Richter, Liselotte (1970) - Jean-Paul Sartre
Richter, Liselotte (1970) - Jean-Paul Sartre
Contents
C hronology 111
N otes 115
v
All dates given in the text, whether for
French originals or their English titles,
refer to the first French publication.
7
Alienation
and Justification:
Roots o f Creativity
TJLt is characteristic of every philosophy of exist
ence that in order to understand it we must pay close
attention to the specific circumstances in which its
author’s existence is inextricably involved. T his is
especially true of the philosophy of Jean-Paul Sartre,
the author of existentialism in the strict sense of the
word. Let us look, then, at Sartre’s face, in a state
of intense mental concentration: the somewhat un
happy and tormented expression, the furrowed fore
head, the stubborn set of his mouth, his absent-
minded right eye straying outward behind its thick
lens. There is about it all an aura of exhaustion, of
homelessness and alienation—the alienation of a lost
or abandoned child who finds himself exposed to
nature and history and there left at the mercy of a
chaos to which he must now, all alone, give meaning
through superhuman work and concentration.
Alone and single-handedly he must create an abso
lutely original design, a bold, unprecedented project
of his life as a person, as an artist, and as a thinker.
As such an individual sees life, every man finds
himself forever on a dreadful proscenium of free
dom, the freedom to which all men are condemned.
Man is forever the absolutely free dramatist staging
the drama of his own life. Sartre himself described
it:
2
Alienation and Justification: Roots of Creativity 3
Or:
Literature was for me, first of all, the search for justification
in the future, the transposition of eternal life; one accepts an
accidental and vague existence, in the present, in order to be
recognized by human society after one's death. . . .
Sophistic R evolt
By now we have learned a good deal of the
roots of Sartre’s convictions: his world without
transcendence, his concern with man alone, his
rejection of the cosmos. T h e great themes of man
kind, such as they present themselves in the history
of philosophy, appear in Sartre’s work only sporad
ically. T h e archaic cosmogony of awakening child
hood is lacking altogether—indeed, he has no feel
ing at all for children. They hardly ever play a part
in his novels, and if they do appear they are in fact
merely small adults. Sartre’s world is made up
16 Jean-Paul Sartre
The Principal
Themes o f
Sartre’s Thought
existing in free self-determination is, so
to speak, no more than an ideal, a model which
never occurs in reality. T h e men who do occur in
reality are a very specific mixture (a marmalade!)
of freedom and the lack of freedom, of being a sub
ject and being an object. They are forever fleeing,
fleeing from the dread of freedom and into the
seriousness of the objective world. In the section of
B ein g and, N othingness explicitly entitled “Ethical
Implications,” Sartre wrote:
“ T h e Chips A re D ow n”
In this light, too, we must understand the
curious contradiction in Sartre’s doctrine of free
dom. I freely choose only myself, he asserts, I alone
establish the rules of the game of my existence; but
in this choice I also want to choose all humanity
and to share in its determination—and all this de
spite my explicit denial of the precedence of es
sence, of the essential idea. Thus I may not, by vir
tue of my choice, impose an essential idea on an
other person; I must allow him the free decision to
establish his own rules. Here Sartre invokes Hegel’s
remark, “If all men are not free, no man is free.”
T h e same holds true of existential freedom which,
Sartre himself has had to admit, is not a complete
freedom from all situational ties. In this sense
Sartre has spoken explicitly of the paradox of free
dom. “It is the paradox of freedom,” he wrote,
"that freedom exists only in the situation, and situ
ation exists only in freedom.”
Sartre thus was unable to carry out his thesis
with that absolute univocity which he had postu
lated. He encountered the dichotomy of m auvaise
The Principal Themes of Sartre's Thought 31
layers of existence, it veils itself, thin and firm, and when you
want to seize it. you find only existents, you butt against
existents devoid of sense. It is behind them: I don't even
hear it. I hear sounds, vibrations in the air which unveil it. It
does not exist because it has nothing superfluous: it is all the
rest which, in relation to it, is superfluous. It is.10
When he set them down, Eve went and touched them in her
turn (she always felt somewhat ridiculous about i t ) . They
had become little bits of dead wood again hut something
vague and incomprehensible stayed in them, something like
understanding. T hese arc his things, she thought. T h ere is
nothing of mine in the room. She had had a few pieces of
furniture before; the m irror and the little inlaid dresser
handed down from her grandmother and which Pierre jok
ingly called “your dresser." Pierre had carried them away
with him.13
Inversion o f A ll P receden t
Thus the traditional view is inverted. Now,
perception and consciousness, world and art are
dominated by the imagination, and not the other
way around. Imagination becomes the primary
function of consciousness, its typical expression by
which it now is analyzed as freedom (spontaneity)
and negation. T h e object is not a stimulus pro
ducing a reaction (Kant’s “being affected’’), because
the object, being nonexistent, has become a
thought. Consciousness, thus, is not part of a causal
relation; rather, it opens up a relation of meaning.
Being free, it rests upon the possibility of with
drawing (rcculer) from reality and positing the
object as nonexistent. “T o posit the world and to
negate it is one and the same act.” T h e world is
transmuted into the unreal and imaginary, the
world situation in which I do so is negated, and this
product of the imagination, according to Sartre, in
turn presents itself at every moment as the meaning
of what is real.
Many of these views have found their way into
modern drama and into surrealism, into sculpture
and poetry. This definition of Sartre changes the
work of art, too, into something unreal. “T h e real
is never beautiful, beauty is a value that can be ap
plied only to the mental image, and this means the
negation of the world in its essential structure.”
Now, nausea in the face of the experience of un-
aesthetic reality becomes the basic experience of
The Principal Thanes of Sartre's Thought 51
Dialogue
with Friend
and Foe
H o w e v e r ready we may be to follow Sartre’s
extraordinary lines of thought, it cannot be denied
that he frequently loses himself in absolutely un
tenable regions, images, and scenes. Even the most
generous appraisal must admit that Sartre goes too
far in using every possible occasion to illustrate
philosophical situations by means of the most re
volting sexual descriptions whose necessity often
remains completely incomprehensible. W e cannot
rid ourselves of the suspicion, then, that Sartre is in
this respect psychopathologically burdened, so that
his thought is virtually blocked.
T h is trend has become more pronounced
through the years. His book Saijit G en et, A ctor and
M artyr obviously represents a unique high point in
this direction. Earlier books had often repelled
even the reader willing to make ample concessions,
by their needless crescendo of repulsive excesses.
“Existential psychoanalysis” does not, after all, en
joy special license to wallow in Neronian scatology,
such as, for example, the sickish sexual experiences
of cripples in T h e R ep riev e. But when it comes to
Saint GenSt, his pornographic descriptions of
homosexual excesses, of the most revolting viola
tions of the law, and of an anarchic lack of convic
tion that leaves Stirner’s anarchism far behind—all
this is beyond discussion. Indeed, there is hardly a
book of Sartre’s without passages that are bound to
provoke the strongest revulsion and objections,
totally lacking in all breeding and good taste,
whether we think of sexual scenes or other matters.
78
Dialogue with Friend and Foe 79
mighty God, who am I other than the fear that the others feel
of m e ?2
T h e D em olition o f Christianity
It was predictable that Sartre would respond
to the justified objections of his partners in the dia
logue 3 with that same topsy-turvy dialectic that he
has demonstrated in philosophy and literature in
ever new variations. T here is, first, the objection of
Christianity, to which Sartre replied by the pecul
iar position he took, and then again failed to take,
with regard to the problem of God. Just as all order
is reversed into its opposite, so the original source
of order, God, must be radically demolished, and
all ethical precepts along with Him. Sartre would
rather be debased into an object, by a man, than
come to terms with the idea of a supreme cause or
an ens a sc. According to him, man is exclusively an
absolute urge for freedom which, however, as we
have seen, is nothing else than spontanditd ndanti-
sante (annihilating spontaneity), directed against
himself and the other. T h e true synthesis between
the for-itself and the in-itsclf could only be God.
Thus the real goal of Sartre's man is to become
God: “T o be man means to reach toward being
God. Or if you prefer, man fundamentally is the
desire to be God. . . . Human reality is the pure
effort to become God, without there being any
84 Jean-Paul Sartre
Christian O pposition
Thus it is worth our while to listen when the
views of Christian thinkers who, after Socrates,
were the first existentialist thinkers—men like St.
Paul, Augustine, Luther, Pascal, Kierkegaard—are
presented in opposition to Sartre. T h e Christian
existentialist Gabriel Marcel in part gives expres
sion to this thinking. T o the mere for-itself and in-
itself he opposes the attitude of the genuine I-Thou
relation whose arch-model is the relation of man to
God, in prayer; in the place of the n ot, he puts the
affirmation that knows its source to be God, and
that against a background of unbelief posits faith;
against a background of hate, love; against a back
ground of treason, loyalty, the readiness for onto
logical permanence.
T h e negative aspects must be taken seriously
for the sake of the positive ones, just as the serious
choice of life can be made only against the back
ground of the temptation to commit suicide. But
Marcel points out that Sartre merely "describes,”
that he is concerned solely with things, "chosiste^
(a thing-like It), and thus gets stranded in agnosti
cism. Sartre’s forever uncompleted man is funda
mentally envious of the in-itsclf of things, and
identifies himself with it. He is a constant lack of
86 Jeatt-Paul Sartre
and then, since it is not the whole chain, can it make any
definite statement about the chain? 5
Ill
112 Chronology
115
116 Notes