The Student Guide To Freire's Pedagogy of The Oppressed-Bloomsbury Academic (2018)
The Student Guide To Freire's Pedagogy of The Oppressed-Bloomsbury Academic (2018)
Antonia Darder has asserted her right under the Copyright, Designs
and Patents Act, 1988, to be identified as Author of this work.
Bloomsbury Publishing Plc does not have any control over, or responsibility for, any
third-party websites referred to or in this book. All internet addresses given in
this book were correct at the time of going to press. The author and publisher
regret any inconvenience caused if addresses have changed or sites have
ceased to exist, but can accept no responsibility for any such changes.
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
A catalog record for this book is available from the Library of Congress.
To find out more about our authors and books visit www.bloomsbury.com
and sign up for our newsletters.
This book is dedicated to the memory of Paulo Freire,
whose work continues to inspire new generations of revolutionaries
committed to a more just and loving world.
Contents
Figures viii
Preface ix
Foreword, Donaldo Macedo xv
About This Book xxi
1 Lived History 1
2 Intellectual History 23
3 In Dialogue with the Text: Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 93
4 Impact, Influences, and Legacy: An Interview with Ana Maria
Araújo Freire 151
Bibliography 172
Index 185
Figures
1
In Art of Loving, Fromm (1956) takes up this question of paradoxical thinking. “Aristotle explains
his position very clearly in the following sentence: ‘It is impossible for the same thing at the same
time to belong and not to belong to the same thing and in the same respect; and whatever other
distinctions we might add to meet dialectical objections, let them be added. This, then, is the most
certain of all principles … ’ This axiom of Aristotelian logic has so deeply imbued our habits of
thought that it is felt to be ‘natural’ and self-evident, while on the other hand the statement that X is
A and not A seems to be nonsensical” (73).
2
About intercultural translation, Santos (2014) writes, “Because it is a work of mediation and
negotiation, the world of translation requires that the participants in the translation process
defamiliarize themselves to a certain extent vis-à-vis their respective cultural backgrounds. In the
case of North/South translations, which tend to be also Western/non-Western translation, the task
of defamiliarization is particularly difficult because the imperial North has no memory of itself as
other than imperial and, therefore, as unique and a universal” (223).
Preface xi
4
Speciesism refers to a human-centric belief system, which views other living species on the planet
as intrinsically inferior to human life. See: Critical Pedagogy, Ecoliteracy, and Planetary Crisis by
R. Kahn (2010) for an better understanding of this critique and some ways he proposes to extend
Freire’s work toward addressing the question of speciesism in our perspectives of education and its
relationship to the well-being of all living beings.
Preface xiii
Antonia Darder
Los Angeles, California
5
Post-disciplinary here draws on the writing of such scholars as Andrew Sayer (1999) and Bob
Jessop and Ngai-Ling Sum (2001), who refer to an approach to teaching and research that extends
knowledge construction beyond disciplinary boundaries, by following a coherent group of “ideas
and connections wherever they lead instead of following them only as far as the border of [the]
discipline” (Sayer 1999: 5). Traditionally, the process of knowledge construction has been held
hostage by the arbitrary boundaries of disciplines (i.e., philosophy, history, political economy,
anthropology, sociology, psychology), which result in the unfortunate compartmentalization and
fracturing of knowledge, which often, wittingly or unwittingly, conceals the extent of power and
control held by the dominant class and culture. As such, we can think of decolonizing epistemologies
as a systematic foray outside the abyssal divide (Santos 2007) of disciplinary approaches within the
Western inspired university tradition.
Foreword
Donaldo Macedo
University of Massachusetts, Boston
False love, false humility, and feeble faith in others cannot create trust… to
say one thing and do another—to take one’s words lightly—cannot inspire
trust. To glorify democracy and to silence the people is a farce; to discourse
on humanism and to negate people is a lie.
—Paulo Freire
Pedagogy of the Oppressed
I could not think of a more suited scholar than Antonia Darder to write The
Student Guide to Paulo Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed. Darder truly embodies
the meaning of solidarity and the value of gratitude for mutual support in the
collective cocreation of a political project that dares to imagine a world where
people are less narcissistic, more just, less dehumanizing and more humane. She
is well aware of the lies that undergird meritocracy as she is painfully cognizant
that, while many educators critique neoliberalism’s heightened individualism
and its theology of the market, their actions, nevertheless, always take a detour
through cost analysis measures which often sabotage the collective political
project of becoming more fully human. That is, “the pursuit of full humanity,
however, cannot be carried out in isolation or [individualistically], but only
in the fellowship and solidarity,”1—a solidarity that should always be shaped
and guided by generosity of the heart, collective responsibility, and gratitude—
values that are almost always trumped by the current crass careerism predicated
in having more instead of being more human.2
Hence, Darder along with Henry Giroux, bell hooks, Linda Brodkey, Stanley
Aronowitz, Lilia Bartolomé, and Peter McLaren are but a handful of activist-
intellectuals who truly understand the “daunting task” of living the Pedagogy of
1
Paulo Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed (London: Bloomsbury, 2012), 85.
2
Ibid., 85–86.
xvi Foreword
the Oppressed to the extent that “[it] requires one to step into a vulnerable
place and embrace a politically and culturally charged sensibility that can
move beyond traditional conceptualizations of scholarship. This [humbling
coherence which is predicated on an unyielding integrity] also demands that
one dares to embody the spirit, passion, and commitment of Paulo Freire
to make a world where it is possible to be more human, a world where it is
possible to love,”3 which is a sine qua non for the existence of dialogue that,
in turn, requires “a profound love for the world and for people.”4 Thus, a
pseudo-Freirean who remains shackled to a blind zeal for power and uses an
anti-establishment critical discourse to disguise his or her need to dominate,
“reveals the pathology of love: sadism in the dominator and masochism in the
dominated.”5
The challenge for the intellectual-activist is to have the courage to refuse
“to dichotomize cognition from the emotion”6—a task that requires courage,
coherence, and integrity—values that are evermore in short supply in a world
where, according to President Trump, what matters is “to make a deal,”
irrespective of the human costs and the probable violation of ethics. Hence,
many educators, including those who claim to be Freirean, sacrifice their
integrity and coherence as they are spellbound by the careerist zeal of another
promotion to a position of power even if it means emptying out the “authentic
word … [which] … is deprived of its dimension of action, [and in which]
reflection automatically suffers … and the word is changed into idle chatter,
into verbalism, into an alienated and alienating ‘blah.’”7
The fossilization of action by many pseudo-critical educators is usually
contextually situated in textual critiques when the self-proclaimed Freireans
hollow out their critical anti-establishment discourse by paralyzing action
so as to maintain their colonizing desires of reaping privileges from the very
establishment that they denounce. Consequently, they reject any dialogue
that includes theory, reducing their denouncement of the establishment to a
fossilized dialogical method while chest-pounding to be a “man [or women]
3
Ibid., 89.
4
Ibid.
5
Ibid.
6
Freire (1998), xviii.
7
Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 87.
Foreword xvii
of action, one who draws his [her] lessons from experience.”8 This false
dichotomy between theory and action not only reveals the distortion of the
wanna-be-Freireans but, it simultaneously points to their failure to understand
that all actions are informed by theory and authentic activists must know how
to theorize their action. To do otherwise is to fall prey to an elitist academicism
where theory and a discourse of critique are often disarticulated from action,
rendering the denouncement of the unjust world to pure academic blah, blah,
blah, “for denunciation is impossible without a commitment to transform,
and there is no transformation without action.”9 In many respects, the pseudo-
critical educator who rejects theory, acts like the “colonist [who] likes neither
theory nor theorists. He who knows that he is in a bad ideological position
boasts of being a man of action, one who draws his lessons from experience,”10
one whose energy is razor focused on the community disarticulated from the
very ideological and cultural factors that gave rise to the human misery that
festers in that community in the first place and where subjugated people are
relegated to sub-humanity.
As a profoundly organic intellectual, Antonia Darder keenly understands
that “the act of love is a commitment to the [oppressed’s] cause—the cause of
liberation. And this commitment, because it is loving, is dialogical.”11 To the
extent that it is dialogical, Darder’s illuminating insights on Freire’s ideals and
philosophy of life make clear the unviability of a critical discourse that only
denounces the social injustices at the level of text without a communion with
the people who need to struggle and announce their freedom. Necessarily, an
act of freedom invariably requires dialogue with the people on whose behalf
the critical educator proclaims to fight as an anti-establishment expert against
the oppressive establishment. To do otherwise is to use a language of critique
that denounces oppression at the level of text “as a pretext for manipulation.”12
That is, educators whose political project is always sacrificed at the altar of
crass careerism and who speak for the people but are not with the people, are
educators who fear the people and who visit the community as anthropological
8
Albert Memmi, The Colonizer and the Colonized (Boston: Beacon Press, 1991), 26.
9
Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 87.
10
Memmi, The Colonizer and the Colonized, 26.
11
Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 91.
12
Ibid., 90.
xviii Foreword
rooted in men’s [and women’s] incompletion, from which they move out in
constant search—a search which can be carried out only in communion with
others. Hopelessness is a form of silence, of denying the world and fleeing
from it. The dehumanization resulting from an unjust order is not a cause
for despair but for hope, leading to the incessant pursuit of the humanity
denied by injustice … As long as I fight, I am moved by hope; and if I fight
with hope, then I can wait.17
14
Anzaldúa (1989).
15
Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 91.
16
Lilia I. Bartolomé, “Beyond the Methods Fetish: Toward a Humanizing Pedagogy.” Harvard
Educational Review 64(2), Summer, 1994, 173–194.
17
Freire, Pedagogy of the Oppressed, 91–92.
About This Book
To write a student guide for a book like Pedagogy of the Oppressed by the late
world-renowned Brazilian philosopher Paulo Freire is, indeed, a daunting
task. It requires one to step into a vulnerable place and to embrace a politically
and culturally charged sensibility, which can move one beyond traditional
philosophical conceptualizations. This also demands that one dare to embody
the spirit, passion, and commitment of this educational philosopher, whose
thought came to represent “the response of a creative mind and sensitive
conscience to the extraordinary misery and suffering of the oppressed around
him” (Shaull 1970: 10).
Pedagogy of the Oppressed, first published in Spanish in 1968 and then in
English1 in 1970, has transformed and deepened social justice educational
discourses worldwide, by highlighting the significant role of education in the
formation of citizens and the perpetuation of oppressive conditions within
schools and societies. Over the past five decades, the powerful message of
Pedagogy of the Oppressed has been embraced by progressive educators and
activists everywhere, while simultaneously shunned, maligned, and banned
by those whose perspectives support the hegemonic order of their times.
Nevertheless, Freire’s imaginative capacity to capture and articulate what
might be understood as the universalism of oppression, particularly as enacted
within the context of educational practice, spoke directly to the hearts and
minds of oppressed people and their allies everywhere, whether they labored
as teachers or social workers or nurses or ministers or community activists.
Hence, this effort to create a student guide for the novice reader of Pedagogy
of the Oppressed has caused me to loose sleep and to rub my hands raw, seeking
to find the way to speak to the complexities of Freire’s political project, in
language that is accessible and meaningful to students who now and in the
coming decades will be assigned the book or simply pick it up serendipitously.
1
The book was translated into English by Myra Ramos.
xxii About This Book
No matter how one comes to Pedagogy of the Oppressed, from its inception,
this book is meant for those who sincerely seek a better world. Never could
Paulo Freire have imagined that his powerful insights into educational and
societal oppression would so deeply resonate with the struggles of so many,
over the past five decades. How can one do justice to such an incredible feat?
How can one tell simply the story of a book that was to become one of the most
internationally read texts in education, making Freire one of the greatest and
most cited educational philosophers of the twentieth century.
That said, it is important that seasoned readers of Pedagogy of the Oppressed
also understand the purpose of this volume. It is to illuminate, as much as
possible, the central thesis and critical concepts that Freire introduced in his
memorable volume. In order to be true to this purpose, the focus of this book
is only on Pedagogy of the Oppressed. Freire, however, went on to write many
more books; and many Freirean scholars have labored persistently over the
past forty years to elucidate and reveal further the strength and influence of
Paulo’s ideas and pedagogical insights.
Hence, for those new to Pedagogy of the Oppressed, I hope this book
will provide emerging readers with ample philosophical support and
encouragement to not only navigate more effectively the underlying intent and
major themes, but also engage more substantively the wisdom and challenge
of this classical educational treatise. For educators who are using Pedagogy of
the Oppressed as a text in their classrooms, this volume is meant to potentiate
and enhance philosophical and pedagogical engagement with the themes, as
well as to more effectively navigate the critical dialogues the book is sure to
generate in classrooms and communities where questions of oppression are
central to teaching and learning.
However, it is important to note that The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy
of the Oppressed is not meant to substitute or supplant the reading of Pedagogy
of the Oppressed as primary text, but rather to serve as a faithful and loyal
companion to readers who strive to overcome the many injustices that persist
in education and society today. Underlying this volume is a radical hope
that its use will sustain the intellectual and political formation of students,
enhancing their sensibility to the political and pedagogical possibilities for
About This Book xxiii
building democratic voice, participation, and solidarity in the struggle for our
humanity.
More importantly, my approach to writing this book constitutes, as
theologian Richard Shaull (1970) suggests, a form of personal witness to the
power of Freire’s praxis, as much as an exciting adventure into critical dialogue
with and across Paulo’s ideas—a process that has persisted, since I first read
Pedagogy of the Oppressed in 1978. Since my first reading, I have engaged the
book as a colonized subject of the United States, a working-class Puerto Rican
women who grew up in dire poverty. As such, my relationship with these ideas
is intimate and embodied. The reader will note that at times my language
in Chapter 3 reflects this inclusivity and identification with the oppressed.
Hence, through both a critical and intimate dialogue with the richness,
depth, and complexity of Paulo’s thought, I hope this book will further your
commitment to the humanizing historical task that awaits us today, igniting
deeper recognition of our significance as historical subjects, empowered
political beings, and cultural citizens—particularly as we labor individually
and collectively to end human suffering wherever encountered. In this way,
we together can ensure that Paulo Freire’s (1970) great hope will endure: “the
creation of a world in which it will be easier to love” (24) and where a new sense
of dignity and self-determination can fuel our revolutionary dreams.
1
Lived History
1
The term “popular culture” is a translation of educação popular. Both Portuguese and English
versions are similar because of their Latin root. However, the meaning of popular is very different
in Latin America. In this context, popular means something that is for and from the poor and
dispossessed. In the Brazilian context, the popular educator is one who teaches the poor, especially
those who are illiterate and unschooled. In addition, popular education, as conceived by Freire and
others of his time, provides a pedagogical approach in which people not only become literate but
also develop critical consciousness about their world and their particular place in that world. Hence,
popular education is understood as community education that seeks the empowerment and well-
being of the oppressed.
2 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
a hint into the significance of context to Freire’s philosophy and the political
sensibility that informs the book.
In the larger historical context, Freire’s life must be understood within
the sorted history of a massive country that occupies over half of the South
American continent. From the inception of European colonization, the
majority of Brazilians—indigenous people and Africans brought by force to
work the lands—were violently subjected to the ravages of colonial subjugation
and slavery. It is therefore impossible to fully comprehend Freire’s Pedagogy of
the Oppressed outside “the backdrop of the Brazilian history of exploitation
and extermination, hunger and malnutrition” Bhattacharya (2011:173). These
were obstinate conditions of oppression that persisted from the 1500s into the
twentieth century. Freire experienced such conditions in his own life and would
constantly reencounter them, through his literacy work in the northeastern
region of Brazil—one of the poorest regions of the nation, where the violence
of racism and poverty fully comingle.
The issue of context, moreover, is also understood here through a Freirean
lens, which recognizes that it is impossible to understand human beings,
including their philosophy and praxis, outside of the concrete historical,
economic, and cultural conditions that shape their intellectual, emotional,
physical, and spiritual sensibilities and, thus, their ongoing evolution as cultural
citizen of the world. Hence, to more precisely grasp the fundamental ideas of
Pedagogy of the Oppressed requires an understanding of the lived history from
whence Freire’s pedagogy emerged. This is also significant to understanding the
man from Recife, himself, whose philosophical and political labor generated
ideas intimately anchored to his everyday praxis in the rural countryside of his
native Brazil, as well as his numerous international experiences. So, it is by way
of understanding Paulo’s lived history that we can achieve a clearer perception
of the whole.
In keeping with this spirit, this chapter examines the manner in which
Freire’s lived history, first and foremost, informed his intellectual sensibilities
and his political commitment to the emancipation of oppressed peasants in
Brazil—a liberatory vision that extended beyond his native country. Paulo,
indeed, encompassed a sincere and genuine concern for the suffering and
oppression of subaltern populations worldwide. His persistent indignation for
Lived History 3
the unmerciful manner in which governments and the wealthy elite thwart
the dignity of human beings is distinguishably palpable in Pedagogy of the
Oppressed and the writings that would follow this groundbreaking testament
to the oppressor’s manufactured suffering of the poor.
An important dimension of Paulo Freire’s pedagogy is found precisely in
his recognition of how the power of lived histories in each individual impacts
our reading of the world and influences the construction of knowledge, within
and beyond the classroom (Darder 2015). Moreover, returning to one’s lived
history is also a vital means by which to continuing learning about one’s place
in the world. In Letters to Cristina, Freire (1996) notes:
Given the key role lived history plays in Freire’s writing of Pedagogy of the
Oppressed, beginning this book with a succinct examination of Paulo’s life
seems a useful place for students to commence their engagement of the book.
By so doing, readers may gain insight into the evolution of Freire’s philosophical
sensibilities, his pedagogical practice, and the expression of his political voice,
which for the last five decades has been a clarion call for liberation.
Early years
Paulo Relus Neves Freire, the youngest of four children, was born on September
19, 1921, to an economically comfortable working-class Catholic family in the
port city of Recife, the capital of the state of Pernambuco. This northeastern
region of Brazil was and continues to be one of the most impoverished in the
country. When Paulo was only three years old, his father, an officer of the
Pernambuco military police, was forced to retire prematurely due to a serious
heart condition. This destabilized the family’s economic condition, forcing
them to move to Jaboatão dos Guararapes, a modest town outside of Recife.
4 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Figure 1.1 Paulo at the age of one year and three years with his three siblings; Freire’s
siblings were Temístocles, Stela, and Armando.
Lived History 5
opinions. From them … I learned early on the value of dialogue” (25), which
would become the cornerstone of his pedagogical approach.
In the years that followed his father’s death, Freire, who was considered
a mediocre student, struggled with school, preferring to spend most of his
time playing with childhood friends from his neighborhood in Jaboatão dos
Guararapes. With his mother left to fend for the family alone, Paulo’s life was
marked by poverty and hunger—conditions he firmly believed diminish a
student’s ability to learn. Drawing inspiration from the anticolonial theorist
Frantz Fanon, Freire often referred to his childhood as one of “sharing the plight
of the ‘wretched of the earth’ ” (30). Undoubtedly, Freire’s lived experience as
a boy deeply influenced his life’s work. About this time in his life, he wrote,
“I didn’t understand anything because of my hunger. I wasn’t dumb. It wasn’t
lack of interest. My social condition didn’t allow me to have an education.
Experience showed me once again the relationship between social class and
knowledge” (Gadotti 1994: 5). His early experiences of poverty, moreover, led
him to discover the “culture of silence” of the oppressed—whose responses
Figure 1.2 Paulo’s mother, Edeltrudis Veves Freire, and father, Joaquin Temístocles
Freire.
Lived History 7
At the age of twenty, Freire enrolled in law school at the University of Recife.
However, the path was not easy and, on several occasions, his studies were
interrupted, having to earn a living and contribute to the family’s finances.
While at the University of Recife, he majored in philosophy, focusing his
8 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
2
Cultural circles refer to a pedagogical process that provides the conditions for learners within
classroom or communities to participate freely in naming their world and developing their voices,
within a meaningful context of cultural respect and affirmation for their lived histories and everyday
experiences. Freire would further develop the concept amid his work in Chile. More discussion will
follow in Chapter 3.
3
Christian Base communities are autonomous religious groups often associated with liberation
theology. The meeting of Latin American Council of Bishops in 1968 in Medellin, Colombia, played
a major role in popularizing them.
Lived History 9
Upon graduation from law school in 1947, Freire completed all requirements
and was admitted to the bar but decided against pursuing law after an epiphany
he experienced with his first client. The young dentist had defaulted on a loan
he had taken to purchase equipment and materials necessary to open his
practice. Stirred by the irony and poignancy of the young dentist’s situation—a
poor man who not only did not have the resources to pay off the loan but was
ready to lose everything in order to meet the debt—Freire decided to return to
the Colégio Oswaldo Cruz, where he had completed his secondary degree three
years earlier, to teach Portuguese. Simultaneously, however, Freire employed his
legal skills as a trade union lawyer, assisting members to navigate legal matters.
Later in 1947, Freire was promoted as Director of the Division of Public
Relations, Education, and Culture of the SESI. Working among illiterate
impoverished communities, Freire embraced the radical Catholic ideas and
values of a burgeoning social movement in the church that was spreading
across Latin America. As point of reference, this was a time in Brazil when only
those who were officially deemed literate could vote in presidential elections, a
policy that raised grave concerns for Freire and others in the nation working to
advance democratic life. Hence, it is not surprising that the historical necessity
of the political moment would catapult Freire’s focus toward the development
of a revolutionary pedagogical approach, which simultaneously focused
on ameliorating illiteracy, while also supporting workers from oppressed
communities to enter collectively into the struggle for humanizing education
and establishing a more just society.
Freire continued his work with SESI and served from 1954 to 1956 as
superintendent of the organization. During these years, Freire’s approach to
literacy gradually drew the attention of the national office. During an effort
in 1957 to appoint Freire as national director of the Division of Research
and Planning, an interdepartmental letter praised Freire’s “experience
and knowledge,” asserting that he would be invaluable to the division by
“encouraging studies and the recruitment of individuals able to provide
us with the effective means to formulate viable solutions pertaining to the
pressing social issues in the current state of the nation” (Freire and Macedo
1998: 16).
10 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
4
A mocambo refers to a village community of runaway slaves in colonial Brazil (Clare 2006).
12 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
The Brazilian present has been enveloped by these colonial legacies: silence
and the resistance to it—the search for a voice—and the rebelliousness that
must become more critically revolutionary. This was the central theme of
my academic thesis, “Education and Present-Day Brazil,” which I defended
in 1959 at the University of Recife … I incorporated parts of this thesis in
my first book, Education as the Practice of Freedom. My thesis reflected my
experiences in SESI, which had significantly affected me. I combined my
experiences at SESI with the critical reflection and extensive reading from a
foundational bibliography. (87)
a larger application of his literacy approach, launching the “Bare feet can
also learn to read” campaign in the state of Rio Grande de Notre, where 300
sugarcane workers in the interior village of Angicos were taught to read and
write in 45 days. In response to the success of Freire’s literacy efforts, President
João Belchior Goulart and Minister of Education Paul de Tarso Santos invited
Freire to rethink adult literacy programs on a national scale in an effort to
forge a national literacy program. It is estimated that under Freire’s direction,
“20,000 cultural circles were programmed to be set up for 2,000,000 illiterate
people” (Gadotti 1994: 15). However, despite this extraordinary opportunity
to expand the reach of Freire’s literacy work, Brazil was again embroiled in
a turbulent moment in its history, where much uncertainty loomed over the
political direction of the nation.
Within three months of its official initiation in January 21, 1964, the new
military government shut down the National Literacy Program, in accordance
with the coup d’état of March 31, 1964—an action supported and partly
financed by the United States to protect its interest in Latin America (Lernoux
1980; William 2015). The Goulart government—whose reforms to socialize
the profits of large corporations and landowners and to improve the well-being
of all Brazilians, were deemed “a communist threat”—was overthrown and a
military dictatorship was to rule the country for more than twenty years. At
the time of the Golpe de 64, Freire had been working with the national program
in Brasilia. Considered “an international subversive, a traitor to Christ and the
Brazilian people” (Gadotti 1994: 34), Freire was accused of alleged “subversive
activities,” arrested twice, and imprisoned in Olinda and Recife for a total of
seventy days. In one instance during his interrogation, Freire was asked, “Do
you deny your method is similar to that of Stalin, Hitler, Peron, and Mussolini”
(Cited in Schugurensky 2014: 23)?
Although Freire was not physically tortured during his incarceration, his
imprisonment and subsequent exile had an enduring impact on his view of
life and his philosophy, intensifying his heartfelt dedication to the struggle for
liberation among the oppressed. About his response to the coup d’état and its
impact on his political understanding of education, Freire (cited in Shor and
Freire 1987) would later say:
14 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Years in exile
Forced into exile in 1964, Freire spent a short time in Bolivia, before arriving
in Chile only days following the inauguration of President Eduardo Frei
Montalvo. This was considered an enthusiastic and progressive moment
in the country’s history, where programs for the poor, including literacy
efforts were supported. A new department was created that focused on
adult education, independent from the Chilean Ministry of Education.
Freire served as a UNESCO consultant for almost five years, working for
the Christian Democratic Agrarian Reform Movement and the Food and
Agriculture Organization of the United Nations. “Freire was able to extend his
collaboration to the Ministry of Education and the people working in adult
literacy, as to organize agrarian reform” (Grollios 2015). Freire’s relationships
and experiences with both liberation theologists and Marxists in Chile were
to leave an indelible mark on his intellectual, pedagogical, and ideological
formation (Holst 2006). Of this Freire wrote:
The Chilean masses know very well that the fundamental contradiction
human beings face is not between them and nature but that it takes place in
the economic, political, and social spheres. Those are the things, I confess,
that I learned in Chile. It is not that Chile made me a completely different
man from the person I was before, but what it did exactly was to deepen in
me a radicalization that was already in process. (Freire and Guimarães 1987:
127 trans. by Holst 2006)
Lived History 15
Figure 1.5 Paulo Freire (left), with also exiled former mayor of Brasilia and minister
of culture under João Belchior Goulart, Paulo de Tarso Santos, who was the first
Brazilian to be granted asylum by the Chilean government.
Writing about Freire’s time in Chile, James Holst (2006)6 noted the often-
ignored relationship between Freire’s extensive hands-on literacy experiences and
profound learning process in Chile and his articulation of what would become
seminal ideas of his pedagogical project (i.e., banking education, problem-
posing education, generative themes, culture of silence, conscientização, cultural
action). Moreover, Freire often affirmed that it was in Chile where he “learned
to learn.” Key associations of that time included Marcela Gajardo, as well as
Raul Veloso, whose theory of intentionality of consciousness became significant
to Freire’s own thinking (Austin 2003: 66). The changes Freire underwent were
reflected in his writing. For example, in his first book, Education as the Practice of
Freedom, which focused on his earlier efforts in Brazil, the text reflected a liberal
democratic style and an emerging Brazilian national consciousness consistent
with Freire’s early views in Brazil (Mackie 1981). The tenor of his discourse,
6
For an excellent discussion of Freire’s years in Chile, see James Holst’s (2006) incisive essay, “Paulo
Freire in Chile, 1964–1969: Pedagogy of the Oppressed in Its Sociopolitical Economic Context”
published in Harvard Educational Review. Also see Robert Austin’s (2003) The State, Literacy, and
Popular Education in Chile.
16 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
however, made a dramatic turn by the following year, when Pedagogy of the
Oppressed was first published.7, 8, 9 Hence, it is safe to say that Chile profoundly
nurtured his “politic shift to the Left,” which unmistakably characterized the
tenor of the book (Roberts 2000: 24).
Freire and his family remained in Chile until April 1969, when he was
offered and accepted a temporary visiting post at Harvard University. The offer
came at an opportune time, as there were suspicions that rising conservative
politics had led to termination of his employment (Grollios 2015). In that
same year, Freire assisted the governments of Peru and Nicaragua with
literacy campaigns. In 1970, English and Spanish translations of Pedagogy of
the Oppressed were released in a world that was still grasping for responses to
the many issues and concerns raised by the social movements of the 1960s.
Shortly after, the family moved to Geneva, Switzerland, where Freire was
given a post with the World Council of Churches and established the Institute
of Cultural Action. During this decade, Freire did literacy work in other parts
of Latin America but also began work in Africa. First with the government of
Julius Nyerere in Tanzania, then with revolutionary organizations in former
Portuguese colonies of Angola (Movimento Popular Libertação de Angola) and
Mozambique (Frente de Libertação de Moçambique), and more substantively
in Guinea-Bissau, Cape Verde (Partido Africans para Independência da
Guinea-Bissau e Cabo Verde), and Sao Tome and Principe, where literacy
campaigns were strongly focused on the process of re-Africanization and
nation building.
Paulo’s efforts in Africa, however, were beleaguered by a variety of
challenging conditions. The Apartheid government of South Africa banned
Pedagogy of the Oppressed, while perpetrating every form of colonial
abuse imaginable upon Black South Africans. Moreover, problems with
7
Myra Bergman Ramos provided the English translation of Pedagogy of the Oppressed.
8
Consistent with the repression of Freire’s ideas in Brazil and the circumstances of his live, Pedagogy
of the Oppressed, written during his time in Chile, was first published in Spanish. The book was not
to be published and circulated in Brazil until 1975, seven years after its first publication (Kirylo
2011).
9
Morrow and Torres (2002) write, “Ironically, due to censorship in Brazil, his most important book—
Pedagogy of the Oppressed—first appeared in Spanish and English in 1970 and did not appear in a
Brazilian Portuguese edition until 1975. . . But by the early 1990s it had sold over half a million copies
worldwide” (7).
Lived History 17
Post-exile years
Freire’s exile was lifted in 1979 and he returned to Brazil in1980, where he
accepted posts to teach at the Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo
and the Universidade de Campinas. Upon his return to Brazil, Freire joined the
Partido dosTrabalhadores (Workers’ Party) in Sao Paulo and headed up its adult
literacy project for nearly six years. In 1988, when the party took control of São
Paulo’s municipality—the third largest city in the world—Freire was appointed
Municipal Secretary of Education. While in office, Freire faced several political
18 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Figure 1.7 Paulo with his second wife, Ana Maria Araújo Freire.
20 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Figure 1.8 Freire continued his work in Brazil and around the world.
10
In 1979, Freire was awarded an honorary doctorate from Claremont Graduate University.
Coincidentally, it was at this ceremony that I received my doctoral degree in Philosophy of
Education. I had the honor of being hooded by Paulo, my political inspiration and most notable
intellectual mentor.
Lived History 21
By way of this brief account of Paulo’s lived history, we learn much about
the powerful ways in which his experiences both shaped his intellectual and
political growth and steadily deepened the development of his liberatory
praxis. We can also gather from this recounting of Paulo’s story the reasons
why he was so adamant about honoring the importance of lived histories as
meaningful aspects of our learning and as powerful forces in shaping our
lives. However, attention to only the context of lived experience is insufficient.
Instead, as exemplified by Freire’s own life, major philosophical influences
from both relationships with people and texts constitute significant contextual
material to motivate our actions, nourish our consciousness, and ultimately
guide our evolution as loving and knowing political subjects, capable of
ameliorating human suffering.
Intellectual History
Early Influences
1
The process of determining who would be discussed in this chapter was made primarily on the
basis of those authors cited by Freire in Pedagogy of the Oppressed, as well as major thinkers of the
traditions mentioned by Freire or about Freire in a variety of autobiographical and biographical
writings about his intellectual influences. However, I acknowledge that in the absence of being able
to directly corroborate with Paulo on this matter, there is the need to acknowledge a subjective
aspect to this approach, which cannot be avoided and for which I take responsibility. Nevertheless,
an effort has been made to rely on Freire’s accounts and those who knew him closely. That said, there
might be omissions, which I regret.
2
Each of the traditions, philosophers, and writings presented in this section must be understood
as hugely complex and deserving of far greater discussion. However, limitations in the scope of
the book and its size prevent more in-depth discussion. It is, therefore, important that the new
readers of Pedagogy of the Oppressed recognize that Freire’s ideas are not one-dimensional and that
they are informed by a wide variety of complex, often philosophically dense, and even seemingly
contradictory traditions and values. If particular ideas here should peak greater interest, the reader
should explore the rich literature that exists in each of the different intellectual influences discussed,
as well as a variety of books and articles that engage specific aspects of each of the traditions and
each thinker identified. Such a project will only serve to widen one’s respect for the intellectual
creativity and unwavering motivation of Freire’s ideas to address both substantively and expansively
questions of human oppression, along with the potential of education to serve as either a means for
oppression or liberation.
Intellectual History 25
3
Cited in Wellington (2011).
26 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
social and political concerns raised by these philosophers were also aroused
by the failure of the Brazilian government to establish an ethical and morally
just social, political, and economic structure; the revolutionary events
transpiring around the world in the 1960s; and, most important, a passionate
belief among Catholic radicals in the collective possibility of overcoming the
oppressive conditions people were facing in the country. In fact, “nowhere had
change gone further in the Roman Catholic Church than in Brazil. Brazil has
the most progressive Catholic episcopate in the Roman Church worldwide”
(Mainwaring 1987: 2). Hence, the influence of these radical Catholic thinkers
was at work in Freire’s early philosophical and pedagogical work, although
his articulations remained focused on the practice of literacy instruction with
impoverished communities of the northeastern region of Brazil.
Following his exile and move to Chile, in 1964, Freire became more
strongly influenced by his close association and engagement with the writings
of liberation theologists, such Gustavo Gutiérrez, Leonardo Boff, Frei Betto,
and Dom Hélder Câmara (Jeria 1986). It is useful to note that this is also
the era of Vatican II (1962–1965), initiated by Pope John XIII and moved
forward by Pope Paul VI—a time in which the church instituted significant
changes in an effort to establish a closer ecumenical relationship with the
people. These changes, however, were not readily embraced by all, constituting
many tensions between more radical and conservative sectors of the Catholic
Church, particularly in Latin America.4
Liberation theology
The roots of liberation theology in Latin America, a perspective in which Freire
was not only well versed but also influenced (Kirylo and Boyd 2017; Reynolds
2013), focused on the importance of context, experience, reflection, action,
and evaluative discernment in the interest of humanity and the well-being
of the entire community (Harnett SJ 2009; International Commission on the
4
The exclusion of women from the priesthood and thus, the leadership of the church also remained
(and remains) a contentious question. In response, fifteen women were appointed as auditors in
September 1964. Eventually twenty-three women were auditors at the Second Vatican Council,
including ten women religious. The auditors had no official role in the deliberations, although they
attended the meetings of subcommittees working on council documents, particularly texts that dealt
with the laity (Allen Jr. 2012; Tobin 1986).
Intellectual History 27
5
Chubbuck and Lorentz (2006), explain that since the early 1970s, Jesuit education or Ignatian
pedagogy has embraced a commitment to a “faith that does justice” (International Commission
on the Apostolate of Jesuit Education 1993: 134), a commitment articulated by Fr. Pedro Arrupe
in 1973 as education to prepare “men [and women] for others” who are “completely convinced
that love of God which does not issue in justice for [humanity] is a farce” (Arrupe 1973: 32). To
read more about the relationship of social justice, Ignatian pedagogy, and critical pedagogy, also see
Chubbuck (2007).
6
The issue of what is meant by “human” can surface in classroom discussions. Within the context
of the church often “human” demarcate the distinction between Godlike and humanlike. Within
secularized philosophical traditions, human nature is used to relate to that quality that is distinctly
human (of women and men), a quality that separates the essence of humankind from other animals.
Qualities that we share with animals are generally attributed to aspects of our animal nature.
Critiques about anthropomorphism are linked to discourses that privilege human life over all other
forms of living beings can also surface. Of concern is the manner in which anthropomorphism
results in inappropriate behaviors or attitudes toward animals, such as trying to adopt an animal
that lives undomesticated as a “pet” or misinterpreting the behaviors of these animals, along human
terms.
7
In Cristianos y Marxista despues del Concilio (cited by Freire), André Moine (1965) writes of some
of the tensions, issues, and concerns at work as radical Catholics working in Christian-based
communities found themselves at odds with Pope John’s more conservative views. Often they were
met by unfounded speculations that liberation theology might leave the needs of people unattended,
in favor of misguided Marxist political fervor.
28 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
and is reborn” to the struggle for a just world (Kirylo and Boyd 2017). Central
to the politics of liberation theology was an internal critique of the church as
sanctioning institutional violence (Gutiérrez 1973). Hence, Freire conceived his
faith, as “a presence in history that does not preclude me from making history, but
rather pushes me toward world transformation … the fundamental importance
of my faith [exists] in my struggle for overcoming oppressive reality and for
building a less ugly society, one that is less evil and more humane” (Freire 1997:
103–104). Palpable in his words is the influence of liberation theology to his
articulation of teacher-student qualities often perceived as spiritual in nature.
Brazilian theologian, Leonard Boff (2011) has affirmed Freire’s connection
to liberation theology: “Paulo Freire is considered one of the founders of
liberation theology. He was a Christian that lived his faith in a liberating way …
Paulo placed the poor and oppressed at the center of his method, which is
important in the concept of preferential option for the poor, a trademark of
liberation theology” (241).
The radical Catholic phenomenological influence of Pierre Teilhard de
Chardon (1959) cannot be overlooked. Teilhard’s writings advocated for an
understanding of reality that would reinsert human beings into the existential
struggle for their autonomy and freedom. Found here, is also the idea that the
oppressed internalize the deficit views cast upon them by the oppressor and,
thus, must undergo a struggle to regain their sense of autonomy and humanity.
Teilhard embraced an evolution of humanity that he conceived as a dialectial
union, which could simultaneously differentiate and personalize the subject.
At the center of his revolutionary spirituality is the belief that the Divine and
the world are not antagonists but rather exist in communion. Hence, human
beings have a duty to challenge social inequalities in community and transform
them in the interest of our evolution.
So, although Freire never formally linked his pedagogy to liberation theology
or spiritual matters, the influence of his Latin American Catholic upbringing,
his labor within a variety of radical Christian contexts, and his strong affiliation
and affinity with revolutionary theologians, nevertheless, influenced and
reinforced his views. More specifically, these included his perspective of
humanity, transformation, the pedagogical indispensability of love, faith and
hope, our capacity to denounce oppression and announce social justice, and his
Intellectual History 29
utopian belief (Madero SJ 2015) in the need to strive for a world where human
indignities would cease.8
Politics, Niebuhr (1960) challenged the unjust structures of power and the
violence of the powerful elite, who easily condemned “the violence of a strike
by workers and [then] call upon the state in the same breath to use violence in
putting down the strike” (130)—a view that also resonated with Freire.
10
This section draws on two very succinct but insightful articles. First Alexander Stehn’s (2017) in
“Latin American Philosophy,” published in the Internet of Encyclopedia of Philosophy; and Jorge
Garcia and Manuel Vargas’s (2013) article, “Latin American Philosophy,” published in the Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Both sources are well-respected peer-reviewed academic resources.
11
Eurocentrism, according to Shohat and Stam (2014), refers to a mode of thought that engages in
a variety of reinforcing intellectual forms. Briefly, five major aspects of this worldview include:
(1) Europe is seen as the “motor” for progressive historical change; (2) attributes to the West an
inherent progress toward democratic institutions; (3) elides non-European democratic traditions
and obscures manipulation of Western democracy in subverting democracies abroad; (4) minimizes
the West’s oppressive practices; and (5) appropriates cultural and material production of non-
Europeans, while denying both their achievements and their appropriation (see 2–3). Also see, J. M.
Balut’s (1993) the Colonizer’s Model of the World for an incisive discussion of Eurocentrism and its
role in the colonizing worldview of the West.
Intellectual History 31
12
Briefly, six major features of positivism include: (1) the logic of inquiry is universal across all
disciplines; (2) the goal of inquiry is to explain and predict conditions of social phenomenon; (3)
research should be empirically observable, using inductive logic to make claims that can be tested; (4)
inquiry should be neutral, objective, and value-free avoiding any form of personal bias; (5) inquiry
should be detached or decontextualized from cultural or political morals, values, or beliefs; and (6)
phenomenon in the world has an independent existence or “essence” which remains constant and is
observable. Positivism is generally associated with the Enlightenment defined in note 25.
13
Alvaro Vieira Pinto’s writings on consciousness and intentionality are important to Freire’s efforts
to link education with co-intentionality and the development of social consciousness. Moreover,
Pinto’s (1960) expansion on Jasper’s notion of limit situations is key to Freire’s sense of hope; in that,
limit-situations become for Pinto not “the impassable boundaries where possibilities end but the
real boundaries where possibilities begin” (284). Moreover, Pinto posits a living sense of historical
consciousness, where the present always contains the past and the future.
32 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
the contradictions of the past, through becoming conscious of the social and
material conditions that stifled their liberation. Similarly, political scientist,
Francisco Weiffert (1967) engaged key questions of revolutionary politics,
class-consciousness, and the state. As struggles waged in China, Chairman
Mao Tse-Tung’s (1964) Little Red Book would inspire calls to actions; and
the Cuban revolution would similarly serve as an impetus for flourishing
movements for liberation, as the writings of Fidel Castro, Ernesto (Che)
Guevara,14 and other revolutionaries, inspired by the Cuban philosopher and
poet, Jose Martí, reignited revolutionary dreams. So too, Freire’s ideas found
resonance in Martí’s writings (Alvarado 2007).
Jose Martí
Jose Martí was one of the earliest critics of positivism in Latin America (Martí
2009). In contrast to European positivists or materialists, who blamed the
problems of Latin America on the genetic inferiority of the races, Martí looked
historically to the colonizing politics of cultural and economic domination
around the world and its persistent impact on subaltern populations. In
response, Martí, a staunch critic of US imperialism, beckoned Latin American
intellectuals to develop their own ideas, rooted in the actual social, political,
religious, and economic issues facing Latin American populations. Martí
espoused a deeply inclusive Latin American identity, where all had the right
to participate in forging a genuinely liberated Latin America. Although, Martí
died during Cuba’s war to gain independence from Spain, his writing called for
liberating Latin America from the imperialistic impulses of both Europe and
the United States.
14
In Pedagogy of the Oppressed, Freire makes note to Che Guevara’s (1969) memorable words regarding
love and revolution, which echo his own: “Let me say, with the risk of appearing ridiculous, that the
true revolutionary is guided by strong feelings of love. It is impossible to think of an authentic
revolutionary without this quality” (398). Also see, Peter McLaren’s (2000) Che Guevara, Paulo
Freire, and the Pedagogy of Revolution for an interesting and creative comingling of Che Guevara
and Paulo Freire’s ideas as foundation for a revolutionary praxis of education.
Intellectual History 33
his writings offered a vision for Latin America that could transform the
destructive social and economic impact of European conquest. Considered
one of the most important Marxist thinkers in the history of Latin America
thought, Mariátegui called for a socialist solution and asserted the key role of
both aesthetics and spirituality to the communal struggle of the oppressed in
creating a new, more egalitarian society. Works by Mariátegui and others of his
era gave way to a distinctive Latin American school of thought that Francisco
Miró Quesada called the forjadores (constructors), who are credited with
developing a genuinely Latin American philosophy that in the 1940s critically
moved the field toward the establishment of a philosophical perspective
notably considered Latin Americanism. This generation and the next, who
built on the writings of Mariátegui, as well as Jose Vascancellos and Leopoldo
Zea, also read the works of Spanish philosophers such as Miguel de Unamuno
and José Ortega y Gasset.
Spaniard philosophers
The Spanish educator and philosopher, Miguel de Unamuno, is considered an
early existentialist whose work engaged the tensions and contradiction that
exists between intellect and emotion, as well as faith and reason. At the heart
of his ideas, Unamuno grappled with the meaning and limits of consciousness
and ongoing conflicts and contradictions that make up the whole of human
existence. Unamuno’s writings, like Freire, are characterized by a deeply
personal and passionate longing to know, even beyond death. A central theme
in his writings reflects an underlying desire to preserve one’s personal integrity
in the face of social conformity, fanaticism, and hypocrisy. Unamuno’s novels
and plays intensely depict characters agonizing with conflicting human
impulses. Unamuno also wrote a book titled Amor y Pedagogía (Love and
Pedagogy), a concept reflected in Pedagogy of the Oppressed and Freire’s later
works (Darder 2015).
The Spanish philosopher and writer, José Ortega y Gasset’s philosophy of
life reflects aspects of pragmatism and realist phenomenology, which give rise
to an early form of existentialism and dialectical historicism. For Ortega y
Gasset, philosophers have an obligation to unveil beliefs, in order to challenge
false notions and promote new ways of understanding the world. Despite
34 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
15
Jorge Larraín (2000) in Identity and Modernity in Latin America, explains,
For Marx, what was the basis of modernity was the emergence of capitalism and the revolutionary
bourgeoisie, which led to an unprecedented expansion of productive forces and to the creation
of the world market. Durkheim tackled modernity from a different angle by following the ideas
of Saint-Simon about the industrial system. Although the starting point is the same as Marx,
feudal society, Durkheim emphasizes far less the rising of the bourgeoisie as a new revolutionary
class and very seldom refers to capitalism as the new mode of production implemented by
it. The fundamental impulse to modernity is rather industrialism accompanied by the new
scientific forces. In the work of Max Weber modernity is closely associated with the processes of
rationalization and disenchantment of the world. (13)
Intellectual History 35
Existentialism
Søren Kierkegaard
The Danish philosopher Søren Kierkegaard (1949),16 often at odds with the
established institution of the church, believed that individual choice and risk is
a fundamental necessity in deciding life’s ultimate meaning. For Kierkegaard,
subjectivity signified the infinite depth of human beings and, therefore, could
not be seen as the opposite of rational objectivity, but rather as something
beyond. Subjectivity, here, refers not merely to the human feelings or emotions,
but rather the way a person (the subject) relates to things in terms of his or her
16
See: The Essential Kierkegaard (2000) edited by H. V. Hong and E. H. Hong and published by
Princeton University Press.
Intellectual History 37
French Existentialists17
Jean-Paul Sartre (1946), one of the most recognizable French existentialist
philosophers, sought to engage those basic existential experiences that could
reveal our fundamental human condition in relation to others and the world.
Similar to other existentialists, Sartre embraced the notion “existence precedes
essence.” Inherent to this view, all existing things in the material universe only
have meaning through consciousness, in that it is through consciousness that
we create meaning. Therefore, there is no predefined essence to humanity and
so human beings must decide the meaning of existence for themselves. As
this infers, Sartre was concerned, in particular, with questions of freedom and
responsibility. He argued that it is through our willingness to accept responsibility
for our freedom, as well as the suffering that may come with it, that we become
authentic human beings. Hence, it is, indeed, our actions that then make us who
we are and these are determined not by predetermined destiny or the will of a
God but by the choices and actions of human beings in the world.
17
Although Freire does not mention the French philosopher Emmanuel Levinas in Pedagogy of the
Oppressed, it seems likely that he would have read Levinas. In fact, given the logical connection
here, there are scholars who have engaged their works simultaneously (Benade 2015; Gomez 2009;
Joldersma 2001).
Intellectual History 39
18
The Feminist movement is often delineated by three waves of feminism. First wave: 1830s—early
1900s, where women fought for the right to vote, as well as equal contract and property rights.
Second wave: 1960s–1980s, is an important period in which feminist debates were broadened
in order to struggle for gender equity across the society; and Third wave, 1980s to present, often
considered a time of micropolitics in the struggle for gender equity, where feminist perspective
became more particularistic with respect to issues of racism, sexuality, ecofeminism, and so on.
There are some, however, that argue we are actually now in the Fourth wave of feminism; a time in
which feminist are working to contend with and move past what has been seen as the lack of focus
and “divisiveness” of the third wave. Whatever the case, it is important to note that within each
of this waves of feminisms there have been tensions and contradictions often linked to ideologies
and epistemologies that exist somewhere across the spectrum from radical to ultraconservative
debates. For more see: An Introduction to Feminism (Finlayson 2016) and Feminism: A Very Short
Introduction (Walters 2006).
19
Mikel Dufrenne (1953) can also be categorized in the tradition of phenomenology. His best-known
book, Phénoménologie de l’expérience esthétique (The Phenomenology of Aesthetic Experience),
expounds on the inextricable link between the larger dimension of human feeling and aesthetics.
This is a book that Freire is bound to also have read, given his expressed interest in aesthetics with
respect to the question of our humanity.
40 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Phenomenology
expressions, which are reflected in Karl Marx’s analysis of social class and later
in Freire’s exposition of the oppressor/ oppressed contradiction in Pedagogy of
the Oppressed.
Equally important to this discussion is Hegel’s claim that social standards
or laws do not reside in objects or in the mind but in the organized social
whole (541). Within the context of this social dimension, each individual
identity is also part of a collective, where values and moral conventions of
the organized social whole are internalized as emanating from oneself. When
political life fails to be the true expression of common ethical life, forms of
social oppression result that seek to annihilate opposing forces. For Hegel,
the ethical encompasses common or communal values, customs, and codes
of conduct that determine how people act, their beliefs, and how they relate
to the world—all which become deeply embedded in the collective culture.
Nevertheless, Hegel argued that culture is a dynamic force always subject
to change, an idea that is in sync with his view of history as a dynamic and
unfolding collective force.
20
In an essay originally published in 1939 entitled “Une idée fondamentale de la phénoménologie
de Husserl: l’intentionnalité,” Jean-Paul Sartre makes reference to Husserl’s famous phrase “All
consciousness is consciousness of something.” Intentionality: A Fundamental Idea of Husserl’s
Phenomenology first appeared in Situations I (Paris: Gallimard, 1947).
44 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Husserl asserts that the only certainty we have is our own conscious
awareness. Hence, this is the place from whence we must begin to know the
world. However, our awareness and consciousness must always be understood
as an awareness and consciousness of something—where something refers to
any object, real or unreal, physical or psychical, which we reflect on—although
experience, in and of itself does not discern states of consciousness from objects
of consciousness. Thus, we cannot know whether objects of consciousness have
an independent existence separate from us, although they do unquestionably
exist as objects of our consciousness. It is precisely this relationship between
experience, the world, and consciousness then that permits human beings to
explore and understand our existence.
For Husserl (1954), consciousness does not exist outside of the lifeworld
nor does the lifeworld exist separate of consciousness—radically confirming
the dialectical relationship between consciousness and the world. “In whatever
way we may be conscious of the world as universal horizon, as coherent
universe of existing objects, we, each ‘I-the-man [woman]’ and all of us
together, belong to the world as living with one another in the world; and the
world is our world, valid for our consciousness as existing precisely through
this ‘living together’” (108). As such, the lifeworld, as the ground for all shared
experience, is understood as fundamental to ontological (of being or existence)
and epistemological (of the nature of knowledge or meaning) reflections and
interrogations.
21
Originally published in 1927.
Intellectual History 45
linked, since human beings are always looking toward the future.22 Hence, he
reasons that being is really just a process of becoming, rejecting the Aristotelian
claim that human beings possess a fixed essence.
Heidegger (1962) however, makes a distinction between authentic human
beings, who have a distinct grasp of their humanity (i.e., farmers and rural
workers); and inauthentic human beings (i.e., city dwellers) who are out of
touch with their own individuality. In turn, this inauthentic state of being causes
anxiety. This anxiety, according to Heidegger, is the result of subjugation to
arbitrary cultural rules. Moreover, human beings respond in two ways: either
to flee or face up to the anxiety. Heidegger proposes that facing the realities of
our human existence, although limiting, is also liberating.
Although Heidegger initially considered his concepts related to time and
being as universal, he later posits that the actual time or period (or epoch)23
in which we live impacts our way of being, providing the concept of Dasein
historicality (Heidegger 1962: 41). This phenomenon also signals a historical
condition or truth that may remain concealed, until a moment when the limits
of inauthentic existence or a fore-sight (a guiding idea that redefines our sense
22
At this juncture, it is useful to signal anew the Eurocentric philosophical foundations of the majority
of thinkers discussed in this chapter. This is particularly apparent here in Heidegger’s theorizing of
time and being—conceived through a lens that corresponds to Eurocentric system of values.
Eurocentrism, as it prevailed during European Enlightenment, was advocated in England by
John Locke and David Hume, in France by A. R. J. Turgot and Voltaire, and in Germany by
Gotthold Ephraim Lessing and Immanuel Kant, to give some examples. This means that during
this period it was in play all over Europe. For the origin and dissemination of Eurocentrism, the
idea of progress is very important. This idea means that world history as a whole, with all of its
relevant developments, comes to its absolute peak in Europe in the second half of the eighteenth
century. In this way it is possible to frame a concept of history that covers the whole world.
However, this possibility comes at a high price. Although certain periods of history are judged
in a differentiated way … Europe is the standard within which all the different phenomena in
space and time get their place as historic stadia. Europe of this period of time understands itself
as superior with regard to all other times and cultures, and … Europe defines what philosophy or
science is. (Kimmerle 2014: 100)
This also points back to the earlier discussion on Latin American thought, which sought to
challenge, destabilize, and transform the Eurocentric worldview in Latin America, fundamentally
linked to the coloniality of power. Moreover, the racism (and sexism, for that matter) that underpins
the worldview of the 1800s and 1900s when these theorists were writing is both inescapable and
indefensible; yet, as critical education theorists like Phillip Kain (2005) and Peter McLaren argue,
disrupting epistemological possibilities simultaneously exist within theories, particularly with
respect to Hegelian dialectics and historical materialism.
23
Freire makes note of the idea of epoch in Pedagogy of the Oppressed, referring to the critical work of
German Sociologist, Hans Freyer (1958), who posited that history enters critical epochs in which
the objective cultural forms are unable to contain the flux of life. As a consequence of the tension,
the historical moment gives rise to the necessity of transformative change.
46 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Revolutionary Influences
The ideas Freire expresses in Pedagogy of the Oppressed clearly reflect the
dramatic impact of his exile from Brazil, as well as a radical shift in his thinking,
inspired by his relationships and associations with revolutionary intellectuals
in Latin America and around the world. This arbitrary dividing line should
not be taken as a hard demarcation, but rather as simply a logical one, given
the historical conditions and pressing issues of his time. Freire’s intellectual
history resumes in this section, bringing together a discussion of Marxism,
the Frankfurt School, and anticolonial thinkers who influenced his thinking.
Marxism
have been overwhelmingly engaged across all disciplines and social movements
for liberation around the world. Marxist philosophy, as with many of the
philosophies discussed earlier, must be understood against the backdrop of the
Enlightenment,24 which gave rise to the overwhelming belief that phenomena
could be known objectively by way of the observing mind, which become the
medium for liberating the human spirit.25 Marx, as did other philosophers
discussed earlier, challenged positivist claims. For example, although initially
influenced by the phenomenology of Hegel, Marx (1933) came to challenge
what he considered to be the idealist tendencies in Hegelian dialectics.
24
The Enlightenment refers to an intellectual and scientific movement of eighteenth-century Europe
that, in defiance of the autocratic rule of monarchy and the Roman Catholic Church, infused a
rational and scientific approach to religious, social, political, and economic views. The ideas of this
historical period led to the American Revolution and French Revolution and strongly influenced
the Industrial Revolution. Thinkers that loom large in this period are Rene Descartes, John Locke,
David Hume, Adam Smith, Spinoza, and Immanuel Kant.
25
Key ideas of the Enlightenment age include: (1) The Individual is starting point for all knowledge
and action and individual reason cannot be subjected to a higher authority; (2) Rationalism, where
reason and rational thought, independent of experience, is innate within the human mind and the
only basis for organizing knowledge; (3) Empiricism: the only valid way to gain knowledge about
the world is through observation or sensory experience; (4) Scientific method is considered to allow
the observation of facts and the discovery of laws that govern these facts; (5) Progress: knowledge
gained by scientific methods can be used to explain or predict events; and (6) Universalism: scientific
methods for acquiring objective knowledge are universal so they can be applied to all spheres of
endeavor. These ideas are foundational to positivism, which was defined in note 17.
26
First published in 1938.
48 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
27
First published in 1854.
28
Resolution of the London Conference on Working Class Political Action. International Workingmen’s
Association written by Marx in 1871. See: https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1871/09/
politics-resolution.htm.
29
The First Congress of the International in Geneva, 1866, written by Marx. See: https://www.marxists.
org/reference/archive/bakunin/works/1872/karl-marx.htm.
Intellectual History 49
contends that all forms of social thought (i.e., art, philosophy, science) and
institutions (including the family) originate from the political economic
superstructure30 of the state. Hence, everything in life is economically
determined. The flow of money informs our relations with one another, with
nature, and with the world. Marx employs the category of value to signify basic
relations of production in capitalism, where all social and material exchanges
are organized on the basis of value (Postone 1996). The alienating structures
of private property, for example, overwhelmingly shape our thoughts and
aspirations, as capital dictates the boundaries of human activity (Marx 1998).
About this Marx (1844) writes,
30
Marx’s theory divides society in two layers, which he terms the “base” and “superstructure.” The base
refers to the sphere of all the material, tangible aspects of life, along with the economic relations that
capital generates. The superstructure refers to the sphere of political and ideological institutions; the
cultural belief system, and the hopes, dream, and spirit generated by the capital. The superstructure
is understood in terms of three aspects: (1) the legal and political expressions of society linked to
relations of production; (2) the forms of consciousness that express particular class views of the
world; and (3) the processes by which human beings become conscious of a fundamental economic
conflict and wage struggle.
50 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
the prospect of perceiving the present as history. Human beings can know the
world, despite its complexity, because they have made it” (Roberts 2003: 174).
Marx confirms that women and men make history, as much as we are made
by history, although often not within conditions of our own making. Hence,
to understand history, ourselves, and the world requires that knowledge be
constructed within the material conditions of our historical continuity This
challenges abstract, neutral, or prescribed views of history, knowledge, or
consciousness, by reasserting our humanity as full and active participants in
the revolutionary process—a process that must begin concretely where lived
history, consciousness, and material existence intersect. Marx (1998) begins
here in that knowledge, like history, does not exist divorced from our lives,
but rather “the production of ideas, of conceptions, of consciousness is at first
directly interwoven with the material activity and the material intercourse of
men [and women], in the language of real life” (42).
However, Marx also notes that society’s phenomenological sphere (or sphere
of appearance) is often quite different from its essence. Thereby, pointing
the way for the development of a theory of ideology that can engage the
contradiction between the appearance and essence of society—a contradiction
that benefits the ruling class. Ideology, in the Marxist sense, signifies the
production, reproduction, and consumption of ideas and behavior that distort
or illuminate the nature of reality (Giroux 1983), obscuring relations of power,
entrapping our sensibilities, and obscuring existence. Moreover, since ideology
is contradictorily situated and recreated within the sphere of appearance, it
expresses not only social and material formations of domination but also
resistance and affirmation. Marx uses the concept of commodity fetishism31 to
31
In Marxism, the concept of commodity fetishism is used to explain how the social organization of
labor is mediated through market exchange, the buying and the selling of commodities (goods and
services). In Capital, Marx and Engels (1996) explain the concepts underlying commodity fetishism
in the following manner:
As against this, the commodity-form, and the value-relation of the products of labour within
which it appears, have absolutely no connection with the physical nature of the commodity and
the material relations arising out of this. It is nothing but the definite social relation between men
[and women] themselves which assumes here, for them, the fantastic form of a relation between
things. In order, therefore, to find an analogy we must take flight into the misty realm of religion.
There the products of the human brain appear as autonomous figures endowed with a life of their
own, which enter into relations both with each other and with the human race. So it is in the
world of commodities with the products of men’s hands. I call this the fetishism which attaches
itself to the products of labour as soon as they are produced as commodities, and is therefore
inseparable from the production of commodities. (83)
Intellectual History 51
unveil the contradiction within a capitalist society, where the value of workers
is gauged through a system of monetary exchange (accepted by the worker),
while concealing the hidden extract surplus value (profit of the producer) and
the workers’ estrangement or alienation32 from their labor.33 For this reason,
Marxists maintain that seldom is domination absolute within the capitalist
mode of production.34 Rather, given the effectiveness of ideology in obscuring
structures of oppression, the working class often became complicit in their
own dehumanization.
Consistent with the discussion above and worth repeating, Marxism posits
the existence of social classes, whereby human beings are separated into distinct
segments of the population, according to their social and material wealth. The
dynamics of a society can only be understood in terms of a system where
the dominant ideas are formulated by the ruling class to secure control over
the working class. The deep structures of human inequality perpetuate and
32
“Alienation” refers to the process whereby workers are made to feel separate from the products of
their own labor. In capitalism, workers are exploited insofar as they do not work to create a product
that they, themselves, can sell to a real person; instead, workers, in order to live and survive, must
sell their labor to capitalists for a wage (as if their labor were itself a property or thing that can be
bought and sold). Workers are alienated from their product (what they make) precisely because they
do own the product they make, which belongs to the owners who have purchased the labor-power of
workers in exchange for exclusive ownership over the workers’ products and all the profit that comes
by the sale of those products. However, the worker’s production does not have to lead to alienation
and can actually be very satisfying. This happens under conditions where workers can pour their
subjectivity into what they make and even gain enjoyment from the fact that another person gains
enjoyment or satisfaction from what they have made. The idea here is that the further workers are
from the products of our labor, the more that we can become alienated and objectified, distanced
from our creativity and opportunities to transform our world. Such estrangement serves to meet the
objectives of capitalism, at the expense of the humanity of workers.
33
It is in his discussion of estranged labor that Marx (1844) differentiates human beings from animals,
which Freire takes up in Pedagogy of the Oppressed. Of this, Marx contends,
The animal is immediately one with its life activity. It does not distinguish itself from it. It is its
life activity. Man makes his life activity itself the object of his will and of his consciousness. He
has conscious life activity. It is not a determination with which he directly merges. Conscious life
activity distinguishes man immediately from animal life activity. It is just because of this that he
is a species-being. Or it is only because he is a species-being that he is a conscious being, i.e., that
his own life is an object for him. Only because of that is his activity free activity. Estranged labor
reverses the relationship, so that it is just because man is a conscious being that he makes his life
activity, his essential being, a mere means to his existence.
34
“Mode of production” refers to “everything that goes into the production of the necessities of
life, including the ‘productive forces’ (labor, instruments, and raw material) and the ‘relations of
production’ (the social structures that regulate the relationship between humans in the production
of goods)” (Felluga 2015: 180 - 81). According to Marx and Engels, (as stated earlier) for individuals,
the mode of production is “a definite form of expressing their life, a definite mode of life on their
part. As individuals express their life, so they are. What they are, therefore, coincides with their
production, both with what they produce and how they produce” (Marx and Engels 1972: 42).
52 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
reinforce class divisions, along with the inherent social class conflicts and
contradictions of capitalist societies. However, the dynamics of class struggle
can move us beyond the negative reading of ideology above, to an arena of
critique where the oppressive ideas, structures, and practices of the ruling
class are openly critiqued and class-consciousness evolves. Marx argues that it
is through this evolution of class-consciousness and organized revolutionary
action that the working class give birth to new theories, along with new social
and political organizations.
For Marx, the historical class struggle of workers must be understood
dialectically—where the interconnections, changes, and movements between
and across individuals and societies, humans and nature, knowledge and
practice all retain the revolutionary tension necessary for critical inquiry and
the possibility of transformation. It is this feature of dialectical materialism
that ruptures the bourgeois (or liberal) farce of individual freedom, in the
absence of revolutionary aims. To this point, Marx argues, “In bourgeois
society capital is independent and has individuality, while the living person
is dependent and has no individuality.” In contrast, Marxism expresses the
importance of communal solidarity, by calling for “an association, in which
the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all”
(Marx and Engels 1848).
Given the fundamentally antidemocratic foundation of capitalist relations,
Marxism considers democratic principles indispensable to overcoming our
alienation (McLaren and Leonard 1993), as well as our efforts to engage
critically across larger arenas of organized class struggle that extend beyond
our daily tensions as individual workers. Marx contends, “social domination in
capitalism does not, on its most fundamental level, consist in the domination
of people by other people, but in the domination of people by abstract social
structures that people themselves constitute” (Postone 1996: 30). Lastly,
Marx responds to this universalism of worker oppression through a call for
Internationalism, where the common interests and struggles of working people
worldwide focus on the abolition of national interests and the formation
of international communities where socialist values of human rights and
economic justice prevail.
Intellectual History 53
Marxist intellectuals
The works of Marxist theorists influenced Freire’s ideas and are cited
throughout Pedagogy of the Oppressed. These include Vladimir Lenin, Rosa
Luxembourg,35 György Lukács, Antonio Gramsci, and Louis Althusser, as
well as Lucien Goldmann, André Nicolaï, and Gavrito “Gajo” Ptrovio. These
socialist philosophers engaged Marx and expanded his ideas in a variety of
ways, particularly with respect to questions of humanist praxis, ideology,
consciousness, cultural hegemony, and language. In several instances,
their writings challenge the Marxist orthodoxy of their time, in an effort to
free Marxism from the vice of an exaggerated scientificity and economic
determinism that betrayed its liberatory intent.
Vladimir Lenin
Bolshevik revolutionary leader, Vladimir Lenin is credited for the success
of the Great October Socialist Revolution36 of 1917. This Bolshevik offensive
is considered to mark the birth of the Soviet Union. Lenin’s What Is to
Be Done?—a book fashioned as a blueprint, based on Lenin’s tactics for
revolutionary praxis—is considered his most formidable contribution to our
understanding of strategic actions for societal reinvention. Lenin’s central
theme is built around three primary questions: (1) the character and main
content of political agitation; (2) organizational tasks; and (3) the plan for
simultaneously remaking society. Lenin points to the significant role of
theory, arguing, “without revolutionary theory there can be no revolutionary
movement” (12).
For Lenin, theoretical (or ideological) struggle is as significant to revolution
as political and economic struggles. On this issue, Lenin is more pragmatic
than Marx, in that he contends that beyond the spontaneity of class struggle,
the revolution requires the active participation of committed organic
intellectuals (which he calls professional intellectuals), who are in relationship
with the working class. It is through this shared relationship of praxis, between
35
Along with Simone de Beauvoir, Rosa Luxembourg is one of only two female intellectuals included
in this intellectual pantheon.
36
Also commonly referred to as Red October, the October Uprising or the Bolshevik Revolution.
54 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Rosa Luxembourg
Socialist philosopher, Rosa Luxembourg, is best remembered for her
passionate discourses that sought to move notions of freedom and truth
beyond dogma or sectarian fixations, in an effort to recover Marx’s dialectical
insistence on an embodied revolutionary process. Hence, Luxembourg’s (1906,
2006) deeply humanistic and revolutionary sensibilities fueled her critique
of so-called reforms that betrayed the essence of working-class struggle.
Similarly, Luxembourg (2007) challenges the antidemocratic tendencies of
many Marxists of her time, who were mired in a lifeless, mechanistic, and
“policemanlike materialism” (116). This she argues undermines Marx’s own
humanism, which calls for “a society in which the full and free development
of every individual is the ruling principle” (Marx 1990: 739). In the face of an
increasingly dogmatic Stalinism, Luxembourg confronted what she perceived
as deceptiveness and dangerous “infallible authorities” of the party, who
undermined and betrayed the communal participatory demands of Marxist
praxis. In response, Luxembourg (1905) asserts in The Political Leader of the
German Working Classes, true to historical materialist ideals,
György Lukács
The major contributions of the Marxist philosopher György Lukács include the
development of a Marxist system of aesthetics that opposed political control
of artists and, like Luxembourg, defended humanism. Through his writings,
Lukács sought to elaborate on Marxist notions of ideology, alienation, and
consciousness within the context of an ever-expanding industrialized society.
In 1923, Lukács wrote History and Class Consciousness (1972), where he forged
a unique Marxist philosophy of history, which laid the basis for a critical
56 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
literary and artistic perspective, which inserted artistic expression within the
theory and practice of revolution. Defying mechanistic tendencies to view
Marxism as merely a scientific analysis of social and economic change, Lukács
delineates Marxism as philosophy. Lukács notes an intrinsic dialectics within
the consciousness of workers, given their class positionality as objects of the
social process that shapes their lives. Lacking is a sense of self-consciousness,
which generates an intrinsic tension. This constitutes three aspects: first is
the worker’s own reified existence as a product of social mediation; second,
the social totality; and third, the workers as the subject-object of that totality.
Lukács (1972) writes, “The act of consciousness overthrows the objective form
of its object” (178) and, thus, the worker too can overcome objectification
through practical engagement with the totality of life.
A significant Marxist idea that Lukács (1972) expands here is that of
reification, an alienating process of rational objectification that detaches people
from their labor and knowledge, converting everything and everyone—
including living ideas, qualities, interests, relationships, and human practices—
into consumable objects, in the interest of capitalist accumulation. Lukács
reinforces the link of reification to the commodity-structure of capitalism,
where social relationships between people are objectified and fetishized, as if
“they possessed an autonomous power and objectivity” (Rooke 1998). “Its basis
is that a relation between people takes on the character of a thing and thus
acquires a ‘phantom objectivity’, an autonomy that seems so strictly rational
and all-embracing as to conceal every trace of its fundamental nature: the
relation between people.”37 Lukács points to the manner in which this process
of commodification, across social, political, and economic spheres, perpetuates
human alienation and our subsequent subordination, within capitalist society.
Antonio Gramsci
The Italian revolutionary thinker, Antonio Gramsci, who was incarcerated
for much of his life by Mussolini, is another key intellectual who wrote in
the Marxist tradition. The compilation of his writing, published in Prison
Notebooks, provided a useful rethinking of several fundamental ideas
37
See: https://www.marxists.org/archive/lukacs/works/history/hcc05.htm.
Intellectual History 57
associated with Marxist thought and the assertion that a genuine democracy,
as a total and integral part of society, had to be the fundamental objective of
revolutionary struggle. Through his philosophy of praxis, Gramsci moved to
overcome what he considered to be the democratic limitations of economic
determinism and, in so doing, expand Marxism’s explanatory possibility.
About this, Gramsci (1971) writes, “The philosophy of praxis … does not tend
toward the peaceful resolution of the contradictions existing within history. It
is itself the theory of those contradictions” (196–197). Of particular concern,
for Gramsci was the failure of the working class to enter into the revolutionary
process, as Marx had theorized, and instead falling captive to the authoritarian
rule of fascist regime (Giltin 1979). This conflict prompted him toward a
theory of hegemony. Starting from the assumption that the historical process
has deposited an infinity of traces (Gramsci 1971:326) within us, Gramsci’s
radical conceptualization of culture opens new theoretical ground from which
to examine the structures of everyday life.
More specifically, “hegemony refers to the ideological control of dominant
beliefs, values, and social practices that are reproduced and distributed
throughout a whole range of institutions, including schools, the family, mass
media, and trade unions” (Giroux 1981: 94). Here, the supremacy of the ruling
class manifests itself in two distinct ways: as material domination and as
intellectual moral leadership. Through inquiry into the nature of hegemony,
Gramsci unveils the contradictions and unravels the entanglements between
structures of political power, ideology, and pedagogy that result in relations
of domination. Important to a theory of hegemony is the complexity that
governs the perpetuation of unacknowledged ideologies that both protect and
conserve the inequalities inherent to capitalist societies. Gramsci affirms the
need to engage dialectically with a variety of ideological ideas and meanings in
the context of everyday social life—ideas that are both imposed from outside
and voluntarily reproduced from within, through widespread common sense
notions—unexamined ideas, beliefs, or assumptions that betray the interests of
the working class, by reinforcing social and material relations of domination.
Here, the question of social agency is paramount to Gramsci’s analysis, which
diverts from an essentialized Marxist economic determinism and, instead,
gives centrality to the response of human beings to their world.
58 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
38
Gramsci’s theory of hegemony has also been employed in debates about civil society. For those
concerned with the ways in which liberal or bourgeois thought both narrowly defines and reduces
civil society to an “associational” or lesser domain in contrast to the state and market, Gramsci’s
definition affirms that civil society, within a genuinely democratic context, can serve as a public
Intellectual History 59
movements, trade unions and so on” (Heywood 1994: 100). This represents a
power preserved by selective silences and manifested in the fragmentation of
social definitions, management of information, and the subsequent shaping
of popular attention, consent, belief, and trust (Forester 1987). However, what
cannot be missed here, according to Gramsci (1971), is that
sphere of political struggle and contestation over ideas and norms. As such, it also offers a public
context for communities to collectively build their critical capacities to challenge oppressive
assumptions, practices, and policies, as well as articulate new ideas and visions (Heywood 1994).
For another interesting discussion into this question, see Marco Fonseca’s (2016) book Gramsci’s
Critique of Civil Society.
60 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
of passion (in knowledge and feeling) where “one cannot make politics-history
without this passion, without this connection of feeling between intellectuals
and [the] people …” (350).
Louis Althusser
Among Marxist scholars, there are two distinct views at play with respect
to the concept of ideology. The first is apparent in the writings of orthodox
Marxists who contend it is possible to get beyond ideology, in an effort to
reach some essential truths about society and freedom. In this perspective,
ideology is essentialized as creating false consciousness—a way of thinking
that prevents individuals from perceiving the true nature of their social
or economic situation, consequently obscuring relations of power. Louis
Althusser (2001) breaks with this essentialism,39 by arguing that ideology is
profoundly unconscious and a deeply embedded aspect of our culture, which
actively determines how we think about reality. By reality, Althusser refers
to that world that we create around us, once we have become a part of the
symbolic order.40 Submerged in this order, our perceptions of reality become
so indistinguishably bound to how we think that as soon as we even try to
articulate new truths, we easily can fall back into our old, conditioned view of
the world. Hence, for Althusser, it is impossible to access the real conditions
of existence due to our reliance on language, which is both generated by and
generates the prism of our ideological lens.
Althusser’s (2001) view on ideology is then constituted according to four
key assumptions.41 (1) Rather than the real world, ideology represents the
imaginary relationship of individuals to their real conditions of existence. (2)
Ideology has material existence and manifests through actions that become
ritualized through human relationships and to social institutions. (3) All
ideology hails or interpellates concrete individuals as concrete subjects. And
39
“Essentialism” refers to (1) a belief that things have a set of characteristics that make them what they
are and science and philosophy is their discovery and expression; and (2) a view that categories of
people, such as women and men, or heterosexuals and homosexuals, or members of ethnic groups,
have intrinsically different and characteristic natures or dispositions.
40
“Symbolic order” refers to the social world of linguistic communication, intersubjective relations,
knowledge of ideological conventions, and the acceptance of the law. Althusser draws this concept
from Jacques Lacan. See: Jacques Lacan’s (1977) Écrits: A Selection.
41
See: Althusser’s (2001) Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays (109–123) for a full discussion of
these key assumptions. The discussion here is drawn from this section of the book.
Intellectual History 61
(4) individuals are always ready-subjects, in that even before birth we are
primed as ready-subjects to accept the hegemonic precepts of the society in
which we are born. Hence, similar to Gramsci, Althusser sees hegemony as
less reliant on the power of the state apparatus than on the power of ideology,
where individuals consider themselves to participate solely through their own
volition. In keeping with these assumptions, Althusser introduces the notion
of ideological state apparatus—which denotes institutions such as education,
churches, family, media, trade unions, and law, which formally exist outside
state control but which served to transmit or interpellate the values of the state.
Within the context of education, Althusser (2001) maintains that the ruling
class has made education its “dominant ideological State apparatus … which
has in fact replaced in its functions the previously dominant ideological State
apparatus, the Church” (104). He argues that as each cohort of students exit
educational institutions, they enter into the workforce “practically provided
with the ideology which suits the role it has to fulfill in class society” (105).
Moreover, Althusser argues, “no other ideological State apparatus has the
obligatory (and not least, free) audience of the totality of the children in the
capitalist social formation, eight hours a day for five or six days out of seven”
(105). Despite this central ideological function, schools are portrayed as neutral
settings “purged of ideology … where teachers respectful of the ‘conscience’
and ‘freedom’ of the children … entrusted to them (in complete confidence)
by their ‘parents’ (who are free, too, i.e., the owners of their children) open up
for them the path to the freedom, morality and responsibility of adults by their
own example, by knowledge, literature and their ‘liberating’ virtues” (105–106).
In Pedagogy of the Oppressed, Freire makes reference to Althusser’s (1967)
discussion of contradictions42 and overdetermination.43 It is through his theory
42
For Althusser (1969), it is important to recognize that “the contradiction is inseparable from the
total structure of the social body in which it is found, inseparable from its formal conditions of
existence and even from the instances it governs; it is radically affected by them, determining in
and the same moment, and determined by the various levels and instances of the social formation it
animates, it might be called overdetermined in its principle” (101). Althusser draws this idea from
Mao’s Tse-Tung (1965).
43
Althusser uses the idea of overdetermination as a way of thinking about the multiple, often
oppositional, forces active at once in any political situation, without falling into an overly simplistic
idea of these multifaceted and multidimensional forces being simply “contradictory.” Moreover,
“overdetermination of a contradiction is the reflection in it of its conditions of existence within the
complex whole” (254).
62 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
“it is in ideology that human beings ‘become conscious’ of their class conflict
and ‘fight it out’; in its religious, ethical, legal and political forms, etc., ideology
is an objective social reality; the ideological struggle is an organic part of the
class struggle” (11–12).
stance of the school. The members of the Praxis School clashed with orthodox
Marxist-Leninists of the Communist Party and were subjected to much
criticism by zealous supporters of Stalin’s regime. In response, Petrović and
his comrades called for freedom of speech, pointing to Marx’s insistence on
the importance of ruthless critique of all that exists.44 The underlying intent
was a return to “the real” Marx, in contrast to Stalin’s authoritarian right-wing
philosophy, which had diverted from the human essence of praxis and thus
fallen into dictatorship.
In his essay, “Why Praxis?,” Petrović (1964) argues that “Socialism is the
only human way out from the difficulties in which humanity has entangled
itself, and Marx’s thought—the adequate theoretical bases and inspiration
for revolutionary activity.” Moreover, he was concerned that an authentic,
humanist socialism was simply impossible without revitalizing Marx’s
humanist philosophy and moving toward an understanding and practice of a
Marxism that could step beyond a dogmatic authoritarian posture. He argued
again the alienation and instrumentalization of human beings, under “the
pressure of mass impersonalism and of the scientific method of ‘cultivation’
of the masses [which] is more and more opposed to the development of a
free human personality.” Petrović and his comrade also fought against the
notion of a “correct” or “pure” form of Marxism; but rather, “to develop vivid
revolutionary thought inspired by Marx.” Ultimately, Petrović saw his work and
that of the Praxis School as “a political project committed to ‘the development
of philosophical thought and realization of a humane community.’”
Critical theory
44
This expression, ruthless criticism of all that exists, is used by Marx in a Letter to Arnold Ruge of
September 1843. The whole expression states:
If constructing the future and settling everything for all times are not our affair, it is all the more
clear what we have to accomplish at present: I am referring to ruthless criticism of all that exists,
ruthless both in the sense of not being afraid of the results it arrives at and in the sense of being
just as little afraid of conflict with the powers that be. (Petrovic 1964)
Intellectual History 65
45
Although Freire does not mention French philosopher Emmanuel Lévinas (1979) or German
philosopher Jürgen Habermas (1987), both are considered important thinkers with respect to a
critique of instrumental reason (Smith 2008). Lévinas points to the manner in which ontology, by its
very nature, attempts to create a totality in which what is different and “other” is necessarily reduced
to sameness and identity. This proclivity for totality is a basic manifestation of “instrumental” reason,
where reason is used as an instrument for determining the best or most efficient means to achieve a
given end. Through its embrace of instrumental reason, Western philosophy displays a destructive
and objectifying “will to domination.” Moreover, because instrumental reason does not determine the
ends to which it is applied, it has been used in the pursuit of goals that are destructive or evil. In this
regard, instrumental reason was responsible for much of the crises of Europe the twentieth century,
particularly with respect to advancing totalitarianism (Wolin 2017). “According to Habermas’ staging,
all the participants in the discourse of modernity see the division between subjects, and the petrification
of sociality due to instrumental reason, as the defining pathology of the times” (Smith 2008: 646). For
Habermas (1987), “Since the close of the eighteenth century, the discourse of modernity has had a
single theme under ever new titles: the weakening of the forces of social bonding” (139).
66 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
A final event that influenced the development of critical theory was the
nature and impact of the unbridled advance of capitalism in the West. The rapid
development of science and technology and their overwhelming penetration
into the political and social systems resulted in new transformations in the
structure of capitalism, accelerating the development of an advanced industrial-
technological society. Both the major historical and political developments
of capitalist society, as well as the rise of bureaucratic communist orthodoxy
affirmed for the members of Frankfurt School the necessity to address two
major issues. First, the need to develop a new critical social theory within a
Marxist framework, which could contend with the complex changes arising
in an industrial-technological, post-liberal, capitalist society; and second, the
need to recover the power of Marx’s dialectical approach, which had undergone
a major economic and materialistic reduction by a new authoritarian Marxist
orthodoxy (Warren 1984).
The intent of the Frankfurt School was to become a material force in the
struggle against domination of all forms, by addressing through their writings
and political participation the following questions (Held 1980: 35).
● Given the fate of Marxism in Russia and Western Europe, is Marxism itself
nothing other than a state orthodoxy? Was there a social agent capable
of progressive change? What possibilities were there for effective socialist
practices?
Theodor Adorno
For Theodor Adorno, a major contributor to the Frankfurt School’s investigation
into the relationship of culture, power, and ideology, conventional views of
culture failed to engage the decisive role of ideology in constructing both
difference and social conflicts. In Negative Dialectics, Adorno (1973b) critiques
the idea of identity thinking (us versus them) and its ties to the exclusionary
universalism of the Enlightenment. He argues that identity thinking constructs
“the other,” by including dominant cultural values and ways of being as
legitimately human, while excluding those cultural values and ways of the
“other” that would counter this legitimacy. Hence, he posits that this cultural
phenomenon of exclusion is, in fact, not a “natural” manifestation, but rather
is constructed by the powerful in order to justify domination.
Adorno, therefore, criticizes philosophical notions that reify (objectify) the
logic of culture as somehow independent of history, materiality, and social
context, arguing, “culture … cannot be fully understood, either in terms of itself
… or in terms of the so-called universal development of the mind” (Giroux
1983: 22). Here, Adorno (1991) problematizes authoritarian historical forms of
Marxism that place “capitalism into a naïve narrative of progress and freedom
[which] becomes, through its attempt to unify and integrate history, complicit
with its object” (3). Informed by this critique, he developed a critical analysis
of culture that makes it central to the development of historical experience, as
much as in the social and material processes of everyday life. Adorno, similar
Intellectual History 69
Max Horkheimer
Max Horkheimer (1972), often associated with a critique of ideology, also
draws on the negative ideology of Marxism—the idea that ideology, as an
individual or set of claims, perspectives, and philosophies masks or conceals
the social contradictions in society, on behalf of the ruling class. More simply
put, Horkheimer viewed ideology as “the veil over the contradictory character
of society” (cited in Stirk 1992: 66). For Horkheimer and the other Frankfurt
school thinkers, ideology spoke to forms of consciousness that become
standardized and homogenized as representing everyone’s general interests
but, in fact, conserve the interests of those in power. This is accomplished
in society by way of reinforcing the notion that “societal outcomes represent
natural ones when they are the result of particular constellations of human
relations; and/or … glorify the social situation as harmonious when it is, in fact,
conflict-ridden” (Held 1980: 186). Hence, ideologies are not mere illusions,
but rather the outcome of reified social relations that mystify and distort
the truth about how and why there exist gross power differentials in society.
Ideologies, moreover, embody “symbols, ideas, and theories through which
people experience their relation to each other and the world” (Held 1980: 186).
70 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Hence, the need made for a critique of ideology to unveil the structures of our
dehumanization and domestication is at the heart of critical theory.
For Horkheimer, ideology underpins capitalist social relations based on
class interests that in practice (essence) negate individual autonomy, despite
ideological adherence (appearance) to the doctrine of individualism. Hence,
the individualism of capitalist ideology simultaneously emphasizes and
denies the individual’s subjectivity. On the one hand, the individual subject,
freed from the bondages of feudalism, is now free to buy and sell on the open
market. The individual’s material success, therefore, becomes a guideline for
judging right and wrong; and consequently, this success also becomes both
the sign and reward of individual value. On the other hand, the individual
subject is negated and alienated in a system of buying and selling. Hence,
as mentioned earlier, the process of exchange becomes the mode by which
individuality is organized and claimed. Pursuit of self-interest is equated
with pursuit of individual material gain. Through this scheme, the liberal or
bourgeoisie defense of individual freedom becomes ideology, in that it masks
capitalist’s interests and the underlying motivation that inform its origins
(Held 1980).
Herbert Marcuse
Also critical to an understanding of how ideology works on and through
individuals is the Frankfurt School’s notion of depth psychology developed
by Herbert Marcuse (1955). Influenced by the more progressive strands of
Sigmund Freud’s46 theories of the unconscious and instinct, Marcuse conceived
of ideology as existing at the depth of the individual’s psychological structure
of needs, common sense, and critical consciousness. Thus, instead of limiting
his notion of ideology only to external social processes, Marcuse (1955), in
Eros and Civilization, dialectically defines it as forms of historically rooted
domination that exist both in the socioeconomic structure of society as well as
in the sedimented history or psychological structures of the individual. In this
manner, he seeks to explain “that the struggle against freedom reproduce[s] …
in the psyche of man [and woman] as the self-repression of the repressed
46
See, for example, Sigmund Freud’s (2002) Civilization and Its Discontents written in 1930 and
Marcuse’s (1955) Eros and Civilization.
Intellectual History 71
individual, and his self-repression in turn sustains his masters and their
institutions” (16). Marcuse’s view of ideology connects with Gramsci’s
notion of cultural hegemony, in that it points to the manner in which human
domestication results from dominant forms of social control encased in a
myriad of contradictions and unresolved conflicts that permeate everyday life.
However, for Marcuse, this is also linked to eros—an erotic instinctual need
for freedom significant to the struggle for liberation (Katsiaficas 2011).
In his writings, Marcuse also sought to imagine a society in which all
aspects of our humanity—our work, play, love, and sexuality—could function
in sustaining a free society, by first considering the ways in which these are
disrupted in modern society. In One Dimensional Man, considered to be one of
the most important books of its time, Marcuse (1964) asserts that, despite the
one-dimensionality of human existence within capitalist society, there actually
exist dimensions of our humanity that have been eroded and that we must
recover. Part of this erosion includes destruction of the intimate spheres of life
(i.e., sexuality), which have been appropriated and commodified in ways that
facilitate domination, without critique or protest. The society, Marcuse writes,
turns everything it touches into a potential source of progress and exploitation,
of drudgery and satisfaction, of freedom and of oppression. The outcome of
this contradictory rationality is “the conquest of the unhappy,” where any sense
that something is wrong and that change is needed or possible is suppressed.
Proceeding on the basis of negative (or dialectical) thinking, Marcuse stresses
the political necessity of overcoming “the oppressive and ideological power of
given facts” (227), if human beings are to recover the multidimensionality of
our existence.
Erich Fromm
Socialist psychoanalyst and philosopher, Erich Fromm sought to combine the
explanatory powers of Marxism with Freud’s more progressive psychoanalytical
ideas, in ways that could breathe new life into the inextricable relationship
that exists between human beings and society. Central to his life’s quest was
an unwavering commitment to illuminate the dynamics of psychological
repression and social domination, by revealing the complex relationship
that exists between the individual and society. Fromm (1955) argues that
72 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
human beings, in the context of modern capitalist society, have been violently
uprooted from our organic connection to nature; and, thus, have been left
poorly equipped to adapt to in a rapidly changing world. He further notes that
since human beings have simultaneously developed the ability to reason and
recognize our increasing alienation—or separation from nature—the human
situation of our objectification causes us an existential dilemma.
Fromm’s writings are anchored in a radical humanism that throughout
his life potentiated his steadfast emancipatory politics. Fromm (1966)
contends,
Hence, the human condition, our potential physical and intellectual capacities,
and the evolution of consciousness are all themes interwoven across the
landscape of Fromm’s psychology of liberation. In a world Fromm perceives as
steadily driven by technology toward a soulless and mechanistic existence, he
seeks to both critically understand and recover the essence of our humanity,
the spirit of our existence, and the possibility for an emancipatory purpose to
human life.
In The Art of Loving, Fromm (1956) takes up a central theme of his life’s
work: Love as the answer to the problem of human existence (7), particularly
within the dehumanizing context of capitalist society. For Fromm, “to analyze
the nature of love is to discover its general absence today and to criticize the
social conditions … responsible for this absence” (133). Fromm, further,
argues, “In a culture in which the marketing orientation prevails, and in which
material success is the outstanding value, there is little reason to be surprised
that human love relations follow the same pattern of exchange which governs
the commodity and the labor market” (4). Underlying his critique of capitalism
as disintegrating society is the assertion that the unbridled commodification of
Intellectual History 73
human beings, as market objects of exchange, has not only separated us from
nature but from one another.
Fromm (1956) asserts, “the principle underlying capitalist society and
the principle of love are incompatible” (131). The anxieties produced by
this incompatibility have generated a culture of lovelessness and alienation;
which effectively perpetuates, on one hand, repression of individual freedom
and expression, while on the other, promotes increasing concentration of
wealth and power among the dominant class. Accordingly, “in contemporary
capitalistic society the meaning of equality now refers to the equality of
automatons—human beings who in fact are devoid of their individuality”
(Fromm 1964: 15). Central to Fromm’s efforts to challenge this phenomenon
is his historical materialist engagement with human relationships, which he
perceives as essential to the future of our humanity. Love as an individual
and collective political force is, therefore, viewed as capable of disrupting our
alienation, recovering our humanity, and propelling human existence toward
greater emancipatory consciousness.
From this sense, “love is not primarily a relationship to a specific person;
it is an attitude, an orientation of character which determines the relatedness
of a person to the world as a whole, not toward one ‘object: of love’” (46); and,
as such, Fromm (1956) maintains, that love is at the root of human solidarity.
Indispensable to this idea of love is a “communication with each other from
the center of [our] existence.”
the indispensable qualities of love, humility, faith, courage, and action. In his
work, Fromm speaks to the reciprocal aliveness (or biophilia47) and horizontal
nature of relationships—human interactions that affirm life—where faith and
respect to for the other abide; where “The teacher is taught by his [or her]
students” (25), relating “to each other genuinely and productively” (25).
Conversely, Fromm (1973) theorizes the deathlike (or necrophilic)48 quality
of loveless relationships where indispensable qualities of love are absent,
particularly with respect to those groups perceived as problematic to advancing
principles of profit and consumption. Here, Fromm makes reference to an
alienating culture of exclusion, which results in the suppression of the objectified
other—whether through ideological signification of inferiority or violent forms
of repression. Fromm (1955) associates this necrophilic phenomenon to the
manner in which “religious and racial minorities, as far as they are powerless,
offer vast opportunities for sadistic satisfaction for even the poorest member
of the majority” (290). Similarly, Fromm argues that possessive mechanisms of
“extreme submission and domination” make people “insane,” to the point that
all relationships become “dependent on those to whom he submits, or whom
he dominates” (31). Such forms of narcissism, rooted in social and material
relations of capitalist production, promote dehumanization and “lost contact
with the world” (34). In the process, the other is perceived and treated as an
object of domination, transformed “into a thing, something animate into
something inanimate” stripped of that “essential quality of life—freedom” (32).
In The Fear of Freedom, Fromm (1942) undertakes a historical examination of
the psychological dynamics associated with freedom and its impact on human
beings. Central to his argument is that true freedom can only be predicated on
an organic relationship of human beings to the world, within the spontaneity
of love and productive work. In the absence of this relationship, the alienation
and isolation brought on by human insecurities and anxieties diminishes
the possibilities of freedom and unravels the integrity of the self. Fromm,
therefore, asserts that true freedom or freedom to requires true connection with
others—a connection that allows us both to enter into spontaneous activity,
47
From defines biophilia as “the passionate love of life and all that is alive; it is the wish to further
growth, whether in a person, plant an idea, or a social group” (Fromm 1973: 365).
48
From defines necrophilia as “the passion to destroy life and the attraction to all that is dead, decaying,
and purely mechanical” (Fromm 1973: 6).
Intellectual History 75
and, as such, experience a “spontaneous realization of the self ” that with each
interaction, unites us “anew with the world …” (224). Hence, freedom is not
an individual stagnant construct or object to be obtained, but rather it is a
living process generated within the relational structures in which we reside.
Fromm contends that the contradictions of capitalism, in conjunction with
Calvinist values, violates the necessary conditions for freedom by trampling
human agency, in order to preserve its social and material domination. This,
Fromm maintains, occurs through a mode of production that both objectifies
and instrumentalizes human beings, alienating us from one another and our
social environment. Fromm complicates this analysis by suggesting that even
when human beings are freed from structures of domination, there is a fear of
freedom (or freedom from) and a tendency to experience a new set of anxieties
that can result in feelings of hopelessness—a hopelessness that can only be
overcome when we can work together spontaneously to use our freedom to in
the process of remaking our world. Unfortunately, Fromm also notes, that a
common response to anxieties associated with the fear of freedom is to move
toward authoritarianism, destructiveness, and conformity, which ironically
become associated with a greater sense of security and safety.
Dismissed from the Frankfurt School by Horkheimer in 1939 and accused
by some of the Frankfurt School members of having “emptied psychoanalysis
of its revolutionary content by abandoning Freud’s49 essential premise that
libidinal drives50 are deeply embedded biological entities that energize
49
Although Fromm (1941) acknowledges that “Freud went further than anybody before him in
directing attention to the observation and analysis of the irrational and unconscious forces
which determine human behavior,” in the Art of Loving (1956), he points to “Freud’s error” or
“his physiological materialism” rooted in an undialectical reading of the relationship between
psychology and biology. This, according to Fromm, results in deterministic conclusions of, for
example, psychosexual stages of development. About this, he accused Freud of ignoring the psycho-
biological aspects in his conclusion of male/female sexuality, which he chalks up to “Freud’s extreme
patriarchalism, which led him to the assumption that sexuality per se is masculine, and thus made
him ignore the specifics of female sexuality” (36).
50
“Libido” refers to the sexual or erotic drive. For Freud, this is analogous to the drive for hunger.
Freud views it as a fundamental human instinct that is evident already at birth. All the libidinal
impulses, for Freud, are inherently attached to vital bodily functions (e.g., nourishment, voiding
of waste). What distinguishes the libidinal dimension from the functional aspect, as pure bodily
necessity, is the pleasure with which the activity is associated. Thus the libidinal drive is tied to the
pleasure principle. In his theory, Freud essentializes these drives as biologically determined, which is
reflected in his libidinal phases psycho-sexual behavior, which are categorized as oral, anal, phallic,
latent, and genital. See Freud’s (1949) The Ego and the Id and Sigmund Freud: Examining the Essence
of His Contributions by Stevens (2008).
76 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Karel Kosik
The Hungarian Marxist humanist, Karel Kosik, is often overlooked with
respect to his critical influence on Freire’s ideas. In Prague, Kosik became a
leading voice for democratic socialism in the period referred to as the Prague
Spring of 1968; his on-the-ground political involvement, however, resulted
in his dismissal from his university post in 1970. Kosik’s (1976) major work,
Dialectics of the Concrete, came to be regarded globally as a major contribution
to critical theory, particularly in Latin America. In the Spanish translation,
Dialéctica de lo Concreto, published in 1968, Adolfo Sánchez Vásquez asserts
in the prologue, “Kosik is not only one of the most important philosophers
of the second half of the twentieth century, but also one of those who best
understood the spirit of resistance of critical thinking.”
Kosik undertakes a masterful reexamination and critique of Heidegger,
while providing a reworking of Marxian categories of humanist phenomenology.
At the heart of his analysis is a criticism of reductive Marxism, in which he argues
51
Apart from being a civil rights activist, Fromm also led vigorous movements against nuclear
weapons, participated in anti-Vietnam war protests, and worked with movements for the protection
of the environment.
52
Although, there is a tendency to only speak about Fromm’s influence on Mexican Psychology and
humanist revolutionary ideas in the region (Burston 1985), I would argue, that Fromm’s evolving
sensibilities were also deeply influenced by his association and friendships with thinkers rooted in
an early Latin Americanism or Southern epistemological tradition, including Paulo Freire.
Intellectual History 77
that we can only grasp the reality of anything through our practical activity.
He contends this praxis is, in fact, the opening by which we gain a sense of
being. Kosik introduces the notion of the dialectical disunity of everyday life to
offer a rational critique of everyday intentionality, within the contentiousness
of modernity. “The dialectical disunity is lived as a social conflict—the conflict
of master and slave, ruler and ruled, of exploiter and exploited, manipulator
and manipulated—and as the spirit of man and nature—subject and object,
freedom and necessity, intent as causality” (Bakan 1983: 83). Given that
human beings have become divided by the deeply hierarchical nature of
capitalist relations of labor, Kosik asserts, uncompromisingly, that it is only by
way of “historical dialectical struggle that the essence of being human can be
developed, transformed and realized” (83).
Anticolonial theory
53
Memmi and Fanon knew each other when both men were working in Tunis. See the essay by
Memmi (1973) titled “The Impossible Life of Frantz Fanon,” where Memmi draws on mutual points
of contact in a testimony to Fanon’s contributions, viewing Fanon’s life “as one possible model for the
dominated individual’s revolt against the conditions of his oppression” (Cassirer and Twomey 1973:
10). However, it is important to note critiques that have been issued regarding Memmi’s analysis and
characterizations of Fanon’s process. For an excellent discussion, see Charles F. Peterson’s (2007)
Dubois, Fanon, Cabral: The Margins of Elite Anticolonial Leadership, where he argues that “Memmi’s
questions of Fanon’s racial, cultural and geographical identifications reveal a mind unable to move
beyond oppressive frameworks. Fanon’s heresy of not sticking with his own kind disrupts Memmi’s
vision of nation, race, and culture” (100).
54
Briefly speaking, “postcolonialism” refers to an area of study that analyzes, explains, and responds
to the cultural legacy of colonialism and imperialism. As an area of study, postcolonialism engages
the human consequences of external control and economic exploitation of native people and their
lands. “The ‘post’ of Colonialism is both the after-time of a historical period and the critique of the
episteme or mind set that led one small part of the world to dominate the Other” (Willette 2013). In
addition to Fanon and Memmi, other key authors often associated with this academic tradition are
Michel Foucault, Edward Said, Gayatri Charkravorty Spivak, and Homi Bhabha.
78 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Frantz Fanon
Frantz Fanon, an Afro-Caribbean psychiatrist, philosopher, and revolutionary,
is considered one of the leading anticolonial thinkers of the twentieth century.
Although revolutionary movements embraced his passionate anticolonial
writings, his forthright challenge to the immorality of colonial rule was viewed
as a threat to the white establishment.57 By expounding on the racializing
dynamics at the heart of what later would be referred to the coloniality of
power, Fanon expanded the revolutionary ideas of Marxists and critical
55
It is precisely of this phenomenon of the oppressed to develop different responses patterns to the
subaltern experience of the oppressor/oppressed or colonizer/colonized contradiction that is at the
heart of the radical bicultural theory of cultural democracy developed in Culture and Power in the
Classroom (Darder 2012)—first published in 1991.
56
For feminists discussions on Fanon and Memmi, see: Frantz Fanon: Conflict and Feminisms by
T. Denean Sharpley-Whiting (1998) and Maria del Guadalupe Davidson’s (2012) essay, “Albert
Memmi and Audre Lorde: Gender, Race, and the Rhetorical Uses of Anger” in Journal of French and
Francophone Philosophy.
57
In 1959, the seriousness of this threat becomes abruptly evident when a car “accident” in Morocco and
a car bomb in Rome were both speculated to be attempts on Fanon’s life (Cherki 2006). Nevertheless,
Fanon persisted in his articulation of his anticolonial thesis until his death in December 1961 from
leukemia.
Intellectual History 79
58
See the essay “The Impossible Life of Frantz Fanon,” written by Memmi (1973) that provides some
discussion of the dilemma’s Fanon grappled with around this question. However, also see Jadallah’s
(2012) incisive critique of Memmi’s perceptions of Fanon in her essay, “The Shibboleths within
Albert Memmi’s Universalism” in Jadaliyya.
80 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
employs Marxist dialectics to show that this disabling impact is both a collective
and an individual phenomenon. His analysis systematically uncovers the
manner in which the colonizer/colonized dichotomy is profoundly predicated
on an ideological fantasy of white superiority and Black inferiority, which is
consciously and unconsciously at work in the theories and practices of white
psychiatry and psychoanalysis.
Fanon contends that one of the most destructive dimensions of the
oppressive colonizer/colonized contradiction or dependency complex is the
manner in which the negation of Black identity becomes deeply internalized by
the colonized, resulting in their social and material alienation. Fanon further
argues that this internalization of self-hate and inferiority—propagated at the
hands of the colonizer—leaves colonized subjects fragmented and estranged
from the very essence of our humanity. At the heart of colonization, Fanon
argues is a ruthless racializing mechanism that denigrates and maligns the
worthiness of the culture, language, and knowledge of the colonized. To
be human is to be white; a commonsensical “truth” rooted in a Eurocentric
taxonomy, which signifies white faces as pure, good, and worthy of power;
while black faces are deemed bestial, violent, and irredeemable.59 Fanon argues
that the debilitating impact of the agonizing twoness60 that ensues, often
functions to destroy the self-determination of the colonized, who are thrust
into a futile dilemma at the mercy of the colonizer—socialized to reject our
59
Although some would dismiss the validity of Fanon’s analysis in today’s context, we need only
examine the overrepresentation of violence perpetrated on the Black population at the hands of
police officers in the United States. In 2015, police killed 102 unarmed Black people, nearly twice
each week. Thirty-seven percent of unarmed people killed by police in 2015 were black, despite
the fact that only 13 percent of the population in the United States is African American. Unarmed
black people were killed at five times the rate of unarmed whites. A police officer was only changed
in less than 10 percent of these cases; and in only two instances were officers convicted. Moreover,
as investigations into some of the most violent police departments in America have shown, police
violence reflects a lack of accountability in the culture, policies, and practices of the institutions of
policing, rather than crime rate levels. See Mapping Police Violence at: https://mappingpoliceviolence.
org/unarmed/.
60
In Culture and Power in the Classroom (Darder 2012), where I engage the notion of twoness through
a radical redefinition of “biculturalism,” I have noted “the early 1900s, writers, educators, and
social theorists of color have made references in their work to the presence of some form of dual or
separate socialization process among their own people. These references have included a variety of
terms used to describe the personality development, identity, or traits of non-whites socialized in
a racist society: double consciousness (DuBois 1903), double vision (Wright 1953), bicultural (de
Anda 1984; Ramirez and Castañeda 1974; Rashid 1981; Red Horse et al. 1981; Solis 1980; Valentine
1971), diunital (Dixon and Foster 1971), multidimensional (Cross 1978), and other references that
closely resemble notions of duality and “twoness” (Fanon 1967; Hsu 1971; Kitano 1969; Memmi
1957; Sue and Sue 1978)” (46).
Intellectual History 81
Albert Memmi
The Colonizer and the Colonized is considered Albert Memmi’s (1957) most
influential work, where he provides an extensive analysis of the condition of
both the colonizer and the colonized. Memmi’s thesis engages with the manner
in which both colonized and colonizer is entrapped in their respective role or
in what Freire refers to as the oppressor-oppressed contradiction. As such, “a
relentless reciprocity binds the colonizer to the colonized—his product and his
fate” (24). Reminiscent of Fanon, Memmi too situates the impetus of his work
in lived history: “I was Tunisian,61 therefore colonized. I discovered that few
aspects of my life and my personality were untouched by this fact. Not only
my own thoughts, my passions and my conduct, but also the conduct of others
toward me was affected” (4). However, unlike Fanon, Memmi’s relationship to
Marxism is present but more tenuous, stating “colonial privilege is not solely
economic … the life of the colonizer and colonized is to discover rapidly that
the daily humiliation of the colonized, his [her] subjugation, are not merely
economic” (8). However, this should not be surprising, given Memmi’s deeply
61
Tunisia became a colony of the French in 1881, gaining its independence in 1956. During the French
colonial period, the country was home to French colonizers, Italians, Tunisian Muslims, and a
minority Jews. The Italians, although not as well off as the French, were also privileged. The Muslim
majority was the most oppressed. Although the Jews were also oppressed, Memmi describes the
Jews as more willing to try to assimilate to the French. According to Memmi, colonialism was not as
difficult for the Jews as it was for the Muslims because of their willingness to take on some aspects of
the colonial cultural. Jews joined the French in the streets of Algiers during independence uprisings.
Although Memmi joined the colonized rather than the colonizer, he contends that he understood
why the Jews chose the side of the French. He writes, “Because of this ambivalence, I knew only too
well the contradictory emotions which swayed their lives” (xiv). Moreover, it is important to note
here that there has existed what some consider a long-standing historical relationship of conflict
between Muslims and Jews in France (Mandel 2014), which surely was also felt in the Tunisian
colonial context.
Intellectual History 83
existential and literary roots.62 Yet, despite his Modernist propensities, Memmi
offers some key insights into the dynamics of colonial bondage and its impact
on both the colonizer and colonized.
Memmi (1957) asserts that colonialism, as an economic and ideological
phenomenon, is akin to fascism; and racialized violence its instrument of
human oppression. Racism, in the colonial context, is understood as “ingrained
in actions, institutions, and in the nature of the colonialist methods of
production and exchange” (20). Hence, for Memmi, colonialism is predicated
on the centrality of racism as a structural mechanism of colonial oppression,
which results in the dehumanization of the colonized. Memmi also takes up
the question of assimilation in the colonial situation, which he contends is an
unattainable goal, given the deeply invasive and vertical relationship of the
colonizer to the colonized. Within this profoundly ambivalent relationship
of domination—requiring the labor and allegiance of the colonized, on one
hand, and the social and political economic repression of the colonized on the
other—results in an oppressive dynamic of ambivalence, leaving the colonized
to survive within a wretched state of “painful and constant ambiguity” (59).
Meanwhile, Memmi claims, even the lowliest from the dominant culture
enjoys a “profound satisfaction of being negatively better than the colonized:
they are never completely engulfed in the abasement in which colonialism
drives them” (61).
However, in his portrait of the colonizer, Memmi also makes note of the
colonizer who refuses; who despite expressed condemnation of injustice often
lives “under the sign of a contradiction which looms at every step, depriving
[them] of all coherence and all tranquility” (64). Forms of incoherence and
contradiction are intertwined within an unacknowledged duplicity associated
with their lack of genuine identification with the colonized—who, consciously
or unconsciously, the colonizer regards as deficit. Of this, Memmi asserts
the benevolent colonizer can be “both a revolutionary and an exploiter” (67),
going “so far as to give [their] approval and even [their] assistance, [but their]
62
It is interesting to note that in certain respect, Jean-Paul Sartre confirms this point when he writes
in the foreword of The Colonizer and the Colonized, Memmi “attempts to live his particularity by
transcending it in the direction of the universal. The transcendence is not toward Man, who does
not yet exist, but toward a rigorous reason enforcing its claims on everyone” (18).
84 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
solidarity stops here” (67); because they do not see the colonized as one of
them nor do they have the desire to be one with the colonizer. Moreover,
denial of the colonizing gaze leads them to rationalize their judgments of the
colonized and their detachment from their struggle for liberation.
How can one deny that they are under-developed, that their customs
are oddly changeable and their culture outdates? Oh, he [she] hastens to
reply, those defects are not attributable to the colonized but to decades of
colonization which galvanized their history … before colonization, weren’t
the colonized already backward? [And even when] he [she] has complete
faith in the genius of the people, all people … the fact remains, however,
that he [she] admits to a fundamental difference between the colonized and
himself [herself]. (68–69)
the colonial context and its impact on the colonized. He points to the manner
in which the conflict between home and school culture creates a permanent
duality in the colonized adolescent. With respect to language, literacy in the
colonizer’s language similarly results in a linguistic dualism, given that the
mother tongue is not permitted to influence the larger spheres of power—
making the colonized foreigners on our own land.
Memmi engages different aspects of the colonized, which although useful
to understanding the cultural politics of colonialism, can at times fall into an
essentialized portrayal, where greater dialectical engagement with issues of
human agency and more open interpretations of human oppression might be
useful. This may exemplify, where Memmi’s classical lens can inadvertently
betray his moral intentions, in ways that reify both the colonized and colonizer
into inescapable bondage. This too may be why he offers only “two answers to
the colonized” (163), by which escape from this colonial bondage is possible. The
first is to become like the colonizer, which he argues is bankrupt; and the second
is revolt, which he sees as the only logical step in the undoing of the colonial
situation. While “the two historically possible solutions are tried in succession
or simultaneously” (144), Memmi argues that it is only with abandonment of
assimilation that recovery of self and of autonomous dignity can be achieved.
63
About this point, Sharpley-Whiting (1998) notes in her book, Frantz Fanon: Conflicts and Feminisms,
that “Black Skin, White Masks is at once a clinical study and an experimental narrative” (11).
86 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
context. As Fanon’s work develops, his Western clinical training gives way
to his revolutionary commitments, which intensify within both his political
activities and philosophical interpretations. Memmi, on the other hand, retains
his traditional orientation as philosopher64 and novelist, whose sensibilities
are more akin to the existentialist influences of Jean-Paul Sartre and Albert
Camus. Moreover, it can be said that Fanon, as Freire, assumes a posture more
akin to epistemologies of the South (Santos 2014).
Henri Bergson
Henri Bergson was considered one of the most influential French philosophers
of the early twentieth century. Although hugely popular in his time, his work
was eclipsed after the Second World War by phenomenologists who built on his
writings, yet received greater acclaim for his ideas. Bergson’s epistemological
claims—tied to the belief that “through intuition … we probe reality—deform
it—though for practical purposes” (Gunter 1995: 379)—have made important
contributions to our contemporary philosophy of education. Bergson engages
64
Memmi, on the other hand, seems to have remained more staunchly rooted in his classical
perspective, to the extent that some scholars argue that Memmi has done an “about-face” in his last
book, Decolonization and the Decolonized (Lieberman 2007). Nevertheless, many critical scholars
continue to view Memmi’s early writings as significant and salient to the continuing anticolonial
debate.
65
Freire does not mention the writings of Croatian-Austrian author, Ivan Illich, in Pedagogy of the
Oppressed. However, as both a radical Catholic priest living many years in Mexico and an acerbic
critic of traditional schooling (Illich 1971), Freire and Illich’s paths crossed over the years and their
ideas have been engaged simultaneously in critiques and discussions of education. For examples see:
Kahn (2010); Kahn and Kellner (2007); Rosiska and Domonice (1974).
Intellectual History 87
the reality of duration (process), where “things flow, are internal to one another,
and exhibit unpredictable creativity” (379), along with its interaction (dialectic)
of intuition and intelligence (Gunter 1995). In Bergson’s writings on education,
he protests the transmission of “dead ideas” and argues that education should
never sacrifice the vitality and reflectiveness of intuition to the transmission of
reified knowledge that is divorced of reflection and connection to the world.
Important to Bergson’s philosophy are his distinctive treatment of the
movement of time and his methodology of intuitionism that led him to
posit a method of multiplicity, in which he recognized the epistemological
disassociation, disharmony, differentiation, and divergences at work in the
construction of knowledge (Mullarkey 1995), in an effort to bring together
elements of heterogeneity and continuity, which he argued were inherently at
work in all phenomena. Many have considered Bergson’s notion of multiplicity
as a revolutionary concept in that it inherently supports efforts in education to
reconceptualize a pluralistic and diverse community.
Moreover,
John Dewey
American philosopher and educator, John Dewey, often referred to as the father
of the progressive education movement, has influenced educators concerned
with advancing democratic ideals. During the early 1900s, Dewey sought to
88 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
guides social interactions. Hence, for Dewey, our experience of the world
is constituted by our interrelationship with it, a relationship that must be
anchored to practical significance.
Dewey’s examination of societal, ethics, and aesthetics sought to expand on
the significance of community and the purpose of education in a democratic
society. His views of education are tied to three fundamental tenets for
teaching practice, including: (1) the idea that education had to engage with
the larger social environment; (2) that reflection must be at the heart of all
teaching; and (3) that students need consistent opportunities to interact freely
with their environment, in the process of knowledge construction. As such,
Dewey attempted “to link the notion of individual and social (cooperative)
intelligence with the discourse of democracy and freedom” (McLaren 1989:
199). Dewey also brought to educational discussions of his time a new language
of possibility, which challenged historical determinism, binary separations
between knower and the world, reinforced the social agency of the teacher
and student, and linked education to the possibilities of social change (Darder,
Torres, and Baltodano 2017).
As such, Dewey (1916) saw moral and social questions in education as
guiding human actions toward socially defined ends—democratic ends that in
practical and concrete ways would result in productive and satisfying outcomes
for both individuals and society. Hence, in contrast to an undesirable society,
“which internally and externally sets up barriers for free intercourse and
communication of experience,” for Dewey, an ideal democratic society
Pierre Furter
Moving forward
From these pages I hope at least the following will endure: my trust in the
people, and my faith in men and women, and in the creation of a world in
which it will be easier to love.
—Paulo Freire
In this chapter, each of the four chapters of Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
are summarized by way of a dialogical discussion1 with the major themes that
inform the composition of each chapter. The organization of each chapter
summary also reflects my pedagogical sensibilities, influenced by four decades
of interacting with the text. The rationale for this dialogical approach is that,
although Freire engages with notions of oppression and, thus, the need for
a pedagogy of the oppressed repeatedly throughout the entire volume, each
chapter is sharply defined by a focused set of themes, which Freire articulates
in juxtaposition to the overall purpose of his larger political project—namely
the creation of a world grounded in an ethics of social and material liberation.
In summary, the focus of Chapter 1 is squarely placed on assisting the
reader to understand the necessity for a pedagogy of the oppressed, given the
conditions of social and material oppression that prevail in the society and its
impact upon subaltern populations. In Chapter 2, the focus is on the concept
of banking education as an instrument of oppression, which Freire counters by
1
Given the dialogical approach that I have used for the chapter-by-chapter discussions of the major
themes, all italicized words and phrases in this chapter are from Pedagogy of the Oppressed as they
appear in the chapter under examination. Although this approach deviates from the standard APA
format used in the earlier chapters, of this book, this stylistic devise permits Freire’s voice to remain
active and present throughout my direct engagement with his work. In essence, this approach is in
sync with Freire’s pedagogy of the oppressed.
94 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
__________________________________
Chapter 1
In the first chapter of the book, Freire contextualizes the need for a pedagogy
of the oppressed by engaging the historical and social conditions under which
the oppressed exist, and juxtaposing these condition with the ruling class.
Freire begins to carefully lay out the specifics of what he terms the oppressor-
oppressed contradiction and how he theorizes the possibilities for engaging and
transforming this contradiction—a contradiction anchored within particular
attitudes, relationships, practices, and dynamics of oppression, perpetuated
within the unjust structures of capitalist society. As his discussion unfolds,
Freire makes it clear that liberation is neither a gift that can be bestowed upon
others nor is it solely an individual pursuit. Rather, he argues, liberation is
the outcome of collective social struggle, which must be carried out through
a coherent commitment to a political project, in the interest of our humanity
and the authentic democratization of society.
Freire begins his seminal work with the problem of humanization, which
he regards as an inescapable concern of those committed to a just world.
However, key to his conceptualization of humanization, as both a pedagogical
and political imperative, is also the manner in which this concern can lead
us, conversely, toward recognition of dehumanization. Here, Freire does not
essentialize either pole of the dialectical relationship between humanization
and dehumanization, in that he argues that both are possibilities in the
context of history and our human unfinishedness. What is particularly
striking here is that Freire, in no uncertain terms, sets down one of his most
important assumptions—an assumption clearly linked to his existential,
phenomenological, and Marxist humanist formation—humanization as the
people’s vocation.
Although Freire is well aware of the manner in which this vocation is
constantly negated and maligned, in concert with Marcuse, he affirms the
negation of the negation. That is to say, that although it is true that this
vocation is often negated by the injustices and violence of the oppressive
order, it is also reasserted by our yearning for freedom and the struggles
waged by the oppressed to recover our dignity and negate our alienation
and disaffiliation as subjects of history and citizens of the world. Freire,
however, does not only see this struggle as an existential concern but also
one that is directly linked to social and material conditions that require the
emancipation of labor, the overcoming of our alienation, and the affirmation
of our humanity. Nevertheless, for Freire, this historical task of the oppressed
is not solely about our liberation but also the liberation of the oppressors as
well. This is a point that often creates some confusion for new readers, in
that it is read through the linear and dichotomous lens of Western positivist
thinking. However, Freire signals here the dialectical relationship between
oppressors and oppressed. So, if one side of this relationship shifts, then so
will the other. Freire’s Marxist view of totality is clearly at work, in that when
he speaks of liberation he is speaking of the totality of the human condition
that encompasses oppressors and oppressed. As such, there is no way the
96 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
oppressed can truly be liberated, without also the oppressors being liberated
in the process.
For Freire, dehumanization is the direct result of the injustice and violence
perpetrated by the dominant class—a phenomenon that distorts the humanity
of both, oppressed and oppressors. The culture of hegemony normalizes and
reifies the unjust hierarchy of the ruling class, as asserted by Gramsci and
other critical theorists, while social and material forms of manipulation and
repression uphold its one-dimensionality. Accordingly, asymmetrical relations
of power are rendered common sense and serve to reinforce adherence to
and reproduction of social and material domination. The educational system,
according to Freire, becomes an instrument of dehumanization in that the self-
determination and empowerment of students from oppressed communities is
systematically thwarted.
Freire thereby speaks to the difficulties faced in the struggle for liberation,
given that those in power are seldom motivated to radically alter conditions of
inequality that benefit them; while those who suffer the concrete consequence
of oppression are far more inclined to do so. Hence, Freire maintains that
the oppressor, who is himself dehumanized because he dehumanizes others, is
unable to lead this struggle. The immorality of unjust power is insufficiently
suited for the task. In contrast, Freire notes, it is through the power generated
by the oppressed, who recognize and assert the need for change, that an
authentic struggle for liberation can be forged; and, in so doing, the oppressor
is compelled to enter into a new relationship.
It is for this reason that Freire links critical thought directly to the pursuit
of our humanity, in that our capacity to think critically is a vital precursor to
the kind of social action necessary for overcoming, as Althusser argues, false
ideologies of oppression that have become interpellated across society. Through
the awakening of critical awareness, Freire contends, the oppressed can come
to perceive the causes for injustice and, in so doing, generate social action that
will create a liberating situation from which our humanity can freely unfold. It
is precisely through our persistent critical engagement with the dehumanizing
conditions we face, that our fixation with the culture of hegemony is shattered
and new possibilities for humanizing power relations can emerge. This idea is
essential for readers to grasp, in that Freire, in concert with staunch critics of
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 97
Dependency: The more that the oppressed internalize the attitudes and ways
of the oppressor, the more estranged we become from self, from one another,
and the world. Hence the lived histories, wisdom, and knowledges of the
oppressed become submerged in the consciousness of the oppressor, where the
inauthentic worldview that drives our objectification and subjugation produces
a state of ambiguity and disempowerment. Simultaneously, there often exists
a belief in the invulnerability of the oppressor—a belief that immobilizes and
thwarts our self-determination and social agency. Freire suggests, the deeper
our submersion into the oppressor worldview, the more likely the oppressed
98 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
will experience confusion, doubt, fear, or guilt, if action is initiated that counters
the status quo. This emotional dependence and adherence to the oppressor
worldview generates what Fromm terms necrophilic behavior—action that
extinguishes life. Moreover, this colonizing dependency can manifest as the
fear of freedom, which Freire argues must be acknowledged and engaged in the
liberatory formation of oppressed communities, in ways that do not create still
greater dependence.
Fatalism: Freire laments the manner in which fatalism has become a trait of
national character, within oppressive societies. He points to the manner in
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 99
False Generosity: False generosity is another key Freirean idea often cited
in the literature. Freire introduces the concept early in the chapter, when he
admonishes those who would attempt to “soften” the power of the oppressor in
deference to the weakness of the oppressed. Freire views the culture of hegemony
in society as a permanent wellspring of false generosity, in that its charitable
practices on behalf of the oppressed generally whitewash both the impact of
poverty and the underlying deficit views, which blame the people for their
own oppression. Employing Fromm’s notion of necrophilia, Freire contends
that false generosity actually fosters the perpetuation of death, despair, and
poverty among the oppressed, given the necessity of an oppressed mass within
capitalist society.
For Freire, false generosity constitutes then a form of violence, in that it
interferes with the individual’s ontological and historical vocation to be more
fully human—and, so, deepens the dependency of the oppressed on the
“benevolence” of the oppressor. False generosity shrouds the lovelessness of
the oppressor who, Freire contends, sustain welfare programs for the people,
as long as these do not tamper with the unjust system of labor, which assures
power and privilege remains in the hands of a few. To drive this point home,
Freire contrasts false generosity with true generosity, which fundamentally
emerges from the pursuit of freedom. Within the dynamics of a true
generosity, the oppressed are never expected to humiliate and erode their
dignity, in supplication for that which should rightly be ours. In contrast, a
true generosity is founded upon a loving relationship of communion with the
people that nourishes respect, freedom, and self-determination.
In direct contrast, the beneficiaries of an unjust system of domination
and exploitation generally refuse to acknowledge that to keep women and
men socially, politically, and materially impoverished, despite their so-
called charity, is to interfere with the capacity of the oppressed to be fully
human. Hence, the oppressors do not perceive their monopoly on having
more as a privilege, which dehumanizes others and themselves. Instead, they
see their wealth as an inalienable right, which they’ve earned through their
wherewithal and intelligence. Meanwhile the have-nots are seen through a
victim-blaming lens, where they are deemed incompetent and lazy, and worst
of all is their unjustifiable ingratitude towards the “generous gestures” of the
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 101
dominant class. It is precisely the violence of this alienating dynamic and its
impact on the oppressed that solidifies and intensifies the tragic dilemma of
the oppressed.
2
Often students struggle to understand the difference between dialectic and dialogic. In a dialectic
process, describing the interaction and resolution between multiple paradigms or ideologies,
generally, one presumed solution establishes primacy over the others. The goal of a dialectic process
is to merge point and counterpoint (thesis and antithesis) into a compromise or other state of
agreement via conflict and tension (synthesis). It encompasses then a synthesis that evolves from
the opposition between thesis and antithesis. In a dialogic process, various approaches coexist and
are comparatively existential and relativistic in their interaction. Here, each ideology can hold more
salience in particular circumstances. Changes can be made within these ideologies if a strategy
does not have the desired effect. Whereas dialogic processes, especially those involved with regular
spoken conversation, involve a type of listening that attends to the implicit intentions behind the
speaker’s actual words. Unlike a dialectic process, dialogics often do not lead to closure and remain
unresolved. Compared to dialectics, a dialogic exchange can be less competitive, and more suitable
for facilitating cooperation. Hence, this helps to explain Freire’s preference for a dialogical approach
in a problem-posing pedagogy. See: Chapter 17 of Critical Thinking (Paul 1993).
102 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
stupid. At this end, being human is considered the domain of the privileged,
who accumulate wealth and power, in the name of productivity and progress.
However, Freire insists, those who oppress others also exist in a state of
dehumanization, hence, they too are inauthentic beings. To step out of their
duality would also require them to discover the conditions of their situation—
which can provoke guilt and suffering. More often than not, unfortunately,
this dynamic does not move the oppressor to overcome the contradiction, but
rather to better rationalize the inequalities and injustices that preserve their
domination. Here, Freire turns to both Fromm and Lukács’ arguments, in that
what tends to prevail is a reification of the oppressor-oppressed contradiction,
in that without possession of power over the oppressed, their sense of “normalcy”
is shattered.
Two Distinct Stages: Freire identifies two major stages in the pedagogy of the
oppressed. In the initial stage, the major concern is unveiling the culture of
domination, dealing with the concerns of the oppressed, and working toward
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 105
Praxis: In this chapter Freire also introduces the notion of praxis, which he links
to critical reflection and action with the people—concepts that he develops in
Chapter 2. Here, Freire asserts, at the core of a revolutionary praxis is critical
dialogue fueled, as Che Guevara contends, by love for humanity and the world.
And such dialogue begins with the concrete concerns and conditions that
emerge from and with the people. This presupposes a humanizing relationship
guided by mutual respect, love, care, trust, and commitment. In contrast to the
domesticating dynamics of oppression experienced by oppressed communities
that demand our passivity and silence, dialogue is a co-intentional and co-
creative act of human interaction focused on the transformation of the
concrete situation. Revolutionary praxis, moreover, recognizes the dynamic
nature of humanity where thoughts will change and new knowledge will be
created—knowledge from which new forms of understanding and action will
be engendered. Freire, as does Fromm, distinguishes revolutionary praxis as
biophilic—a life-affirming expression of love and solidarity with the oppressed.
As such, liberating praxis becomes raison d’etre—the underlying purpose
for existence or literally, reason for being—of the oppressed. Freire extends
this raison d’etre to revolutionary leadership, who understand liberation
implicitly as a pedagogical and political undertaking. He argues here that
revolutionary praxis, which inaugurates the historical moment of this raison
d’etre, is not feasible without the conscious participation and commitment of
106 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
the oppressed. With this in mind, Freire reminds revolutionary leaders that
their own conviction of the necessity for struggle (an indispensable dimension of
revolutionary wisdom) was not given to them by anyone else—if it is authentic.
In this manner, he reaffirms the underlying purpose of a pedagogy of the
oppressed, where teachers and students or leaders and communities exist as
historical subjects, in the fight for liberation.
On the question of liberation, Freire draws from Fromm to argue that when
the oppressed forge the fight for their freedom and humanity, they also must,
in turn, embrace their total responsibility for the struggle. This process entails
a refusal to exist as objects to be manipulated by the oppressor and, instead,
take on the struggle as fully present and committed subjects of history. It is
through this process that the oppressed unveil conditions of oppression and,
in this way, become both objects and subjects of transformative action. As our
collective criticality and political sensibilities evolve, we can more consciously
activate our participation in history, and in so doing, overcome the oppressor-
oppressed contradiction that incarcerates our humanity.
Freire argues, in order to wage the struggle for liberation, the oppressed
must recognize the reality in which we are immersed as never a fait
accompli, but a limit-situation that can be transformed. Freire maintains, it
is precisely from the vantage point of our unfinishedness—and recognition
that the oppressor cannot exist without the oppressed—that radical hope
and liberating action can ensue. Our concrete commitment to enter into
the struggle for our liberation initiates our unshackling from the oppressor-
oppressed contradiction. More important, through a revolutionary praxis of
collective struggle, the oppressed (and those who fight in solidarity at their
side) build the critical awareness necessary to, step by step, vie for a liberatory
vision of our collective human existence. Freire reminds us that at all stages
of our liberation, we must see ourselves as women and men engaged in an
ontological and historical vocation of becoming more fully human. In this
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 107
way, Freire pronounces one of the most important, yet often missed, dialectical
principles of his pedagogy: while no one liberates oneself by one’s own efforts
alone, neither is one liberated by others.
__________________________________
Chapter 2
For apart from inquiry, apart from the praxis, individuals cannot be truly
human. Knowledge emerges only through invention and re-invention,
through the restless, impatient, continuing, hopeful inquiry human beings
pursue in the world, with the world, and with each other.
—Paulo Freire
Banking education
The “humanism” of the banking approach masks the effort to turn women and
men into automatons—the very negation of their ontological vocation to be
more fully human.
3
The term neoliberal subjects is used here to refer to individuals from the oppressed class who become
educated or “accomplished” within the status quo and, hence, affiliate themselves with the oppressor
class and participate in the social control and management of oppressed populations.
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 109
reduced to words [that] are emptied of their concreteness and become a hollow,
alienated, and alienating verbosity—hence, lifeless and powerless to transform
conditions of human suffering. Also important to understand is that the means
used are not important, in that when human beings are fundamentally denied
the right to decide about our own lives, we are objectified—a phenomenon
tied to the epistemology (theory) and methodology (practice) of oppression
in combination that informs banking education. This results in an overarching
pedagogical expectation that students memorize mechanically the narrated
content, becoming receptacles’ to be “filled” by the teacher.
4
The reader should recall here the earlier discussion of the oppressor-oppressed contradiction, in the
immediately preceding discussion of Chapter 1.
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 111
classroom. In essence, students are regarded as clean slates, whose cultural and
linguistic histories and everyday lived experiences mean little in a mechanized
culture of teaching and learning, built on abstracted, fragmented, and
instrumentalized views of knowledge. Here, students are allowed to act only in
the interest of receiving, filing, and storing the deposits. Anything outside this
assimilative epistemology is perceived erroneous, irrelevant, misguided, or an
obstruction to the student’s academic or material achievement. Accordingly,
students’ creativity and imagination are sidelined by an approach that seldom
proposes that they think critically about the concrete conditions of their own
lives. As a consequence, the oppressor-oppressed contradiction—enacted
through verticalization of the teacher-student relationship and inherent in
the deposits themselves—is preserved. The outcome is a system of educational
attitudes and values that preserve and fortify the contradiction, mirroring the
oppressive society as a whole.5
However, Freire contends that neither the domestication of consciousness
nor the teacher-student contradiction comprise essentialized forms of
existence from which there is no exit. In fact, he argues that the anguish and
tensions generated by the teacher-student contradiction, for example, can
invoke students who were formally passive to resist and reject against their
dehumanization. Nevertheless, Freire reminds readers that, as historical beings,
when the organic movement of students’ ideas and participation is stymied in
the classroom, this constitutes a violation of their humanity. Here, he confirms
that the oppression of human beings cannot be understood apart from the
dehumanizing conditions that engender alienation. Moreover, Freire suggests,
in line with Fanon, that when students resist or push against this violation it is
5
Here, Freire connects the following attitudes and values with the mirroring of oppressive society:
a. the teacher teaches and the students are taught;
b. the teacher knows everything and the students know nothing;
c. the teacher thinks and the students are thought about;
d. the teacher talks and the students listen—meekly;
e. the teacher disciplines and the students are disciplined;
f. the teacher chooses and enforces his or her choice, and the students comply;
g. the teacher acts and the students have the illusion of acting through the action of the teacher;
h. the teacher chooses the program content, and the students (who were not consulted) adapt to it;
i. the teacher confuses the authority of knowledge with his or her own professional authority, which
she and he sets in opposition to the freedom of the students;
j. the teacher is the subject of the learning process, while the pupils are mere objects.
112 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Dialogue
A problem-posing pedagogy acknowledges the meaningfulness of human
communication and communal relations in our lives. For this reason, Freire
considers pedagogical dialogue as indispensable to developing relationships of
cooperation and collective action within schools and society. He argues that a
problem-posing educational approach provides students with the foundation
for cultivating liberatory sensibilities and establishing the solidarity necessary
for social transformation. Hence, dialogue is essential to a revolutionary
praxis, in that without it students are left at the mercy of a brutal domesticating
worldview and a mode of production that interferes with their authentic human
existence. Through dialogue, a problem-posing pedagogy creates the conditions
for new pedagogical relations to emerge, where teachers are also students and
students are also teachers. In this liberatory dynamic, the hierarchical banking
method of the teacher, as the only one who teaches, is ruptured. Instead, the
teacher is also taught in dialogue with students, who in turn while being taught
also teach. In this way, a sense of joint responsibility for a process in which all
grow is established and nurtured between teacher and students.
It goes without saying, that for Freire, dialogue as a communal activity seeks
to establish a democratic process of engagement that can ultimately lead to
transformative action and greater critical awareness of the concrete conditions
that impact our lives. The dialogical relationship, therefore, precludes
dichotomies between teacher-student and student-teacher. The cultural and
historical knowledges that both teachers and students bring must be allowed
to intermingle organically with texts and materials (cognizable objects). In this
liberatory environment of knowledge production, teachers and students are
always both cognitive and narrative subjects involved in study. An important
concept that Freire raises here, influenced by Marxism, is our need to overcome
a view of both knowledge and cognizable objects as private property. Instead,
the knowledge, texts, and materials introduced become objects of reflection by
teachers and students alike, brushed against the realities of our lived histories.
This organic dialogical process of knowledge construction provides the
pedagogical space for educators to, time and again, rethink our reflections,
within the reflections and contributions our students make to the dialogue.
Hence, passivity of students as docile listeners is overcome, as they become
114 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Praxis revisited
With a dialogical enactment of praxis, a problem-posing pedagogy creates
the space, place, and time for teachers and students to discover and rethink
6
In brief, Freire is referring here to Doxa, the place where common beliefs or opinions guide human
thought.
7
Again, briefly speaking, Freire is referring here to Logos, the place where rational principles,
grounded on thoughtful reflection, guide human thought.
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 115
together the social and material contradictions that impact their world. Freire
contends that it is precisely through this critical dialogical approach that the
oppressed come to identify together actions that will support efforts to resist,
counter, and challenge oppressive conditions within schools, communities,
and society that rob our humanity. Revolutionary praxis, as an existential
human necessity, makes this possible; in that—through reflection, naming
of the world, and action—human beings come to understand ourselves
interdependently within history and within the world. And, with this
discovery, we come to know our history, our world, and ourselves as, indeed,
interrelated, living, organic beings, existing always as unfinished and in the
process of becoming. As such—no matter to what extent the situations of our
existence may conceal or limit the power of our creativity and capacity to
speak and act against injustices, we nevertheless, exist in the ever presence of
historical possibilities for transformation. It should be no surprise, then, why
Freire insists, problem-posing theory and practice take the peoples’ historicity as
the starting point of their education.
Anchored in dialectical thought, revolutionary praxis as a transforming
principle transcends the theory–practice contradiction and enhances the
pedagogical interaction of action and reflection. In the process of reflection,
Freire inspired by Husserl notes, teachers and students enhance the landscape
of their perceptions and begin to appreciate the background intuitions and
background awareness, which in the past may have been obscured by the
oppressor-oppressed contradiction. Now, praxis gives rise to new awareness
and an evolving consciousness of the self as subject of history. Similarly,
such reflection, in conjunction with action, breaks through the dichotomy
of the contradiction, in that it also brings a greater realization that practice
never exists independent of theory, because one is the foundation and
consequence of the other. Grounded, thereby, in this recognition of the ever-
present interplay of permanence and change, the oppressed engage the world
as the object of transformative action, through which liberation is forged.
Hence, Freire affirms that revolutionary praxis is the foundation for a critical
consciousness that seeks to transform oppression as an action pursuing
freedom.
116 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Conscientização
The evolution of critical consciousness or conscientização is one of
the underlying aims of a problem-posing pedagogy. Freire’s concept of
conscientização signals an understanding of critical awareness and the
formation of social consciousness as both a historical phenomenon and a
human social process, linked to our emancipatory necessity as human beings
to participate as both cognitive and narrative subjects of our destinies. It is
vital that we keep in mind that conscientização does not occur automatically,
naturally, nor should it be understood as an evolving linear phenomenon.
Instead, Freire speaks to an emancipatory consciousness that arises through
an organic process of human engagement, which requires critical pedagogical
interactions that nurture the dialectical relationship of human beings with
the world. This entails a grounded appreciation for the dialectical tension
that must be retained between the empowerment of the individual and the
collective empowerment of the people.
Whereby, banking education seeks to undermine the liberatory
consciousness of the oppressed, Freire calls for the development of a living
pedagogy that affirms life, through engendering a liberatory consciousness.
In concert, Freire reaffirms, “a deepened consciousness of [our] situation
leads people to apprehend that situation as an historical reality susceptible
of transformation.” In this way, women and men committed to liberation
create the conditions for empowerment and their mutual liberation. A
problem-posing pedagogy, through the power of embodied revolutionary
praxis, supports the intentionality of consciousness, in a way that displaces
the estrangement of alienation by ushering in a new consciousness of self
and the world. It is here that Freire makes reference to the Jasperian split—or
consciousness of consciousness—which in actuality refers to the moment when
the oppressed begin to experience the eclipse of their unconscious acceptance
of the oppressor-oppressed contradiction and become aware (or conscious)
that a new liberatory consciousness has emerged in their lives and their
relationship to the world. Hence, it is the moment within revolutionary praxis
when the oppressed become conscious of the revitalization of their humanity—a
revitalization rooted in the practice of freedom, where fatalism gives way to
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 117
supports our conscious emergence from the contradictions that once ruled our
lives as colonized populations. Freire draws on Sartre to express that, within
a revolutionary praxis of education, consciousness neither precedes the world
nor follows it. Therefore, the point of departure for a liberating praxis, whether
in schools or communities, lies in the people themselves and a consciousness
that exists, steadfast, in the here and now. This practice of freedom as true
communication must also engender solidarity, in that pursuit of our humanity
cannot be a solo endeavor, but rather the praxis of the people. With all this in
mind, Freire warns: In the revolutionary process, the leaders cannot utilize the
banking method as an interim measure, justified on grounds of expediency, with
the intention of later behaving in a genuinely revolutionary fashion. They must
be revolutionary—that is to say dialogical—from the onset.
1. How does Freire define the banking concept of education? How does the
banking educational model function as an instrument of alienation?
2. Describe what Freire means by the teacher-student contradiction. How
might you envision teachers and students as revolutionary partners in the
educational process?
3. How does Freire define problem-posing education? How can teachers
integrate a problem-posing approach in the classroom? What obstacles
might they face?
4. How do you understand the development of critical consciousness
(conscientização) and what is its pedagogical role in the practice of
freedom?
__________________________________
Chapter 3
The word
Human existence cannot be silent, nor can it be nourished by false words, but
only by true words, with which men and women transform the world.
Freire begins the discussion of dialogics with the concept of the word, which
he considers to be the essence of dialogue itself. Engaging its constitutive
elements, Freire argues, the word becomes truly the means by which dialogue
is possible. Here, as he does in his discussion of praxis, he insists that if the
radical interaction of reflection and action is sacrificed, an authentic or true
word and, therefore, praxis is nullified. This is essential to understand, in that
Freire conceives of true word as a transformative requirement. Inherent, is the
idea that, on one hand, with absence of action there is no transformation; and,
120 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
on the other, action without dialogue negates true praxis. Of course, the reason
for this is that Freire equates the true word to be the underlying work of praxis.
Moreover, Freire upholds both an egalitarian and communal view of the word;
insisting, the word is not the privilege of [the] few, but the right of everyone. No
one can say a true word alone nor can they say it for another.
Freire identifies an inauthentic word as one that perpetuates alienation
and the oppressive dichotomy of the subject-object contradiction. This
occurs when the word is stripped of any possibility of transformative action,
since the reflection required to produce the true word is distorted. He links
the lifelessness of the inauthentic word with an alienating verbalism, where
the empty word has no power to denounce the world and therefore unable
to support the action required for transformation. Similarly, he speaks of
an activism, where action occurs for action’s sake, negating true praxis and
making dialogue impossible. Hence, any dichotomy of reflection and action
leads to expressions of inauthentic existence, reinforcing the culture of silence
produced by the oppressor-oppressed contradiction.
Culture of silence
To glorify democracy and to silence the people is a farce;
to discourse on humanism and to negate people is a lie.
Within Freirean thought, the means by which women and men name our
world is through our participation in critical dialogue. In this way, naming the
world opens up the transformative possibilities for unveiling the oppressive
conditions of our existence and, by so doing, renaming our world. Freire rightly
asserts that we have not been built in silence; but, rather, through dialogical
action and reflection, we imbue our word and our labor with the essence
of our existence. Here, Freire employs Pierre Furter’s notion of authentic
human existence: that which permits the emergence of the awareness of our full
humanity, as a condition and as an obligation, as a situation and as a project.
It is, therefore, through the dialogical emergence of awareness that the true
word is spoken and possibilities for humanizing praxis manifest. It is with this
in mind that Freire reaffirms: Dialogue is thus an existential necessity. Critical
dialogue, as the means for purposeful reflection and action with one another
and the world, must be understood as a communal undertaking. It cannot be
reduced to one person “depositing” ideas in another, nor can it become a simple
exchange of ideas to be “consumed.” Freire also distinguishes dialogue from
polemic arguments or hostile debates, informed by an authoritarian culture
of conquest—where epistemologically only certain truths are given legitimacy,
while others are marginalized, ignored, or rendered invisible.
Instead, dialogue provides ample opportunity for naming the world, as
mediated and expressed by the oppressed, to be addressed as legitimate and
122 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Horizontal relationships
Founding itself upon love, humility, and faith, dialogue becomes a horizontal
relationship of which mutual trust between the dialoguers is the logical
consequence.
humanity reveals what Freire terms the pathology of love, where a destructive
sadist-masochist contradiction emerges. In direct contrast, dialogue founded
in love, generates the courage, responsibility, and discipline of women and
men committed to the struggle for liberation. However, Freire warns, as an act
of bravery, love cannot be sentimental; as an act of freedom, it must not serve as
a pretext for manipulation. It must generate other acts of freedom; otherwise, it
is not love. Hence, it is only through the resolution of the oppressor-oppressed
contradiction, that we restore love and defy the lovelessness of asymmetrical
relations of power that defy our humanity.
Humility: Freire makes the case for the manner in which the unjust
verticalization of human relationships results in false humility, authoritarian
fixations, and disabling alienation—for both the oppressor and the oppressed.
Arrogance and paternalism, fueled by a sense of superiority and supremacy
are features of oppressive relationships that interfere with open human
expression and the people’s right to recreate our world. In the process, banking
educators, researchers, and leaders who lack humility enter into necrophilic
encounters, obstructing the possibility of any partnership in the naming of the
world. Hence, Freire asserts, men and women who lack humility and cannot
acknowledge [themselves] to be as mortal as everyone else, still [have] a long way
to go before [they] can reach the point of encounter.
Hope: Foremost for Freire is the recognition that the struggle for our humanity
and our liberation is impossible without hope—for without hope, fatalism
can overcome us, disintegrating our dreams and leaving us in the oppressive
zone of antidialogical existence. What Freire is signaling here is the manner
in which he conceives of hope as an existential necessity. This is so, for in
an antidialogical climate of hopelessness, it is nearly impossible to envision
our lives beyond the limit-situations that bind our humanity. Nor can hope
manifest in a context of crossing ones arms and waiting. Instead, Freire affirms,
As long as I fight, I am moved by hope; and if I fight with hope, then I can wait.
Freire suggests, our tolerance for waiting is directly linked to our capacity to
generate a sense of hope in our lives, despite the oppressive conditions that
surround us. He also links this hope to communion: Hope is rooted in [our]
incompletion; from which [we] move out in constant search—a search which can
be carried out only in communion with others.
Dialogical praxis
Only human beings are beings of praxis … only human beings are praxis.
8
Body politic refers to the people of a nation, state, or society considered collectively as an organized
group of citizens.
9
Freire’s view of animals has been contested among animal rights activists and some scholars of
indigenous knowledge. In his essay, “Toward an Animal Standpoint,” Richard Kahn refutes the
notion that “nonhuman animals are … unthinking, unfeeling, and lesser objects, instead of rational,
sentient, and equal beings” (4). Again see: Critical Pedagogy, Ecoliteracy, and Planetary Crisis (Kahn
2010) for an insightful discussion on this question.
126 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
who treat our actions and ourselves as objects of reflection. This capacity for
human reflection is what, Freire contends, distinguishes humans from animals
who are unable to separate themselves from their activity … [nor] reflect upon
it. Freire fashions here a boundary in the life space of humans and animals,
asserting only human beings are beings of praxis.
Another difference Freire asserts is the historical nature and social agency
of human beings, in that we instill the world with our creative presence by
means of transformation. In contrast, he posits animal activity as being neither
praxis nor creative transformation but, rather, an ahistorical activity of species
who are beings in themselves. Hence, humans are capable of praxis precisely
because we can be critically aware of our world and ourselves and, thus, exist
in a dialectical relationship between the determination of limits and [our] own
freedom. As such, it is through our capacity to be conscious of our autonomy
and our responsibility for decisions and actions in the world that offers human
beings the possibility of overcoming the limitations we face.
Freire maintains that true dialogue is impossible without critical thought, in
which reality is understood as process, as transformation, rather than as a static
entity. Here, critical thought is both inextricably tied to action and immersed
in the progression of time—the past, present, and future of our existence—
open to the risks of change this may involve. Hence, critical thought contrasts
with naïve thought that, wittingly or unwittingly, invests in accommodation to
the “normalized” and guaranteed space, seemingly ignorant of the injustices
reproduced. Critical thinkers, on the other hand, are committed to the change
required for our continued humanization. Freire draws on Furter’s work to
assert, “the goal will no longer be to eliminate the risks of temporality by clutching
to guaranteed space, but rather to temporalize space” in ways that permit the
world to be revealed.
Dialogical praxis generates the basic conditions for the development
of critical thought, through opening the field for engaging the limitations
that surround our lives. Without true dialogue neither communication
nor education can generate critical thinkers. It is only through dynamic
engagement of the world, by way of critical thought, that we unveil reality,
unmask the myths that obscure oppression, and continue to generate and
regenerate our critical faculties. In this way, Freire contends, a critical analysis
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 127
Methodology of conscientização
When carried out with a methodology of conscientização the investigation …
introduces or begins to introduce women and men to a critical form of thinking
about their world.
A central feature of the second part of this chapter is Freire’s discussion of his
liberatory methodology. Here, the pragmatic dimension of Freire’s ideas begin
to crystallize in his efforts to articulate the aspects of a methodology embodied
through the concrete, existential, present situation of real people. He provides
an example of critical guidelines for the emergence of generative themes and
the investigative stages that result in a liberatory pedagogical approach to
community research with the oppressed, whether students in a classroom or
people in community contexts. In contrast to banking approaches that reify
the oppressed as objects of study, the lived histories of the oppressed are the
starting point of his work in communities. Anything short of this, Freire notes,
constitutes false generosity—a vertical structure of study that perpetuates the
domestication and disempowerment of students and communities. About
this Freire contends: One cannot expect positive results from an educational or
political action program which fails to respect the particular view of the world
held by the people. Such a program constitutes cultural invasion, good intentions
notwithstanding.
Freire’s methodology of conscientização affirms the various dimensions
of people’s culture as absolutely significant to informing both a humanizing
educational praxis and a critical investigation into people’s lives and their
actual needs. As an empowering and liberating pedagogical force, Freire
128 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Generative themes
The concept of generative themes—which is neither arbitrary invention nor
hypothesis to be proved—is at the heart of Freire’s methodological approach.
He utilizes the term generative to signify themes that hold the possibility of
constantly unfolding and recreating into new and different themes, given that
the historical conditions associated with themes are ever changing. This also
means actions connected to particular generative themes will also change, as
the new untested feasibly is identified. This organic and dialogical quality of
generative themes merits some focus here. For if the methodology of study
follows the hierarchical ethos of traditional research, there is no need to
determine the nature of the theme, instead the emphasis will be placed on
proving whether the theme is actually legitimate or not. In this supposedly
neutral scientific pursuit of verifying the objective legitimacy of the theme—
which is usually predicated on the prescribed criteria of the dominant class—
its richness, its significance, its plurality, its transformations, and its historical
composition are sacrificed.
In direct contrast, Freire proposes a methodology that is fundamentally
dialogical, providing ample opportunity for the people to identify meaningful
themes, through their participation as subjects of their own study. This
dialogical approach cultivates and nurtures critical awareness about the
meanings people attach to the themes generated. Freire also asserts that the
very nature of the generative theme is best understood through one’s own
existential experience and critical reflection on the relationship between men
and women with one another and our relationship with the world. Hence,
the more actively engaged the people are in exploring their thematics, the
more profoundly aware they become of their situation and their ability to
take possession of that reality. In this way, their growing critical awareness or
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 129
Limit-situations
Freire draws on Jaspers’ idea of limit-situations as de-essentialized by Vieira Pinto,
who provides a more optimistic reading of the concept. In this sense, a limit-
situation is not an impassible boundary of which there is no escape, but rather
the frontier, which separates being from being more. Hence, limit-situations point
to those human situations that bind our humanity and, thus, become obstacles
or challenges to dialogical praxis. Inherent to limit-situations are asymmetrical
relations of power, where the dominant class benefits from perpetuating the
limiting conditions. To overcome, for example, our dehumanization, which
assumes the end of dehumanization, we have to overcome the limit-situation
that converts human beings into things. To enter into a liberating praxis requires
us to engage more critically with the dialectics of our existence as subjects and
objects of our lives. In this way, we can come to reflect in new ways, with greater
clarity about our individual and collective actions, as well as begin to accept
greater responsibility for our decisions. In turn, we begin to overcome the limit-
situations that demean and oppress our lives.
Freire posits dialectically that themes both contain and are contained
in limit-situations. However, often limit-situations are not clearly seen nor
understood; corresponding responses—as historical action—will then fail not
only to transcend the situation but to see the untested feasibility that could
overcome the contradiction. Nevertheless, Freire suggests that through critical
engagement, a limit-situation’s true nature as concrete historical dimension
of a given reality can be unveiled. In so doing, the oppressive ideology that
normalizes perpetuation of the limit-situation is disrupted by limit-acts—
acts carried out by the oppressed to overcome the limitation. To transform
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 131
Untested feasibility
Dialogical praxis serves as a pedagogical and political means by which the
oppressed come to reflect critically on the conditions that limit our freedom,
in order to discover the unjust conditions that engender limitations, as well
as the untested feasibility. By untested feasibility, Freire is referring to those
human possibilities that lie just beyond the limit-situations, which often
remain obscured. Freire engages Goldmann’s idea of potential consciousness
and Nicolai’s view of perceived/unperceived practicable solutions to bring
complexity to his discussion of untested feasibility and its relationship to
consciousness. He reminds us that limit-situations imply that there exist those
who are served by the limitations and those who are negated and curbed by
them. Fatalism and other responses to alienation interfere with our capacity to
perceive the untested feasibility.
On the other hand, when limit-situations are perceived as the frontier
between being and being more human, the oppressed begin to increasingly
direct their actions toward the untested feasibility implicit in their perception.
Freire does warn though that those served by the limit-situation will perceive
the untested feasibility as a threat to the status quo and, therefore, block
dialogical praxis. It is, however, through problem-posing investigation that
the people engage conditions that limit their freedom and move more intently
toward bringing an untested feasibility of liberation to the present.
Problem-posing investigation
Even when people may be struggling with what may seem as superstitious or
naïve perceptions of a situation, Freire maintains that deep faith in people’s
capacity to rethink the assumptions that inform their situation in community
must be at the core of thematic investigation, in that how people express their
situation at any given moment in time is inseparable from the larger social and
material context in which they must survive. Freire contends, Human beings
are because they are in a situation. And they will be more the more they not
only critically reflect upon their existence but critically act upon it. The stages
of investigation encompass a dialogical relationship between the investigative
team and community people participating in the study. Freire warns that
the process of investigation must never become mechanized, abstracted, or
reductive, but rather retain its dialogical sensibilities, without losing sight of
the totality from which the meaningful thematics of the people emerge. This
also entails a liberatory relationship in which both investigators and the people
work together in becoming jointly educated about the situations that impact
the life of the community.
them, posing as problems both the codified existential situation, as well as their
own responses. These discussions are recorded to ensure that the investigative
team can return to them for subsequent analysis. Freire also notes that it is
at this stage in which the cathartic force of the methodology may surface, as
participants express emotions, sentiments, and opinions related to their lives,
which they would not otherwise share outside their home. As participants
express their connection between self and their existential situation, Freire
advocates for the conscientização of the situation, a process that prepares
participants for actions that can counter obstacles to their humanity.
Revolutionary leadership
Revolutionary leaders do not go to the people in order to bring them a message
of “salvation,” but in order to come to know through dialogue with them both
their objective situation and their awareness of that situation.
1. What does Freire mean by the true or authentic word? How does the
culture of silence prevent the oppressed from naming the world?
2. For Freire, what constitutes humanizing dialogue? What are the essential
components of dialogical praxis?
3. Freire maintains that through horizontal relationships, the oppressor-
oppressed contradiction can be resolved. What does he mean by this and
what are the indispensable qualities of horizontal relationships?
4. What is the underlying purpose of a methodology of conscientização?
Describe, in particular, the idea of generative themes and limit-situations,
as well as the four stages of Freire’s thematic investigation.
__________________________________
Chapter 4
Throughout the book, Freire suggests, in subtle and more direct ways, that
pedagogy of the oppressed is, in fact, a pedagogy of revolutionary change and
societal transformation that must be carried out by the people. In this chapter,
he unapologetically asserts the revolutionary nature of cultural action, squarely
examining the differences between antidialogical and dialogical approaches.
Freire argues that antidialogical conditions, given their alienating purpose,
serve as instruments of oppression; while a dialogical praxis, on the other hand,
is enacted through a pedagogical and political commitment to the liberation
of the oppressed. He expounds on the characteristics of antidialogical action,
which enact a pedagogy and politics of conquest, divide and rule, manipulation,
and cultural invasion. In direct contrast, he points to the characteristics of
dialogical action, which enact radical cultural expressions of cooperation,
unity, organization, and cultural synthesis. In a variety of ways, this last
chapter serves as a synthesis of the book, in that it revisits and weaves together
Major Themes, Chapter-by-Chapter 139
many of the central themes Freire has explored in the previous chapters, in
ways that speak to authentic revolutionary leadership, whether it be within
schools or communities. Freire, in particular, draws on Gramscian ideas of
both moral leadership and the formation of organic intellectuals, to engage
with the complexities of political authority and communal participation, both
deeply essential to a revolutionary praxis of cultural action.
Freire reaffirms the central thesis of his work: human beings are beings of
praxis; and, as such, authentic humanizing activity is the outcome of theory and
practice—a praxis that is the outcome of the dialectical relationship between
self, others, and the world. He posits the need for a dialogical relationship of
leadership between those who are designated as leaders and the people who
must participate as central figures in the process of transformation. Freire also
undertakes a critique of hegemonic or antidialogical leadership founded on a
banking concept, where leaders are the narrators and subjects of history, while
the people are expected to merely serve as docile objects of a prescribed political
agenda in which they are estranged from all decision-making. For Freire, this
does not constitute true revolutionary leadership but rather the reformulation
of the old oppressor-oppressed contradiction, with the leaders as its “thinkers”
and the oppressed as mere “doers.” Freire again maintains that revolutionary
leaders, who invalidate the praxis of the people, inherently invalidate the
legitimacy of their own praxis—a false, dichotomous, and oppressive praxis
that imitates the dominant elites. In doing so, antidialogical revolutionary
leadership is reduced to a revolution without the people, [who are now] drawn
into the process by the same methods and procedures used to oppress them.
Freire further warns against a mechanistic view of reality, where there
exists little awareness of the manner in which concrete situations impact
consciousness and, therefore, how consciousness impacts our world. Freire
notes the fallacy of a mechanistic view of transformation, where leaders
ignore the need to problematize false consciousness, convinced that slogans
and directives from an elite leadership is sufficient to changing historical
conditions. Freire returns here to Marx and the historicity of humanity,
asserting that there is no history without human beings and no human beings
without history. Hence, to deny people the right to participate in history begets
conditions of oppression, irrespective of rhetorical intentions.
140 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
In concert with Lenin, Freire adamantly insists that a true commitment to the
people requires a revolutionary theory of cultural action, where the dialogical
praxis of leaders and the people—in solidarity—engage critically the structures
to be transformed. This necessitates authentic community relationships of
struggle rooted in authentic dialogue, where revolutionary praxis emerges from
a shared commitment and emancipatory vision, where leaders do not reify the
oppressed as their possession. Freire calls for revolutionary leaders to incarnate a
genuine humanism, grounded in principles of a dialogical revolutionary process,
where leaders embody both a commitment and revolutionary solidarity with
people as comrades in the struggle for our liberation.
contends, there do not exist oppressive conditions that are not, at their root,
also antidialogical; just as there is no antidialogue in which the oppressors do
not untiringly dedicate themselves to the constant conquest of the oppressed.
Freire goes on to discuss further what he means by antidialogical actions by
presenting major pillars that bolster the structures of antidialogical action—
namely, conquest, divide and rule, manipulation, and cultural invasion.
Divide and Rule signals intolerance for the unification of the oppressed, an act
perceived as a serious threat to the dominant class. As a minority in number,
the ruling class deems the struggle for liberation as a potential danger. In an
effort to disrupt and silence the voices and participation of the people, the
oppressor utilizes a variety of hegemonic strategies to isolate and alienate the
10
A few other myths Freire includes:
that the dominant elites, “recognizing their duties,” promote the advancement of the people, so
that the people in a gesture of gratitude should accept the words of the elites and be conformed to
them; the myth that rebellion is a sin against God; the myth of private property as fundamental to
personal human development (so long as oppressors are the only true human beings); the myth
of the industriousness of the oppressors and the laziness and dishonesty of the oppressed.
144 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
society survive in the new. And they will then be able to free themselves more
rapidly of these specters …
then that Freire ends his seminal tome by asserting: Only in the encounter of
the people with revolutionary leaders—in their communion, in their praxis—can
this theory be built.
The spirit that guides this book is very much connected with a desire to
provide insights into Paulo Freire: the educational philosopher, international
dignitary, revolutionary humanist, teacher, comrade, and friend. Underlying
this commitment is also the realization that we make very specific choices in
how we tell the story, for all books are, to one extent or another, the telling of
a story—with the same characteristics of everyday stories, including what we
focus on and what we do not; what voices are centered and what voices are not;
stories filled with the humanity of our fuzzy memories and contradictions, as
Figure 4.1 Ana Maria Araújo and Paulo Freire, circa 1990s.
152 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
well as our insights and brilliance. With this in mind, this chapter presents an
interview conducted in Brazil with Ana Maria Araújo Freire—or Nita, as she is
known to friends—in May 2016.1 From the following, I hope the reader will glean
insights into Paulo’s lasting influence and relevance, as well as a more intimate
portrayal of the man from Recife, who would spark the imaginations and
revolutionary dreams of educators around the globe for more than fifty years.
Paulo’s background
A/D2: Can you tell us some things that you think were key in Paulo’s background?
Nita: Paulo came to live in Jaboatão at an early age. In Recife, he lived in a big
house, played in the backyard, and went to school, and had few friends. He
lived primarily within the sphere of his family. But when he arrives to Jaboatão,
he comes into conditions of a very poor child, an impoverished boy and he
begins to share experiences with the children of the factory and farm workers,
and to learn about this new reality from them. He also begins to realize how
people, like his grandmother and friends of the family, would call the people
“riffraff ” (essa gentinha). It was said as if to condemn them, as if they were
nothing but trash. In other words, as if the common people were not worth
anything and could be exploited and subjugated. Essa gentinha was then used
disparagingly to refer to the poor, as if they were the lowest level of people,
in every sense. This did not strike Paulo right. So, he would ask, “But why?
They are exactly like me. These boys are just like me. What is the difference?
What is the difference between the factory worker’s son and me in the world?”
He was not able to understand why people said such things. Paulo would tell
me, “I had a sensitive awareness of injustice as a child, but only at the level of
my feeling and sensations; not on a rational level, not at a level of conscious
reflection.” Paulo could not understand the reason for such injustices in the
1
I extend my heartfelt gratitude to my comrade, colleague, and friend, Donaldo Macedo—considered
to be the foremost translator of Paulo Freire’s work—for his most generous assistance with this
interview. This interview would not have been possible without his kindness, patience, and
bountiful spirit of solidarity. Also many thanks to Alexandre Oliveira for his excellent translation of
the recorded interview material.
2
A/D refers to Antonia and Donaldo.
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 153
world. So, by the age of twelve, he began to concern himself more seriously
with knowing the reason for such things beings as they are and understanding
social phenomena. This, of knowing the reason for being or why something
is this way and not that, all of this was an important preoccupation for him.
A/D: When did Paulo begin to gain awareness of the circumstances of his life?
the ideas that were being transmitted. So this made Paulo begin to think more
deeply about what people needed and wanted to improve their lives. With
this what I want to say is that the deepest historic roots of Paulo’s intellectual
formation are connected to his constant questioning and realizations gained
living within the northeastern reality in Brazil. It’s here when he begins to
think about the why and how of education and society Where he begins to ask,
“In favor of what or whom? Is it against what or whom?” These became the
fundamental questions of Paulo’s epistemology—which cannot be separated
from the historical context in which he grew-up and lived his life.
A/D: What was the initial impact of Pedagogy of the Oppressed in Brazil?
Nita: Pedagogy of the Oppressed was published in the United States in 1970.
The book was published in English even before it was published in Portuguese.
And why was this? We, in Brazil, were in the heights of a dictatorship, back
in the days of General Emilio Garrastazu Medici and it was impossible for
the book to be published in Brazil. In fact, Paulo’s name could not be spoken
in public spaces, at the time. It was forbidden. If one wrote his name in any
periodical, a newspaper, or magazine, you would have to justify this before the
authorities that often employed torture on the people. So, Paulo’s name was
not mentioned. For that reason, it was first published in the US, even before
Brazil.
Fernando Gasparian from Paz e Terra publishers did have copies of the
original manuscript of Pedagogy of the Oppressed. How did the manuscript
make its way to Brazil? Paulo had met a Swiss congressman at the University
of Geneva. The congressman offered to take the manuscripts to Brazil, since he
knew his luggage would not be opened. He was a foreign government official,
who could enter and leave Brazil without being searched. He brought the
copies and got them to Gasparian. But at that time, Gasparian said there was
no possible way to publish the book in Brazil. At the universities, Paulo’s work
could not be discussed, as it was prohibited. It was forbidden in schools as well,
and it was forbidden in the mainstream media.
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 155
3
Darcy Ribeiro is the Brazilian author, anthropologist, and politician, whole ideas of Latin American
identity influenced later scholars of Latin American studies. As Minister of Education of Brazil he
carried out wide reforms, which brought him invitations to participate in university reforms in
Chile, Peru, Venezuela, Mexico, and Uruguay, after his exile from Brazil after the 1964 coup d’état.
156 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
show they could read and write. The literacy campaign at the time of Paulo’s
exile was working to bring literacy programs to three million Brazilians—this
was the goal for the National Literacy Program of 1964. It only existed briefly,
but there had been much preliminary work done, prior to 1964; extensive
development work with literacy workers had been in progress. The decree
was issued in March, but by April the program had been eliminated. It was
believed that among the three million people who would have been served by
the literacy program, the great majority would have joined with leftist forces
to change the rule of power. That, of course, was the regime’s greatest fear; you
see, and it is the same to this day. The powerful elite did not want to lose their
hierarchy of power. The 2016 coup is the same. The 1964 coup was absolutely
necessary from the standpoint of the right elite, “the heirs to the big house”
where the slaves had not been entitled to literacy. So, a great fear persisted (and
persists) that the impoverished masses could become literate and rebel against
the status quo.
Paulo was very celebrated in the US. His concept of critical pedagogy, of
an education that is not mere reproduction of something memorized, where
one makes students repeat what has already been said. Rather, his pedagogy
encourages the creativity and autonomy of individuals. Critical education is,
above all, about that. It started in the US, but has spread through a large part
of the world. Now, the concern with the term “critical pedagogy” is that it is
very North American, and it is very much the same case in Spain as well. Here
in Brazil, when one mentions Freirean Pedagogy, the idea that it is critical is
understood. There isn’t as much of an emphasis on “criticalness,” as there seems
to be in the US. It is a given here that you cannot have authentic education
that is not critical. You are not educating for repetition and memorization;
we are instead educating ourselves and other men and women for our critical
participation in society.
Intellectual influences
A/D: Who were the intellectuals that influenced Paulo’s ideas in Pedagogy of the
Oppressed?
158 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
flashcards that Paulo would write out. There are many on Erich Fromm,
whom he met in Mexico. He was with him in Mexico. Paulo was greatly
influenced by Erich Fromm. The idea of biophilia and necrophilia is very
present in Pedagogy of the Oppressed. He brought aspects to his work from
Fromm. He was in the tradition of radical German thought. Then with the
problem of the war, he had to leave Germany. For Paulo, Erich Fromm is one
of the most important intellectuals of that time. With the advent of the war,
Jews and progressive thinkers that did not endorse Nazism had to escape
Germany. Many of them went to the United States, and some went to Mexico.
Erich Fromm went to Mexico, and when he meets Paulo he says, “Paulo,
Pedagogy of the Oppressed is a book I wanted to see, dealing with the issue of
necrophilia and biophilia in educational terms, in educative terms.” Fromm
always acknowledged Paulo’s work.
Phenomenology, I must say, is another strand of thought that influenced
Paulo’s thinking. There is the issue of humanism from Emmanuel Mounier.
Above all from Mounier comes the issue of humanism, the necessity of
treating the other as one wants to be treated. It is the issue that every human
being, every human experience, every living thing must be respected. Paulo
even loved rocks; he had a collection of rocks. Some, then, say he was an
ecologist. No, Paulo was a humanist; and from there comes his attachment to
all beings, above all living beings, and his deep value for life. For Paulo, it is this
comprehension of humanism that supports an ethics of life; when today, ethics
is the ethics of the marketplace—an ethics of that permeates all discourse and
interpretations of society and the world. So, the humanist authors he read
influenced Paulo’s ethics; and always ethics for him was an ethics of life—
where life must prevail over economic interests.
Paulo was both influenced and also had an influence on the development
of liberation theology. Paulo is considered by some to be one of the founders
of liberation theology. In fact, Friar Boff was once speaking about Paulo at
a conference and someone from the audience asked, “Are you saying that
Paulo Freire was a liberation theologist?” Boff responded, “Yes, I am saying
that Paulo Freire is a liberation theologist.” When liberation theology was
first emerging out of the praxis of Gustavo Gutiérrez … he was beginning
to outline the precepts for a liberation theology, following the meeting in
160 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
Epistemological sensibility
A/D: Something apparent about Paulo was his epistemological sensibility. Can
you speak to this aspect of his praxis?
Nita: I would say, perhaps immodest, because Paulo would never say this, but
Paulo was a genius. Paulo had a sensibility that helped him to anticipate facts
4
Here, the meeting that Nita is referring to is the Conference of Latin American Bishops held in
Medellin, Colombia, in 1968. At this conference, the bishops agreed that the church should take
“a preferential option for the poor.” The bishops decided to form Christian “base communities”
to teach the poor how to read by using the Bible. The expressed intent was to liberate the people
from the institutionalized violence of poverty, by informing the people that poverty and hunger
were preventable. They pronounced that the poor were the blessed people and that the church has
a duty to help them. The movement drew on the influence of Paulo, who was regarded as one of the
great literacy teacher of the region. The movement eventually became known as liberation theology
(discussed in Chapter 2).
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 161
and things. He had a profound capacity for guessing what tomorrow might
bring, in the sense of how people thought about issues. And, I believe, that was
due to his radicalness of thought … his radical sensibility in both experiencing
and making sense of the world. He used to say, “I plant my roots so firmly in
the present that I can make use of the past to foresee the future.” That’s why I
think of him always as a wise man. A wise man is in the present, but always
remembers the past to also think about what might be. Paulo had a wisdom
that was above the average person, not only the northeastern or Brazilian
sensibility, but a sensibility of the world. When, he would set out to study, he
used to say, “To me, just what I produce is not sufficient, my intuitions and
realizations. I need to also find the scientific, theoretical substantiation from
other authors.” Paulo was very open-minded in that way.
Paulo’s sensibilities may also be the question of culture. He was Latin
American. The North American academic culture, in comparison, is not much
given to certain sensibilities and to emotions; it does not value emotions in the
act of knowing. Paulo’s sensibility was one where he felt life and experiences
within his body. He was also very compassionate and could put himself in the
other’s shoes. He was able to say, “What is this other man or woman feeling
or experiencing?” It’s about the capacity to put oneself in the other’s place.
That was part of Paulo’s sensibility. A human sensibility that could value and
take into account, as an important category of knowledge production, feelings,
being emotional, experiencing indignation, facing up to it. For Paulo, those
are necessary conditions for sharpening our sensibility and, therefore, our
intellect. If a poor person on the street … for example, like a group of boys
who killed an Indian man, and when asked about it said, “Oh, but he was
just a beggar.” Their actions showed no sensibility toward the man they killed,
toward his condition. In their mind, he was a beggar … a thing.
Even here in Brazil, these days, many people do not want to consider the
question of sensibility with respect to actions in the world that shock them,
that frighten them, that causes them to be perplexed. To Paulo, it made him
perplexed to see people making a living by working day and night, always
barefoot, not even owning shoes. I remember downtown Recife, when people
from the lower classes never wore shoes; they would have to walk around
barefoot. They worked on their bare feet, even in the urban centers. So much
162 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
so that, today, the popular classes are quite fanatical about buying shoes. A
most profitable business in Recife is then shoe stores, which, I believe, comes
from this legacy of not being able to own shoes. They have lots and lots of
shoes, as if to make up for the time when their parents and grandparents went
barefoot. Situations like this caused Paulo to wonder, “Why is it that I need
shoes? I could not go out on the streets, tripping over on things, as my bare
feet are not adept at walking on the ground and over rocks and poorly made
sidewalks. How can they do this without shame or embarrassment?” It was
because they were subjected to conditions of poverty; they had to adapt to it to
survive; in a sense, they were educated since birth not to have shoes. This is an
example of the way class difference deeply touched Paulo’s sensibility. The issue
of hunger, for example, was a major concern for him. Why is it that they have
nothing to eat, and many don’t complain. They are forced to live in conditions
of starvation.
There is a poem by João Cabral de Melo Neto, a great northeastern poet,
which says they die each day. And what do they die of? They die from being
politically and economically ambushed before thirty, and they die of hunger.
These conditions of poverty caused Paulo great pain and puzzlement. This
again was part of his sensibility; the sensibility to recognize the things that
are real in one’s own reality … around a person, without fantasies, without
camouflage, without justifications, “Oh, they are poor, but they revel in
carnival; they are poor, but they have the religious festivals.” In other words,
Paulo did not romanticize poverty and misery. Instead, for Paulo, his sensibility
caused him to notice that, in spite of hunger, in spite of their conditions of
submission and homelessness and no sanitation, no clean water, they could
make music of the best quality, and they could create and participate in
carnival. Not because conditions of poverty did not have an impact on them
or cause them suffering, but because they have an impetus for living that many
in the middle class simply lack, even with their affluence. So, for Paulo, it was
important to realize such things … to be aware of the humanity of the poor.
This was Paulo’s sensibility to others and to the world. But Paulo’s sensibility
did not end there. He did not simply stop and cry over those who suffered.
He set out to find epistemological resonances in philosophers and historians
and sociologists and linguists, people from other sciences, to help him explain
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 163
more profoundly, more scientifically, what his sensibility stirred him to see and
experience in the world.
While in the United States, it seems that such level of sensibility has become
dormant, in what is a positivist and reductive epistemological approach. So
these human sensibilities are present but they tend to become latent due to
the structure of the way they think. Paulo believed that it is up to teachers to
awaken in their students this human sensibility that we all have; a sensibility that
helps us develop a more profound concern for life … for the “the other,” for the
society, for the country in which we live, for the world. How is it possible that a
young adult, for example, not know about the many forms of North American
exploitation that have been carried out around the world … pillaging wealth
and forbidding the self-determination of other countries … imposing upon
them self-serving rules and regulations. How could this not have an impact on
how a young person is educated? For Paulo, he felt that teacher must work with
students so that they can begin to ask, “How can all this take place around the
world, and still we say we are a democratic country that teaches democracy?”
Another thing about this question of epistemology, Paulo would often
say, “We must never be too sure of our certainty. Our certainties must always
be put in check; we must always question our certainties.” He believed that
questioning is how we evolve and can contribute to social transformation. And
this requires that we not ever be too sure of our certainties. That’s why Paulo
never said he was sure; he would, at best, say, “I am somewhat sure …” It’s a
kind of certain/uncertainty … a way of rejecting the need to be absolutely
certain that something is either right or not. This reflects, again, Paulo’s open-
mindedness that he believed we needed for dialogue and to not reproduce
oppression in schools and in the society.
On class struggle
Nita: Sometimes, in the US, this denial of class struggle makes contending with
problems faced by impoverished people more difficult than even in Brazil. It’s
as if many people in the US don’t want to see that class struggle is everywhere.
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 165
Here, in Brazil, a large segment of the population sees the problem of class;
but in the US you cannot readily find people dealing with class struggle … I
mean, you do find individuals here and there who think about and challenge
this problem, but the collective population, for the most part, seems oblivious
and too certain that class is not the problem. Here, in Brazil, with very, very
rare exceptions, recognizing class struggle … recognizing that there exist class
divisions, antagonism is expected in academic thesis and dissertation work.
However, as Paulo would say, “The dominant class truly hates the poor. It’s as if
the poor were to blame for their poverty.” Instead, he said social and material
domination is to blame for human oppression in Brazil, North America, and
other places in the world.
A/D: What did Paulo think about neoliberalism, relative to what is happening in
education now in Brazil?
Nita: In Under the Shade of the Mango Tree [published in the United States as
Pedagogy of Hope], a most beautiful book, Paulo precisely makes a condemnation
of neoliberalism. He links capitalism to the history of human oppression
and refers to neoliberalism as how it exists today. For Paulo, neoliberalism
decrees the death of history. It decrees the end of class struggle. That we are all
supposedly equals and can move around the world with no borders. However,
current conditions are the exact opposite! In fact, class struggle has hardened;
the concentration of wealth has increased in all countries of the world, and
poverty continues to grow. The impoverished are still more illiterate; illiteracy
has grown in some parts of the world; hunger is increasing around the world;
unemployment is growing around the world; and all that is taking place as a
result of neoliberalism. Paulo used to say that neoliberalism is the antithesis
of any possibility for an egalitarian society. Neoliberalism, with its false face as
bringer of benefits, in fact brings social and material poverty to the world; so,
in many ways, the world is becoming more miserably poor.
In Pedagogy of Hope, Paulo deals above all with the manner in which
neoliberalism leaves no other way out than the poverty of many; that such is
the world and that we must cut jobs for the benefit of the economy, even if it
leaves so many in poverty. Paulo would say, “That is so only when it results
in gain for the dominant classes.” There is a discourse of the inevitability of
166 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
neoliberalism. But from the standpoint of the rights of workers and the rights
of the oppressed, none of that is inevitable. The message of neoliberalism is that
“Things cannot change and must indeed be as they are.” This implies a double
standard that in all circumstances favors the powerful and wealthy. There is
no chance for a fairer society with the canvas of neoliberalism, which is what
imperialist countries impose on us—the formerly termed “Third World” now
called “developing countries.”
Brazil is among these nations, so-called in process of becoming developed.
Yet, Brazil was until recently the eighth economy in the world. However, it will
likely suffer a setback—a lowering of its economic standing in the world—not
as a result of our incompetence, but as a preordained consequence of adopting
the neoliberal model. The neoliberal discourse camouflages reality; it deceives
and seems quite plausible and fair to the unwary. They have hope in what
the government we have now, which is becoming more intently neoliberal or
something worse, imposing an unfair political economy in the people of Brazil.
This is a government geared toward the external economic interests that now
dominate the world. I believe we can term it a neoliberal government, which it
seems to be; although it presents itself as democratic one, while it closes down
democratic possibilities for the participation by the people in the decision-
making and management of domestic policy.
This democratic participation by the people is what horrifies the dominant
classes in Brazil—a certain autonomy that was being created for policy decision-
making by the subordinate classes. This phenomenon stirred the arrogant
dominant class into frenzy. Paulo used to often wonder when we would put
an end to such injustice in the world. Today, reactionary conservatives find
new pretexts to attack progressive state officials. They are trying to find so-
called crimes committed by the president [Dilma Rouseff],5 while the greatest,
fairest jurists in Brazil say they have found no responsibility for any crimes
on her part. Even so, they have caused the Congress, as it is compromised
5
Dilma Rouseff, a progressive Brazilian economist, was president from 2011 until her impeachment,
where she was found guilty of breaking budget laws and was removed from office in August 2016,
three months after this interview was conducted. As a socialist activist during the dictatorship,
Rouseff was captured, tortured, and jailed from 1970 to 1972. However, some of her political stances
(i.e., anti-abortion, anti-gay marriage, neoliberal initiatives) were considered rather contradictory
to her constituency, which may have been one of the reason that conservative groups in Brazil found
space and opportunity to launch an assault on her presidency.
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 167
A/D: Paulo died almost twenty years ago; what has remained? What is his
legacy?
168 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
6
Nita is speaking here of the Movimento dos Trabalhadores Rurais Sem Terra (MST): a mass social
movement, formed by rural workers and those who want to fight for land reform and against
injustice and social inequality in rural areas. The MST was born through a process of occupying
latifundios (large landed estates), becoming a national movement in 1984. The movement has led
more than 2,500 land occupations, with about 370,000 families—families that today settled on 7.5
million hectares of land that they won as a result of the occupations. Through their organizing, these
families continue to push for schools, credit for agricultural production and cooperatives, and access
to health care. Currently, there are approximately 900 encampment holding 150,000 landless families
in Brazil. Those camped, as well as those already settled, remain mobilized, ready to exercise their
full citizenship, by fighting for the realization of their political, social economic, environmental and
cultural rights. See: Friends of the MST website for more information: http://www.mstbrazil.org/.
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 169
the publisher to give them permission to publish Paulo’s writings, but with
introductions written by them, as a way of providing the theoretical base for
their pedagogical practice among the people. Therefore, this movement, MST
as we call it, has all its political educational practice based on Paulo’s work.
They often honor Paulo; I am often invited. They have debates about the work.
I mean he is a name that is not forgotten, in any way. João Pedro Stédile, who is
the head of the movement, exercises an effective form of democratic leadership.
He is a man who came from the impoverished classes of Rio Grande do Sul,
and he is a most capable economist, as well. He is a very intelligent man, and
a very good man. He sustains that movement, by maintaining its status as a
large organization capable of facing the great inequities that exist in Brazil, the
wide gaps in having, knowing, and being able to do. They are always geared to
mobilize … the media calls their actions invasions but Paulo used to say that
it is not invasions. What they are doing is occupying lands that have been kept
unproductive till now.
These days, I see that the reach of Paulo’s work is widening to include spaces
we would never have imagined. One of Paulo’s books was translated last year
in Israel, into the Hebrew language. I think this is an important and positive
fact. With all the difficulties in the region, it is good to know there are people
in Israel who care about building a spirit of tolerance. Also, Paulo’s books are
being read in places like Indonesia, Pakistan, Kazakhstan, and India. Educators
in these countries are embracing Paulo’s ideas. Yes, sometimes only in small
areas, but there are groups, even if small ones, that are working to combat the
status quo in those national states and they are looking toward Paulo’s insights
as a starting point for their work in communities, in combination with their
own intellectuals. It is good to see that in those countries where citizens still
experience repression, there remains an interest in liberation, an interest
in social transformation. Brazil in 1997 after Paulo’s death, for example,
coincided with a very turbulent political period in Brazil. During that time,
there was greater demand for Paulo’s books. In difficult years, like then and
in this period now, from 2012 to now, Paulo’ books are again being read more
widely in Brazil. And, of course, his books continue to sell around the world.
About Paulo’s legacy, what I can say is that there is just one Paulo. The one
who started out with Education as Practice for Freedom, and already he was
170 The Student Guide to Freire’s Pedagogy of the Oppressed
asking, “Whose freedom?” Even if not named, it was that of the oppressed.
But, above all, starting from the publishing of Pedagogy of the Oppressed,
Paulo’s work is one and the same; it has been consistent in its commitment to
the poor; commitment to social transformation … this remained with Paulo
to the day of his death. I was able to live that with him with great intensity.
Some say I am too in love with him. Yes, I am very much in love with him,
but all that subjective passion never got in the way of my objective analysis of
Paulo’s stance before the world, of what Paulo wrote, and what Paulo practiced.
I do not look upon Paulo with benevolent eyes, so as to establish that he was a
great man. I indeed knew I had a great man by my side!
It is a great pleasure and honor to have been able to participate in life with
Paulo, but I would like readers to see Paulo as a man able to bring light to the
darkest and most hidden recesses of human degradation. Paulo’s ideas are
able to illuminate us, so that we can see the nefarious impact of domination.
It is important to see how Paulo thought about and dealt with difficult societal
problems, without rancor, without hate, and without meanness. No one can
truthfully accuse Paulo of being of bad temperament, of being envious, or of not
being a serious intellectual or revolutionary. He lived his politics. He denounced
oppression with a great spirit and announced justice with great hope for
transformation and change. I would like readers to find this in his writings and
to experience, even if only a little, Paulo’s enormous capacity for feeling and
experiencing the world, which led him to reflection deeply about liberation.
Paulo used to say, “I don’t think with my head; I think with my whole body.”
I think that is what was so fantastic about him! He would say, “I think with my
desires, with my frustrations, with my emotions, with my virtues. I think with
everything that fits into my body. It is my conscious body that tells me to focus
my reflection upon this or that.” Again, I think that is fantastic! He would say,
I don’t think with my head. I think with my whole body. How do I think
with my whole body? When my hairs go up, it is my body telling me there is
something I should look at, to reflect upon. When my heartbeat accelerates
to tachycardia, it is because some phenomenon is calling to me, to my
attention, but doing so through my body and not only my head. My body is
conscious. My whole body, my sensibility, comes before my head. It precedes
my ability to engage in reflection. It comes before.
An Interview with Ana Maria Araújo Freire 171
This is why Paulo would say that his intuition never left him on the road.
About this, Paulo would say,
Abreu, A. A. (1975), Nationalisme et action politique au Brésil: une étude sur l’ISEB.
Tese (Doutorado). Paris, France: Universidade de Paris.
Adorno T. (1973a), Prisms. London: Neville Spearman.
Adorno, T. W. (1973b), Negative Dialectics. New York: Continuum.
Adorno, T. W. (1991), The Culture Industry. London, UK: Routledge.
Allen Jr., J. L. (2012), “Remembering the Women of Vatican II,” National Catholic
Reporter. See: https://www.ncronline.org/blogs/ncr-today/remembering-women-
vatican-ii
Allensandrini, A. C. (2014), Frantz Fanon and the Future of Cultural Politics. London,
UK: Lexington Books.
Althusser, L. (1967), Pour Marx. Le Landreau, France: Editions François Maspero.
Althusser, L. (1969), For Marx. New York: Penguin Press.
Althusser, L. (2001), Lenin and Philosophy and Other Essays, Trans. Ben Brewster.
New York: Monthly Review.
Almeida, C. Mendes de (1966), Momentos dos Vivos: A Esquerda Católica no Brasil.
Rio de Janeiro, Brazil: Tempo Brasilero.
Alvarado, Arias M. (2007), “José Martí y Paulo Freire: aproximaciones para una
lectura de la pedagogía crítica,” Revista Electrónica de Investigación Educativa,
9(1): 1–19. See: https://redie.uabc.mx/redie/article/view/157
Anzaldúa, G. (1989), Borderlands: The New Mestiza. San Francisco: Aunt Lute.
Arrupe, P., S. J. (1973), “Men for Others,” In C. E. Meirose, SJ (Compiler) (1994),
Foundations, 1–40. Washington, DC: Jesuit Secondary Education Association.
Austin, R. (2003), The State, Literacy, and Popular Education in Chile, 1964–1990.
London, UK: Lexington Books.
Bakan, M. (1983), “Karel Kosik’s Phenomenological Heritage,” In W. L. McBride and
C. O. Schrag (eds.), Phenomenology in a Pluralistic Context, 9. New York: SUNY
Press.
Balut, J. M. (1993), The Colonizer’s Model of the World. New York/London: The
Guilford Press.
Beauvoir, S. de (1955), Le Pensée de Droite, Aujourd’hui. Paris: Gallimard.
Benade, L. (2015), “Bits, Bytes, and Dinosaurs: Using Levinas and Freire to Address
the Concept of ‘Twenty-first Century Learning’,” Educational Philosophy and
Theory, 47(9): 935–948.
Bibliography 173
Bergson, H. (1911), Creative Evolutio. New York: Henry Holt and Co.
Bhattacharya, A. (2011), Paulo Freire: Rousseau of the Twentieth Century. Berlin,
Germany: Springer Science & Business Media.
Boff, L. (2011), “The Influence of Freire on Scholars: A Select List,” In J. Kirylo (eds.),
Paulo Freire: The Man from Recife, 235–269. New York: Peter Lang.
Brady, J. (1994), “Critical Literacy, Feminism, and a Politics of Representation,” In
P. McLaren and C. Lankshear (eds.), Politics of Liberation, 142–152. New York:
Routledge.
Bruneau, T. C. (1974), Catolicismo Brasilero em época de transição. São Paulo: Loyola.
Buber, M. (1958), I and Thou. New York: Free Press.
Burston, D. (1985), The Legacy of Erich Fromm. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.
Cammarota, J. and A. Romero (2014), Raza Studies: The Public Option for Educational
Revolution. Tucson, AZ: University of Arizona Press.
Cassirer, T. and M. Twomey (1973), “Introduction to A. Memmi’s The Impossible Life
of Frantz Fanon,” The Massachusetts Review, 14(1): 9–39.
Cesaire, A. (1955), Discours sur le colonialism. Paris: Présence Africaine.
Cherki, A. (2006), Frantz Fanon: A Portrait. Ithaca and London: Cornell University
Press.
Chubbuck, S. (2007), “Socially Just Teaching and the Complementarity of Ignatian
Pedagogy and Critical Pedagogy,” Christian Higher Education, 6(3): 239–265.
Chubbuck, S. M. and R. Lorentz (2006), “Critical Pedagogy and Ignatian Pedagogy:
Piecing Together the Why, the What, and the How of Teaching for Social Justice,”
Paper presented at Commitment to Justice Conference, Marquette University.
Clare, R. (2006), “Paulo Freire,” La Mirada, CA: Talbot School of Theology, Biola
University. See: http://www.talbot.edu/ce20/educators/catholic/paulo_freire/
Cortesão, L. (2011), “Paulo Freire and Amilcar Cabral: Convergences”, Journal for
Critical Education Policy Studies, 9(2): 260–296.
Cross W. E. (1978), “The Thomas and Cross Models on Psychological Nigrescence: A
Literature Review.” Journal of Black Psychology 4: pp. 13-31.
Darder, A. (2012), Culture and Power in the Classroom. Boulder, CO: Paradigm.
Darder, A. (2015), Freire and Education. New York: Routledge.
Darder, A., R. D. Torres, and M. P. Baltodano (2017), Critical Pedagogy Reader (3rd
ed.). New York: Routledge.
Davidson, M. (2012), “Albert Memmi and Audre Lorde: Gender, Race, and the
Rhetorical Uses of Anger,” Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy—Revue
de la philosophie française et de langue française, 20(1): 87–100.
deAnda D. (1984), “Bicultural Socialization: Factors Affecting the Minority
Experience.” Social Work 2: pp. 101-07.
174 Bibliography
Debray, R. (1967), Revolution in the Revolution?: Armed Struggle and Political Struggle
in Latin America. New York: Penguin Books.
Dewey, J. (1916), Democracy and Education. New York: The Free Press.
Dixon V., and Foster B. (1971), Beyond Black or White. Boston: Little Brown.
Du Bois, W. E. B. (1903), Souls of Black Folk. Chicago: A. C. McClurg.
Dufrenne, M. (1953), Phénoménologie de l’expérience esthétique. Paris: Presses
Universitaires de France.
Dufrenne, M. (1968), Pour L’Homme. Paris: Éditions de Seuil.
Dussel, E. (2013), Ethics of Liberation: In the Age of Globalization and Exclusion.
Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Elias, J. L. (1994), Paulo Freire: Pedagogue of Liberation. Malabar, FL: Kreiger
Publishing Company.
Elie, P. (2007), “A Man for all Reasons,” The Atlantic, (November). Retrieved
from: https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2007/11/a-man-for-all-
reasons/306337/
Facundo, B. (1984), “Freire-inspired Programs in the United States and Puerto Rico”.
Retrieved from: http://www.bmartin.cc/dissent/documents/Facundo/Facundo.
html
Fanon, F. (1952), Peau Noire Masques Blancs. Paris, France: Éditions du Seuil.
Fanon, F. (1963), Wretched of the Earth. New York: Grove Press.
Fanon, F. (1965), A Dying Colonialism. New York: Grove Press.
Fanon, F. (1967), Black Skin, White Masks. New York: Grove Press.
Felluga, D.F. (2015), Critical Theory: The Key Concepts. New York: Routledge.
Finlayson, L. (2016), An Introduction to Feminism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Fonseca, M. (2016), Gramsci’s Critique of Civil Society. New York: Routledge.
Forester, J. (1987), Critical Theory and Public Life. Boston, MA: MIT Press.
Foy, R. (1971), “Review of Pedagogy of the Oppressed,” Educational Studies
(October).
Freire, A. M. A. and D. Macedo (eds.) (1998), The Paulo Freire Reader. New York:
Continuum.
Freire, P. (1970), Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York: Seabury.
Freire, P. (1970b), Pedagogia do Oprimido. Rio de Janeiro: Edicões Paz e Terra.
Freire, P. (1978), “A Alfabetização de adultos: é ela um quefazer neutro?,” Educação
and Sociedade (Campinas, Brazil), 1(1): 64–70.
Freire, P. (1985), “Caminhos de Paulo Freire. Entrevisita a J. Chasin et al.,” Ensaio:
revista da UFPb (João Pessoa, Brazil), (14).
Freire, P. (1991), Pedagogy of the City. New York: Continuum.
Bibliography 175
Freire, P. (1994), Pedagogy of Hope: Reliving Pedagogy of the Oppressed. New York:
Continuum.
Freire, P. (1996), Letters to Christina: Reflections on My Life and Work. New York:
Routledge.
Freire, P. (1997), Pedagogy of the Heart. New York: Continuum.
Freire, P. (1998), Teachers as Cultural Workers: Letters to Those Who Dare Teach.
Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
Freire, P., and S. Guimarães (1987), Aprendendo com a própria história. Rio de
Janeiro: Editora Paz e Terra.
Freire, P. and D. Macedo (1987), Literacy: Reading the Word and the World. New
York: Taylor and Francis.
Freud, S. (1949), The Ego and the Id. London, UK: The Hogarth Press Ltd.
Freud, S. (2002), Civilization and Its Discontent. London, UK: Penguin.
Freud, S. (2010), The Ego and the Id. New York: W.W. Norton and Company.
Freyer, H. (1958), Teoria de la Epoca Actual. Mexico: Fondo de Cultural Economica.
Friedman, L. J. and A. Schreiber (2014), The Lives of Erich Fromm: Love’s Prophet.
Cambridge, MA: Colombia University Press.
Fromm, E. (1941), Escape from Freedom. New York: Henry Holt and Co.
Fromm, E. (1955), The Sane Society. New York: Routledge.
Fromm, E. (1956), The Art of Loving. New York: Harper and Row.
Fromm, E. (1964), The Heart of Man. New York: Harper and Row.
Fromm, E. (1966), The Heart of Man. New York: Harper and Row.
Fromm, E. (1973), The Anatomy of Destructiveness. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and
Winston.
Furter, P. (1966), Eduçacão e Vida. Rio de Janeiro: Voces.
Gadotti, M. (1994), Reading Paulo Freire: His Life and Work. New York: SUNY Press.
Garcia, J. and M. Vargas (2013), “Latin American Philosophy,” Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy. Retrieved from: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/latin-american-
philosophy/
Gerhardt, H. (1993), “Paulo Freire (1921–97),” Prospects: the quarterly review of
comparative education (Paris, UNESCO: International Bureau of Education),
XXIII (3/4): 439–58.
Gibson, R. (1994), “The Promethean Literacy: Paulo Freire’s Pedagogy of Reading,
Praxis, and Liberation,” Dissertation. Pennsylvania State University. Retrieved
from: https://lbsu300s12.wikispaces.com/file/view/Paulo+Freire+(2).pdf
Giroux, H. (1981), Ideology, Culture, and the Process of Schooling. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press.
Giroux, H. (1983), Theory and Resistance in Education. New York: Bergin and Garvey.
176 Bibliography
Marx, K. and F. Engels (1996), Collected Works: Capital, vol. 1. New York:
International Publishers.
Mayo, P. (2010), Gramsci and Educational Thought. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
McLaren, P. (1989), Life in Schools: An Introduction to Critical Pedagogy and the
Foundations of Education. New York: Longman.
McLaren, P. (2002), “A Legacy of Hope and Struggle: Afterword,” In A. Darder (ed.),
Reinventing Paulo Freire: A Pedagogy of Love. Boulder, CO: Westview.
McLaren, P. and P. Leonard (1993), Paulo Freire: A Critical Encounter. New York:
Routledge.
McLennan, G. (1989), Marxism, Pluralism and Beyond: Classic Debates and New
Departures. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Memmi, A. (1957), The Colonizer and the Colonized. Boston, MA: Beacon.
Memmi, A. (1973), “The Impossible Life of Frantz Fanon,” The Massachusetts Review,
14(1): 9–39.
Memmi, A. (2006), Decolonization and the Decolonized. Minneapolis, MN: University
of Minnesota Press.
Mignolo, W. (2000), “Dussel’s Philosophy of Liberation: Ethics and the Geopolitics of
Knowledge,” In L. M. Alcoff and E. Mendieta (eds.), Thinking from the Underside
of History, 27–50. Lannham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Mignolo, W. D. (2007), “Delinking: The Rhetoric of Modernity, the Logic of
Coloniality and the Grammar of De-coloniality,” Cultural Studies, 21(2): 449–514.
Moine, A. (1965), Cristianos y Marxista despues del Concilio. Buenos Aires, Argentina:
Arandu.
Morrow, R.A. and C.A. Torres (2002), Reading Freire and Habermas: Critical
Pedagogy and Transformative Social Change. New York: Teachers College Press.
Mounier, E. (1970), O Personalismo. Lisboa: Moraes.
Mullarkey, J. C. (1995), “Bergson’s Method of Multiplicity,” Metaphilosophy, 28(3):
230–259.
Mussett, S. M. and W. S. Wilkerson (2012), Beauvoir and Western Thought from Plato
to Butler. New York: SUNY Press.
Nicolaï, A. (1960), Comportment Économique et Structures Sociales. Paris: Presses
Universitaire France.
Niebuhr, R. (1960), Moral Man and Immoral Society: A Study in Ethics and Politics.
New York: Scribner.
Nowacek, R. S. and S. M. Mountin (2012), “Reflections in Action: A Signature
Ignatian Pedagogy for the 21st Century,” In N. L. Chick, et al. (eds.), Exploring
More Signature Pedagogies: Approaches to Teaching Disciplinary Habits of the Mind,
129–142. Sterling, VA: Stylus Publishing.
Bibliography 181
Ohliger, J. (1995), Critical Views of Paulo Freire’s Work. Madison, WI: Basic Choices.
Oliveira, P. A. Ribeiro (2007), “‘Libertação’: idéia-força da ‘Esquerda Católica,’” In L.
A. Gpmez de Souza (org.), Relativismo e transcendência, 31–45. Rio de Janeiro:
EDUSC.
Orbe, M. P. (2009), “Phenomenology,” In S. Littlejohn, and K. Foss (eds.),
Encyclopedia of Communication Theory, 749–751. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage
Publications.
Paiva, V. P. (1979), “Sobre a Influência de Mannheim na Pedagogia de P. Freire,”
Síntese Politica Econômica Social (SPES), 14: 43–64. Retrieved from: http://acervo.
paulofreire.org:8080/xmlui/handle/7891/1612
Paiva, V. P. (1980), “Estado, Sociedade e Educação no Brasil,” Encontros com a
Civilização Brasileira, No. 22 (abril).
Paraskeva, J. (2011), Conflicts in Curriculum Theory. New York: Palgrave.
Patzi-Paco, Felix (2004), Sistema Comunal. Una Propuesta Alternativa al Sistema
Liberal. La Paz, Bolivia: Comunidad de Estudios Alternativos.
Paul, R. (1993), Critical Thinking (3rd ed.). Tomales, CA: Foundation for Critical
Thinking.
Peterson, C. F. (2007), Dubois, Fanon, Cabral: The Margins of Elite Anti-colonial
Leadership. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Petrović, G. (1964), “Why Praxis?,” In Praxis. Retrieved from: https://www.marxists.
org/subject/praxis/issue-01/why-praxis.htm
Petruzzi, A. P. (1998), “Between Conventions and Critical Thinking: The Concept
of ‘Limit-Situations’ in Critical Literacy and Pedagogy,” JAC: Journal of Rhetoric,
Culture, and Politics, 18(2): 309–332.
Petruzzi, A. P. (2001), “Kairotic Rhetoric in Freire’s Liberatory Pedagogy,” JAC:
Journal of Rhetoric, Culture, and Politics, 21(2): 350–381.
Pinto, A. V. (1960), Consciencia e Realidade Nacional. Rio de Janeiro: MEC/ISEB.
Planas, R. (2014), “Why ‘Book Ban’ is the Right Term for What Arizona did to
Mexican American Studies,” Huntington Post (September 26). Retrieved from:
http://www.huffingtonpost.com/2014/09/26/arizona-book-ban_n_5887926.html
Postone, M. (1996), Time, Labor, and Social Domination. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Prado, J. C. (1969), The Colonial Background of Modern Brazil. Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press.
Quijano, A. (2000), “Coloniality of Power, Eurocentrism, and Latin America,”
Napantla: Views from the South, 1(3): 533–580. Retrieved from http://iss.sagepub.
com/content/15/2/215.short?rss=1andssource=mfr
182 Bibliography
Note: Page references with letter ‘n’ followed by locators denote note numbers.
critical social theory 65, 67. See also Dufrenne, Mikel 39–40
critical theory Dussel, Enrique 31
critical theory 64–7, 70, 76 Dying Colonialism (Fanon) 81
cultural action 24, 94, 133, 137–40, 142,
145–9 Eduçacão e Vida (Furter) 90
Cultural Extension Service (SEC) 12 education. See also banking education
cultural invasion 35, 97, 137–8, 143–5 as alienation instrument 109–10
cultural revolution 142, 145, 147–8, 158 as practice of freedom 117–18
culture industry 69 problem posing 112–13
culture of silence 6, 15, 119–21 revolutionary praxis 104–8, 112–13,
115–16, 118–19, 122, 125, 133, 137,
Dasein 45 139–42, 145, 148
de Souza, Herbert Jose 25 teacher-student contradiction 110–12
de Tarso, Santos, Paul 13, 15 Education and Society (Dewey) 88
dehumanization 51, 70, 74, 83, 94–7, 101, education movements 1, 17–18
103, 111, 119–21, 130, 146 educators 8, 59, 87, 110, 112–13, 117,
dependency 80–1, 84, 97–8, 100, 142 122–3, 137, 152, 168–9
Descartes, Rene 34, 42, 47 Enlightenment rationality 65
Dewey, John 86–9 epistemological reflections 1, 25, 42, 44–5,
naturalist approach 88–9 62, 65, 76, 86–7, 101, 128, 160–4
views of education 89 Eros and Civilization (Marcuse) 70
Dialéctica de lo Concreto (Vásquez’ Ethics of Ambiguity, The (Beauvoir) 39
translation) 76 Eurocentrism 30
dialectical historicism 33 European colonization 2, 7, 12, 16–17
dialectical movement 42, 132 European labor movements 67
dialectics 47, 56, 63, 68, 80, 101–2, 114, existence of things in general (Seindes) 44
130 existentialism 33, 35–6. See also French
Dialectics of the Concrete (Kosik) 76 existentialism
dialogical cultural action 145–7 phenomenology 41
dialogical praxis 41, 93–4, 101, 104, 112–15
cooperation 145 faith 123–4
critical consciousness 94, 125–7 false generosity 99–101, 119, 127, 145, 148
cultural synthesis 147 Fanon, Frantz 6, 77–82, 85–6, 97, 99, 111,
of leadership 139–40 158
liberatory struggle 142, 147–9 on colonized and colonizer 79–80
limit-situations 130 Memmi comparison with 85–6
name the world 141 fascism 67, 83
organization 146–7 fatalism 25, 98–9, 109, 116–17, 119–20,
problem-posing pedagogy 112, 131–2 124, 131
unity for liberation 146 fear
untested feasibility 131 authentic existence 98
dialogue with people 41, 104–5, 119, freedom 98, 142, 145
134, 140. See also problem-posing Fear of Freedom, The (Fromm) 74
pedagogy feminism (French existentialism) 39
disempowerment 7, 97, 109, 127 First World War 66
divide and rule 138, 143–4 Food and Agriculture Organization of the
domestication 7, 70–1, 97–8, 111, 127 United Nations 14
Index 187