Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4 David Sobel Download PDF Chapter
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4 David Sobel Download PDF Chapter
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Oxford Studies in
Political
Philosophy
Volume 4
Edited by
D av i d S o b e l, Pe t e r Va l l e n t y n e,
a n d S t ev e n Wa l l
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
3
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, ox2 6dp,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
© the several contributors 2018
Te moral rights of the authors have been asserted
First Edition published in 2018
Impression: 1
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
198 Madison Avenue, New York, NY 10016, United States of America
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Data available
ISBN 978–0–19–881397–2 (Hbk.)
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Preface
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Contents
List of Contributors ix
Part I: Legitimacy
1. Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 3
Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
2. Te Power of Public Positions: Ofcial Roles
in Kantian Legitimacy 28
Tomas Sinclair
3. Institutional Legitimacy 53
Allen Buchanan
Index 219
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
List of Contributors
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
PA RT I
LEGITIMACY
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
1
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy
Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
1. INTRODUCTION
those at the receiving end claim they were wronged? Suppose, further, that
you had the power not only to resist the coercion but coercively to impose
an alternative policy on others. Perhaps you have some control over police
budgets and can secretly divert resources from some neighbourhoods to others.
Perhaps you are the clerk to a legislature and can amend legislation without
anybody noticing (Overland and Barry, 2011). Could it be permissible for
you to do so?
Te conventional view in the philosophical literature holds both that it
would be impermissible for you to do so and that it would be permissible
for the state to coerce you. In what follows we focus mainly on the latter:
the permissibility of state coercion. Te conventional view is that democratic
decisions are permissibly enforceable unless they are gravely unjust—perhaps
when they blatantly violate basic human rights—but we assume that none
of the cases we have outlined meets that standard. In cases of less serious
social injustice, it is generally thought that their democratic provenance
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
4 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
those decisions, which in the case we present here amounts to their being
democratic.
Our use of “legitimate” difers from that in some of the philosophical
literature. Sometimes the question of whether a decision is legitimate is
simply that of whether it is permissible to enforce the decision. (Sometimes
the question of legitimacy is substituted for, or taken together with, the
1
Something is permissibly enforceable, let us say, when enforcing it (in line with
any further requirements of proportionality and status of the enforcer) does not wrong
anyone. A decision may be permissibly enforceable without there being any reason to
enforce it: the fact that the decision was made in a given way may make it permissibly
enforceable without there being a good reason to enforce it all the same. Tat said, in
what follows we assume that there is a reason to enforce the permissibly enforceable
decisions in question. We are grateful to David Estlund and Andrew Williams for
discussion.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 5
further question of whether the decision has authority; i.e., whether those
subject to coercion have a duty to comply with the coercion, or even the
duty to obey.) Te issue of permissible enforceability is generally thought
to depend on both the content and the provenance of the decision; the
conventional view holds that democratic decisions are not permissibly
enforceable in cases where their content is gravely unjust.
We, by contrast, restrict the term “legitimate” to the issue of provenance,
to the procedural aspect. Whether a coercive decision is legitimate, for us,
depends entirely on how it was made; it is a further question whether it is
in fact permissibly enforceable. One can thus accept that a procedure—and
the decision it has produced—are perfectly legitimate, while insisting that
the injustice of its content would make it impermissible to enforce that
decision. Te dethroning of democratic legitimacy we aim to achieve in this
chapter is a weakening of the contribution that legitimacy in our sense makes
to legitimacy in the other sense.
We have said that the justice of a decision is a matter of its content
rather than its provenance. But of course ways of making decisions can
themselves be evaluated as just or unjust, and so we could have framed our
argument in terms of the familiar contrast between “procedural” and
“substantive” justice. If citizens have a right to an equal say in the procedures
by which their laws are made, then justice itself—procedural justice—requires
that the laws be made that way. Indeed, we might have followed Pettit
(2015) in framing the “content/provenance” distinction as being between
“social justice” and “political justice”: the latter, for him, coincides “with
what is often described as the legitimacy as distinct from the justice—I would
say, the social justice—of the structure” (11). For Pettit, then, what we are
calling “legitimacy” is labelled, in the political context, “political justice”.
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
6 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
2
Te conventional view is also often claimed to establish authority, or is ambiguous
between the two claims; we put this aside.
3
We put aside some complications, such as that in circumstances of emergency
permissible enforceability could be grounded in other ways. In addition to Rawls, this
view is endorsed by Tomas Christiano (2004, 2008), Philip Pettit (2015), Jonathan
Quong (2010), Tomas Sinclair (chapter 2 of this book [and private correspondence]),
Laura Valentini (2012), and, as we suggest in §4.5, possibly Daniel Viehof (2014). More
generally, we think that most Rawlsians are supporters of the view and possibly also most
Kantians, though the latter may deny that justice and democracy can come apart. Estlund
(2008: 111) is carefully non-committal on the limits of democracy’s ability to permit
enforcement.
4
Notice that Rawls talks about the case when procedures or laws are “too gravely
unjust” (our italics). For him, apparently, there can be grave injustices that are not “too
grave” and which do not thereby corrupt the legitimacy of the procedure. We will ignore
this complication, henceforward taking him to hold that “grave” injustice is grave enough
to “corrupt” legitimacy. An alternative reading of the phrase is also possible, according to
which Rawls holds an implicit balancing view.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 7
certain ways in which citizens meet one another’s justice claims qualify as
“social justice” only if they are put, and kept, in place by democratic
procedures (Pettit 2015). All this can be granted while retaining the crucial
point that the demands of social justice, fully and properly understood, may
difer from, and confict with, the demands that result even from perfectly
legitimate democratic procedures.
5
Assuming the absence of less gravely unjust alternatives.
6
Whether or not it is necessary is left unclear, given Rawls’s views on global justice,
which we put aside. We dispute both the sufciency and the necessity claims.
7
Tis can be done by stipulating the conditions for a genuinely democratic process
(e.g. that all participants see their co-citizens as their moral equals). Such a move might
also ensure that we could always locate some value in the democratic process. We are
sympathetic to such a stipulation but insist that, while it may rule out some substantively
unjust outcomes from being decided by the demos, it cannot plausibly rule out all of
them.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
8 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
Our alternative proposal is that democratic legitimacy and social justice both
ground pro tanto claims to a decision’s permissible enforceability; these
claims have to be weighed or otherwise taken into account on a case-by-case
basis. We say “weighed or otherwise taken into account,” since we are not
committed to a simple view of weighing (though we refer to “weighing”
throughout, for simplicity). Perhaps in some contexts one consideration
can pre-empt or otherwise eliminate the need to consider the other: what
matters is whether, taking into account what can be achieved, there is greater
reason to advance legitimacy or justice in any given case.8 Te two ideals at
stake invoke diferent normative considerations; they embody and advance
(that is, respect or promote) diferent values. Even with grave injustice of the
table, we see no reason to regard the considerations invoked by the former as
invariably weightier or more forceful than those invoked by the latter.
In terms of our proposed analysis, the conventional view can be regarded
as a claim about a particular case: it holds that only injustices of a particular
level of severity—those deemed “grave”—are unjust enough to outweigh or
otherwise block the pro tanto permissible enforceability conferred on them
in virtue of their having been produced by procedures that realize or
promote legitimacy values to a certain degree. Tat degree need not be
100%—recall Rawls: “A legitimate procedure gives rise to legitimate laws
and policies made in accordance with it; and legitimate procedures may be
customary, long established, and accepted as such. Neither the procedures
nor the laws need be just by a strict standard of justice, even if, what is also
true, they cannot be too gravely unjust” (our emphasis). For us, casting the
conventional view in this light—bringing out the scalarity in both components
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
8
It might be doubted that democratic procedures always give even a pro tanto reason
for its being permissible to enforce a decision. Unlike our balancing view, the conventional
view can deny that the fact that a gravely unjust outcome was the outcome of an otherwise
ideal procedure does anything to support the view that that outcome is permissibly
enforceable. We fnd this position implausible: if the value of the procedure does not
depend solely on the outcome it delivers, it is unclear why the mere fact that an outcome
is unjust, even if gravely so, deprives the procedure of all value.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 9
that this relationship holds whether we are interested in what is right and
wrong relative to the facts or relative to the evidence available.9
More schematically, the balancing view holds that the avoidance of (more)
grave injustice is necessary and sufcient for permissible enforceability: it is
permissible to enforce the outcome that avoids (more) grave injustice than
the alternative, and it is impermissible to enforce any alternative. So the
avoidance of (more) grave illegitimacy is neither necessary nor sufcient for
permissible enforceability. But we also deny that full justice is necessary
for permissible enforceability: sometimes the imperfectly just legitimate
decision will be permissibly enforceable.
Our negative case for our balancing view is to point out the problems with the
conventional view, which is either vague or implausible. It is vague if it amounts
to the view that anything that outweighs legitimacy should count as grave
injustice. If so, then the conventional view may even collapse into the balancing
view on the quiet. If, on the other hand, the view invokes some independent
account of what counts as grave injustice then it is implausible. Tere is no
good reason to think that democratic legitimacy should generally outweigh
social justice when the two values confict, even with grave injustice of the
table. Te conventional view gains credibility when the value of legitimacy—
democratic procedures—is not properly analysed. Once it is (and our
analysis is mostly ofered in §§4.3–4.5) we see that the credence-giving
value of democratic procedures is not unique to them, while the remaining
value or values—variously articulated as non-subordination or treating
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
9
On “fact-relativity,” and distinctions between it and “belief-relativity” and “evidence-
relativity,” see Parft (2011: 150–62).
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
10 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
what is the majority view. In this case, let us suppose, the outcome derives
its permissible enforceability entirely from its being the outcome of the
procedure, because there is no procedure-independent reason to enforce one
colour over the other. If so, my vote cannot even represent an independent
judgement of what colour it would be permissible to enforce.
When I vote on whether to protect an area of outstanding natural beauty
I may believe that there is a procedure-independent reason to enact such
coercive legislation—this area of natural beauty ought to be protected no
matter what everyone thinks. But I may also think that the decision is not
10
Tat said, the view that judgements of justice are mere recommendations could not
hold that a vote for X means “X ought to be enforced if and only if it is democratically
decided.” Tat view is satisfed even if nothing is democratically decided, since then the
conditional has not been violated. A vote surely means more than “don’t enforce this
unless it is democratically passed.” We are grateful to David Estlund for this point as well
as for making us clarify our argument in this section.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 11
one of justice and in such cases only the procedure can confer permissible
enforceability on the decision.
But we can also imagine cases where in voting for a given outcome,
I am making an independent judgement about what just outcome it
would be permissible to enforce. Put diferently, we can imagine cases
where I am making a judgement about what justice demands about what
should be decided and enforced. In such cases if I lose, and the fact that
I lose does not lead me to change my mind, I believe that we have made
a mistake somewhere along the line when we enforce the outcome I voted
against.
At this point we can consider two possibilities. First, we might hold that
the mistake occurred at the point of decision-making but, once the wrong
decision was made, it became permissible to enforce the wrong decision:
only the procedure—and not the correctness of the judgment—confers
permissible enforceability on the decision. Tis is compatible with seeing
judgements of justice as provisional recommendations.
Second, we might hold that the mistake occurred both at the point of
decision-making and at the point of enforcement of the (wrong) decision.
We could accept that a democratic body should decide X and enforce what
it decided, without being committed to believing that the body should
enforce what is decided if it did not decide X. We could further hold that X
is so important that it should be enforced even if X was not decided by the
democratic body. If so, when voting, we could be inputting our judgement
about X precisely as a judgement about what permissibly enforceable claims
people have, and the judgement about what those claims are can be made
on grounds independent of the collective procedure to which they are
inputting their judgement. On this view, the question others are getting
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
the wrong answer to when they do not vote for X is precisely what it
would be permissible to enforce on grounds independent of the procedure for
collectively deciding that question, rather than the question of what should
be provisionally recommended for enforcement.
Te “recommendation” view rules out the very possibility that individuals’
inputs to democratic procedures could be understood by them (and others)
as judgements about citizens’ claims against one another that are permissibly
enforceable on procedure-independent grounds. Our claim is not that we
must, on pain of conceptual incoherence, accept that some judgements
of social justice take this unconditional form. Rather, we hold that seeing
some claims of justice this way confers special importance on them, or rather,
in our view, captures the importance they already have. Tey are claims that
deny others the normative power to block their enforcement. Tese claims
are so important, in other words, that others lose the standing objection to
coercion they enjoy in other cases.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
12 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
unclear how this trick can be pulled of. We will argue that it cannot.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 13
they include: the actual votes of actual citizens. But including and responding
appropriately to the views and preferences of others may well be important
to the correct identifcation of what social justice requires as that identifcation
is attempted by each individual.
To avoid confusion, let us call such procedures undertaken by an individual,
in contrast to the democratic ones, processes.11 Such a process may be needed
because for one to have any confdence that one’s input to the legitimate
decision-making procedure correctly identifes social justice, one must have,
and be able to ofer to others, certain kinds of reasoning or considerations
as relevant. As an individual making one’s own judgement about what social
justice requires, it is likely to be helpful to engage with others, consider their
reasoning, see if their reasoning undermines one’s justifcations, and so on.
But one must also satisfy an internal justifcatory process, have subjected it
to critical refection, and so on (Goodin, 2000). Tinking about what people
would or would not agree to, or what could be justifed to them under certain
idealized conditions, or would emerge from a certain kind of procedure, were
it undertaken, may be part of that process. In some senses the individual’s own
process will be “collective” or “inclusive” in that it is likely to incorporate,
or at least in some ways respond to, the views of others. But this concerns
the individual forming her judgement about the correct input to the
legitimating procedure. It does not concern the sum of those individual
inputs being combined into a collective decision through an actual procedure
for combining them.12
Crucially, then, it is possible to distinguish between (i) processes to which
we as individuals (albeit perhaps through deliberation with others) must
subject candidate principles in order to assess them correctly as principles of
justice and (ii) procedures that individuals’ judgements about principles of
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
11
We thank David Estlund for pressing us to clarify this.
12
For a similar suggestion, presented as a criticism of Forst (2014), see Caney’s (2014:
156) insistence on the importance of distinguishing between “the justifcation required
for political legitimacy (political justifcation) and the justifcation required for a view to
be philosophically correct (philosophical justifcation)” (his emphases).
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
14 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
13
Amartya Sen (2009: 326) risks running the two modes—(i) and (ii)—together: “If
the demands of justice can only be assessed with the help of public reasoning, and if
public reasoning is constitutively related to the idea of democracy, then there is an
intimate connection between justice and democracy, with shared discursive features.” Te
thought here is that the way one goes about identifying justice, if one is doing it right,
involves a kind of reasoning (which Sen calls “public reasoning”) that will itself play a role
in any properly democratic way of making a collective decision. Even if that is true, we
are not sure that Sen always holds on to the distinction between the two distinct elements
in the picture. His emphasis on “social choice theory,” which is “deeply concerned with
the rational basis of social judgments and public decisions” (95, our emphases), seems to
involve a slide from the frst to the second. An individual’s judgement can be “social” in
being about social matters and it can be “public” in the sense of being about public matters
(or publicly available, or based on public reasoning). But talk of “public decisions,” and
indeed the very idea of “social choice,” takes us across the analytical divide into the (for
us) entirely distinct business of combining individuals’ judgements into a collective
decision. Te legitimacy of such a decision may well depend on its democratic provenance
(including perhaps considerations concerning the kinds of reasoning that citizens may
properly engage in when deciding on public matters), but it remains a distinct question
whether that decision is right about social justice.
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 15
But in other cases, we should expect people to be less confdent about what
would be legitimate than about what would be just. Te view that, society’s
resources permitting, children with weak immune systems have the right
that mass vaccinations be compulsory for the sake of herd immunity, or that
social justice requires that proper resources be spent on protecting poor
citizens from crime, or that a 5% pay gap between citizens who difer only
by gender or ethnicity is unjust, can be held with greater confdence than a
view about what would be the legitimate procedure for deciding those
questions. Tese doubts can take the form of disagreement over the specifc
democratic procedure that ought to be adopted or, more radically, whether
a given issue should be decided by democratic procedures at all.
14
For discussion of the problem see D. Christensen (2009). We are grateful to David
Estlund for the reference.
15
Jonathan Quong (2010).
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
16 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
warrants a particular kind of response, one that treats each citizen as equally
a source of authority. Unlike the individual judgements that are their inputs,
the outcomes of democratic procedures may permissibly be enforced—even
where they are mistaken—because those procedures are the way of responding
to disagreement that accords citizens equal respect.
Of course, the conventional view holds that the outcomes of otherwise
legitimate procedures lack permissible enforceability when those outcomes
are gravely unjust. So that view does not always prefer the “equally respectful”
procedure to the just outcome; it allows content-reasons to outweigh
procedure-reasons when the former reach a particular level of seriousness.
In addition, many who ground the normative force of democratic decisions
16
See Fabienne Peter (2016) for discussion of how procedures could ground permissible
enforceability because they deliver “sufciently justifed beliefs about normative authority”
and/or “adjudicate between conficting wills.”
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Dethroning Democratic Legitimacy 17
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
18 Zofa Stemplowska and Adam Swift
right to that of others in determining how the shared aspects of social life ought to
be arranged. Tus, they act unjustly. (ibid.: 286)
Let us grant that there is a kind of injustice when a decision about social
justice is enforced that difers from that which would have emerged from
a procedure that equally respected people’s judgement, or that publicly
treated them as equal members of society. Tere is also a kind of injustice
when a decision about social justice is enforced that fails to treat people
equally with respect to those properties or capacities that would have been
treated equally had the correct decision been enforced. Christiano (ibid.:
286) insists that “Te interests involved in being publicly treated as an equal
member of society are the preeminent interests a person has in social life . . .”
(his italics). We accept that those interests are weighty. But the idea of
“interests involved in being publicly treated as an equal member of society”
does not deliver the conclusion that procedural interests take priority over
all other interests (subject to the not-too-grave-injustice clause)—after all,
being publicly treated as an equal could involve both. Or, if the phrase is
mean to denote merely the procedural interests, the claim is unpersuasive.
People’s (non-procedural) interests are equally respected when people get
what they are owed as a matter of social justice, and these interests are
also important.
How should we compare these two diferent aspects of what might be
involved in respecting people equally, or treating them justly? Is it worse to
be denied (i) that procedure for deciding social arrangements which treats
those subject to it with equal respect, or (ii) those social arrangements that
would result from the correct identifcation of the implications of each
person’s claim to equal respect?
We might think about this by contrasting the diferent properties or
Copyright © 2018. Oxford University Press USA - OSO. All rights reserved.
capacities at stake. On the one hand are those properties that are equally
respected by the democratic procedure. Examples here would be the capacity
to make judgements about which distributions should be enforced, or having
that capacity recognized and afrmed by one’s fellow citizens. On the other
hand, are those properties equally respected when the correct, socially just,
decision is enforced? For example, the correct decision about allocation of
resources to health care or education can respect people’s capacities to lead
autonomous lives: democratic publics can decide to devote disproportionate
resources to end-of-life care, or to university education, to the relative
neglect of health care and education for young children. We see no reason
to suppose that the capacities respected by the democratic procedure are so
much more important than the capacities respected by the socially just
education or health care policy as to make only grave mistakes grounds for
denying the permissible enforceability of collective misjudgements. When
we refect on what we ourselves care about, we readily accept that it may
Oxford Studies in Political Philosophy Volume 4, edited by David Sobel, et al., Oxford University Press USA -
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.F.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.
Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.