissiveness
State courts allowed prosecutions for bribes that were offered
but not accepted and bribes that did not clarify the precise offi-
cial action that the briber wanted done.7 A public official could
be guilty of accepting a bribe even if he had no intent to change
his behavior. She could be guilty of bribery for being influenced
on actions over which she had no authority.8 The criminal law,
like the lobbying law before it, was designed to protect citizens
from situations in which they might be tempted.
The language that surrounded these cases emphasized the
democratic harm that bribery posed. As one court said, “the gist
of the crime of bribery is the wrong done to the people by cor-
ruption in the public service.” 9 In a 1940 case, an Oklahoma
court explained why bribery had to be interpreted broadly.
the jury decides 201
What Is “Corruptly”?
As the Hobbs Act and other motive-based criminal laws started
being used by prosecutors with increasing frequency, courts
had to confront jury instructions for decidedly political terms.
Did juries need to be told that an act had been done “corruptly”?
If so, what constituted “corrupt”? If “corrupt” was an element of
the crime, courts largely left the definition of corrupt up to the
jury or described it in equally moral and imprecise language.
Nor was it always entirely clear whether “corruptly” was a sepa-
rate element of an offense that needed to be found, a superfluous
adjective, or an essential adjective. Corruption could mean “im-
proper motive.”15 It could mean “intent to influence” governmen-
tal action.16 One court held that New Jersey law required a “cor-
ruptly” instruction to accompany an extortion charge, concluding
that “corruptly” meant knowing the payment was unlawful.17 It
could mean “committed for a personal benefit.”18
the jury decides 203
j
Operation Gemstone
Buckley v. Valeo
The law was immediately challenged in court. In 1976, in Buck-
ley v. Valeo, the Supreme Court upheld most of the law but
struck down the spending limits on First Amendment grounds.
It upheld the contribution limits, disclosure, and the presiden-
tial system for publicly funding elections. The unsigned opin-
ion, 138 pages long, held that legislatively passed spending limits
were unconstitutional because they infringed upon the First
Amendment and were not sufficiently related to solving the
problem of corruption. The primary interest of the Federal Elec-
tion Campaign Act, the Court concluded, is “the prevention of
corruption and the appearance of corruption spawned by the real
or imagined coercive influence of large financial contributions on
candidates’ positions and on their actions if elected to office.”1
208 corruption in america
j
A West Virginia State of Mind
A Question of Fact
The earliest cases confronting the prosecution of campaign con-
tributions as bribes treated them the same as other bribery
charges. A 1927 case put it simply: “If it was accepted as a campaign
contribution it was, nevertheless, bribery. It is not the use to which
the money was put, but the purpose for which it was paid.”4 A 1938
appeal upheld a jury conviction for bribery based on campaign
contributions. There was conflicting evidence about a series of in-
teractions between a de facto public officer and the owner of a pipe
company. The jury heard statements like “If we would get together,
we might do both ourselves some good,” that led the owner of the
pipe company to believe that he was being asked to give campaign
contributions in exchange for a government contract. On appeal,
a west virginia state of mind 219
j
Citizens United
Democratic Responsiveness
Nine years after Sun Diamond, a small, conservative nonprofit cor-
poration named Citizens United wanted to air a ninety-minute
230 corruption in america
“Questions”
The Polity
Kennedy’s opinion paints an apolitical vision of democracy, far
removed from the founding vision. We are a nation of consum-
citi zens united 235
Buckley mentions quid pro quo, and then courts started as-
sociating it with criminal law definitions. Even since Buckley, its
use is inconsistent, and most states have not adopted a quid pro
quo requirement for any of their bribery laws. In New York, the
first mention of quid quo pro in the bribery context was in
1972,11 and it has been mentioned only seven times after that.
When the elements of bribery are listed, quid pro quo is not one
of them. Florida recently concluded that its statute includes no
quid pro quo requirement.12 The Arizona bribery statute does
not incorporate an explicit quid pro quo requirement.13 Ohio
does not use quid pro quo, but measures by “improper influ-
ence.”14 In Alabama, corrupt intent is the key and is measured
by the jury.15 Michigan’s statutes that use “corrupt” do not have a
quid pro quo requirement.16 Of course, some state courts—like
Indiana, Texas, and Massachusetts—have found that the bribery
statute does require quid pro quo.17
In the minority of jurisdictions that use quid pro quo there is no
agreement about what it means. As the Sixth Circuit quipped, just
before citing The Godfather: “Not all quid pro quos are made of the
same stuff.”18 Quid pro quo sometimes means the solicitation or
offer of something specific in exchange for some specific govern-
mental action. It sometimes means an agreement without a partic-
ular governmental action identified. It sometimes requires a spo-
ken or written request, sometimes something less, when the
potential bribe is a campaign contribution. Sometimes quid pro
quo means intent to influence unspecified governmental activity
“as opportunities arise.”19 As we have seen, quid pro quo also means
something different in campaign finance situations, because of the
Supreme Court’s own jurisprudence limiting the application of
general bribery and extortion laws to campaign activity.
citi zens united 241
The phrase quid pro quo, in short, seems related to ideas about
specificity and explicitness but does not actually stand for a
completely coherent concept. It certainly does not refer to a
historical one. But quid pro quo is a new phrase, both in rela-
tion to corruption laws and in relation to bribery laws. When
Justice Scalia refers to the “quid pro quo roots” of corruption,
he means, in fact, a rootless phrase, or a phrase rooted in an-
other area of law.
This uprooting has real consequences. It is now legal to spend
as much money as possible to influence politics except in two
ways: First, you cannot directly offer an exchange of money for
official action. Second, you must abide by direct campaign con-
tribution limits. These remaining limits are arbitrary. There is
not a deep logic to them.
• • •
j
The New Snuff Boxes
that are indirect and implicit. The former may be only the
more detectable, not necessarily the more deliberate or
damaging, form of corruption. Corruption that works
through patterns of conduct, institutional routines, and
informal norms may leave fewer footprints but more wreck-
age in its path.8
money was once an incidental part of the job. Since the 1990s,
however, raising money is the primary job of federal officials:
they spend between 30 and 70 percent of their time every week
raising money.11
If the CEO of a corporation came to a senator and said, “I
will give you $1 million to reverse the role of two priorities on
your agenda,” that would be an illegal bribe. Instead, the corpo-
ration pays a lobbyist $1 million to figure out the set of gifts and
relationships that will lead to something it wants (or in this case
doesn’t want—getting taken off the senator’s agenda). The in-
terplay presents the same issues as the moral temptations posed
by foreign gifts that the framers imagined. From the perspec-
tive of each of the parties, a changed agenda seems simply like a
genuine need getting met and a genuine appreciation being ex-
pressed. To return to West Virginia, McCormick already cared
about the lack of medical services, and he met someone who
had an idea that related to it. The lobbyist was happy to get paid
and to communicate ideas and relevant information about the
doctors to McCormick. And the doctors were genuinely sup-
portive of McCormick and wanted him to get reelected. They
wanted him to know that they supported him because they knew
he was more likely to work on their bill, instead of another, if
they gave him money. But they also felt good about him and felt
personal warmth and generosity toward him after he passed
the bill.
After each positive interaction, everyone involved will look
for more ways to connect. McCormick—or his campaign
manager—knew the foreign doctors had money, and he needed
money to get reelected. The doctors felt their money made a big
difference. And the lobbyist was happy to facilitate and get
the new snuff boxes 253
j
Facts in Exile, Complacency,
and Disdain
cal community. Yet to deny the positive law structure, and the
premise of the self-interested man or woman, would be to deny
the grammar of her academic community. The failure of the law
and economics movement to provide a theory of corruption that
makes sense in modern democracy is a fatal failure, a failure that
shows the limits of the theory itself.
Her ambition reflects a widespread effort to replace corrup-
tion’s historical association with private interest with law and
economics’ deep association with efficiency, while still using the
superficial language of corruption. The problem is that it be-
comes very hard to talk about corruption without talking about
virtue or becoming circular. This view about what constitutes a
person—and what constitutes corruption—has deep roots in an
older ideological fight, as I discussed earlier, the fight between
Montesquieu and Hobbes.
As you will recall, according to Hobbes’s theory of language,
the word corruption refers to nothing. He had little patience for
words like good, bad, or covetous, which, to him, just meant “what
I like,” and “what I don’t like.” He believed that whoever governs
also governs language, so the idea of “injustice” does not make
sense, because the lawgiver would not ever accuse himself, and
the lawgiver would not create a word for others to accuse him
with. The political theorist J. Peter Euben contrasted Hobbes’s
and Aristotle’s ideas about corruption in a lovely essay about the
history of the term.4 He argued that Hobbes’s view
The same may be true for some of the modern justices’ views
of corruption. It may not be so much that they disagree with
the historical meaning but that it simply does not make sense
to them.
Complacency
Given the selfish man model that undergirds much of modern
thinking, you might expect the majority of the Supreme Court
to have a dismal view of society. But instead, the 2014 Court is
striking for its lack of concern about the threat of political col-
lapse. Instead of a Hobbesian battle for food and shelter and
power, the government is described as largely, if not entirely,
static in the corruption cases. One gets the sense that no theory
of government is needed because the democratic state is like
air—necessary, a part of life itself, unavoidable in the best sense,
invisible because so central. Their thin descriptions of govern-
ment make sense if problems of political organization are not
serious ones. Democracy may be, in their minds, fundamentally
solved and stable. While we can quibble at the margins about
the scope of government, the basic shape of government is stable
and not likely to change.
This feature suggests that the Court’s indifference toward
corruption might reflect an end of history ideology that has
facts in exile, complacency, and disdain 265
been part of our culture for the last quarter century, an ideology
that also has its roots in law and economics. In 1989 the Berlin
Wall came down, and the Soviet Union began to splinter. Ron
Brown became chair of the DNC, the first African American to
head a major political party. Francis Fukuyama wrote an essay
(later expanded into a book) arguing that liberal democracy is
an equilibrium state and there is no postliberal democracy sys-
tem. He argued: “What we may be witnessing is not just the
end of the Cold War, or the passing of a particular period of
post-war history, but the end of history as such: that is, the end
point of mankind’s ideological evolution and the universaliza-
tion of Western liberal democracy as the final form of human
government.”
Fukuyama’s article was largely about the nature of thinking,
not the nature of events. His argument was essentially that the
ideal form of government had been discovered, not that it would
stop history. In this, it was not so different from the prior 200
years of argument: that liberal representative democracy was a
superior form of government. However, its powerful impact on
the popular culture, the thing that turned him into an object of
constant discussion, was not the theory of the history of thought
but the theory of the history of world events. The key feature of
this view—as interpreted, not as written—was its political op-
timism. Fukuyama came to be a stand-in for the view that lib-
eral democracy is an end of history in a different sense: liberal
democracy is unlikely to turn into a totalitarian regime, and it is
just a matter of time before other countries catch up to the
United States and Western Europe.6
Fukuyama caught fire because he said (or was perceived to
have said) what so many at the time believed, and continue to
266 corruption in america
Disdain
Perhaps, like Russell Hardin, some justices have abandoned
faith in democratic politics. There is some evidence that the jus-
tices still believe in a broad theory of corruption but think of
politics as essentially corrupt, and not worth saving. For in-
stance, the same justices who concluded that no facts were nec-
essary in Citizens United argued that there should be close judi-
cial inspection of facts in takings clause cases, to determine
whether private interest played too large a role in legislative
choices. In the case of Kelo v. City of New London, New London
used eminent domain to take Suzette Kelo’s home and give the
land to a private developer with ties to the drug company Pfizer.
The Supreme Court had to decide whether this action vio-
lated the Fifth Amendment. The Constitution states that pri-
vate property cannot be taken for “public use” without “ just
compensation.” The implication of the clause is that taking
for public use—the exercise of eminent domain—is legitimate,
whereas taking for private purposes is not. It is difficult to draw
a clear line between what constitutes a public use and what con-
stitutes a private use. In early law, “public use,” was interpreted
as “use by the public.” Any taking from one private party to give
to another private party was outside the governmental power. A
268 corruption in america
and rejected it. The majority held that the city would not be al-
lowed to “take property under the mere pretext of a public pur-
pose, when its actual purpose was to bestow a private benefit.”
This language advocates for a review that Fletcher v. Peck argu-
ably precluded: a close examination of the reasons that a legisla-
tive body passed something, an examination of motive. Justice
O’Connor, in dissent, essentially argued that the “public use” pro-
vision of the takings clause was an anticorruption provision:
“The beneficiaries are likely to be those citizens with dispropor-
tionate influence and power in the political process, including
large corporations and development firms.”
Justice Kennedy, in concurrence, pointedly argued for greater
scrutiny of the process by which takings happen. In Kelo, he said
that the equal protection clause protects against “a govern-
ment classification that is clearly intended to injure a par ticu-
lar class of private parties, with only incidental or pretextual
public justifications.”
Because the different working parts of modern corruption
law exist in isolation, each from the other, the dissonance be-
tween Kennedy’s approach here and in political cases was not
addressed. In Citizens United, he argued that it was the essence
of politics to seek out influence for private reasons. In Kelo, he
argued against partiality. Scalia reveals a similar schizophrenia.
In another case, outside the field of election law, he argues that
there is a “fundamental constraint” that democratic decisions
“be taken in order to further a public purpose rather than a purely
private interest.”10 But in the campaign finance cases, he derides
the idea that any public purpose can be understood. To put it
another way: anything but quid pro quo corruption seems too
vague for Justices Kennedy and Scalia when they are reviewing
270 corruption in america
treme case where there was no need for direct evidence of actual
bias. Objective facts, he held, raised the probability of bias.
In Caperton, Kennedy’s language was psychological and re-
ferred to temptation and human nature and the dangers that
come from actions that are not criminal bribes. He recognized
that “the fact that the inquiry is often a private one, simply
underscore[s] the need for objective rules.” Otherwise, he held,
judges could be influenced and there would be no recourse.11
The same argument about the need for objective rules applies to
spending around nonjudicial elections. However, there are two
different standards. The best explanation for the different stan-
dards may lie in the fact that Kennedy has greater respect for
judicial processes than democratic ones.
Biography
The disconnection from political facts, and apparent distaste
for politics, may also be exacerbated by the rarified biographies
of the modern Supreme Court justices. Personal history may
have particular force when it comes to judicial understanding of,
and respect for, democratic politics. Our current Court is en-
tirely made up of elite academics and appellate judges. It was not
always so.
When Justice Noah Haynes Swayne wrote the opinion of
the Court in Trist v. Child—the opinion that refused to enforce
a contract to lobby as against the public policy of the United
States—it was not as a naive academic or utopian but as some-
one who had lived inside the logic of politics for over fifty years,
as a candidate, organizer, appointee, councilman, and state repre-
sentative. Swayne wrote that lobbying is “contrary to the plainest
272 corruption in america
who have lived a political life will undoubtedly admit there are
dingy deals and terrible pressures, they may be more likely to
believe in the human capacity for civic attention and love. Those
involved in politics will bring a more subtle understanding of
the psychological ways in which gifts and money change poli-
tics. The visceral experience of politics—like the visceral expe-
riences of art, theater, and love, perhaps—is fundamentally dif-
ferent than the imagined, or theorized, life of politics.
At their worst, the lack of experience of politics may lead to
the apparent contempt for politics itself.14 They may perceive
corruption as a minor threat, or perhaps they perceive it as part
and parcel of politics, which is essentially rabble: not responsive,
not efficient. Political theorist Hannah Arendt describes the
antipolitical strain in modern society as coming from both the
platonic philosophical tradition and the Christian tradition
that encourages people to remove themselves from the contam-
inating political society. A rejection of politics may represent
both fear and hope—fear of politics taking over everything
and hope for a future without politics. This imagined a-politi-
cal politics involves a wise bureaucratic state managing policy
issues; the citizen is free to pursue his or her own ends without
having to engage in self-government. Rationality controls, and
the parceling power, is not a primary puzzle. In Arendt’s char-
acterization, academics sometimes see politics as a refuge of
those who have lesser virtues; it is associated with the antiphi-
losophical. Politics contaminates thinking. She rejects this
view, but her description resonates with some of the academics
on the Court.
The antipolitical strain aligns with the way that some justices
treat corruption, fully imagined, as an incoherent and outdated
facts in exile, complacency, and disdain 275
j
The Anticorruption Principle
and influence that flows from that donation, not all voices are
heard equally. Governments should be free to pursue relative
political equality in their campaign financing systems. This,
equality theorists say, is the real problem, not corruption. Bruce
Cain argues that “by littering the intellectual landscape with
irrelevant issues, moral idealists obstruct the path to a full, open
discussion of the public’s views about the proper distribution of
power and influence.”14 According to Cain, the language of cor-
ruption serves to disrupt a serious discussion of equality
concerns.
David Strauss similarly argues that corruption is a “deriva-
tive problem.” He argues that those who claim they are worried
about corruption are “actually concerned” about inequality. He
argues that if there were actual political equality, “much of the
reason to be concerned about corruption would no longer ex-
ist.”15 Any remaining worries would themselves be functions of
other inequality concerns that arise when interest group poli-
tics takes over the democratic process to give unequal power to
voters. Kathleen Sullivan argues that corruption “is really a vari-
ant on the problem of political equality: unequal outlays of politi-
cal money create inequality in political representation.”16
Rick Hasen has been a prominent proponent of the equality
argument as both a normative and descriptive matter. He ar-
gues that the non–quid pro quo arguments from the justices
after Buckley are described in terms of corruption but are actu-
ally, and rightly, grounded in equality concerns.17 As he describes
it, “A political equality argument is one which seeks to justify a
law on grounds that it distributes political power fairly or seeks to
attack a law in court on grounds that it distributes political power
in an unequal way.”18 When the Court describes nonexchange
282 corruption in america
public good. The goal of the equality theorists and the tradi-
tional corruption theorists is substantially similar. But equality
theorists are not as focused on public orientation. The grammar
of politics, its emotional and intimate role, is less important for
them. Political actors (citizens and officials) play a fairly me-
chanical role in this worldview. They process information (gained
by access) fairly directly—the more of one kind of input, the more
of that kind of output. The elected officials play a processing role
and do not operate as independent moral agents. They are influ-
enced directly: the more pressure from campaign contributions,
the more likely their decisions will be shaped. There are stronger
and weaker versions of this—radical equality or rough equality,
or simply the absence of radical inequality.
One way to understand the difference is to imagine the mind
of a senator. The equality theorist would want that senator to
consider each member of his constituency equally and would be
satisfied if the senator did so because each citizen gave him
$100, an equal amount. The framers, on the other hand, wanted
that, but also a fundamental, emotional identification with the
public. A senator who considers each constituent equally only be-
cause of the campaign money, but whose core obsession is getting
reelected so he can get a great job as a lobbyist afterward, could
serve equality goals but still be corrupt. Whereas the equality
theorists focus on the equal treatment of multiple private inter-
ests, the framers believed that one could imagine “the public in-
terest” and that people, at their best, would put others’ interests
on equal footing with their own in a nonmechanical way.
Montesquieu treated corruption and equality as related con-
cepts when he described virtue in a republic as the “love of equal-
ity.”19 Montesquieu believed citizens should love equality not
284 corruption in america
Structural Rules
At the Constitutional Convention the anticorruption principle
led to many bright-line rules, which have fared pretty well, and
the anticorruption principle 285
Plurality
As Deborah Hellman argued many years ago, a commitment to
understanding corruption requires public engagement in defin-
ing what does and does not constitute legitimate private inter-
est.23 One cannot shy away from fundamental determinations
about the scope of public and private morality, many of which I
cannot fully engage here, but one seems important: the rela-
tionship of concepts of corruption to group interest. Is someone
who serves their own group interests—like the interests of a
church, a union, or a trade association—corrupt, or virtuous?
What if they do so knowing it hurts the public good? The clas-
sic conception of corruption might seem incompatible with
modern “plural” democracies. Modern pluralists note that
people tend to be most politically engaged when they work with
associations, and these associations work to further their own
interests. Democracy is at its best when people form into groups,
288 corruption in america
New Structures
Fortunately, the same history that teaches us that corruption
was a foundational principle teaches us that structural changes
are possible even within the constraints of a misinterpreted Con-
stitution. We can fundamentally rearrange power dynamics and
improve representative democracy even without a new Court, or
court packing. For instance, states and the federal government
conclusion 299
• • •
In April 2014, shortly before this book went to press, the Su-
preme Court decided McCutcheon v. FEC. The question before
the Court was whether Congress violated the First Amend-
ment by passing a law that limited the total amount of money
an individual could give to all federal candidates. Chief Justice
John Roberts wrote for the majority, concluding that this ag-
conclusion 303
j
Anticorruption
Constitutional Provisions
The Number of Representatives shall not exceed one for every thirty Thou-
sand, but each State shall have at Least one Representative; and until such
enumeration shall be made, the State of New Hampshire shall be entitled
to chuse three, Massachusetts eight, Rhode Island and Providence Planta-
tions one, Connecticut five, New York six, New Jersey four, Pennsylvania
eight, Delaware one, Maryland six, Virginia ten, North Carolina five, South
Carolina five, and Georgia three.
article i, section 3, clause 1. The Senate of the United States shall
be composed of two Senators from each State, chosen by the Legislature
thereof for six Years, and each Senator shall have one Vote.
article i, section 3, clause 3. No Person shall be a Senator who shall
not have attained to the Age of thirty Years, and been nine Years a Citizen
of the United States, and who shall not, when elected, be an Inhabitant of
that State for which he shall be chosen.
article i, section 5, clause 3. Each House shall keep a Journal of its
Proceedings, and from time to time publish the same, excepting such Parts
as may in their Judgment require Secrecy; and the Yeas and Nays of the
Members of either House on any question shall, at the Desire of one fifth of
those Present, be entered on the Journal.
article i, section 6, clause 1. The Senators and Representatives
shall receive a Compensation for their Services, to be ascertained by Law,
and paid out of the Treasury of the United States.
article i, section 6, clause 2. No Person holding any Office under
the United States, shall be a Member of either House during his Continu-
ance in Office. No Senator or Representative shall, during the Time for
which he was elected, be appointed to any civil Office under the Authority
of the United States, which shall have been created, or the Emoluments
whereof shall have been increased during such time.
article i, section 8. Congress shall have the power . . .
Clause 8. To promote the Progress of Science and useful Arts, by secur-
ing for limited Times to Authors and Inventors the exclusive Right to
their respective Writings and Discoveries.
appendix 1 309
j
Major Nineteenth- and
Twentieth-Century
Anticorruption Laws
mail fraud act (1872). Covered state and federal officials, criminalized
the use of the mails for fraud, including, controversially, defrauding the
public. Interpreted in 1927 to criminalize the theft of honest services.
tillman act (1907). Prohibited corporations from contributing money
to federal campaigns.
In the 1920s, in response to the Teapot Dome scandal, Congress passed
laws requiring disclosure to enable enforcement of the corporate contribu-
tion laws.
hatch act (1939). Enacted regulation of primaries by Congress. Limited
contributions and expenditures in congressional elections. Prohibited all fed-
eral employees from soliciting campaign contributions. Amended in 1940 to
place limits on how much an individual could give to a candidate and a limit
on how much a national party committee could spend. After the Hatch Act,
total campaign spending dipped and did not reach 1936 levels until nearly a
quarter century later.
hobbs act (1946). Covered state and federal officials, controversially held
to criminalize the use of an official position to extort funds.
312 appendix 2
Introduction
1. Larry Tise, The American Counterrevolution: A Retreat from Liberty,
1783–1800 (Mechanicsburg, PA: Stackpole Books, 1998), 59.
2. Letter from William Temple Franklin to Thomas Jefferson, April 27,
1790, in The Founders’ Constitution, vol. 3, ed. Philip B. Kurland and Ralph
Lerner (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 385. Picture of the cur-
rent portrait available at the website of the American Philosophical Society,
http://www.amphilsoc.org/exhibits/treasures/louis.htm.
3. Washington correspondent of the Chicago Press and Tribune, New
York Times, March 29, 1860, http://www.nytimes.com/1860/03/29/news
/the-newspaper-press-of-washington-and-new-york.html.
4. Robert Penn Warren, All the King’s Men (San Diego: Harcourt Brace,
1996), chapter 5.
15. Richard Henry Lee, The Life of Arthur Lee (Boston: Wells and Lilly,
1829), 143.
16. Letter from Arthur Lee to the Committee of Foreign Affairs, Janu-
ary 19, 1780, in The Diplomatic Correspondence of the American Revolution
(Washington, DC: Rives, 1818), 580.
17. Letter from Vergennes to Luzerne, February 5, 1780, in Emerging Na-
tion: A Documentary History of the Foreign Relations of the United States under
the Articles of Confederation, vol. 1, ed. Mary A. Giunta (Washington, DC: U.S.
Independent Agencies and Commissions, 1996), 24, discovered in T. Lawrence
Larkin, “A ‘Gift’ Strategically Solicited and Magnanimously Conferred: The
American Congress, the French Monarchy, and the State Portraits of Louis
XVI and Marie-Antoinette,” Winterthur Portfolio 44 (2010): 31.
18. Letter from Arthur Lee, Diplomatic Correspondence, 580.
19. Emerging Nation, 198.
20. Letter from John Jay to Don Diego de Gardoqui, March 1, 1786, re-
printed in The Diplomatic Correspondence of the United States of America
(Washington, DC: Frances Preston Blair, 1833), 142.
21. Catherine Drinker Bowen, Miracle at Philadelphia: The Story of the Con-
stitutional Convention, May–September 1787 (Boston: Back Bay Books, 1986), 17.
22. Schiff, Great Improvisation, 153.
23. This was discussed in an opinion by the Office of Legal Counsel,
“President Reagan’s Ability to Receive Retirement Benefits from the State
of California,” Opinion of the Office of Legal Counsel 5 (1981): 188.
24. The other difference is that the “or any of them” is collapsed into the
“them” of the clause.
25. See Letter from John Quincy Adams to John Adams, June 7, 1797, in
Writings of John Quincy Adams, vol. 2, ed. Worthington Chauncey Ford
(New York: McMillan, 1913), 180n1.
26. The historical treatment of the “box” as Franklin’s comes from this
note, which was included in Max Farrand’s Records of the Federal Conven-
tion and therefore has achieved notoriety: “Dr. Franklin is the person al-
luded to by Randolph. In the winter of 1856, in Philadelphia, under the roof
of a venerable granddaughter of Dr. Franklin, I saw the beautiful portrait of
Louis XVI, snuff-box size, presented by that king to the doctor. As the por-
trait is exactly such as is contained in the snuff-boxes presented by Crowned
316 notes to pages 28–33
heads, one of which I have seen, it is probable this portrait of Louis was
originally attached to the box in question, which has in the lapse of years
been lost or given away by Dr. Franklin.” The Records of the Federal Conven-
tion of 1787, vol. 3, ed. Max Farrand (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press,
1911), 327, citing H. B. Grigsby, History of the Virginia Federal Convention of
1788, vol. 9 (Richmond: Virginia Historical Society Collections, 1980), 264.
It is of course possible that the snuff box was Lee’s or Deane’s.
27. See Edmund Randolph, “Remarks at the Virginia Convention De-
bates,” in David Robertson, Debates and Other Proceedings of the Convention
of Virginia of 1788, 2nd ed. (Richmond, VA: Enquirer Press, 1805), 321–345.
28. A First Amendment written with the same emphatic language would
have to be “Congress Shall Make no Law of any kind whatever . . .”
29. Merrill D. Peterson, Thomas F. Jefferson and the New Nation: A Biog-
raphy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975), 401.
30. Martha Rojas, in Old World, New World: America and Europe in the
Age of Jefferson, ed. Leonard Sadowsky (Richmond: University of Virginia
Press, 2010), 179.
31. Howard C. Rice Jr., Thomas Jefferson’s Paris (Princeton, NJ: Prince-
ton University Press, 1976), 123.
32. “To Thomas Jefferson from William Short, 2 May 1791,” Founders
Online, National Archives, http://founders.archives.gov/documents/Jeffer
son/01-20-02-0103, source: The Papers of Thomas Jefferson, vol. 20, April
1–August 4, 1791, ed. Julian P. Boyd (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1982), 345–352.
33. John Bassett Moore, A Digest of International Law, vol. 5 (Washing-
ton, DC: Government Printing Office, 1906), section 651.
3. “Begs the favour from mr. franklin that he Pleases to let him know by the
way of the Penny post if he wants more mr. Gibbon’s history of the Roman
Empire and Garma’s teatro de España. Mr. franklin may keep them if not
Read as long as he pleases but mr. Sarsfield wants to know it as one of those
Books do not belong to him and he desires to be able to give an account of it to
the owner.” “To Benjamin Franklin from the Comte de Sarsfield,” November
7, 1777, Founders Online, National Archives, http://founders.archives.gov
/documents/Franklin/01-25-02-0093, source: The Papers of Benjamin Franklin,
vol. 25, October 1, 1777, through February 28, 1778, ed. William B. Willcox (New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1986), 143. He asked first in April, then in
late fall begged, “Si monsieur franklin n’a plus besoin . . . de l’histoire romaine
de M. Gibbons, il fera plaisir a M. de Sarsfield de les lui rapporter mercredi”
(“If Mr. Franklin doesn’t need M. Gibbon’s Roman history, it would please Mr.
Sarsfield if you could bring it back Wednesday”).“To Benjamin Franklin from
Guy-Claude, Comte de Sarsfield,” April 4, 1778, Founders Online, National
Archives, http://founders.archives.gov/documents/Franklin/01-26-02-0175,
source: The Papers of Benjamin Franklin, vol. 26, March 1 through June 30, 1778,
ed. William B. Willcox (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1987), 241.
4. Bernard Bailyn, The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution
(Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1992), 26.
“Did not Persia and Macedon distract the councils of Greece by acts of cor-
ruption?” (quoting Madison).
5. Ibid., 173.
6. Carl J. Richard, Greeks and Romans Bearing Gifts: How the Ancients In-
spired the Founding Fathers (Lanham, MD: Roman and Littlefield, 2009), 129.
7. Edmund Burke, “Speech on Conciliation with America,” March 22,
1775, reprinted in Edmund Burke, Selected Writings, ed. Peter Stanlis (New
Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers, 2009), 193.
8. Gordon S. Wood, The Americanization of Benjamin Franklin (New
York: Penguin, 2005), 96.
9. Patrick Henry, “Speech in the Convention of Virginia on the Expedi-
ency of Adopting the Federal Constitution,” June 7, 1788, reprinted in E. B.
Williston, Eloquence of the United States, vol. 1 (Middletown, CT: E. and H.
Clark, 1827), 223. Note that Britain is a model and bogeyman—fundamental
admiration for British form undergirds design efforts for federalists and
318 notes to pages 37–42
antifederalists alike. See also Gordon S. Wood, The Creation of the Ameri-
can Republic, 1776–1787 (New York: W. W. Norton, 1969), 32.
10. Notes of Yates, June 22, 1787, in The Records of the Federal Convention
of 1787, vol. 1, ed. Max Farrand (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press,
1911) (hereafter Records).
11. Catherine Drinker Bowen, Miracle at Philadelphia: The Story of the Con-
stitutional Convention, May–September 1787 (Boston: Back Bay Books, 1986), 17.
12. Notes of Madison, August 14, 1787, in Records, vol. 2; Woody Holton
develops this idea in Unruly Americans and the Origins of the Constitution
(New York: Hill and Wang, 2007).
13. J. G. A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought
and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1975), 507.
14. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, xiii.
15. James D. Savage, “Corruption and Virtue at the Constitutional Con-
vention,” Journal of Politics 56 (1994): 181.
16. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, 131.
17. Notes of Yates, June 22, 1787, in Records, vol. 1, quoting Mason.
18. Gordon S. Wood, Radicalism of the American Revolution (New York:
Knopf, 1992), 109.
19. Ibid., 183.
20. Ibid., 108.
21. Ibid., 176.
22. Ibid., 175.
23. Lance Banning, The Jeffersonian Persuasion (Ithaca, NY: Cornell Uni-
versity Press, 1980), 47.
24. Bailyn, Ideological Origins, 345; one can also find a discussion in Don-
ald S. Lutz, “The Relative Influence of European Writers on Late Eighteenth-
Century American Political Thought,” American Political Science Review 78
(1984): 189.
25. Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, Book 8, ch. 10, para. 1 (Minneapolis,
MN: Filiquarian Publishing, 2007).
26. Charles de Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws [1748], trans. Melvin
Richter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991), Book 4.
27. Ibid., Book 5, ch. 3, para. 1.
notes to pages 42–49 319
3. Removing Temptations
1. “Letter from Benjamin Franklin to Jean-Baptiste Leroy,” in Memoirs of
the Life and Writings of Benjamin Franklin, vol. 6 (London: Henry Colburn,
1818), 496.
2. Federalist No. 68 (Alexander Hamilton).
3. See James D. Savage, “Corruption and Virtue at the Constitutional
Convention,” Journal of Politics 56 (1994): 181. A review of Madison’s and
Yates’s notes shows that “corruption,” and “corrupt” (not including “corrup-
tion of blood” and its variants) show up in discussions twice as often as “fac-
tion” or “factions” and twice as often as “violent” or “violence.” See generally
Notes of Madison and Notes of Yates, in The Records of the Federal Conven-
tion of 1787, vols. 1 and 2, ed. Max Farrand (New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1911) (hereafter Records).
4. J. G. A. Pocock, The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought
and the Atlantic Republican Tradition (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1975), 513.
5. Notes of Madison, June 2, 1787, in Records, vol. 1.
6. Annals of Congress, vol. 1 (1789–1790), 581, in Records, vol. 3.
7. U.S. Term Limits, Inc. v. Thornton, 514 U.S. 779, 794 n.11 (1995) (Thomas,
J. dissenting, “The Ineligibility Clause was intended to guard against corrup-
tion.”). See also “Remarks of Alexander Hamilton,” in Records, vol. 1, 381;
Freytag v. IRS, 501 U.S. 868, 904 (1991) (Scalia, J. concurring in part and con-
curring in the judgment, “The Framers’ experience with postrevolutionary
self-government had taught them that combining the power to create offices
with the power to appoint officers was a recipe for legislative corruption.”)
8. Notes of Yates, June 22, 1787, in Records, vol. 1.
9. Notes of Madison, August 14, 1787, in Records, vol. 2.
10. Selected Works of Thomas Paine & Citizen Tom Paine, ed. Howard
Fast (New York: Modern Library, 1946), 6, 10.
11. Notes of Madison, September 6, 1787, in Records, vol. 2.
12. Notes of Yates, June 22, 1787, in Records, vol. 1, quoting Mason.
13. Ibid., quoting Butler.
14. Annals of Congress, vol. 1 (1798), 905, in Records, vol. 3, 375.
15. Ibid.
16. Ibid.
322 notes to pages 66–74
vol. 2, ed. James Harvey Robinson and Charles Austin Beard (Boston:
Ginn & Company, 1909), 240.
35. Speech of John Wilkes, “Debate on Mr. Wilkes Motion for a More
Equal Representation,” in The Parliamentary History of England, vol. 18,
1774–1777 (London: T. C. Hansard, 1803), 1296.
36. Ralph Griffiths, “Review of George Edwards, Royal and Constitu-
tional Regeneration of Great Britain,” in The Monthly Review (London: T.
Becket, January–April 1791), 72.
37. Notes of King Rufus, August 8, 1787 (quoting Mason); Notes of
Madison, August 8, 1787, in Records, vol. 2.
38. Notes of Madison, August 8, 1787, in Records, vol. 2.
39. Akhil Reed Amar, America’s Constitution: A Biography (New York:
Random House, 2005), 70.
40. Notes of Madison, July 20, 1787, in Records, vol. 2.
41. See, e.g., Colonel Richard D. Rosen, “Funding ‘Non-Traditional’
Military Operations: The Alluring Myth of a Presidential Power of the
Purse,” Military Law Review 155 (1998): 25–44 (describing English his-
tory that formed the background for the appropriations clause); and
Kate Stith, “Congress’ Power of the Purse,” Yale Law Journal 97 (1988):
1352–1353.
42. Adrien Vermeule, “Essay: The Constitutional Law of Official Com-
pensation,” Columbia Law Review 102 (2002): 509.
43. See United States v. Richardson, 418 U.S. 166, 167 n.1 (1974).
44. Malla Pollack, “Purveyance and Power or Over-Priced Free Lunch:
The Intellectual Property Clause as an Ally of the Takings Clause in the
Public’s Control of Government,” Southwestern University Law Review 30
(2000).
45. Notes of Madison, September 8, 1787, in Records, vol. 2.
46. Lawrence Lessig, “A Reply to Professor Hasen,” Harvard Law Re-
view Forum 26 (2013): 70.
4. Yazoo
1. “Report from Congress, January 4,” New York Evening Post, January 8,
1808, 2.
2. Ibid.; “Tombigbee Celebration of the Declaration of Independence,”
Raleigh (NC) Weekly Register, November 9, 1809, 4.
324 notes to pages 83– 91
22. For a further discussion and arguments that governments are agents
of their constituents, see Ethan J. Leib, David L. Ponet, and Michael Se-
rota, “A Fiduciary Theory of Judging,” California Law Review 101 (2013);
Robert G. Natelson, “The Agency Law Origins of the Necessary and Proper
Clause,” Case Western Law Review 55 (2004); and D. Theodore Rave, “Politi-
cians as Fiduciaries,” Harvard Law Review 126 (2013).
23. Theoretically, if Peck attempted to enforce his contract against the
state, he could lose, because in that case it would not be incidental. This
leads to two different legal determinations of the validity of a legislative act
depending on whether the corruption charges are incidental or central.
Probably because of the problems that would arise out of this inconsistency,
most commentators and courts have treated this case as standing for a hold-
ing he claims he is not making: that corrupt process is irrelevant.
24. For a further discussion of this argument, see Mark Graber, “Naked
Land Transfers and American Constitutional Development,” Vanderbilt
Law Review 53 (2000): 79.
25. According to Marshall, “The contract between Georgia and the pur-
chasers was executed by the grant. A contract executed, as well as one which
is executory, contains obligations binding on the parties. A grant, in its own
nature, amounts to an extinguishment of the right of the grantor, and im-
plies a contract not to reassert that right. A party is, therefore, always es-
topped by his own grant.” However, the changing of the contract to a grant
(an executed contract) does not change the obligations of the initial con-
tract. He concluded that “a law annulling conveyances between individuals,
and declaring that the grantors should stand seised of their former estates,
notwithstanding those grants, would be as repugnant to the constitution as
a law discharging the vendors of property from the obligation of executing
their contracts by conveyances. It would be strange if a contract to convey
was secured by the constitution, while an absolute conveyance remained
unprotected. . . . If, under a fair construction of the constitution, grants are
comprehended under the term contracts, is a grant from the state excluded
from the operation of the provision? Is the clause to be considered as inhib-
iting the state from impairing the obligation of contracts between two indi-
viduals, but as excluding from that inhibition contracts made with itself?
The words themselves contain no such distinction. They are general, and
are applicable to contracts of every description. If contracts made with the
326 notes to page 98
state are to be exempted from their operation, the exception must arise
from the character of the contracting party, not from the words which are
employed.” Even if it is a contracts case, Mark Graber argues, persuasively,
that the bulk of the reasoning in Fletcher v. Peck relies on common-law rules
about contracts and conveyances, and it is not really a case about the im-
pairment of contracts. Graber, “Naked Land Transfers.” It is also, as a his-
torical matter, a weak reading. Forrest McDonald has argued that this
clause was not even intended to be there in the first place. Forrest McDon-
ald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the Constitution (Law-
rence: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 273. As David Currie suggested in
his classic treaty, the “impairments of contract” clause can be seen in many
ways as an early, Marshall Court version of the later “substantive due pro-
cess.” David P. Currie, The Constitution in the Supreme Court: The First Hun-
dred Years, 1789–1888 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985). Both
were restrictions on the scope of legislative supremacy. See Timothy Sand-
efur, “Privileges, Immunities, and Substantive Due Process,” New York Uni-
versity Journal of Law and Liberty 5 (2010) (discussion of the relationship be-
tween substantive due process and the impairment of contracts). See also
James Oakes, “ ‘Property Rights’ in Constitutional Analysis Today,” Wash-
ington Law Review 56 (1981): 590–591. Oakes draws the parallel between the
obligations of contracts cases and the substantive due process cases neatly,
arguing that the first phase of property rights treatment was from Fletcher to
1887, when the contracts clause was used to invalidate dozens of pro-debtor
pieces of legislation; the second phase was the substantive due process era.
26. It is also, as a historical matter, a weak reading. Forrest McDonald
has argued that this clause was not even intended to be there in the first
place. Forrest McDonald, Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of
the Constitution (Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1985), 273. As David
Currie suggested in his classic treaty, the “impairments of contract” clause
can be seen in many ways as an early, Marshall Court version of the later
“substantive due process.” David P. Currie, The Constitution in the Supreme
Court: The First Hundred Years, 1789–1888 (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1985). Both were restrictions on the scope of legislative supremacy.
See Timothy Sandefur, “Privileges, Immunities, and Substantive Due Pro-
cess,” New York University Journal of Law and Liberty 5 (2010) (discussion of
the relationship between substantive due process and the impairments of
notes to pages 99–102 327
14. For a fuller discussion of the case’s role in contempt proceedings, see
Morton Rosenberg, Congress’s Contempt Power: Law, History, Practice, and
Procedure (Washington, DC: Congressional Research Service, 2008), 7–9.
15. The 1797 list of indictable crimes in Delaware included extortion, but
not bribery. Just as removal from office was the preferred method of pun-
ishment for many bribery statutes, the primary way in which extortion
was litigated was in the context of either contract law or “fee bills.” Fee
bills were statutes that allowed people who had been extorted to get their
money back. No intent was required in the fee bill—all someone would
have to do is demonstrate that they had paid an officer an amount in excess
of what was legally owed. See the discussion of fee bill statutes in Irons v.
Allen, 169 Pa. 633, 32 A. 655 (PA 1895) and State v. Andrews, 51 N.H. 582
(NH 1872).
16. All of these statutes are on file with the author.
17. On file with the author, cited in State v. Darnall, 20 Tenn. 290 (1839).
18. This tradition continued for some time. In 1881 Pennsylvania had a
law that anyone guilty of election-law violations—including bribery around
elections—was not eligible for future public office. Leonard v. Common-
wealth, 112 Pa. 607 (Pa. 1886).
19. See, e.g., Commonwealth v. Chapman, 1 Va. Cas. 138 (1803) (conviction
for offering the sheriff money to appoint certain people to a jury).
20. Newell v. Commonwealth, 2 Va. 88 (Va. 1795).
21. Thurston Greene, The Language of the Constitution: A Sourcebook and
Guide to the Ideas, Terms, and Vocabulary Used by the Framers of the United
States Constitution (Westport, CT: Greenwood, 1991), 108 (emphasis omit-
ted; quoting New Hampshire); The constitution of New Hampshire: as al-
tered and amended by a convention of delegates, held at Concord, in said state,
approved by the people, and established by the Convention, on the first Wednes-
day of September, 1792 (Concord: G. Hough, 1792), 67.
22. Supreme Court of Delaware, Definition of Indictable Crimes, 2 Del.
Cas. 235 (Del. Supr. 1797).
23. Compare with State v. Pritchard, 107 N.C. 921 (1890) and Leeman v.
State, 35 Ark. 438 (1880). See Respublica v. Hannum, 1 Yeates 71, 4 (Pa. 1791),
requiring intent, held: “There appear no criminal intentions, passionate ex-
pressions, threats, or partiality. It is proved that the prosecutor, believing the
bill to be reasonable, actually paid it willingly. We are therefore unanimously
330 notes to pages 112– 117
of 1870 to that of 1896 Inclusive, and All Other Acts of a General Nature for the
Same Period, comp. and ann. Solomon Wolff (New Orleans: F. F. Hansel,
1897), Act 4, 218.
44. State v. Ellis, 33 N.J.L. 102 (N.J. 1868).
45. Walsh v. People, 65 Ill. 58 (Ill. 1872). (“At common law, bribery is a
grave and serious offense against public justice; and the attempt or offer to
bribe is likewise criminal.”) See also Commonwealth v. Brown, 23 Pa. Super.
470 (1903); State v. Farris, 229 S.W. 1100 (Mo. Ct. App. 1921); State v. Collins,
210 P. 569, 571 (N.M. 1922).
46. See, e.g., State v. Ragsdale, 59 Mo. App. 590 (Mo. App., 1894).
47. Joel Prentiss Bishop, Commentaries on the Criminal Law (Boston:
Little, Brown, 1882), sections 396–397, 225.
48. Francis Wharton, A Treatise on the Criminal Law of the United States,
5th ed., vol. 1 (Philadelphia: Kay and Brother, 1861), 411.
49. Randall v. Evening News Association, 97 Mich. 136, 143 (Mich. 1893).
50. Republic of Hawaii v. Young Hee, 10 Haw. 114 (Haw. 1895).
51. Reed v. State, 43 Tex. 319 (Tex. 1875).
52. Of course there were exceptions, as in In re Wellcome, 23 Mont. 450
(Mont. 1899).
53. People v. Tweed, 13 Abb. Pr. n.s. 25 (1872).
54. There was a small growth in reported criminal bribery and corruption
cases, but even with this growth, the number of extortion and bribery cases
was in the hundreds, not thousands. Though presumably this represents just a
fraction of the total cases at trial, and differently worded statutes may help ac-
count for the low number of cases I identified, the evidence nonetheless signals
a paucity of criminal corruption cases. Of those reported cases, a tiny fraction
involved legislators at the state or federal levels—a majority of the legislative
corruption cases involved school boards or other local officials, typically bribed
to vote for a particular candidate for a municipal office. The majority of bribery
cases involved a juror, a judge, or a libel charge; the majority of extortion cases
involved a sheriff or other local official charging too much in a fee.
55. Even in 1880 there were 20,000 people in American prisons, and fed-
eral prisons held just over 1,000 inmates in 1885. Kristofer Allerfeldt, Crime
and the Rise of Modern America: A History from 1865–1941 (London: Rout-
ledge, 2011), 75.
332 notes to pages 122–131
6. Railroad Ties
1. Gilbert Geis, White-Collar and Corporate Crime: A Documentary and
Reference (Santa Barbara, CA: Greenwood, 2011), 113.
2. For a full history of this story, see John T. Noonan, Bribes: The Intel-
lectual History of a Moral Idea (Collingdale, PA: Diane Publishing Com-
pany, 1984), 460–501.
3. “Report of the Select Committee to Investigate the Alleged Credit
Mobilier,” in The Congressional Globe, Debates and Proceedings of the 3rd Ses-
sion of Forty-Second Congress (Washington, DC: Office of the Congressio-
nal Globe, 1873), 1466.
4. Robert Ewing Corlew, Stanley John Folmsbee, and Enoch L. Mitch-
ell, Tennessee: A Short History (Knoxville: University of Tennessee Press,
1981), 359.
5. “Tennessee’s Credit Redeemed,” New York Times, April 6, 1881.
6. “Continuance of Testimony before the Bribery Committee,” Louisville
Courier-Journal, December 25, 1881, 1.
7. Lynn v. Polk, 76 Tenn. 121, 203 (1881).
8. “Continuance of Testimony,” 6.
9. “The Bribery Investigating Committee Meets,” Louisville Courier-
Journal, December 13, 1881, 1.
10. “A State Senator Shot,” New York Times, December 9, 1881, 1; Wilm-
ington Morning Star, December 11, 1881.
11. Ibid.
12. “Bribery Investigating Committee Meets,” 1.
13. Sam D. Elliott, “The 200-Page Decision,” Tennessee Bar Journal 9
(2010): 3.
14. Adam Liptak, “Justices Are Long on Words but Short on Guidance,”
New York Times, November 17, 2010. This article inspired the idea of com-
paring the length of corruption opinions to great novels.
notes to pages 136–142 333
15. The judge wrote: “For this court to exercise the jurisdiction invoked,
would be to assume that the co-ordinate departments of the government
are liable to corruption but we are not. If we were to take jurisdiction, and
determine that this act was passed by bribery and corruption, the Legisla-
ture would have the same right to enquire whether or not our judgment was
procured by the same means.”
16. This comes from Clifford J. Downey, Chicago and the Illinois Central
Railroad (Charleston, SC: Arcadia, 2007), a history of the relationship be-
tween the railroad and the city.
17. For this, and all the other colorful and useful details behind the his-
tory of Illinois Central, see Joseph D. Kearney and Thomas W. Merrill,
“The Origins of the American Public Trust Doctrine: What Really Hap-
pened in Illinois Central,” University of Chicago Law Review 71 (2004): 859.
18. Ibid., 868.
19. Ibid., 888. Kearney and Merrill also uncovered indirect but damning
evidence of bribery in some Illinois Central correspondence—but that cor-
respondence was not available at the time to the public.
20. There were two efforts within the backlash to the bill: an effort to
investigate corruption in the initial passage of the bill and an effort to repeal
the bill. The railroads, according to Merrill and Kearney, put more of their
efforts into defeating the investigation than defeating the repeal, although
they put substantial resources into each. The bill to have an investigation
led to a tie vote. Ibid.
21. Illinois Central R.R. Co. v. Illinois, 146 U.S. 387 (1892).
22. Wallace Mendelsohn, “New Light on Fletcher vs. Peck and Gibbon vs.
Ogden,” Yale Law Journal 58 (1949): 573, fn. 24.
23. Joseph L. Sax, “The Public Trust Doctrine in Natural Resources Law:
Effective. Judicial Intervention,” 68 Michigan Law Review 68 (1970): 471.
24. For a further discussion of this development, see Richard Epstein’s
argument that the best way to understand Illinois Central is as something
like a corruption protection: it restrains the legislature from giving away
public property for private ends. Richard A. Epstein, “The Public Trust Doc-
trine,” Cato Journal 7, no. 2 (Fall 1987): 411–430. He writes, “Well-organized
political groups may well be able to obtain net transfers from legislation.”
Elsewhere, Carol Rose writes, “From quite different directions, Louise
334 notes to pages 144–145
46. Powers, 280–281, citing Clippinger v. Hepbaugh, 5 Watts & Serg. 315
(Pa. 1843).
47. Powers, 281.
48. Ibid.
49. Clippinger, 321.
50. Marshall, 336; Clippinger, 315; Wood v. McCann, 36 Ky. 366 (1838); Foltz
v. Cogswell, 25 P. 60 (Cal. 1890); Rose; Frost v. Belmont, 88 Mass. 152 (1863).
51. Barber Asphalt Paving Co. v. Botsford, 44 P. 3, 5 (Kan. 1896).
52. An example is in McBratney v. Chandler, 22 Kan. 692 (Kan. 1879).
53. See, for instance, McDonald v. Buckstaff, 76 N.W. 476, 481 (1898).
54. Richard Briffault, “Anxiety of Influence,” Election Law Journal 13,
no. 1 (March 2014): 160–193, writes: “Today, however, we would certainly
view the efforts of a hired agent to draft a bill, explain it to legislators, and
seek the bill’s introduction as lobbying.”
55. Steele v. Drummond, 275 U.S. 199 (1927).
56. Textile Mills Sec. Corp. v. C.I.R., 314 U.S. 326, 337–338 (1941).
57. 345 U.S. 41 (1953).
58. 347 U.S. 612 (1954)
59. Cammarano v. U.S., 358 U.S. 498 (1959).
60. E. R.R. Presidents Conference v. Noerr Motor Freight, Inc., 365 U.S.
127, 135 (1961).
appealed to the public through rhetoric and action, not direct ties to the
past. William Nester, The Age of Jackson and the Art of American Power
1815–1848 (Herndon, VA: Potomac Books, 2013); Sean P. Adams, ed., A
Companion to the Era of Andrew Jackson (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell,
2013), 260. Jackson won a plurality of votes—over 40 percent—followed by
John Quincy Adams with 30 percent of the vote. Because no candidate re-
ceived the majority of the electoral votes, the House of Representatives,
led by Speaker Henry Clay, had the power to appoint the president. They
chose Adams. When Adams then appointed Clay to be his secretary of
state, Jackson’s supporters denounced the decision as a “corrupt bargain”
(Adams, Companion, p. 280). For the next four years, Jackson’s supporters
used the corruption theme to bring momentum to his rematch with Adams
in 1828. The argument of this second—and successful—campaign was that
the country was in a struggle between democracy and corruption, and Jack-
son represented the former, whereas incumbents and insiders represented
the latter. Jackson won in a landslide. The anticorruption rhetoric of the
time led to changes in corporate law. In the prior practice of special incor-
poration, government officials had more discretion to grant or deny, leading
to personal relationships being necessary to gain corporate charters.
Business entities with directors close to politically powerful legislators
sought, and received, the grants of corporate charters from state govern-
ments. Jacksonians supported general incorporation—essentially the right
to automatically get a corporate charter if one met certain objective criteria.
See John Wallis, “Constitutions, Corporations, and Corruption: American
States and Constitutional Change, 1842 to 1852,” Journal of Economic His-
tory 65, no. 1 (2005): 211–256; Morton J. Horwitz, “Santa Clara Revisited:
The Development of Corporate Theory,” West Virginia Law Review 88
(1985): 181; Morton Horwitz, The Transformation of American Law, 1870–
1960: The Crisis of Legal Orthodoxy (Oxford: Oxford Paperbacks 1992), 204.
Jackson vetoed the renewed corporate charter of the Second Bank of the
United States because of fears of corruption. During the 1832 presidential
campaign—one that was almost exclusively about Jackson’s bank veto—the
theme continued. A leading newspaper patron described Jackson’s fight as
“the cause of democracy and the people, against a corrupt and abandoned
aristocracy,” and South Carolina senator Robert Jay Hayne called his vic-
notes to pages 176–182 339
tory “the triumph of the people over corruption.” Harry L. Watson, Liberty
and Power: The Politics of Jacksonian America (New York: Hill and Wang,
2006), 168. Unlike some of the founders before him, Jackson rejected the
association of virtue with elitism. But like the founders before him, he por-
trayed corruption as anathema to liberty. His farewell address in 1837
sounded like Franklin fifty years later. If we allowed ourselves to become a
corrupt public, he warned, we would become “easier victims to tyranny.”
His language was that of Madison: “It is from within, among yourselves,
from cupidity, from corruption, from disappointed ambition, and inordi-
nate thirst for power, that factions will be formed and liberty endangered.”
(Presidential Documents: The Speeches, Proclamations, and Politics That Have
Shaped the Nation from Washington to Clinton, ed. Fred L. Israel and
Thomas J. McInerney [New York: Routledge, 2013], 71.)
2. Justus D. Doenecke, The Presidencies of James A. Garfield and Chester
A. Arthur (Lawrence: Regents Press of Kansas, 1981), 46.
3. Eldon Cobb Evans, A History of the Australian Ballot System in the
United States (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1917), 10.
4. Ibid., 7.
5. Ibid., 8.
6. John Henry Wigmore, The Australian Ballot System as Embodied in
the Legislation of Various Countries, 2nd ed. (Boston: Charles C. Soule,
1889), 31.
7. Ibid., 32.
8. Mark Twain and Charles Dudley Warner, The Gilded Age (New York:
Modern Library, 2006), 253.
9. “Funds for the Campaign,” New York Times, September 27, 1900.
10. “Trusts and Monopolies,” in 1896: The Presidential Campaign: Car-
toons and Commentary, a Vassar College website, http://projects.vassar.edu
/1896/trusts.html.
11. Speech by Teddy Roosevelt at the Centennial Exercises in the New
York Avenue Presbyterian Church, Washington, D.C., November 16, 1903,
http://www.theodore-roosevelt .com/images/research/txtspeeches/92.txt;
“Put Down Corruption, Says the President,” New York Times, November
16, 1903, http://query.nytimes.com/mem/archive-free/pdf?res=F50E1FF73
F5D11738DDDAE0994D9415B838CF1D3.
340 notes to pages 185–199
12. State v. Lopez, 522 So. 2d 997, 1000 (Fla. App. 3d Dist. 1988).
13. State v. Ross, 214 Ariz. 280, 284 (Ariz. App. Div. 1 2007).
14. Ohio Ethics Advisory Opinion No. 2001-04 (Ohio Eth. Com. 2001) at 3.
15. Barnette v. State, 855 So. 2d 1129, 1132 (Ala. Crim. App. 2003).
16. People v. Coutu, 235 Mich. App. 695, 706–707, 599 N.W.2d 556, 562
(Mich. App. 1999).
17. Wurster v. State, 708 N.E.2d 587, 594 (Ind. App. 1999), aff ’d. 715
N.E.2d 341 (Ind. 1999); Winn v. State, 722 N.E.2d 345, 347 (Ind. App. 1999);
Isassi v. State, 330 S.W.3d 633 (Tex. Crim. App. 2010); Scaccia v. State Ethics
Commission, 727 N.E.2d 824, 828–829 (Mass. 2000).
18. United States v. Abbey, 560 F.3d 513 (6th Cir. 2009). In Abbey the court
said that quid pro quo did not require “a particular, identifiable act when
the illegal gift is given to the official. Instead, it is sufficient if the public of-
ficial understood that he or she was expected to exercise some influence on
the payor’s behalf as opportunities arose.”
19. United States v. Rosen, 716 F.3d 691 (2013).
20. See Richard A. Primus, “Canon, Anti-Canon and Judicial Dissent,”
Duke Law Journal 48 (1998): 250.
21. See Stewart Jay, “The First Amendment: The Creation of the First
Amendment Right to Free Expression from the Eighteenth Century to the
Mid-Twentieth Century,” William Mitchell Law Review 34 (2008): 773–782.
22. Bridges v. California, 314 U.S. 252, 281 (1941).
23. J. M. Balkin, “Some Realism about Pluralism: Legal Realist Ap-
proaches to the First Amendment,” Duke Law Journal 39, no. 3 (1990): 393.
See also Brandenberg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969).
24. Ibid., 392.
25. Owen M. Fiss, “State Activism and State Censorship,” Yale Law
Journal 100 (1991): 287.
26. Palko v. Connecticut, 302 U.S. 319, 327 (1937).
27. William Chillingworth, The Religion of Protestants (Oxford: Leonard
Lichfield, 1638).
28. Francis Warton, The Revolutionary Diplomatic Correspondence of the
US, vol. 6 (Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1889), 10.
29. Notes of Yates, June 23, 1787, in The Records of the Federal Convention
of 1787, vol. 1, ed. Max Farrand (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press,
1911), quoting Mason.
notes to pages 246– 256 345
violate their fiduciary obligations only inasmuch as they fail to keep public
interests first in the use of public rights; and uninvolved citizens rarely have
fiduciary obligations.
5. Laura Underkuffler, Captured by Evil: The Idea of Corruption in Law
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2013).
6. Lawrence Lessig, Republic, Lost: How Money Corrupts Congress and
a Plan to Stop It (New York: Hachette Publishing, 2011).
7. Samuel Issacharoff, “On Political Corruption,” Harvard Law Review
124 (2010): 118.
8. Deborah Hellman, “Defining Corruption and Constitutionalizing
Democracy,” Michigan Law Review 111 (2013): 1385.
9. Jong-Sung You, “Corruption as Injustice,” paper presented at the an-
nual meeting of the American Political Science Association, 2007, http://
irps.ucsd.edu/assets/001/503060.pdf.
10. For an exception, see Ronald Dworkin, Law’s Empire (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1986), 174.
11. See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 1971), 235.
12. Lessig, Republic, Lost.
13. For a discussion of the fiduciary strain in political thought, see Ethan
Leib, David Ponet, and Michael Serota, “A Fiduciary Theory of Judging,”
California Law Review 101 (2013): 699; and D. Theodore Rave, “Politicians as
Fiduciaries,” Harvard Law Review 126 (2013): 671.
14. Bruce Cain, “Moralism and Realism in Campaign Finance Reform,”
University of Chicago Legal Forum 1995 (1996): 112.
15. David A. Strauss, “Corruption, Equality, and Campaign Finance Re-
form,” Columbia Law Review 94 (1994): 1369, 1370, 1382.
16. Kathleen M. Sullivan, “Political Money and Freedom of Speech,”
University of California at Davis Law Review 30 (1997): 679.
17. Richard L. Hasen, The Supreme Court and Election Law: Judging Equal-
ity from Baker v. Carr to Bush v. Gore (New York: New York University
Press, 2003).
18. Richard Hasen, “Is ‘Dependence Corruption’ Distinct from a Politi-
cal Equality Argument for Campaign Finance Reform? A Reply to Profes-
sor Lessig,” Election Law Journal 11 (2013).
notes to pages 283– 291 349
19. Baron de Montesquieu, The Spirit of Laws [1748], trans. Melvin Rich-
ter (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991).
20. Edward van Roy, “On the Theory of Corruption,” Economic Develop-
ment and Cultural Change (October 1970): 86.
21. Stephen Sachs, “Corruption, Clients and Political Machines: A
Response to Professor Issacharoff,” Harvard Law Review Forum 124
(2010): 62.
22. See Underkuffler, Captured by Evil, 112.
23. Hellman, “Defining Corruption and Constitutionalizing Democ-
racy,” 1385.
24. Hannah Arendt, The Promise of Politics (New York: Random House,
2005), 20–21. Another way to express the same idea is that people have dif-
ferent identifications of their personal interest that they might maximize. I
might identify as self first and foremost, and spend my energies and atten-
tions on my own private enrichment. Or I might identify as a member of my
family first and foremost, and spend my energies to maximize the good of
my family. I might identify as a lawyer, or a Vermonter (where I grew up), or
a Congregationalist, or a New Yorker (where I live now), or an American.
All of these are “groups” with which I can plausibly, psychologically identify
and whose interests I can plausibly put before my own. The psychological
experience of putting a group interest first is fundamentally different from
attempting to maximize one’s own interests. Because people are capable of
loving different groups (self, family, nation), it is coherent to say that “Peter
Thiel put private interests ahead of group interests.”
Conclusion
1. Franklin’s will, in The Works of Benjamin Franklin: Containing Several
Political and Historical Tracts Not Included in Any Former Edition, and Many
Letters, Official and Private, Not Hitherto Published (Chicago: Townsend
MacCoun, 1982), 601.
2. Friedrich Nietzsche, “The Case of Wagner,” in Basic Writings of
Nietzsche (New York: Random House, 2009), 626. I am grateful to Roger
Berkowitz for leading me to this passage. See Roger Berkowitz, “The Irony
of the Elite,” Weekly Read, Hannah Arendt Center, February 21, 2014,
http://www.hannaharendtcenter.org/?p=12585.
350 notes to pages 292–296
3. Tim Mak, “Corruption Is Number 2 Issue for 2103,” Politico, July 30,
2013, http://www.politico.com/.
4. Kristofer Allerfelt, Crime and Rise of Modern America 1865–1941
(London: Routledge, 2011), 169.
5. Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law, rev. ed. (New Haven, CT: Yale Uni-
versity Press, 1969), 33–42.
Cases Cited
Kaiser, Robert. So Damn Much Money: The Triumph of Lobbying and the
Corrosion of American Government. New York: Vintage, 2009.
Lessig, Lawrence. Republic, Lost: How Money Corrupts Congress and a Plan
to Stop It. New York: Hachette Publishing, 2011.
Locke, John. The Second Treatise of Government and A Letter Concerning
Toleration. Mineola, NY: Dover, 2002.
Machiavelli, Niccòlo. Discourses of Livy. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1997.
McDonald, Forrest. Novus Ordo Seclorum: The Intellectual Origins of the
Constitution. Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 1985.
McGrath, Peter C. Yazoo: Law and Politics in the New Republic, the Case of
Fletcher v. Peck. Providence: Brown University Press, 1966.
Montesquieu, Baron de. The Spirit of Laws [1748]. Translated by Melvin
Richter. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991.
Noonan, John T. Bribes: The Intellectual History of a Moral Idea. Colling-
dale, PA: Diane Publishing, 1984.
Pocock, J. G. A. The Machiavellian Moment: Florentine Political Thought
and the Atlantic Republican Tradition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press, 1975.
Rose-Ackerman, Susan. Corruption and Government: Causes, Conse-
quences, and Reform. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Schiff, Stacy. A Great Improvisation: Franklin, France, and the Birth of
America. New York: Henry Holt, 2006.
Shain, Barry Alan. The Myth of American Individualism. Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 1994.
Underkuffler, Laura. Captured by Evil: The Idea of Corruption in Law. New
Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2013.
Wood, Gordon S. The Americanization of Benjamin Franklin. New York:
Penguin, 2005.
———. The Creation of the American Republic, 1776–1787. New York:
W. W. Norton, 1969.
———. Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York: Knopf, 1992.
Acknowledgments
Gratitude may be dangerous in the wrong situation, but in the right situa-
tion it is among the most glorious of emotions.
There are many friends without whose help I could not have finished
this book. Scott Faber, my writing partner, was like a weightlifter’s spotter,
encouraging me to write while he wrote at the same time on video chat, one
brutal Hower of Power at a time over five years. Kelly Jean Kelly, who com-
bines generosity with logic in all of her suggestions, edited early drafts and
provided extraordinary advice on connecting, storytelling, and persever-
ence. Larry Lessig encouraged me from the first e-mail to the last period.
His belief in me was such a source of strength. I was blessed to work with
two crack research assistants: Margaret Monaghan, who helped me de-
velop, think through, and research early ideas; and Megan Banfield, a wise,
careful, and critical-minded research assistant who cheerfully and carefully
read every idea, checked my cites (and corrected many of them), and uncov-
ered the early lobbying cases and many old bribery statutes. Thanks to
Larry Abraham and Jacob Seward for stellar research; to John Kulka, my
wise, kind, and unbelievably patient editor; to Amanda Michel for Russian
baths; to Bill Blachly and Ann O’Brien, each for a wonderful place to work
in the summer; to Lynn Marie Ruse for dancing; to Alissa Quart for find-
ing magic in the dullest chapters and giving them sparkle; and to Jennifer
Dworkin for making me laugh about philosophy, and myself, and protecting
me from category mistakes. I had many helpful comments on different ideas,
and I thank everyone who contributed. These wonderful people stand out
360 ac know ledg ments
for their thoughtful and deep engagement: Jamie Boyle, Richard Briffault,
Nestor Davidson, Jacob Eisler, James Gardner, Paul Haagen, Robert Kaczo-
rowski, Jonathan Mattingly, Robert Post, Jedediah Purdy, Seth Barrett Til-
man, and Alex Zakaras. To my parents, Mary and Peter Teachout, thank you
for encouraging me to turn toward complications, instead of away from them,
and for expecting the most difficult thing: that I say what I mean. Special
thanks to Duke Law School and the New America Foundation for their sup-
port at the beginning and end of the project, respectively. And great gratitude
to the faculty of Fordham Law School. You took a chance on me, and gave
me time, freedom, and support.
Finally, to Benjamin Franklin, for giving me hope.
Index
importance of, 11, 31; political corrup- Railroad-related cases: Illinois Central
tion laws as, 183–184; and revival of RR, 140–143; Lynn, 131–137; overview,
anticorruption principle, 284–287; 125–127; in Tennessee, 127–137
Supreme Court’s actions on, 10 Randall, James A., 119–120
Prosecutorial post-Watergate culture, Randall, Robert, 107
rise of, 5 Randolph, Edmund, 27–28, 59, 60,
Protected speech, political spending as, 62, 68
231. See also First Amendment Randolph, John, 80, 87, 88
Pro-Yazooists, 88, 93 Rawls, John, 278
Psychological dependence, 54 Reconstruction era, 125–126
The public (common people), 95, Reed, Stanley Forman, 192
292–293. See also Citizens Representative bodies, Gibbon on, 33
“Public Choice v. Democracy” (Hardin), Representative democracy, lobbying and,
266 145–146
Public good (public interest), 9, 52, 289, Representatives, age and citizenship
303. See also Private interests requirements for, 75–76
Publicly funded elections, 299–300 Republic, Lost (Lessig), 278
Public morality, lobbying and, 157–158 Republicanism, influence on early
Public-oriented government, private Americans, 35
behavior and, 15 Republican Party (Tennessee), 127
Public prosecutors, actions by, against Residency requirements, 4–5, 75, 184, 254
elected officials, 195 Revolving door, 246–247, 298
Public sphere, traditional view of, 9 Rights, personal, 160–161, 162
Public trust doctrine, 6, 140–141, The Rights of Man (Paine), 73
142–143 Roberts, John: on campaign contribu-
“The Public Trust Doctrine in Natural tions, 17–18; during Citizens United oral
Resources Law” (Sax), 142 arguments, 231; corruption nihilism of,
Public use, 267–268 101; in McCutcheon, 7, 302–303, 304; on
Public waters. See Illinois Central RR v. quid pro quo, 238
Illinois Robinson-Patman Act (1936), 301
Pufendorf, Samuel, 45 Rojas, Martha, 29
Roman republic, 32–35
Questions of fact, and campaign Roosevelt, Franklin Delano, 189
donations, as bribes, 215–218 Roosevelt, Theodore (“Teddy”), 182, 183,
Questions of law, Scalia on, 258 185–189, 302
Quid pro quo: disputed meaning of, Rose v. Traux (1855), 153–154
8; early American references to, 50; Rose-Ackerman, Susan, 261–263
in extortion, 201; for Hobbs Act Rot, corruption as, 39
violations, 224; Kennedy on, 7; Rotation in office, 175–176
mistake of, in Citizens United, 238–241; Rotten boroughs, 72–74, 253–255
multiple meanings of, 240–241; Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 278–279
Roberts on, 7. See also Bribes and Rule of law, Fuller on, 296–297
bribery; Corruption Rumely, United States v. (1953), 171–172
Quids Party, 88 Russell, John, 102
374 index