Why Should We Read Spinoza
Why Should We Read Spinoza
SUSAN JAMES
Abstract
Historians of philosophy are well aware of the limitations of what Butterfield called
‘Whig history’: narratives of historical progress that culminate in an enlightened
present. Yet many recent studies retain a somewhat teleological outlook. Why
should this be so? To explain it, I propose, we need to take account of the emotional
investments that guide our interest in the philosophical past, and the role they play in
shaping what we understand as the history of philosophy. As far as I know, this
problem is not currently much addressed. However, it is illuminatingly explored
in the work of Spinoza (1632–77). Spinoza aspires to explain the psychological
basis of our attachment to histories with a teleological flavour. At the same time,
he insists that such histories are epistemologically flawed. To study the history of
philosophy in a properly philosophical fashion we must overcome our Whiggish
leanings.
1.
110
2
Jonathan Bennett, A Study of Spinoza’s Ethics (Cambridge
University Press, 1984), para. 9, page 35.
3
Jonathan Israel, Enlightenment Contested (Oxford University Press,
2006), 11.
111
4
Herbert Butterfield, The Whig Interpretation of History (London:
G. Bell, 1931).
5
Bertrand Russell, History of Western Philosophy (London: George
Allen and Unwin, 1946), 601.
112
113
commit firmly to one side or the other is to forego (or attempt to forego)
a powerful intellectual pleasure. Historians who are convinced of the
value of Whiggish interpretations may still suffer anthropological
yearnings, just as those who are officially hostile to Whig approaches
may find themselves drawn to interpretations with a teleological
flavour. The pleasures that we seek in studying the past do not always
line up with our explicit philosophical beliefs about the methods we
ought to employ, and are not completely stilled by argument.
As far as I am aware, analytical historians of philosophy have not
paid much attention to this aspect of philosophical practice. While
many acknowledge that individual interpreters invest emotionally
in the philosophers they study, wanting them, for example, to be
morally or metaphysically admirable, the affective dimension of our
relation to the past is not on the whole discussed. Perhaps this is
because it is seen as a psychological phenomenon that lies beyond the
bounds of properly philosophical investigation; but whatever the
reason, explorations of this dimension of philosophising are largely
absent from current debate. One may find this is a little surprising,
the more so since there has recently been an increased recognition
within analytical epistemology that humans are not very good at rea-
soning, and more the playthings of their passions than they know.7 If
this is view is right, should we not bring it to bear on our own practice
as philosophers? Should we not try to get some critical distance on our
researches by supplementing the back and forth of argument with an
examination of the pleasures, anxieties and desires that are intertwined
with our explicitly intellectual convictions?
There are many ways to reconnect with the emotional aspect of
studying the history of philosophy, but an attractively reflexive route
turns back to the history of philosophy itself, and specifically to past
philosophers for whom affects lie at the heart of our thinking and activ-
ity. Here Spinoza’s work offers an obvious starting point since, for
him, all thinking is a manifestation of our striving for a satisfying
and empowering way of life, and philosophising, like the rest of our
thinking, expresses this orientation. Philosophy, we can say, is identi-
fied as an activity that gives us a certain kind of emotional satisfaction.
Together with Spinoza’s analysis of the operations of our affects, I shall
suggest, this conception secretes an account of the desires and pleasures
underlying teleological interpretative approaches to the history of phil-
osophy, and an assessment of their role within philosophical enquiry.
7
Daniel Kahneman, Thinking Fast and Slow (Allen Lane, 2011);
Quassim Cassam, Self Knowledge for Humans (Oxford University Press,
2014).
115
2.
and determines many features of our lives, we are to some extent able
to offset its limitations by cultivating a fuller knowledge of the world,
and a wiser practical sense of how to live in an empowering fashion.
As Spinoza puts it, we can compensate for the deficiencies of what
he calls imagining by developing what he describes as the capacity
to reason or understand. Moreover, as we do so we exercise our
own power and become increasingly active.
Empowering ourselves thus consists in cultivating ways of life that
do justice to our existing knowledge of ourselves and our environment,
and leave room for us to enhance both our knowledge and our capacity
to live in the light of it. However, in the account of this unending
project that Spinoza offers in his Ethics, he focuses on the importance
of understanding ourselves. While our capacity to live in an empower-
ing fashion is often blocked by our ignorance of the world around us,
our greatest problems stem from lack of self-knowledge, which is in
turn partly due to our own imaginative dispositions. Since our efforts
to empower ourselves are habitually limited by psychological disposi-
tions that beckon us down paths leading to sadness, one of our first
tasks is to learn to compensate for them.
Among the most pervasive of these tendencies is a disposition to
exaggerate our individual power and overestimate what we can
achieve. To offset it, we need to acknowledge the extent to which
we are individually dependent on external things for our wellbeing,
and learn how to put this insight to work in our ways of life. Rather
than struggling on our own, we need to strengthen our power to per-
severe in our being by joining forces with other people. However, as
Spinoza goes on to argue, this project is attended by its own difficul-
ties. To manage it successfully, we have to deal with a further ambiva-
lent aspect of our psychology, deriving from the fact that our affects
are primarily focused on those of other human beings. We experience
other people as like us in the sense that they share our repertoire of
affects. Just as we can respond to their emotions so they can
respond to ours, and this mutual recognition is in turn reflected in
our individual and collective efforts to enhance our power.
To some extent, Spinoza argues, the mere fact that we recognise
other human beings as sharing our emotional constitution is
enough to make us imitate their affects. Whereas we do not envy
trees their height or lions their strength, we pity humans with
whom we have no other connection and may desire things simply
because other people want them.8 Moreover, these affective
8
Spinoza, Ethics in E. Curley ed., The Collected Works of Spinoza
(Princeton University Press, 1985), E3p27.
117
118
119
3.
123
There seem, then, to be two ways in which the study of the history
of philosophy can further the philosophical project as Spinoza con-
ceives of it. First and most straightforwardly, dead philosophers
may teach us how nature operates. Spinoza, for example, is interested
in the natural philosophy of his era, particularly the work of Bacon
and Descartes, and is alert to earlier theories of the affects including
those of the Stoics. These figures belong to a philosophical commu-
nity that encompasses the dead as well as the living and is relatively
indifferent to chronology. In addition, past philosophers may help
their descendants to live in the light of the philosophical knowledge
they possess by offering them models or images of empowering
ways of life that they can use as guides. In some cases, these will be
models of the good life; for example, images of the virtuous man as
discussed by Aristotle, Cicero and Seneca are all present in
Spinoza’s work. As well as these forms of theoretical guidance,
however, Spinoza is if anything more interested in seeking historical
advice about the practical aspects of philosophy. His supreme exem-
plar of a philosophical life is that of Jesus Christ; and he clearly thinks
that there are many other accounts of the lives of rulers and statesman
from which we can draw lessons about the art of good government.
The philosophical community, as he now begins to portray it, in-
cludes historians such as Tacitus, Livy and Josephus, statesmen
such as Machiavelli, and rulers such as Alexander and Moses,
whose actions or writings can inform our efforts to live in the light
of our understanding.
Assessing the strategies and decisions of past legislators and sover-
eigns can therefore help us to learn to live together; but we also need
to see how their actions contributed or failed to contribute to the
security and longevity of political communities. One of Spinoza’s
most comprehensive historical investigations consequently focuses
on the history of the ancient Hebrew commonwealth. By studying
its laws and the decisions of its leaders, he contends, Dutch philoso-
phers such as himself can identify the flaws that led to its downfall
and, thereby enabling the Dutch Republic to avoid the same
mistakes.
The view that Spinoza endorses therefore looks to the history of
philosophy not as a source of self-congratulation or reassurance,
but rather of inspiration. Living philosophers are committed to pro-
moting a way of life in which they pool their insights and help one
another to live as their shared understanding dictates; but part of
this project involves drawing on the theoretical and practical insights
that have come down to us in the works of philosophers, historians,
prophets and rulers. Some of these figures were themselves
124
125