This document discusses why individuals demand insurance and how risk aversion drives this demand. It models individuals' utility from income and shows that utility increases with income but at a decreasing rate, meaning individuals exhibit risk aversion. The document introduces the concepts of expected value and expected utility to model individuals facing uncertain health outcomes and income. It describes how insurance can eliminate this uncertainty for risk-averse individuals by providing an actuarially fair, full insurance contract that equalizes income in both healthy and sick states.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
58 views
Chapter 7
This document discusses why individuals demand insurance and how risk aversion drives this demand. It models individuals' utility from income and shows that utility increases with income but at a decreasing rate, meaning individuals exhibit risk aversion. The document introduces the concepts of expected value and expected utility to model individuals facing uncertain health outcomes and income. It describes how insurance can eliminate this uncertainty for risk-averse individuals by providing an actuarially fair, full insurance contract that equalizes income in both healthy and sick states.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 35
CHAPTER 7
DEMAND FOR INSURANCE
Why buy insurance? Demand for insurance driven by the fear of the unknown Hedge against risk -- the possibility of bad outcomes
Purchasing insurance means forfeiting income in
good times to get money in bad times If bad times avoided, then money lost Ex: The individual who buys health insurance but never visits the hospital might have been better off spending that income elsewhere.
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Risk aversion Hence, risk aversion drives demand for insurance
We can model risk aversion through utility from
income U(I) Utility increases with income: U(I) > 0 Marginal utility for income is declining: U(I) < 0
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Income and utility Graphically, Utility increasing with income U’(I) > 0 Marginal utility of income decreasing U’’(I) < 0
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Adding uncertainty to the model An individual does not know whether she will become sick, but she knows the probability of sickness is p between 0 and 1 Probability of sickness is p Probability of staying healthy is 1 - p
If she gets sick, medical bills and missed work will
reduce her income IS = income if she does get sick IH > IS = income if she remains healthy
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Expected value The expected value (mean) of a random variable X, E[X], is the sum of all the possible outcomes of X weighted by each outcome’s probability If the outcomes are X=x1, x2, . . . , xn, and the probabilities for each outcome are p1, p2, . . . , pn respectively, then: E[X] = p1 x1 + p2 x2 + · · · + pn xn
In our individual’s case, the formula for expected
value of income E[I]: E[I]p = p IS + (1- p) IH
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Example: expected value Suppose we offer a starving graduate student a choice between two possible options, a lottery and a certain payout: A: a lottery that awards $500 with probability 0.5 and $0 with probability 0.5. B: a check for $250 with probability 1.
The expected value of both the lottery and the
certain payout is $250: E[I]p = p IS + (1- p) IH E[I A] = .5(500) + .5(0) = $250 E[I B] = 1(250) = $250
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
People prefer certain outcomes Studies find that most people prefer certain payouts (like B) over uncertain scenarios (like A)
If a student says he prefers uncertain option,
what does that imply about his utility function?
To answer this question, we need to define
expected utility for a lottery or uncertain outcome.
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Expected Utility The expected utility from a random payout X E[U(X)] is the sum of the utility from each of the possible outcomes, weighted by each outcome’s probability.
If the outcomes are X=x1, x2, . . . , xn, and the
probabilities for each outcome are p1, p2, . . . , pn respectively, then: E[U(X)] = p1 U(x1) + p2 U(x2) + · · · + pn U(xn)
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Example The student’s preference for option B over option A implies that his expected utility from B, is greater than his expected utility from A: E[U(B)] ≥ E[U(A)] U($250) ≥ 0.5 U($500) + 0.5 U($0)
In this case, even though the expected values of
both options are equal, the student prefers the certain payout over the less certain one. This student is acting in a risk-averse manner over the choices available.
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Expected utility without insurance Lottery scenario similar to case of insurance customer She gains a high income IH if healthy, and low income IS if sick where her income I is a random variable Uncertainty about which outcome will happen, though she knows the probability of becoming sick is p Expected utility E[U(I)]p is: E[U(I)]p = p U(IS) + (1- p) U(IH)
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
E[U(I)] and probability of sickness Figure shows how expected utility changes as the probability of sickness changes. Consider a case where the person is sick with certainty (p = 1): E[U(I)] = U(IS) equals the utility from certain income I S (Point S) Consider case where person has no chance of becoming sick (p = 0): E[U(I)] = U(IH) equals utility from certain income I H (Point H)
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
What if p lies between 0 and 1? For p between 0 and 1, expected utility falls on a line segment between S and H
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Ex: p = 0.25
For p = 0.25, person’s expected income is:
E[I] = 0.25·IS + (1 - .25)·IH Utility at that expected income is E[U(I)]0.25 (Point A)
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Expected utility and expected income
Crucial distinction between
Expected utility E[U(I)]
Utility from expected income U(E[I])
This distinction in the case when p=0.5:
The individual's expected income from the sickness
lottery: E[I]0.5 = 0.5·IS + (1 - 0.5)·IH And expected utility from the sickness lottery: E[U(I)]0.5= 0.5·U(IS) + (1 - 0.5)·U(IH)
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
For risk-averse people, U(E[I]) > E[U(I)]
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Risk-averse individuals in the utility- income model Synonymous definitions of risk-aversion: Prefer certain outcomes to uncertain ones with the same expected income. Prefers the utility from expected income to the expected utility from uncertain income U(E[I]) > E[U(I)]
Concave utility function
U’(I) > 0 U’’(I) < 0
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
A basic health insurance contract The individual approaches a health insurance company that offers a policy with the following features: The individual pays an upfront fee r regardless of whether she stays healthy or becomes ill. Payment r is known as the insurance premium If ill, customer receives q -- the insurance payout If healthy, customer receives nothing from the insurance company Either way, customer loses the upfront fee r Customer’s final income is: Sick: IS + q – r Healthy: IH + 0 – r
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Income with insurance Let IH’ and IS’ be income in the healthy and sick states with the insurance contract. Sick: I S’ = I S + q – r Healthy: IH’ = IH + 0 – r
Remember that risk-averse consumers want to
avoid uncertainty in buying insurance For them, optimally E[I]p = IH’ = IS’ An insurance contract that fulfills this equation is said to be actuarially fair, full insurance. Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics Full insurance Full insurance means no income uncertainty IS’ = IH’
Final income is state-independent
Regardless of healthy or sick, final income is the same
Risk-averse individuals prefer full insurance
to partial insurance (given the same price) Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics Full insurance payout State independence implies IH’ = IS’ So IH + 0 – r = IS + q – r IH = IS + q q = IH – IS
The payout from a full insurance contract is
difference between incomes without insurance
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Actuarially fair insurance Actuarially fair means that insurance is a fair bet i.e. the premium equals the expected payout r=pq
Insurer makes zero profit/loss from actuarially
fair insurance in expectation
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Actuarially fair, full insurance
The above algebra shows that with contract, the individual’s
income is E[I]p regardless of whether she turns out to be sick or healthy. Notice that consumers with actuarially fair, full insurance achieve their expected income with certainty!
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics Insurance and risk aversion As we have seen, simply by reducing uncertainty, insurance can make this risk-averse individual better off. The nature of the insurance contract is that the individual loses income in the healthy state (IH > IH) and gains income in the sick state (IS < IS) relative to the state of no insurance In other words, the risk-averse individual willingly sacrifices some good times in the healthy state to ease the bad times in the sick state.
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Insurer profits Now consider the same insurance contract from the point of view of the insurer Premium r
Payout q
Probability of sickness p
E[] = Expected profits that the insurer makes
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Fair and unfair insurance In a perfectly competitive insurance market, profits will equal zero
Same definition as actuarially fair!
An insurance contract which yields positive profits is called actuarially unfair insurance:
An insurer would never offer a contract with
negative profits Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics When insurance is fair, in a sense, it is also free. The customer’s expected income does not change from buying the contract, so she effectively pays nothing for it. Despite the fact that the Premium r is positive in an actuarially fair contract, the price is actually zero. Thus, the Premium associated with an insurance contract is not its price.
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Full vs. partial insurance Partial insurance does not achieve state- independence
Size of the payout q determines the fullness of the
contract Closer q is to IH – IS , the fuller the contract
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Comparing insurance contracts AF -- Actuarially fair & full AP -- Actuarially fair & partial A – Uninsurance
U(AF) > U(AP) > U(A)
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
The income uncertainty the individual faces is largest in the case of no insurance: She receives either IH or IS, which may be significantly different. Partial insurance lowers her uncertainty but does not eliminate it altogether since ISP is still less that IHP. Only with the highest quantity of insurance – full insurance – does the individual reach state independence and fully eliminate income uncertainty. Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics The ideal insurance contract For anyone risk-averse, actuarially fair & full insurance contract offers the most utility Hence, it is called the ideal insurance contract
Ideal and non-ideal insurance contracts:
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Comparing non-ideal contracts AF – Full but actuarially unfair contract AP – Partial but actuarially fair contract
Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics
Comparing non-ideal contracts In this case, U(AF) > U(AP) Even though AF is actuarially unfair, its relative fullness (i.e. higher payout) makes it more desirable But notice if contract AF became more unfair, then expected income E[I] falls If too unfair, AF may generate less utility than A P
Similarly, AP may become more full by increasing its
payout Uncertainty falls, so point AP moves At some point, this consumer will be indifferent between the two contracts Bhattacharya, Hyde and Tu – Health Economics Conclusion Demand for insurance driven by risk aversion Desire to reduce uncertainty Diminishing marginal utility from income U(I) is concave, so U’’(I) < 0 U(E[I]) > E[U(I)]
Risk aversion can explain not only demand for
insurance but can also help explain Large family sizes Portfolio diversification Farmers scattering their crops and land holdings