Kibalnik Iftheresimmortality 2016
Kibalnik Iftheresimmortality 2016
Chapter Title: “If there’s no immortality of the soul, . . . everything is lawful”: On the
Philosophical Basis of Ivan Karamazov’s Idea
Chapter Author(s): Sergei A. Kibalnik
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Academic Studies Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
Dostoevsky Beyond Dostoevsky
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
VIII
In its various versions, the popular formula “If there is no God, . . . everything is
lawful” is presented in many of Dostoevsky’s works. It plays an especially signif-
icant role in his novel The Brothers Karamazov. It is commonly known that
Dostoevsky determined “the main question which is asked” to be “the question
of God’s existence” (PSS, 29[1]:117).1 As he confessed, that was the question
that tormented him all his life.
In the second book of Brothers Karamazov, Piotr Miusov recites the words
of Ivan Karamazov, who claimed,
If there is and ever has been any love on earth, this is not from any natural law
but simply because people believed in immortality . . . precisely in this
consists the whole natural law, so that if you destroy humanity’s faith in
immortality, there will immediately dry up in it—not only love but also
every living force necessary to perpetuate life on earth. Even more: there will
1 Dostoevsky, Polnoe sobranie sochinenii v tridtsati tomakh [PSS], ed. V. G. Bazanov et al.
(Leningrad: Nauka, 1972–90); hereafter cited as PSS by volume and page.
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
166 Sergei A. Kibalnik
Robert Louis Jackson shows the dialectics of this motive further developed in
Brothers Karamazov. Let me quote here a long passage from his Dialogues with
Dostoevsky, which will serve as a good introduction to my analysis:
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
“If there’s no immortality of the soul, . . . everything is lawful” 167
Ivan finds nothing in man, no action of the eternal law in man’s conscious-
ness, to counteract his criminal tendencies to guide him toward salvation.
Hence his reliance on an authoritarian church-state. The position of Father
Zosima is quite different. Like Ivan, he believes in a universal church “at the end
of the ages.” In the meanwhile, however, he does not despair. While Ivan places
his hope in social-religious compulsion and excommunication, Zosima believes
in the divine law acting in man and in “the law of Christ expressing itself in the
recognition of one’s own conscience.” Zosima essentially affirms a faith in man’s
conscience, in the possibility of man freely arriving at a sense of truth and good-
ness through his own consciousness.2
Having placed this motive in the framework of Augustinian and Pelagian
theological controversy, Jackson quite reasonably concludes that “Ivan’s posi-
tion would seem to gravitate toward radical Augustinian doctrine, or Jansenism,
according to which post-Fall man lacks the power to abstain from sin and can be
saved only by virtue of God’s grace,” while Zosima’s thought “would seem to
gravitate in the direction of Pelagian doctrine, which places less emphasis on
the original sin and affirms man’s perfect freedom to do right and wrong and, in
the end, to discover his path of salvation.”3 According to Jackson, Ivan’s view-
point also evokes quite reasonable parallels with Thomas Hobbes’s ideas.4 For
her part, Valentina Vetlovskaya, in her commentaries published in the Academy
edition of Dostoevsky’s Complete Works, refers in this regard to Blaise Pascal
(PSS, 15:536). Yet, the question concerning the philosophical basis of this
motive in the framework of nineteenth-century European philosophy that was
contemporaneous for Dostoevsky is still open.
In a way, Ivan Karamazov’s formula (“If there is no God . . .”) already prom-
ises the next step, taken by Nietzsche, who in his The Gay Science, published
after Dostoevsky’s death, declared that “God is dead.” However, there was
another philosopher who, when Dostoevsky was young, claimed that God—at
least in his conventional concept—did not exist, pronouncing religion as the
“objectification” of human consciousness. This was Ludwig Feuerbach. The
above phrase is to be found in his book The Essence of Christianity (1841), of
2 Robert Louis Jackson, Dialogues with Dostoevsky: The Overwhelming Questions (Stanford,
CA: Stanford University Press, 1993), 295–98.
3 Ibid., 298.
4 Ibid., 297.
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
168 Sergei A. Kibalnik
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
“If there’s no immortality of the soul, . . . everything is lawful” 169
claims Stirner, is that “I no longer do anything for it, ‘for God’s sake,’ I do
nothing ‘for man’s sake,’ but what I do I do ‘for my sake’” (158). An introduction
to Stirner’s book concludes with the declaration: “The divine is God’s concern;
the human, man’s. My concern is neither the divine nor the human, not the
true, good, just, free, etc., but solely what is mine, and it is not a general one, but
is—unique, as I am unique. Nothing is more to me than myself!” (18).
The denial of not only God but of Feuerbach’s “God-man,” and the
declaration of “my self-enjoyment,” is the main idea of Stirner’s book. So,
Ivan Karamazov simply reproduces Stirner’s objection to Feuerbaсh when
he declares,
that for every individual, like ourselves, who does not believe in God or
immortality, the moral law of nature must immediately be changed into the
exact contrary of the former religious law, and that egoism, even to crime,
must become not only lawful but even recognised as the inevitable, the most
rational, even honourable outcome of his position. (PSS, 14:64–65)
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
170 Sergei A. Kibalnik
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
“If there’s no immortality of the soul, . . . everything is lawful” 171
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
172 Sergei A. Kibalnik
17 Ludwig Feuerbach (anonymous), “The Essence of Christianity in Relation to The Ego and Its
Own,” trans. Frederick M. Gordon, http://www.lsr-projekt.de/poly/enfeuerbach.html.
18 Fyodor Dostoevsky, A Writer’s Diary, ed. with an introduction by Gary Saul Morson, trans.
and annotated by Kenneth Lantz (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 2009),
1:735–36.
19 Jackson, Dialogues with Dostoevsky, 294.
20 Dostoevsky, Writer’s Diary, 1:736.
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
“If there’s no immortality of the soul, . . . everything is lawful” 173
Ivan insists that love and virtue can come to one only through faith. Zosima,
however, believes that belief in God and faith are inseparable from love. “Try
to love your neighbors actively and ceaselessly,” Zosima counsels Mrs. Khokla-
kova. “To the extent that you succeed in love, you will become convinced in
the existence of God and in the immortality of your soul. But if you reach the
point of total self-renunciation in love for your neighbor, then without ques-
tion you will believe, and no doubt will be able to enter your soul.”22
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
174 Sergei A. Kibalnik
“I love humanity,” he said, “but I wonder at myself. The more I love humanity
in general, the less I love man in particular. In my dreams,” he said, “I have
often come to making enthusiastic schemes for the service of humanity, and
perhaps I might actually have faced crucifixion if it had been suddenly neces-
sary; and yet I am incapable of living in the same room with anyone for two
days together, as I know by experience.” (PSS, 14:53)
Ivan Karamazov says that his Grand Inquisitor has been “loving . . . mankind”
“all [his] life” (PSS, 14:238).
At the end of the novel, Kolya Krasotkin asks Alyosha Karamazov: “It’s
possible for one who doesn’t believe in God to love mankind, don’t you think
so? Voltaire didn’t believe in God and loved mankind?’ (‘I am at it again,’ he
thought to himself.)” Alyosha answers: “Voltaire believed in God, though not
very much, I think, and I don’t think he loved mankind very much either.” The
narrator’s comment on how Alyosha said this is quite remarkable—“quietly,
24 Feuerbach (anonymous), “The Essence of Christianity in Relation to The Ego and Its Own.”
25 Dostoevsky, A Writer’s Diary, 1:736.
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
“If there’s no immortality of the soul, . . . everything is lawful” 175
gently, and quite naturally, as though he were talking to someone of his own age,
or even older. Kolya was particularly struck by Alyosha’s apparent diffidence
about his opinion of Voltaire. He seemed to be leaving the question for him,
little Kolya, to settle” (PSS, 14:500). This comment is in a way analogous to the
title of Dostoevsky’s article “Unsubstantiated Statements,” fairly commented on by
Jackson. Alyosha’s “diffidence” reminds us of Dostoevsky’s proclaiming his own
assertions as “arbitrary.” Both words are aimed at eliminating any pattern of
dogma, which was always alien to the writer. Dostoevsky’s manifestations of
faith were always styled in such a way, both in his literary works and in the Diary
of a Writer. Without sharing Stirner’s anarchical individualism, Dostoevsky
advocates coming back to the “immortality of the soul,” which was rejected by
Feuerbach.
Ivan’s discourse on “if there is no God . . .” clearly fits this pattern. “I don’t
know whether or not it has been sufficiently pointed out that [Ivan’s formula] is
not an outburst of relief or of joy, but rather a bitter acknowledgment of a fact,”
asked Albert Camus, who continued, “The certainty of a God giving a meaning
to life far surpasses in attractiveness the ability to behave badly with impunity.
The choice would not be hard to make. But there is no choice, and that is where
the bitterness comes in.”26 No wonder Jean-Paul Sartre turned Ivan’s statement
upside down. And the essence of existentialism was formulated by Sartre in the
following way: “Nothing will be changed if God does not exist . . . even if God
existed that would make no difference from its point of view. Not that we
believe God does exist, but we think that the real problem is not that of His
existence; what man needs is to find himself again and to understand that
nothing can save him from himself, not even a valid proof of the existence of
God.”27 Ivan Karamazov’s idea, which according to Camus is partly Dostoevsky’s
one, was regarded by Sartre as the starting point of existentialism.
In this respect, both European and Russian existentialism seem to follow
Feuerbach and many other partisans of the Pelagian tradition in European
philosophy rather than Dostoevsky. But as Jackson has shown, according to
26 Albert Camus, The Myth of Sisyphus and Other Essays, trans. Justin O’Brien (1955), 44,
http://www.dhspriory.org/kenny/PhilTexts/Camus/Myth%20of%20Sisyphus-.pdf.
27 Jean-Paul Sartre, “Existentialism Is a Humanism,” in Existentialism from Dostoyevsky to Sartre,
ed. Walter Kaufman, trans. Philip Mairet (Meridian, 1989), https://www.marxists.org/
reference/archive/sartre/works/exist/sartre.htm.
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
176 Sergei A. Kibalnik
Dostoevsky the primary force is love—“not virtue through faith but faith
through love—this is Dostoevsky’s reply to Ivan.”28 So one can say that Sartre
followed Zosima rather than Ivan Karamazov. And thus he still followed
Dostoevsky.
As we can see, the “voices” of Dostoevsky’s characters are to a certain
extent associated with the ideas of European philosophers of the mid-nine-
teenth century. And the twentieth- century European and Russian
philosophers—Nietzsche and Camus, Semion Frank and Sergei Bulgakov—
clearly found their philosophical frameworks in Dostoevsky’s novels.
The complicated dialectics of faith and morality, disbelief and Man-
godhood, love for one’s neighbor and love for mankind in Brothers Karamazov
cannot be understood without taking into account their interdependence with
contemporaneous philosophical discourses.
This content downloaded from 49.37.46.187 on Thu, 22 Feb 2024 18:03:39 +00:00
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms