Archetypes and Architecture Through The
Archetypes and Architecture Through The
ARCHITECTURE
Through the Eyes of
Aldo Rossi & Christian Norberg-Schulz
Paolo Barış
Scrivano Kavraroğlu
Archetypes & Architecture
Through the Eyes of Aldo Rossi &
Christian Norberg-Schulz
A dissertation submitted to the Politecnico di Milano, Milan for the degree of Laurea Ma-
gistrale (Master of Science).
Presented by
Barış Kavraroğlu
Architect, Mimar Sinan University of Fine Arts, Istanbul, Turkey
born in Tarsus, Turkey
July 27, 1994
Supervised by
Prof. Dr. Paolo Scrivano
Milan
2023
Cogito,
ergo sum.
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
The following dissertation has been developed within Architecture
and Urban Design master program, at Politecnico di Milano in Milan
between 2022 and 2023.
I would like to express my deepest gratitude to Paolo Scrivano, who
had been a supportive and patient supervisor. Thanks to his kind, re-
spectful and understanding attitude, I’ve found the opportunity to ex-
press my intentions and ideas freely and comfortably.
A special thanks to my friends, specifically Dipon Bose, Zeki Eneshan
Kavaklı and Nijat Mahamaliyev, who critically went throught the writ-
ings at different stages of the process and assisted me to clarify the
main points of the dissertation.
Finally, I would like to thank my family, my father Hakan Kavraroğlu,
my mother Semiha Kavraroğlu, and my brother and colleague Burak
Kavraroğlu, for their unconditional support.
I
ABSTRACT
The purpose of this dissertation is to investigate the understanding of the
concept of Archetype in the field of architectural theory. Even though the
use of the term type by architectural theorists is a relatively recent phe-
nomenon, which can be traced back to Plato, the idea of Archetype,
as opposed to the explicit use of this term by theorists, has pervaded
much of architectural theory ever since Vitruvius. In fact, many theorists
have been concerned with issues that convey a notion of Archetype,
like the origins of architectural form, the systematization of architectural
knowledge, and the understanding of the process of creativity.
The fundamental premise of this work is that in order to comprehend
the true significance of the concept of Archetype in architecture, it is
necessary to get past some long-held misconceptions that link Arche-
type to the works of particular authors at a certain time. The concept
of the archetype is fundamentally nebulous and challenging to pre-
cisely define, as Quatremère de Quincy notes, “Everything is precise
and given in the model; everything is more or less vague in the type.”
Due to the vagueness of the concept, only a comparative study of the
most relevant ideas formulated in the field of architectural theory can
reveal the essential understanding, or understandings, of Archetype.
This work attempts to provide such a comparative study.
In this regard, our starting point was a comparative study of the writ-
ings of several architectural theorists. By comparing and contrasting
the ideas of these authors, a reference framework for “archetypes”
was developed with the intention of identifying specific informational
patterns. Aldo Rossi and Christian Norberg-Schulz were the two au-
thors whose works we chose to research for this project.
This research’s other goal was to investigate the connection between
the concept of Archetype and the historical development of archi-
tectural form. This work aims to demonstrate how the evolution of ar-
chitectural form and the various understandings that Archetype has
taken on throughout history are inextricably linked. Because of this,
this work is both an investigation into the nature of architectural form
while also serving as a study of the concept of Archetype.
III
CONTENT
01 INTRODUCTION 000
02 ARCHETYPES 008
Archetypes in Architecture 014
03 TWO AUTHORS 038
Biography of Aldo Rossi 040
Biography of Christian Norberg-Schulz 043
Understanding Aldo Rossi 046
Understanding Christian Norberg-Schulz 072
04 RESEMBLANCE & DIVERGENCE 116
Psychology & Phenomenology 124
Meaning: Image, Memory, Locus 134
Physical Elements and Types 158
Living and Rituals 174
05 CONCLUSION 186
V
LIST OF FIGURES
Figure 1.1: Italian honeybee (Apis mellifera Ligustica) comb cell at (a) ‘birth’, and at (b) 2-days old, scale
bar is 2 mm.
Figure 1.2: Alpine Vernacular Architecture.
Figure 1.3: Diagram of Process of Formation of Archetype
Figure 3.1: “The Temple of Juno at Agrigentum”, Caspar David Friedrich, 1830. From the article “Heideg-
ger’s Thinking on Architecture”, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
Figure 3.2: The Collage of Analogous City, Aldo Rossi.
Figure 3.3: Drawings of “Teatro del Mundo”, Aldo Rossi.
Figure 3.4: Drawings of Monument to the Resistance, Cuneo, Aldo Rossi.
Figure 3.5: School-Cemetery [montage] Left: Fagnano Olona School, Right San Cataldo Cemetery, Both
drawings by Aldo Rossi.
Figure 3.6: Façade and Plan Drawings of “Colonnades de la Place Louis XV”, Paris, Quatremère de Quincy
VII
Figure 3.7: Doric Order, “Principi di architettura civile”, Francesco Milizia.
Figure 3.8: A Drawing of Aldo Rossi.
Figure 3.9: Untitled Architectural Drawing, Aldo Rossi.
Figure 3.10: Application of écorché to architectural drawings, examples from the Dictionnaire, Vio-
llet-le-Duc,1875.
Figure 3.11: A Child’s Grave, Hale County, Alabama, 1936, Photo by Walker Evans.
Figure 3.12: Diagrams of “Space cells. Closure, guiding walls”, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
Figure 3.13: Bruder Klaus Field Chapel, Peter Zumthor.
Figure 3.14: The difference between vertical and horiztonal dimension can be observed on a Renais-
sance façade. Palazzo Medici Riccardi, Michelozzo di Bartolomeo, 1396-1472.
Figure 3.15: An example given by Norberg-Schulz, Palomba Sabina, Lazio.
Figure 3.16: Ancient Greek Temple at Paestum, Mahaffy John Pentland,1890.
Figure 3.17: The Roman division in quarters, The Concept of Dwelling, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
Figure 3.18: A photo of Casa Baldi, Paolo Portoghesi.
Figure 3.19: A photo of “Les Espaces d’Abraxas”, Ricardo Bofill.
Figure 3.20: Engravings, “In welchem Style sollen wir bauen?”, Heinrich Hübsch.
Figure 3.21: Drawings of Ancient Egyptian Architecture, “De l’architecture égyptienne”, Quatremère de Quincy.
Figure 3.22: Drawing of Ancient Greek Homes, Jean-Nicolas-Louis Durand,1800.
Figure 3.23: Ancient Roman House, Georg Rehlender, 1894.
Figure 3.24: A photo of Ronchamp chapel, Le Corbusier.
Figure 3.25: Drawings of Trenton Bathhouse, Louis I. Kahn.
Figure 3.26: Plans of “Unité d’Habitation”, Marseille, France, Le Corbusier.
Figure 3.27: Models of sign and symbols, Charles Jencks.
Figure 3.28: Sections (Area I, A–C, 11–7) of the Great Naquane rock. This shows a number of houses
raised on pile foundations (nos. 175, 207, 255) as well as the great maze (no. 270), The Idea of a Town,
Joseph Rykwert.
Figure 3.29: A Diagram of Heidegger’s Concept of Dwelling.
Figure 3.30: Longitudinal section of the old basilica, Rome, Il Tempio Vaticano, Carlo Fontana, 1694.
Figure 3.31: “İki”, Bursa, Turkey, Yıldız Moran, 1955.
VIII
Figure 4.12: Life in a Norwegian, “tun” at the end of the nineteenth century, The Concept of Dwelling,
Christian Norberg-Schulz.
Figure 4.13: The Duck and the Decorated Shed Diagrams, Robert Venturi.
Figure 4.14: The Egyptian grid towns.
Figure 4.15: “On the way to figurative architecture”, Michael Graves. From The Concept of Dwelling,
Norberg-Schulz.
Figure 4.16: A View of Walton Bridge, Canaletto, 1753–1755
Figure 4.17: Therme Vals, Peter Zumthor, Photo by Fernando Guerra.
Figure 4.18: Ayub National Hospital, Dhaka, Bangladesh, Louis I. Kahn, 1962. Photo by Cemal Emden.
Figure 4.19: The simplest model of man’s existential space, Existence, Space and Architecture, Christian
Norberg-Schulz.
Figure 4.20: Aphrodisias, Ara Güler, 1958.
Figure 4.21: Monument to Sandro Pertini, Milan, Aldo Rossi, 1988-90.
Figure 4.22: Stonehenge, Wiltshire, England.
Figure 4.23: In Morning on the River, Jonas Lie,1911-12.
Figure 4.24: The Repetitive images of the German Tudor facades.
Figure 4.25: “The Ideal City”, Fra Carnevale, 1480–1484.
Figure 4.26: Ancient Greek Orders.
Figure 4.27: ”Road to Power” , Serge Najjar, 2011.
Figure 4.28: Sukhala Houses, Gurunsi Villages, Tiebele, Burkina Faso.
Figure 4.29: “A possible beginning for contacts at other levels”, From “Life Between Buildings”, Jan Gehl.
Figure 4.30: House on an island, Ellidaey, Iceland.
Figure 4.31: “Tour de France”, Robert Capa, 1939.
Figure 4.32: Nebelivka Hypothesis, David Wengrow, 18th International Architecture Exhibition of the
Biennale di Venezia.
IX
INTRODUCTION
1
vagueness makes it quite hard to define what an “archetype” is. There
are various studies to achieve such a definition. However, it almost
always ends up with a subjective or arguable conclusion. Needless
to say, although the conclusions are arguable, these studies help us
to get closer to an answer. They pave the way for future research to
better understand the concept of “archetypes” and their relation with
architecture. Thus, a comparative approach to these studies can give
us an idea about different understandings of this vague concept.
2
exactly the case. A study on “Honeybee Combs” in 2013 showed
that actually bees form “circular” cells at first, but in a short time, they
turn into “rounded hexagonal” shapes due to the flow of melting wax.
The excess wax melts due to the body heat of honeybees and the rest
of the wax naturally forms a structurally optimized form in the context
of mechanical integrity.1 Thus, the information we previously related
to the “creative act” of the honeybee turned out to be a combination
of “creative act” and “physical conditions”.
3
Figure 1.2: Alpine Vernacular Architecture.
4
Physical Conditions
4. Giulio C. Argan, “On the Typology of Here, we can observe Argan underlines the reduction of the form from
Architecture,” translated by J. Rykwert, in a “complex of formal variants” to a “common root form”. This process
Theorizing a New Agenda for Architec- of reduction is directly related to the cognitive abilities of the “perceiv-
ture: An Anthology of Architectural Theo-
ry, ed. Kate Nesbit (New York: Princeton ing subject”. Thus, the transformation of the information of “archetypes”
Architectural Press, 1996), 246. is deeply connected to the cognitive processes of human beings.
5
These examples show that there are various aspects of the formation
of archetypes. As we observed in them, the “creative act” and “phys-
ical conditions” are the major elements that shape the archetype.
However, there is another element that should be taken into consid-
eration. This is the “essential act” that leads the subject to a necessity
to take a “creative act” in the first place. “Essential acts” are the rituals
of living in a space that creates the necessity to build. It is the main el-
ement that needs enclosure from the negative “physical conditions”.
On one hand, “essential acts” are related to “creative acts” in the
context of the formation of the “form”. On the other hand, “deriving
subject” mainly builds the “image” of the “form” based on “essential
acts”. Rossi calls these acts “human events”. Norberg-Schulz calls
these acts “human actions”. Kahn calls the space which is specified
for these acts “served spaces”. Semper calls the element that gathers
these acts the “hearth”. These are the acts that create the necessity
to build. Thus, they play an essential role in the formation of “arche-
types”. In this research, we will examine the relation between archi-
tecture, archetypes, and essential acts.
6
derivative act, and essential act- in architecture. It is an important part
of this research to understand how the rituals shaped the architecture
we know today. Also, another important part is to understand the role
of “physical conditions” in the existence of archetypes.
7
ARCHETYPES
9
Figure 2.1: A Photograph of Carl Gustav Jung.
As Jung said, what Plato meant by the concept of “idea” is quite close
to the modern term “archetype”. In his famous allegory of the cave,
9. Carl G. Jung, Four Archetypes, trans.
Plato pointed out that the physical world we perceive is a shadow or R.F.C. Hull (London: Routledge, 2003),
imitation of the true reality. He names these two different sides of exis- 7-8.
10
Figure 2.2: The Fresco of “The School of
Athens” by Italian Renaissance artist Ra-
phael, 1509-1511. Plato(left) and Aristo-
tle(right) are in the center of the painting tence as the world of Forms which is the domain of imitations and the
creating the symmetry to underline the
duality in the intellectual world.
world of Ideas which is the domain of reality. In the article, British his-
torian of philosophy David Sedley explains this notion in this passage:
11
Figure 2.3: A diagram of Carl Jung’s model of psyche.
Figure 2.4: Jung’s diagram of the psyche for one of his private seminars given in English in 1925 for the Psychological Club Zurich.
12
Although Jung directly relates the term “archetype” to Plato’s “Idea”,
his interpretation of the subject is quite different. First and foremost,
Jung considers “archetypes” not as unchangeable and eternal be-
ings, but as derived beings. He explains this point in this passage:
“The archetype does not proceed from physical facts, but de-
scribes how the psyche experiences the physical fact, and in so
11. Plato, “78B–80C: Third Argument. The doing the psyche often behaves so autocratically that it denies
Kinship of Souls and Forms,” Chapter, In
Plato: Phaedo, edited by R. Hackforth, tangible reality or makes statements that fly in the face of it.”14
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1972), 81–86. As we can observe here, Jung considers “archetypes” as an experi-
12. Carl G. Jung, Four Archetypes, trans. ence of reality rather than reality itself. Thus, the existence of “arche-
R.F.C. Hull (London: Routledge, 2003), 8. type” deeply relates to our cognitive abilities.
13. Ibid, 4.
Influenced by Jung’s work on the human psyche, American psycho-
14. Gerhard Adler, R. F. C. Hull, Barbara linguist Noam Chomsky creates the concept of “deep structure” and
Forryan, and Janet M. Glover, eds. Col- “surface structure” to differentiate this new concept from grammar.
lected Works of C.G. Jung, Volume 20:
General Index, (Princeton: Princeton Uni- He introduces these concepts with these words:
versity Press, 1979), 151.
13
“Consequently, the syntactic component of a grammar must
specify, for each sentence, a deep structure that determines
its semantic interpretation and a surface structure- that deter-
mines its phonetic interpretation.”15
In conclusion, the term “archetype” has quite old roots in the history
of humankind. Nonetheless, the popularity and use of the term have
increased in the Modern era. It has been a part of various disciplines.
In the meanwhile, the complexity of the discourse about the term has
evolved as well as its popularity.
16. Ibid, 6.
14
ARCHETYPES IN ARCHITECTURE
The word “type” appears in the stage of history when Johann Guten-
berg invented the modern printing press in 1445. According to Bri-
tannica, this version of the word means “small metal blocks that are
used for printing letters and numbers on paper”.17 In the dissertation
“The Reasoning of Architecture”, Sam Jacoby mentions this notion
with these words: “‘Type’, as Johann Gutenberg’s invention of the
modern printing press with movable types around 1445 demon-
strates, is a medium of non-imitative reproduction.”.18 Thus, the main
feature of the first meaning of the word consists of being “a medium
of non-imitative reproduction”. Jacoby also mentions the background
of the word “typology” in this passage:
15
of their characteristics. Paul-Alan Johnson states, ‘strictly, “typol-
ogy” is the knowledge (-logy, Greek logos) and study of types,
their succession and their meaning or symbolism, the systemics
of types, or the categorical overview of types. […] To say, for
example, that the temple is a “typology” if what is meant is that
it is one type of shrine, or to use “typological” as the adjectival
form instead of “typical” or “typal”, merely confuses.’. He distin-
guishes between type as the general (classifying) term and its
specific meanings as archetype, the original (ideational) pat-
tern for subsequent copies, prototype, the first (material) rep-
resentation of the archetype, and stereotype, the conventional
and continued reproduction of a (proto)type when it becomes
a norm, the average and typical model in use.”21
Here, Jacoby points out that the study of Fréart de Chambray intend-
ed a return to the “authentic” architecture of Greek. Later, Jacoby
mentions two other theorist in this manner:
Jacoby underlines the fact that Blondel and Perrault, which were both
21. Sam Jacoby, “The Reasoning in Ar-
scientists and architects, were criticizing the classical understanding chitecture” (PhD diss., Technical University
of the architecture of the era as being unscientific. Jacoby mentions Of Berlin, 2013), 8.
Blondel’s stance in this passage:
22. Ibid, 34.
16
studies of buildings, François Blondel (1618–1686), the first
professor of architecture in the first state-sponsored school
in France, the Académie Royale d’Architecture, but also a
mathematician and member of the Académie des Sciences,
is predominantly interested in theory. His arguments derive
from the study of texts, especially the Ten Books on Architec-
ture (De architectura, c. 25 BC) by Marcus Vitruvius Pollio,
which he, despite acknowledging a deflection by a Roman
taste, considers as truthful transmission of the Greek orders.”24
Figure 2.7: Archetypical modes of orga-
nization: centrality, axiality and network, For Jacoby, Blondel majorly shapes his stance around the texts of
Norberg-Schulz, Existence; Space & Vitrivius. On the other hand, Perrault takes another stance:
Architecture.
“In contrast to F. Blondel, Claude Perrault (1613–1688), hav-
ing translated Vitruvius’s Ten Books of Architecture into French
in 1673, is impelled to question the authority of the ancients.”25
25. Ibid, 35. On the other hand, Jacoby also mentions that “rationalization” and “stan-
dardization” creates new problems yet to resolve in the architecture:
26. Ibid, 36.
27. Ibid, 42. “Yet the deep ideological divides emerging with the eigh-
17
teenth-century normative debate would remain unresolved
and caused a loss of disciplinary unity. By the early nine-
teenth century the quest for a cohesive French canon waned,
partly due to the impossibility of the ambition itself but also
increasingly displaced by the problems arising from techno-
logical rationalisation and stylistic standardization.”28
As we can see here, Le Roy takes a stance against the Vitruvian un-
derstanding of Greek antiquity. Therefore, he studies Greek antiquity
himself. Similarly to Perrault, Le Roy also mentions the perceptional
aspect of the architecture as well:
18
Figure 2.8: The Architecture Volume
of “Encyclopédie méthodique” and
“Dictionnaire historique d’architecture”
by Antoine Chrysostôme Quatremère de “Examining the historical changes of the temple, Le Roy in-
Quincy.
troduces once more an important diagrammatic plate. Or-
ganised by three columns, he compares the progressive
transformation of the Egyptian and Phoenician, Greek and
Roman, and Christian hut into temples with increasing scale,
complexity, and detail, accompanied by a text explaining
the relation of each example to its evolutionary and typolog-
ical predecessor. The graphical comparison is presented as
objective, ordered by typological and morphological differ-
ences or similarities as they occur relative to each other.”31
19
Figure 2.9: The drawing of “Ensembles D’Edifices” by Jean-Nicolas-Louis Durand.
20
ated. But, apart from the question of the origins, Laugier’s the-
ory of the primitive hut participates in the preoccupation with
perception that dominated the thought of British empiricists in
the preceding century. From this point of view, the cabane can
be understood as the idea that the architect abstracts from the
realm of sensible forms. Laugier’s cabane is, in this regard, a
conceptual construct rather than a sensible one.”33
21
the Mémoire, it redefines the architecture by framing the con-
ditions of invention not as a historical inevitability of progress
but a social effort and achievement. This proclaims a social
thesis very different from the predominantly formal argument of
the Mémoire. De l’architecture égyptienne postulates that form
is essentially metaphysical and unspecific but possesses cultur-
al and social values, thus architecture is a social language.”38
As we can see here, Jacoby points out that the fundamental difference 39. Leandro Madrazo, “The Concept of
between Quatremère and Durand is how they approach the notion of Type in Architecture” (PhD diss., ETH Zu-
rich, 1995), 201.
“invention”. In another article, Jacoby explains this notion with these words:
40. Ibid, 202.
“With history in the natural sciences defined as rational, as
41. Sam Jacoby, “The Reasoning in Ar-
directly linked to verifiable structural development, Durand chitecture” (PhD diss., Technical University
considered the effects of style and character on buildings Of Berlin, 2013), 63.
22
Figure 2.10: Caribbean Hut (The Great Exhibition), Gottfried Semper, The Four Elements of Architecture, 1851
Here, Jacoby points out that Durand prioritizes the “structural rela-
tions” and “material verification of historical progress” over “style”
and “character”. Madrazo mentions this notion in this passage:
23
Figure 2.11: Drawings of “Primitive Hut”.
24
Madrazo noted the translation of the German quotation: “lt is the
first and most important, the moral element of architecture.”. Thus, for
Semper, fundamentally the most important point of architecture is “the
hearth” which gathers the living around itself. The “hearth” is simply the
social aspect of architecture, its true connection to the human being. It
is the center of living, while other elements are surrounding the living
around the “hearth”. In this manner, “hearth” can be considered as an
essential element of architecture among others. Later, Madrazo sums
up the important notions of Semper’s work in this passage:
25
Semper create the basis of modern typology. In the nineteenth centu-
ry, the paradigm of typology shifts from a visual reference to an ab-
stract understanding of “type”. Madrazo mentions this in this passage:
Here, Madrazo points out this shift of theories about the origins of archi-
tectural forms, from the visual similarity, like “primitive hut” and “Greek tem-
ple”, to a contextual approach. In this respect, the works of Viollet-le-Duc
are worth mentioning. Madrazo refers his works with these words:
26
Figure 2.12: The square archetypes
based on Zucker: a) the closed squore,
b) the nuceor squore, c) the dominoted
square and d) the grouped square. In Although Zucker was the first one to mention the “archetype” in archi-
addition, there is the amorphous square
(not shown), Paul Zucker, Town and
tecture, the theory and the discourse expanded among Italian theo-
Square. rists in the 1960s. A typological debate has started and it expanded
the hinterland of typology in architecture. Jacoby mentions this notion
in this passage:
27
Figure 2.13: Volumetric archetypes, project for a school, Leon Krier.
28
azine Casabella Continuità by the time Aldo Rossi started writing.
Before we move further on, with Rossi’s contributions to the discourse,
examining Argan’s perspective would be an appropriate approach
since Rossi was fundamentally influenced by his ideas. .”. In the article
“That Obscure Object of Desire”, Mary Louise Lobsinger underlines
the influence of Quatremère and Argan on Rossi with these words:
29
ing a complex of formal variants to a common root form.”56
30
Figure 2.15: The Site plan of the Cemetery of San Cataldo, Modena, Italy, Aldo Rossi.
31
Figure 2.16: Roosevelt Island Housing Competition, Oswald Mathias Ungers.
32
allelism between Quatremère’s and Rossi’s understanding of “type” at the fun-
damental level. We also understand Rossi considers “type” as a “logical
principle” rather than a particular form. Rossi also states that “type” is the
idea of architecture itself. However, Madrazo also mentions a funda-
mental difference between Quatremère and Rossi:
Madrazo points out the fact that although they share a similar ap-
proach to “type”, the fundamental intention of Rossi is completely dif-
ferent from that of Quatremère.
33
to an ‘anti-intellectual bias’, which lacked a ‘strong tradition
in Modernism’ and belief in ‘the unity of theory and practice
for architectural design’, and when it finally occurred, was
largely dominated by formal research.”64
What Jacoby underlines here is the fact that Ungers understand ar-
chitecture as a concept emerging from art and utility rather than the
traditional visual and compositional values. Later, Jacoby explains
Ungers’ stance further in this passage:
34
Figure 2.17: , Worm’s eye axonometric
of Museum in Merida, Rafael Moneo,
Hand drawn by Stan Allen,1984. logical reasoning signifies to him a creative process that relies
on analogies, images, and metaphors, and is a means of rec-
ognising, in a Goethean sense of morphology, transformable
types and archetypes and ‘defines a way of thinking in basic
all-encompassing contingencies, of having a universal view
of the world of ideas, as well as that of reality’.”67
Jacoby points out the fact that Ungers considers “type” in a much more
dynamic and rich sense rather than stable and reduced stereotypes.
35
“For type to remain relevant, the architectural object must be
considered beyond its singularity through what it has in com-
mon with others, and requires the renewal of its relation to a
formal structure: ‘the old definitions must be modified to ac-
commodate an idea of type that can incorporate even the
present state, where, in fact, subtle mechanisms of relationships
are observable and suggest typological explanations’.”69
36
37
TWO AUTHORS
39
Figure 3.1: “The Temple of Juno at Agri-
an important part in the roots of Norberg-Schulz’s world of ideas. gentum”, Caspar David Friedrich, 1830.
In his writings, he quoted him frequently. In terms of our research, From the article “Heidegger’s Thinking on
Architecture”, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
two main concepts of Heidegger was quite important. One of which
was “nearness”. Nearness was one of the fundamental elements of
his thought world. He explained, depending on the changes, how a
subject experience a spatial relation in terms of practical and per-
ceptional aspects. “Nearness” is what the subject experiences when
these two aspects come together. Thus, it can be related to the role
of rituals in our research. Another important concept of Heidegger
was “dwelling” which can be defined in a very simplified manner as
“living that constantly redefined the environment as a continuation of
the design process”. Thus, the concept of “dwelling” had immense
importance and a deep connection with the subject of our research.
40
of the 20th-century earned him widespread fame and admiration.
Graduating from Politecnico di Milano in 1959, Rossi embarked on
a career that encompassed both practice and academia, leaving an
indelible mark on the world of architecture. He was the first Italian to
receive the Pritzker Prize for architecture. Tragically, his life was cut
short on September 4, 1997, in Milan, Italy, but his legacy continues
to inspire generations of architects and designers.76
77. “Aldo Rossi,” Architectuul, Accessed Rossi’s professional career began to take shape even during his stud-
June 24, 2023, https://architectuul.com/
architect/aldo-rossi. ies. From 1956 to 1957, he had the opportunity to work at the studios
of influential architects and furniture designers Ignazio Gardella and
78. “Aldo Rossi Biography, architecture & Marco Zanuso, gaining practical experience and insights into design
drawings,” Casati Gallery, Accessed June
24, 2023, https://www.casatigallery. and craftsmanship. His early academic engagement came in 1963
com/designers/aldo-rossi/. when he assumed a position as an assistant professor under Ludovico
41
Quaroni at the School of Urban Planning in Arezzo. This marked the
beginning of Rossi’s dual role as both a practitioner and an educator.
In 1965, he became an assistant professor under Carlo Aymonino at
the Institute of Architecture in Venice, further honing his teaching skills
and sharing his architectural vision with a new generation of students.79
In 1979, Rossi was commissioned to design the Teatro del Mondo 83. Ibid.
42
for the Venice Biennale, further solidifying his reputation as a vision-
ary architect. This floating theater, with its enigmatic geometric form,
served as a testament to Rossi’s ability to merge art, architecture, and
theatricality into a single, captivating experience.84
43
showcased Norberg-Schulz’s early talent and innovative design ap-
proach.87
In 1964, Norberg-Schulz obtained his Ph.D. from the Norwegian 88. “Christian Norberg-Schulz,” Large
Norwegian Encyclopedia, Accessed June
Institute of Architecture and Design. His doctoral dissertation, titled 10, 2023, https://snl.no/Christian_Nor-
“Intentions in Architecture,” aimed to establish an open theory of ar- berg-Schulz/.
chitecture adaptable to various contexts. Drawing inspiration from
89. “Norberg-Schulz’s House,” architec-
Gestalt psychology, he emphasized the significance of visual per- ture norway, Accessed June 10, 2023,
ception in architectural design. Norberg-Schulz’s book, published https://www.architecturenorway.no/
the same year, garnered international recognition, establishing him questions/histories/otero-pailos-planet-
veien/.
as an esteemed architectural theorist.91
90. “Christian Norberg-Schulz,” Large
In 1965, Norberg-Schulz ventured into academia as a professor at Norwegian Encyclopedia, Accessed June
10, 2023, https://snl.no/Christian_Nor-
Yale University, where he shared his wealth of knowledge and men- berg-Schulz/.
tored countless aspiring architects. He continued to expand his aca-
demic endeavors by accepting a visiting professorship at Cambridge 91. “Christian Norberg-Schulz,” Architec-
tuul, Accessed June 10, 2023, https://
University in the United States in 1966. Ultimately, he returned to his architectuul.com/architect/christian-nor-
alma mater, the Oslo School of Architecture and Design, where he berg-schulz/.
44
held a professorship from 1966 until his retirement in 1994, leaving
an indelible mark on generations of students.92
45
UNDERSTANDING ALDO ROSSI
Aldo Rossi is one of the first theorists that popularized the term “arche-
type” in the architecture of modern times. Rossi was a multidirectional
architect who expressed and explained himself in different mediums,
such as drawing, writing, and architectural practice.
Despite the fact that these are not all his written works, Rossi has written
two books: “The Architecture of the City” in 1966 and “A Scientific
Autobiography” in 1981. However, Rossi’s life in literature started way
before these books in the late 1950s with Casabella Continuità. Italian
architect Robin M. Graziadei says “Paradoxically, Rossi believed that
through this disassociation of techniques he would be able to get clos-
er to an identification of the creative process with the project in question
than if he were to write purely physical descriptions of projects.”.96
As Rossi writes in The Architecture of the City, “I use the term archi-
tecture in a positive and pragmatic sense, as a creation inseparable
from civilized life and the society in which it is manifested. By nature,
it is collective.”.97 Therefore, for Rossi, collectiveness is a fundamental
element of, not only archetypes as we mentioned before but archi-
tecture as well. Graziadei says “What art and architecture have in
common, says Rossi, is that they are both born in unconscious life.
By reaching into a deep well of personal memories, he describes
his projects not simply as objects, but as labours of love rooted in
his personal history.”.98 Here, we can understand, for Rossi, another
definitive element of architecture is memory.
46
Bandini says “Ludovico Quaroni had a special part to play in Rossi’s
thinking.”.100 However, despite the influence, Rossi’s perspective differ-
entiates from Quaroni’s. Bandini points this out and says “So for Rossi,
to be an architect meant to think about architecture as a field in which
only precise theoretical constructions were permissible, and by saying
this he reduces the lyrical quality of Quaroni’s writing to a few principles
which can hardly capture Quaroni’s rich thought on a human flexible
architecture and its place in the life of a city, an ancient “more beau-
tiful” city” Whose memory should help us to design for the present.”.101
100. Ibid. Later in the book, Rossi also says “Generally, the most difficult histor-
ical problems of the city are resolved by dividing history into peri-
101. Micha Bandini, “Aldo Rossi,” AA Files, ods and hence ignoring or misunderstanding the universal and per-
no. 1 (1981): 106.
manent character of the forces of the urban dynamic; and here the
102. Ibid, 109. importance of a comparative method becomes evident.”.103 Firstly,
he mentions two other main characteristics of archetypes here: uni-
103. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; versality and permanency. However, more importantly, he points out
Original: 1966), 27. that there is a methodological disparity in our approach to under-
47
standing the history of architecture. One of our most efficient tools to
understand a particular era or place is to atomize and categorize
the subject. This kind of practice is mostly focused on the difference
between things. However, since we are looking for similarities and
permanences of differently categorized as we try to understand ar-
chetypes, our mainstream approach doesn’t give proper outcomes
and even creates a perception that all the information comes from this
differentiation ignoring the information that is inherent in the subject.
“In the beginning of a study of the city, we find ourselves con- 105. Seungkoo Jo, “Aldo Rossi: Architec-
ture and Memory,” Journal of Asian Archi-
fronted with two very different positions. These are best ex- tecture and Building Engineering 2, no. 1,
emplified in the Greek city, where the Aristotelian analysis of (2003): 232.
urban reality is counterposed to that of Plato’s Republic.”.107
106. Ibid, 234.
Later in the book, Rossi while explaining the relationship between urban 107. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the City
artifacts and the individual, says “All these experiences, their sum, consti- (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; Origi-
nal: 1966), 23.
tute the city.”.108 Graziedei mentions this idea of Rossi and says “For Rossi,
it is the event that takes place in a building that is architecture, not the inert 108. Ibid 29.
object.”.109 We can understand that he considers the city, not as a phys-
109. Robin M. Graziadei, “The Personal
ical object, but as a perceptional result of physical experiences, which is Universal: On Aldo Rossi’s Autobiogra-
gives us a hint about how he understands the architecture and the city. phy,” Architectural Design, 89 (2019): 63.
48
Figure 3.2: The Collage of Analogous City, Aldo Rossi.
49
As we can see Rossi’s understanding of architecture can be related
to social life and human activity as well as archetypes. He underlines
the relation by saying “I believe that the importance of ritual in its col-
lective nature and its essential character as an element for preserving
myth constitutes a key to understanding the meaning of monuments
and, moreover, the implications of the founding of the city and of the
transmission of ideas in an urban context.”.110 Rossi implies the simi-
larity between myths and architecture by saying that “Myths come
and go, passing slowly from one place to another; every generation
recounts them differently and adds new elements to the patrimony
received from the past; but behind this changing reality, there is a
permanent reality that in some way manages to elude the action
of time.”.111 Therefore, he says, “For if the ritual is the permanent and
conserving element of myth, then so too is the monument, since, in the
very moment that it testifies to myth, it renders ritual forms possible.”,112
and describes the similar role of rituals and monument in the context
of collective memory of a community.
Rossi also mentions about the memory as “an inseparable whole” 116. Ibid, 234.
and says “This inseparable whole is at once the natural and the ar-
117. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the City
tificial homeland of man, and suggests a definition of natural which (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; Origi-
also applies to architecture.”.117 Later in the same chapter, he quotes nal: 1966), 27.
50
from Francesco Milizia: “Although architecture in reality lacks a mod-
el in nature, it has another model derived from man’s natural labor in
constructing his first house.”.118 Especially, here in the last quotation,
we can observe how he relates the concept of “memory” and “ar-
chetype”.
Here, it is important to mention the role of “teatro” and its relation with
memory in Rossi’s understanding of architecture. Jo says “Rossi(1982)
sees the city as the theater of human events, …”.119 He also says “The
locus Rossi defines is the intersection of space, time, form, and site of
a succession of both ancient and more modern events.”.120 We can
see that the allegory of theater has a significant role in Rossi’s under-
standing of architecture. This notion becomes clear with this passage
from Jo’s article:
Here, we can see, much more clearly, Rossi perceives the world as a
theater and considers a deep relation between city and theater since
they are both “locus” of the collective memory. This notion underlines
the importance of a work of Rossi, Teatro del Mundo, which was a
temporary theater building built in 1979 for 1980 Venice Biennale.
Jo says “In the Venice of modern times, Aldo Rossi tried to grasp the
highest reality through a magically activated imagination in his proj-
ect, Teatro del Mundo(1979), where the mind and memory of man
118. Ibid. was considered divine.”.122
119. Seungkoo Jo, “Aldo Rossi: Architecture Rossi often points out connections between architecture and psychol-
and Memory,” Journal of Asian Architec-
ture and Building Engineering 2, no. 1, ogy. Jo says “Rossi stated, the idea of analogy can never be fully
(2003): 233. possessed by the conscious and rational mind, this is what makes it
real to the human psyche.”.123 Rossi mentions about “collective mem-
120. Ibid.
ory” as “the deepest structure of urban artifacts”:
121. Ibid.
“With these considerations we approach the deepest struc-
122. Ibid.
ture of urban artifacts and thus their form -the architecture of
123. Ibid, 234. the city. “The soul of the city” becomes the city’s history, the
sign on the walls of the municipium, the city’s distinctive and
124. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; definitive character, its memory.”124
Original: 1966), 130.
51
Here, we can see a direct connection with the term “deep-structure” in
Jungian psychology, which is defined as the fundamental information
of the Jungian archetypes by Carl Gustav Jung. In the first chapter of the
book “Four Archetypes”, Jung refers to Plato’s “idea” as a similar con-
cept to this “deep structure”. As between Plato’s world of ideas and the
world of forms, the “collective memory” and the “city” can be confused
in Rossi’s work. Rossi responds this confusion with this passage:
“One can say that the city itself is the collective memory of
its people, and like memory it is associated with object and
places. The city is the locus of the collective memory. This re-
lationship between the locus and citizenry then becomes the
city’s predominant image, both of architecture and of land-
scape, and as certain artifacts become part of its memory,
new ones emerge. In this entirely positive sense great ideas
flow through the history of the city and give shape to it.
52
Figure 3.3: Drawings of “Teatro del Mundo”, Aldo Rossi.
53
Figure 3.4: Drawings of Monument to the Resistance, Cuneo, Aldo Rossi.
“We need, as I have said, only consider one specific urban ar- 128. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
tifact for a whole string of questions to present themselves; for it City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
Original: 1966), 29.
is a general characteristic of urban artifacts that they return us to
certain major themes: individuality, locus, design, memory.”.129 129. Ibid, 32.
54
Rossi also talks about the relationship between urban artifacts and
collectiveness, and says “At this point, we might discuss what our idea
of the building is, our most general memory of it as a product of the
collective, and what relationship it affords us with this collective.”.130
Another point he makes about urban artifacts is about the functionality
of the urban artifacts: “In an urban artifact, certain original values and
functions remain, others are totally altered; about some stylistic aspects
of the form we are certain, others are less obvious.”.131 Here, he points
out that the original and first functionality of an urban artifact is not an
inherent feature. Jo mentions this notion and says “Rossi(1982) makes
the observation that forms have an autonomous life which supersedes
the functions for which they were designed.”.132 Later in the same arti-
cle, Jo also says “Rossi argued that architecture should achieve formal
autonomy, to gain identity, in order to meaningfully relate and to con-
vey meaning.”.133 Later, he talks about the relationship between urban
artifacts and the individual: “If one takes any urban artifact -a building,
a street, a district- and attempts to describe it, the same difficulties
arise which we encountered earlier with respect to the Palazzo della
Ragione in Padua. Some of these difficulties derive from the ambiguity
of language, and in part these difficulties can be overcome, but there
will always be a type of experience recognizable only to those who
have walked through the particular building, street or district.”.134 As he
pointed out while he was defining the “city”, he underlines the phe-
nomenological aspect of this interaction between the artifacts and the
subject. In the following sentence, he also mentions about the subjec-
130. Ibid, 29. tivity of this kind of experience: “Thus, the concept that one person has
of an urban artifact will always differ from that of someone who “lives”
131. Ibid, 29. that same artifact.”.135 Graziadei mentions this idea and says “For Ros-
132. Seungkoo Jo, “Aldo Rossi: Architec- si, it is to childhood that the phenomenological separation between
ture and Memory,” Journal of Asian Archi- the self and the world can be traced, and this is the separation experi-
tecture and Building Engineering 2, no. 1, enced by the architect between the project as merely a representation
(2003): 234.
and the project as a completed and lived building.”.136
133. Ibid.
While he describes the “city”, he quotes from French anthropologist
134. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; and ethnologist Lévi-Strauss and, says “Setting forth the problem in
Original: 1966), 33. this manner, Claude Lévi-Strauss brought the study of the city into a
realm rich with unexpected developments. He noted how, more than
135. Ibid, 33.
other works of art, the city achieves a balance between natural and
136. Robin M. Graziadei, “The Personal artificial elements; it is an object of nature and subject of culture.”.137
is Universal: On Aldo Rossi’s Autobiogra- Here, he mentions this notion of balance between naturality and ar-
phy,” Architectural Design, 89 (2019): 63.
tificiality, nature and culture. This notion is later mentioned in another
137. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the City paragraph: “It is in this sense not only the place of the human condi-
(Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; Origi- tion, but itself a part of that condition, and is represented in the city
nal: 1966), 33.
and its monuments, in districts, dwellings, and all urban artifacts that
138. Ibid. emerge from inhabited space.”.138 Here, there is an important point.
55
He points out that “urban artifacts” emerge from “inhabited space”.
Thus, he describes “urban artifacts” as a perceptional thing that is
surrounded by the life, not as a physical object of its own. Also, this
point also can be related to Heidegger’s concept of “dwelling” and
“building”.
56
Figure 3.5: School-Cemetery [montage] Left: Fagnano Olona School, Right San Cataldo Cemetery, Both drawings by Aldo Rossi.
57
Figure 3.6: Façade and Plan Drawings of “Colonnades de la Place Louis XV”, Paris, Quatremère de Quincy
58
Here, we can understand that Argan considers “type” as a vague
and derived concept which is developed from a “series of instances”.
He also mentions “type” as a “reduced” concept:
Here, we can sense the roots of the concept of “event” and “sign”
in Rossi’s architectural perspective. We can see it in a more direct
manner in Lobsinger’s these words: “For Argan, the past is neutralized
in type as an “absolute within the present,” and thus type presents
the past as a historical abstract form in the present.”.151 Graziadei
mentions this notion and says “For Rossi, cities are places for both the
living and the dead, where fragments and elements of the dead act
as signals and warnings to the living.”.152
59
ture is even better individuated at the urban level.
60
Figure 3.7: Doric Order, “Principi di architettura civile”, Francesco Milizia.
61
Figure 3.8: A Drawing of Aldo Rossi.
62
contains natural artifacts as well as civic ones and becomes
associated with the composition of the city. In the urban
composition, everything must express as faithfully as possible
the particular life of the collective organism. At the basis of
this organism that is the city is the persistence of the plan.
63
at a certain moment. I maintain, on the contrary, that the
city is something that persists through its transformations, and
that the complex or simple transformations of functions that it
gradually undergoes are moments in the reality of its struc-
ture.”162
Later, Rossi examines the role of persistence with a question: “In what
way did the ancient city become the origin of the modern city?”.164 This
comparison leads him to an answer, “Such a transformation could not
have occurred except within or around the ancient cities, since these
represented a man-made complex, a halfway point between artifice
and nature, meaning to give permanences: they are a past that we are
still experiencing.”.165 Then he explains his perspective through the theory
of Poëte in the context of “persistences”:
“Poëte’s theory is not very explicit on this point, but I will try to
summarize it briefly. Although he presents a number of hypoth-
eses among which are economic considerations that relate to
the evolution of the city, it is in substance a historical theory cen-
tered on the phenomenon of “persistences.” These persistences
are revealed through monuments, the physical signs of the past,
as well as through the persistence of a city’s basic layout and
plans. This last point is Poëte’s most important discovery. Cities 162. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
tend to remain on their axes of development, maintaining the City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
Original: 1966), 55-56.
position of their original layout and growing according to the
direction and meaning of their older artifacts, which often ap- 163. Ibid, 56.
pear remote from present-day ones. Sometimes these artifacts
164. Ibid, 57.
persist virtually unchanged, endowed with a continuous vitality;
other times they exhaust themselves, and then only the perma- 165. Ibid, 57-59.
64
Figure 3.9: Untitled Architectural Drawing, Aldo Rossi.
nence of their form, their physical sign, their locus remains. The
most meaningful permanences are those provided by the street
and the plan. The plan persists at different levels; it becomes
differentiated in its attributes, often deformed, but in substance,
it is not displaced. This is the most valid part of Poëte’s theory;
even if it cannot be said to be completely a historical theory, it is
essentially born from the study of history.”166
65
Figure 3.10: Application of écorché to architectural drawings, examples from the Dictionnaire, Viollet-le-Duc,1875.
66
tions of a city to search a definition for “primary elements”: “When
we study a city, we find that the urban whole tends to be divided
according to three principal functions: housing, fixed activities, and
circulation.”.171 One of these functions is, later, he relates with “prima-
ry elements”. This function is “fixed activities”. He explains this term:
““Fixed activities” include stores, public and commercial buildings,
universities, hospitals, and schools. In addition, the urban literature
also speaks of urban equipment urban standards, services, and infra-
structures.”.172 Later, he explains the relation between “fixed activities”
and “primary elements” as well:
171. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the City In the context of value among primary elements, Rossi puts “monu-
(Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; Origi- ments” before anything else. He explains this with these words: “A
nal: 1966), 86.
monument stands at a center. It is usually surrounded by buildings and
172. Ibid. becomes a place of attraction. We have said that it is a primary ele-
ment, but of a special type: that is, it is typical in that it summarizes all of
173. Ibid.
the questions posed by the city, but it is special because by virtue of its
174. Ibid, 87. form its value goes beyond economics and function.”.175 The reason-
ing behind this is later explained in the “Locus” chapter of Rossi’s book.
175. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; However, before this explanation, the importance of the relation be-
Original: 1966), 92. tween the city and the history in Rossi’s work should be understood:
67
“The history of the city is always inseparable from its geog-
raphy; without both we cannot understand that architecture
that is the physical sign of this “human thing”. “The art of ar-
chitecture,” wrote Viollet-le-Duc, “is a human creation,” and
again, “Architecture, this human creation, is, in fact, only an
application of principles born outside us and which we ap-
propriate to ourselves by observation.” These principles are
in the city; the stone landscape of building -of “brick and
mortar,” in C.B. Fawcett’s expression- symbolizes the conti-
nuity of a community.”176
68
Figure 3.11: A Child’s Grave, Hale County, Alabama, 1936, Photo by Walker Evans.
69
buried here.”. That is architecture.” The mound six feet long *The Italian fatto urbano comes from the
French faite urbaine. Neither the Italian
and three feet wide is an extremely intense and pure archi- nor the English translation “urban artifact”
tecture precisely because it is identifiable in the artifact. It is (also used by Sir John Summerson in an
only in the history of architecture that a separation between essay of 1963 entitled “Urban Forms,”
see note 7, chapter l) adequately renders
the original element and its various forms occurred. From this the full meaning of the original, which im-
separation, which the ancient world seemingly resolved for- plies not just a physical thing in the city,
ever, derives the universally acknowledged character of per- but all of its history, geography, structure,
and connection with the general life of
manence of those first forms.”183 the city. This meaning is the one intended
throughout this book.
Another important primary element in Rossi’s perspective is “plan”. -Ed.
Before he starts describing the role of plan as a primary element in
the city, he explains the architectural and urban stance towards the
“plan”: “We know that many geographical or urbanistic texts classify
cities into two large families: planned and unplanned. “In urban stud-
ies it is usual to emphasize as primary the difference between planned
and unplanned towns. The former has been conceived and founded
as towns, whereas the latter have emerged without conscious plan-
ning. They are settlements that have grown and been adapted to
discharge urban functions. Their urban character has appeared in
the course of their growth, and their layout is essentially the product
of accretion of buildings about some pre-urban nucleus.” Thus writes
Arthur E. Smailes in his text on urban geography, as have many oth-
ers.”.184 After this short explanation, he explains his perspective: “Con-
sequently, I consider the plan to be a primary element, the equal of a
monument like a temple or a fortress. The nucleus of a planned city is
itself also a primary element; it does not matter whether it initiates an
urban process or characterizes it, as in Leningrad or in Ferrara. The
notion that the existence of a plan makes for a rigidly defined spatial
solution of a city from an overall perspective is very much debatable;
the plan is always but one moment of the city in the same way that
any other primary element is.”.185 Here, we can understand that the
value of the plan is not directly related to the order it brings to the
city, rather its value comes from the epochal and temporal features
of the plan which marks a specific timeframe in the city as it continues
to change and develop. He underlines this notion with these words:
70
that show their direct connection to man. For the elements constitut-
ing the city -these urban artifacts which are by nature characteristic
and characterizing and as much a product of human activity as a
collective artifact- are among the most authentic human testimonies.
Naturally when we speak of these artifacts we are speaking of their
architecture, their meaning as a human creation.”.187 In this relation
between the urban artifacts and humankind, we understand a rela-
tion that works in both ways. Rossi describes this notion with a quo-
tation from a French scholar who was criticizing the French university:
“It is the architectural nothingness of the French university which made
me understand its intellectual and spiritual nothingness.”.188 Here, we
can understand that Rossi perceives architecture as a reflection of the
representation of humankind. Graziedei says “For Rossi, the pursuit of
architectural representation is in itself a way of addressing the issue
of mortality.”.189 Rossi sums this up in this passage: “I am not speaking
of the monumental character of these works of architecture, nor of
their stylistic aspects: I refer to their presence, their construction, their
history, in other words, to the nature of urban artifacts. Urban artifacts
have their own life, their own destiny.”.190
We can see Rossi goes on particular patterns over and over again.
There are two main concepts in his understanding of the city: “city as
a man-made object” and “city as a work of art”.
71
of a series of values. Thus it concerns the collective imagina-
tion. Clearly the first and second approaches are intimately
linked, so much so that the facts they uncover may at times be
confounded with each other. Athens, Rome, Constantinople,
and Paris represent ideas of the city that extend beyond their
physical form, beyond their permanence; thus we can also
speak in this way of cities like Babylon which have all but
physically disappeared.”191
One may ask “What is the relation between “urban artifacts” and
“city as a work of art”?” or “in which context are these related?”. He
explains how he relates the “urban artifacts”* and “city as a work of
art” in the first chapter of the book:
72
UNDERSTANDING CHRISTIAN NORBERG-SCHULZ
73
In Norberg-Schulz’s work, the effect of “psychology” can be ob-
served as well. He was specifically interested in “Gestalt psychol-
ogy” which is a school of psychology founded in 20th-century. It
provided the foundation of the modern study of “perception”. In the
dictionary of Britannica, it is described with these words:
In the article “The Heaven, the Earth and the Optic Array”, Akkelies van
Nes mentions this interest and says “Literature and art, phenomenology,
and Gestalt Psychology influence Norberg-Schulz’s work.”.200 Haddad
also mentions this interest in his article and says “Norberg-Schulz’s dis-
cussion of perception was largely influenced by Gestalt psychology, to
which were also added the socialization of perception and the process
of ‘‘schematization’’, that is the way in which perception leads to the con-
struction of an understanding of the world, based on the pioneering stud-
ies of Jean Piaget in child psychology.”.201 As Haddad mentions, Nor-
berg-Schulz’s works are also affected by Swiss psychologist Jean Piaget.
Piaget’s theory suggests that children actively construct their understanding
of the world through a series of stages, which are characterized by distinct
cognitive abilities and ways of thinking. According to Piaget, individuals
199. “Gestalt psychology,” Britannica, Ac-
actively construct their schemata through their interactions with the envi- cessed June 2, 2023, https://www.britan-
ronment. Initially, children have very basic schemata, but as they interact nica.com/science/Gestalt-psychology.
with and learn about the world, these schemata become more complex
200. Akkelies van Nes, “The Heaven,
and sophisticated. Schemata can be thought of as mental categories that the Earth and the Optic Array: Nor-
allow us to organize and interpret incoming information. They help us berg-Schulz’s Place Phenomenology and
recognize patterns, make predictions, and understand new experiences its Degree of Operationability,” Footprint
3 (2008): 114.
based on our existing knowledge. “Schemata” exists for various domains,
such as objects, actions, relationships, and concepts. Piaget proposed 201. Elie Haddad, “Christian Nor-
that cognitive development involves two important processes: assimilation berg-Schulz’s Phenomenological Project In
Architecture,” Architectural Theory Review
and accommodation. Assimilation occurs when individuals incorporate 15, no. 1 (2010): 89.
new information into existing schemata.202
202. Jean Piaget, The Construction Of Re-
ality In The Child, (New York : Ballantine
Norberg-Schulz was also affected by “semiology” which means “the Books, 1971), 395-402.
study of signs and sign-using behaviour” according to Britannica Dictio-
nary.203 In the article, Haddad says “This theory, influenced to a large 203. “semiotics,” Britannica, Accessed
June 2, 2023, https://www.britannica.
extent by Charles Morris’s interpretation of semiotics, constituted a similar com/science/semiotics.
attempt to develop a comprehensive structure—that is, an “architectural
totality” that would account for all the dimensions of architecture: the tech- 204. Elie Haddad, “Christian Nor-
berg-Schulz’s Phenomenological Project In
nical structure, environment, context, scale and ornament.”.204 In a book Architecture,” Architectural Theory Review
review of “Architecture: Meaning and Place”, Linda Krause sums up Nor- 15, no. 1 (2010): 89.
74
Figure 3.12: Diagrams of “Space cells. Closure, guiding walls”, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
In the later years of his career, he was also influenced by the book “The
Language of Architecture Postmodern” which was published in 1977 by
Charles Jencks. With this impact, he joined Po-Mo with enthusiasm and
excitement for new possibilities of expression. However, his excitement
didn’t last long. In the 1990s, due to the growing isolation of Postmodern
Movement, by pronouncing that it “was dissolved in playful superficiali-
ty”, he returned to a major study of fundamentals of modernity which we
later see in his last book “Principles of Modern Architecture”.206
75
Figure 3.13: Bruder Klaus Field Chapel, Peter Zumthor.
76
Therefore, despite the difficulty, he considers “phenomenology” and
“grammar” as crucial necessities of architectural practice.
77
The vertical axis, the axis mundi, is therefore an arche-
typal symbol of a passage from one cosmic region to
another. If verticality has something surreal about it, the
horizontal directions represent man’s concrete world of
action . . . The simplest model of man’s existential space
is then a horizontal plane pierced by a vertical axis. On
the plane man chooses and creates paths which give
his existential space a more particular structure.
78
Figure 3.14: The difference between
vertical and horiztonal dimension can
be observed on a Renaissance façade.
Palazzo Medici Riccardi, Michelozzo di as a concretization of environmental schemata or images, which form a
Bartolomeo, 1396-1472.
necessary part of man’s general orientation or “being in the world”.”.216
As we can see Haddad understands this notion of “being in the world”
as a “move towards a phenomenological approach”.
79
Figure 3.15: An example given by Norberg-Schulz, Palomba Sabina, Lazio.
80
Stimmung. This German word means something like “atmosphere” or
“character”, and moreover it says that man is gestimmt, “tuned”, by his
environment.”.220 Here, we encounter with a new term “Stimmung”
which is a German word for “atmosphere” as it says in the passage
as well. This term for “atmosphere” is also a commonly used word in
the phenomenological approach in architecture. In the article “Heide-
gger’s Thinking on Architecture”, Norberg-Schulz explains the term
“inhabited landscape” and says “An inhabited landscape obviously
is a known landscape, that is, something that is gewohnt. This land-
scape is brought close to us by the buildings, or in other words, the
landscape is revealed as what it is in truth.”.221 In the book “Christian
Norberg-Schulz’s Interpretation of Heidegger’s Philosophy”, Hendrik
Auret says “Christian Norberg-Schulz’s stedskunst mined the poetic
depths of understanding lived space in terms of Heidegger’s notion
of place. However, when it came to understanding the nature of lived
time, he relied on Sigfried Giedion’s formulation of time as continuity
and change.”.222 Thus, we can observe here how Norberg-Schulz
brings together the “locality” and “phenomenology” with the “bridge”
of Heidegger’s ideas. This notion will be clearer later in his book.
81
“According to Gunila Jiven and Peter Larkham’s reading of
Genius Loci, four “thematic levels” can be recognized in
Norberg-Schulz’s treatment of the concept of genius loci.
These are:
1. “the topography of the earth’s surface”;
2. “the cosmological light conditions and the sky as natural
conditions”;
3. “buildings”; and
4. “symbolic and existential meanings in the cultural land-
scape”.”226
82
Figure 3.16: Ancient Greek Temple at Paestum, Mahaffy John Pentland,1890.
83
Figure 3.17: The Roman division in quarters, The Concept of Dwelling, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
84
that nothing is present to me.”. 231 Here, we can understand his basis of a
“thing” is an interaction or a reflection it creates with the subject.
Here, we can understand that he sees a great value in the cultural and
geographical traditions of building knowledge which is accumulated
over a long time by the collective experience of the communities. After
this passage, he directly points out his stance on this notion:
233. Ibid, 139. Here, we can understand Norberg-Schulz considers the “phenom-
enological” approach as a better alternative to the “analytic” and
234. Ibid, 139.
“abstractive” approach like Bauhaus. In his review of “Genius Loci”,
235. Ibid, 139. Harris Forusz underlines this notion with these words:
85
“The appeal that Christian Norberg-Schulz makes is that af-
ter decades of abstract, “scientific” theory it is urgent that we
return to a qualitative, phenomenological understanding of
architecture. The intent of this theoretical approach, which
draws on Norberg-Schulz’s broad experiences and exten-
sive knowledge base, is to reveal the “spirit of place,” which
he names from Classical Roman sources, “genius loci”.”236
86
Figure 3.18: A photo of Casa Baldi, Paolo Portoghesi.
87
Figure 3.19: A photo of “Les Espaces d’Abraxas”, Ricardo Bofill.
mentality two aspects of one general problem: the need for meaning
in architecture.”.243 After this, he underlines an important notion in Sig-
fried Giedion’s approach to regionalism in this passage:
88
wrote, “that is architecture.”.”.245 He starts by drawing our attention
to the necessity of “meaning” in architecture. Wilken underlines this
notion and says “Norberg-Schulz’s overarching claim is that “when
all the components seem to embody basic existential meanings, we
may talk about a ‘strong’ place”.”.246 Forusz mentions this notion with
these words: “Norberg-Schulz believes that beyond the pragmatic
and the experiential aspects of architecture there is a specific need
for a metaphysical belief in architecture, an aspect which can con-
tribute to the architect’s understanding of the existential “meaning” of
place.”.247 Almost referring to these “metaphysical” aspect of archi-
tecture, Norberg-Schulz continues with a quotation from Giedion:
89
house of Being”, Heidegger says, and, “man speaks only as he re-
sponds to language”.”.252 Thus, he considers “language” as kind of a
reference system to “be” and to “express”, in the most general terms.
Here, there are a few points that need explanation. One of which
is the meaning of “Ding an sich”. It is a term in Kantian philosophy
that means “the-thing-in-itself” in German. Another point is the fact
that Norberg perceives the “archetype” as an abstract idea, rather
than a material being. Then, he explains his stance on architectural
language and style:
“There can only be one architectural language, since there is
only one world and spatiality. (Analogously there is basically
only one spoken language, although there are many “tongues”.)
The styles represent different choices within the one and same
language, or, in Heidegger’s terms, different responses to Lan-
guage. Thus we have three systems of images:
language, which consists of invariant archetypes,
style, which is a temporal choice among the archetypes, and
tradition, which is a local adaptation of the archetypes.”254
90
Figure 3.20: Engravings, “In welchem Style sollen wir bauen?”, Heinrich Hübsch.
91
Figure 3.21: Drawings of Ancient Egyptian Architecture, “De l’architecture égyptienne”, Quatremère de Quincy.
92
related to Aristotelian philosophy. Here, he takes a dualist stance on this
notion and says, “In a certain sense both hypotheses are correct.”, which
is an important point to understand. In his explanation, on the one hand,
archetypes are “interworldly” structures that are not present in the phys-
ical world, just like Plato’s world of ideas. On the other hand, types are
“developed” and “changed” with “experience” and “experiment”. Later,
he says “Modern architecture wanted to return to the “beginning as if
nothing had ever been done before”. One did not recognize, however,
that this can only mean a new interpretation of the archetypes.”.258 Here,
we can see that his understanding of archetypes are as a fundamental
component of architecture as we mentioned before. Thus, he criticizes
“functionalism” for denying this notion, and says: “Functionalism, thus, did
not accept the existential roots which give architecture its meaning.”.259
93
axial causeway, which gives directed movement concrete
presence. Finally, Egyptian architecture realized the obvious
complement to the desert: the artificial oasis of the walled en-
closure. A comprehensive inventory of archetypal forms is thus
set into work: grid, path, center and enclosure.”260
Here, he underlines the “order” as a well-known feature of Ancient 260. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of
Greek architecture. He relates the “order” in architecture to the or- Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
der of a culture. This order is deeply related to the “meaning”. Nor- 1988), 157.
berg-Schulz explains this notion and he says, “In the temple, the order 261. Elie Haddad, “Christian Nor-
plays a constituent role, that is, the character it embodies is given a berg-Schulz’s Phenomenological Project In
“pure”, dominant presence. In other Greek buildings the orders are Architecture,” Architectural Theory Review
15, no. 1 (2010): 93.
rather used as “characterizing elements” which do not constitute the
structure, but relate it to a world of meanings.”.264 Norberg-Schulz 262. Linda Krause, Journal of the Soci-
considers this notion as a significant point to understanding the rela- ety of Architectural Historians 50, no. 2
(1991): 197.
tion between “locality” and “universality” of architecture. He explains
this with a quotation from Heidegger: 263. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of
Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
1988), 157.
“The orders endowed Greek building with the concrete
presence of a “thing”. “Thinking is the nearing of the world”, 264. Ibid.
94
Figure 3.22: Drawing of Ancient Greek Homes, Jean-Nicolas-Louis Durand,1800.
“We understand that the spatial types remain mute until they are
“set back on earth” and given presence by means of the orders.
Thus “the temple, in its standing there, first gives to things their look
and to men their outlook on themselves”, Heidegger says.”267
95
Figure 3.23: Ancient Roman House, Georg Rehlender, 1894.
96
Here, he underlines the relation between Greek and Roman archi-
tecture. He also creates a continuous connection from Ancient Greek
architecture to Western architecture which he will further develop lat-
er in the book. Then, he explains the importance of “basilica” in the
context of this continuity:
Here, we can see there are several features and orders of the Roman
“basilica” and “rotunda” that inspired the Christian churches. Thus, Nor-
berg-Schulz considers there is a great value in such relation in architec-
ture in the course of history. He underlines this notion with these words:
“Thus a temporal understanding of a complete world of earth, sky, man
and divinity is concretized, and architecture becomes a true imago
mundi.”.273 Here, we understand Norberg-Schulz sees architecture as
a tool that “concretizes” the periodical understanding and meaning of
existence and carries it through time, thus, giving us a chance to see the
whole. After this standpoint, he continues to example:
97
fore most divine form is the circle, and centralized buildings
therefore came to visualize cosmic order.”274
98
Figure 3.24: A photo of Ronchamp chapel, Le Corbusier.
ing us, but still, it remains unique solution without typological value.”.277
Thus, he accepts there were interpretations to create an “architectur-
al image”, however, it remained in unique solutions which we can-
not benefit from in a typological way, as exampled in Ancient Greek
architecture. He determines the problem of Modern architecture on
the “architectural image” as lack of holistic approach in architecture
and he says “Thus modern architecture tended to oscillate between
abstract generalization and atypical particularization.”.278
99
Figure 3.25: Drawings of Trenton Bathhouse, Louis I. Kahn.
from the destruction of the “urban fabric” to the loss of character and
place.”.282 Thus, Norberg-Schulz underlines the necessity of arche-
types in such architecture through a quotation by Louis I. Kahn:
100
In this manner, Norberg-Schulz mentions two architects that he ad-
mires their works in this context in this sentence:
Haddad mentions this connection and says “…he joined Venturi, Ja-
cobs, and Rossi in criticizing Modern Architecture for its shortcomings,
especially at the level of the urban environment.”.286 He, later, explains
the value he sees in their works. Firstly, he explains the value of Venturi’s
work, and he says “The resulting independence of form and function is
in the interest of a more effective functionalism, because our “allowing
form and function to go their separate ways permits function to be truly
functional.”.287 Thus, he considers there is a great value and potential
for a typical architectural image in the separation of “form” and “func-
tion”. Also, there are methodological similarities in Norberg-Schulz’s
work to Venturi’s. Haddad says “As in the case of Venturi, but using a
different approach, Norberg-Schulz returned to history in its wider
sense to give comparative examples of buildings, towns and land-
scapes as examples that naturally incorporate these qualities of ‘‘ex-
istential space’’, creating meaningful and wholistic environments.”.288
Later, Norberg-Schulz underlines the work of Rossi and says “His point
of departure is a wish for a typology which is commonly understand-
able and which may help us to recover the city as a “work of art”.”.289
285. Ibid. He also underlines the importance of the distinction between “type”
and “model” which was pointed out by Rossi for the first time. Also, in a
286. Elie Haddad, “Christian Nor-
berg-Schulz’s Phenomenological Project In previous passage, Norberg says “When an architectural image unites
Architecture,” Architectural Theory Review spatial and plastic qualities, it becomes an “architectural thing” which
15, no. 1 (2010): 91. forms part of a work of architecture.”.290 This term “architectural thing” is
287. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of quite relatable when we consider Rossi’s term “urban artifact”.
Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
1988), 169. However, Norberg-Schulz also criticizes Rossi and explains the im-
288. Elie Haddad, “Christian Nor- perfections he sees: “Although some of them are given slight overtones
berg-Schulz’s Phenomenological Project In of local memories, they are not articulated with reference to earth and
Architecture,” Architectural Theory Review sky. Rather they seems to exist in a realm which is outside time and
15, no. 1 (2010): 91.
place.”.291 Then, he also says “The embodiment in the here and now
289. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of is almost entirely lacking, and thus his compositions do not allow for
Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita, orientation and identification, and for life to take place.”.292 Here we
1988), 169.
can understand Norberg-Schulz considers the relation with the place
290. Ibid, 153. as an essential value in architecture, and he opposes an approach
that abstracts and isolates the architecture from the place. He ends this
291. Ibid, 175.
chapter of “New Monumentality” underlining this stance:
292. Ibid, 175.
101
“Typology is not architecture, and before it can become a
useful aid in our pursuit of meaning, it has to be freed from the
rationalists’ world of abstractions and brought back to the con-
crete world of phenomena. This does not mean that we con-
sider the language of types a matter of mere feeling, but rather
that it ought to get an existential foundation, where thinking and
feeling are united, through a phenomenological understand-
ing of the world which relates the given to the archetypes.”293
102
Figure 3.26: Plans of “Unité d’Habitation”, Marseille, France, Le Corbusier.
103
Figure 3.27: Models of sign and symbols, Charles Jencks.
At this point of the chapter, Norberg-Schulz points out the most important 303. Ibid, 179.
104
notion to understand what he means by “visualization” and “complemen-
tation”. He starts with a poem of Heidegger, named “The Thinker as Poet”:
“Forests spread
Brooks plunge
Rocks persist
Mist diffuses
Meadows wait
Springs well
Winds dwell
Blessings muses”304
105
this structured emptiness, architecture has to adapt to the spatiality of
human life itself.”.307 Here, he underlines the importance of the living
and the rituals around a built environment. Also, he considers that ar-
chitecture should adapt to such a living. Then he connects this notion
with the concept of “place” in this passage:
106
Figure 3.28: Sections (Area I, A–C,
11–7) of the Great Naquane rock. This
shows a number of houses raised on pile
himself when he settles, and his being-in-the-world is thereby deter-
foundations (nos. 175, 207, 255) as well mined.”.311 He also says “When settling is accomplished, other modes
as the great maze (no. 270), The Idea of of dwelling which concern basic forms of human togetherness, come
a Town, Joseph Rykwert.
into play.”.312 Thus, “settlement” is the fundamental mode of dwelling
that opens up the possibility of other modes. Another mode of “dwell-
ing” is “collective dwelling” which is represented by “urban space” in
the book. Norberg-Schulz says “In urban space man “dwells” in the
sense of experiencing the richness of a world. We may call this mode
collective dwelling, using the word “collective” in the original sense
of gathering or assembly.”313 Another mode of “dwelling” is “public
dwelling” which is represented by “institution” in the book. Norberg
311. Christian Norberg-Schulz, The Con- Schulz says “Agreement thus implies common interests or values, and
cept of the Dwelling: On the Way to Fig-
urative Architecture (New York: Rizzoli, forms the basis for a fellowship or society. An agreement also has to
1985), 13. “take place,” in the sense of possessing a forum where the common
values are kept and expressed. Such a place is generally known as
312. Ibid.
an institution or public building, and the mode of dwelling it serves
313. Ibid. we may call public dwelling, using the word “public” to denote what
107
Figure 3.29: A Diagram of Heidegger’s Concept of Dwelling.
108
is shared by the community.”.314 Last but not least, another mode of
“dwelling” is “private dwelling” which is represented by “house” in the
book. Norberg-Schulz explains this and says “Choices, however, are
also of a more personal kind, and the life of each individual has its
particular course. Dwelling therefore also comprises that withdrawal
which is necessary to define and develop one’s own identity. We may
call this mode private dwelling, intending those actions which are se-
cluded from the intrusion of others.”.315 Thus, we can understand how
Norberg-Schulz categorizes different types of “dwelling” processes.
315. Ibid. He further explains this notion with the elements he presented in this
chapter and brings everything together in this passage:
316. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of
Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
1988), 179. “Thus the house primarily complements the lacks of the site and
makes what is close at hand emerge. It constitutes a concrete,
317. Elie Haddad, “Christian Nor- individual “here”, and allows life to take place “now”. In the
berg-Schulz’s Phenomenological Project In
Architecture,” Architectural Theory Review past, however, the concrete “here” became typical, because
15, no. 1 (2010): 90. “neighbourly dwelling” implied the sharing of a site and a
109
way of life. Vernacular houses therefore appear as variations
of types, and visualize a particular “inhabited landscape”. To-
gether they make up a meaningful place, and their constituent
parts, floor, roof and wall, possess the quality of images.”318
After talking about the “house” as the most personal and individual archi-
tectural being, Norberg-Schulz begins to talk about the other side of the
medallion, the “public institution”. As “house” represents the individuality
of architectural experience, “public institution” takes the role of the socio-
cultural representation. Norberg explains this with these words:
110
Figure 3.30: Longitudinal section of the old basilica, Rome, Il Tempio Vaticano, Carlo Fontana,1694.
we have already pointed out, the great unitary hall (centralized, lon-
gitudinal or gridded), and the distinct volume, such as the tower and
the dome. In the past, public buildings were generally conceived as
compositions of such volumes… We do not have to expand on what
has already been said about the modes of standing etc., but should
emphasize that the articulate built form of the public institution reveals
how a historical epoch understands its being between earth and
sky”.322 Here, we can understand that Norberg-Schulz referred to
the “earth” and “sky” which are two of the four fundamental elements
of Heidegger’s philosophy, when he was saying “…what is faintly
suggested becomes a significantly and clearly revealed…”.
111
Figure 3.31: “İki”, Bursa, Turkey, Yıldız Moran, 1955.
112
Here, he underlines the “flexibility” for the interpretation of the “city” as
a collective being. However, he also considers the “city” as a reference
point. He explains this notion and says “But also has to be rooted in a
locality and constitute a center which makes a region emerge as what
it is.”.324 We can see he considers the source of its reference as “local-
ity” and “centricity”. He further explains this notion with these words:
113
ture. Then, he underlines the importance of the new approaches to
recover the “language” of architecture:
114
have called a “poetical vision”. Only through love and respect for
things, and thus be able to “save the earth”.” In terms of architecture
this means the creation of true places, and thus the recovery of the
built image.”.332 Here, we can see that Norberg-Schulz considers
“places” as a representation of “built image” and he also relates
these with living in a meaningful narrative. He also criticizes our daily
vision to things in the Modern world with these words:
Here, he points out the lack of the role of images in the Modern way
of thinking in comparison to abstraction. He explains deeper this no-
tion more through the Greek word “techne” and the German word
“Andenken” in this passage:
115
RESEMBLANCE
& DIVERGENCE
The most fundamental difference between the two authors is the dif-
ference between their intellectual approaches. Rossi mentions many
times the necessity of a scientific approach to architecture in both of
his books. Thus, he mainly aims to keep his arguments in the scientifi-
cally or at least logically debatable area of thought. Although at first
sight Norberg-Schulz’s approach seems quite scientific, as we went
through details, we can observe there are numerous references to
the Heideggerian terminology which is vaguely defined. This notion
makes Norberg-Schulz’s arguments quite unclear and lowers the
strength of his arguments.
117
Figure 4.1: Drawing of San Cataldo Cemetery, Aldo Rossi.
Another important notion about these two authors is that they are both
interested in the mental process and perception of the subjects of
architecture. We can easily observe the influence of psychology and
phenomenology on both architects.
118
berg-Schulz was also influenced by Heideggerian phenomenology.
He often uses the Heideggerian terminology. Most important terms in
this sense are “nearness” and “dwelling” which are strongly related to
the perceptional and cognitive aspects of the architectural process.
One of which is “image”. Rossi relates the need for “image” to “mem-
ory” and “history”. To Rossi, “image” is one of the most important tools
to understand our context in terms of time. It helps us to understand
the references by revealing “persistences” and “permanences” in the
city. Rossi considers the most crucial notion of architecture is to reveal
the “history” and “memory” with the “event” and the “sign”. He says
“I have asked many times in the course of this book, where does the
singularity of an urban artifact begin? In its form, its function, its mem-
ory, or in something else again? We can now answer that it begins
in the event and in the sign that has marked the event.”.337 Thus, he
describes the main necessity of architecture as “event & sign”, in other
words, memory.
119
Rossi defines the physical elements of the city as “urban artifacts”.
According to Rossi, these “urban artifacts” have four main features:
individuality, locus, design, and memory. Among these urban arti-
facts, Rossi prioritizes certain artifacts and names them as “primary
elements”. In his writings, he examples these “primary elements” as
monuments, plans of the city, and basic layouts of the city. Rossi does
not consider the “function” of these artifacts as their fundamental fea-
ture. Thus, to Rossi, these artifacts are a part of the city, even though
their function changes over time. Rossi has two main perspectives to
understand “city”: “a man-made object” and “a work of art”. Thus, we
can understand Rossi’s thinking of urban artifacts is mainly abstractive
and analytical. As “a man-made object”, he considers the city and
the urban artifacts as “traces of time”. This perspective leads him to
consider types as “logical principles” which are “permanent” and
“complex”. On the other hand, as “a work of art”, he considers the
city and the urban artifacts as a result of “collective imagination”.
120
Figure 4.2: Diagrams of Space, Intentions in Architecture, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
Another common subject of the authors is how they relate daily activities
and rituals, in other words, living, with architecture. Both have different
perspectives on this subject with some similarities and common points.
There are numerous points that Rossi’s perspective coincides with dai-
ly life and rituals. On the fundamental level, as we mentioned before,
Rossi has two main understandings of the “city”: “a man-made object”
and “a work of art”. As we can see here, both of these definitions are
derived from human activities fundamentally. Thus, the presence of
daily life and rituals can be found in the foundation of Rossi’s under-
standing. We can better understand Rossi’s aspect, if we understand
his relation with “teatro”. Rossi considers “city” as a “teatro” in which
human events take place. Also, he often underlines the importance of
“collectiveness” which is not only related to daily life but also related
to the social interactions of individuals. This notion of “collectiveness”
is quite important. It is related to other important concepts of Rossi
such as “collective memory” and “collective imagination”. Another
important notion is Rossi’s description of “type”. He relates “type”
with the form and the way of life of certain timeframe. He explains this
and says “as “… developed according to both needs and aspirations
to beauty; a particular type was associated with a form and a way
121
Aldo
Rossi
Christian
Norberg-Schulz
Figure 4.3: Diagram of Resemblences & Divergences of Aldo Rossi & Christian Norberg-Schulz.
122
of life, although its specific shape varied widely from society to soci-
ety.”.341 Thus, he associates the “logical principle” of the “type” as a
knowledge which is obtained through experiences of the past. Most
importantly, Rossi describes the fundamental objective of architecture
as revealing the “memory” with the “event” and “sign”. Thus, we can
understand the crucial role of human events in Rossi’s architecture.
123
PSYCHOLOGY AND PHENOMENOLOGY
Considering the impact, the most significant subject that directs the
thoughts and writings of Rossi and Norberg-Schulz is presumably psy-
chology. Both writers create connections between their works and var-
ious psychological fields in their writings. Although there are common
points, most of the time, they mention different works of psychology.
For Rossi, the main influence was from the Swiss psychologist and
founder of analytical psychology Carl Gustav Jung. The term “arche-
type” was popularized in psychology by Carl Jung, long before intro-
duced to architecture. Jung defines and describes the term “archetype”
in his works, in many ways. These traces of these various definitions and
343. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
descriptions can be observed in the writings of Rossi. Clearly, Jung’s City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
approach to this term inspires Rossi to adapt and use the term in the ar- Original: 1966), 112.
chitectural vocabulary. The architectural description of Rossi has many
344. Ibid.
fundamentally common points with Jung’s description despite the differ-
ence between the two disciplines. Defining the “archetype” is not the 345. Ibid, 114.
124
Figure 4.4: The Map of Psyche, Carl Gustav Jung.
125
only point of connection among their works. In an article, Micha Ban-
dini mentions how Jung influenced Rossi’s understanding of “analogy”
and, through this, his work “Analogous City” in this passage:
126
places. The city is the locus of the collective memory. This re-
lationship between the locus and citizenry then becomes the
city’s predominant image, both of architecture and of land-
scape, and as certain artifacts become part of its memory,
new ones emerge. In this entirely positive sense great ideas
flow through the history of the city and give shape to it.”348
Here, we can see that Rossi clearly describes his understanding of “collec-
tive memory” not as a physical element like “urban artifacts” of the city, but
as an “idea” of these elements which is completely a mental projection.
127
psychology. Then, he explains “schemata” with these words: “A sche-
ma may be defined as a typical reaction to a situation.”.353 Then, he
mentions different concepts of Piaget’s terminology in the passage:
“We thus see that the synthetic space of primitive man has been
split into several specialized constructs which serve us in our ori-
entation and adaptation to different aspects of the environment.
In addition to the cognitive spaces, we have within the psycho-
logical dimension to distinguish between immediate perceptu-
al space and the more stable space schemata. The latter are
composed of elements which have a certain invariance, such
as universal elementary structures (archetypes) and socially or
culturally conditioned structures, and, of course, some personal
idiosyncrasies. Together these make up man’s “image” of this
environment, that is, a stable system of three-dimensional rela-
tions between meaningful objects. We will therefore unify the
schemata in the concept existential space.”.355
128
Figure 4.5: Principles of Gestalt Psychology.
129
Figure 4.6: Aerial photo of Göbeklitepe, oldest permanent human settlements, Şanlı Urfa, Turkey.
Here, specifically “going through spaces” and “going toward the door”
are quite important examples of how Heidegger thinks about the phe-
nomenological and psychological process which we go through in in-
teraction with space. Thus, the act of “going toward the door” starts in
the mental processes before the physical action. This notion is also pres-
ent in Norberg-Schulz’s writings as well. We can observe the traces of
this notion if we examine how Norberg-Schulz explains the interaction
between subject and space. As we mentioned before in the previous
chapters, Norberg-Schulz explains this interaction with two terms:
130
Another significant point that is related to the role of Heideggeri-
an phenomenology in the relation between psychology and Nor-
berg-Schulz’s works is two terms that are frequently referred to in his
writings. These are “nearness” and “dwelling”. In the book “Poetry,
Language, Thought”, Heidegger explains “nearness” and underlines
the notion that what he means by “nearness” is not the distance:
“Man puts the longest distances, behind him in the shortest time.
He puts the greatest distances behind himself and thus puts ev-
erything before himself at the shortest range. Yet the frantic abo-
lition of all distances brings no nearness; for nearness does not
consist in shortness of distance. What is least remote from us in
point of distance, by virtue of its picture on film or its sound on
the radio, can remain far from us. What is incalculably far from
us in point of distance can be near to us. Short distance is not in
itself nearness. Nor is great distance remoteness.”359
131
…
Last but not least, there is another notion that reveals the role of psy-
chology in Norberg-Schulz’s understanding of architecture. This no-
tion occurs in the chapter in which he describes “type”. He mentions
different ways of understanding “type” in this passage:
132
potheses are correct.”, which is an important point to understand. On
the other hand, Carl Jung underlines a similar point in his book “Four
Archetypes”. In the chapter named “On the Concept of the Arche-
types”, Carl Jung describes the concept of “archetype” and its fea-
tures. In the chapter, he describes “archetype” as the same concept
as the “idea” of Platonic philosophy. Considering what he later says
about “idea”, this becomes a significant point:
133
MEANING: IMAGE, MEMORY, LOCUS
Another significant subject that directs the works of Rossi and Nor-
berg-Schulz is “meaning” in architecture. The lack of “meaning” in
Modern architecture was a norm that was recognized by Rossi, Nor-
berg-Schulz, and also other architects of the era. Norberg-Schulz
points out this by explaining the main intention of his professor, Sigfried
Giedion: “When Giedion launched the idea in 1954, he had already
ten years earlier published an article entitled “The Need for a New
Monumentality”. Evidently he considered regionalism and monumen-
tality two aspects of one general problem: the need for meaning in
architecture.”.363 This norm would eventually play an important role in
the Post-Modern Movement and various individual responses.
Norberg-Schulz, on the other hand, has a more direct approach 366. Ibid, 19.
134
Figure 4.8: Diagram of “The Theory of
Evolution”, Charles Jencks.
to the necessity of “meaning” in architecture. Firstly, he recognizes
the previous effort of Modern architecture to create such a world of
meaning in this passage:
135
Figure 4.9: A Manifest Drawing and Writing on “The Room”, Louis I. Kahn.
136
As we can see, according to Norberg-Schulz, the approach of post-mod-
ern architecture is to use “image” as a tool to represent “meaning” in ar-
chitecture. Norberg-Schulz agrees with the fact that “image” is the essen-
tial tool to represent the “meaning”. He relates the “image” with various
concepts in architecture. In this manner, he mentions most frequently “mon-
umentality”. However, it is important to understand what he means by
“monumentality”. He starts with an etymological explanation of the word
monumentum which is the Latin word “monument” comes from:
In this passage, there are two major crucial points. One of which is the
meaning of the word momentum, “things that remind”. This is a direct refer-
ence to “memory”. The other point is Norberg-Schulz’s understanding of the
term “monumentality” which he describes as “meaning in architecture”. Thus,
he creates a connection between memory, monumentality, and meaning.
371. Ibid, 169. Both authors responded to this necessity of “meaning” in their own
ways. However, there were numerous common points in the ap-
372. Ibid, 175.
proach to the solution of this problem. These common points can be
373. Ibid, 169. gathered under three subjects: image, locus, and memory.
137
IMAGE, MEMORY, LOCUS
Rossi mentions “image” at various points in his writings. Rossi first un-
derlines the importance of image on the urban scale. He points out
this with these words:
Here, there are two major points in this statement. One of which is his
understanding of “architecture” as an equivalent concept to “urban
image”. Thus, we can say that Rossi considers “urban image” as a
crucial part of architecture. The other point is that he considers “urban
image” as a notion that is “deeply rooted in the human condition”.
We can relate this to the existential perspective of Norberg-Schulz
who frequently refers to the term “human existence”.
138
Figure 4.10: Urban Scene: Scena Per il Teatrino, Aldo Rossi, 1978. Magic marker and paint on board, 730 × 1073 mm.
how the past is perceived and passed on. Halbwachs’ ideas have had
a lasting impact on the fields of sociology, anthropology, and memo-
ry studies, shaping our understanding of how societies construct and
maintain their shared historical narratives and identities. The concept of
collective memory continues to be relevant in analyzing how societ-
ies remember and commemorate events, and how memory influences
group cohesion and identity.375 In the chapter “Collective Memory” of
his book, Rossi relates “image” with the “memory” with a quotation from
Halbwachs with these words:
139
Figure 4.11: A Drawing of a Building Block from IBA 84, Aldo Rossi. Watercolor and ink on paper, 36.6 x 50.5 cm.
“One can say that the city itself is the collective memory of
its people, and like memory it is associated with object and
places. The city is the locus of the collective memory. This re-
lationship between the locus and citizenry then becomes the
city’s predominant image, both of architecture and of land-
scape, and as certain artifacts become part of its memory,
new ones emerge. In this entirely positive sense great ideas
flow through the history of the city and give shape to it.”377
Here, the first point Rossi makes is the fact that he considers “memory”
as an abstract notion which later mentions as an “image”, not as a
physical being which he calls “permanences and persistences” later
in the book to differentiate. The other point he makes is the relation
between “locus” and “collective memory”. We can understand he
considers “locus” as a place where “collective memory” takes place.
However, the most important point is that he considers this relation
between “locus” and “memory” as the source that creates the pre-
dominant “image” of the city. Later, he mentions “memory” as “con-
sciousness of the city” in this passage:
377. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
“Memory, within the structure, is the consciousness of the city; Original: 1966), 130.
140
it is a rational operation whose development demonstrates
with maximum clarity, economy, and harmony that which has
already come to be accepted.”378
Here, we can that Rossi examines the relation between “myth” and
“ritual” to render a deeper understanding of “memory”. Later, he
compares this relation with “monument”:
This notion of “event & sign” can be related to the “image” through
“memory”. Rossi mentions this notion with a quotation from Adolf Loos:
141
separation, which the ancient world seemingly resolved for-
ever, derives the universally acknowledged character of per-
manence of those first forms.”382
Here, we can understand that Rossi values the “image” of the city as
a concept beyond its “memory” and its “permanences”.
Last but not least, mentioning Rossi’s drawings would help us to un-
derstand his relation with “image”. One of which is the drawing of
“Analogous City” which can be considered as a visual representa-
tion of the values mentioned in the book “Architecture of the City”.
“Analogy” is an important tool of Rossi. He mentions this notion in the
“Introduction to the First American Edition” section of the book:
Norberg-Schulz has a different approach in the context of “image”. 384. Ibid, 18.
142
Figure 4.12: Life in a Norwegian, “tun” at the end of the nineteenth century, The Concept of Dwelling, Christian Norberg-Schulz.
However, there are also points that intersect with Rossi’s approach.
Inspired by Heidegger, Norberg first defines three systems of imag-
es. These systems are “language”, “style” and “tradition”. He men-
tions and explains this with these words:
143
Figure 4.13: The Duck and the Decorated Shed Diagrams, Robert Venturi.
Norberg-Schulz also details his understanding of “language”. Firstly, 386. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of
he describes the relation between “language” and “architecture” in Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
1988), 153.
this passage:
387. Ibid, 169.
144
“Architecture is a language. As such it keeps the spatiality
of the world. The architectural language consists of arche-
typal images that reveal those structures which are invariant
with respect to place and time. The archetypes are not forms
which exist in some distant realm as an ideal Ding an sich.
Rather they represent basic modes of being in the world, or
“existential structures”. As a matter of fact the archetypes do
not exist at all, only their various manifestations. A “typical”
tower, thus, does not exist, but “towernesss” is revealed in
its multifarious aspects by means of ever new tower-images.
Thus the work of architecture becomes “an offering to Ar-
chitecture”. These words of Loius Kahn suggest that it is pos-
sible and meaningful to talk about architecture in general,
although only single works exist.”388
Here, there are three main points. First of all, Norberg-Schulz defines
“architecture” as a “language” previously described as “which consists
of invariant archetypes”. The second point is parallel to this notion. He
describes “architectural language” through “archetypal images”. Thus,
he brings together these four concepts. Another point is how he defines
“archetypes”. He defines it as “basic modes of being in the world” or
“existential structures”, not as abstract forms as an ideal “Ding an sich”.
Thus, Norberg-Schulz considers “archetypes” as being strongly con-
nected to “context” and “existence”. In this passage, he also makes a
point about the term “typical image” we mentioned before.
145
er, he mentions Rossi’s contribution in his point of view with these words:
146
Figure 4.14: The Egyptian grid towns.
147
Figure 4.15: “On the way to figurative architecture”, Michael Graves. From The Concept of Dwelling, Norberg-Schulz.
In various parts in his writings, he mentions this aspect with the term
“imago mundi”. However, before examining “imago mundi”, we
need to understand what an “architectural thing” is. He explains the
term “architectural thing” with these words:
148
Norberg-Schulz gives some hints about the “gathering” he will later
mention, with the words “relationships between down and up, here
and there, outside and inside”. What he means by “achieving ima-
go mundi” is that when a subject interacts with a complete work that
“gathers the Fourfold” in Heideggerian terms, the specific image of the
“architectural thing” expands and gives a glimpse of a deeper under-
standing of the world. Norberg mentions this notion with these words:
“We could also say that the above-mentioned forms are im-
ages because they possess a place-creating potentiality. Any
place reveals a particular relationship of earth and sky, and is
constituted by architectural images. The loss of the image there-
fore brings about a loss of place, and hence a “loss of life”.”400
400. Ibid, 169. “Spaces, and with them space as such—”space”—are always
149
provided for already within the stay of mortals. Spaces open
up by the fact that they are let into the dwelling of man. To say
that mortals are is to say that in dwelling they persist through
spaces by virtue of their stay among things and locations. And
only because mortals pervade, persist through, spaces by their
very nature are they able to go through spaces. But in going
through spaces we do not give up our standing in them. Rather,
we always go through spaces in such a way that we already
experience them by staying constantly with near and remote
locations and things. When I go toward the door of the lecture
hall, I am already there, and I could not go to it at all if I were
not such that I am there. I am never here only, as this encap-
sulated body; rather, I am there, that is, I already pervade the
room, and only thus can I go through it.”401
The answer to this question will clarify for us what building, under-
stood by way of the nature of dwelling, really is. We limit ourselves
to building in the sense of constructing things and inquire: what is a 401. Martin Heidegger, Poetry, Language,
built thing? A bridge may serve as an example for our reflections. Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New
York : Harper & Row, 1971), 154-155.
The bridge swings over the stream “with ease and power.” It does
not just connect banks that are already there. The banks emerge 402. Ibid, 163.
150
Figure 4.16: A View of Walton Bridge, Canaletto, 1753–1755
as banks only as the bridge crosses the stream. The bridge de-
signedly causes them to lie across from each other. One side is
set off against the other by the bridge. Nor do the banks stretch
along the stream as indifferent border strips of the dry land. With
the banks, the bridge brings to the stream the one and the other
expanse of the landscape lying behind them. It brings stream and
bank and land into each other’s neighborhood.
151
Figure 4.17: Therme Vals, Peter Zumthor, Photo by Fernando Guerra.
In the first paragraph, we can see that Heidegger relates not only
the connection but also the opposing banks not existing before the
“bridge”. The realization of the “bridge” created the connection as
well as the two sides of the river as places. Especially in the last para-
graph, we can see that Heidegger directly considers “dwelling” as a
tool to define a “location”.
152
This statement offers a clue to the problem of architectural
gathering. What is gathered, Heidegger says, is the “in-
habited landscape.” An inhabited landscape obviously is a
known landscape, that is, something that is v. This landscape
is brought close to us by the buildings, or in other words, the
landscape is revealed as what it is in truth.”404
Now, we can examine the term “locus”. This term directly appears in
the term “genius loci” which is one of the most important terms in Nor-
berg-Schulz’s writings. The word “loci” comes from the word “locus”
which means “place” or “locality”.405 Norberg-Schulz introduced the
term “genius loci” in the book “Genius Loci: Towards a Phenomenology
of Architecture”. He describes the term in the book with these words:
153
Norberg-Schulz underlines the importance of the term “inhabited
landscape”. This concept of “inhabited landscape” can be related
to the term “inhabited space” in Rossi’s writings. Later, he explains this
term in this passage:
154
Figure 4.18: Ayub National Hospital, Dhaka, Bangladesh, Louis I. Kahn, 1962. Photo by Cemal Emden.
up a world and gives to things their look”. The forms which are
related to a particular region evidently possess similar proper-
ties, and become elements of a tradition or “way of building”.
Symbolization is therefore a derivation from the original act of
revelation, and a meaningful language of architecture is not an
arbitrary system of conventional “sign”, but an interrelated set of
visualizations and complementations. Place is hence the point of
departures of architecture, as well as its goal.”412
155
each of them helps the others to emerge. We have called this
emerging of things by means of images “visualization”.“413
The term “locus” is present in Rossi’s writings as well. Although his approach
to “locus” does not consist of the rich understanding of Norberg-Schulz,
Rossi also underlines the value of “locus”. He defines it with these words:
156
This is an important point when we consider Norberg-Schulz defines
“genius loci” as unique “qualities” of a specific place, as we men-
tioned before. Thus, we can understand what Rossi means by “locus”
is similar to what Norberg-Schulz means by “genius loci”. Rossi un-
derlines the importance of “locus” to understanding “urban artifact”
by describing it as one of its four main features of it:
“We need, as I have said, only consider one specific urban ar-
tifact for a whole string of questions to present themselves; for it
is a general characteristic of urban artifacts that they return us to
certain major themes: individuality, locus, design, memory.”417
157
PHYSICAL ELEMENTS AND TYPES
“The second point of view sees history as the study of the actu-
al formation and structure of urban artifacts. It is complemen-
tary to the first and directly concerns not only the real structure
of the city but also the idea that the city is a synthesis of a
422. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
series of values. Thus it concerns the collective imagination. City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
Clearly the first and second approaches are intimately linked, Original: 1966), 127.
158
Figure 4.20: Aphrodisias, Ara Güler, 1958.
“We need, as I have said, only consider one specific urban ar-
tifact for a whole string of questions to present themselves; for it
423. Ibid, 127-128.
is a general characteristic of urban artifacts that they return us to
424. Ibid, 32. certain major themes: individuality, locus, design, memory.”424
159
Figure 4.21: Monument to Sandro Pertini, Milan, Aldo Rossi, 1988-90.
160
generator of a form of the city, remains constant. In this sense,
monuments are always primary elements.”426
Thus, Rossi considers “event” and “sign” which marks the event as a
fundamental raison d’être for “urban artifacts”. Rossi underlines this
objective of the “monuments” that will carry the “memory” through time
with these words at another point of his book:
161
three feet wide is an extremely intense and pure architecture
precisely because it is identifiable in the artifact. It is only in the
history of architecture that a separation between the original
element and its various forms occurred. From this separation,
which the ancient world seemingly resolved forever, derives
the universally acknowledged character of permanence of
those first forms.”430
162
Figure 4.22: Stonehenge, Wiltshire, England.
163
“I would define the concept of type as something that is per-
manent and complex, a logical principle that is prior to form
and that constitutes it.”433
164
other branch of human inventions and institutions ....
We have engaged in this discussion in order to ren-
der the value of the word type-taken metaphorically
in a great number of works-clearly comprehensible,
and to show the error of those who either disregard
it because it is not a model, or misrepresent it by im-
posing on it the rigor of a model that would imply the
conditions of an identical copy.”
In the first part of this passage, the author rejects the possibility
of type as something to be imitated or copied because in
this case there would be, as he asserts in the second part,
no “creation of the model”-that is, there would be no mak-
ing of architecture. The second part states that in architecture
(whether model or form) there is an element that plays its own
role, not something to which the architectonic object conforms
but something that is nevertheless present in the model. This is
the rule, the structuring principle of architecture.”435
Here, there are two major points that are important to understand.
One of which is the difference between “model” and “type”. Rossi
as well as Quatremère considers “model” as a “precise” and “given”
concept which can be considered as the information to produce a
specific form, and type as a “vague” concept which can be consid-
ered as the principles and rules that manifest that form. Rossi explains
this notion with these words:
Rossi relates “type” with the various aspects of architecture like “tech-
nique”, “function” and “style”. He also states that he considers “type”
as a “character of necessity” in architecture. He underlines this notion
with these words:
165
Figure 4.23: In Morning on the River, Jonas Lie,1911-12.
166
stand forth as such, and by bringing them together in a poem,
each of them helps the others to emerge. We have called this
emerging of things by means of images “visualization”.
“The bridge swings over the stream “with ease and power.” It
does not just connect banks that are already there. The banks
emerge as banks only as the bridge crosses the stream. The bridge
designedly causes them to lie across from each other. One side
is set off against the other by the bridge. Nor do the banks stretch
along the stream as indifferent border strips of the dry land. With
the banks, the bridge brings to the stream the one and the other
expanse of the landscape lying behind them. It brings stream and
bank and land into each other’s neighborhood.
167
a thing; it gathers the fourfold, but in such a way that it allows
a site for the fourfold. By this site are determined the localities
and ways by which a space is provided for.”440
On the other hand, the relation between “form” and “image” in Nor-
berg-Schulz’s perspective can be observed in the concept of “type”.
Firstly, we need to understand how he defines “type”. He points out
that in this passage:
168
Figure 4.24: The Repetitive images of the German Tudor facades.
169
Figure 4.25: “The Ideal City”, Fra Carnevale, 1480–1484.
170
“As a matter of fact the archetypes do not exist at all, only their
various manifestations. A “typical” tower, thus, does not exist,
but “towerness” is revealed in its multifarious aspects by means
of ever new tower-images. Thus the work of architecture be-
comes “an offering to Architecture”. These words of Louis Kahn
suggest that it is possible and meaningful to talk about archi-
tecture in general, although only single works exist.”447
Thus, “archetypes” are what we have left when we separate the tem-
porary tendencies in architecture. Then, he relates this fact with the
intention of a “new architecture” in Modern architecture:
447. Ibid, 153. Jung considers the term “archetype” as a synonym of the term “Idea”
in Platonic philosophy. Then, he answers this question of “a priori” with
448. Ibid, 169.
these words:
449. Ibid, 155.
“Once again, in the age-old controversy over universals, the
450. Carl G. Jung, Four Archetypes, trans.
R.F.C. Hull (London: Routledge, 2003), nominalistic standpoint has triumphed over the realistic, and
7-8. the Idea has evaporated into a mere flatus vocis. This change
171
Figure 4.26: Ancient Greek Orders.
Jung points out that he considers “archetypes” not “a priori” but “second-
ary” and “derived”. This approach coincides with Norberg-Schulz’s ap-
proach to the issue. He describes his approach with these words:
172
These statements rises a new question: Where these “types” can
be derived from? We can understand this by examining what Nor-
berg-Schulz states about “typical image” previously. Norberg-Schulz
examples “typical image” through ancient civilizations. He starts with
Ancient Egyptian architecture and underlines the importance of gram-
mar which consists of “order”, “hierarchy” and “classification” and its
relation with the values and environmental conditions of Egyptians.
He explains how the route of the Sun and the direction of the Nile
River shapes the general orientation of the civilization through “grid”,
“path”, “center” and “enclosure”. These elements of “grammar” and
“orientation” mainly derived from civilization’s interaction with the “envi-
ronmental conditions”, in other words, the interaction between “culture”
and “nature”. Naturally, the outcomes of these interactions are strongly
dependent on the “locality”. However, Norberg-Schulz states that in
specific cases, it can have outcomes that is beyond their geography:
173
LIVING AND RITUALS
Another significant subject that directs the works of Rossi and Nor-
berg-Schulz is the role of “living” and “rituals” in architecture. For both
authors, “living” has a crucial role in architecture which is beyond the
Modernist understanding that is limited to “function” and “circulation”.
Both authors point out different deeper relations between “life” and
“architecture”. We will examine these to understand the intersection
of both perspectives.
“Within this idea exist the actions of individuals, and in this sense
not everything in urban artifacts is collective; yet the collective
and the individual nature of urban artifacts in the end constitutes
the same urban structure. Memory, within the structure, is the
consciousness of the city; it is a rational operation whose de-
velopment demonstrates with maximum clarity, economy, and
harmony that which has already come to be accepted.”457
On another point, Rossi says “The changes in housing and in the land
on which houses leave their imprint become signs of this daily life.”.458
Thus, he underlines the role of “daily life” in architecture. Rossi also
describes “architecture” through two main points: “Aesthetic intention
and the creation of better surroundings for life are the two permanent
characteristics of architecture.”.459 Thus, Rossi considers the objective
of architecture as the creation of better surroundings “for life”. 456. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
Original: 1966), 21.
As we mentioned before, Rossi has two main approaches to “city”.
These are “city as a man-made object” and “city as a work of art”. 457. Ibid, 131.
We can clearly see that both of these approaches are fundamen-
458. Ibid, 22.
tally connected to “human creation” as Viollet-le-Duc calls it. This is
not a conscious process of creation. This is a creation mostly as a 459. Ibid, 21.
174
Figure 4.27: ”Road to Power” , Serge Najjar, 2011.
result of “living” and “rituals”. Thus, Rossi’s two main approaches are
fundamentally derived from “living” and “rituals”. Rossi mentions this
connection with these words:
175
Figure 4.28: Sukhala Houses, Gurunsi Villages, Tiebele, Burkina Faso.
“It is in this sense not only the place of the human condition,
but itself a part of that condition, and is represented in the
city and its monuments, in districts, dwellings, and all urban
artifacts that emerge from inhabited space.”461
Rossi points out that he considers “urban image” gives value to “in-
habited space” which he considers it is deeply connected to the “hu-
man condition”. However, these statements do not give a clue about 461. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
what is exactly the “human condition” or “inhabited space”. We can City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
Original: 1966), 34.
find an answer to this question in this sentence of Rossi:
462. Ibid, 27.
176
“All these experiences, their sum, constitute the city.”463
“One can say that the city itself is the collective memory of
its people, and like memory it is associated with object and
places. The city is the locus of the collective memory. This re-
lationship between the locus and citizenry then becomes the
city’s predominant image, both of architecture and of land-
scape, and as certain artifacts become part of its memory,
new ones emerge. In this entirely positive sense great ideas
flow through the history of the city and give shape to it.”464
463. Ibid, 29. “Rossi argues in his book, A Scientific Autobiography (1981),
that his model, the Teatro, was Shakespear’s Globe Theater,
464. Ibid, 130. revealing the similarity even in the common names of The-
465. Seungkoo Jo, “Aldo Rossi: Architec- aters of the World. Rossi quoted Shakespear’s dictum, All the
ture and Memory,” Journal of Asian Archi- World’s stage, and looked for the universal knowledge of the
tecture and Building Engineering 2, no. 1, world in the Teatro, where it seems likely that the Globe would
(2003): 234.
have searched for a way to express the space of theater.”468
466. Ibid, 233.
Thus, Rossi considers the “city” as a “theater” where “human events”,
467. Ibid, 233.
in other words, “life” takes place. This is deeply connected to Nor-
468. Ibid, 233. berg-Schulz’s notion of “life takes place” which we will examine later.
177
Another significant point Rossi makes about the role of daily life in
architecture is through “primary elements”. He describes the “primary
elements” with these words:
After this description, Rossi relates “primary elements” with the major
human activities and daily life in the city which he calls “fixed activities”:
178
Figure 4.29: “A possible beginning for
contacts at other levels”, From “Life Be-
tween Buildings”, Jan Gehl.
Here, Rossi reveals one of the most important points of his understand-
ing of architecture which gives us an understanding of the role of “human
events” in Rossi’s architecture. He considers the fundamental raison d’être
of an urban artifact as a “sign” of an “event”. Thus, we can see that “human
events” play a fundamental role in architecture in Rossi’s perspective.
Another important notion is how Rossi relates “type” with “daily life”.
He points out that there are two main elements that define “type”:
“form” and “way of life”. He underlines this notion with these words:
Last but not least, Rossi directly mentions “rituals” in the book, while
he was explaining the relation between “myth”, “ritual” and “monu-
ments”. Firstly, he starts to talk about “myth” and he explains its refer-
ence to the past. Then, he underlines the importance of “rituals” as a
tool to transfer myths from generation to generation. He mentions this
notion with these words:
179
Figure 4.30: House on an island, Ellidaey, Iceland.
Rossi points out the “collective nature” of rituals and also its “essential
character” that preserves “myth”. He also mentions the necessity of
“myths” to understand the meaning of “monuments”. Later, he under-
lines this relation with these words:
Rossi points out that “rituals” are similar to “monuments” in the context
of “permanent” and “conserving” the myths which are our connection
to the past.
180
“Rooms are unspecific spaces, empty stages for human
action, where we perform the rituals and improvisations of
living. They provide generalized opportunities for things to
happen, and they allow us to do and be what we will.”475
Another frequently used term is “being in the world” which can be re-
lated to “life” as well in an existential and phenomenological context.
181
“Basically a type is not a sign or a metaphor, but a relatively
stable gathering of a world, which possesses the capacity of
adaptation and variation.”479
182
Figure 4.31: “Tour de France”, Robert Capa, 1939.
183
Figure 4.32: Nebelivka Hypothesis, David Wengrow, 18th International Architecture Exhibition of the Biennale di Venezia.
Norberg-Schulz underlines the fact that the act of “settlement” transforms 483. Christian Norberg-Schulz, The Con-
cept of the Dwelling: On the Way to Fig-
the “site” and allows “human life” to take “place”. This statement also urative Architecture (New York: Rizzoli,
points out that when “human life” comes to a site by “settling”, the “site” 1985), 31.
184
turns into a “place”. This is the fundamental and existential change Nor-
berg-Schulz considers happening as the result of “settlement”.
“Thus the house primarily complements the lacks of the site and
makes what is close at hand emerge. It constitutes a concrete,
individual “here”, and allows life to take place “now”. In the
past, however, the concrete “here” became typical, because
“neighbourly dwelling” implied the sharing of a site and a way
of life. Vernacular houses therefore appear as variations of
types, and visualize a particular “inhabited landscape”.486
484. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of Here, we can observe that Norberg-Schulz considers “house” as a
Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita, marker of a particular place and time. This way, it allows “life” to take
1988), 135.
“place”. This notion frequently gets mentioned by a specific sentence
485. Ibid. in Norberg-Schulz’s writings:
486. Ibid, 179.
“The loss of the image, therefore, brings about a loss of
487. Ibid, 169. place, and hence a “loss of life”.”487
185
CONCLUSIONS
187
Figure 5.1: Drawings of Gallaratese Housing Complex, Aldo Rossi.
188
ture, “collective memory”, is a term taken from Jungian psychology.
Rossi also refers to Jung through the term “collective imagination” as
well. Rossi also often uses Jung’s definitions in various points in his
works. An example of this is in Rossi’s article “Analogical Architecture”
in which he mentions Jung’s definition of “analogy”. Another example
can be the definition of “archetype”. Rossi refers to Jung’s definition of
“archetype” in his book.
“Gestalt psychology” has an immense influence on Norberg-Schulz’s
understanding of architecture. However, he also criticizes it and con-
siders it “static” and “absolute”. He considers Jean Piaget’s work as
an update to Gestalt psychology which brings “dynamism”. He men-
tions this notion with these words:
“Like those used in physics, early psychological concepts
had a static, absolute character, but recently a more dynam-
ic approach has been introduced. The absolute “laws” of
Gestalt psychology, for instance, have been replaced by
Piaget’s more flexible “schemata”.”490
Norberg-Schulz uses Gestalt psychology and Piaget’s concept of
“schemata” to have a better understanding of space. In the book
“Existence, Space and Architecture”, he structures a system of spaces
through these two elements of psychology. His understanding of the
interaction between subject and space is mostly shaped by the psy-
chological and phenomenological experiences of the subject.
In this respect, Norberg-Schulz often refers to Heideggerian phe-
nomenology as well. He underlines the points of Heidegger’s ref-
erences to the psychological aspect of this experience. One of the
most important references to this notion can be found in this passage:
“Spaces, and with them space as such—”space”—are always
provided for already within the stay of mortals. Spaces open
up by the fact that they are let into the dwelling of man. To say
that mortals are is to say that in dwelling they persist through
spaces by virtue of their stay among things and locations.
And only because mortals pervade, persist through, spaces
by their very nature are they able to go through spaces. But in
going through spaces we do not give up our standing in them.
Rather, we always go through spaces in such a way that we
already experience them by staying constantly with near and
490. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Existence
Space & Architecture (New York: Praeger,
remote locations and things. When I go toward the door of
1971), 10. the lecture hall, I am already there, and I could not go to it at
all if I were not such that I am there. I am never here only, as
491. Martin Heidegger, Poetry, Language,
Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter (New
this encapsulated body; rather, I am there, that is, I already
York : Harper & Row, 1971), 154-155. pervade the room, and only thus can I go through it.”491
189
Here, we can understand the value Norberg-Schulz gives to the cog-
nitive aspects of the spatial experience by referring to this passage of
Heidegger. He points out that the act of “going through” happens in
the mind of the subject before the physical act and he considers this
cognitive process as the essence of the act.
Before we go through a deeper grasp of these cognitive process-
es in Norberg-Schulz’s understanding of architecture and its relation
with Rossi’s understanding of architecture, we need to underline and
point out a few terminological similarities between both authors. One
of which is the similarity between Rossi’s “urban artifact” and Nor-
berg-Schulz’s “architectural thing”. These two terms are the terms they
use to describe an architectural form or a physical object. Rossi first
mentions “urban artifact” in his description of architecture with these
words:
“Architecture came into being along with the first traces of the
city; it is deeply rooted in the formation of civilization and is a
permanent, universal, and necessary artifact.”492
Then, he explains the concept of “urban artifact” further with these words:
“We need, as I have said, only consider one specific urban ar-
tifact for a whole string of questions to present themselves; for it
is a general characteristic of urban artifacts that they return us to
certain major themes: individuality, locus, design, memory.”493
Norberg-Schulz on the other hand defines “architectural thing” with
these words:
“When an architectural image unites spatial and plastic
qualities, it becomes an “architectural thing” which forms part
of a work of architecture.”.494
Here, Norberg-Schulz points out that an “architectural thing” consists
of a gathering of “image”, “space” and “form”. As we can see in
both cases, there is a reference to “locality”, “form” and “memory” of
the physical object.
Another important similarity is between the terms Rossi’s “locus” and Nor-
berg-Schulz’s “genius loci”. Although Norberg-Schulz as well uses the 492. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
term “locus”, he usually uses it to point a “place” or a “locality”. However, Original: 1966), 21.
Rossi uses the term “locus” in the same way Norberg-Schulz uses the term
“genius loci”. Rossi defines the term “locus” with these words: 493. Ibid, 32.
“The locus is a relationship between a certain specific loca- 494. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of
Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
tion and the buildings that are in it. It is at once singular and 1988), 153.
universal.”495
495. Ibid, 103.
190
Here, we can understand Rossi understands “locus” as the relation
between “building” and the “location”. Later, he explains further with
these words:
“The locus, so conceived, emphasizes the conditions and
qualities within undifferentiated space which are necessary
for understanding an urban artifact.”496
Here, we can observe that Rossi considers “locus” as “conditions”
and “qualities” of the space which are necessary to understand “ur-
ban artifacts”.
In the chapter “New Regionalism” of the book “Principles of Modern Ar-
chitecture”, he describes the meaning of “genius loci” with these words:
“As all buildings form part of a concrete “here”, they can-
not be alike everywhere, but have to embody the particular
qualities of the given place. From ancient times, this quality
has been recognized as the genius loci, and historical build-
ings normally had a distinct local flavor, although they often
belonged to a general “style”.”497
Here, we can understand that Norberg-Schulz considers “genius
loci” as unique “qualities” of a specific place. Also, he understands
“locus” by examining the relation between “building” and “place”.
This is an important point when we consider Rossi defines “locus” as
“conditions” and “qualities” of the space and Norberg-Schulz de-
fines “genius loci” as unique “qualities” of a specific place. Thus, we
can understand what Rossi means by “locus” strongly coincides with
what Norberg-Schulz means by “genius loci”. This concept which
Rossi names “locus” and Norberg-Schulz names “genius loci” is
quite important in the process of formation of archetype which we
mentioned in the introduction. Because the “locus” determines the
“physical conditions” which will test the “form” for better optimization
and fitness. Thus, the features of the ”locus” will be represented in the
“form” and this will eventually alter the “image”.
After we pointed out these terminological differences, we can now
examine the role of cognitive processes in Norberg-Schulz’s un-
derstanding of architecture and its relation with Rossi’s understand-
ing of architecture. The importance of cognitive processes in Nor-
berg-Schulz’s understanding of spatial experience can be observed
in the two acts he mentions as the “fundamental acts of architecture”.
These are “visualization” and “complementation”. These two acts
496. Ibid, 103.
strongly coincide with Rossi’s two complementary understandings of
the city: “city as a man-made object” and “city as a work of art”. This
497. Ibid, 135.
191
Figure 5.2: A Drawing of Ancient Roman City.
proximity can be one of the most important points of this study, due to
the importance of these concepts in the authors’ understanding of ar-
chitecture. These are the fundamental notions of both authors’ studies
and it shapes and touches all other segments of their works. Thus, we
will deeply examine and reveal this similarity.
Firstly, we need to understand the proximity of these concepts. Thus,
we need to go through the points which define and describe these
concepts. Norberg-Schulz explains the concept of “visualization by
mentioning a poem from Heidegger. Later, he comments on it:
“…Heidegger’s words are therefore selective. But they are not
arbitrary, and they do not abstract from the given phenomena.
Rather they penetrate to their core, and reveal basic and easily
understood meaning. Thus they make the things stand forth as
such, and by bringing them together in a poem, each of them
helps the others to emerge. We have called this emerging of
things by means of images “visualization”.498
In this case, “visualization” is mostly about what the “thing” represents
with its existence through time and space. This notion can also be
498. Christian Norberg-Schulz, Roots of
observed in this passage: Modern Architecture (Tokyo: A.D.A. Edita,
1988), 179.
192
“Visualization and complementation produce forms which
do not represent anything else, and therefore may be con-
sidered fundamental architectural acts. Vernacular architec-
ture is in general based on these modes, but the same also
holds true for the great “monuments” of the early civilizations.
Thus Heidegger uses a Greek temple to show how a build-
ing “opens up a world and gives to things their look”. The
forms which are related to a particular region evidently pos-
sess similar properties, and become elements of a tradition
or “way of building”.”499
As we can see, “visualization” is directly related to the existing prop-
erties of a form. With this in mind, the term “visualization” coincides
with “memory” or the past of the “thing”.
On his part, Rossi explains the concept of “city as a man-made ob-
ject” in a quite similar manner. He sums up his understanding of the
“city as a man-made object” in this passage:
“The study of history seems to offer the best verification of cer-
tain hypotheses about the city, for the city is in itself repository
of history. In this book we have made use of the historical
method from two different points of view. In the first, the city
was seen as a material artifact, a man-made object built over
time and retaining the traces of time, even if in a discontinuous
way. Studied from this point of view -archaeology, the history
of architecture, and the histories of individual cities- the city
yields very important information and documentation. Cities
become historical texts; in fact, to study urban phenomena
without the use of history is unimaginable, and perhaps this is
the only practical method available for understanding specif-
ic urban artifacts whose historical aspect is predominant. We
have illustrated this thesis, in part the foundation of this study, in
the context of the theories of Poete and Lavedan as well as in
relation to the concept of permanence.”500
We can consider the “city” as a man-made object “built over time”
which retains “traces of time”. He states that in this perspective “cities
become historical texts” which is related to the “locality” and “history”
of the city.
Depending on these statements, we can understand that both of these
concepts refer to the existing position of an architectural form in the
499. Ibid, 135. context of “time” and “space”. Norberg-Schulz relates the “genius
loci” of a place with its “past” and “memory” and considers “visualiza-
500. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
tion” as an act to acknowledge this information through the interaction
Original: 1966), 127. of the subject with the place. Rossi considers the “city” as a “man-made
193
object” and in this perspective, he interacts with “collective memory”
which consists of the historical and local values of the space and the
urban artifacts which form the city.
A similar situation applies to the relation between the terms “com-
plementation” and “city as a work of art”. Norberg-Schulz explains
“complementation” in this passage:
“When man makes language speak about the thing, how-
ever, he usually does not only tell how they are, but also
how they could be, that is, how he would like them to be at
this moment. In the speaking about thing thus, a “dream” or
“project” is generally present. To reveal how things could be,
means to add something they are “lacking”. A lack, however,
is not only mean visualization, but also “complementation”. It
is what the situation lacks, which sets the historical process in
motion, and makes ever new interpretations necessary.”501
Here, “complementation” is mainly related to what a form could
be potentially. Hence, the term “complementation” coincides with
“dream” or “project” as Norberg also mentions, in other words, the
potential future of the form.
On the other hand, Rossi sums up his understanding of the “city as a
work of art” in this passage:
“The second point of view sees history as the study of the
actual formation and structure of urban artifacts. It is com-
plementary to the first and directly concerns not only the real
structure of the city but also the idea that the city is a synthesis
of a series of values. Thus it concerns the collective imagina-
tion. Clearly the first and second approaches are intimately
linked, so much so that the facts they uncover may at times be
confounded with each other. Athens, Rome, Constantinople,
and Paris represent ideas of the city that extend beyond their
physical form, beyond their permanence; thus we can also
speak in this way of cities like Babylon which have all but
physically disappeared.”502
Rossi underlines the perspective that understands the city as a result
of “collective imagination” which “represents ideas of the city that
extend beyond their physical form” and creates an urban image that
reflects the “universal” understanding of the city.
These statements show that both of these concepts refer to an imag- 501. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
inary projection of a form. Norberg-Schulz underlines the creative Original: 1966), 179.
process of the interaction between the subject and the form. He
502. Ibid, 127-128.
194
Figure 5.3: “The Tower of Babel”, Pieter Bruegel, 1563.
points out that the subject finds a “lacking” aspect of the form and
interprets it in his mind. This perspective is deeply related to Gestalt
psychology. The result of the process is a “dream” or “project” of the
form which gives us an idea about what the form could be. On the
other hand, Rossi underlines the “representative” aspect of this cre-
ative process. He points out that the information formed due to the
“collective imagination” gives us an idea about the “universal” and
“timeless” understanding of the form.
As we underlined the similarities between these concepts of Rossi and
Norberg-Schulz, we can examine the role of these concepts in their
understanding of architecture. One of the first and most obvious points
is the fact that both authors refer to the physical elements in the city
while defining and describing these concepts. Norberg-Schulz uses
the word “thing” for this description. Undoubtedly, the word “thing” is
related to the term “architectural thing” in Norberg-Schulz’s terminol-
ogy of architecture. As we mentioned before, this term coincides with
Rossi’s term of “urban artifact”. Rossi, on the other hand, describes the
city as a man-made “object” and a “work” of art. Thus, he underlines
the physicality of these concepts. He underlines the notion that the city
is fundamentally a cluster of physical objects. This notion is important
due to its role in the process of the formation of archetypes. As we
195
Figure 5.4: “The Persistence of Memory”, Salvador Dali, 1931.
196
a city’s basic layout and plans. This last point is Poëte’s most
important discovery. Cities tend to remain on their axes of
development, maintaining the position of their original layout
and growing according to the direction and meaning of their
older artifacts, which often appear remote from present-day
ones. Sometimes these artifacts persist virtually unchanged,
endowed with a continuous vitality; other times they exhaust
themselves, and then only the permanence of their form, their
physical sign, their locus remains. The most meaningful per-
manences are those provided by the street and the plan. The
plan persists at different levels; it becomes differentiated in
its attributes, often deformed, but in substance, it is not dis-
placed. This is the most valid part of Poëte’s theory; even if
it cannot be said to be completely a historical theory, it is
essentially born from the study of history.”503
As we can observe here, explaining Poëte’s theory, Rossi often refers
to the importance of “locus”. We can also understand that Rossi re-
lates the concept of “city as a man-made object” to the “persistenc-
es” and “permanences” of the physical elements of the city, like mon-
uments, plans, or basic layout of the city.
On the other side, Rossi relates the other point of view “city as a work
of art” with the “collective imagination” of the city. The term “collective
imagination” is related to the “image” of the city which goes beyond
the “memory” and “permanences”.
Norberg-Schulz values these two acts through their potential. This
potentiality was mentioned previously in our writings as well while we
were examining how Norberg-Schulz relates “loss of image” to “loss
of place” and “loss of place” to “loss of life”.
“We could also say that the above-mentioned forms are
images because they possess a place-creating potentiali-
ty. Any place reveals a particular relationship of earth and
sky, and is constituted by architectural images. The loss of the
image therefore brings about a loss of place, and hence a
“loss of life”.”504
He states that he considers particular “forms” he mentioned as “imag-
es” due to their “place-creating potentiality”. He underlines the fact that
he values the forms he mentioned as images due to their “place-cre-
ating potentiality”. He reinforces this statement by equating “loss of
503. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the images” with “loss of place” and “loss of place” with “loss of life”. This
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984; statement repeats several times in various books by Norberg-Schulz.
Original: 1966), 59.
It fundamentally underlines the value of “locus” in Norberg-Schulz’s
504. Ibid, 169. understanding of “image”. However, another important notion about
197
this quotation is the part where he relates the “loss of place” through
the “loss of image” with the “loss of life”. This statement gives out the
hierarchical order in Norberg-Schulz’s understanding of architecture
which is fundamentally based on “life”. Thus, this statement underlines
the fact that Norberg-Schulz as well considers the main intention of the
architectural production process to maintain and protect the “essential
act” which we mentioned in the introduction. However, due to the in-
fluence of Heideggerian philosophy, Norberg-Schulz understanding
of the “essential act” overlaps with the “creative act” and “derivative
act”. Thus, the living itself creates the form, place, and image. The fact
that Norberg-Schulz expresses his thoughts on architecture through
two acts reinforces this statement.
Rossi, on the other hand, has a separate understanding of this notion.
As we mentioned before, Rossi has two main approaches to “city”.
These are “city as a man-made object” and “city as a work of art”.
We can clearly see that both of these approaches are fundamen-
tally connected to “human creation” as Viollet-le-Duc calls it. This is
not a conscious process of creation. This is a creation mostly as a
result of “living” and “rituals”. Thus, Rossi’s two main approaches are
fundamentally derived from “living” and “rituals”. Rossi mentions this
connection with these words:
“How are collective urban artifacts related to works of art?
All great manifestations of social life have in common with
the work of art the fact that they are born in unconscious life.
This life is collective in the former, individual in the latter; but
this is only a secondary difference because one is a product
of the public and the other is for the public: the public pro-
vides the common denominator.”505
Rossi considers the “city as a work of art” as an outcome of “uncon-
scious life”. He also mentions that this “unconscious life” is primarily
collective. Thus, Rossi considers the urban artifacts which form the city
as an outcome of the unconscious life.
In conclusion, although Rossi and Norberg-Schulz have quite different
fundamental philosophies of architecture, they have a similar basis to
understand architecture. This similarity can be unclear at first sight. How-
ever, under serious examination, it is obvious that this intersection of their
interpretations is strongly related to the elements that shape the process
of formation of archetypes. This process of formation is fundamentally
based on the intention to maintain and protect the “essential act” which
is the living and the rituals. Hence, Rossi and Norberg-Schulz under-
stand the main intention of architecture is to let “life take a place”. 505. Aldo Rossi, The Architecture of the
City (Massachusetts: MIT Press, 1984;
Original: 1966), 33.
198
199
BIBLIOGRAPHY
200
Karihaloo, B. L., Zhang, K., & Wang, J. “Honeybee combs: how the
circular cells transform into rounded hexagons.” Journal of the Roy-
al Society, Interface, 10:86 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1098/
rsif.2013.0299.
Nes, Akkelies van. “The Heaven, the Earth and the Optic Array: Nor-
berg-Schulz’s Place Phenomenology and its Degree of Operation-
ability.” Footprint 3 (2008): 113–134.
201
méthodique: Architecture, III, 543–45. 1788.
DIGITAL SOURCES
202
Architectuul. “Aldo Rossi.” Accessed June 24, 2023. https://architectu-
ul.com/architect/aldo-rossi.
203