Davis Whitney How To Make Analogies Digital
Davis Whitney How To Make Analogies Digital
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/40368434?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The MIT Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to October
WHITNEY DAVIS
I will start with a truism even though, like all truisms, it reduces and c
flates distinctions and nuances to which I will need to revert: painting - in
sense of "painting as an art" - has been a classic analog mode of representa
whether or not every painter in the history of art has used it this way. It cannot
a surprise, then, that it might be specifically in painting - in its specifica
painterly and pictorial achievements and reversions - that we might best be
to gauge the depth and direction of digital technologies of image productio
well as notions of phenomena, appearance, and representation associated
them in their theoretical foundation and recent history.
The best logical analysis of the analog property of painting as an art - for
him, denning depiction as a symbol system - remains Nelson Goodman's Languages
of Art, published in 1968. It will be useful to recall Goodman's terms, not least
because "analog" and "digital" do not figure prominently among them despite
their increasingly widespread circulation at the time his book was written.1
Indeed, Goodman seems to have intended Languages of Art partly as a founda-
tional explication (and to some extent a critique) of contemporary vocabularies
of information, computation, and representation - including a growing tendency
to suppose that their domains of "analog" and "digital" exhaustively parse the
OCTOBER 117, Summer 2006, pp. 71-98. © 2006 October Magazine, Ltd. and Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
entire field o
ingly basic p
masks a host o
symbol system
Thus it does n
"inscription")
which I will r
and precise ch
equally impor
struggled to o
wrote, "the di
illustrate than to define."3
II
6. Ibid., p. 20.
7. Goodman, Languages of Art, p. 162.
8. Ibid., pp. 162, 164. In the late 1960s, when Languages of Art was written, "length of the message"
was a dominant constraint on the deployment of digital computers in the replication of virtually all
symbol systems. Now, it has faded away in the replication of most of them - including some that were at
one time unprocessable.
density and r
ial scheme is
differentiatio
morphologica
order of notat
no mark or in
"a" belongs to
must be theo
belong to one
character A it
(articulation).
atively dense
not hold. In a
one and the s
flank of Mou
depicts just on
flank of Moun
and if it is not
Strictly spea
infinitely ma
Looking ahead
representation
if we were to
salient modul
able pixels p
cannot discov
inexchangeabl
in principle t
and incarnati
This possibili
zons for the
pictorial sche
stitutive in
density - wo
might try to
ture.12 As Go
the line, its c
10. Goodman, La
11. Ibid., p. 136.
12. Ibid., pp. 229-30. I have added this emphasis on the possible morphological indiscernibility of
the "analog" and "digital" representations - the dense/replete and the disjoint/articulate symbol
schemes respectively - for reasons that will become apparent. It is not, however, a point pursued by
Goodman, who tended to stress the palpable difference - however fine or subtle - between the phe-
nomenal morphology of analog and digital schemes.
of the syntac
Richard Woll
ment that we
to the project
painting.19
In this regar
symbol system
expression to
torial art wor
not possible t
Andre Bazin,
photograph o
knew them -
tationality, i
depiction.20
In a telling experiment, for example, Fry made a copy of a drawing by Paul
Klee: he used a ruler to trace its each and every line. But the copy, a kind of scan,
cannot fully capture the slight wobble of Klee's line - a wobble that helps depict the
little man's tense liveliness. Fry offered this juxtaposition in part as a visual proof of
his kind of formalism - its unformalizable attentiveness to the configurative inter-
minability of pictorial art works and other complex manmade forms.21
18. Other ambiguous symbol schemes do not have this peculiarity. In the written text of a poem
(because it is a notation), the ambiguity of marks and their compliants (letters that spell words) must be
modest - even if the ambiguity of the poetic image (the imaginative picture it creates) can be extreme. A
painted pictorial representation (/that poetic image can transfer - it must transfer - the ambiguity into
both the definition of the mark (the painting) and its discriminability from the correlate (the figured poet-
ic image). In this respect, the ambiguity of depictions and the ambiguity of descriptions must be distin-
guished. Because they do not notate, pictures do not describe. The implications for computationalism -
and the ubiquitous "computer metaphor" for the human mind - are obvious; as Ned Block has put it neat-
ly, "the computer metaphor goes naturally with descriptional representations, but it is not at all clear how
it can work when the representations are nondescriptional" ("Mental Pictures and Cognitive Science,"
Philosophical Review 92 [1983], p. 535; by "descriptional," Block means digital - i.e., Goodman's disjoint
and articulate). For my own crude efforts to describe the awa/og-computational (density-preserving)
image-construction program of depiction, see Whitney Davis, "The Origins of Image Making," Current
Anthropology 27 (1986), pp. 193-215, and "Replication and Depiction in Paleolithic Art," Representations 19
(1987), pp. 111-47 (both reprinted in Replications: Archaeology, Art History, Psychoanalysis [University Park:
Pennsylvania State University Press, 1996], pp. 46-94).
19. See Richard Wollheim, Two Kinds of Formalism (Barcelona: Fondation Tapies, 1994).
20. See especially Last Lectures by Roger Fry, ed. Kenneth Clark (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1939); Andre Bazin, What Is Cinema?, trans. Hugh Gray, 2 vols. (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1967-71); and Wollheim, Painting as an Art.
21. Last Lectures by Roger Fry, pp. 22-23, 57-58. It is perhaps no surprise that the first illustration in
Goodman's Languages of Art (p. 2) reproduces a perspectival drawing of a floor and/or a facade from
Klee's 1925 Pedagogical Sketchbook. Following Klee, Goodman mobilized the drawing to help launch his
argument that marks can only be interpreted in terms of the symbol system in which they function - not in
terms of what they resemble or in terms of a world whose visual configuration they supposedly reproduce.
But we could readily cite it as a perspicuous instance of pictorial richness and ambiguity in the terms con-
sidered here: the drawing is both floor and facade - and dense and replete in either case/both cases.
On the face of it, Fry's experiment would pose a challenge - albeit a chal-
lenge somewhat avant la lettre - to the analytical diagramming, and especially to
the computational digitizing, of pictorial art works that must characterize another
kind of formalism. In these operations, a mechanism tries to "see," compute,
transform, and replicate a scene (it is often called "the target scene" by computer-
vision specialists) using technology and algorithms like Fry's copy-scan in which a
straight line is placed wherever one of Klee's original lines (straight or not) is to
be found. In digital imaging - and taking Fry's analytic diagramming to one tech-
nical and logical endpoint - the replicative mechanism breaks the scene down
into discrete units (in Goodman's terms, disjoint and articulate marks putatively
compliant with the drawing, disjoint and articulate or not) in order to "process"
(or, in Goodman's terms, to notate) both its inscriptional order and its objective
correlate, that is, how the scene depicts what it does. Throughout, and because of
its conversion of dense and replete pictoriality relayed in the original representa-
tion, the scan must overlook variations or modulations that have not been
programmed into the digital replications - dense, replete variations and modula-
tions that cannot be programmed when the original image (the mark and its
correlate together in ambiguous parallel, or [l] + [2] + [3] + [4] + [5]) cannot be ren-
dered in discrete, differentiated units, especially in the highly abstracted form of
identical, interchangeable units.
To be sure,
ing can certa
a digital tech
mark - or th
when the pa
notationally
replete picto
marking tha
possibly did
mark making
had a notable
Stiegler's Tech
For my pur
crete inscrip
the disjoint
Paleolithic p
torial, which
to disjoint, a
tion, or dat
marking, Gr
detain us her
tizing constr
image-scan w
22. A vigorous
Walter Seitter, "
erally his Physik
trades on two s
crete (if not dis
makes the case
sentational syst
pictorialization
Goodman has b
ple, Antony Rai
[1972], pp. 1-21
computer-assiste
23. Andre Leroi
Press, 1993); Be
Beardsworth an
points out, disc
required in nota
many symbol sy
we have seen, th
the mark "A" is
not be discrete e
acters A, B, and
terms of the p
(Dordrecht: D. R
here I cite the d
Ill
24. This useful term is Kent Bach's ("Part of What a Picture Is," British Journal of Aesthetics 10 [1970],
pp. 119-37). Bach explicitly developed his account as a refinement and (re)specification of
Goodman's model of density and repleteness, but it is not necessary to engage the intricacies here. For
the overall approach, see also Michael Polanyi, "What Is a Painting?," British Journal of Aesthetics 10
(1970), pp. 225-36. For technical perspective, see Clare D. McGillem and George R. Cooper,
Continuous and Discrete Signal and System Analysis (New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston, 1974).
immediately.
granulation b
let alone any
might coin a p
tinuous corre
correlation c
lively human
units of their
But then ag
reason, I think
ence between
importance
diversity of r
systems. If a
they might h
historical and
many new m
image - typic
digital mode
recursions of the two modes.
As I want t
increasingly
resentation
duplicate wi
tions that can be rendered in any analog mode. The analog and digital
replications are often indiscernible from each other and frequently they are func-
tionally interchangeable. That is to say, analog and digital modes are now
themselves wholly continuous. They are continuously correlated with each other
despite internal discontinuity on the one (digital) side and continuity with the
external correlates on the other (analog) side.28
IV
At this point we should turn to the artistic "co-mingling" of analog and digital
modes, to use the term applied by Ludwig Seyfarth to certain new media art works.29
It is possible, I suppose, that art works are essentially indifferent - constitutionally
impervious or constitutionally resistant - to any categorical distinction of their ana-
log and digital faces. I will not try to characterize the ontology of art in these
suggestive terms. But this interdigitation - creating a continuity of the discontinu-
ous that is parallel to a discontinuity of the continuous - appears to be one
constitutive concern in the construction, installation, and display of many contem-
porary pictorial arts, including paintings or highly painterly works. And if the real
indiscernibility and interchangeability of analog and digital has de-differentiated
these modes, then the representational value of their distinction (if any remains)
can only be generated figuratively in analogies to this condition - a range of possi-
bilities that must depend on what the image-producer (and the replication
mechanisms he or she used) has taken to be dense and replete (or not) in the
inscriptions and referential correlates secured in various media.
into computer graphics software and often into the hardware itself." This was clearly true in the tight
constraints that were placed on - and the spatial or perspectival "knowledge" that had to be provided
programmatically to - the early line-finder and other polygonal-modeling programs of the mid-1960s
and early 1970s (see Boden, "Adding the Third Dimension," Artificial Intelligence and Natural Man, pp.
180-90). By the mid-1980s, the application of Benoit Mandelbrot's mathematics of fractals enabled
emergent computer graphics programs to recognize and construct such "natural" entities as trees, coast-
lines, mountains, and (at last) human bodies (Benoit B. Mandelbrot, The Fractal Geometry of Nature [New
York: Freeman, 1982]; for naturalistic modeling, see R. F. Voss, "Random Fractal Forgeries," in R. A.
Earnshaw, ed., Fundamental Algorithms for Computer Graphics [Berlin: Springer, 1985], pp. 805-35).
28. I have tried to heed Manovich's remarks on "the myth of the digital" (The Language of New
Media, pp. 52-55); as Manovich suggests, since the 1980s, at least, the logical distinction between ana-
log and digital has subsisted disjunctively in relation to the technical capacities of analog and digital
replication relative to one another.
29. Ludwig Seyfarth, "The Best Destinations Are Just Down the Street: Where Painters Travel to
Today," in Painting Pictures, p. 43. Seyfarth refers specifically to the work of the painter Ben Edwards, to
which I will turn momentarily.
Jeff Wall.
Untangling. 1994.
Courtesy the artist
and Marian
Goodman Gallery,
New York.
that we are l
fidelity by t
also in index
component in
trompe-Uoeil
late. This disc
a sign - and
gized but als
devices of "s
paintings and
of images the
play (Wall's l
they functio
ones - of "pa
afforded by e
then, the ima
of art - in th
sion of "pain
and airport s
photograph
digital-multi
In fact, the
photograph -
projected on
affixed. And
instead of fa
television scr
Not a photog
no longer in
relay of the a
Resolution o
seems to be v
relative weig
configuratio
material and
the chiaroscu
generated in
have been re
figuratively u
brings the an
or discontinu
tography in
this effect: at this scale, and lighted from behind, many digital p
despite high resolution - -just might reveal their discontinuities in corre
the illuminated scene, which could no longer be seen as everywher
with the uniform radiation emanating within the light box. For tha
Wall's analogy would fail; its delicate recursions would break down.
then, digital technology cannot really be used to make the work. The
cally figures its possibility. By the same token, however, the figu
depends essentially on emergent technical identities and phenomen
bilities of analog and digital.
Wall is not a new media artist. By contrast, painter Ingrid Cala
within the world of technique now defined by software - the digi
and printing of pictures and paintings - like Photoshop, Paintbox, a
In one series, the clarity and visible computability of the intricate su
derives from a sequence and layering of transfers and duplications.
image must be distinguished from a mixture, a soak, of dripped or
and spots that cannot be untangled or separated - that is, differenti
registrations. Calame begins by tracing the contours of spots, stain
imprints in the streets or on walls in Los Angeles. In making and o
traces, she partly obeys - she actively literalizes and digitizes - recom
painters proffered by Leonardo da Vinci and other proponents of t
imagination. These configurations have been transferred at scal
enlarged in square-by-square transcriptions, assigned color values, a
hand with enamels on square sheets of aluminum - nearly two meter
case of Ckckhckhckg/ruh
(2002). One could do this
entirely on a computer - the
painting analogizes a possi-
ble, if possibly mad, print
out - if it were not for the
fact, of course, that one can-
not do it entirely on a
computer. Printing in non-
computational media hovers
nearby: the painting analo-
gizes color lithography or
silkscreen as if routed
Ingrid Calame. Ckckhckhckg/ruh. 2002. Courtesy the artist and James Cohan Gall
In fact, Cala
But this circu
could be gene
reproduced b
tion and the
analog proced
tion of visibl
symbol schem
analogizes tec
in a continuo
continuous t
painting that
in digital mo
analog paintin
Analogy - lik
thus analogy
purposes, an
respects with
secured and r
in what seem
image looks l
quality" mon
of a real pla
garage and a
can seem to d
finest discrim
rative lookin
light-box/ph
television br
then, the ana
ative to a cor
respects. The
son, measure
"two by twos
figure, analog
correlates. W
30. I am indebte
Down the Street
and deeply mult
and glazes" in tr
signature" - unl
selves and which
dure not unlike
pursued in the p
not that they are stains in the street or even that they are p
street. (We also say that they look like drip paintings by
like the raveled ropes in Wall's Untangling, sort of; and s
image relays its analogization: the fact that Calame's stain
hand-painted, neither quite like real stains nor quite
images, is figuratively crucial.
Both Wall and Calame seem to remain on the "old media" side - a side
With this in mind, we can formulate a question for new media art or, more
broadly, for any artists working in a culture of digital media and digitized images.
What happens when artistic analogy - striving for the richness and ambiguity of
analogy and art - arrives at the indiscernibility and interchangeability of analog
and digital? - when it is indifferent to analog and digital modes of representation
in securing apparently identical figurative interactions? Indeed, what happens
when digital modes become more popular or preferred - literally required by the
digital filtering and compression of images, analog as they might be in an
unprocessed state, when they are uploaded to and downloaded from the Web or
local networks? In the visual and spatial arts, analog modes of representation his-
torically did the heavy lifting of artistic analogy, despite crucial digital mediations.
Now, though probably not for the first time, the emphasis has changed. In fact,
the equation might appear to be reversed. In visual/spatial configurations, digital
modes constitute analogies.
In contemporary art we find the emergence of what might be called the
New Analogy: of palpably or at least discernibly discontinuous correlation as the
ground of the figure. In principle this need not be inimical to the construction
of analogical figuration as such. Analogy emerges in limited continuities with
part-correlates, a relation that conceivably can be handled just as well in the dis-
joint and differentiated terms (or notations) of the digital mode as in the dense
and replete terms (or images) of the analog mode. But not surprisingly - and
precisely because of the new indiscernibility of analog and digital modes and the
new indifference of image making in using them - the new analogies, digitally
relayed, look quite like the old, analogically generated. Indeed, they must look
quite like the old if they are to do any deep or rich work of analogization, at least
for the time being.
In Massimo
C-prints beh
beach at Ricc
and from tw
facts of tem
because the
it seems to b
Moreover, ev
tion, and dis
a big Deardo
structed platf
A close insp
have related
them: they a
ers - most o
giant podium
anyone looki
digitally in b
does seem a
whether by
series of Ital
Berlusconi in
to observe m
standing of
Italian norm
bances of th
leisure, delud
the social cor
of the beach
twinned ana
images: we se
In contrast
tographs - o
techniques -
removing (th
of the repr
synthesizing
31. Quoted in A
tion about Vital
of their own an
belie this asserti
naturalistic pain
manipulated pict
VI
Compared to
shore of new
a Bourgeois S
The Monumen
landscaping f
mages to Lui
photographs
and metric pr
porate parks
already digitiz
have been com
photographi
coordinate gr
of Edwards's c
the superimp
looks like det
As Seyfarth h
figurative an
marble, or st
"corporate ar
course, contin
tionality, ex
correlates. Non
tions of digiti
so on) remain
actual digitizi
and between
digital pictor
Both painted
ric space of p
representatio
in it. (Indeed
early-sixteen
tions of per
technology in
ends it has su
Presumably
potential ma
mercialized s
use digitized
heterogeneit
structed wor
digital units
sented. Anal
might well b
conclusion in
correlate pse
To be fair,
that would b
painting in a
tions, it se
proportional
of an averag
unit that ap
each side (or
digital! We c
of a real, dig
regimes of s
Edwards. The
Courtesy the art
36. David Marr, Vision: A Computational Investigation into the Human Repre
Information (New York: W. H. Freeman, 1982). In turn, Marr's work was
research of David Hubel and Torsten N. Wiesel in the early 1960s on the v
On its appearance, Marr's book generated great excitement; it motivated
doctoral dissertation in art history in the early 1980s - that the "sociolo
combined with what I called a cognitive history and algorithmic ana
Davis, The Canonical Tradition in Ancient Egyptian Art [New York: Camb
xvii, 6; for comments on Cassirerean epistemology as it constituted th
gy in art history - its movement between "visual" and "mental" images
and Pictoriality," Res 46 [2004], pp. 9-31). For representative applicat
biology of vision to an array of problems in human imaging, see Ro
Visual Arts (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1994); Shimon Ullman, High
and Visual Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1996); Donald D. H
We Create What We See (New York: Norton, 1998); and Zenon W. Pylyshy
What You Think (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2003). Despite the pub
tertexts - I might cite Michael Podro's Depiction (New Haven: Yale Un
Maynard's two superb books The Engine of Visualization: Thinking Th
Cornell University Press, 1997) and Drawing Distinctions: The Varieties o
Cornell University Press, 2005) - this debate has yet to be joined, eve
most important nexus for art history and criticism to address at the adv
In the recen
using digital
digital proce
in the image
world. The s
haps "new,"
drawings ph
basis for fre
and acute ang
the picture -
constructed
seems to em
GH), and "fr
transversal o
tric line of
artistic analo
materially fo
alized there.
morphing st
ogy of movem
My point h
New Analogy
tion of the
continuous c
extra-pictor
unless and u
new media d
current new
versely, anal
closed) new (
kinds. But in
digital analog
nitions of an
possibility o
cance - even
mediations.
How is this to be done? Bite before bit, we might say: to make analogies in a
digital age, analog your digitizations! What's between your fingers but that world
into which you have thrust your hand?