Martineau, Alain (1986) - Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
Martineau, Alain (1986) - Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
Utopia
Copyright © 198b by Harvest House Ltd.
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be
reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means,
electronic or mechanical, including photography, recording,
or any information storage retrieval system, without
permission in writing from the publisher.
Deposited in the Hibliothe(|iie Nationale of Quebec,
3rd Quarter 198b
Typography and Cover: Naoto Kondo
Printed in Canada
First Harvest House F.dition
For information address:
Harvest House Ltd.,
Suite 1, 1200 Atwater Ave.,
Montreal, Canada H3Z 1X4
b y
Alain Martineau
Translated by
Jane Brierley
Harvest House
MONTREAL lUH(i
To the memory of my father
and to my mother
without whom my education
woidd have been impossible
Translator’s Note
I would like in iliank die auiltor, Dr. Alain Martincau, lor his
generous cooperation, despile a busy leaching and research
schedule, in discussing the text and providing material lor many
of the English citations throughout die work. In the course of
translation, the author has taken the opportunity to make slight
changes or clarifications to the original manuscript (or the
benefit of English-speaking readers. My thanks are also due to
Drew McCarthy, for reading the manuscript and notes.
Not all of Marcuse’s translated writing is the same as the
original, for he too sometimes took the opportunity of adding,
retouching, or even revising his work for publication in another
language. 'Texts that were originally speeches, or recorded
<]uestion-and-answer periods, do not always contain identical
material in English and French versions. Wherever possible,
the published English version has been ({noted. Where this
proved impossible or impracticable, the translator has provided
an English rendition, but the citation refers to the original work.
The same method has been used for other writers cited in this
book.
Contents
Introduction
1
Conclusion
112
Notes
114
Index
149
Acknowledgments
This translation, as well as the original work, has been published
with the help of a grant from the Canadian Federation for the
Humanities, using funds provided by the Social Sciences and
Humanities Research Council of Canada. We also gratefully
acknowledge a translation grant from the Canada Council.
Introduction 1
Introduction
We only seem to have absorbed what u<e don't
understand about M arcuse. 1
1here are many utopias. No one has ever seen them except in
imagination, and yet they are real enough, for they have influ
enced our destiny over the centuries. Utopias are created in
response to the existing world. Just as the worlds of Plato, Sir
Thomas More, and Karl Marx differed, so did their philo
sophical utopias. It is Herbert Marcuse’s utopia that has made
him so significant and controversial a figure in our generation,
and possibly for generations to come.
Marcuse endeavored to describe a viable alternative to the
present dilemma of civilization through the projection of utopian
ideals, and to liberate humans front the repressive forces of
modern society in order to build a better world. Not surpris
ingly, his philosophical ideas took shape in relation to socialist
and Marxist theory and its application to reality. Unlike many
of his utopian predecessors, including Marx, he was privileged
to witness the progress of a full-scale social experiment based
on a philosophical concept.
Marx wrote in his 1844 “Contribution to the Critique of
Hegel’s Philosophy of Law" that the head of man’s “emanci
pation is philosophy, its heart is the proletariat. Philosophy cannot
be made a reality without the abolition of the proletariat, the
proletariat cannot be abolished without philosophy being made
a reality."2 Marx’s programmatic statement did not mean that
philosophy is doomed, however. As Henri Lefebvre remarked
in 1947, “It is not a question of suppressing philosophy, but of
waking it a reality by transcending abstract philosophy and by
suppressing the abstract element of speculative, metaphysical
philosophy.”5 Gerard Raulet, in a fairly recent study of Marx
ism and critical theory, noted that Marcuse’s aim in 1937 was
to give philosophy status within Marxism, as demonstrated in
2 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
The Forerunners of
Marcuse’s Utopia
It is only by studying the long history o f utopia, from Plato
to Thomas M ilnier, from M ore to Fourier and M arx, that we ran
appreciate the real significance o f the utopian theses in
Eros and Civilization.1
Marcuse’s
Romantic Aesthetics
“In a world that has descended to the prosaic, the most impor
tant thing to bring back is the aesthetic dimension . . . which
alone can guarantee the revolution of the twenty-first century.”1
Marcuse was speaking about his short work, The Aesthetic Dimen
sion, during a final conversation with Jean Marabini. “This is
the heritage I leave to world youth on the threshold of the
terrible years that seem imminent.”2
It is no accident that Marcuse’s philosophical testament should
be a work on aesthetics. Throughout his life the question of art
was central to Marcuse’s thinking. His first academic disserta
tion in 1922 contained the seeds of several themes that were
to mark his intellectual journey, and dealt with the German
Kiinstlerroman, the genre of novel in which art plays a signif
icant role.*1 It is therefore crucial to ask exactly what place the
aesthetic dimension occupies in the critical theory of Herbert
Marcuse.
Before we can answer this question, however, there is a
preliminary problem to be resolved. The fact is that, while some
commentators ignore or are unaware of Marcuse’s explicit
utopianism, others have read into Marcusian aesthetics mere
resignation instead of the renewal of his revolutionary spirit.
Ben Agger and Fred Alford were two cases in point. In 1973
Agger wrote an article entitled “The Aesthetic Politics of Herbert
Marcuse.” Referring to Counterrevolution and Revolt, Agger
represented Marcuse’s interest in art as the most recent devel
opment in his critical theory.1This was largely untrue. Not only
was Marcuse always interested in art—it could be considered
his main concern in one sense, as we shall see—but art was a
symbol of the Great Refusal, ’ at least in its extreme forms. Agger
contended that art does not take the place of politics, although
it can “become political by maintaining a ‘dialogue’ with the
()2 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
natural world and with social fact." He pointed out that
“Marcuse’s argument is really quite simple and plausible: we
create ourselves through our art which depicts our true relation
to nature and to our fellow man and woman. Art raises our
consciousness and helps us to imagine a new world. It acts as
a theoretical and spiritual catalyst when all else has failed.”0 It
is perhaps our only hope, Agger concluded. His interpretation
was generally correct, except that he considered Marcuse’s
involvement in aesthetics as the final phase and ignored his
early interest in the subject. This meant that six years later, in
1979, Agger would try to save Marcuse from “aesthetic
resignation"' on the basis of Paul Piccone’s notion of “artificial
negativity."” Piccone asserted that it is possible to go beyond
one-dimensionality by penetrating the world of spontaneous
subjectivity. But surely spontaneity and creativity are both
inherent aspects of art and the revolutionary spirit? (It should
be mentioned in passing that Ben Agger is, in my view, one of
the rare commentators who respects the spirit of Marcuse’s
work.)
Fred Alford also purported to save Marcuse from an impasse.
In reviewing The Aesthetic Dimension,9 he compared some of its
statements with others taken from Marcuse’s essay on Rudolf
Bahro.10 According to Alford, Marcuse’s theory would have
been trapped in a vicious circle, had he not been able to break
out of it with Bahro’s help. Alford wrote, “He did integrate
Bahro’s catalog into the structure of his own project, in order
to begin to overcome its outstanding theoretical deficit: the
vicious circle, which has led to so much unwarranted resigna
tion. No assessment of Marcuse’s work that fails to take seriously
this last step can be complete.”11
I shall refrain from commenting on the idea that Marcuse’s
theory can be better understood by referring to his sources
instead of his own statements. A good many commentators have
seen in Marcuse an interpretation of Marx, Freud, or some
other writer—Bahro in this instance—whereas he almost never
interpreted anyone, except in book reviews. Marcuse was a crit
ical theorist who expressed his own ideas and whose thinking
was not deflected by affinities of thought encountered in his
long intellectual journey.
Alford found two basic tendencies in Marcuse: one good—
his commitment to human happiness; the other bad—his
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 63
romanticism. Fortunately, said Alford, Marcuse appeared to
have sublimated the less desirable of these two tendencies in
the following ways.1* In the first place, Marcuse supposedly
admitted in The Aesthetic Dimension that certain elements of his
vision of liberation, such as “the resurrection of nature,” would
never be realized. Alford supported this by Marcuse’s statement
that “the world was not made for the sake of the human being
and it has not become more human.”13 This freed Marcuse to
solve the problem of “the vicious circle that recurs so often . ..
in Bahro’s book.”11 Alford wrote: "The way out of the vicious
circle turns out to be remarkably easy. Bahro’s book, says
Marcuse, implies that socialist strategy must be essentially the
same before and after the revolution. The cultural revolution
implies the total transformation of society, but the subjects of
the revolution must think and act today as they will after the
revolution.”1’ This, according to Alford, was the only means
of avoiding aesthetic resignation and breaking out of the vicious
circle. It was by no means the only way out, however; Marcuse
stated his own view clearly in his essay on “Protosocialism and
Late Capitalism.” The only acceptable means of altering the
status quo, he said, was through “Plato’s position (an educa
tional dictatorship of the most intelligent) and Rousseau’s
(people must be forced to be free),” and however scandalous
it might seem, one had to uphold the paradox that a socialist
stale needs “a recognized . . . elite.”n’
But how did Marcusian aesthetics strive to renew the revo
lutionary spirit? To answer this question, we must establish
Marcuse’s objectivity in relation to Marxist aesthetics by defin
ing and evaluating Marcusian aesthetics.
One of the errors of Marxist aesthetics, according to Marcuse,
was “the denigration of romanticism as simply reactionary.”17
And yet romanticism, adventurism, or imagination form the
basis of any revolution in Marcuse’s view. “If the revolution
does not contain an element of adventurism, it is worthless,”
he stated in a L'Express interview.18 What did he mean by this
romanticism, in this sense?
To begin with, even if the Romantic Movement per se was a
nineteenth-century phenomenon, the elements were present in
eighteenth-century culture. As Georges Gusdorf noted, “Not
one of the elements of what was called Romanticism in the
nineteenth century was absent from the arts and literature of
64 Herbert Marcuse's Utof/ia
the preceding century.”1'' In “L’Existence esthetique," the last
chapter of Xaissance de la conscience romantique an siecle des lumieres,
Gusdorf demonstrated that the contemporary definition of
aesthetic activity was fairly specific. He analyzed several essays
on the arts, beginning with Baumgarten, who first used the
word “aesthetic” in the manner specifically referred to by
Marcuse in Eros and Civilization. 20 Consequently, there was no
contradiction in Marcuse’s attempt to trace aesthetic romanti
cism back through Marx to Fourier and beyond. Fhe active
cultivation of imaginative commitment and an emphasis on the
creative will of the ego are rooted in a long tradition. In any
case, even Marx contained romantic elements, and these were
precisely what interested Marcuse.
The presence of these elements has not always been recog
nized. Michael Loewy, for example, in his 1976 sociological study
on revolutionary intellectuals, wrote that “Marx’s socialism has
nothing to do with anticapitalist romanticism, sociologically or
ideologically.”21 Fortunately, he later corrected this statement.
Admitting the justice of criticism leveled by the Americans Paul
Brcines22 and Jeffrey Herf,2Mhe even went so far as to devote
an entire book to the subject, Marxisme et romantisme revolution-
naire,21 which included a demonstration of the profound influ
ence of Thomas Carlyle2, and Honore de Balzac2*’ on Marx
and Engels. A year later, in a 1980 essay in Telos,27 Loewy again
emphasized the romantic dimension in the theory of Marcuse
and Benjamin, although he weakened his argument somewhat
by maintaining that there was a periodic waning of Marcuse’s
interest in aesthetic and romantic questions, and in the problem
of art and culture.
If we look at the major stages in Marcuse’s life outlined in
chapter 1, it is evident that aesthetic and romantic considera
tions remained constant throughout his work. When complet
ing his studies during the Weimar period, he produced “Der
deutsche Kiinstlerroman,” his 1922 dissertation on novels with
the artist as protagonist. The central theme of this dissertation
was "the contradiction between the world of Idea and empirical
reality, art, and bourgeois life—a contradiction painfully
perceived and expressed by the Romantics,” as Loewy pointed
out. Marcuse, he said, stressed “the burning aspiration of many
Romantic or neo-Romantic writers for a radical change of life,
bursting through the narrow limits of bourgeois philistine
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 05
materialism," and compared them with "contemporary utopian
socialists such as F o u rie r.L o e w y felt that Marcuse had
repeated some of his earlier ideas without alteration in Eros and
Civilization and One-Dimensional Man. Barry Katz explained that
the issue raised in this dissertation reflected the neo-Hegelian
principles of Georg Lukacs outlined in The Theory of the Novel
(1920). This work originally appeared in 1916, in a journal
devoted to aesthetics and art criticism. The journal’s director
was Max Dessoir, one of Marcuse’s teachers at the time. Conse
quently, Marcuse wrote very much in the style of a young
romantic whose theory and method were taking root in the
aesthetics of Hegel, “the most serious of all serious philoso-
i **29
pliers.
During the period between 1933 and 1942, Marcuse’s
aesthetic interests centered on the Frankfurt School’s analysis
of mass culture. As Martin jay noted/0 he made a considerable
contribution to this analysis. An example is his 1937 article,
“The Affirmative Character of Culture.” In the later phases of
his work, beginning with Eros and Civilization, Marcuse’s aesthet
ics and utopianism clearly assumed greater importance as his
criticism became more radical. Marcuse’s commentators gener
ally ignore this fact, often more or less intentionally, depending
on their view of Marxist orthodoxy. The more importance they
attach to the latter, the less they give to the romanticism and
libertarian idealism present in Marx himself.
Other scholars have readily admitted the importance of the
romantic dimension in Marcuse’s thought, either to criticize or
commend it. Peter Clecak, for example, in an excellent 1973
study on Marcuse and the paradoxes of American radicalism,
saw him as a romantic and revolutionary intellectual/1 although
this was apparently a reproach. In reviewing Clecak’s study
Richard Flacks concluded that the New Left need not shed its
romanticism, and that adequate practical strategies would
provide a balance.42 The title of his article, “The Importance
of the Romantic Myth for the Left,” left no doubt on this score.
At the beginning of this chapter, I stated that Alford was
wrong in believing that Marcuse could break out of the vicious
circle in which he had confined himself. To be more exact, I
consider Alford mistaken on the practical level, since Marcuse’s
article on Bahro did not offer an effective new strategy for
implementing the true revolution. On the theoretical level,
66 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
however, there is a logical way out of Marcuse’s dilemma, and
a very simple one at that. One need only demonstrate which
elements can occur both before and after the revolution.
Romanticism as revolutionary conservatism is one such element,
since it is possible to say of Marcuse, as Martin Buber said of
Gustave Landauer: “Ultimately what he has in mind is revo
lutionary conservatism: a revolutionary choice of the elements
of the social being that are worth preserving and that are valid
in a new construct."*3 Seen in this light, romanticism, far from
being a paradox or a mark of resignation, is one among a number
of factors of change. It must be understood that romanticism
conforms to the revolutionary spirit and is not to be rejected
where the interpretation of Marcuse is concerned.
Some writers have not understood this distinction. Eric
Volant, in a thesis submitted to the University of Montreal, was
a case in point.*’1 After reminding his readers that “during
debates at the Berlin Free University, Marcuse described himself
as ‘an incurable and sentimental romantic,’ ” he went on to say
that Marcuse did not belong to the romantic tradition because
his argument was based on the future. *3 Volant also attempted
to contradict John Ra/.er's analogy between Marcuse and the
European romantic tradition, which appeared in “A Conver
sation with Herbert Marcuse” in Psychology Today.36 Brigitte
Croisier, when only a student in 1969, was aware of Marcuse’s
romanticism.37 Yet commentators nevertheless persist in turn
ing a blind eye to it. Michel de Certeau, commissioned by the
Encyclopaedia Universalis to prepare an entry on Marcuse for
Umversalia 1980** had reservations similar to those of Volant.
While Marcuse’s philosophy, said de Certeau, could be construed
as “revolutionary romanticism,” it probably originated in the
Jewish tradition to which he belonged.’9 Marcuse had never
theless denied this explicitly. In a conversation with Richard
Kearney, he stated that the qualitative change he proposed was
certainly aesthetic, but had nothing whatever to do with the
messianic optimism of Judaism.’0
What, then, is the meaning of the revolutionary romanticism
to which Marcuse laid claim? Among the definitions of roman
ticism that come closest to the truth, stated H. Peyre in Ency
clopaedia Universalis, “are those that emphasize its inherent spirit
of revolt: not only the metaphysical revolt already evident in
certain German writers and in Rousseau when he cried out
Marcuse's Roman lie Aesthetics (>7
against the sullocating limitations of the universe; hut also social
and political revolt."11 The term romanticism in this context
does not mean a particular literary genre, but a social and polit
ical vision ol the world. The romantic figure is one who tries
to change the world, said Hegel.,J According to Jean-Michel
Palmier, “Generally speaking, any action that violently contests
the existing order in the name ol ethical, aesthetic, or instinctual
demands is an act of ‘revolutionary romanticism.’ Roman
ticism as a negation of established order is therefore to be found
at the basis of all art. It is this thesis that Marcuse developed
in One-Dimensional Man,11 as Michel Haar noted.1’ But to what
extent can art be revolutionary? Marcuse replied that it must
transcend, without eliminating, all particular class content.10
We are therefore dealing with two levels of consideration: the
proletarian and the revolutionary. The question is, what are
the respective preconditions of proletarian and revolutionary
art from the Marxist standpoint?
In the eighth and final section of Marcuse’s study on “Art
and Revolution,” Marcuse asked point blank if proletarian art
were possible. What is “the meaning and the very possibility of
a ‘proletarian literature’ (or working class literature)”?1' Rich
ard Kearney asked almost the same question in bis interview,
and Marcuse replied in more or less the following terms. Let
us presuppose the existence of a proletarian culture; one must
also demonstrate that the proletariat as described by Marx
himself does in fact exist, since today's working class is not always
and everywhere interested in socialism. Even supposing that a
proletarian socialism actually exists, it still must be shown that
this can be the definite negation of capitalism. Marcuse
clearly did not think so. Consequently, efforts to demonstrate
that tlie working class would care about an authentic, radical,
socialist art would only increase the already prevalent atmos
phere of alienation.
Proletarian art is therefore impossible for several reasons,
the first and foremost of which stems from the universal nature
of art, as Marcuse explained in answer to another ol Richard
Kearney’s questions.Il> Art can transcend any particular class
interest without eliminating it. Art is always concerned with
history—the history ol all classes. It is this all-embracing quality
that accounts for the objectivity and universality of art, which
Marx described as the quality of “prehistory," and Hegel as the
68 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
“continuity of substance —the truth that links the modern novel
with the medieval epic, the reality of human existence with its
potentiality, and conflict with reconciliation, whether between
man and man or man and nature. A work of art clearly has a
particular class content in that it reflects a vision of a particular
world, whether feudal, bourgeois, or proletarian. In terms of
the human dream, however, it is transcendent. Genuine art
does much more than mirror one class, and is not limited to
the spontaneous expression of the f rustrations or desires of a
single group. The immediate sensuous impact of art, which
popular culture does not always apprehend and which only the
initiated can appreciate, presupposes the formal organization
of experience on universal principles, and it is these principles
alone that give a work any meaning that is not purely private.
It is interesting to note that the most politically radical people
often have apolitical tastes—yet further proof of the univer
sality of art.
The notion of proletarian art is also doomed to failure,
according to Marcuse, because it presupposes the obsolescence
of earlier forms of art, classical as well as romantic. Unlike
Herbert Read, he did not see classicism and romanticism as
opposites. For Read, “There is a principle of life, of creation,
of liberation, and that is the romantic spirit. There is a principle
of order, of control and of repression, and that is the classical
spirit.’”0 Neither did Marcuse confuse classicism with capital
ism/ He considered the disruptive characters of bourgeois
literature, such as the prostitute, the great criminal, the rebel
poet, the fool, and others, as representing a negative force
confronting the Establishment.52 Although this literature is not
proletarian, it retains its revolutionary dimension, and this was
what counted for Marcuse.
Present-day artistic realism, however, appears to have lost its
revolutionary dimension. This is surely true of current protag
onists, who often appear in the guise of beatnik, neurotic house
wife, star, business tycoon, and the like. “They are no longer
images of another way of life but rather freaks or types of the
same life, serving as an affirmation rather than negation of the
established order,” wrote Marcuse.53 In this respect the list is
long: in the United States the songs of the black community
have been swallowed up in white rock music; the indiscriminate
use of scatological terms does more harm than good to sexual
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 69
liberation; ‘‘living theater” or “anti-art," which has taken root
in the spontaneous feelings of the oppressed proletariat, is
doomed to failure, and so on ad infinitum.
Basically, Marcuse believed that proletarian art, if' it exists,
has lost its revolutionary potential because the majority of the
working class has developed an antirevolutionary conscious
n e ss/1 This being the case, can there still be a relationship
between art and revolution?
Why should future revolutions be concerned with aesthetics
if they wish to succeed? Marcuse considered it evident that the
advanced industrial nations have long since reached the degree
of productivity and wealth that Marx counted on as a base for
building a socialist society. It therefore follows that quantitative
growth in production no longer provides a sufficient goal, and
that society as a whole must change qualitatively. Merely alter
ing working conditions is not enough. “The qualitative change
necessary to build a truly socialist society, something we haven’t
yet seen, depends on other values not so much economic (quan
titative) as aesthetic (qualitative) in character."” In other words,
it is not enough merely to satisfy needs; the needs themselves
must be changed. This is how the new society can become a
work of art.
But can one really consider art as an agent of revolution?
Marcuse faced a genuine dilemma in this regard. Art is both
affirmative and negative. Its essentially negative, critical nature
is seen in the refusal of art to obey the rules of established reality
in terms of language, order, conventions, and images. Art of fers
asylum to disreputable humanity, providing an alternative to
the reality asserted by the Establishment. It can be used to
denounce not only the affirmed reality, but those responsible
for the affirmation. Paradoxically, however, art is also affirm
ative by nature. Literature, for example, is af firmative in that
it gives pleasure to the reader—otherwise there would be no
reader. The element of entertainment is part and parcel of even
the most radical art. Like Bertolt Brecht, Marcuse made the
point that even when describing the most brutal things in the
world, one must still entertain.50 Actually, a work of art can
acquire an affirmative content through its social and political
character, whereas it remains negative by virtue of its form
(novel, play, or poem), which is forever demonstrating its
removal from reality. Art always transforms reality. "No matter
70 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
how realistic, naturalistic, it remains the other of reality and
nature.”37
If art can liberate us from the domination of reality—that is
to say, if it can be revolutionary—then why did Marx not say
so? The answer is simply this: Marx did not emphasize the role
of art in the transition to a new society because he lived over
a hundred years ago, and could not see for himself that it is
indeed possible to resolve material problems through genuine
socialist relations and institutions. He did not realize that a purely
economic solution would not suffice, nor did he perceive that
a twentieth-century revolution would require a different type
of human being, striving for totally new personal and sexual
relations, new morality, new sensitivity, and total reconstruction
of the environment. All these values, in the name of which the
revolution must be carried out, are in fact aesthetic values in
the large sense used in Eros and Civilization, and in the tradition
of Kant and Schiller. That is why art is an important factor in
change.
It now becomes clear that the subtitle of Marcuse’s last work,
Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics, was far from indicating a
late and unexpected development of his thought—or resig
nation, as has been suggested. On the contrary, adhering to his
own logic until the end, he continued his search for all possible
means of revolution. He refused to countenance the form of
Marxist orthodoxy that reduces all cultural phenomena to an
ideological reflection of class interests, or that expects art to
reflect the production relations of a given society and assumes
that art and social classes are necessarily linked. Seen from the
latter perspective, art and society are closely related; political
and aesthetic values coincide so that only the highest social class
is capable of true artistic expression, while the lowest can only
produce decadent ai l. Artistic realism is the only form of art
that mirrors society, according to this argument. Such a concep
tion of art makes no allowance for variety of subject matter,
personal feelings, or imagination, and equates individual
consciousness to class consciousness. Marcuse, on the other hand,
submitted the following thesis: "The radical qualities of art, that
is to say, its indictment of the established reality and its invo
cation of the beautiful image (schbner Schein) of liberation are
grounded precisely in the dimensions where art transcends its
social determination and emancipates itself from the given
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 71
universe of' discourse and behavior while preserving its over
whelming presence.”:>H He opposed cultural determinism and
made out a case for autonomy in art, giving it a more important
role and an enhanced political function. Instead of limiting
himself to describing art in present-day society, he attempted
to define its potential in the society of the future. For Marcuse,
the world of art embodied “the promise of liberation.”VI
One may ask, however, whether Marcuse’s critique is as rele
vant as he made it out to be, and whether it did not represent
an outmoded school of thought. He himself admitted that he
was dealing with a theory current between 1920 and 1935,60
meaning the work of Walter Benjamin, Ernst Bloch, Bertolt
Brecht, Georg Lukacs, and several others. It was with Lukacs
that he differed especially, however. Unlike the latter, Marcuse
argued that literature cannot realistically reflect objective social
reality: “But precisely this requirement offends the very nature
of art. The basic structure and dynamic of society can never
find sensuous, aesthetic expression: they are, in Marxian theory,
the essence behind the appearance, which can only be attained
through scientific analysis, and formulated only in the terms
of such an analysis.”61 Nevertheless, by taking up an antirealist
position, Marcuse would seem to be abandoning the only
perspective Marxism had to offer at the time. Gerald Graff
remarked on this, pointing out that one cannot dismiss such
American theorists as Edmund Wilson, Richard Chase, Irving
Howe, Harold Rosenberg, Kenneth Burke, Philip Rahv, Alfred
Kazin, Isaac Rosenfield, and Lionel Trilling.62 Annette Rubin
stein had much to say in the same vein, noting that Marcuse
completely ignored current writing on Marxist aesthetics by
Robert Weimann in the German Democratic Republic, Arnold
Kettle in England, Zdanek Strbrny in Gzechoslovakia, and others
in such countries as Poland and Hungary.6’ In short, contrary
to the thinking of early twentieth-century Marxist aestheticians,
and without reference to those of the present day, Marcuse
declared it an error to think that only proletarian literature can
develop a revolutionary consciousness. The objectives and
conditions of a revolution against monopolistic world capitalism
cannot be expressed in terms of a proletarian revolution. “It is
by means of the aesthetic imagination that one can transcend
one’s alienated world, in order to ‘experiment with and
72 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
‘remember’ alternative forms of life.”'*1What, then, is the func
tion of aesthetic philosophy?
Invited to chair a meeting of the American Philosophical
Association,0’ Marcuse delivered a paper on Marx’s eleventh
thesis on Feuerbach: “Philosophers have only interpreted the
world in various ways; the point is to change it.” Marcuse
contended: “ This never meant that now it is no longer necessary
to interpret the world—we can just go about changing it.” What
it really meant was, “The world must be interpreted again in
order to be changed.”00 During an interview with Pierre Vians-
son-Ponte for the newspaper Le Monde, he commented on the
eleventh thesis in slightly different terms: “It is the intellectual’s
job to promote radical education.”07 In other words, one has a
moral duty to promote any theory that can be used for social
subversion. Marcuse felt this duty to be all the more imperative
because philosophical theory and all forms of critical thought
are today facing a greater task than ever, since historical condi
tions lend to silence the spirit of criticism. Philosophy underlies
the will to transform the world and make it free and rational,
Marcuse pointed out. Its task cannot end until its goal is reached.
Philosophy has not achieved its goal, however, since theory and
practice do not yet coincide. Even though the philosopher may
realize that unity of theory and practice is a purely utopian
goal, he must never stop working for it until this end is attained.08
Philosophers, said Marcuse, “should be worthy” of the compli
ment implied by Marx’s statement that philosophy is “the head
of the emancipation of man.”0'' It should perhaps be noted that
Marcuse conveniently omitted the rest of the quotation—“It’s
heart is the proletariat—thereby downplaying the role of the
proletariat in realizing the goals of philosophy, lie that as it
may, Marcuse’s reexamination of Marxism didn’t stop there.
He looked at another well-known thesis, to which he gave a new
direction. Marx stated, “It is not the consciousness of men that
determines their being, but, on the contrary, their social being
that determines their consciousness.’” 1Elsewhere he expressed
it as, “It is not consciousness that determines life, but life that
determines consciousness."72 In fact, wrote Marcuse, “With the
possibility of the revolution being a ‘qualitative leap' comes the
appropriate dialectic for historical materialism—the idealistic
core that was always there. The determination of consciousness
through social assistance undergoes a change. Based on an
Marcuse’s Romantic Aesthetics 73
economy aimed at eliminating poverty and exploitation, it is the
liberated consciousness that would determine the social being."1*
Marcuse was therefore proposing a philosophy that was both
materialistic and idealistic: “materialistic to the extent to which
it preserves in its concepts the full concreteness, the dead and
living matter of the social reality; . . . idealistic in as much as it
analyzes this reality in the light of its ‘idea,’ that is, its real possi
bilities.”71 However, the element o f ‘idealism’ present in histor
ical dialectic assumed such dimensions that, when discussing
the topic in Reason and Revolution, he concluded, “Theory will
preserve the truth even if revolutionary practice deviates from
its proper path. Practice follows the truth, not vice versa.”' 5
Marcuse never abandoned "this faith in the primacy of correct
theory,” stated Martin Jay.76 He was always concerned about
preserving the primacy of reason, although he must surely have
been aware of another famous Marxist thesis: "Not criticism
but revolution is the driving force of history, also of religion,
of philosophy and all other kinds of theory."77 In an affluent
society such as ours, however, revolution is impossible.'8 It is
only possible when based on poverty. Therefore reason has
only one function left, that of recalling both the poverty and
the highest aspirations of the past, because “the authentic utopia
is grounded in reco llectio n .W h ere are we to look for such
aspirations? “In philosophy,” said Marcuse, for this is where
“traditional theory developed concepts oriented to the poten
tialities of man lying beyond his factual status.”80 One must be
careful, however, not to exaggerate the importance of concep
tual thought. Marcuse considered it useful only in that philos
ophy is the basis of liberation. Even though philosophy may
develop into critical theory, "the abyss between rational and
present reality cannot be bridged by conceptual thought.”81
What philosophy did Marcuse use in his process of reinter
pretation? In his presidential address to the American Philo
sophical Association, he provided a clear answer in the form
of a four-point program.8* He recommended that several areas
of the history of philosophy be reinterpreted, beginning with
Plato’s demonstration of the best form of government, all too
often subjected to ridicule. In addition, he asked philosophers
to develop political linguistics, because language has become
“an instrument of control and manipulation.” He also suggested
they investigate physiological and psychological epistemology
71 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
through transcendental “rather than sociological analysis. Such
analysis would differ from Kant" in that "forms of intuition”
and "categories of understanding" would be treated as histor
ical rather than pure. “These would be a priori because they
would belong to the ‘conditions of possible experience,’ but they
would be a historical a priori in the sense that their universality
and necessity are defined (limited) by a specific, experienced
historical universe." Marcuse also called for "the renewal of
philosophical aesthetics.” Note that he spoke of philosophic
aesthetics and not aesthetic philosophy. Philosophy is limited to
revealing the goals, values, and moral ideals that we should
strive for, as ethics and religion have always done in the past.
However, since all three disciplines are incapable of translating
the said goals, values, and moral ideals into reality, this must
be accomplished by other means. “Only art achieves it—in the
medium of beauty.”83 Marcuse therefore gave aesthetics in
general, and art in particular, a special status that philosophy
does not possess, but which it has a duty to promote. Philosophy
is concerned with the purposes and values governing human
activity, or with what Marcuse understood by "the norms and
aspirations which motivate the behavior of social groups in the
process of satisfying their needs, material as well as cultural.”8'
Through a process of politicization and a fresh analysis of human
potential, philosophy can attempt to show how these eschatal-
ogical aims can be transformed into real, aesthetic needs. As
long as these aims and values do not become real needs,
predicted Marcuse, the qualitative change between past and
future society will not take place.85 “By virtue of its historical
position Marxian theory is in its very substance philosophy."80
Marxian philosophy and aesthetics therefore share the common
task of promoting the realization of beauty. "An animal,” wrote
Marx, “forms objects only in accordance with the standard and
the need of the species to which it belongs, whilst man knows
how to produce in accordance with the standard of every species,
and knows how to apply everywhere the inherent standard to
the object. Man therefore also forms objects in accordance with
the laws of beauty.”*' Of what does this process of aesthelici-
zation consist? It must first be understood that Marcuse
perceived and expressed modernity in terms of crisis.** Before
discussing the social f unction of art and its ontological and
Marcuse’s Romantic Aesthetics 75
historical position, 1 would therefore like to look at the problem
of the "crisis of art."8'*
Philosophy is not yet obsolete, contended Marcuse. It has a
task to perform: the promotion of aesthetics. The specific, basic
aim of aesthetics is to subvert reality. How can art do this if it
is constantly threatened by developing cultural conditions? In
analyzing social reality, are we forced to consider “the end of
art”? Can art possibly retain its independence? Jurgen Haber
mas asked Marcuse about this dilemma.90 He pointed out that
in “The Affirmative Character of Culture” written in 1937,
Marcuse had asserted, “Beauty will find a new embodiment
when it no longer is represented as real illusion but, instead,
expresses reality and joy in reality. A foretaste of such poten
tialities can be had in experiencing the unassuming display of
Greek statues or the music of Mozart or late Beethoven. Perhaps,
however, beauty and its enjoyment will not even devolve upon
art. Perhaps art as such will have no objects. For the common
man it has been confined to museums for at least a century.”'*1
Now, said Habermas, Marcuse was defending another position,
as in this statement from "Art and Revolution" in 1972: “The
‘end of art’ is conceivable only if men are no longer capable of
distinguishing between true and false, good and evil, beautiful
and ugly, present and future. I bis would be the state of perfect
barbarism at the height of civilization—and such a state is indeed
a historical possibility.”'*2 Habermas asked Marcuse what had
led him to revise his initial theory. Marcuse replied that he still
saw art as communication, but was now emphasizing its inher
ently critical nature for the very reason that this was its most
threatened function. In fact, however, he approached the ques
tion from three different angles.
As Andrew Arato noted, Marcuse appeared to have changed
his approach in response to a critique by Adorno.'** In the 1937
essay on "'File Affirmative Character of Culture," Marcuse
followed the Marxist tradition, equaling art too closely with
ideology. In 1909, he interpreted the rebellion of the young
intelligentsia as the dialectical cultural leap that makes art part
of life.'*1 With "Ai l and Revolution" in 1972, however, art was
definitively geared to permanent aesthetic subversion: “The
abolition of the aesthetic form, the notion that art could become
a component of revolutionary (and prerevolutionary) praxis,
until under fully developed socialism, it would be adequately
70 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
translated into reality (or absorbed by ‘science’)—ibis notion is
false and oppressive: it would mean the end of art.”',‘' Adorno’s
influence could not explain everything, however. There were
more deep-seated reasons for Marcuse’s change in outlook.
Where did Marcuse get his interest in art and aesthetics? In
an interview with Bryan Magee he explained that he and the
members of the Frankf urt School shared a critical perspective
based on their justifiable and objective disillusionment with the
progress of social change. Contrary to expectations, the incre
dible social wealth accumulated by the achievements of Western
civilization in general, and capitalism in particular, have
progressively hindered rather than helped the building of a
more decent, humane society.1"’ The language of art, however,
provides a means of looking at reality from two vantage points.
It stands outside established reality and the reality of everyday
life; and it holds out the promise of a liberated world. The break
with reality allows art to perform a critical function. It can be
subversive as long as it maintains this break. If not, then we
are facing the end of art. F.ven so, nothing can destroy the
promise of happiness inherent in art. Marcuse recounted his
personal reaction to these two dimensions of aesthetic expe
rience in his lecture on “Art in the One-Dimensional Society.'"!W
The more he felt that traditional forms of artistic expression
had lost their critical powers, the more despondent he became,
foreseeing the end of art. Conversely, however, as more and
more new forms of artistic expression appeared, he became
increasingly hopeful. Then one day, while taking part in an
anti-Vietnam demonstration where young people were singing
the songs of Bob Dylan, he realized that this was the only revo
lutionary language left today.1WIf Marcuse learned anything
from this experience, it was this: although one art form can
overtake another that has lost its critical edge, the aesthetic form
endures. A careful reading of various aesthetic analyses
throughout Marcuse’s career makes it clear how intertwined
were the two strands of theory concerning the end and the
autonomy of art. These analyses were constructed on a fairly
basic system, and it is unnecessary to review them all in detail.
I would, however, like to list their salient points.
Between 1934 and 1937, the Frankfurt School was interested
in mass culture, as Martin Jay showed.111' Marcuse’s contribution
was a condemnation of the “affirmative culture”1"” of content-
Marcuse’s Romantic Aesthetics 77
porary Germany.101 In 1958, lie turned his attention to Soviet
culture.10- Between 1964 and 1967 he looked at the situation
in the United States, his adopted country,103 and in 1969 he
evaluated the aesthetic/political aspect of the Paris student revolt
of May 1968.101 In 1972, he produced a critical study of the
New Left and of his own aesthetics, making a clear distinction
between “material culture" and “intellectual culture"10’ in order
to analyze the “culture industry.”100 In 1977 he published the
original German text of The Aesthetic Dimension, which appeared
in English the following year. This was a final and highly critical
review of Marxist aesthetics, as a preliminary to proposing a
revised form—Marcusian aesthetics. At this juncture it is worth
noting that the major French collection of his essays bears the
title Culture et societe, which expresses the underlying thrust of
Marcuse’s work better than the runaway bestsellers Eros and
Civilization, One-Dimensional Man, or even Repressive Tolerance.
Let us look at one or two examples. Each time Marcuse
considered the problem of art, culture, or aesthetics, he asked
questions such as: What is their role under present historical
conditions? Have they preserved their essential nature? Have
they been assimilated by the socio-historic context? Upon care
ful consideration, it seems to me that these questions fall into
three main categories: What is the socio-historical context with
which we are dealing? Can art (or culture, or aesthetics) contest
this socio-historical context, and if so, what is stopping it? Has
art any real chance of contesting the socio-historical context?
In Germany, as Marcuse demonstrated in an article written
in 1934,107 Fascism had attempted to mobilize all levels of soci
ety in order to consolidate its political interests. He therefore
spoke out against the decline of bourgeois culture in the face
of National Socialism, asserting that “the greatest intellectual
heritage of German history” must be preserved by being
absorbed “in scientific social theory and the critique of political
economy,” although he felt that the prospect was “clouded with
uncertainty.”108
The Soviet Union was distinctive, as Marcuse pointed out in
Soviet Marxism, in that the state controlled economic develop
ment, contrary to capitalist countries where the economy
controlled the state.100 By nationalizing socio-economic inter
ests, the Soviet state stifled effective opposition, so that "the
ideological sphere which is remotest from the reality (art,
78 Herbert Marcuse’s Utopia
philosophy), precisely because of its remoteness, becomes the
last refuge for the opposition to this order.”11" Nevertheless,
art retains its transcendent, “critical cognitive function: to sustain
the image of freedom against a denying reality.”111
O n its d e e p e s t le v e l, art is a p r o te s t a g a in st th a t w h ic h is.
B y th at v e r y to k e n , art is a “p o litica l" m a tte r . . . . B u t art
as a p o litic a l fo r c e is art o n ly in s o fa r as it p r e s e r v e s th e
im a g e s of lib e r a tio n ; in a s o c ie ty w h ic h is in its to ta lity th e
n e g a tio n o f th e s e im a g e s , art c a n p r e s e r v e th e m o n ly by
total refusal.11'
What real chance has art to hold its own in the Soviet context?
The avowed aim of Soviet aesthetics is to reflect reality in the
form of artistic images. “In other words,” said Marcuse, “once
the reality itself embodies the ideal,. . . art must necessarily
reflect the reality.”11’ Aesthetic realism is the only form of art
permitted in the Soviet Union. Even though Marcuse felt that
art should indeed try to reflect the ideal, he criticized Soviet
aesthetics on three counts. In the first place, the reality does
not yet embody the ideal “in its pure form."1M Furthermore,
“In its societal function, art shares the growing impotence of
individual autonomy and cognition.”11' Finally, "The works of
the great ‘bourgeois’ antirealists and ‘formalists’ are far deeper
committed to the idea of freedom than is socialist and Soviet
realism.”1
In the United States Marcuse took a similar approach. In
One-Dimensional Man, he contended that American capitalism
has produced a closed society because the forces of opposition
predating capitalism have been integrated. Assimilation is
complete: the system “swallows up or repulses all alternatives;”
negation and criticism are reduced to cohesion and affirma
tion.11' “'fhe world of facts is, so to speak, one-dimensional.”,,H
Marcuse continued to develop this idea, first put forward in
1936, including it in his course at the Ecole pratique ties halites
etudes in 1958-59.11!*He worked on it again in articles published
in 1961 and 1962, later to become passages in One-Dimensional
Man, published in 1964.120 Generally, his writing on one-
dimensionality leads one to believe that his theory went from
being a mere stalking horse to an all-pervading idea: the growth
of rationality engenders a corresponding growth in irration
ality. To combat the latter, however, Marcuse still posited the
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 79
“total refusal” of 1958,121 the aesthetic “Great Refusal.”122
Aesthetic values are the definite negation of dominant values,
he asserted.123 But the assimilative force of capitalist society is
so great that even aesthetic imagination merges with reality.121
I his is “the end of art”—a theme taken from Hegel by all the
exponents of critical theory.125
Hegel is the key to understanding “the end of art." He
considered all theoretical and practical endeavour to be based
on introspective thought. Liberated subjective consciousness thus
adopts a stance opposed to socio-historical reality, creating a
gap that art can no longer bridge, even by reconciling extremes.
Marcuse, on the contrary, held that it was important to base
oneself on an ethical/aesthetic ideal, an “illusory reality that
neither philosophy nor religion can attain. Only art achieves
it—in the medium of beauty."12'’ He was therefore not prepared
to accept the theory of "the end of art” as being the last word,
and instead looked to the “autonomy of art.” It was Habermas
who touched on the real issue, however, when he asked whether
Marcuse had generally revised his thinking on the “end of art”
to the point of opting for the “autonomy of art.” What distin
guishes these two viewpoints is how each relates to revolution.
When art is assimilated by the Establishment, it contributes to
its own end. When, on the contrary, it recognizes its revolu
tionary potential and revives “the categorical imperative: ‘tilings
must change,’ ”12~ then art, by its very function, acquires and
maintains autonomy. What, therefore, is the function of art in
Marcuse’s aesthetics?
Utopia and art have similar functions in Marcuse’s critical
theory. These can be examined in a number of ways. We can
study Marcuse’s ethical perspective for consistency of approach.
We can look at the functions of critical theory, as resumed by
Vincent Geoghegan in his 1981 work, Reason and liras, 7 he Social
Theory of Herbert Marcuse, 128 We can also examine the functions
of utopia, as outlined by Ernst Bloch, the utopian philosopher
par excellence,' ”' and by Paul Ricoeur, a much less enthusiastic
commentator of concrete utopia.130 In addition, there are the
contemporary functions of Marxist utopia described by Pavel
Kovaly,131 and the function of art in Marcuse and Hegel, as
given in George Friedman’s recent work, 7he Political Philosophy
of the Frankfurt School.
80 Herbert Marcuse’s Utopia
Tin.* consistency of Marcuse’s aesthetic perspective through
out iiis work lias been the subject of comment more than once.
Francois Chirpaz, for example, came to the following conclu
sion in 1069: “Marcuse’s strong point is that he invites us to
think in terms of a radical transformation of our society and
culture; hut he is nevertheless unable to provide the theoretical
tools for planning and realizing such a transformation. In fact,
it is u'it/iiu the scope of aesthetic utopia to expect such a transfor
mation, considering the advances that have been made in auto
mation, not to mention the emergence of new n e e d s . T h e r e
is no doubt that Marcuse wanted to make use of an aesthetic
utopia. Why then reproach him for having done so? Whatever
else it may he, it is not inconsistent.
In a more recent study in 1977, Parviz Piran contended that
Marcuse’s approach dif fered from that of critical theory.1Vl Piran
claimed that the revolutionary change sought by Marcuse
contradicted the change implied by his aesthetic perspective.
Furthermore, on the basis of One-Dimensional Man, one might
agree with Michel I laar’s statement that, “If it is true that tech
nology represents violence and repression, then it is utopian to
base the advent of a world without violence and repression on
technology."1’ ’ But are these actually contradictions in Marcuse’s
theory, or real contradictions that Marcuse was trying to eval
uate from a Marxist perspective?
For the sake of argument, let us use Roger (laraudy’s defi
nition of the Marxist perspective: File vantage point from which
we can see all the avenues of Marx’s thought is his awareness
of man’s basic situation in capitalist society. Marx enunciated
the inherent contradiction of this situation, which is that the
birth and growth of capitalism have created conditions for both
the unlimited development and oppression of all men.1"’
If, therefore, the Marxist perspective consists in demonstrat
ing society’s contradictions, and if this is what Marcuse did on
the aesthetic level, then one cannot argue that his thought is
confined to the contradictions of the capitalist world. For exam
ple, although Marcuse advocated a radical aesthetic education,
he considered it obvious that the present concept of education,
designed to promote a better future society, is a contradiction.
However, it is a contradiction that must be resolved if progress
is to be made.1 I his last assertion was not an admission of
weakness on his part, but rather the expression of a desire to
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 81
benefit humanity. Marcuse tended to express society’s contra
dictions in pairs, juxtaposing them to a third, utopian element
of his argument, located outside of present time and space so
as to avoid setting arbitrary limits to the historical process.
The consistency of Marcuse’s thought was evident, for exam
ple, in the following pairs of opposites: total refusal versus one-
dimensionality; the autonomy of art versus the possibility of
the end of art; and non-repressive sublimation versus repres
sive desublimation. Critical theory was the only intellectual
bridge he offered to span the gap between one historical moment
and another. What, then, are the functions of critical theory?
Vincent Geoghegan considered the functions of critical theory
to be threefold: it sets forth the present historical situation; it
reveals the inherent possibilities of this situation; and it antici
pates the future by emphasizing the role of imagination. These
functions are, in fact, surprisingly like those of utopia itself.138
Ernst Bloch also summarized the functions of utopia accord
ing to three principals, as listed by Pierre Furter and Laennac
Hurbon. Utopia is the protest against the status quo; the antic
ipation of the possibilities of radical change; and the insistence
on realizing everything immediately, which constitutes a refusal
of defeatism.1™
Ernst Bloch was not the only utopian philosopher to outline
these functions, however. Paul Ricoeur, although not a partic
ular supporter of utopia, proposed using it as a means of refut
ing the threat of meaningless existence.110 “The basic function
of utopia is to maintain a project for humanity in the face of
meaninglessness,” he wrote.111 In another article, he enlarged
upon this idea: "I believe . . . there is an historic function of
utopia in the social order. Only utopia can give to economic,
social and political action a human intention and, in my sense,
a double intention: on the one hand the will of humanity as a
totality; on the other hand, the will of the person as a singu
larity.”112
In general, Ricoeur considered it the task ol the educator to
be utopian.111 On the strictly political level, he explained, the
intellectual is responsible for offering a social project geared
to both general and individual human needs, and capable of
maintaining a healthy balance between the ethics of conscience
and the ethics of responsibility.111
82 Herbert Marcuse’s Utopia
Mow does this view of utopian functions compare with the
Marxist approach? Let us look at Paul Kovaly’s critique of the
contemporary functions of Marxist utopia.11’ He based it on a
statement by Adam Schaff, head of the Institute of Philosophy
and Sociology at the University of Warsaw, and one of the most
influential Polish socialist writers. Schaff said, “Reading the
classic Marxist texts on man under communism one sometimes
gets the feeling that they are utopian. No doubt they contain
a residue of utopia.”146 Kovaly felt that it was not enough,
however, simply to admit that Marxism contained utopian
elements. One must also understand how utopia functions in
social and political life, and ask whether it affects society as a
whole.
The ultimate goal assigned by Marx and Engels to future
society may be grand, noble, and just. However, this ideal goal
has become the unique criterion by which Marxists judge and
evaluate Ikx Ii individual actions and social movements. All means
and methods are considered as serving this goal. At this junc
ture, utopia becomes dystopia. “I think that Marxism can be a
very good tool of analysis—but a dangerous tool when it is taken
as a theory of totality,” stated Ricoeur.117 The social phenom
enon, whether viewed as civilization or culture, is better under
stood if a distinction is made among levels of reality, instead
of systematizing every aspect of existence. It is not as though
we had no format for discussing historical totality. On the
contrary, our historical experience seems to affect everything
in our lives. But every imaginable totality is always premature
or else merely a limitation of the historical process.
The Marxist utopia may suffer from a monolithic structure
that makes it difficult to develop in more than one direction,
but this does not lessen the importance of its utopian function.
In a passage on the constituent function of utopia, Ricoeur
explained that, in social theory, the fiction of another society
allows us to distance ourselves from reality and discover how
strange it seems from another perspective. Through utopia, he
said, man distances himself from his symbolical system, thereby
putting all his institutions into question; in oilier words, he
rethinks his status as a political animal.MM
Unlike Ricoeur, Marcuse saw aesthetic utopia as playing a
far more important role. The functions of critical theory and
Marcuse's Romantic Aesthetics 83
art arc similar, he maintained. In fact, lie used this premise to
define a work of art in the last section of One-Dimensional Man:
L ik e t e c h n o lo g y , a rt c r e a t e s a n o t h e r u n iv e r s e o f t h o u g h t
a n d p r a c tic e a g a in s t a n d w ith in th e e x is t in g o n e . B u t in
c o n tr a s t to th e te c h n ic a l u n iv e r s e , th e a r tistic u n iv e r s e is
o n e o f illu s io n , s e m b la n c e , Schein. H o w e v e r , th is s e m b la n c e
is r e s e m b la n c e to a r e a lity w h ic h e x is ts as th e th r e a t a n d
p r o m is e o f th e e s ta b lis h e d o n e . In v a r io u s fo r m s o f m ask
a n d s ile n c e , t h e a r tis tic u n iv e r s e is o r g a n iz e d by th e im a g e s
o f a lif e w ith o u t f e a r . . . . T h e m o r e b la ta n tly ir r a tio n a l th e
s o c ie t y b e c o m e s , t h e g r e a t e r th e r a tio n a lity o f th e a rtistic
* I IM
u n iv e r s e .
Marcuse’s
Ideological Polidcs
Inevitably, when we think of Mart use the phrase “political liber
ation" conies to mind. Yet there seems to be widespread confu
sion as to what this phrase means, and more particularly, what
Marcuse meant by it.
Martin jay, in his article on Marcuse and "The Metapolitics
of Utopianism," ended with the following words: "The political
imperative that follows from all of this is the cul-de-sac of apoc
alyptic metapolitics, which is really no politics at all."1 Jay’s
conclusion was correct, in mv view. He had reached it after
4
a popular song:
I saw a n d p a r tic ip a te d in th e ir d e m o n s t r a t io n s a g a in s t th e
w a r in V ie t n a m , w h e n 1 h e a r d th e m s in g in g th e s o n g s o f
B o b D y la n , I s o m e h o w fe lt, a n d it is v e r y h a r d to d e f in e ,
th a t this is really the only revolutionary language lejt today."
a movement:
Ideological differences a n d d iv is o n s b e c o m e u tte r ly ir r e le v a n t
a n d r id ic u lo u s w h e n s u c h a m a ss b a s e h a s y e t to b e
cre a ted .
Marcuse's Ideological Politics 99
a distinctive aphorism:
T h e c la ss ic a l a lt e r n a t iv e " so c ia lism o r b a rb a rism " is m o r e
u r g e n t t o d a y th a n e v e r b e f o r e .57
Marcuse’s
Revolutionary Ethics
Like Rousseau, Marcuse believed in the value of negative
philosophy. One must know that-which-is-nol in order to judge
properly thal-which-is.' The comparison of "that-which-is" to
“that-which-is-not” is the basic requirement of a system of ethics
that is increasingly critical.2 Marcuse demonstrated in his 1938
critique “On Hedonism” that from the ancient world through
the Christian Middle Ages to the bourgeois period, “The moral
interpretation of happiness, its subjection to a universal law of
reason, tolerated both the essential isolation of the autonomous
person and his actual limitation."' However, he himself used
morality to condemn present society because, he said, "morality
has long ceased to be mere ideology,”' and "the humanitarian
and moral arguments are not merely deceitful ideology. Rather,
they can and must become central social forces.’” In Marcuse’s
view, historical conditions changed sufficiently between 1938
and 19G7 to justify both the earlier condemnation of traditional
morality, and the later recourse to “a certain moral tradition,"
as in his 1958 comparison of Soviet and Western ethics in Soviet
Marxism.° On one hand there is the tradition of Western society—
a tradition that, according to Marcuse, presupposes the possi
bility of fulfilling the nature of reasonable man within existing
institutions. On the other is the heretical tradition to which
Soviet and orthodox Marxist ethics belong with respect to their
use of the humanist ideals of the Enlightenment, the French
Revolution, and German idealism.7 The problem which Marcuse
enunciated was this: what conditions are needed to realize the
humanist ideal today? His solution was “libertarian socialism,”K
which in turn raised other problems. How did Marcuse resolve
the question, inherent in any utopia, of the relation between
the ethics of conscience and the ethics of responsibility? Why
did lie resort to a “double morality”? In the final analysis, did
106 Herbert Marcuse's (Jtof)ia
his use of the notion of "aesthetic morality" transform his poli-
ticism into moralism?
Max Weber’s famous distinction between the ethics of consci
ence and responsibility in his essay, "Politics as a Vocation,” is
very useful in pinpointing the difficult relation between ethics
and politics.'* Paul Ricoeur employed it in his article," 1he I asks
of the Political Educator.”10 Weber’s solution to this basic para
dox of action is well known. Reasonable action is based both
on responsibility, which guides the statesman in justifying his
actions, and on conscience, which guides the citizen in his critique
of the statesman. These complementary guidelines meet in the
reasonable man. Marcuse’s solution to this paradox is perhaps
less well known. Me formulated it by trying to imagine the crit
icisms that, as he put it, "I hope you have long been addressing
to me" for having developed “a utopia in which it is asserted
that modern industrial society could soon reach a state in which
the principle of repression that has previously directed its
development will prove itself obsolete.”11 It was as though he
felt a need to clear himself: “It may be less irresponsible today
to depict a utopia that has a real basis than to defame as utopia
conditions and potentials that have long become realizable
possibilities.”12 Utopia, in fact, offers a good example of how
the ethics of conscience influence the ethics of responsibility.
As Ricoeur explained, it is the historical function of utopia to
give economic, social, and political activity a doubly human aim.
Humanity should be seen both as a totality guided by a universal
ethic, and as a singularity or a unique condition in which the
vocation of each individual is realized.1' I bis is why a healthy
balance must he maintained between the ethics of conscience
and responsibility.11 But in line with the rest of his philosophy,
Marcuse subordinated the ethics of responsibility to the ethics
of conscience, forgetting that, as Ricoeur pointed out, “A utopian
thesis, it is necessary to repeal, does not have an effectiveness
of its own; it has such only to the extent that it transforms step
by step the historical experience that we are able to make on
the level of institutions and on the level of industries. I bis is
why utopia becomes falsehood when it is not articulated correctly
concerning the possibilities offered to each epoch."15 It was
these concrete historical facts that Marcuse consciously and
deliberately suppressed, for example, during the discussion
following his remarks at the 1961 conference on Max Weber
Marcuse’s Revolutionary Lillies 107
at Heidelberg. This passage has already been cited in another
context, but bears repeating here: “I would really like to confess
to Utopia for the simple reason that nowadays the concept of
Utopia has become meaningless. If we look at present-day intel
lectual and material wealth, if we look at ourselves, what we
know and can do, there is actually nothing which rationally and
with a good conscience we should despise and denounce as
Utopian. We could actually do anything today. We could
certainly have a rational society, and just because that is such a
near possibility its actual realization is more “Utopian" than
ever before; the whole force of the status quo is mobilized against
it.”16
Basically, he was speaking of himself. Note, however, that
he spoke in the conditional, the utopian tense. We can observe,
as did Weber, that by adopting the ethics of conscience, Marcuse
became a prophet of the millenium.1' What is more, by setting
aside the ethics of responsibility he also postponed the choice
of the means suited to the desired end. The only thing he
retained was an ideal of perfection supposedly handed down
to us through two long and parallel traditions—the heretical
or revolutionary tradition, and the orthodox or reactionary
tradition. This brings us to the eternal problem of a double
moral standard: my ethics are good, yours are bad.
“I believe there is a double moral standard in history," stated
Marcuse unequivocally in answer to Julien Freund during the
discussion following his lecture on “Freedom and the Historical
Imperative.” In the lecture he had stated, “There has always
been a dual morality: that of the status q u o ,. .. and revolu
tionary morality.”18 Marcuse used this dualist approach in judg
ing a situation such as the Watergate scandal. Americans tried
to show that it was a case of exceptional corruption, an aber
ration, he explained, when in fact it was merely “an extreme
political form of the normal state of things.” Watergate should
be seen in context, he maintained, the context being that of
American capitalism, which could only perpetuate itself through
illegal and illegitimate means—in other words, through the use
of violence in the various branches of intellectual and material
culture.19 With Marcuse, as the following statement shows, the
theory of a double moral standard corresponded to a double
standard of violence. “There is a violence of police forces or
armed forces or the Ku Klux Klan, and there is a violence in
108 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
the opposition to these aggressive manifestations of violence.”'"
Elsewhere, he distinguished between “the institutionalized viol
ence of the established system and the violence of resistance.”21
He made a further distinction: "In terms of historical function,
there is a difference between revolutionary and reactionary
violence, between violence practiced by the oppressed and by
the oppressors."22 Marcuse appeared to see it as a very straight
forward matter: two parallel traditions, two kinds of morality,
and two types of violence. Yet, in his contribution to A Critique
of Pure Tolerance, which is a somewhat cavalier mixture of ethics
and politics, the terms he used gave a dif ferent impression. He
appeared to favor the specifically utopian technique of inver
sion, coining contradictory expressions such as totalitarian
democracy, democratic dictatorship, and repressive tolerance.
Indeed, he seemed to positively wallow in opposites, although
when we look more closely we find that here, too, he distin
guished between totalitarian democracy23 and real democ
racy,21 between democratic dictatorship2’ and dictatorship
period,2" and between repressive tolerance and liberating toler
ance, which he defined as being “intolerance against move
ments from the Right, and toleration of movements from the
Left."27
What was this liberating tolerance that Marcuse advanced as
one of the principle values of revolutionary ethics? It was the
type of tolerance which must he practiced by the revolutionary
or intellectual in order to reaffirm the existence of “historical
possibilities which seem to have become utopian possibilities.”2K
For Marcuse, then, it was a moral duty to proclaim the end of
utopia, because “all the material and intellectual forces which
could be put to work for the realization of a free society are at
hand. That they are not used for that purpose is to be attributed
to the total mobilization of existing society against its own poten
tial for liberation.”2"
In other words, as he remarked in One-Dimensional Man, “The
unrealistic sound of these propositions is indicative, not of their
utopian character, but of the strength of the forces which prevent
their realization.”30 Contemporary society must not be
condemned for what it has accomplished (and it has done more
than any other), but for what it refuses to do, by which is meant
the total liberation of the individual, the total emancipation of
humanity. Marcuse submitted to this revolutionary ideal because
Marcuse's Revolutionary Ethics 109
he did not consider it possible to progress toward a better soci
ety through the historical continuum. There must be a break. ’1
"A non-explosive evolution" would produce nothing.32 Only an
authentic revolution could guarantee qualitative change, which
was why Marcuse pvit the following question: “Can a revolution
be justified as right, as good, perhaps even as necessary, and
justified not merely in political terms . . . but in ethical terms?"31
Furthermore, “Is the revolutionary use of violence justifiable
as a means for establishing or promoting human freedom and
happiness?”31 He tried to prove that the use of violence for
radical, qualitative, social change was justified if one applied
“ethical terms such as ‘right’ or ‘good’ . . . to political . . . move
ments.’’3’ In so doing, he confronted us with the distinction
between the just and unjust enemy of revolutionary ideology.36
The just enemy is always revolutionary, while the unjust enemy
is always against the revolution. However, the notion of the
unjust enemy is based on a confusion between ethics and poli
tics.
Marcuse deliberately maintained this confusion for subver
sive purposes; the ultimate goals of his lilxnating project masked
the consequences of action. He pretended to be unaware that
the implementation of a generous idea could have dangerous
consequences, in virtue of what Max Weber called “the paradox
of consequences.”37 Marcuse saw the transcendent historical
project as a feasible present-day goal, since both technology and
economy could now guarantee general emancipation. The proj
ect justified the use of revolutionary violence that would end
man’s domination of man, and inaugurate a reign of happiness.
In effect, revolutionary ethics were to guarantee the transition
from traditional morality, according to which the personal ideal
is impervious to happiness, to a morality that could accom
modate an aesthetic ideal. Marcuse stated, "If the individual is
ever to come under the power of the ideal to the extent of
believing that his concrete longings and needs are to be found
in it—found moreover in a state of fulfillment and gratification,
then the ideal must give the illusion of granting present satis
faction. It is this illusory reality that neither philosophy nor
religion can attain. Only art achieves it—in the medium of
beauty.”38
These revolutionary ethics were transitory. Marcuse claimed
that they could bring about a “new morality,”3'' an “aesthetic
110 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
morality"10 that would realize both the ethical and aesthetic
ideals at once. But here again Marcuse was open to the charge
of being misleading. Although it is true that the beautiful and
the good resemble each other in several respects, and that beauty
can be a “symbol of morality," as is the Kantian expression11
used by Marcuse,12 it is no less true that there are differences
which Marcuse passed over. Indeed, we might well compare
Marcuse s vision, which tended toward a unity of all values, with
what Max Weber called "the antagonism of values,”1’
But this is not the only misleading aspect of Marcuse’s
discourse that I feel should be brought into the open. There
is another, and to my way of thinking, more serious aspect.
Marcuse, anxious to discover the "common denominator of
aesthetics and politics," made use of the idea of an “aesthetic
e t h o s He well understood that the fate of a civilization is
decided at this level of values, and he actually proposed a new
ethos that would assume the role of a universal ethos. On the
strictly ethical level, this universal ethos was the direct opposite
of puritanism.1’ On the eihico-religious level, it was the nega
tion of the Judeo-Christian tradition, although only in part,
since it needed the revolutionary elements inherent in the
promise of happiness and freedom."’ And finally, looking at
the question from the political perspective in the sense that
Marcuse understood it—that is, from a unitary, universal
perspective—this new aesthetic ethos was formulated in accord
ance with the dual connotation of the word aesthetic.17 On one
hand, it implied a new sensitivity that would create a "libidinal
morality"IK and “aesthetic needs."1'1On the other, it related to
art, which would include science.,0 According to Marcuse, this
was the only valid way, the only permissible telos or ultimate
end. He underscored this view by noting that it involved “the
aesthetic ethos of socialism" in which “the construction of the
world of art” may be “akin to the reconstruction of the real
world.” ' 1 It would not involve just any socialism, however, only
that aimed at realizing utopia.,2
In the last analysis, the ultimate criterion of the Marcusian
perspective is the dichotomy between that-which-is and that-
which-should-be, between barbarism and socialism, Thanalos
and Eros. In discussing the last two basic principles or explan
atory hypotheses, he asserted that he would have been unable
to comprehend present events, were it not for the concept of
Marcuse's Revolutionary Ethics 111
the destructive instinct posited in Freud’s metapsychology.
“Today the intensification of this instinct is a political necessity
for those in power. Without this hypothesis I must believe that
the world has become crazy and that we are being ruled by
madmen, or by criminals or by idiots, and that we have let
ourselves go to pieces.’” ' As for the constructive instinct that
would inspire the building of a non-repressive civilization, he
wrote that “today the fight for life, the light for Eros, is the
political light.’” 1
Marcuse saw only one solution, in consequence: while await
ing the revolution we must prepare future humanity fora radi
cal change through adequate education. “All education today
is therapy: therapy in the sense of liberating man by all available
means from a society in which, sooner or later, he is going to
be transformed into a brute, even if lie doesn’t notice it any
more. Education in this sense is therapy, and all therapy is polit
ical theory and practice.’” 5 This political education had already
begun at the university level,3(1 he felt, and must be spread to
include all human activities, “all spheres of culture.’” ' The more
the all-powerful, contemporary technology is dominated by the
establishment, “the more it will become dependent on political
direction.”58 Instead of being “an instrument of destructive
politics,”59 the established technology could be "a political a
priori’’ for “pacified existence.”,>(l Science must therefore be put
to work for social reorganization.'*1 Moral argument must
become a social force.02 Art is not meaningful unless it can join
in the "political struggle,”63 for only the aesthetic dimension
can guarantee the revolution ol the twenty-first century.'*1
Conclusion
Does the hope of modernity lie in Marcuse’s utopia? That is
the initial question posed by this book. Marcuse tried to convince
us that society was one-dimensional. In the past, he explained,
there were two dimensions. The social dimension allowed man
to integrate himself with society; the personal dimension
permitted him to question society. T his second dimension no
longer exists, he asserted, because the system today assimilates
everything. The loss of man’s faculty for negative thought has
forced him into an impasse. No matter what reforms are made,
they reinforce rather than change the system. Only revolution
is left, but even that is impossible because the forces opposing
it are too powerful, despite the fact that general economic and
technological conditions have never been so promising, and
that the suppression of utopia through its realization has become
a genuine possibility. But, we may ask, is existing society in fact
moving toward the suppression of utopia, comparable to Marx’s
suppression of philosophy? In reality, specific human activities
continue to be numerous. Politics, for example, has its partic
ular phenomena, such as the police and the army; religion has
its own special manifestations, such as prayer and mystical
theology. One cannot resolve political or economic problems
with ethics, or vice versa. It is impossible to reduce all human
activities to a single entity—even if it were art. And the fact
that there are many activities means that there are many values.
Each activity creates its own values, which do not necessarily
harmonize with the values of others. It is therefore not logically
justifiable to propose a transcendent historical project to
humankind solely because it is founded on values such as free
dom and happiness. Marcuse relied on the assumption that
man would have the option of choosing so grandiose a project.
But i( man still has the possibility of choice, it is because he has
not yet been totally alienated by his past. In any case, if he makes
a definitive choice such as Marcuse proposed, particularly with
Conclusion 113
out knowing exactly where it will lead, he is surely alienating
himself with regard to his future. 'Phis is the underlying signif
icance of Marcuse’s utopia: it closes humanity in upon itself, as
utopia confines itself within its insular perspective. But let us
immediately add that Marcuse, more than anyone else, was aware
of the problem of encirclement. Indeed, the dilemma of the
vicious circle was one of the things for which he became known.
And this is probably why he wanted his theory to be understood
as a call, a cry of mingled hope and despair. The following
anecdote reported by Reinhard Lettau can perhaps help us
comprehend his desire.1 Marcuse recounted how one day
someone asked Beckett to explain the structure of his writing.
Beckett answered, “I was once in a hospital, and in the room
next door a woman who was dying of cancer screamed all night.
This screaming is the structure of my writing.”
Marcuse has made this terminal cry his own, describing it
with Wedekind’s words from the last scene of Pandora’s Box:
“Es war doch so schon!”—“So fair has it been!”2 And he echoes
Strindberg’s cry from Dreamplay: “Es ist schade um di
Menschen”—“It is a pity about human beings!”’
Notes
Abbreviations of Works by Marcuse
AC Actuels. Paris: E d itio n s G a lile e , 11)70.
AD The Aesthetic Dimension: Toward a Critique of Marxist Aesthetics.
B o s to n : B e a c o n P r e ss, 11)78.
Introduction
1 A le x a n d r e C io r a n e s c u , L'Avenir du passe (P a ris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 7 2 ),
121.
2. K arl M a r x , “C o n tr ib u tio n to th e C r iti(|iie o f H e g e l’s P h ilo s o p h y
o f L aw , I n tr o d u c tio n ,” Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works, (N e w
Notes 115
Y o rk : I n te r n a t io n a l P u b lis h e r s , 1 9 7 5 ), 3 : 1 8 7 . S u b s e q u e n t r e f e r e n c e s
to M a r x a n d E n g e ls a r e to th is e d it io n , u n le s s o t h e r w is e s ta te d .
3 . H e n r i L e fe b v r c , Pour connaitre la pensee de Karl Mm x (Paris: B o r d a s,
(1 9 4 7 ] I9 6 0 ), 100.
4 . “P h ilo s o p h y a n d C ritical T h e o r y ," in N E , 1 5 1 -1 5 2 . C ite d by G e ra rd
K a u le t, " P o u r tin e r e c o n s t r u c t io n d e la t h e o r ie c r itiq u e : L ’I n te g r a tio n
tie s v a le u r s d e la c r it iq u e ,” in P a u l-L a u r e n t A s s o u n a n d G e r a r d R a u le t,
Marxisme el theorie critique (P a ris: P a y o t, 1 9 7 8 ), 1 24.
5 . I b id ., 1 5 3 .
0 . K arl M a r x , " T h e s e s o n F e u e r b a c h ," Karl Marx, Frederick Engels:
Collected Works, 5 : 5 .
7. “P r e fa c e ” (1 9 0 4 ) , Culture et societe (Paris: E d itio n s d e M in u it, 19 7 0 ),
18. C f ., N E , x x .
8. NE, x ix .
9 . EL, ix .
10. SM, 5 .
11. H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , Eros et civilisation (P a ris: E d itio n s d e M in u it,
1 9 0 8 ), 10 (fr o m a sp e c ia l p r e fa c e w ritten in 1901 fo r th e F r e n c h e d itio n ).
C f ., EC, 5 .
12. S e e ODM, 4 , a n d " T h e E n d o f U t o p ia ,” in EL, 0 4 , 0 5 .
13. H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , “ L ib e r a tio n fr o m th e A f f lu e n t S o c ie ty ,” in To
Free a Generation: The Dialectics of Liberation, e d . D a v id C o o p e r
( H a r m o n d s w o r t h : P e n g u in B o o k s L td ., 1 9 0 9 ), 184.
14. H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , " P r o to s o c ia lis m a n d L a te C a p ita lism : T o w a r d
a T h e o r e t i c a l S y n t h e s is B a s e d o n B a h r o ’s A n a ly sis," International Jour
nal of Politics 10, n o s . 2 -3 (S u m m e r -F a ll 1 9 8 0 ): 2 5 , 3 3 ; th is e s s a y a ls o
p u b lis h e d in Rudolf Bahro: Critical Responses, e d . U l f W o lte r (W h ite
P la in s, N .Y .: M .E . S h a r p e , I n c ., 1 9 8 0 ), 2 5 - 4 8 . S e e a ls o id ., “S o m m e s -
Partisans 2 8 (A p r il 1 9 0 0 ): 2 0 ; “O n th e N e w
n o u s d e ja d e s h o m in e s ? ”
L e f t ,” in The New Left: A Documentary History, e d . M a ssim o T e o d o r i
( I n d ia n a p o lis : B o b b s -M c r r ill, 1 9 0 9 ), 4 0 9 ; a n d " L ib e r a tio n fr o m th e
A f f lu e n t S o c ie ty ," 1 8 4 .
15. " F h e E n d o f U t o p i a ,” FL, 0 3 .
10. “ P h ilo s o p h y a n d C r itic a l T h e o r y ,” N E , 14 3 .
17. L e sz e k K o la k o w sk i, L'Esprit revolutwnnaire suivi de Matxisme: Utopic
et anti-utopie (B r u s s e ls : E d itio n s C o m p l e x e , 1 9 7 8 ), 1 13.
18. S id n e y L ip s h it e s , Herbert Marcuse: From Marx to Freud and Beyond,
(C a m b r id g e : S c h e n k m a n P u b lis h in g C o ., 1 9 7 4 ).
19. M o r to n S c h o o lm a n , The Imaginary Witness: The Critical Theory of
Herbert Marcuse ( N e w Y o rk : F r e e P re ss, 1 9 8 0 ).
2 0 . V in c e n t G e o g h e g a n , Reason and Eros: The Social Theory of Herbert
Marcuse ( L o n d o n : P lu to P r e ss, 1 9 8 1 ).
2 1 . M a r tin Jay, The Dialectical Imagination: A History of the Frankfurt
School and the histitute of Social Research, 1923-1950 (L o n d o n : H e in e -
m a n n , 1 9 7 3 ).
1 16 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
2 2 . D a v id I ie l d , Introduction to Critical Theory: Hotkheirner to Habermas
(B e r k e le y : U n iv e r s ity o f C a lifo r n ia P re ss, 1 9 8 0 ).
2 3 . G e o r g e F r ie d m a n , The Political Philosophy oj the Frankfurt School
(I th a c a a n d L o n d o n : C o r n e ll U n iv e r s ity P re ss, 1 9 8 1 ).
2 4 . G e r a r d R a n le t, “ P o u r u n e r e c o n s tr u c tio n d e la ih e o r ie c r itiq u e ,"
1 0 1 -1 4 8 .
2 5 . B e n A g g e r , Western Marxism: An Introduction, Classical and Contem
porary Sources (S a n ta -M o n ic u : G o o d y e a r P u b lis h in g , 1 9 7 9 ).
2 6 . T h o m a s M o ln a r , Utopia, the Perennial Heresy ( N e w Y ork : S lic e d
a n d W a r d , 1 9 6 7 ), 2 3 4 - 2 3 5 , 2 0 5 .
2 7 . J e a n -M a r ie D o m e n a c h , “ U lo p ie o u la r a iso n d a n s r im a g in a ir c ,"
Esprit (A p r il 1 9 7 4 ): 3 5 1 , n . I I .
Chapter I
1. H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , “O n t h e Q u e s t io n o f R e fo r m o r R e v o lu t io n ,”
Listening, 8 , n o s. 1-2-3 (1 9 7 3 ): 8 8 .
2 . E rica S h e r o v e r M a r c u s e a n d P e te r M a r c u s e , “O p e n L e tte r to
F r ie n d s o f H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” N ew German Critique, 6 , n o . 3: 2 8 .
3 . G e r s h o m S c b o le m , Fidelite et ulopie: Essais sut le judaisme content-
porain, (P aris: C a lm a n n -L e v y , 1 9 7 8 ), 2 5 6 .
4 . H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , “ R e v o lu tio n et c r itiq u e d e la v io le n c e : S u r la
p h ilo s o p h ic d e I'h isto ir e d e W a lte r B e n j a m in ,” Revue d'eslhelique, n o .
I (1 9 8 1 ): 1 0 1 -1 0 2 . C L , W a lte r B e n ja m in , “N a c h w o r t,” Zur Kritik der
Gewalt and andere Aufsatze (F r a n k fu r t a m M a in : S u h r k a m p V e r la g ,
1 9 6 5 ), 9 9 - 1 0 6 . O n J u d a is m in th e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l, s e e G e o r g e F r ie d
m a n , The Political Philosophy o f the Frankfurt School (Ith a c a : C o r n e ll
U n iv e r s ity P re ss), 9 2 - 1 0 2 .
5 . “C a n C o m m u n is m B e L ib eral?" N ew Statesman, 8 3 , n o . 2 1 5 3 (2 3
J u n e 1 9 7 2 ): 8 6 1 . A r o n : " Y o u a r e still liv in g in W e im a r G e r m a n y .”
M a r c u se : “Y e s 1 k n o w th a t.”
6 . FL, 1 0 2 -1 0 3 .
7. “ T h e o r y a n d P o litics: A D is c u s s io n w ith H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , J u r g e n
H a b e r m a s , H e in z L u b a s/., a n d T e lm a n S p e n g le r ," tr a ils, by L e slie
A d e ls o n , S u s a n H e g g e r , B e tty S u n , a n d H e r b e r t W e in r y b , Telus, 11,
n o . 3 (W in te r 1 9 7 8 -7 9 ): 1 2 6 . Ita lic s m in e .
8 . J o h a n n Pall A r n a s o n , " M a r c u s e c r itiq u e d e sta lin is m e ," Partisans,
n o . 6 8 ( N o v .- D e e . 1 9 7 2 ): 1 03.
9 . “ R e v o lu tio n et c r itiq u e d e la v io le n c e ," 1 05.
10. C la u d e S a m u e l, "L a F a m e a M a r c u se . . . ," Le Point, n o . 2 5 6 (1 7
O c t. 1 9 7 7 ): 8 8 .
1 1. “ D e a r A n g e la ,” Ramparts M agazine, 9 (F e b . 1 9 7 1 ): 2 2 .
12. M a r c u s e , “ P r o to s o c ia lis m a n d L a te C a p ita lis m .”
13. M a r c u s e s u m m e d u p th e p r o te s t o f th e s ix tie s in a little -k n o w n
sp e c ia l in te r v ie w w ith th e d ir e c to r o f th e c o lle c tio n “L es G r a n d s T h e m e s "
Notes 117
(G 1 ). H e n r i I is s o t, eel., LesJnines et hi contestation, v o l. 9 3 o f Bibliotheque
Laffont des grands tlihnes (L a u s a n n e : E d itio n s G r a m m o n t; Paris: R o b e rt
L a f f o n t ; a n d B a r c e lo n a : S a lv a t, 1 9 7 5 ), 8 - 1 7 , GO-67.
14. D o u g la s K e lln e r , “ In R e m e m b r a n c e o f H e r b e r t M a r c u se , 1 8 9 8 -
1 9 7 9 ,” Socialist Review, 9 , n o . 5 (S e p t.-O c t. 1 9 7 9 ): 13 3 .
15. I v o F ra n ze l, “U to p ia a n d A p o c a ly p s e in G e r m a n L iteratu re," Social
Research, 3 9 , n o . 2 ( S u m m e r 1 9 7 2 ): 3 0 7 . ( T h is w a s a s p e c ia l n u m b e r
d e v o t e d to t h e W e im a r c u lt u r e .)
16. C f ., P h ilip p e B e n e t o n , Histoire de wots: Culture et civilisation (P aris:
P r e s s e s d e la F o n d a t io n n a t io n a le d e s s c ie n c e s p o litiq u e s , 1 9 7 5 ).
17. “ F b e R e v o lu t io n N e v e r C a m e ," Time M agazine, C a n a d ia n e d ., 13
A u g . 1 9 7 9 , 13.
18. “O n t h e Q u e s t io n o f R e fo r m o r R e v o lu tio n ," 8 8 .
19. J a y , The Dialectical Imagination, 2 8 .
2 0 . J e a n - M ic h e l P a lm ie r , “ L e C r o u p e d e n o v e m b r e o u I’a ri c o m m e
a r m e r e v o lu tio n n a ir e ," in Apocalypse et revolution, v o l. 1 o f L ’Expres-
sionnisme comme revolte. Contribution a I'elude de la vie artistiejue sous la
Republique de Weimar (P a ris: P a y o t, 1 9 7 8 ), 3 9 2 - 4 0 0 .
2 1 . J a y , The Dialectical Imagination, 2 8 .
22. “O n t h e Q u e s t io n o f R e fo r m o r R e v o lu tio n ," 8 9 .
23. “T h e o r y a n d P o litics," 12 6 .
24. J a y , The Dialectical Imagination, 8.
25. S id n e y L ip s h ir e s , Herbert Marcuse: From M a n to Freud and Beyond
( C a m b r id g e : S c h e n k m a n P u b lis h in g C o ., 1 9 7 4 ), 13 n. 4 3 .
2 6 . C f ., J u r g e n H a b e r m a s , " P sy c h ic T h e r m id o r a n d th e R eb irth o f
R e b e llio u s S u b je c tiv ity ,” Berkeley Journal o f Sociology, 2 4 - 2 5 (1 9 8 0 ): 6 .
S e e a ls o K e lln e r , “ In R e m e m b r a n c e o f H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” 132.
2 7 . O n th e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l s e e : A n d r e w A r a to , “P o litica l S o c io lo g y
a n d C r itiq u e o f P o litic s ,” in The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, e d s .
A n d r e w A r a to a n d L ik e G c b h a r d t ( N e w Y o r k ,: U r iz e n B o o k s , 1 9 7 8 )
3 - 2 5 ; Esprit, s p e c ia l is s u e o n t h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l, n o . 17 (M ay 19 7 9 );
D a v id H e ld , Introduction to Critical Theory, Horkheimer to Habermas, s e le c
t i v e b i b l i o g r a p h y 4 8 3 - 4 9 9 , i n d e x 5 0 1 - 5 1 I, a n d p a s s im ; R ic h a r d
K ilm in s te r , Praxis and Method: A Sociological Dialogue with Lukiics, Gram-
sci and the Early Frankfurt School ( L o n d o n , H e n le y , a n d B o s to n :
R o u t le d g e & K c g a n P a u l, 1 9 7 9 ), c f ., in d e x 3 2 9 ; L e sz e k K o la k o w sk i,
" T h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l a n d ‘C r itic a l T h e o r y ,’ ” tr a n s la te d b y P .S. Falla,
in The Breakdown, v o l. 3 o f M ain Currents o f Marxism, Its Origin, Growth,
and Dissolution ( O x f o r d : C la r e n d o n P r e ss, 1 9 7 8 ) 3 4 1 - 3 9 5 , e s p . 3 4 4 - 3 4 5 ,
3 4 8 , 3 7 7 , 3 9 0 ; P h il S la te r , Origin and Significance o f the Frankfurt School:
A M arxist Perspective ( L o n d o n : R o u t le d g e & K e g a n P a u l, 1 9 7 7 ), in d e x
1 8 3 -1 8 5 .
2 8 . P a u l A . R o b in s o n , The Freudian Left ( N e w Y o rk : H a r p e r a n d R ow ,
1 9 6 9 ), 1 5 1 , c it in g International Institute o f Social Research: A Report on
Its History, Aims, an d Activities, 1 9 3 3 -1 9 3 8 , 4 , 6 .
118 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
29. Introduction to Critical Theory, 1 4 -1 5 .
D a v id H e ld ,
110. |a v , The Dialectical Imagination, 3 9 .
111. K arl M a r x . "L e P ro jet d e m ig r a t i o n d u c ito y e n ( l a b e l ,” La Revue
coninmniste, n o . 1 ( 1 9 5 8 ) , c ite d b y L o u is M a r in , Utopit/ues: Jeux d ’espaces,
(P aris: L es E d itio n s d e M iiu iil, 1 9 7 3 ), 3 4 3 * 3 5 1 .
3 2 . " P r e fa c e lo t h e O r ig in a l E d itio n ,'' R ll (p o c k e t e d it io n ) , xv.
3 3 . “T h e o r y a n d P o litics," 129.
3 4 . M ax H o r k h e im e r , T r a d itio n a l a n d C ritic a l T h e o r y ," ( 1 9 3 7 ) ,
Critical Theory, tr a n s la te d b y J .O . M a tth e w , C o n n e ll, et a l., ( 1 9 3 7 ; N e w
Y ork : T h e S e a b u r y P r e ss. 1 9 7 2 ), 1 8 8 -2 5 2 .
3 5 . Ib id ., 2 4 4 .
3 6 . I b id ., 2 4 4 - 2 5 2 .
3 7 . XL, 1 3 4 -1 5 8 .
38 . M artin J a y a ttr ib u te s th e first u s e o f th e e x p r e s s io n “critical th eo ry "
to M ax H o r k h e im e r . " T h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l in E x ile ,” in Perspectives
in American History, 0 : 3 4 0 . T h e r e f o r e te x ts w r itte n b e f o r e th e y e a r 1 9 3 7
m e r e ly c o n ta in e x p r e s s io n s th at p r e f ig u r e w h a t s u b s e q u e n t ly b e c a m e
th e " critical th e o r y " o f t h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l. T h u s , in M a r c u s e ’s first
p u b lis h e d a rticle in 1 9 2 8 , w e fin d h im u s in g e x p r e s s io n s s u c h as “th e o r y
o f so c ia l a c tiv ity ,” o r " th e o r y o f h is to r ic a l a c tio n " to d e s c r ib e w h a t h e
u n d e r s t o o d by M a r x ism at th a t tim e . (C L , " C o n tr ib u tio n s to a P h e
n o m e n o lo g y o f H isto r ic a l M a te r ia lism ." ) W h a t d is t in g u is h e s th e s e
e x p r e s s io n s fr o m “c r itic a l t h e o r y ” is th e d e s ir e to m a k e a c o n t r ib u t io n
to M a rx ist t h o u g h t .
3 9 . W illia m L eiss, " T h e C ritic a l T h e o r y o f S o c ie ty : P r e se n t S itu a tio n
a n d F u tu r e T ask s," in Critical Interruptions: Xeu< l.ejl Perspectives on Herbert
Marcuse, eel. P au l B r e in e s , ( N e w Y o rk : H e r d e r a n d H e r d e r , 1 9 7 0 ), 7 5 .
4 0 . I b id ., 7 6 , 8 8 - 8 9 .
4 1 . " T h e o r y a n d P olitics," 1 3 6 . S e e a ls o X L , 15, 13 5 .
4 2 . ODM, x -x i.
4 3 . C L , H o r k h e im e r , " T r a d itio n a l a n d C r itic a l T h e o r y ," 2 4 4 n . l .
4 4 . I b id ., 2 4 2 .
4 5 . K e lln e r , “ In R e m e m b r a n c e o f H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," 1 32.
4 6 . Jay, The Dialectical Imagination, 8 0 .
4 7 . " O n th e Q u e s t io n o f R e fo r m o r R e v o lu t io n ,” 8 9 .
4 8 . C h a r le s M o r itz , e d .. Current Biography Yearbook, 1969, 2 8 3 . S e e
a ls o J a y , The Dialectical Imagination, 1 6 9 .
4 9 . S id n e y L ip s h ir e s , Herbert Marcuse: Prom Marx to Trend and Beyond,
27.
50. EC, x x v iii.
5 1 . J o h n W a k e m a n , e d ., World Authors, 1950-1970, 9 4 5 .
5 2 . “A c k n o w le d g m e n t s ," SM, xvii.
5 3 . J o h a n n Pall A r n a s o n , “ M a r c u s e c r itiq u e d u s t a lin is m c /’ / ’ar/JMUi.t,
n o . 6 8 ( N o v .- D e e . 1 9 7 2 ): 1 0 3 .
5 4 . “O n th e Q u e s t io n o f R e fo r m o r R e v o lu t io n ,” 9 0 .
Notes 119
5 5 . A n d r e w H a c k e r , “P h ilo s o p h e r o f th e N e w L eft," The Neu< York
Times Book Review, 7 3 , n o . 1 0 ( 1 0 M ar. 1 9 6 8 ): 1.
5 6 . H a b e r m a s , “ P sy c h ic T h e r m i d o r a n d th e R e b ir th o f R e b e llio u s
S u b je c tiv ity ," 9 .
57. Who's Who in America with World Notables, 3 5 ( 1 9 6 8 - 6 9 ) .
5 8 . H a b e r m a s , “ P sy c h ic T h e r m i d o r ,” 2.
5 9 . ODM, x v i.
6 0 . R o b e r t P a u l W o lf f , “ H e r b e r t M a r c u se : 1 8 9 8 - 1 9 7 9 , A P e r so n a l
R e m in is c e n c e ,” Political Theoty, 8 , n o . 1 (F e b . 1 9 8 0 ): 7.
6 1 . “ I n d u s tr ia liz a tio n a n d C a p ita lis m in th e W o rk o f M ax W e b e r ,”
NE, 2 0 1 - 2 2 6 .
6 2 . B e n ja m in N e ls o n , “S to r m o v e r W e b e r ," The New York Times Book
Review, 3 J a n . 1 9 6 5 , se c . 7 , p . 2 4 .
63. R aym ond A ron, Les Etapes de la pensee sociologique (P aris: G alli-
m a r d ), 5 6 6 .
6 4 . “C o m m e n t ,” The New York Times Book Review, 2 8 F eb . 1 9 6 5 .
6 5 . “ I n d u s tr ia lis a tio n et c a p ita lis m e c h e z M ax W e b e r ,” CS, 2 7 3 . N o t e
th e d if f e r e n c e b e t w e e n th is a n d th e last p a r a g r a p h in th e E n g lish
p u b lis h e d v e r s io n .
66. NE, 2 0 3 .
6 7 . M ic h a e l H o r o w itz , “ P o rtr a it o f th e M a rx ist as an O ld T r o u p e r ,”
Playboy, 17, n o . 9 (1 9 7 0 ): 1 7 5 - 1 7 6 , 2 2 8 , 2 3 1 - 2 3 2 .
6 8 . I b id ., 1 7 6 , c itin g M a r c u se .
69. NE, x x .
7 0 . ODM, 4 .
7 1 . M e lv in J . L a sk y , “ L e ttr e d e B e r lin -O u e s t, a v e c le s e tu d ia n ts d u
S .D .S .,” Preuves, n o s . 2 1 5 - 2 1 6 (F e b .-M a r . 1 9 6 9 ), 6 8 . S e e a ls o c o m m e n
ta ry b y J a c q u e s E llu l, De la revolution aux revoltes (P aris: C a lm a n n -L e v y ,
1 9 7 2 ), 3 0 0 n . 2 .
7 2 . The Times, L o n d o n , 17 A p r . 1 9 6 8 , p. 10.
7 3 . " I n te r v ie w w ith M a r c u s e ,” Australian Left Review (D e c . 19 6 9 ): 3 6 .
7 4 . I b id ., 3 8 - 3 9 .
7 5 . A n d r e F r a n q o is -P o n c e t, "La C r is e d e la j e u n e s s e a lle m a n d e ,” Le
Figaro, Selection hebdomadaire, 18 A p r . 1 9 6 8 .
7 6 . “ M e n a c e s d e m o r t ,” Le Figaro, 5 A u g . 1 9 6 8 .
7 7 . G la d w in H ill, “T h e M a r c u s e C ase: C o n s e r v a tis m A r o u s e d by a
L e g io n n a ir e in S a n D ie g o ,” The New York Times, 6 O c t. 1 9 6 8 , sec. 1,
86 .
78. The Times, L o n d o n , 19 F eb . 1 9 6 9 , 6 .
7 9 . I b id ., 12 J u ly 1 9 6 8 , 6.
8 0 . H e r b e r t G o ld , “C a lifo r n ia L e ft, M a o , M arx a n d M a r c u s e !” The
Saturday Evening Post, n o . 2 4 1 (2 7 O c t. 19 6 8 ): 5 7 .
8 1 . I b id ., 5 6 - 5 9 .
8 2 . E d m u n d S tillm a n , “H e r b e r t M a rc u se,” Horizon, 1 1, n o . 3 (S u m m e r
1969) 27.
120 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
8 3 . A g u e s G u illo u , “ M a r c u s e p o u r q u o i Faire?” La AY/, n o . 3 6 (Jan.*
M ar. 1 0 6 9 ): 7.
8 4 . “AYw Left News, th e ir r e g u la r n e w s le tte r o l t h e C o lu m b ia U n iv e r
sity S I)S , o f f e r s an Adventures of One-Dimensional Man c o m ic s tr ip . ’ P au l
B r e in e s , “ M a r c u s e a n d t h e N e w L e ft in A m e r ic a ,” in Antworten auf
Herbert Marcuse, e d . J u r g e n H a b e r m a s (F r a n k fu r t a m M a in : S u h r -
k a m p , 1 9 6 8 ), 111.
La Theorie el la pratique. Dialogue imaginaire mais
8 5 . C h a r lo tte D e lb o ,
non tout a fait apocrypbe entre H. Marcuse et / / . Lefebvre (P a ris: E d itio n s
A n th r o p o s, I9 6 0 ).
8 6 . P ete r C leca k , Radical Paradoxes (N e w Y ork : H a r p e r & R ow , 1 9 7 3 ),
212.
8 7 . W o lf f , “ H e r b e r t M a r c u se : A P e r s o n a l R e m in is c e n c e ,” 7.
L ’Enseignement,
8 8 . G e r a r d B e r g e r o n , “Q u i e s t H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ? ”
n o . 8 , (1 5 D e c . 1 9 6 8 ): 2 2 : “ In Italy, tw o film s a r e b e in g s h o t. A Mother's
Heart by S a lv a to r S a m p ic r i te lls th e s to r y o f a m id d le cla ss w o m a n w h o ,
o n th e b a sis o f w h a t s h e th in k s s h e u n d e r s t a n d s o f M a r c u s e ’s b o o k s ,
d e c id e s to fo r m a g a n g o f y o u n g te r r o r is ts . T h e sa tir e is e v e n m o r e
e x a g g e r a t e d in B r u n o B a r r a ti’s Film. S o th a t n o o n e c a n m is ta k e h is
m e a n in g , h e is c a llin g it The Marcusienne, or the One-Dimensional Woman.
I n s te a d o f a m o d e s t m id d le -c la s s w o m a n , h e h a s a m illio n a ir e s s w h o
d e c id e s to a m u s e h e r s e lf by p la y in g at r e v o lu t io n ! ”
8 9 . J e a n -M ic h e l P a lm ie r , “ P o r tr a it d ’H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” in AC, 9 6 .
9 0 . M in e N . B ., “ M . F r a n c o is P e r r o u x in t r o d u it M a r c u s e a u C o lle g e
d c F r a n c e ,” Le Monde, 2 9 J a n u a r y 1 9 6 9 , p . 11.
9 1 . F r a n c o is P e r r o u x , Francois Perroux interroge Herbert Marcuse. . .
qui repond (P a ris: A u b ie r - M o n t a ig n e , 1 9 6 9 ), 1 00.
9 2 . L o u is W iz n itz e r , “ I n te r v ie w e x c lu s iv e d ’H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , th e o -
r ic ie n r e v o lu tio n n a ir e fo r t d o u x ,” La Presse, M o n tr e a l, 4 J a n . 1 9 6 9 , 7.
9 3 . “ U .S . S t u d e n t G a o le d f o r A r s o n A t t e m p t ,” The Times, L o n d o n ,
2 2 F eb . 1 9 6 9 , 5.
9 4 . J a y A c to n , “M u g S h o ts , W h o ’s W h o in th e N e w E arth ," World
1 972, 1 38.
9 5 . “ P o n t if f A ssa ils E r o tic is m A g a in , S c o r e s F r e u d a n d M a r c u s e in
H o m ily B a s ilic a ,” The New York Times, 2 O c t. 1 9 6 9 , 2 3 .
9 6 . H o r o w itz , “ P o r tr a it o f th e M a r x ist a s a n O ld T r o u p e r ,” 2 2 8 .
9 7 . I b id ., 2 3 1 .
9 8 . A lle n R. N e w m a n , “N o t e s o n M a r c u s e ’s C r itiq u e o f I n d u s tr ia l
S o c ie ty ,” Rei’iew of Social Economy, 3 4 , n o . 2 (O c t. 1 9 7 6 ): 1 7 3 .
9 9 . Britannica Book of the Year, 1 9 6 9 : 15 8 .
100. S o l S te r n , “T h e M e ta p h y s ic s o f R e b e llio n ,” Ramparts Magazine,
6 (2 9 J u n e 1 9 6 8 ): 5 6 .
1 01. P a lm ie r , “ P o r tr a it d ’H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” 1 0 3 .
1 02. M a r tin J a y , “ I h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l in E x ile ,” Perspectives in Amer
ican History ( C a m b r id g e , M ass.: 1 9 7 2 ), 6 : 3 8 2 . O t h e r s in c lu d e d R on
Notes 121
A r o n s o n , M ic h a e l H o r o w itz , D a v id K e ttle r , D o n a ld L e e , M y ria m
M ie d z ia n M a lin o v ic h , a n d J o h n O ’N e ill.
1 0 3 . W illia m L e is s , J o h n D a v id O b e r , a n d E rica S h e r o v e r , “ M a r c u se
as I e a c h e r , in 7 he Critical Spirit, Essays in Honor of Herbert Marcuse,
e d s . K u rt H . W o lf f a n d B a r r in g t o n M o o r e , J r ., (B o s to n : B e a c o n P ress,
1 9 6 7 ), 4 2 1 -4 2 5 .
104. Ibid., 425. Italics mine.
1 0 5 . I b id ., 4 2 4 . Ita lic s m in e .
1 0 6 . R a y m o n d A r o n , La Revolution introuvable: Reflexions sur les evene-
ments de mai (P a r is: F a y a r d , 1 9 6 8 ), 11 9 .
1 0 7 . “ P r o f e s s o r s , O n e - D im e n s io n a l P h ilo s o p h e r ," rime M a g a z i n e , 22
M ar. 1 9 6 9 , 6 7 .
1 0 8 . “D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a s n ’t a F u tu r e . . . a P r e s e n t ,” The New York
Times Magazine, 2 6 M ay 1 9 6 9 , 11 4 . T h is is a r e c o r d o f a p u b lic d e b a te
h e ld in N e w Y o r k at a m e e t in g o f T h e T h e a t e r fo r I d e a s . M a r c u se
s a id , “ I n o w fin a lly r e v e a l m y s e lf as a f in k .”
1 0 9 . S e e a ls o J e a n W e tz , “ U n D e s a v e u d e B o ll ct M a rc u se," Le Devoir,
M o n t r e a l, 2 0 S e p t . 1 9 7 7 , a n d G e o r g e E c k s te in , “C o p in g w ith T e r r o r
ism ," Dissent ( W in t e r 1 9 7 8 ): 8 2 - 8 4 .
110. Rudi Dutschke, article in D i e Z e i t , 39 (23 Sept. 1977), translated
as "Toward Clarifying Criticism of Terrorism,” N e w G e r m a n C r i t i q u e ,
4, no. 3: 9-10.
111. Herbert Marcuse, “Mord clarf keine Waffen tier Politik sein,”
Die Zeit, 39 (23 Sept. 1977), translated as "Murder is not a Political
Weapon,” New German Critique, 4, no. 3: 7-8.
112. Ibid., 8.
1 1 3 . C f ., J e f f r e y H e r f , “T h e C r itic a l S p ir it o f H e r b e r t M a rc u se," New
German Critique, 6 , n o . 3: 2 4 - 2 7 .
1 1 4 . O n F r e u d ia n M a r x is m , s e e “W h e n D o g m a B ite s D o g m a : O r th e
D iffic u lt M a r r ia g e o f M a r x a n d F r e u d ,” Times Literaiy Supplement, 8
J a n . 1 9 7 1 , 2 5 - 2 7 ; E r n e s t J o n e s , “S o c io lo g y ,” in Last Years (1 9 1 9 -1 9 3 9 ),
v o l. 3 o f The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud (N e w Y ork : B a sic B o o k s ,
In c ., 1 9 6 9 ); a n d Freudo-Marxisme et sociologiede Talienation (Paris: E d ition s
A n t h r o p o s a n d U n io n g e n e r a l e d ’e d it io n s , 1 9 7 4 ).
1 15. C f ., W ilh e lm R e ic h , La Crise sexuelle, fo llo w e d b y “ M a te r ia lism e
d ia le c t iq u e et p s y c h a n a ly s e ," a tr a n s la tio n e x p u r g a t e d by th e F r e n c h
C o m m u n is t P a r ty (P a r is: E d itio n s S o c ia le s I n te r n a t io n a le s , 1 9 3 4 ).
1 1 6 . C f ., f o r e x a m p le , J a c q u e s M o u s s e a u , “ W ilh e lm R eich p r e c u r s e u r
d e M a r c u s e ," in P s y c h o l o g i c , 9 (O c t. 1 9 7 0 ): 1 0 -1 2 , 1 4 -1 5 .
1 1 7 . C f ., A n d r e N ic o la s , Herbert Marcuse ou la quite d'un
univers transprometheen (P a r is: S e g h c r s , 1 9 7 0 ), a n d Wilhelm Reich ou la
revolution radicale (P a ris: S e g h e r s , 1 9 7 3 ).
1 1 8 . Jay, The Dialectical Imagination, 8 9 , 9 8 , 1 0 0 -1 0 1 , a n d 1 0 4 -1 0 5 .
119. Erich Fromm, The Revolution of Hope: Toward a Humanized Tech
nology (New York, Evanston, and London: Harper and Row, 1968),
9.
122 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
1 20. F r a n c o is C h a te le t a n d G ille s L a p o n g e , “A c tu a lite d e 1 u t o p ie , in
Quelle crise? Quelle societe? (G r e n o b le : P r e s s e s u n iv e r s ila ir e s d e G r e n
o b le . 1 9 7 4 ), 3 3 .
1 2 1 . A n d r e N ic o la s , Herbert Marcuse (P aris: S e g h e r s , 1 9 7 0 ), 7.
1 2 2 . I b id ., p . 13.
1 2 3 . G e r h a r d H o lm a n d G e r a r d R a u le t, “L 'K co le d e F r a n c fo r t e n
F r a n c e , B ib lio g r a p h ic c r itiq u e ," Esprit, n o . 17 (M a y 1 9 7 8 ): 1 3 5 -1 4 7 .
1 24. A n d r e C la ir , “ U n e P h ilo s o p h ic d e la n a tu r e ," Esprit, n o . 3 7 7 (Jan .
1 9 0 9 ): 0 8 - 7 3 .
1 2 5 . J e a n -M a r ie V in c e n t , La Theorie de I'ecole de Francfort (P aris: G a li
le e . 1 9 7 0 ), 9 .
120. P a u l-L a u r e n t A ss o u ti a n d G e r a r d R a u let, Marxisme et theorie critique
(P aris: P a y o t, 1 9 7 8 ).
1 2 7 . A n d r e S t e p h a n e ( p s e u d o n u m o f tw o p s y c h o a n a ly s ts ), “ M a r c u s e ,
c o n t r ib u t io n a F reud ou c o n t r ib u t io n aux m y th e s ? ” f o llo w e d by
" M a r c u se , M a ssa c r e p o u r d e s b a g a t e lle s ,” in U'Univers contestalionnaire
ou les nouveaux chretiens, Etude psychanalytique (P a ris: P a y o t, 1 9 0 9 ), 10 9 -
192 a n d 1 9 3 -2 0 1 .
Sociologie de la revolution, Mythologies politiques du
1 2 8 . J u le s M o n n e r o t ,
XXe si'ecle, At a txis tes-lenin isles et fascistes, La Nouvelle Strategic revolution-
naire (P aris: F a y a r d , 1 9 0 9 ), 7 0 0 .
129. R a y m o n d R u y e r , Eloge de la societe de consummation (Paris: C a lm a n n -
L e v y , 1 9 6 9 ), 1 8 8 . ’
1 3 0 . J a c q u e s E llu l, De la revolution aux revoltes, 3 0 0 .
Res Publica, 14, n o .
1 3 1 . J u lie n F r e u n d , “ La D e tr e s s e d u p o litiq u e ,"
3 (1 9 7 2 ): 4 3 3 .
13 2 . P ie r r e M a sse t, La Pensee de Herbert Marcuse ( T o u lo u s e : P riv a t,
I 9 6 0 ) , 1 88.
13 3 . A n d r e V a c h e t, “ M a r c u s e vu p a r F. P e r r o u x ,” Dialogue, 9 , n o . 3
(1 9 7 0 ), 4 2 5 .
Francois Perroux interroge Herbert Marcuse, 1 0 3 .
13 4 . P e r r o u x ,
135. R e n e V ie n e t , Enrages et Situationnistes dans le mouvement des occu
pations (P aris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 0 8 ), 1 5 3 .
1 36. V a d im D e la u n a y , " M a rcu se," Esprit, n o . 9 (S e p t. 1 9 7 7 ): 2 0 .
1 37. I. A . Z a m o s h k in a n d N . V . M o ir o s h ilo v a , “ Is M a r c u s e ’s ‘C r itic a l
T h e o r y o f S o c ie ty ’ C ritical?" The Soviet Review, 1, n o . 1 (S p r in g 1 9 7 0 ):
3 -2 4 .
1 38. Y u r y Z h u k o v , “T a k in g M a r c u s e fr o m th e W o o d s h e d ,” Atlas, 6 ,
n o . 3 (S e p t. 1 9 0 8 ): 3 3 - 3 5 .
139. A la s d a ir M a c I n ty r e , XIarcuse ( L o n d o n : F o n ta n a , 1 9 7 0 ), 17.
140. I b id ., 9 2 .
1 41. L ip s h ir e s , From Marx to Freud and Beyond, 10 4 .
1 42. G e r d -K la u s K a lt e n b r u n n e r , “M u tm a s s u n g e n lib e r M a r c u se ,"
Neues Forum: Oesterreichische monatblaetter fur KultureUe Freiheit, 15,
V ie n n a , n o s . 1 6 9 - 1 7 0 (J a n u a r y 1 9 6 8 ): 5 5 - 6 1 , a n d M aria S z e c s i, “Z u r
Notes 123
P a t h o lo g ic t ie r U t o p i e ,” Neues Forum, 15, n o . 173 (M ay 1 9 6 8 ): 3 2 5 -
328.
1 4 3 . O lg a S e m y o n o v a , “T h e N ew D is s id e n ts , L e n in g r a d ’s Y o u n g
I n te lle c t u a ls M ay T u r n to T e r r o r is m ," Nrw Statesman, 14 S e p t. 1 9 7 9 ,
3 7 4 -3 2 8 .
1 4 4 . R u s s ia n p u b lic a t io n s o n M a r c u s e a r e g e n e r a lly r e v ie w e d by
1 h o m a s j . B la k e le y in Studies in Soviet Thought.
C hapter II
1. J e a n - M ic h e l P a lm ie r , Herbert Marcuse et la Nouvelle Gauche (P aris:
B e l f o n d , 1 9 7 3 ), 3 7 8 .
2 . H e n r i D e s r o c h e , “ P e tite B ib lio t h e q u e d e I’U to p ie ," Esprit, n o . 4 3 4
(A p r . 1 9 7 4 ): 6 6 3 - 6 7 0 ) .
3 . C io r a n e s c u , “L ’A v e n ir d u p a s s e ,” 17.
4 . C f ., F r a n k E. M a n u e l a n d F r itz ie P. M a n u e l, Utopian Thought in
the Western World, 3 d e d . ( C a m b r id g e , M ass: T h e B e lk n a p P ress o f
H a r v a r d U n iv e r s it y P r e ss, 1 9 8 2 ). P a u l R ic o e u r , “ I d e o lo g y a n d U to p ia
as C u ltu r a l I m a g in a t io n ,” Philosophic Exchange, n o . 2 ( S u m m e r 197G):
1 7 -2 8 , c f ., 2 4 - 2 8 . T h is a r tic le w a s c o m p le t e d in th e F r e n c h e d itio n :
“ L ’H e r m e n e u t iq u e d e la s e c u la r is a tio n , fo i, id e o lo g ic et u t o p ie ,” in
Hermeneutique de la secularisation, E n r ic o C a ste lli et al. (P aris: A u b ie r -
M o n ta ig n e , 197G ), 49-G 8. L y m a n T o w e r S a r g e n t, “A N o te o n th e O th e r
S id e o f H u m a n N a t u r e in t h e U t o p ia n N o v e l," Political Theory, 3 , n o .
1 (F e b . 1 9 7 5 ): 8 8 * 9 7 , a n d “ U t o p ia — T h e P r o b le m o f D e fin itio n ,"
Extrapolation, 16 (May 1975): 137-1 IS. Paul A. Su ada, “Toward the Defi
nition of Utopia,” in Moreana, n o s . 3 1 - 3 2 (1 9 7 1 ): 1 3 5 -1 4 6 .
5 . SCP, 2 0 3 .
G. " C an C o m m u n is m B e L ib e r a l? ” 8G 1.
7. EL, 3 -4 .
8. FL, 6 2 .
9 . C . M o s s e , “ L c s U t o p i e s e g a l i t a i r e s a l ’e p o q u e h e lle n i s t i q u e ,” Revue
historique, 2 4 1 ( 1 9 6 9 ) : 2 9 7 - 3 0 8 .
10. C io r a n e s c u , "L’A v e n ir d u p a s s e ,” 7 1 .
11. P la to , Republic, 4 7 2 d , 4 7 3 a , in The Dialogues of Plato, tr a n s la te d
b y B . J o w e t t , 4 t h e d . ( O x f o r d : C la r e n d o n P r e ss, 1 9 5 3 ), 2 : 1 6 3 - 4 9 9 .
Republic a n d Laws a r e to th is e d it io n .
R e f e r e n c e s to
12. E rn st B lo c h , Le Principe Esperance, tr a n s la te d by F ra n q o ise W u il-
m a r i (P a ris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 7 6 ) 1 :1 2 4 . O r ig in a lly p u b lis h e d as DasPrin-
zip Hoffnung ( F r a n k fu r t a m M a in : S u h r k a m p V e r la g , 1 9 5 9 ).
13. O n th e u s e o f t h e n o t io n o f t h e “d a y - d r e a m ” by P la to a n d A r is
to tle , c f ., H e n r i D e s r o c h e , Sociologie de iesperance (Paris: C a lm a n n -L e v y ,
1 9 7 3 ), 2 3 n . 8.
14. H e n r i-1 r e n e e M a r r o u , H i s t o i r e d e I 'e d u c a tio n d a n s I ’a n l i q u i t e (P aris:
S e u il, 1 9 6 5 ) , c f ., 1 5 4 .
124 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
15. H e n r i D e s r o c h e , “L ’O r ig in e u t o p iq u e ,” Esprit (O ct. 1 9 7 4 ): 3 3 7 -
366.
16. P a u l R ic o e u r . E. R. D o d d s , a n d J e a n R o y h a v e a ls o fo r m u la te d
th e p r o b le m in t h e s e te r m s . P au l R ic o e u r , “ L ’H e r m e n e u t iq u e d e la
Les Grecs et Virrationnel (A u b ie r , 1 9 6 5 );
s e c u la r is a tio n ,” 5 8 ; E. R. D o d d s ,
a n d Jean R o y , " M o d e r n ity e t u t o p ie ,” Phitosophiques, 6 , n o . I (A p r .
197 9 ): 2 2 . R o y c ite s D o d d s ’ a r tic le .
17. R a y m o n d T r o u s s o n , Voyages aux pays de unite part, Histoire litteraire
de la pernee utopique (B r u s se ls : E d itio n s d e I’U n iv e r s it e d e B r u x e lle s ,
1 9 7 5 ), 3 8 .
18. M a r io n , “ H is to ir e d e ('e d u c a tio n d a n s l’a n tiq u ite ," 1 1 6 -1 1 7 .
19. R a y m o n d R u y e r , L'Utopie et les atopies (P aris: P U F , 1 9 5 0 ), 3 8 .
2 0 . I b id ., «14.
2 1 . P la to ,Republic, 5 4 1 a .
2 2 . M o ln a r , Utopia, The Perennial Heresy, 14 9 .
2 3 . P la to , The Statesman, 2 9 3 d - e . I b is a n d s u b s e q u e n t c ita tio n s to The
Statesman a r e ta k e n fr o m Plato: T h e S o p h is t and T h e S ta te s m a n , tr a n s
la te d b y A . E. T a y lo r (L o n d o n : T h o m a s N e ls o n a n d S o n s L td ., 1 9 6 1 ),
2 5 3 -3 4 4 .
2 4 . M o ln a r , Utopia, The Perennial Heresy, 149.
2 5 . J u lie n F r e u n d , “A narchic* fu h r t zu D ik ta tu r — W a s v o n H e r b e r t
M a r c u se s P h ilo s o p h ic tib r ig g e b lie b c n i s i ?” Die Politische Meinung, n o .
148 (M a y -J u n e 1 9 7 3 ): 2 2 - 2 3 . In c o n f ir m a t io n o f F r e u n d ’s r e m a r k s ,
see RR, 3 9 4 ; EC, 2 2 5 ; ODM, 4 0 ; ER, 1 3 7 -1 3 8 ; RT, 1 0 6 , 1 2 0 -1 2 2 .
2 6 . RT, 106.
2 7 . RT, 12 0 .
2 8 . RT, 12 2 .
2 9 . " C an C o m m u n is m B e L ib eral?" 8 6 1 . S e e a ls o M . J . S o b r a n , “T h e
F u tu r e F u tu r e o f M a r c u s e ,” National Review, 8 D e c . 1 9 7 2 , 1 3 5 2 .
3 0 . Ib id .
3 1 . P la to , The Statesman, 2 9 3 d ; J e a n J a c q u e s R o u s s e a u , “D e r n ie r e
R e p o n s e d e J.*J. R o u s s e a u (a B o r d e s ) ,” inOeuvres completes, B ib lio -
t h e q u c d e la P le ia d c , 3 : 9 0 - 9 1 .
3 2 . L ju b o m ir T a d ic , “ R e v o lu tio n s o c ia lis te et p o u v o ir p o lit iq u e ,”
Praxis, n o s. 1-2 (1 9 6 9 ): 2 5 0 - 2 5 9 .
33. FU, 101.
RT, a n d “E th ics a n d R e v o lu t io n ,” in Ethics and Society: Orig
3 4 . C f.,
inal Essays on Contemporary Moral Problems, e d . R ic h a r d T . D e G e o r g e
( N e w Y ork : D o u b le d a y , 1 9 6 6 ), 1 3 3 - 1 4 7 , p a r tic u la r ly 1 3 7 -1 3 8 .
35. EC, 2 2 5 .
3 6 . “T h e o r y a n d P o litic s ,” 1 36.
3 7 . J e a n R o y , “ L a T o l e r a n c e r e p r e s s iv e ,’ n o u v e lle r u s e d e la R a iso n
d 'E t a t f ” in Rationality Today, La Rationalite aujourd'hui, e d . T h e o d o r e
F. G e r a e ts (O tta w a : E d itio n s d e I’U n iv e r s it e d ’O tta w a , 1 9 7 9 ), 4 8 5 f f .
Notes 125
3 8 . D a v id S p itz , " P u r e T o le r a n c e : A C r itiq u e o f C r itic is m s," Dissent,
13 , n o . 5 ( S e p t .- O c t . 1 9 6 6 ): 5 1 0 - 5 2 5 , r e p r in te d (S p r in g 1 9 7 4 ): 2 5 9 -
2G 9. T h e a r tic le w as a g a in r e p r in t e d , w ith a n in t r o d u c t io n , in Beyond
the New Left, e d . I r v in g H o w e ( N e w Y o rk : M cC a ll P u b . C o ., 1 9 7 0 ), 100-
119. T h e a r tic le w as t h e s u b je c t o f s e v e r a l c o m m e n t a r ie s , to w h ic h th e
a u t h o r r e p lie d : (1 ) M ic h a e l W a lz e r , “O n th e N a t u r e o f F r e e d o m ,” in
Dissent, 13 . n o . 6 ( N o v .- D e e . 1 9 6 6 ): 7 2 5 - 7 2 8 ; D a v id S p itz , “T h e P le a s
u r e s o f M is u n d e r s t a n d in g F r e e d o m ,” ib id ., 7 2 9 - 7 3 9 ; (2 ) R o b ert P aul
W o lf f , “O n T o le r a n c e a n d F r e e d o m ,” in Dissent, 14, n o . 1 (J a n .-F e b .
19G 7): 9 5 - 9 7 ; D a v id S p itz , "A R e j o in d e r to R o b e rt P au l W o lf f ,” ib id .,
9 7 - 9 8 ; (3 ) P h ilip G r e e n , “ A g a in : T o le r a n c e , D e m o c r a c y , P lu r a lism , 1.
C o m m e n t P h ilip G r e e n ,” in Dissent, 14, n o . 3 (M a y -J u n e 19G7): 3 0 8 -
3 7 1 ; D a v id S p itz , "2. A R e j o in d e r to P h ilip G r e e n ,” ib id ., 3 7 1 - 3 7 2 ;
P h ilip G r e e n , "3. P h ilip G r e e n A n s w e r s D a v id S p itz," ib id , 3 7 2 - 3 7 3 .
39. T rou sson , Voyages mix pays de nolle part, 17 8 .
4 0 . R u y e r , L ’Utopie et les atopies, 9 . O n th e c o n tr a d ic tio n in R u y e r ’s
w o r k r e g a r d in g h is d is t in c t io n b e t w e e n th e “u to p ia n m o d e " a n d th e
“u t o p ia n g e n r e ,” c f ., C io r a n e s c u , L'Avenir da passe, 2 6 4 - 2 6 7 .
41. I b id ., 1 8 7 .
42. RR, 18G.
4 3 . C f ., RR, 3 2 , 3 9 4 ; EC, 2 2 5 ; ODM, 3 9 - 4 0 ; SCR, 9 8 , 1 1 2 , 1 22.
4 4 . F r e u n d , " A n a r c h ie fttr h t zu D ik ta tu r ,” 2 1 - 2 2 . C f., id ., "La P h ilo
Revue d'Allemagne, 1 (A p r il-
s o p h i c ‘p o lit ic is t c ’ tie H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," in
J u n e 1 9 6 9 ): 1 9 9 , 2 0 7 , a n d Utopie et violence (P aris: E d itio n s M arcel
R iv id te e t C ie ., 1 9 7 8 ), 1 1 6 .
4 5 . J .-M . B e n o is t , " M a r c u s e , u n A u fk liir e r c o n t r e le s lu m ie r e s ,” in
Marx est mart (P a ris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 7 0 ) 1 0 9 , 1 1 3 -1 2 7 .
4G. A . B ir o u , “S ig n if ic a t io n d u d e v e l o p p e m e n t d e s id e o lo g ie s ," Eco-
logie et humanisme, n o . 194 (J u ly -A u g . 1 9 7 0 ): 9 - 1 0 .
4 7 . J e a n J a c q u e s R o u sse a u ," L e ttr e s e c r ite s d e la m o n ta g n e ," in Oeuvres
completes, 3 : 8 1 0 ; c it e d b y B . lla c z k o , “ L u m ie r e s et U t o p i e ,” 3 5 8 - 3 5 9 ,
w ith r e f e r e n c e to J . F a b r e , “ R c a lite et U t o p i e d a n s la p e n s e e p o litiq u e
d e J . - J . R o u s s e a u ," Annates J.-J. Rousseau, 3 5 ( 1 9 5 9 - 1 9 6 2 ) : 1 8 1 -2 1 6 .
4 8 . H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , “S o m m e s - n o u s cleja d e s h o m in e s ? ” Partisans,
n o . 2 8 (A p r . 1 9 6 6 ): 2 6 .
49. J ea n J a cq u es R ou sseau , The Social Contract, b k. 1, c h a p . 6 . T h is
a n d s u b s e q u e n t r e f e r e n c e s a r e ta k e n fr o m J e a n J a c q u e s R o u s s e a u , The
Social Contract: An Eighteenth-Century Translation Completely Revised, Edited,
with an Introduction, e d . C h a r le s F r a n k e l ( N e w Y o rk : H a f n e r P u b lis h in g
C o ., 1 9 4 7 ).
5 0 . ODM, 2 5 0 - 2 5 1 .
5 1 . R o u s s e a u , 7'he Social Contract, b k . 2 , c h a p . 7.
5 2 . EL, 8 0 . S e e a ls o ODM, 2 2 3 .
5 3 . R R , 3 9 4 . R o u s s e a u e x p r e s s e d th is id e a in The Social Contract, bk.
1, c h a p . 7.
126 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
5 4 . ODM, 2 23.
5 5 . R o u s s e a u , Discours
sur I'origine et les fondements de I’intgalile panni
les homines, in Oeuvres completes, 3 : 1 3 3 .
5 6 . I b id ., 132.
5 7 . “A N o t e o n D ia le c tic ," H R, x.
5 8 . R o u s s e a u , The Social Contract, b k. 1, in tr o .
5 9 . RR, x.
60. R o u ssea u , The Social Contract, b k. 2 , c h a p . 7. C f. M ic h e le A n s a r t-
D o u r le n , “ L ’U t o p i e p o lit iq u e d e R o u s s e a u e t le j a c o b in is m e ,” in Le
Discours utopique, p a p e r s d e liv e r e d at a c o llo q u iu m , C e r is y -la -S a lle , 2 3
J u ly -1 A u g . 1 9 7 5 (P a ris: U n io n g e n e r a le d ’e d ilio n s , 1 9 7 8 ), 2 7 1 - 2 7 9 .
6 1 . “C a n C o m m u n is m B e L ib e r a l? ” 8 6 1 .
6 2 . EC, 1 5 8 .
6 3 . W ilh e lm E. M u h lm a n n , Messianismes rh>olutionnaires du tiers monde,
tr a n s la te d b y J e a n B a u d r illa r d (P a ris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 6 8 ), 3 0 1 . O r ig i
n a lly p u b lis h e d a s Cliiliasmus and Nativismus (B e r lin : D ie tr ic h R e im e r ,
1 9 6 1 ).
6 4 . J u lie n F r e u n d , “ B r e f E ssai s u r le s s c ie n c e s h u m a in e s ,” Revue de
Tenseignement pliilosopliique, n o . 6 (1 9 6 0 ) : 5 5 .
6 5 . M y r d a l, Das Politische Element in der nationalbkonomischen Dohtrin-
bildung, 1 9 3 2 , 1 77; c ite d in M a r c u s e , NE, 13, 2 7 1 n . 18.
6 6 . “T h e o r y a n d P o litic s ,” 1 40.
6 7 . “La S o c ie tc d e P o p u le n c e e n p r o c e s ,” Le Monde, 11 M ay 1 9 6 8 ,
111.
68. T rou sson , Voyages aux pays de nolle part, 1 80.
69. H e r b e r t M a rc u se, “T h o u g h ts o n th e D e fe n s e o f G r a cch u s
B a b e u f," in The Defense of Gracchus Ilabeuf, e d . a n d tr a n s. J o h n A n t h o n y
S c o tt (B o s to n : U n iv e r s it y o f M a s s a c h u s e t t s P re ss, 1 9 6 7 ), 1 0 3 .
7 0 . I b id ., 9 8 - 9 9 .
7 1 . I b id ., 9 6 , c itin g G r a c c h u s B a b e u f , "La D e f e n s e d e G r a c c h u s
B a b e u f d e v a n t la H a u te C o u r d u V e n d o m e ."
7 2 . I b id ., 9 8 .
7 3 . “D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a s n ’t a F u tu r e ," 3 1 .
7 4 . I b id ., 10 4 .
7 5 . I b id ., 1 0 4 , a n d M a u r ic e C r a n s to n , “ H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” in The
New Left, e d . M a u r ic e C r a n s to n ( L o n d o n : B o d le y H e a d , 1 9 7 0 ), 8 6 .
7 6 . M a r c u s e , “T h o u g h t s o n th e D e f e n s e o f G r a c c h u s B a b e u f ,” 9 8 .
7 7 . “D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a s n ’t a F u t u r e ,” 10 3 .
7 8 . F r e u n d , " A n a r c h ie f iir h t zu D ik la tu r ," 2 2 .
7 9 . “D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a s n ’t a F u t u r e ,” 10 1 .
8 0 . M a r c u s e , “T h o u g h t s o n th e D e f e n s e o f G r a c c h u s B a b e u f," 104.
8 1 . M a r c u s e , “ D is c u s s io n o n I n d u s tr ia liz a tio n a n d C a p ita lis m ,” in
Max Weber and the Sociology Today, e d . O t t o S ta m m e r ( O x f o r d , 1 9 7 1 ),
1 8 5 . First G e r m a n e d it io n 1 9 6 4 . S e e a ls o R a y m o n d A r o n , Les Rapes de
la pensee sociologique (P a ris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 6 7 ), 5661T.
Notes 127
8 2 . " D ie G e s e lls c h a f t a ls K u n t s w e r k ,” Neues Forum, 14, n o s . 1 6 7 -1 6 8
( N o v .- D e c . 1 9 6 7 ): 8 6 6 .
Philosophische Schriften (B a s e l, 1 9 4 6 ), 7 9 , c ite d
8 3 . F r ie d r ic h S c h ille r ,
b y F r e d e r ic J a m e s o n , “ M a r c u s e a n d S c h ille r ," in Monism and Form,
Fwenlieth-Centuiy Dialectical Theories of Literature (P r in c e to n : P r in c e to n
U n iv e r s it y P r e ss , 1 9 7 1 ), 8 8 .
81. NE, 1 1 7 .
8 5 . EL, 2 6 .
8 6 . M o r to n S c h o o lm a n , " M a r c u se 's A e s th e tic s a n d th e D is p la c e m e n t
Telos, 3 , tio . 2: 7 9 . A s w e n o w k n o w , M a r c u se
o f C r itic a l T h e o r y , ” in
w e n t o n to p u b lis h The Aesthetic Dimension in 1 9 7 7 .
8 7 . J a m e s o n , " M a r c u s e a n d S c h ille r ,” 9 0 .
Fourier, aujourd'hui (P aris: D e n o e l, 1 9 6 6 ), 161.
8 8 . E m ile L e h o u c k ,
8 9 . R u y e r , L'Utopie et les utopics, 2 1 8 .
9 0 . I b id ., 2 2 2 .
91. L e h o u c k , Fourier, aujourd'hui, 164.
92. I b id ., 11.
93. C ite d b y T r o u s s o n , Voyages aux pays de nolle part, 190.
94. J e a n L a c r o ix , Le Desire! les desirs, (P a ris: P U F , 1 9 7 5 ), 6 6 . L a cro ix 's
w o r k in c lu d e s “ F o u r ie r e t le f lu x d u d e s ir ," 6 6 - 7 6 , a n d v a r io u s r e f e r
e n c e s to M a r c u s e , 9 5 - 1 0 1 . S e e a ls o a r e v ie w by U m b e r to C a m p a g n o lo ,
Comprendre, n o s . 4 1 - 4 2 ( 1 9 7 5 - 7 6 ) : 2 6 0 - 2 6 2 .
9 5 . J e a n - P a u l T h o m a s , Liberation instinctuelle liberation politique,
Contribution fourieriste a Marcuse (P a ris: L e S y c o m o r e , 1 9 8 0 ). S e e a lso
a r e v ie w b y J e a n -M ic h e l B e s n ie r , " D e M a r c u s e a F o u r ie r ," Esprit, n o .
5 2 ( A p r . 1 9 8 1 ): 1 3 9 - 1 4 1 .
9 6 . M a r c u s e , “S o m m e s - n o u s d e ja d e s h o m in e s ? ” 2 6 .
97. EC, 1 8 7 .
9 8 . EC, 2 1 7 .
9 9 . F r a n c is H e a r n , " T o w a r d a C r itic a l T h e o r y o f P la y ,” Telos, 9 , n o .
4 ( W in t e r 1 9 7 6 -7 7 ): 1 4 5 - 1 6 0 .
100. FL, 6 8 .
101. FL, 6 3 . S e e a ls o EL, 4 9 .
1 0 2 . EL, 2 2 .
1 0 3 . B e s n ie r , “ D e M a r c u s e ft F o u r ie r ," 141.
1 0 4 . H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , " L ib e r a tio n fr o m t h e A f f lu e n t S o c ie ty ,” in The
Dialectics of Liberation, e tl. D a v id C o o p e r ( H a r m o n d s w o r t h : P e n g u in
B o o k s, 1 9 6 8 ), 1 7 5 -1 9 2 .
1 0 5 . I b id ., 1 7 7 ; ita lic s m in e .
1 0 6 . I b id ., 1 8 4 .
1 0 7 . I b id ., 1 7 7 .
1 0 8 . I b id ., 1 8 5 .
109. H a rry B u rro w s A c to n , The Illusion of an Epoch (London, 1955),
2 3 3 -2 3 6 .
1 10. M a r x - E n g e ls , “T h e G e r m a n I d e o lo g y ,” in Collected Works, 5 : 4 7 .
128 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
11 1 . “S o c ia list H u m a n is m ,” in Socialist Humanism, e d . E rich F r o m m
(N e w Y o r k : D o u b le d a y , 1 9 6 5 ), 11 2 .
1 12. M a r c u s e . “S o m m e s - n o u s d e ja d e s h o m m e s ? ” 2 5 - 2 6 .
I IS . “T h e R e a lm o f F r e e d o m a n d th e R e a lm o f N e c e s s it y , A R e c o n
Praxis, 5 , n o s . 1-2 (1 9 6 9 ): 2 2 .
s id e r a t io n ,”
114. S e e New Left Review, 5 6 (1 9 6 9 ): 2 7 - 3 4
115. M a r c u se , as c ite d by G e r a r d B e r g e r o n , “Q u i est H e r b e r t M a rc u se? ”
Action pcdagogiquc, n o s . 1 2 -1 3 (1 9 6 8 ): 9 1 - 9 2 ; ita lics m in e .
1 16. EL, 8 9 .
1 17. Ib id .
1 18. CRR, 4 7 .
1 19. E. M ., “C o p s C le a r K an t," San Francisco Good Times, 12 F eb . 1 9 7 1 ,
18.
1 2 0 . Ib id .
1 21. P e r r o u x , Francois Perroux interroge Herbert Marcuse, 1 0 0 .
122. M m e . N . B ., “ M . Francois P e r r o u x in tr o d u it M a r c u s e a u C o lle g e
d e F r a n c e ,” 11.
1 23. EL, 8 9 .
Encyclopaedia universalis ( 1 9 6 8 ) ,
1 2 4 . H e n r i A r v o n , “ B a k o u n in e ,"
2 : 1 0 3 2 . S e e a ls o id ., Michel Bakounine on la vie contre la science (P aris:
S e g h e r s , 1 9 6 6 ), 5 0 .
125. SM, 1 28.
126. SM, 1 2 5 .
127. RR, x .
1 2 8 . RR, x iv .
1 2 9 . A r t h u r M itc h e ll, The Major Works of Herbert Marcuse, A Critical
Commentary ( N e w Y o r k : S im o n &: S c h u s t e r , 1 9 7 5 ), 9 8 - 1 0 0 , a n d G il
G r e e n , The New Radicalism: Anarchist or Marxist? ( N e w Y o rk : I n t e r
n a tio n a l P u b lis h e r s , 1 9 7 1 ), 1 1 2 -1 1 4 .
130. ODM, 2 5 6 .
131. ODM, 5 3 .
1 3 2 . M ik h a il B a k u n in , “ E crit c o n t r e M arx," in Socialisme autoritaire ou
liberlaire, M ik h a il B a k u n in a n d K arl M a r x (P a ris: U n io n g e n e r a t e d ’e d i-
tio n s , 1 9 7 5 ), 2 : 1 9 .
1 3 3 . F r ie d r ic h E n g e ls , “ P r e fa c e a ‘L a G u e r r e d e s p a y s a n s e n A lle -
m a g n e ,' " in Oeuvres chords, F r ie d r ic h E n g e ls a n d K arl M a r x (M o sc o w :
E d itio n s d u p r o g r e s , 1 9 7 5 ), 2 4 8 .
1 3 4 . “ D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a s n ’t a F u t u r e ,” 104.
13 5 . A n d r e R e s z le r , L'Esthetique anarchiste (P a ris: P U F , 1 9 7 3 ), 2 9 , 2 9 -
40.
136. I b id ., 3 1 , c itin g M ik h a il B a k u n in , Confession.
13 7 . “ M o r a le e l p o litiq u e d a n s la s o c ie t e d ’a b o n d a n c e ,” FU, 8 6 .
138. O liv ie r R e b o u l, Langage et ideologic (P a ris: P U F , 1 9 8 0 ), 3 3 , c itin g
N . M a n d e ls ta m , Contre tout espoir.
Notes 129
1 3 9 . J u le s M o n n e r o t , Sociologie de la revolution (P aris: F a y a r a d , 1 9 6 9 ),
9.
1 4 0 . J a c q u e s E llu l, De la Revolution aux revoltes, 3 2 3 ; s e e a ls o “ La R e v o
lu t io n q u i n e s ig n if ie l ie n ,” 3 2 3 - 3 2 8 .
141. R aym on d A ro n , La Revolution introuvable.
1 4 2 . F r a n c o is C h a t e le t , G ille s L a p o u g e , a n d O liv ie r R e v a u lt d ’A l-
lo n n e s , La Revolution sans mod'ele (P a r is-L a H a y e : N lo u to n , 1 9 7 4 ), 3 5 .
1 4 3 . I b id ., 1 3 1 .
1 4 4 . " T h e o r y a n d P o litics," 1 5 0 - 1 5 2 .
1 4 5 . M a r c u s e , " P r o to s o c ia lis m a n d L a te C a p ita lis m ,” 3 6 - 3 7 .
1 4 6 . I b id ., 2 5 - 2 6 ; ita lic s m in e .
1 4 7 . D o n a ld C . L e e , " T h e C o n c e p t o f ‘N e c e s s it y ’: M a rx a n d M a r c u s e ,”
Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 6 (W in te r 1 9 7 5 ): 4 7 - 5 3 .
1 4 8 . M a x im ile n R u b e l, " U t o p ie et r e v o lu t io n ,” in Marx critique du
marxistne (P a ris: P a y o t, 1 9 7 4 ), 2 9 8 . C f., " U to p ia a n d R e v o lu t io n ,” in
Socialist Humanism, An International Symposium, 2 d e d ., e d . E rich F r o m m
( N e w Y o r k : D o u b le d a y , 1 9 6 6 ), 2 1 1 - 2 1 9 . T h e s e n t e n c e q u o te d d o e s
n o t a p p e a r in t h e E n g lis h v e r s io n .
1 4 9 . " E th ic s a n d R e v o lu tio n ," in Ethics and Society: Original Essays on
Contemporary Moral Problems, e d . R ic h a r d T . D e G e o r g e ( N e w Y ork :
D o u b le d a y , 1 9 6 6 ), 1 3 3 - 1 4 7 .
1 5 0 . " T h e o r y a n d P o litic s ,” 1 26.
SCP, 2 9 .
1 5 1 . “T h e F o u n d a t io n o f H is to r ic a l M a te r ia lism ,"
1 5 2 . J . P. G u in le , r e v ie w o f RR in Archives de philosophic du droit, 15
(1 9 7 0 ): 4 4 6 .
1 5 3 . “T h e O b s o le s c e n c e o f M a r x is m ,” in Marx and the Western World,
e d . N ic h o la s L o b k o w ic z ( N o t r e D a m e , In d .: U n iv e r s ity o f N o tr e D a m e
P r e ss, 1 9 6 7 ), 4 1 3 . M a r c u s e c o m p la in e d a b o u t th e o m is s io n o f th e q u e s
tio n m a r k in th is title .
1 5 4 . “ L ib e r a tio n f r o m t h e A f f lu e n t S o c ie t y ,” I 7 7 f f .
1 5 5 . " E th ic s a n d R e v o lu t io n ,” 1 3 4 - 1 3 5 .
1 5 6 . " R e e x a m e n d u c o n c e p t d e r e v o lu tio n ," Diogene, n o . 6 4 (O c t.-D e c .
1 9 6 8 ): 2 3 . C f ., “ R e e x a m in a t io n o f t h e C o n c e p t o f R e v o lu tio n ," in Marx
and Contemporary Scientific Tbought!Marx et la pensee scientifique content-
poraine, p a p e r s p r e s e n t e d at a UNESCO s y m p o s iu m o n “T h e R o le o f
K arl M a r x in t h e D e v e lo p m e n t o f C o n t e m p o r a r y S c ie n tific T h e o r y ,"
8 - 1 0 M a y 1 9 6 8 (P a r is-L a H a y e : N lo u to n , 1 9 6 8 ), 4 7 6 - 4 8 2 .
1 5 7 . A n t o n y M a r k R u p r e c h t , “M a r x a n d M a r c u se : a C o m p a r a tiv e
A n a ly sis o f th e ir R e v o lu tio n a r y T h e o r ie s ," Dialogue, Journal of Phi Sigma
Tau, 17, n o s . 2 - 3 ( A p r il 1 9 7 5 ): 5 1 - 5 6 .
1 5 8 . M a r x - E n g e ls , " T h e G e r m a n I d e o lo g y ," 5 : 5 2 - 5 3 .
1 5 9 . K arl M a r x , 1 8 5 9 p r e f a c e to “A C o n t r ib u tio n to th e C r itiq u e o f
P o litic a l E c o n o m y ," in The Marx-Engels Reader," R o b e r t C . I u c k e r , e d .
(N e w Y ork: W . W . N o r to n Sc C o . I n c ., 1 9 7 2 ), 5 .
130 Herbert Marcuse's iftopia
1 60. R R , 3 1 8 , a n d H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , " S o c ia lism in t h e D e v e lo p e d
C o u n t r ie s ,” International Socialist Journal, 2 , n o . 8 (1 9 6 5 ): 1 3 9 -1 5 2 ; c f ..
139.
1 61. M a r x , 1 8 5 9 p r e f a c e , 5 ; M a r x -E n g e ls , “T h e G e r m a n I d e o lo g y ,”
5 :5 4 .
1 62. M a r x -E n g e ls , “T h e H o ly F a m ily ,” in Collected Works, 4 : 3 6 - 3 7 .
163. EL, 16, 5 3 ; FL, 9 8 .
1 6 4 . " T h e o r ie et p r a t iq u e ,” in AC, 8 8 . T h is e s s a y o r ig in a lly a p p e a r e d
as “T h e o r i e u n d P r a x is ,” in Zeit-Messungen (F r a n k fu r t a m M ain :
S u h r k a m p V e r la g , 1 9 7 5 ), 2 1 - 3 6 .
165. M a r x -E n g e ls , “T h e H o ly F a m ily ,” 4 : 3 6 - 3 7 .
166. J u lie n F r e u n d , L'Essence du politique (P a ris; S ir e y s, 1 9 6 5 ), 5 7 6 -
577.
1 6 7 . O D M , 189.
1 6 8 . “T h e R e ific a tio n o f th e P r o le ta r ia t,” Canadian Journal of Political
and Social Theory, 3 , n o . I (W in te r 1 9 7 9 ): 2 0 - 2 3 .
E m p ir ic a l s t u d ie s h e a r o u t th e M a r c u sia n th e o r y o f t h e r e ific a tio n
o f t h e p r o le ta r ia t, f o r e x a m p le : B e n n e tt B e r g e r , The Working-Class
Suburb (B e r k e le y : U n iv e r s ity o f C a lifo r n ia P re ss, 1 9 6 0 ); W illia m
G o m b e r g a n d A r th u r S h o sia k , e d s ., lllue-Collar World (E n g le w o o d C liffs:
P r e n tic e -H a ll I n c ., 1 9 6 4 ); F r e d e r ic k C . K le in , " R isin g P ay L ifts M o r e
B lu e -C o lla r M e n in t o a N e w A f f lu e n t C la s s,” W all Street Journal, 5 A p r .
1 9 6 5 , 1 a n d 12; D a n ie l S e lig m a n , " T h e N e w M a sse s,” in America as a
Mass Society, e d . P h ilip O ls e n ( N e w Y o rk : F r e e P re ss, 1 9 6 3 ), 2 4 4 - 2 5 6 .
T h e r e is at le a st o n e e x c e p t i o n , h o w e v e r . J o h n C . L e g g e tt, fo r
e x a m p le , d is a g r e e s w ith th e th e o r y th a t t h e w o r k e r s lack r e v o lu tio n a r y
p o te n tia l; s e e L e g g e t t , Class, Race and Labor: Working Class Consciousness
in Detroit (F a ir la w n : O x f o r d U n iv e r s ity P r e ss, 1 9 6 8 ).
1 6 9 . C f., R R , 2 7 9 .
1 7 0 . R ic h a r d K in g , " H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," in The Party of Eros, Radical
Social Thought and the Realm of Freedom (C h a p e l H ill: U n iv e r sity o f N o r th
C a r o lin a P r e ss , 1 9 7 2 ), 1 2 6 .
1 7 1 . M a r c u s e , “P r o to s o c ia lis m a n d L a te C a p ita lis m ," 3 8 . O n c u ltu r a l
r e v o lu tio n , s e e 3 3 - 3 4 .
1 7 2 . J e a n - P a u l S a r tr e , " L es B a s tille s d e R a y m o n d A r o n ," d is c u s s io n
r e p o r t e d b y S e r g e L a fa u r ie , Le N ouvel Obsen-atrur, n o . 1 8 8 ( 1 9 - 2 5 J u n e
1 9 6 8 ); 2 7 .
1 7 3 . EL, 7 9 ; ita lics m in e .
1 7 4 . H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , “V a r ie tie s o f H u m a n is m ,” Center M agazine, 1
(J u ly 1 9 6 8 ): 14.
17 5 . I d ., “ R e v o lu tio n a r y S u b je c t a n d S e lf - G o v e r n m e n t ," Praxis 5 , n o s .
1-2 (1 9 6 9 ): 3 2 6 .
17 6 . I b id ., 3 2 6 .
1 7 7 . I b id ., 3 2 7 .
1 7 8 . “T h e O b s o le s c e n c e o f M a r x ism ," 4 0 9 - 4 17.
Notes 131
1 7 9 . I b id ., 4 1 0 .
1 8 0 . I b id ., 4 1 7 .
1 8 1 . “S o c ia lis m in th e D e v e lo p e d C o u n tr ie s ," 151.
1 8 2 . M a r x - E n g e ls , “G e r m a n I d e o lo g y ," 5 : 5 8 .
1 8 8 . RR, 8 1 9 .
1 8 4 . O n t h e id e a o f r e v o lu t io n a n d j u s t if ic a t io n , s e e K e ith C a m p b e ll,
" M a r c u s e o n t h e J u s t if ic a t io n o f R e v o lu tio n ," Politics (A u s tr a la sia ), 4 ,
n o . 2 ( N o v . 1 9 6 9 ): 1 6 1 - 1 6 7 ; K ai N ie ls e n , “O n th e C h o ic e B e tw e e n
R e f o r m a n d R e v o lu t io n ,” Inquiry, 14. n o . 3 ( A u t u m n 1 9 7 1 ), 2 7 1 - 2 9 5 ,
r e p r in t e d in V ir g in ia M e ld , K ai N ie ls e n a n d C h a r le s P a r s o n s , Philos
ophy and Political Action ( N e w Y o r k : O x f o r d U n iv e r s ity P re ss, 1 9 7 2 ),
1 7 -5 1 . J u lie n F r e u n d , “A s p e c ts p o le m o lo g iq u e s d e la v io le n c e ,” Actions
et recherches sociales, 2 - 3 ( S e p t . 1 9 8 1 ): 3 6 - 5 1 , a n d “L 'E x e m p le d e
M a r c u s e ," 4 0 - 4 2 ,
1 8 5 . “ R e e x a m e n d u c o n c e p t d e r e v o lu tio n ," 3 1 .
1 8 6 . FL, 9 0 .
1 8 7 . L o u is W iz n itz e r " I n te r v ie w e x c lu s iv e d ’U e r b e r t M a r c u se , tluH>*
r ic ie n r e v o lu t io n n a ir e fo r t d o u x , ” La Presse, 4 J a n . 1 9 6 9 , 7 . T h is a rtic le
a p p e a r e d u n d e r t h e title " M a r c u s e , le L e n in e d e la N o u v e lle G a u c h e ,”
in L ’Amerique en crise (M o n tr e a l: L es E d itio n s La P r e ss e , 1 9 7 2 ), 3 5 7 -
3 6 6 ; c f ., 3 6 2 .
1 8 8 . “ E th ic s a n d R e v o lu tio n ," 1 4 6 - 1 4 7 .
1 8 9 . " D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a sn 't a F u tu r e ," 1 04.
1 9 0 . “C o p s C le a r K an t," 18.
191. FL, 8 1 , a n d HU, 10 ( p r e f a c e to th e F r e n c h e d it io n o f ODM).
1 9 2 . FU, 1 0 1 .
1 9 3 . EC, 1 5 9 , c ite d b y J a m e s o n , Marxism and Form, 111.
1 9 4 . " T h e o r ie et p r a t iq u e ,” A C , 7 5 - 7 6 .
1 9 5 . H o l m a n d R a u le t, “ L ’E c o le d e F r a n c fo r t e n F r a n ce ," Esprit, 141.
1 9 6 . I b id ., 1 4 2 .
1 9 7 . J a y , " T h e D ia le c tic a l I m a g in a tio n ," 4 2 - 4 3 .
1 9 8 . W a lte r L a q u e u r , Weimar, Une Histoire cullurelle de I'Allemagne des
annees 20 (P a ris: L a f f o n t , ( 1 9 7 4 ) 1 9 7 8 ).
1 9 9 . A lf r e d K a n to r o w ic z , "L a F in d e I’U t o p i e ,” Etudes (B r u s s e ls ), n o .
4 (1 9 6 3 ): 2.
Sozialreform oder Revolution (L e ip z ig , 1 8 9 9 ), c f.,
2 0 0 . R o sa L u x e m b u r g ,
Social Reform or Revolution ( N e w Y o r k , 1 9 3 7 ).
201. I b id ., p r e f a c e .
2 0 2 . FL, 1 0 2 .
2 0 3 . L u x e m b u r g , Sozialreform, p r e f a c e .
2 0 4 . T h e d e b a t e o n " so c ia lism o r b a r b a r ism ," th e o r ig in o f w h ic h 1
h a v e a t t e m p t e d to tr a c e , s h o u ld n o t b e c o n f u s e d w ith th e n a m e o f th e
jo u r n a l f o u n d e d in 1 9 4 9 by a g r o u p o f f o r m e r T r o tsk y ists le d by C la u d e
L e fo r t a n d P au l C a r d a n , w h ic h c e a s e d p u b lic a tio n in 1 9 6 5 , as d e sc r ib e d
in The Unknown Dimension, European Marxism Since Lenin, e d s . D ick
132 Herbert Marcuse’s Utopia
H o w a r d a n d Karl F.. K lare ( N e w Y o rk a n d L o n d o n : B asic B o o k s, 19 7 2 ),
6 6 , 7 1 . N e it h e r s h o u ld it b e c o n f u s e d w ith th e title g iv e n b y C o r n e liu s
C a sto r ia d is , a m e m b e r o f th is g r o u p , to h is s ix - v o lu m e w o r k w h ic h
a p p e a r e d in t h e 1 0 /1 8 s e r ie s in F r a n c e (n o s . 7 5 1 , 8 0 6 , 8 2 5 , 8 5 7 , 1 3 0 3 ,
a n d 1 3 0 4 ).
2 0 5 . “ F ile F a ilu r e o f th e N e w L e f t ,” N ew German Critique, 6 , n o . 3 ( f a l l
1 9 7 9 ): 11.
2 0 6 . “ R e e x a m e n d u c o n c e p t d e r e v o lu t io n ,” 3 1 .
2 0 7 . “ La L ib e r te e t le s im p e r a tifs d e I’H is t o ir e ,” in K. M ’B a y e e t a l.,
La Liberte et I'ordre social (N e u c h a t e l: E d itio n s d e la B a c o n n ie r e , 1 9 6 9 ),
135. T h is p a p e r a n d th e s u b s e q u e n t d is c u s s io n w e r e fir st p u b lis h e d
in F r e n c h , a lt h o u g h th e p a p e r w a s o r ig in a lly g iv e n in E n g lis h . T h e
d is c u s s io n w a s n o t in c lu d e d in th e E n g lish v e r s io n s u b s e q u e n tly
p u b lis h e d as “F r e e d o m a n d t h e H isto r ic a l I m p e r a t iv e ,” in Studies in
Critical Philosophy (B o s to n : B e a c o n , 1 9 7 3 ), 2 1 1 - 2 2 3 , c f., 2 1 6 .
2 0 8 . M ich a el L o e w y , “L a S ig n ific a tio n m e t h o d o lo g iq u e d u m o t d ’o r d r e
‘s o c ia lis m e o u b a r b a r ie ,’ " in Dialectique et revolution, Essais de sociologie
et d'histoire du marxisme (P aris: A n t h r o p o s , 1 9 7 3 ), 1 1 3 -1 2 9 .
2 0 9 . I b id ., 1 1 3 , c itin g G . L u k a c s, Histoire el conscience de classe (P aris:
E d itio n s d e m in u it), 6 1 .
2 1 0 . R osa L u x e m b u r g , “T h e C r isis in G e r m a n S o c ia l D e m o c r a c y ( T h e
J u n iu s P a m p h le t: Part O n e ) ,” in Selected Political Writings o f Rosa Luxem
burg , e d . D ick H o w a r d ( N e w Y o r k a n d L o n d o n : M o n th ly R e v ie w P r e ss,
1 9 7 1 ), 3 3 4 .
2 1 1 . “4 'h e p r o d u c t iv e fo r c e s c r e a t e d b y th e m o d e r n c a p ita lis t m o d e
o f p r o d u c t io n a n d a ls o th e s y s te m o f d is tr ib u tio n o f g o o d s e s ta b lis h e d
by it h a v e c o m e in to b u r n in g c o n t r a d ic t io n w ith th a t m o d e o f p r o d u c
tio n its e lf, a n d in fa ct to s u c h a d e g r e e th a t, i f th e w h o le o f m o d e r n
s o c ie ty is n o t to p e r is h , a r e v o lu tio n o f th e m o d e o f p r o d u c t io n a n d
d is tr ib u tio n m u st ta k e p la c e .” F r ie d r ic h E n g e ls , H err Eugen D uhring’s
Revolution in Science (Anti-Duhring) ( N e w Y o rk : I n te r n a tio n a l P u b lis h
e r s , ( 1 9 3 9 ] 1 9 6 6 ), 1 7 4 . It is in th is p a s s a g e th a t th e id e a o f so c ia lis m
as an a lte r n a tiv e c h o ic e in a m a jo r h is to r ic a l d ile m m a fir st a p p e a r e d .
2 1 2 . L o e w y , Dialectique et revolution" 1 20.
2 1 3 . “T h e F a ilu r e o f th e N e w L e f t ,” 1 1.
2 1 4 . “T h e o r y e t p r a t iq u e ,” A C , 8 8 - 8 9 .
2 1 5 . E d w a r d S h ils , “Ideology and Utopia by K arl M a n n h e im ,” Daedalus,
1 0 3 , n o . 1 (W in te r 1 9 7 3 ): 8 3 - 8 9 .
2 1 6 . P a lm ie r , Herbert Marcuse et la Nouvelle Gauche, 3 9 7 .
2 17 . R a y m o n d R u y e r , Les Nuisances ideologiques (P a ris: C a lm a n n -L e v v ,
1 9 7 2 ), 2 9 8 .
2 1 8 . I d ., L ’Utopie el les utopies, 5 4 .
2 1 9 . J o s e p h G a b e l, “M a n n h e im e t le m a r x is m e h o n g r o is ,” in Ideologies
(P aris: A n t h r o p o s , 1 9 7 4 ), 2 7 8 . T h is e s s a y a ls o a p p e a r e d in L ’Homme
et la sociele, n o . 1 1 (J a n .-F e b .-M a r . 1 9 6 9 ): 1 2 7 - 1 4 5 . O n M a n n h e im a n d
Notes 133
M a r x is m , s e e a ls o id ., "La O i s e d u m a r x is m e et la p s y c h o lo g ic ,” Argu
ments, 4 , n o . 18 ( I 9 6 0 ) .
2 2 0 . " D eb a ts G o ld m a n n -M a r c u s e (19G 2)," in Coldmann, S am i N’air a n d
M ic h a e l L o c w y (P a ris: S e g h e r s , 1 9 7 3 ), 15 4 . O n G o ld m a n n -M a r c u s e ,
s e e L u c ie n G o ld m a n n , “ L a P e n s e e d e H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," La Nef, n o .
3 6 ( 1 9 6 9 ) : 3 5 - 5 7 ; “ A R e p ly to L u c ie n G o ld m a n n ," Partisan Review, 3 8 ,
n o . 4 ( 1 9 7 1 - 1 9 7 2 ) : 3 9 7 - 4 0 0 ; “S o m e G e n e r a l R e m a r k s o n L u c ie n G o ld
m a n n ,” Revue de Vhistitut de sociologie de VUniversite tibre de Bruxelles, 3-
4 (1 9 7 3 ): 5 4 3 -5 4 4 .
221. J o s e p h G a b e l, “ L 'ln t e llig e n t s ia s a n s a tta c h e s ( 1 9 6 5 ) ,” in Ideologies,
294.
222. I b id ., 3 0 0 .
2 2 3 . “ D e b a ts G o ld m a n n - M a r c u s e ," 15 4 .
224. ODM, 1 8 9 .
2 2 5 . K arl M a n n h e im , Ideology and Utopia, An Introduction to the Sociology
of Knowledge, tr a n s la te d b y L o u is W ir th a n d E d w a r d S h ils ( N e w Y ork:
H a r c o u r t , B r a c e a n d W o r ld , I n c ., 1 9 3 6 ), 2 5 0 .
2 2 6 . G e r a r d R a u lc t, " E n c e r d e m e n t t e c lm o c r a iiq u e e t d £ p a s s e m e n t
Utopie-Marx-
p r a t iq u e , L ’U t o p i e c o n c r e t e c o n ii n e t h e o r ie c r it iq u e ,” in
isme selon Ernst Bloch, Un systeme de I'inconstructible, Hommages a Ernst
Bloch pour son 9 (f anniversaire publics sous la direction de Gerard Runlet
(P a ris: P a y o t, 1 9 7 6 ), 2 9 1 - 3 0 8 , c f ., 3 0 7 n . 4 9 .
2 2 7 . A r m a n d C u v illie r , “A v a n t-p r o p o s ," in K arl M a n n h e im , Ideologic
et utopie (P a ris: M a r c e l R iv ie r e , 1 9 5 6 ), 7.
2 2 8 . J a y , The Dialectical Imagination, 6 3 .
2 2 9 . P a u l B r e in e s , “ P r a x is a n d its T h e o r is t s : T h e Im p a c t o f L u k d cs
a n d K o r s c h in t h e 1 9 2 0 ’s," Telus, n o . 11 (S p r in g 1 9 7 2 ): 6 7 - 1 0 3 , c f., 9 5 .
2 3 0 . “Z u r W a h r h e ils p r o b le m a t ik d e r s o z io lo g is c h e n M e th o d e ," in Die
Gesellschaft, Internationale Reimefur Soiialismus undPoliiik, 6 , part 2 (1 9 2 9 ):
3 5 6 -3 6 9 .
2 3 1 . M a r tin J a y , " T h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l's C r itiq u e o f K arl M a n n h e im
a n d t h e S o c io lo g y o f K n o w le d g e , Telos, 7 , n o . 2 ( S u m m e r 1 9 7 4 ): 7 9 .
J a y e x p la i n e d th a t t h e o t h e r m e m b e r s o f th e s c h o o l m o v e d a w a y fr o m
M a n n h e im a s tim e w e n t o n .
232. Jay, The Dialectical Imagination, 6 3 .
2 3 3 . K arl M a n n h e im , Ideologic und Utopie, 3 d e d . (F r a n k fu r t, 1 9 6 5 ),
5 3 . " T h is c r u c ia l s e n t e n c e is m is s in g in all tr a n s la tio n s ," a c c o r d in g to
J o se p h G a b e l, “C o n s c ie n c e u to p iq u e et fa u ss e c o n s c ie n c e ,” in Le Discours
ulopique, p a p e r s d e li v e r e d at a c o llo q u iu m , C e r is y -la -S a lle , 2 3 J u l y - 1
A u g . 1 9 7 5 (P a ris: U n io n g e n e r a l c d e d it io n s , 1 9 7 8 ), 3 7 , 4 6 n . 6 .
234. NE, 1 4 7 - 1 4 8 .
2 3 5 . C f ., G a b e l, “C o n s c ie n c e u t o p iq u e et fa u s s e c o n s c ie n c e ,” 4 4 .
2 3 6 . J a m e s S c h m id t , “C r itic a l T h e o r y a n d t h e S o c io lo g y o f K n o w l
e d g e , A R e s p o n s e to M a r tin J a y ,” Telos, 7 . n o . 3 (F all 1 9 7 4 ): 171.
134 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
2 3 7 . R o g e r B a s tid e , “ M y th e s e t u t o p ie s ,” Colliers international^ de
sociologic, 2 8 (J a n .-J u n e 1 9 0 0 ): 4 . B a s tid e a ls o q u o t e s A u g u s t e C o m te
in a s im ila r v e in : “ U to p ia s a r e to th e so c ia l art w h a t g e o m e t r ic o r
m e c h a n ic a l m o d e ls a r e to th e ir c o r r e s p o n d in g a rts. S u c h m o d e ls a r e
a c c e p te d as a n in d is p e n s a b le s t e p in th e m o st m o d e s t c o n s t r u c t io n s ,
and m u st t h e r e f o r e b e e q u a lly n e c e s s a r y in t h e m o s t e la b o r a te .
F u r th e r m o r e , d e s p it e th e e m p ir ic a l n a tu r e o f th e p o litic a l a r t, all m a jo r
c h a n g e in th is H eld h a s b e e n p r e c e d e d , o n e o r tw o c e n t u r ie s e a r lie r ,
by a n a n a la g o u s u to p ia th a t h a s in s p ir e d H u m a n it y ’s a e s th e tic sp irit
w ith a s ix th s e n s e r e g a r d in g its s itu a tio n a n d its n e e d s .” Discours sur
I'ensemble do positivisme, (E d itio n s d u C in q u a n te n a ir e ), 3 0 2 .
2 3 8 . M a n n h e im , Ideology and Utopia, 2 5 3 .
2 3 9 . F o r a m o r e d e ta ile d c o m p a r is o n b e tw e e n M a n n h e im a n d M a rc u se,
s e e J o s e p h L. D e v itis , “ M a n n h e im a n d M a r c u se : S o c ia l C o n tr o l in
R e c o n s tr u c tio n a n d R e v o lu t io n ,” Southwestern Journal of Philosophy, 6
(S u m m e r 1 9 7 5 ): 1 2 9 -1 4 1 . A f u r t h e r c o m p a r is o n b e tw e e n id e o lo g y a n d
u to p ia by P a r e to c a n b e f o u n d in J u lie n F r e u n d , Pareto (P a ris: S e g h e i s),
17 3 .
2 4 0 . D a v id K e ttle r , “T h e V o c a tio n o f R a d ica l I n te lle c t u a ls ,” Politics
and Society, 1, n o . 1 ( N o v . 1 9 7 0 ): 3 4 .
C hapter III
1. J e a n M a r a b in i, “ La R e v o lu tio n d u X X I e s ie c le s e r a p o e t iq u e ,”
M a r c u s e ’s last in te r v ie w , Les Nouvelles litteraires, 2 - 9 A u g . 1 9 7 9 , 3 , c o l.
4 -5 .
2 . I b id ., c o ls . I a n d 5.
3. Schriften l: Der deutsche Kiimtlerroman, Friihe Aufscitze (F r a n k fu r t:
S u h r k a m p V e r la g , 1 9 7 8 ). S e c c o m m e n t a r y b y B a r r y M . K atz, “N e w
S o u r c e s o f M a r c u s e ’s A e s th e tic s ," New German Critique, 6 , n o . 2 ( S p r in g
1 9 7 9 ), 1 7 6 -1 8 8 .
4 . B e n A g g e r , “T h e A e s t h e tic P o litic s o f H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” The
Canadian Forum, 5 3 (O c t. 1 9 7 3 ): 2 4 .
5. ODM, 6 3 .
6 . A g g e r , “T h e A e s t h e tic P o litic s o f H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," 2 6 , 3 0 .
7. B e n A g g e r , “T h e G r o w in g R e le v a n c e o f M a r c u s e ’s D ia le c tic o f
I n d iv id u a l a n d C lass," Dialectical Anthropology, 4 , n o . 2 (J u ly 1 9 7 9 ): 1 35.
8 . I b id ., 1 4 4 , 145 n . 14, c itin g P au l P ic c o n e , “A r tific ia l N e g a t iv it y ,”
Telos, 11, n o . 1 ( S p r in g 1 9 7 8 ): 4 3 - 5 4 .
9 . F r e d C . A lf o r d , r e v ie w o f AD, Telos, 14, n o . 2 (S u m m e r 1 9 8 1 ):
1 7 9 -1 8 8 .
10. M a r c u s e , “ P r o to s o c ia lis m a n d L a te C a p ita lis m .”
11. A lf o r d , r e v ie w o f A D , 1 8 8 .
12. I b id ., 1 7 9 , 185.
13. I b id ., 1 8 2 , c itin g AD, 6 9 .
Notes 135
14. M a r c u s e , “ P r o to s o c ia lis m a n d L a te C a p ita lism ," 2 8 .
15. A lf o r d , r e v ie w o f A D , 1 8 5 . S e c a ls o p . 1 8 1 , w h e r e h e s ta te s th at
M a r c u s e “c a n a p p r o p r ia t e a s p e c t s o f B a h r o ’s w o r k to b r e a k o u t o f th e
v ic io u s c ir c le b e c a u s e in The Aesthetic Dimension h e r e c o n c ile s h im s e lf
to t h e fa ct th a t a b s o lu t e f r e e d o m w ill n o t b e r e a liz e d in th is w o rld ."
16. M a r c u s e , “P r o to so c ia lism a n d L it e C a p ita lism ,” 3 2 . O n th e vicio u s
c ir c le , s e e a ls o ib id ., 2811; O D M ( 1 9 6 4 ) 2 2 3 , 2 5 1 ; “ L ib e r a tio n fr o m th e
A f f lu e n t S o c ie t y ” ( 1 9 6 7 ) , 1 7 8 ; FL ( 1 9 7 0 ) , 3 6 , 8 0 (th is last r e f e r e n c e is
th e o n ly o n e m e n t io n e d b y A lf o r d ) . R o u s s e a u ’s w e ll-k n o w n s ta te m e n t
o f t h e p r o b le m is g iv e n in c h a p . 2 , n . 4 9 ) .
17. A D , 6 .
18. L ’E x p r e s s va plus loin avec ces theoriciens (P aris: L a ffo n t, 1 9 7 3 ),
93.
19. G e o r g e s G u s d o r f , Naissance <le la conscience romantique au siecle des
lumieres, v o l. 7 o f Les Sciences humaines et la pensee occidentale (P aris:
P a y o t, 1 9 7 6 ), 4 4 3 .
2 0 . EC, 1 8 Iff.
2 1 . M ic h a e l L o e w y , Four une sociologie des intellectuels revolutionnaires;
L ’Evolution politique de Lukdcs, 1 9 0 9 -1 9 2 9 (P aris: P r e sse s u n iv e r s ita ir e s
d e F r a n c e , 1 9 7 6 ), 2 8 .
2 2 . P a u l B r e in e s , “ M a r x is m , R o m a n tic is m , a n d th e C a se o f G e o r g
L u k a cs: N o t e s o n S o m e R e c e n t S o u r c e s a n d S itu a tio n s ,” Studies in
Romanticism, n o . 16 (F a ll 1 9 7 7 ): 4 7 5 - 4 7 6 .
2 3 . J e f f r e y H e r f , r e v ie w o f L o e w y , Four une sociologie des intellectuels
revolutionnaires, Telos, 1 1, n o . 3 (F a ll 1 9 7 8 ): 2 2 8 .
2 4 . M ic h a e l L o e w y , Marxisme et romantisme revolutionnaire, Essais sur
Lukdcs et Rosa Luxemburg (P a ris: L e S y c o m o r e , 1979).
25. I b id ., 1 8 -1 9 .
2 6 . I b id ., 2 0 .
2 7 . I d ., “ M a r c u s e a n d B e n ja m in : T h e R o m a n tic D im e n s io n ," Telos,
13, n o . 2 ( S u m m e r 1 9 8 0 ): 2 5 - 3 3 .
2 8 . I b id ., 2 6 , c itin g M a r c u s e , Der deulsche Kunstlerroman, 4 3 - 4 9 , 8 6 ,
1 1 7 - 1 1 9 ,1 3 3 - 1 4 3 .
2 9 . K atz, “N e w S o u r c e s o f M a r c u se ’s A esth e tics," 182, c itin g M a rcu se,
NE, 229.
3 0 . J a y , " A e s t h e t ic T h e o r y a n d th e C r itiq u e o f M ass C u lt u r e ,” in The
Dialectical Imagination, 1 7 3 - 2 1 8 , s e e 175.
3 1. P e te r C le c a k , " H e r b e r t M a r c u s e : F r o m H is to r y to M y th ,” in R adi
cal Faradoxes, Dilemmas o f the American Left: 1 9 4 5 -1 9 7 0 ( N e w Y ork :
H a r p e r a n d R o w , 1 9 7 3 ), 1 7 5 - 2 2 9 , s e e 2 1 3 .
3 2 . R ic h a r d F la c k s, “T h e I m p o r t a n c e o f th e R o m a n tic M y th fo r th e
L eft," a d is c u s s io n o f C le c a k , " H e r b e r t M a rcu se: F ro m H isto r y to M yth,"
Theory and Society, 2 , n o . 3 , (F all 1 9 7 5 ): 4 0 1 - 4 1 4 ; s e e 4 1 4 .
3 3 . L o e w y , M arxisme et romantisme revolutionnaire, 15, c itin g M artin
Bul>er, Utopie et socialisme (Ffade in Utopia) (H e id e lb e r g : V e r la g L u n b e r t
136 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
S c h n e id e r , 1 9 5 0 ), tr a n s la te d b y P a u l C o r s e t a n d F r a n c o is G ir a r d (P aris:
A u b ie r - M o n t a ig n e , 1 9 7 7 ), 8 9 .
3 4 . E ric V o la n t, LeJen des affranchis. Confrontation Marcuse-Mollmanti
(M o n tr e a l: F id e s, c l 9 7 6 ) .
3 5 . I b id ., 1 9 2 .
3 6 . S a in K e e n a n d J o h n R a se r , “A C o n v e r s a t io n w ith H erbert
M a r c u se ," Psychology Today, 4 , n o . 9 (1 9 7 1 ): 3 3 - 3 6 .
3 7 . B r ig itte C r o is ie r , “ U n e C o n s c ie n c e t o u t e n e u v e ," La Nef, n o . 3 6
(J a n .-M a r . 1 9 6 9 ): 1 8 8 -1 8 9 .
3 8 . M ic h e ld e C e r t e a u , “ H e r b e r t M a r c u s e , 1 8 9 8 -1 9 7 9 ," in Universalia
1980, 5 7 2 - 5 7 3 .
3 9 . I d ., “ L ’E n d u r a n c e d e I’e s p o ir ,” Les Nouvelles litteraires, A u g . 2 -9 ,
1979, 4.
4 0 . R ic h a r d K e a r n e y , “ I n te r v ie w w ith H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” The Crane
Hag, 1, n o . 1 (S p r in g 1 9 7 7 ): 8 3 - 8 4 .
4 1 . H . P e y r e , “ R o m a n tis m e ," in Encyclopaedia Universalis, 1 4 :3 6 7 c .
4 2 . G e o r g W ilh e lm F r ie d r ic h H e g e l, “L ’A r t r o m a n t iq u e ,” Esthetique
(P aris: A u b ie r - M o n t a ig n e , 1 9 6 4 ), 5 : 1 2 6 .
4 3 . J e a n - M ic h e l P a lm ie r , " S ig n if ic a t io n c r it iq u e d u r o m a n t is m e
r e v o lu lio n n a ir e ,” in Herbert Marcuse et la nouvelle gauche, 5 6 6 - 5 7 1 ,5 8 2 .
44. ODM, 6 0 .
4 5 . M ic h e l H a a r , L’Homme unidimensionnel, Marcuse (P a ris: H a lie r ,
1 9 7 5 ), 6 0 - 6 1 .
46. CRR, 8 9 .
47. CRR, 12 2 .
4 8 . K e a r n e y , “ I n te r v ie w w ith H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," 8 1 - 8 2 .
4 9 . I b id ., 8 0 - 8 1 .
5 0 . H e r b e r t R e a d , “S u r r e a lis m a n d th e R o m a n tic P r in c ip le ," in Crit
icism: The Foundations of Modern Literary Judgment, 9 6 , c ite d by G e r a ld
G r a lf, “A e s th e tic is m a n d C u ltu r a l P o litics," Social Research, 4 0 , n o . 2
( S u m m e r 1 9 7 3 ), 3 2 2 .
51. CRR, 9 2 .
52. ODM, 5 9 .
5 3 . ODM, 5 9 .
5 4 . CRR, 5 .
5 5 . K e a r n e y , “ I n te r v ie w w ith H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ,” 7 7 .
5 6 . I b id ., 8 0 .
57. CRR, 8 6 .
58. AD, 6 .
59. CRR, 89.
60. CRR, 12 2 .
61. CRR, 12 5 .
6 2 . G r a ff, “A e s t h e tic is m a n d C u ltu r a l P o litic s ,” 3 3 9 .
6 3 . A n n e tte T. R u b in s te in , r e v ie w o f AD, Science and Society, 4 2 , n o .
4 (1 9 7 9 ): 5 0 3 . T h e r e v ie w n o te s th e w e a k n e s s o f M a r c u s e ’s a r g u m e n t
Notes 137
a g a in s t t h e t y p e o l t h e o r y p u t lo r w a r d b y L u k a c s, s in c e M a r c u se m a k e s
u se o f th e sa m e c o n c e p t. M a r c u s e w r o te : “T h e p a r tic u la r so cia l
c o n f r o n t a t io n s a r e b u ilt in t o t h e p la y o l m e ta s o c ia l fo r c e s b e tw e e n
in d iv id u a l a m i in d iv id u a l, m a le a n d fe m a le , h u m a n ity a n d n a tu r e .”
AD, 2 7 . L u k a c s , a s q u o t e d in t h e r e v ie w (p . 5 0 1 ) , sta te d : “T h e c e n tr a l
c a t e g o r y a n d c r it e r io n o f r e a lis tic lite r a tu r e is th e ty p e , a p a r tic u la r
s y n th e s is w h ic h o r g a n ic a lly b in d s t o g e t h e r t h e g e n e r a l a n d th e p a r tic
u la r in b o th c h a r a c te r s a n d s it u a t io n s .”
0 4 . K e a r n e y , “ I n te r v ie w w ith H e r b e r t M a rc u se," 8 2 . S e e a ls o CRR,
90.
0 5 . “ T h e R e le v a n c e o f R e a lity ," Proceedings and Addresses of the Amer
ican Philosophical Association, 4 2 (O c t. 1 9 0 9 ): 3 9 - 5 0 .
00. I b id ., 5 0 .
07. Le Monde, I I M ay 1 9 0 8 , 3 .
0 8 . “T h e R e le v a n c e o f R e a lity ," 5 0 . M a r c u s e ’s c o m m e n t s a r e r e m i
n is c e n t o f t h e o p e n i n g w o r d s o f A d o r n o ’s Negative Dialectics, tr a n sla te d
by E. B . A s h t o n ( N e w Y o r k : S c a b u r y P r e ss , 1 9 7 3 ), to th e e f f e c t th at
p h ilo s o p h y w h ic h a p p e a r s o b s o le t e k e e p s a liv e b e c a u s e its m o m e n t o f
r e a liz a tio n w a s m is s e d .
0 9 . I b id ., 4 7 .
7 0 . K arl M a r x , “C r itiq u e o f H e g e l ’s P h ilo s o p h y o f L aw , I n tr o d u c
tio n ,"Collected Works, 3: 1 87.
7 1 . P r e fa c e t o A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy, in The
Marx-Engels Reader, e d . R o b e r t C . T u c k e r ( N e w Y o rk : W . YV. N o r to n
& C o ., I n c ., 1 9 7 2 ), 4 .
Collected Works, 5 :3 7 .
7 2 . M a r x - E n g e ls , " T h e G e r m a n I d e o lo g y ,”
7 3 . “T h e o r i e e t p r a tiq u e ," AC, 7 5 ; ita lics m in e . S e e a ls o RR, 3 1 9 .
7 4 . “T h e R e le v a n c e o f R e a lity ,” 4 8 ; ita lics m in e .
7 5 . RR, 3 2 2 .
7 0 . J a y , The Dialectical Imagination, 7 9 .
7 7 . M a r x - E n g e ls , “T h e G e r m a n I d e o lo g y ," Collected Works, 5 :5 4 .
78. AC, 7 5 .
7 9 . AD, 7 3 .
8 0 . NE, 1 4 0 .
8 1 . NE, 1 5 4 .
8 2 . “T h e R e le v a n c e o f R ea lity ," 4 8 - 4 9 .
8 3 . NE, 1 1 9 .
8 4 . “ A R e v o lu t io n in V a lu e s ,” in Political Ideologies, e d s . J a m e s A .
G o u ld a n d W illis H . T r u it t ( N e w Y o rk : T h e M a c m illa n C o ., 1 9 7 3 ),
331.
8 5 . " T h e C o n c e p t o f N e g a t io n in th e D ia le c tic ," Telos, n o . 8 (1 9 7 1 ):
1 3 0 -1 3 2 .
8 0 . SM, 1 11. S e c a ls o RR, 3 2 1 , a n d CRR, 7 3 - 7 4 .
87. Collected
M a r x , " E c o n o m ic a n d P h ilo s o p h ic M a n u sc r ip ts o f 1 8 4 4 ,”
Works, 3 : 2 7 7 . S e e a ls o “ M a r x is m a n d t h e N e w H u m a n it y ,” in Marxism
138 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
and Radical Religion, Essays toward a Revolutionary Humanism, e d s . J o h n
C. R a in e s a n d T h o m a s D e a n (P h ila d e lp h ia : T e m p l e U n iv e r s ity P re ss,
1 9 7 0 ), 8; A r n o ld T o y n b e e , “ A rt as a F o r m o f R e a lity , in On the Future
of Art ( N e w Y o rk : V ik in g P r e ss, 1 9 7 0 ), 1 33; CRR, 7 3 - 7 4 .
8 8 . C f. G e o r g e F r ie d m a n , “ P o s in g th e P r o b le m o f M o d e r n ity ,” in
The Political Philosophy of the Frankfurt School, p a r t II, se c t. 10, “ I h e
C risis o f th e E n lig h t e n m e n t ,” 11, “T h e C r isis o f A rt a n d C u lt u r e ,” 12,
“T h e C risis o f th e H u m a n P sy c h e ," a n d 13, “T h e C risis o f H isto r y ,"
109-203.
8 9 . “T h e R e le v a n c e o f R e a lity ,” 4 8 .
9 0 . “T h e o r y a n d P o litic s ,” 141.
91. NE, 131.
9 2 . CRR, 1 21.
93. T h eo d o r A dorno, Theorie esthetique (P a ris: K lin c k sie c k , 1 9 7 4 ). I d .,
Aesthetische Theorie, Paralipomena, Friihe Einleitung, e d s . G r e te l A d o r n o
a n d R o lf T ie d e m a n n , v o l. 7 o f Complete Works ( 1 9 7 0 ) , 3 7 4 , as c ite d by
A r a to e t a l., The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, 2 0 7 , 3 5 1 n . 7 7 .
9 4 . EL, 3 0 f f .
9 5 . CRR, 1 07.
9 6 . B r y a n M a g e e , “ M a r c u s e a n d th e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l, D ia lo g u e w ith
H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," in Man of Ideas: Some Creators of Contemporary Philos
ophy, e d . B r y a n M a g e e ( L o n d o n : B r itish B r o a d c a s tin g C o r p o r a t io n ,
1 9 7 8 ), 6 9 - 7 0 . S e e a ls o H a b e r m a s ’s c o m p a r is o n b e tw e e n M a r c u s e a n d
B e n j a m in , “ C o n s c i o u s n e s s - r a is in g o r R e d e m p t iv e C r it ic is m — T h e
C o n t e m p o r a n e it y o f W a lte r B e n j a m in ,” in New German Critique, 6 ,
n o . 2 (S p r in g 1 9 7 9 ), p a r t I: 3 2 - 3 7 .
9 7 . “A r t in t h e O n e - D im e n s io n a l S o c ie ty ,” A rts Magazine, M ay 1 9 6 7 ,
2 6 -3 1 .
9 8 . I b id ., 2 6 .
9 9 . J a y , “A e s th e tic T h e o r y a n d t h e C r itiq u e o f M ass C u lt u r e ,” The
Dialectical Imagination, 1 7 3 -2 1 8 .
1 0 0 . “T h e A f f ir m a t iv e C h a r a c te r o f C u ltu r e ," in NE, 8 8 - 1 3 3 .
1 0 1 . “T h e S t r u g g le A g a in s t L ib e r a lis m in t h e T o ta lita r ia n V ie w o f th e
S ta te ,” in NE, 3 -4 2 .
1 0 2 . “B a s e a n d S u p e r s tr u c t u r e — R e a lity a n d I d e o lo g y ,” in SM, 1 0 5 -
120.
103. One-Dimensional Man.
104. EL, a n d in p a r tic u la r a little -k n o w n in te r v ie w r e p o r t e d in Les
Jeunes et la contestation, (P aris: L a f f o n t , B ib lio t h e q u e L a ffo n t d e s g r a n d s
t h e m e s , n o . 9 3 .)
105. CRR, p a s s im , a n d in p a r tic u la r 8 3 - 8 4 .
1 0 6 . M a r c u se 's id e a s o n " c u ltu r e in d u str y " w e r e s im ila r to t h o s e o f
H o r k h e im e r a n d A d o r n o in 1 9 4 4 , g iv e n a w id e r a u d ie n c e b y A d o r n o
in 1 9 6 3 a n d 1 9 6 7 ; c f ., D a v id H e ld , Introduction toCritical Theory ( B e r k e
ley: U n iv e r s ity o f C a lifo r n ia P r e ss, 1 9 8 0 ), p p . 9 0 f f . T h e n o t io n o f
Notes 139
p o p u la r c u lt u r e a llo w s lo r t h e id e a th at a c e r ta in e le m e n t o f c u ltu r e
o r ig in a t e s s p o n t a n e o u s ly w ith th e m a s s e s , w h e r e a s to d a y , a c c o r d in g
to t h e m e m b e r s o ( t h e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l, c u lt u r e is c o n t r o lle d a n d
m a n ip u la t e d , a n d its a u t o n o m y is t h r e a t e n e d by in d u str ia l c iv iliz a tio n .
1 h is is w h y t h e y fin a lly p r e f e r r e d th e e x p r e s s io n “c u lt u r e in d u str y "
to “ m a s s c u ltu r e ."
1 0 7 . " T h e S t r u g g le A g a in s t L ib e r a lis m in th e T o ta lita r ia n V ie w o f th e
S t a t e ,” ME, 3 - 4 2 .
1 0 8 . I b id ., 4 2 .
1 0 9 . S M , 10 7 .
1 1 0 . SM , 1 1 0 .
111. SM , 115.
1 1 2 . SM , 11 7 ; ita lics m in e .
1 1 3 . SM , 1 1 6 .
114. SM , 116.
115. SM , 120.
1 16. S M , 11 8 .
1 1 7 . “ P r e f a c e ft f e d it io n fr a n y a ise ," H U , 7; c f ., O D M , xvi.
1 1 8 . " T h e C o n c e p t o f E s s e n c e ,” in ME, 6 5 .
1 1 9 . “ D e I 'o n t o lo g ie ft la tech n o lo g ic* ; L es T e n d a n c e s d e la s o c ie te
in d u s t r ie ll e ,” Arguments, 4 , n o . 18 (1 9 6 0 ): 5 4 - 5 9 .
1 2 0 . “T h e L a n g u a g e o f T o t a l A d m in is tr a tio n ," a n d “T h e N e w F o rm s
o f C o n t r o l” in O D M .
1 2 1 . SM , 1 1 7 .
122. ODM , 6 3 .
1 2 3 . " P r e fa c e ft I 'e d itio n fr a n y a ise ," H U , 10.
124. ODM , 2 4 8 .
1 2 5 . C L , G e r a r d K a u le t, "La R e v o lu tio n im p o s s ib le ? E n h o m m a g e ft
H e r b e r t M a r c u s e ," Allemagnes d'aujourd'hui, (S e p t. 1 9 7 9 ):2 5 .
1 2 6 . ME, 1 1 9 .
1 2 7 . A D , 13.
1 2 8 . V in c e n t C e o g h e g a n , Henson o w l Eros, The Social Theory of Herbert
M arcuse ( L o n d o n : P lu to P re ss, 1 9 8 1 ), 2 8 .
1 2 9 . E r n st B lo c h , “ l .e C o n c e p t d e f u n c tio n u t o p iq u e ,” in Le Principe
Esperance ( 1 9 5 9 ; P aris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 7 6 ), 1 7 4 -2 1 6 . P ie r r e F u lle r ,
" U t o p ie et m a r x is m e s c io n E r n st B lo c h ," Archives de sociologies des reli
gions, n o . 21 (J a n .- J u n e 1 9 6 6 ): 3 - 2 1 , s e e 9 - 1 3 . L a e n n e c H u r b o n , “T r o is
f u n c t io n s d e I’u to p ie ," in Ernst Bloch, utopie et esperance (P aris: C e r f,
1 9 7 4 ), 7 3 - 7 5 .
1 3 0 . P a u l R ic o e u r , “T h e T a s k o f th e P o litic a l E d u c a to r ," tr a n s la te d
b y D a v id S te w a r t, Philosophy Today 17, n o .2 /4 (S u m m e r 1 9 7 3 ): 140-
1 52, s e e 1 5 0 -1 5 1 ; “ P r e v isio n e c o n o m iq u c et c h o ix e th iq u e ," Esprit, (F eb .
1 9 6 6 ), r e p r in t e d in Histoire et verite, 3 d e d . (P a ris: S e u il, n .d .) 3 0 1 - 3 1 6 ,
s e e 3 1 2 - 3 1 5 ; ‘Lit F u n c tio n c o n s lil u a n t e d e E u to p ic ,' in "L’l l e r m e n e u -
140 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
tiq u e d e la s e c u la r is a tio n , F o i, Id eologic*, U t o p i e ,” in Hermhieutique de
la secularisation, 4 9 - 6 9 , s e e 5 9 .
1 3 1 . P avel K o v a ly , “C o n t e m p o r a r y F u n c tio n s o f th e M a rx ist U t o p ia ,”
in U topic)Dystopia?, e d . P e y to n E. R ic h te r (C a m b r id g e , M a ss.: S c h e n k *
m a n . 1 9 7 5 ). 8 9 - 9 2 .
1 3 2 . G e o r g e F r ie d m a n , The Political Philosophy of the Frankfurt School,
1 4 0 -1 4 1 , 1 58.
1 3 3 . F r a n c o is C h ir p a z , “ A lie n a tio n e t u to p ie ," Esprit, n o . 3 7 7 (J a n .
1 9 6 9 ): 8 8 ; ita lic s m in e .
1 3 4 . P arvis Pit a n , 'M a r c u s e ’s A e s t h e tic P e r p e c t iv e ,’ in “ M a r c u s e a n d
th e P r o b le m o f I n s t r u m e n t a l R a tio n a lity ,” Mid-American Review of Soci
ology, 2 , n o . 2 (W in te r 1 9 7 7 ): 1 9 -2 8 , s e e 2 4 - 2 8 .
1 3 5 . M ic h e l H a a r , L’Homme unidimensionnel, Marcuse, 7 6 .
1 3 6 . R o g e r G a r a u d y , Perspective de I'homme (P aris: P r e s s e s u n iv e r s i-
ta ir e s d e F r a n c e , 1 9 6 9 ), 3 7 3 - 3 7 4 .
1 37. “ R e m a r k s o n a R e d e f in it io n o f C u lt u r e ,” Daedalus, 9 4 , n o . 1
(W in te r 1 9 6 5 ): 2 0 7 ; ita lics m in e .
1 38. G e o g h e g a n , Reason and Eros, The Social Theory of Herbert Marcuse,
28.
139. F u i te r , “ U t o p ie e t m a r x is m e s e lo n E rn st B lo c h ,” 9 - 1 3 . H u r b o n ,
" T r o is F o n c tio n s d e I’u t o p ie ,” 7 3 - 7 5 .
140. R ic o e u r , “ P r e v is io n e c o n o n iiq u e et c h o ix e t h iq u e ,” 3 1 4 .
14 1 . I b id ., 3 1 2 ; ita lics m in e .
142. 111., “T h e T a s k o f th e P o litic a l E d u c a to r ,” 15 0 ; ita lic s m in e .
14 3 . I d ., “ P r e v is io n e c o n o m iq u e e t c h o ix e t h iq u e ,” 3 1 3 .
14 4 . I d ., “T h e T a s k o f th e P o litic a l E d u c a t o r ,” 1 4 7 .
145. K o v a ly , “C o n t e m p o r a r y F u n c tio n s o f th e M a r x ist U to p ia ," 8 9 -
92.
1 46. A d a m S c h a f f , Marxism and the Human Individual ( N e w Y ork :
M c G r a w -H ill, 1 9 7 1 ), 1 3 5 , c ite d b y K o v a ly , 8 9 .
147. R ic o e u r , “T h e T a s k o f th e P o litic a l E d u c a to r ,” 145.
1 4 8 . I d ., “ L ’H e r m c n e u t i q u c d e la s e c u la r is a t io n , F o i, I d e o l o g i c ,
U t o p ie ,” 5 9 .
1 49. ODM, 2 3 8 - 2 3 9 ; s e e a ls o AD, 6 .
150. G e o r g W ilh e lm F r ie d r ic h H e g e l, Philosophy of Fine Art, tr a n s la te d
by F. P. B . O s m a s t o n ( N e w Y o r k , 1 9 7 5 ), 1 : 4 2 -4 3 , 2 6 3 - 2 6 4 , c ite d by
F r ie d m a n , The Political Philosophy of the Frankfurt School, 1 41.
1 5 1 . C f., M a r c u s e , in c h a p . 2 o f EL\ M a x H o r k h e im e r , “A u th o r ity in
th e F a m ily ,” in Critical Theory, Selected Essays ( N e w Y ork : S e a b u r y P re ss,
1 9 7 2 ), 4 7 - 1 2 8 ; B e n ja m in a n d A d o r n o , as c ite d by F r ie d m a n , The Polit
ical Philosophy of the Frankfurt School, 1 3 8 n. 6 .
1 5 2 . W a lte r B e n ja m in , “T h e W o r k o f A rt in a n A g e o f M e c h a n ic a l
Illuminations: Essays and Reflections e d . H a n n a h A r e n d t
R e p r o d u c tio n ,” in
(N e w Y o r k [ 1 9 5 3 ] 1 9 6 8 ), 2 4 1 - 2 4 2 , as c ite d b y F r ie d m a n , The Political
Philosophy of the Frankfurt School, 1 4 8 n . 3 0 .
Notes 141
1 5 3 . F r ie d m a n , 1 5 8 - 1 5 9 .
1 5 4 . I b id ,, 1 5 9 .
155. EC, 144.
1 5 6 . F r ie d m a n , 1 5 9 .
157. ODM, 2 4 9 ; s e e a ls o 2 2 8 - 2 2 9 .
1 5 8 . " D £ b a ts G o ld m a n n - M a r c u s e ," 1 54.
1 5 9 . AD, 3 2 .
1G0.EL, 2 4 , 1 9 -2 0 .
1G1. P la to , The Statesman, 2 9 3 b ; K arl P o p p e r , The Open Society and Its
Enemies: The Spell of Plato (P r in c e to n : P r in c e to n U n iv e r sity P ress, [I9G 2]
1 9 6 6 ) , 16 5 .
1 6 2 . P la to , Reptihlic, 5 0 0 e - 5 0 1 a .
1 6 3 . I b id ., 5 4 1 a .
1 6 4 . I d ., The Statesman, 2 9 3 d - e .
1 6 5 . EU, 8 6 .
166. P o p p e r , The Open Society, 1 6 6 -1 6 8 .
1 6 7 . S o u r c e s o n P o p p e r - M a r c u s e r e la tio n s w ith in th e c o n t e x t o f th e s e
w e ll-k n o w n c o n t r o v e r s ie s a r e , in c h r o n o lo g ic a l o r d e r , as fo llo w s: Karl
The Positivist
P o p p e r , " R e a s o n o r R e v o lu tio n ? " in T . W . A d o r n o e t a l.,
Dispute in German Sociology ( N e w Y o rk : H a r p e r a n d R o w , 1 9 7 6 ); Times
Literary Supplement, “ D ia le c tic a l M e t h o d o lo g y ,” 12 M ar. 1 9 7 0 ; W o lf
L e p e n ie s , " A n t h r o p o lo g y a n d S o c ia l C r itic ism : A V ie w o n th e C o n t r o
v e r s y b e t w e e n A r n o ld G e lile n a n d J u r g e n H a b e r m a s ,” The Human
Context, 3 , n o . 2 (J u ly 1 9 7 1 ): 2 0 5 - 2 4 8 ; I I. T . W ils o n , “S c ie n c e , C r itiq u e ,
a n d C r itic is m : T h e O p e n S o c ie ty ‘R e v is ite d ,’ ” in On Critical Theoty, e d .
J o h n O 'N e ill ( N e w Y o r k : T h e S e a b u r y P re ss, 1 9 7 6 ), 2 0 5 - 2 3 0 ; J e a n -
F r a n g o is M a lh e r b e , “ La ‘T h e o r i e c r it iq u e ’ e t les lim ite s d u r a tio n a lis m e
d e P o p p e r ," in La Philosophic tie Karl Popper et lepositivisme logitjue (P aris:
P r e s s e s u n iv e r s it a ir e s d e F r a n c e , 1 9 7 6 ), 2 2 9 - 2 5 4 ; L. J . R ay, “C ritical
T h e o r y a n d P o s itiv is m : P o p p e r a n d th e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l,” Philosophy
of Social Sciences, 9 , n o . 2 , ( 1 9 7 9 ) : 1 4 9 -1 7 3 .
1 6 8 . P o p p e r , " R e a s o n o r R e v o lu tio n ? " 2 4 4 .
1 6 9 . Theodor W. Adorno zum Gedachtnis (F r a n k u r t a m M a in : S u h r k a m p
V e r la g , 1 9 7 1 ), 5 0 - 5 1 .
1 7 0 . M a g e e , “ M a r c u s e a n d th e F r a n k fu r t S c h o o l," 7 3 .
1 7 1 . P o p p e r , " R e a s o n o r R e v o lu t io n ? ” 2 4 5 .
C hapter IV
1. Martin Jay, "Metapolitics of Utopianism," D i s s e n t , 17, no. 4 (Jnly-
Aug. 1970): 350. In Marcuse’s article on “Art and Revolution” published
in 1972, he himself spoke of “metapolitics" (cf., C R R , 104).
2. O D M , 4.
3. Raymond Aron, E s s a i s u r le s lib e r ie s (Paris: Calmann-Levy [ 1965)
1976), 27, citing Alexis de Tocqueville, "Preface,” L ' A n c ie n R e g i m e e t
la r e v o lu tio n .
142 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
4 . C r a w fo r d B r o u g h M a c p h e r s o n , The Political Theory o] Possessive
Individualism—Hobbes to Locke ( O x f o r d : O x f o r d U n iv e r s ity P r e ss [1 9 0 2 ]
1 9 8 3 ). I d ., The Life and Times of Liberal Democracy ( O x f o r d : O x f o r d
U n iv e r s ity P r e ss, [ 1 9 7 7 ] 1 9 8 0 ).
5. RT, 8 7 .
6 . ME, x ix .
7. F reu n d , L'Essence du politique, 0 5 0 * 6 5 1 .
8. RR, “S u p p le m e n t a r y E p ilo g u e W r itte n in 1 9 5 4 ,” 4 3 9 .
9 . RT, 8 8 .
10. R o g e r G a r a u d y , Perspectives de I'homme: Existentialisme, pensee cath-
olique, structuralisme, marxisme (P aris: P r e ss e s u n iv e r s ita ir e s d e F r a n c e ,
1 9 0 9 ), 3 7 3 - 3 7 4 .
11. I b id ., 3 7 5 .
12. Ib id .
13. ODM, 18.
14. A n d r e G o r z , " T e c h n iq u e s , te c h n ic ie n s e t lu tte d e s cla sse s," Temps
modernes, n o . 3 0 1 (1 9 7 1 ): 1 44.
15. FL, 0 2 .
10. FL, 6 4 .
17. ODM, 4 .
18. G e o r g e K a teb , “ T h e P o litic a l T h o u g h t o f H e r b e r t M a r c u se ," -
Commentary, 4 9 , n o . 1 (J a n . 1 9 7 0 ): 4 8 - 4 9 .
19. RR, 2 8 8 .
20. CRR, 134.
21. AC, 7 5 .
2 2 . FL, 6 4 , a n d ODM, 4 .
2 3 . “M a r c u s e D e f in e s H is N e w L eft L in e ,” tr a n s la te d b y H e le n
W e a v e r , in The American Experience, e d s . H a r o ld J a f f e a n d J o h n T y te ll
( N e w Y o r k : H a r p e r a n d R o w , 1 9 7 0 ), 120.
2 4 . J o h n F ry, Marcuse—Dilemma and Liberation. A Critical Analysis
(S to c k h o lm : A lm q v is t a n d W ik s e ll, 1 9 7 4 ), 1 9 -2 0 .
25. ODM, 3 4 ; ME, x iv -x v ; EL, 8 0 .
26. ODM, 3 4 . S e e a ls o EL, 8 4 - 8 5 .
27. SM, 6 0 .
28. SM, 8 3 .
29. ME, 2 4 8 ; SM, 1 9 -2 0 .
30. EL, 1 3 -1 4 .
31. ODM, x iii, 18; SM, 0 0 ; ME, x v .
32. ME, 2 4 8 ; ODM, 3 4 , 2 4 2 .
33. EL, v iiff.
34. FL, 9 3 .
35. EL, 8 0 , 8 2 .
30. FL, 9 5 .
37. ODM, 2 3 .
Mutes 143
38. EL, 8 2 . It is p e r h a p s w o r th n o t in g h e r e th a t, w h e n a s k e d by
M a r c e l R io u x a b o u t t h e r o le o f s m a ll n a tio n a l e n t it ie s s u c h as Q u e b e c ,
M a r c u s e c o n s id e r e d th a t t h e y w e r e t o o sm a ll a u n it to h e s ig n ific a n t,
a n d th a t t h e in d e p e n d e n c e o f Q u e b e c w o u ld h e a s u p e r fic ia l a n d
Forces, n o . 2 2 (1 9 7 3 ): 6 0 .
p e r ip h e r a l c h a n g e .
39. ODM, 4 9 .
4 0 . ODM, 1 8 9 .
4 1 . ODM, x v i, 2 2 0 - 2 2 1 .
4 2 . J u lie n F r e u n d , “A p r o p o s tin b e s o in e l d e la v io le n c e : I-es R a p p o rts
e n t r e I’e c o n o m iq u e , le p o lit iq u e et la n a tu r e h u m a in e ,'' Paysans, 19.
n o . 1 1 0 (F e b .-M a r . 1 9 7 5 ): 10, c itin g : F r e d e r ic B a stia t, Harmonies econ-
omiques, v o l. 6 Oeuvres completes (P a ris: G u illa u m in , 1 8 9 3 ), 5 8 9 . C la u d e
H e n r i d e R o u v r o y , C o m t e S a in t - S im o n , De la reorganisation de la sociele
europeenne, v o l. 15 o f Oeuvres de Saint-Simon et Enfantin, 2 4 8 . A u g u s te
C o m t e , Cours de pliilosophie positive, v o l. 6 , 5 7 th le s s o n .
4 3 . ODM, 1 1 9 - 1 2 0 , c it in g T h e o d o r W . A d o r n o , “ I d e o lo g ic ,” in Ideo-
logie ( L u c h t e r h a n d : N e u w ie d , 1 9 6 1 ), 2 6 2 ff.
4 4 . R e b o u l, Langage et ideologic, 13.
4 5 . I b id ., 2 1 .
4 6 . I b id ., 2 1 - 2 5 . J u lie n F r e u n d , L'Essence du politique, 4 1 2 - 4 4 1 , a n d
" Q u ’e s t - c e q u e la p o lit iq u e id e o lo g iq u e ? " Revue europeenne des sciences
sociales, 17, n o . 4 6 ( 1 9 7 9 ) : 1 3 9 - 1 4 6 . J e a n B a e c h le r , Qu’est-ce que I'idto-
logic? (P a ris: G a llim a r d , 1 9 7 6 ), p a r tic u la r ly th e c h a p t e r o n “ L es F u n c
tio n s d e r id d o lo g ic ," 6 3 - 1 0 5 .
4 7 . O liv ie r R e b o u l, “L a V io le n c e et I’id e o lo g ie ," Dialogue, 17, n o . 3
(S e p t. 1 9 7 8 ) , 4 3 1 - 4 4 1 .
4 8 . W illia m L e iss , e t a l., “ M a r c u s e a s T e a c h e r ,” 4 2 5 .
4 9 . C f ., R a y m o n d A r o n , Plaidoyer pour une Europe decadente (P aris:
L a f f o n t , 1 9 7 7 ), a n d J u lie n F r e u n d , La Fin de la Renaissance (P aris:
P r e s s e s u n iv e r s it a ir e s d e F r a n c e ).
50. FU, 8 6 .
5 1 . L u d w ig F e u e r b a c h , Cours sur I’histoire de la pliilosophie modetne
( 1 9 3 5 ) , c it e d b y M a r c u s e in t h e e p ig r a p h to Pliilosophie el revolution
(P a ris: D e n o e l- G o n t h ie r , 1969).
52. I d .,Principes de pliilosophie ( 1 8 4 3 - 1 8 4 4 ) , c ite d by M a r c u se in th e
e p ig r a p h t o Pliilosophie et revolution.
5 3 L o e w y , Marxisme et romanlisme revolutionnaire, 1 4 -1 5 .
5 4 . " T h e R e a lm o f F r e e d o m a n d t h e R e a lm o f N e c e s s ity , A R e c o n
s id e r a tio n ," 2 0 .
5 5 . “ A rt in t h e O n e - D im e n s io n a l S o c ie ty ," 2 6 .
5 6 . " T h e M o v e m e n t in a N e w E ra o f R e p r e s s io n ," Berkeley Journal
of Sociology, 16 (1 9 7 1 -7 2 ): 9 .
5 7 . " T h e F a ilu r e o f t h e N e w L e ft," 11.
5 8 . B a e c h le r , Qu’est-ce que l’ideologic?, 6 9 .
144 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
59. “T h e R e a lm o f F r e e d o m a n d th e R e a lm o f N e c e s s ity , A R e c o n
sid e r a tio n ," 2 0 .
f>0. “T h e o r y a n d P o litic s ,” 1 3 6 .
6 1 . ODM, 2 3 4 .
6 2 . K arl R. P o p p e r , “ U to p ia a n d V io le n c e ,” in Conjectures and Refu
tations: The Growth o f Scientific Knowledge ( N e w Y ork : H a r p e r , 1 9 6 8 ),
3 5 8 . T h is a r tic le first a p p e a r e d in The Hibbert Journal, 4 6 (1 9 4 8 ).
6 3 . X E 143. O n th e w o r d “E ig e n s in n ,” s e e c o m m e n ta r y b y P ie r r e V .
Z in ia , L ’Ecole dr Franc fort (P aris: E d itio n s u n iv e r s ita ir e s ), 2 4 .
6 4 . FU, 8 6 - 8 7 .
6 5 . “D e m o c r a c y H a s , H a s n ’t a F u tu r e ," 104.
6 6 . R e b o u l, Langage et ideologic, 2 3 .
6 7 . T h is c o n n e c t io n b e tw e e n to ta l id e o lo g y a n d u to p ia is a n a ly z e d
by B a e c h le r , QiTest-ce (/ur Videologicf, 9 5 , 101, 120, 315.
6 8 . G io v a n n i B u s in o , c itin g B a e c h le r in a r e v ie w o f Q u’cst-ceque I’ideo-
logir? in Revue europeenne des sciences societies, 17, n o . 4 8 (1 9 7 9 ): 5 1 - 5 2 .
6 9 . Jean M a r a b in i, “ L es D e r n ie r s D e s ir s d e M a r c u s e ,” Le Deimir, 7
A ug. 1979, 4.
70. FL, 1 0 2 .
71. K e a r n e y , “I n te r v ie w w ith H e r b e r t M a rc u se," 8 4 .
72. “T h e o r y a n d P olitics," 136.
7 3 . R R , x.
7 4 . O D M , 18 9 .
7 5 . “L e D ia lo g u e d e d e u x p e n s e u r s ‘c o n t e s t a t a ir e s ,1 ” Paris-M atch, 2 3
M ar. 1 9 7 9 , 9 . E ls e w h e r e M a r c u s e s ta te d . “ I h a v e tr ie d to b a s e m y
a n a ly sis o n th e fa c ts ,” in “ R e p r e s s io n et lib e r te ,” in La Liberie et I'ordre
social, p r o c e e d in g s o f th e 2 2 d R e n c o n tr e s in te r n a tio n a le s d e G e n e v e
( N e u c h a te l: E d itio n s d e la B a c o n n ie r e , 1 9 6 9 ), 2 7 3 . f l i c la tte r a p p e a r e d
in E n g lish a s “F r e e d o m a n d th e H isto r ic a l I m p e r a t iv e ,” in Studies in
Critical Philosophy (B o s to n : B e a c o n , 1 9 7 3 ).
7 6 . W o lff, “ H e r b e r t M a r c u se : A P e r so n a l R e m in is c e n c e ,” 6 .
7 7 . T h e id e a s e x p r e s s e d in th is p a r a g r a p h a r c b a se d o n a c o n s id
e r a tio n o f th e d is tin c tio n b e t w e e n g e n u s a n d s p e c ie s in A r is to tle , w ith
r e f e r e n c e to: J u lie n F r e u n d , “S e n s et r e s p o n s a b ilite d e la r e f le x io n
p h ilo s o p h ic jn e a I’h e u r e a c t u e lle ,” Revue de I'rnsrignemrnt philnsophique,
n o . 2 (1 9 6 2 ): 1 -1 6 , c f., 2 , 9 , 10; P au l R ic o e u r , Le Volontaire et I'invo-
lontaire (P aris: A u b ie r - M o n t a ig n e , 1 9 6 7 ), 18.
7 8 . J e a n R oy, “M ille n a r is m e et s ilu a t io n n is m e ,” Pliilosopliiques, 8 , n o .
1 (A p r . 1 9 8 1 ): 2 7 . S e e a ls o , id ., "La ‘T o le r a n c e r e p r e s s iv e ,1 n o u v e lle
r u s e d e la R a iso n d 'E tat?" 4 8 8 .
7 9 . R u s s e ll J a c o b y , “ H e r b e r t M a r c u se : T h e P h ilo s o p h e r as P e r p e tu a l
S c a n d a l," Los Angeles Times, 5 A u g . 1 9 7 9 , se c . 5 , p. 2 , c o l. 1.
8 0 . “M a r c u s e D e f in e s H is N e w L eft L in e ,” 11 7 .
8 1 . Time, The Weekly M agazine, “ P r o fe s s o r s , O n e - D im e n s io n a l P h ilo s
o p h e r ," C a n a d ia n e d ., 2 2 M ar. 1 9 6 8 , 6 7 .
Notes 145
82. R a y m o n d A r o n , Im Revolution introuvable, 119.
83. D o n a ld R o b in so n , The 100 Most Important People in the World Today
(N e w Y ork: P u tn a m , 1 9 7 0 ), 2 7 5 .
84. AC, 8 8 .
85. AC, 7 5 .
8 6 . N likel D u f r e n n e , Subversion-perversion (Paris: P resses u n iv ersi-
ta ires d e F r a n ce, 1 9 7 7 ).
8 7 . I b id ., 147.
8 8 . I b id ., 153.
8 9 . I b id ., 1 4 6 , 1 5 1 * 1 5 2 , 171. O n “u to p ia n a c tio n ,” see a lso id ., Art et
politique (P aris: U n io n g e n e r a te d 'ld itio n s . 1 9 74), 2 7 5 * 3 1 5 .
9 0 . FL, 6 8 .
9 1 . FL, 9 2 .
9 2 . “M a rcu se D e fin e s H is N e w L eft L in e ,” 135.
9 3 . " T h e o r y a n d P o litic s,” 136. O n th e p o litics o f p ro v o c a tio n , see
EL, 6 4 .
C hapter V
1. J e a n J a c q u e s R o u s s e a u , E m i l e , c ite d b y G e r a r d R a u le t, " E scha-
t o lo g ie e t u t o p ie o n la d e c o u v e r t e d e I’h is to ir e ," in S t r a t e g i e s d e I 'u to p ie ,
P ie r r e F u r te r , G e r a r d Raulet, et al. (P aris: G a lile e , 1 9 7 9 ), 1 7 9 n . 2 .
2 . R R ( 1 9 5 4 e d .) , x .
3. NE, 182.
4. F L , 101.
5. F L , 96.
6. SM , 180.
7. S M , 1 8 3 -1 8 5 .
8. “Sommcs-nous deja des homines?” 21-27.
9 . M a x W e b e r , " L e M e tie r e t la v o c a tio n d ’h o m m e p o litiq u e ," in L e
S a v a n t e t l e p o l i t i q u e (P a ris: P lo n , 1 9 5 9 ), 9 9 - 1 8 5 . S e e a ls o “ P o litics as a
V o c a t io n ,” in F r o m M a x W e b e r , e d s . H . H . G e r tb a n d C . W r ig h t M ills
( N e w Y o r k : 1 9 4 6 ).
10. R ic o e u r , “T h e T a s k s o f th e P o litic a l E d u c a to r ,” 1 4 2 -1 5 2 .
11. F L , 4 3 .
12. Ib id .
13. R ic o e u r , “T h e T a s k s o f t h e P o litic a l E d u c a to r ," 150.
14. I b id ., 1 4 9 -5 0 .
15. I b id ., 1 5 1 .
16. “C o n c lu s io n ,” in M a x W e b e r a n d th e S o c i o l o g y T o d a y , e d . " O tto
S t a m m e r ( O x f o r d , 1 9 7 1 ) , 18 5 .
17. W e b e r , “ L e M e tie r e t la v o c a tio n d ’h o m m e p o lit iq u e ,” 174.
18. “ F r e e d o m a n d t h e H is to r ic a l I m p e r a tiv e ," 2 1 6 .
19. “ W h e n L a w a n d M o r a lity S ta n d in t h e W ay," S o c ie ty , 10, n o . 6
( S e p t .- O c t . 1 9 7 3 ), 2 3 .
146 Herbert Mare use's Utopia
2 0 . “M arcu se D e fin e s H is N e w L eft Line" 127.
2 1 . FL, 9 0 .
2 2 . RT, 103. S e e a lso P ierre M erten s, “V io le n c e ‘in s titu tio n n e lle ,’ v io
le n ce ‘d e m o c r a iiq u e ’ et r e g r e s s io n ,” La Violence et .srs causes, ( unksco,
1980). 2 2 7 -2 4 8 .
23. RT, 99.
2 4 . R T , 1 22.
2 5 . R T , 106.
2 6 . “T h e o r y a n d P o litics," 136.
27. RT, 109.
28. RT, 81.
29. F L , 64.
3 0 . O D M , 4.
31. F L , 62.
3 2 . O D M , x iii.
3 3 . “ E th ic s a n d R e v o lu t io n ,” 1 33.
3 4 . I b id .. 1 3 5 .
3 5 . I b id ., 13 3 .
3 6 . O n th e o r ig in o f th e m o d e r n c o n c e p t o f th e u n ju s t e n e m y in
K a n t’s p h ilo s o p h y , s e e C . S c h m itt, D e r N o m a s d e r E r d e ( C o lo g n e , 1 9 5 0 ),
c h a p . 3 , p a r a . 2 , 14 I f f ., as c ite d b y F r e u n d , L 'E s s e n c e d u p o l i t i q u e , 6 14-
t il 5 . R e g a r d in g w a r, K ant w r o te th at n e it h e r o f th e tw o p a r tie s c a n
t h e r e f o r e h e d e s c r ib e d as a n u n ju s t e n e m y (w h ic h a lr e a d y p r e s u m e s
a j u d g m e n t ) , hut th a t it is th e is s u e w h ic h d e c id e s w h ic h s id e is r ig h t
( P r o j e t d e P a i x p e r p e t u e l l e , se c t. 1, p a r a . 2 ). H e a ls o d e f in e d th e u n ju st
e n e m y as h e w h o s e p u b lic ly e x p r e s s e d w ish (e it h e r in w o r d o r d e e d )
r e v e a ls a m a x im w h ic h , i f set fo r th as a g e n e r a l r u le , w o u ld m a k e p e a c e
b e tw e e n p e o p le s im p o s s ib le , w h e r e a s th e s ta te o f n a tu r e o u g h t , o n th e
c o n tr a r y , to b e c o n s id e r e d e t e r n a l. K ant d e f in e d th e just e n e m y as o n e
w h o m it w o u ld b e u n ju st o n h is p art to r e sist, a lt h o u g h in th a t c a s e it
w o u ld n o lo n g e r b e a n e n e m y . M e t a p h y s i q u e tie s m o e u r s , D o c t r i n e d u d r o i t ,
p a rt 2 , "L e D r o it p u b lic ," p a r . 6 0 . S e e a l s o j u l i e n F r e u n d , 'M o r a le et
v io le n c e , L 'F .x etu p le d e M a r c u s e ,’ in “A s p e c ts p o le m o lo g iq u e s d e la
v io le n c e ,” A c t i o n s e t r e e h e r c h e s s o r i a l e s , n o s . 1-2 (S e p t. 1 9 8 1 ): 4 0 - 4 2 .
3 7 . W e b e r , L e S a v a n t e t l e p o l i t i q u e , 1 8 0 -1 8 1 .
3 8 . N F ., 1 19.
3 9 . CRR, 13 0 .
40. E L . 28.
41. I m m a n u e l K an t, " O f b e a u ty as th e S y m lx il o f M o ra lity ,” in C r itiq u e
o f J u d g m e n t , tr a n s . ). H . B e r n a r d ( L o n d o n : M a c m illa n , 1 8 9 2 ). p a r a .
59.
4 2 . EC, 174; CRR, 7 3 -7 4 ; s e e a lso CRR, 6 6 -6 7 , a n d EL, 2 8 , 3 2 .
4 3 . M ax W eb er, “Essai stir le sen s d e la ‘n eu tra lite a x io lo g iq u e ’ d a n s
les scie n c e s s o c io lo g iq u e s et e r o n o m iq u e s ,” in Essais stir la throne de la
science, tran s. Julien F r e u n d ( 1 9 1 7 ; Paris: P lo n , 1 9 6 5 ), 4 2 5 , 4 2 8 .
Notes 147
44. EL, 2 6 .
45. EL, 2 8 .
46. EL, 6 5 .
47. EL, 2 4 ; FL, 6 8 .
48. EC, 2 2 8 .
49. CRR, 7 4 .
50. EL, 2 4 .
51. EL, 4 8 .
52. EL, 4 9 , 2 1 ; FL, 6 3 .
5 3 . “T h e o r y a n d P o litic s ,” 1 47.
5 4 . " P o litic a l P r e f a c e , 1 9 6 6 ,” EC, x x v ii.
5 5 . " L ib e r a tio n f r o m t h e A f f lu e n t S o c ie ty ," 1 9 0 -1 9 1 . O n th e id e a o f
p o litic a l p h ilo s o p h y a s th e r a p y , s e e G e r t r u d e A . S t e u e r n a g e l, Political
Philosophy as Therapy: Marcuse Reconsidered (W e s tp o r t, C o n n .: G r e e n
w o o d P r e ss , 1 9 7 9 ).
56. FL, 8 6 ; RT, 1 1 2 .
57. ODM, 1 5 8 .
58. ODM, 2 3 5 .
59. ODM, 2 2 7 .
60. ODM, 1 5 4 , 2 3 5 .
61. ODM, 1 5 6 - 1 5 8 , 166.
62. FL, 9 6 .
63. AD, 3 6 .
6 4 . M a r a b in i, “ L a R e v o lu t io n d u X X I e sid c le sera p o l t i q u e ,” 3.
Conclusion
1. R e in h a r t! L e tta u , " H e r b e r t M a r c u s e a n d t h e V u lg a r ity o f D e a th ,”
New German Critique, 6 , n o . 3 (F a ll 1 9 7 9 ): 2 0 .
2 . AD, 5 9 .
3 . AD, 6 0 .
Index 149
Index
Aberic, Kathleen, 16 Aspiration, 4, 45, 51, 64, 73, 74
Acton, Jay, 120, 127 Assoun, Paul-Laurent, 115, 122
Acton, Harry Burrows, 127 Atlantis, 28
Adorno, Theodor Wiesengrund, 7, 12, Augustine, Saint, 46
13.75, 7 6 .8 3 -8 6 ,9 6 , 137, 138, 140, Authority, 19, 140
141, 143 Autonomy o f art, 76, 79
Aesthetics, 25, 38-40, 42, 61-67, 69- Axiological neutrality, 85
72, 74-80, 82-86, 88, 104, 109-111,
127, 134-136, 138, 140 Baader-Meinhof, 21
A esth etics D im e n sio n , 2 5 ,6 1-63,77, 111, Babeuf, Gracchus, 28, 34, 36-38, 126
127, 135 Baczko, Bronislaw, 125
Aesthetic form, 75, 76 Baechler, Jean, 96, 143, 144
Affirmative culture, 76 Bahro, Rudolf, 9, 46, 62, 63. 65, 115,
Affluent society, 41, 48, 73, 93, 95, 135
115, 127, 129, 135, 147 Bakunin, Mikhail, 28, 43-45, 58, 128
Agger, Ben, 5, 61, 62. 134 Balint, 15
Aggression, 50, 52 Balzac, Honors de, 40, 64
Albert, Hans, 85 Barbarism, 55, 56, 75, 99, 110, 131
Alexander, Edwin, 15 Barrati, Bruno, 120
Alford, Charles Frederick, 61-63, 65, Bastiat, Frddtfric, 95, 143
134, 135 Bastide, Roger, 59, 134
Alienation, 48, 67, 89, 94 Baudrillard, Jean, 126
Ambiguity, 21, 24, 34, 104 Baumgarten, Alexander Gottlieb, 64
Anarchism, 43, 44 Beauty, 39. 40, 74. 75, 79, 109, 110.
Ansart-Dourlcn, Michdlc, 126 146
Antagonism o f values, 110 Beckett, Samuel Barclay, 113
Anti-art, 69 Beethoven, 75
Antisthenes, 28 Bencton, Philippe, 117
Arato, Andrew, 4, 32, 75, 117, 138 Benjamin, Waller, 7, 16, 64, 71, 83,
Archimedes, 85 84, 116, 119, 135, 140
Arcndt, Hannah, 140 Benoist, Jean-Marie, 34, 125
Aristotle 123, 144 Berger, Bennett, 120, 128, 130
Arnason, J6hann P.111, 9, 15, 116, 118 Bergeron, Gdrard, 120, 128
Aron Raymond, 16, 2 1,2 7 ,3 1 ,4 6 , 89, Bergson, Henri, 54
116, 119, 121, 126, 129, 130, 141, Besnier, Jean-Michel, 41, 127
143, 145 Birou, A., 34, 125
Aronson, Ronald, 121 Blakeley, Thomas J., 123
Art, 1, 2, 4-14, 16-19, 21, 23-25, 27, Bloch, Ernst, 3, 4, 7, 22, 25, 29, 58,
28. 30, 33-35, 37-39. 41. 42, 44-46, 71, 79, 81, 123, 133, 139, 140
48-50, 52, 54-59, 61-81, 83-91, 93, Blueprint, 39, 45, 97
96-98, 100, 102-104, 106, 109-112, Boll, Heinrich, 21, 121
115-118, 120, 121, 123-128, 130- Bordes, Charles, 124
135, 137-141, 143-146 Bourgeois society, 2
Arvon, Henri, 44, 128 Brecht, Arnold, 69, 71
150 Herbert Marcuse's Utopia
Breines, Paul, 58, 118, 120, 133, 135 16, 77, 115
C u ltu r e et s o c itte ,
Buber, Martin, 66, 135 Cuvillier, Armand, 133
Burke, Kenneth, 71
Busino, Giovanni, 144 Davis, Angela, 9, 21, 116
Daydream, 23
Dean, Thomas, 138
Cabet, Etienne, 12, 118 Debray, R£gis, 103
Campagnolo, Umberto, 127 Definite negation, 41, 53, 67, 79
Campbell, Keith, 131 Delaunay, Vadim, 24, 122
Capitalism, 4, II, 16, 22, 41, 47, 48, Delbo, Charlotte, 120
5 1 ,5 9 ,6 3 ,6 7 ,6 8 , 7 1 ,7 6 .7 8 ,8 0 ,9 1 . Democracy, 8, 31, 33, 36-38, 55, 56,
92, 107,115,116, 119,126, 129,130, 89,108, 121,125,126,128,131,132,
134, 135 142, 144
Cardan, Paul, 131 D e r d eu tsch e K u m tle r r o m a n , 10,64, 134,
Carlyle, Thomas, 64 135
Castelli, Enrico, 123, 140 Desroche, Henri, 27, 29, 123, 124
Castoriadis, Cornelius, 132 Dessoir, Max, 65
Castro, Fidel, 7, 16 Desublimation, 81
Certeau, Michel de, 66, 136 Devitis, Joseph Libcralorc, 59, 134
Chase, Richard, 71 Dialectics, 2. 14.22, 4 4 ,4 8 ,5 1 , 54,56.
Chatelet, Francois, 23, 46 7 2 ,7 3 ,7 5 ,8 6 ,9 1 ,9 2 , 115, 117, 118,
Chirpaz, Francois, 80, 140 121, 126, 127, 131, 133-135, 137,
Cioranescu, Alexandre, 27, 28, 1 14, 138, 141
123, 125 D ia le c tic a l I m a g in a tio n , 86, 115, 117,
Clair, Andre, 23, 122 118, 121, 131, 133, 137, 138
Class, 3, 6, 11, 20, 26. 28. 34, 38, 46, Dialectical materialism, 2, 22, 48
48-52, 54, 56-58, 67-70, 82, 93-95, Dilthey, Wilhelm, 11, 54
9 7 ,99, 116, 120, 130, 132, 134, 142 Dion o f Syracuse, 29
Classicism, 68 Disenchntment, 3
Clecak, Peter, 65, 120, 135 Doods, E.R., 124
Cohn-Bendit, 49 Domenach, Jean-Marie, 6, 116
College de France, 44, 120, 128 Domination, 2, 42-44, 51, 56, 70, 91,
Columbia University, 12-14, 59, 120 109
Comic strip, 19, 120 Dufrennc, Michel, 104, 145
Communism, 12, 18, 31, 32, 42, 43, Duhring, Eugen, 56, 132
49, 68, 75, 82-84, 116, 118, 121, 123. Durkheim, Emile, 95
124, 126 Dutschke, Rudi, 18, 21, 22, 103, 121
Comte, Auguste, 95, 134, 143 Dylan, Bob, 76, 98
Confusion, 41, 88, 95, 100-103, 109
Conservatism, 66, 119 Eckstein, George, 121
Cooper, David, 115, 127 Economy, 5, 11-13, 15, 20, 3 1 ,4 4 , 46.
Counter-culture, 3 47, 54, 5 6 .6 9 , 70, 73, 77, 81,88-95,
C o u n te rre v o lu tio n a n d R e v o lt, 25, 61 106, 109, 112, 120, 137
Cranston, Maurice, 37, 126 Education, 29-33, 35. 39, 49. 63, 72.
Critias, 28, 29 80, 104, 111
Critical theory, 1,2,4-6, 13-15,23,40, Educational dictatorship, 31-33, 63
4 1 ,5 1 ,5 5 , 59. 6 1 ,73, 79-82, 91,94. Elleinstein, Jean, 102
100, 115-118, 122, 127, 133, 138, Ellul, Jacques, 2 4 ,4 6 , 119, 122, 129
140,141 Emancipation, 1, 72, 88, 90, 91, 99,
Croisier, Brigitte, 66, 136 108, 109
Culture, 3, 8, 9, 12, 15, 16, 30, 53, 55, End o f an . 75, 76, 79, 81, 83
63-65, 67, 68, 75-77, 80, 82, 104, E n d o f U to p ia , 3. 17, 25, 27, 52, 59. 92,
107, 111, 115, 117, 131, 135, 138- 108, 115
140 Enfantin, 143
Index 151
Engels, Friedrich, 4 ,4 1 ,4 2 ,4 5 ,4 8 ,5 1 , Gerth, H.H., 145
56, 64. 82, 114, 115, 127-132, 137 Gold, Herbert, 119
Enlightenment, 36, 105 Golden age, 37
Environment, 4, 70 Goldmann, Lucien, 57, 133, 141
Erikson, 15 Gomberg, William, 130
Eros, 21, 33, 79, 110, 111, 115, 130, Gorz, Andr£, 92, 142
139, 140 Gould, James A., 137
E ro s a n d C iv iliz a tio n , 14, 1 5 ,2 7 ,3 9 ,4 0 , Graff, Gerald, 71, 136
53, 64, 65, 70, 77 Gramsci, Antonio, 117
Eschatology, 3, 7, 52, 145 Great refusal, 61, 79, 88
E ssa y on L ib e r a tio n , 19, 25, 27, 44, 45 Green, Philip, 44, 125, 128, 147
Essence, 5 6 ,7 1 ,9 8 , 130, 139, 142, 143, Grossman, Henryk, 12
146 Guevara de la Serna, Ernesto (Che),
Established order, 8, 55, 67 103
Ethics, 5. 19. 32. 47, 48, 52. 74. 81. Guillou, Agn£s, 120
9 0 ,9 1 , 105-109, 112, 124, 129, 131, Guinle, J.P., 48, 129
146 Guru, 3, 20, 103
Gusdorf, Georges, 63, 64, 135
ISBN 88772-027-7