Georg W. F. Hegel Encyclopedia of The Philosophical Sciences. Volume 3 Philosophy of Mind 1893
Georg W. F. Hegel Encyclopedia of The Philosophical Sciences. Volume 3 Philosophy of Mind 1893
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no
restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the
terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online
at http://www.gutenberg.org/license
Language: English
Oxford
Clarendon Press
1894
Contents
Preface.
Five Introductory Essays In Psychology And Ethics.
Essay I. On The Scope Of A Philosophy Of Mind.
Essay II. Aims And Methods Of Psychology.
Essay III. On Some Psychological Aspects Of Ethics.
Essay IV. Psycho-Genesis.
Essay V. Ethics And Politics.
Introduction.
Section I. Mind Subjective.
Sub-Section A. Anthropology. The Soul.
Sub-Section B. Phenomenology Of Mind. Consciousness.
Sub-Section C. Psychology. Mind.
Section II. Mind Objective.
Distribution.
Sub-Section A. Law.
Sub-Section B. The Morality Of Conscience.
Sub-Section C. The Moral Life, Or Social Ethics.
Section III. Absolute Mind.
Sub-Section A. Art.
Sub-Section B. Revealed Religion.
Sub-Section C. Philosophy.
Index.
Footnotes
[pg v]
Preface.
The translation is made from the German text given in the Second Part of
the Seventh Volume of Hegel's Collected Works, occasionally corrected by
comparison with that found in the second and third editions (of 1827 and
1830) published by the author. I have reproduced only Hegel's own
paragraphs, and entirely omitted the Zusätze of the editors. These addenda
—which are in origin lecture-notes—to the paragraphs are, in the text of the
Collected Works, given for the first section only. The psychological part
which they accompany has been barely treated elsewhere by Hegel: but a
good popular [pg vi] exposition of it will be found in Erdmann's
Psychologische Briefe. The second section was dealt with at greater length
by Hegel himself in his Philosophy of Law (1820). The topics of the third
section are largely covered by his lectures on Art, Religion, and History of
Philosophy.
I do not conceal from myself that the text offers a hard nut to crack. Yet
here and there, even through the medium of the translation, I think some
light cannot fail to come to an earnest student. Occasionally, too, as, for
instance, in §§ 406, 459, 549, and still more in §§ 552, 573, at the close of
which might stand the words Liberavi animam meam, the writer really “lets
himself go,” and gives his mind freely on questions where speculation
comes closely in touch with life.
In the Five Introductory Essays I have tried sometimes to put together, and
sometimes to provide with collateral elucidation, some points in the Mental
Philosophy. I shall not attempt to justify the selection of subjects for special
treatment further than to hope that they form a more or less connected
group, and to refer for a study of some general questions of system and
method to my Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel's Philosophy which
appear almost simultaneously with this volume.
OXFORD,
December, 1893.
[pg xi]
Five Introductory Essays In Psychology
And Ethics.
[pg xiii]
Essay I. On The Scope Of A Philosophy Of Mind.
The art of finding titles, and of striking out headings which catch the eye or
ear, and lead the mind by easy paths of association to the subject under
exposition, was not one of Hegel's gifts. A stirring phrase, a vivid or
picturesque turn of words, he often has. But his lists of contents, when they
cease to be commonplace, are apt to run into the bizarre and the grotesque.
Generally, indeed, his rubrics are the old and (as we may be tempted to call
them) insignificant terms of the text-books. But, in Hegel's use of them,
these conventional designations are charged with a highly individualised
meaning. They may mean more—they may mean less—than they habitually
pass for: but they unquestionably specify their meaning with a unique and
almost personal flavour. And this can hardly fail to create and to disappoint
undue expectations.
It has sometimes been said that Kant settled this controversy between the
old departments of philosophy and the new branches of science. And the
settlement, it is implied, consisted in assigning to the philosopher a sort of
police and patrol duty in the commonwealth of science. He was to see that
boundaries were duly respected, and that each science kept strictly to its
own business. For this purpose each branch of philosophy was bound to
convert itself into a department of criticism—an examination of first
principles in the several provinces of reality or experience—with a view to
get a distinct conception of what they were, and thus define exactly the
lines on which the structures of more detailed science could be put up
solidly and safely. [pg xvi] This plan offered tempting lines to research, and
sounded well. But on further reflection there emerge one or two difficulties,
hard to get over. Paradoxical though it may seem, one cannot rightly
estimate the capacity and range of foundations, before one has had some
familiarity with the buildings erected upon them. Thus you are involved in a
circle: a circle which is probably inevitable, but which for that reason it is
well to recognise at once. Then—what is only another way of saying the
same thing—it is impossible to draw an inflexible line between premises of
principle and conclusions of detail. There is no spot at which criticism can
stop, and, having done its business well, hand on the remaining task to
dogmatic system. It was an instinctive feeling of this implication of system
in what professed only to be criticism which led the aged Kant to ignore his
own previous professions that he offered as yet no system, and when Fichte
maintained himself to be erecting the fabric for which Kant had prepared
the ground, to reply by the counter-declaration that the criticism was the
system—that “the curtain was the picture.”
In that total process of the mind's liberation and self-realisation the portion
specially called Morals is but one, though a necessary, stage. There are, said
Porphyry and the later Platonists, four degrees in the path of perfection and
self-accomplishment. And first, there is the career of honesty and worldly
prudence, which makes the duty of the citizen. Secondly, there is the
progress in purity which casts earthly things behind, and reaches the angelic
height of passionless serenity. And the third step is the divine life which by
intellectual energy is turned to behold the truth of things. Lastly, in the
fourth grade, the mind, free and sublime in self-sustaining wisdom, makes
itself an “exemplar” of virtue, and is even a “father of Gods.” Even so, it
may be said, the human mind is the subject of a complicated Teleology,—
the field ruled by a multifarious Ought, psychological, aesthetical, social
and religious. To adjust their several claims cannot be the object of any
science, if adjustment means to supply a guide in practice. But it is the
purpose of such a teleology to show that social requirements and moral duty
as ordinarily conceived do not exhaust the range of obligation,—of the
supreme ethical Ought. How that can best be done is however a question of
some difficulty. For the ends under examination do not [pg xxi] fall
completely into a serial order, nor does one involve others in such a way as
to destroy their independence. You cannot absolve psychology as if it stood
independent of ethics or religion, nor can aesthetic considerations merely
supervene on moral. Still, it may be said, the order followed by Hegel
seems on the whole liable to fewer objections than others.
Mr. Herbert Spencer, the only English philosopher who has even attempted
a System of Philosophy, may in this point be compared with Hegel. He also
begins with a First Principles,—a work which, like Hegel's Logic, starts by
presenting Philosophy as the supreme arbiter between the subordinate
principles of Religion and Science, which are in it “necessary correlatives.”
The positive task of philosophy is (with some inconsistency or vagueness)
presented, in the next place, as a “unification of knowledge.” Such a
unification has to make explicit the implicit unity of known reality: because
“every thought involves a whole system of thoughts.” And such a
programme might again suggest the Logic. But unfortunately Mr. Spencer
does not (and he has Francis Bacon to justify him here) think it worth his
while to toil up the weary, but necessary, mount of Purgatory which is
known to us as Logic. With a naïve realism, he builds on Cause and Power,
and above all on Force, that “Ultimate of Ultimates,” which seems to be,
however marvellously, a denizen both of the Known and the Unknowable
world. In the known world this Ultimate appears under two forms, matter
and motion, and the problem of science and philosophy is to lay down in
detail and in general the law of their continuous redistribution, of the
segregation of motion from matter, and the inclusion of motion into matter.
The third part of the Hegelian System corresponds to what in the Synthetic
Philosophy is known as Psychology, Ethics, and Sociology. And here Mr.
Spencer recognises that something new has turned up. Psychology is
“unique” as a science: it is a “double science,” and as a whole quite sui
generis. Whether perhaps all these epithets would not, mutatis mutandis,
have to be applied also to Ethics and Sociology, if these are to do their full
work, he does not say. In what this doubleness consists he even finds it
somewhat difficult to show. For, as his fundamental philosophy does not on
this point go beyond noting some pairs of verbal antitheses, and has no
sense of unity except in the imperfect shape of a “relation3” between two
things which are “antithetical [pg xxiii] and inseparable,” he is perplexed by
phrases such as “in” and “out of” consciousness, and stumbles over the
equivocal use of “inner” to denote both mental (or non-spatial) in general,
and locally sub-cuticular in special. Still, he gets so far as to see that the law
of consciousness is that in it neither feelings nor relations have independent
subsistence, and that the unit of mind does not begin till what he calls two
feelings are made one. The phraseology may be faulty, but it shows an
inkling of the a priori. Unfortunately it is apparently forgotten; and the
language too often reverts into the habit of what he calls the “objective,” i.e.
purely physical, sciences.
The first Section deals with the range of what is usually termed Psychology.
That term indeed is employed by Hegel, in a restricted sense, to denote the
last of the three sub-sections in the discussion of Subjective Mind. The
Mind, which is the topic of psychology proper, cannot be assumed as a
ready-made object, or datum. A Self, a self-consciousness, an intelligent
and volitional agent, if it be the birthright of man, is a birthright which he
has to realise for himself, to earn and to make his own. To trace the steps by
which [pg xxv] mind in its stricter acceptation, as will and intelligence,
emerges from the general animal sensibility which is the crowning phase of
organic life, and the final problem of biology, is the work of two
preliminary sub-sections—the first entitled Anthropology, the second the
Phenomenology of Mind.
At this point, perhaps, having rounded off by a liberal sweep the scope of
psychology, the ordinary mental philosophy would stop. Hegel, instead of
finishing, now goes on to the field of what he calls Objective Mind. For as
yet it has been only the story of a preparation, an inward adorning and
equipment, and we have yet to see what is to come of it in actuality. Or
rather, we have yet to consider the social forms on which this preparation
rests. The mind, self-possessed and sure of itself or free, is so only through
the objective shape which its main development runs parallel with. An
intelligent Will, or a practical reason, was the last word of the psychological
development. But a reason which is practical, or a volition which is
intelligent, is realised by action which takes regular shapes, and by practice
which transforms the world. The theory of Objective Mind delineates the
new form which nature assumes under the sway of intelligence and will.
That intellectual world realises itself by transforming the physical into a
social and political world, the given natural conditions of existence into a
freely-instituted system of life, the primitive struggle of kinds for
subsistence into the ordinances of the social state. Given man as a being
possessed of will and intelligence, this inward faculty, whatever be its
degree, will try to impress itself on nature and to reproduce itself in a legal,
a moral, and social world. The kingdom of deed replaces, or rises on the
foundation of, the kingdom of word: and instead of the equilibrium of a
well-adjusted soul comes the harmonious life of a social organism. We are,
in short, in the sphere of Ethics and Politics, of Jurisprudence and Morals,
of Law and Conscience.
[pg xxix]
Here,—as always in Hegel's system—there is a triad of steps. First the
province of Law or Right. But if we call it Law, we must keep out of sight
the idea of a special law-giver, of a conscious imposition of laws, above all
by a political superior. And if we call it Right, we must remember that it is
neutral, inhuman, abstract right: the right whose principle is impartial and
impassive uniformity, equality, order;—not moral right, or the equity which
takes cognisance of circumstances, of personal claims, and provides against
its own hardness. The intelligent will of Man, throwing itself upon the mere
gifts of nature as their appointed master, creates the world of Property—of
things instrumental, and regarded as adjectival, to the human personality.
But the autonomy of Reason (which is latent in the will) carries with it
certain consequences. As it acts, it also, by its inherent quality of uniformity
or universality, enacts for itself a law and laws, and creates the realm of
formal equality or order-giving law. But this is a mere equality: which is not
inconsistent with what in other respects may be excess of inequality. What
one does, if it is really to be treated as done, others may or even must do:
each act creates an expectation of continuance and uniformity of behaviour.
The doer is bound by it, and others are entitled to do the like. The material
which the person appropriates creates a system of obligation. Thus is
constituted—in the natural give and take of rational Wills—in the inevitable
course of human action and reaction,—a system of rights and duties. This
law of equality—the basis of justice, and the seed of benevolence—is the
scaffolding or perhaps rather the rudimentary framework of society and
moral life. Or it is the bare skeleton which is to be clothed upon by the
softer and fuller outlines of the social tissues and the ethical organs.
[pg xxx]
And thus the first range of Objective Mind postulates the second, which
Hegel calls “Morality.” The word is to be taken in its strict sense as a
protest against the quasi-physical order of law. It is the morality of
conscience and of the good will, of the inner rectitude of soul and purpose,
as all-sufficient and supreme. Here is brought out the complementary factor
in social life: the element of liberty, spontaneity, self-consciousness. The
motto of mere inward morality (as opposed to the spirit of legality) is (in
Kant's words): “There is nothing without qualification good, in heaven or
earth, but only a good will.” The essential condition of goodness is that the
action be done with purpose and intelligence, and in full persuasion of its
goodness by the conscience of the agent. The characteristic of Morality thus
described is its essential inwardness, and the sovereignty of the conscience
over all heteronomy. Its justification is that it protests against the authority
of a mere external or objective order, subsisting and ruling in separation
from the subjectivity. Its defect is the turn it gives to this assertion of the
rights of subjective conscience: briefly in the circumstance that it tends to
set up a mere individualism against a mere universalism, instead of
realising the unity and essential interdependence of the two.
But what Hegel chiefly deals with under this head is the interdependence of
form and content, of social order and personal progress. In the picture of an
ethical organisation or harmoniously-alive moral community he shows us
partly the underlying idea which gave room for the antithesis between law
and conscience, and partly the outlines of the ideal in which that conflict
becomes only the instrument of progress. This organisation [pg xxxii] has
three grades or three typical aspects. These are the Family, Civil Society,
and the State. The first of these, the Family, must be taken to include those
primary unities of human life where the natural affinity of sex and the
natural ties of parentage are the preponderant influence in forming and
maintaining the social group. This, as it were, is the soul-nucleus of social
organisation: where the principle of unity is an instinct, a feeling, an
absorbing solidarity. Next comes what Hegel has called Civil Society,—
meaning however by civil the antithesis to political, the society of those
who may be styled bourgeois, not citoyens:—and meaning by society the
antithesis to community. There are other natural influences binding men
together besides those which form the close unities of the family, gens,
tribe, or clan. Economical needs associate human beings within a much
larger radius—in ways capable of almost indefinite expansion—but also in
a way much less intense and deep. Civil Society is the more or less loosely
organised aggregate of such associations, which, if, on one hand, they keep
human life from stagnating in the mere family, on another, accentuate more
sharply the tendency to competition and the struggle for life. Lastly, in the
Political State comes the synthesis of family and society. Of the family; in
so far as the State tends to develope itself on the nature-given unit of the
Nation (an extended family, supplementing as need arises real descent by
fictitious incorporations), and has apparently never permanently maintained
itself except on the basis of a predominant common nationality. Of society;
in so far as the extension and dispersion of family ties have left free room
for the differentiation of many other sides of human interest and action, and
given ground for the full development of individuality. In consequence of
[pg xxxiii] this, the State (and such a state as Hegel describes is essentially
the idea or ideal of the modern State)9 has a certain artificial air about it. It
can only be maintained by the free action of intelligence: it must make its
laws public: it must bring to consciousness the principles of its constitution,
and create agencies for keeping up unity of organisation through the several
separate provinces or contending social interests, each of which is inclined
to insist on the right of home mis-rule.
But the God of the State is a mortal God. It is but a national and a limited
mind. To be actual, one must at least begin by restricting oneself. Or, rather
actuality is rational, but always with a conditioned and a relative
rationality12: it is in the realm of action and re-action,—in the realm of
change and nature. It has warring forces outside it,—warring forces inside
it. Its unity is never perfect: because it never produces a true identity of
interests within, or maintains an absolute independence without. Thus the
true and real State—the State in its Idea—the realisation of concrete
humanity,—of Mind as the fullness and unity of nature—is not reached in
any single or historical State: but floats away, when we try to seize it, into
the endless progress of history. Always indeed the State, the historical and
objective, points beyond itself. It does so first in the succession of times.
Die Weltgeschichte ist das Weltgericht.13 And in that doom of the world the
eternal blast sweeps along the successive generations of the temporal, one
expelling another from the stage of time—each because it is inadequate to
the Idea which it tried to express, and has succumbed to an [pg xxxv]
enemy from without because it was not a real and true unity within.
So, again, religion does not supervene upon an [pg xxxvii] already existing
political and moral system and invest it with an additional sanction. The
true order would be better described as the reverse. The real basis of social
life, and even of intelligence, is religion. As some thinkers quaintly put it,
the known rests and lives on the bosom of the Unknowable. But when we
say that, we must at once guard against a misconception. There are religions
of all sorts; and some of them which are most heard of in the modern world
only exist or survive in the shape of a traditional name and venerated creed
which has lost its power. Nor is a religion necessarily committed to a
definite conception of a supernatural—of a personal power outside the
order of Nature. But in all cases, religion is a faith and a theory which gives
unity to the facts of life, and gives it, not because the unity is in detail
proved or detected, but because life and experience in their deepest reality
inexorably demand and evince such a unity to the heart. The religion of a
time is not its nominal creed, but its dominant conviction of the meaning of
reality, the principle which animates all its being and all its striving, the
faith it has in the laws of nature and the purpose of life. Dimly or clearly
felt and perceived, religion has for its principle (one cannot well say, its
object) not the unknowable, but the inner unity of life and knowledge, of act
and consciousness, a unity which is certified in its every knowledge, but is
never fully demonstrable by the summation of all its ascertained items. As
such a felt and believed synthesis of the world and life, religion is the unity
which gives stability and harmony to the social sphere; just as morality in
its turn gives a partial and practical realisation to the ideal of religion. But
religion does not merely establish and sanction morality; it also frees it
from a certain narrowness it [pg xxxviii] always has, as of the earth. Or,
otherwise put, morality has to the keener inspection something in it which is
more than the mere moral injunction at first indicates. Beyond the moral, in
its stricter sense, as the obligatory duty and the obedience to law, rises and
expands the beautiful and the good: a beautiful which is disinterestedly
loved, and a goodness which has thrown off all utilitarian relativity, and
become a free self-enhancing joy. The true spirit of religion sees in the
divine judgment not a mere final sanction to human morality which has
failed of its earthly close, not the re-adjustment of social and political
judgments in accordance with our more conscientious inner standards, but a
certain, though, for our part-by-part vision, incalculable proportion between
what is done and suffered. And in this liberation of the moral from its
restrictions, Art renders no slight aid. Thus in different ways, religion
presupposes morality to fill up its vacant form, and morality presupposes
religion to give its laws an ultimate sanction, which at the same time points
beyond their limitations.
But art, religion, and philosophy still rest on the national culture and on the
individual mind. However much they rise in the heights of the ideal world,
they never leave the reality of life and circumstance behind, and float in the
free empyrean. Yet there are degrees of universality, degrees in which they
reach what they promised. As the various psychical nuclei of an individual
consciousness tend through the course of experience to gather round a
central idea and by fusion and assimilation form a complete mental
organisation; so, through the march of history, there grows up a
complication and a fusion of national ideas and aspirations, which, though
still retaining the individuality and restriction of a concrete national life,
ultimately present [pg xxxix] an organisation social, aesthetic, and religious
which is a type of humanity in its universality and completeness. Always
moving in the measure and on the lines of the real development of its social
organisation, the art and religion of a nation tend to give expression to what
social and political actuality at its best but imperfectly sets in existence.
They come more and more to be, not mere competing fragments as set side
by side with those of others, but comparatively equal and complete
representations of the many-sided and many-voiced reality of man and the
world. Yet always they live and flourish in reciprocity with the fullness of
practical institutions and individual character. An abstractly universal art
and religion is a delusion—until all diversities of geography and climate, of
language and temperament, have been made to disappear. If these energies
are in power and reality and not merely in name, they cannot be applied like
a panacea or put on like a suit of ready-made clothes. If alive, they grow
with individualised type out of the social situation: and they can only attain
a vulgar and visible universality, so far as they attach themselves to some
simple and uniform aspects,—a part tolerably identical everywhere—in
human nature in all times and races.
But Religion (thus widely understood as the faith in sempiternal and all-
explaining reality) at first appears under a guise of Art. The poem and the
pyramid, the temple-image and the painting, the drama and the fairy legend,
these are religion: but they are, perhaps, religion as Art. And that means
that they present the eternal under sensible representations, the work of an
artist, and in a perishable material of limited range. Yet even the carvers of
a long-past day whose works have been disinterred from the plateaux of
Auvergne knew that they gave to the perishable life around them a quasi-
immortality: and the myth-teller of a savage tribe elevated the incident of a
season into a perennial power of love and fear. The cynic may remind us
that from the finest picture of the artist, readily
“We turn
To yonder girl that fords the burn.”
[pg xlii]
And yet it may be said in reply to the cynic that, had it not been for the
deep-imprinted lesson of the artist, it would have been but a brutal instinct
that would have drawn our eyes. The artist, the poet, the musician, reveal
the meaning, the truth, the reality of the world: they teach us, they help us,
backward younger brothers, to see, to hear, to feel what our rude senses had
failed to detect. They enact the miracle of the loaves and fishes, again and
again: out of the common limited things of every day they produce a bread
of life in which the generations continue to find nourishment.
But if Art embodies for us the unseen and the eternal, it embodies it in the
stone, the colour, the tone, and the word: and these are by themselves only
dead matter. To the untutored eye and taste the finest picture-gallery is only
a weariness: when the national life has drifted away, the sacred book and
the image are but idols and enigmas. “The statues are now corpses from
which the vivifying soul has fled, and the hymns are words whence faith
has departed: the tables of the Gods are without spiritual meat and drink,
and games and feasts no longer afford the mind its joyful union with the
being of being. The works of the Muse lack that intellectual force which
knew itself strong and real by crushing gods and men in its winepress. They
are now (in this iron age) what they are for us,—fair fruits broken from the
tree, and handed to us by a kindly destiny. But the gift is like the fruits
which the girl in the picture presents: she does not give the real life of their
existence, not the tree which bore them, not the earth and the elements
which entered into their substance, nor the climate which formed their
quality, nor the change of seasons which governed the process of their
growth. Like her, Destiny in giving us the works of ancient art does not give
us their world, [pg xliii] not the spring and summer of the ethical life in
which they blossomed and ripened, but solely a memory and a suggestion
of this actuality. Our act in enjoying them, therefore, is not a Divine service:
were it so, our mind would achieve its perfect and satisfying truth. All that
we do is a mere externalism, which from these fruits wipes off some rain-
drop, some speck of dust, and which, in place of the inward elements of
moral actuality that created and inspired them, tries from the dead elements
of their external reality, such as language and historical allusion, to set up a
tedious mass of scaffolding, not in order to live ourselves into them, but
only to form a picture of them in our minds. But as the girl who proffers the
plucked fruits is more and nobler than the natural element with all its details
of tree, air, light, &c. which first yielded them, because she gathers all this
together, in a nobler way, into the glance of the conscious eye and the
gesture which proffers them; so the spirit of destiny which offers us those
works of art is more than the ethical life and actuality of the ancient people:
for it is the inwardising of that mind which in them was still self-estranged
and self-dispossessed:—it is the spirit of tragic destiny, the destiny which
collects all those individualised gods and attributes of substance into the
one Pantheon. And that temple of all the gods is Mind conscious of itself as
mind17.”
Religion enters into its more adequate form when it ceases to appear in the
guise of Art and realises that the kingdom of God is within, that the truth
must be felt, the eternal inwardly revealed, the holy one apprehended by
faith18, not by outward vision. Eye hath not seen, nor ear heard, the things of
God. They cannot [pg xliv] be presented, or delineated: they come only in
the witness of the spirit. The human soul itself is the only worthy temple of
the Most High, whom heaven, and the heaven of heavens, cannot contain.
Here in truth God has come down to dwell with men; and the Son of Man,
caught up in the effusion of the Spirit, can in all assurance and all humility
claim that he is divinified. Here apparently Absolute Mind is reached: the
soul knows no limitation, no struggle: in time it is already eternal. Yet, there
is, according to Hegel, a flaw,—not in the essence and the matter, but in the
manner and mode in which the ordinary religious consciousness represents
to itself, or pictures that unification which it feels and experiences.
“In religion then this unification of ultimate Being with the Self is
implicitly reached. But the religious consciousness, if it has this symbolic
idea of its reconciliation, still has it as a mere symbol or representation. It
attains the satisfaction by tacking on to its pure negativity, and that
externally, the positive signification of its unity with the ultimate Being: its
satisfaction remains therefore tainted by the antithesis of another world. Its
own reconciliation, therefore, is presented to its consciousness as something
far away, something far away in the future: just as the reconciliation which
the other Self accomplished appears as a far-away thing in the past. The one
Divine Man had but an implicit father and only an actual mother;
conversely the universal divine man, the community, has its own deed and
knowledge for its father, but for its mother only the eternal Love, which it
only feels, but does not behold in its consciousness as an actual immediate
object. Its reconciliation therefore is in its heart, but still at variance with its
consciousness, and its actuality still has a flaw. In its field of consciousness
the place of [pg xlv] implicit reality or side of pure mediation is taken by
the reconciliation that lies far away behind: the place of the actually present,
or the side of immediacy and existence, is filled by the world which has still
to wait for its transfiguration to glory. Implicitly no doubt the world is
reconciled with the eternal Being; and that Being, it is well known, no
longer looks upon the object as alien to it, but in its love sees it as like itself.
But for self-consciousness this immediate presence is not yet set in the full
light of mind. In its immediate consciousness accordingly the spirit of the
community is parted from its religious: for while the religious
consciousness declares that they are implicitly not parted, this implicitness
is not raised to reality and not yet grown to absolute self-certainty19.”
“That process of the mind's self-realisation” says Hegel in the close of his
Phenomenology, “exhibits a lingering movement and succession of minds, a
gallery of images, each of which, equipped with the complete wealth of
mind, only seems to linger because the Self has to penetrate and to digest
this wealth of its Substance. As its perfection consists in coming completely
to know what it is (its substance), this knowledge is its self-involution in
which it deserts its outward existence and surrenders its shape to
recollection. Thus self-involved, it is sunk in the night of its self-
consciousness: but in that night its vanished being is preserved, and that
being, thus in idea preserved,—old, but now new-born of the spirit,—is the
new sphere of being, a new world, a new phase of mind. In this new phase
it has again to begin afresh and from the beginning, and again nurture itself
to maturity from its [pg xlviii] own resources, as if for it all that preceded
were lost, and it had learned nothing from the experience of the earlier
minds. Yet is that recollection a preservation of experience: it is the
quintessence, and in fact a higher form, of the substance. If therefore this
new mind appears only to count on its own resources, and to start quite
fresh and blank, it is at the same time on a higher grade that it starts. The
intellectual and spiritual realm, which is thus constructed in actuality, forms
a succession in time, where one mind relieved another of its watch, and
each took over the kingdom of the world from the preceding. The purpose
of that succession is to reveal the depth, and that depth is the absolute
comprehension of mind: this revelation is therefore to uplift its depth, to
spread it out in breadth, so negativing this self-involved Ego, wherein it is
self-dispossessed or reduced to substance. But it is also its time: the course
of time shows this dispossession itself dispossessed, and thus in its
extension it is no less in its depth, the self. The way to that goal,—absolute
self-certainty—or the mind knowing itself as mind—is the inwardising of
the minds, as they severally are in themselves, and as they accomplish the
organisation of their realm. Their conservation,—regarded on the side of its
free and apparently contingent succession of fact—is history: on the side of
their comprehended organisation, again, it is the science of mental
phenomenology: the two together, comprehended history, form at once the
recollection and the grave-yard of the absolute Mind, the actuality, truth,
and certitude of his throne, apart from which he were lifeless and alone.”
Such in brief outline—lingering most on the points where Hegel has here
been briefest—is the range of the Philosophy of Mind. Its aim is to
comprehend, not to explain: to put together in intelligent unity, [pg xlix] not
to analyse into a series of elements. For it psychology is not an analysis or
description of mental phenomena, of laws of association, of the growth of
certain powers and ideas, but a “comprehended history” of the formation of
subjective mind, of the intelligent, feeling, willing self or ego. For it Ethics
is part and only part of the great scheme or system of self-development; but
continuing into greater concreteness the normal endowment of the
individual mind, and but preparing the ground on which religion may be
most effectively cultivated. And finally Religion itself, released from its
isolation and other-world sacrosanctity, is shown to be only the crown of
life, the ripest growth of actuality, and shown to be so by philosophy, whilst
it is made clear that religion is the basis of philosophy, or that a philosophy
can only go as far as the religious stand-point allows. The hierarchy, if so it
be called, of the spiritual forces is one where none can stand alone, or claim
an abstract and independent supremacy. The truth of egoism is the truth of
altruism: the truly moral is the truly religious: and each is not what it
professes to be unless it anticipate the later, or include the earlier.
It may be said, however, that for such a range of subjects the term Mind is
wretchedly inadequate and common-place, and that the better rendering of
the title would be Philosophy of Spirit. It may be admitted that Mind is not
all that could be wished. But neither is Spirit blameless. And, it may be
added, Hegel's [pg l] own term Geist has to be unduly strained to cover so
wide a region. It serves—and was no doubt meant to serve—as a sign of the
conformity of his system with the religion which sees in God no other-
world being, but our very self and mind, and which worships him in spirit
and in truth. And if the use of a word like this could allay the “ancient
variance” between the religious and the philosophic mood, it would be but
churlish perhaps to refuse the sign of compliance and compromise. But
whatever may be the case in German,—and even there the new wine was
dangerous to the old wine-skin—it is certain that to average English ears
the word Spiritual would carry us over the medium line into the proper land
of religiosity. And to do that, as we have seen, is to sin against the central
idea: the idea that religion is of one blood with the whole mental family,
though the most graciously complete of all the sisters. Yet, however the
word may be chosen, the philosophy of Hegel, like the august lady who
appeared in vision to the emprisoned Boëthius, has on her garment a sign
which “signifies the life which is on earth,” as also a sign which signifies
the “right law of heaven”; if her right-hand holds the “book of the justice of
the King omnipotent,” the sceptre in her left is “corporal judgment against
sin20.”
“voice proclaims
How exquisitely the individual Mind
(And the progressive powers perhaps no less
Of the whole species) to the external World
Is fitted;—and how exquisitely too
The external World is fitted to the Mind;
And the creation (by no lower name
Can it be called) which they with blended might
Accomplish.”
The verse which expounds that “high argument” speaks
“As we look
Into our Minds, into the Mind of Man—
My haunt, and the main region of my song;
Beauty—a living Presence of the earth
Surpassing the most fair ideal forms
... waits upon my steps.”
“That inspires
The human Soul of universal earth
Dreaming of things to come”
will be a greater glory than the ideals of imaginative fiction ever fancied:
[pg lii]
If Wordsworth, thus, as it were, echoing the great conception of Francis
Bacon,
[pg liii]
Essay II. Aims And Methods Of Psychology.
It is not going too far to say that in common estimation psychology has as
yet hardly reached what Kant has called the steady walk of science—der
sichere Gang der Wissenschaft. To assert this is not, of course, to throw any
doubts on the importance of the problems, or on the intrinsic value of the
results, in the studies which have been prosecuted under that name. It is
only to note the obvious fact that a number of inquiries of somewhat
discrepant tone, method, and tendency have all at different times covered
themselves under the common title of psychological, and that the work of
orientation is as yet incomplete. Such a destiny seems inevitable, when a
name is coined rather as the title of an unexplored territory, than fixed on to
describe an accomplished fact.
The De Anima of Aristotle, gathering up into one the work of Plato and his
predecessors, may be said to lay the foundation of psychology. But even in
it, we can already see that there are two elements or aspects struggling for
mastery: two elements not unrelated or [pg liv] independent, but hard to
keep fairly and fully in unity. On one hand there is the conception of Soul
as a part of Nature, as a grade of existence in the physical or natural
universe,—in the universe of things which suffer growth and change, which
are never entirely “without matter,” and are always attached to or present in
body. From this point of view Aristotle urged that a sound and realistic
psychology must, e.g. in its definition of a passion, give the prominent
place to its physical (or material) expression, and not to its mental form or
significance. It must remember, he said, that the phenomena or “accidents”
are what really throw light on the nature or the “substance” of the Soul. On
the other hand, there are two points to be considered. There is, first of all,
the counterpoising remark that the conception of Soul as such, as a unity
and common characteristic, will be determinative of the phenomena or
“accidents,”—will settle, as it were, what we are to observe and look for,
and how we are to describe our observations. And by the conception of
Soul, is meant not a soul, as a thing or agent (subject) which has properties
attaching to it; but soul, as the generic feature, the universal, which is set as
a stamp on everything that claims to be psychical. In other words, Soul is
one, not as a single thing contrasted with its attributes, activities, or
exercises of force (such single thing will be shown by logic to be a
metaphysical fiction); but as the unity of form and character, the
comprehensive and identical feature, which is present in all its
manifestations and exercises. But there is a second consideration. The
question is asked by Aristotle whether it is completely and strictly accurate
to put Soul under the category of natural objects. There is in it, or of it,
perhaps, something, and something essential to it, which belongs to the
order of the eternal and self-active: [pg lv] something which is “form” and
“energy” quite unaffected by and separate from “matter.” How this is
related to the realm of the perishable and changeable is a problem on which
Aristotle has been often (and with some reason) believed to be obscure, if
not even inconsistent21.
But even at the best, such a popular or empirical psychology has no special
claim to be ranked as science. It may no doubt be said that at least it
collects, describes, or notes down facts. But even this is not so certain as it
seems. Its so-called facts are very largely fictions, or so largely interpolated
with error, that they cannot be safely used for construction. If psychology is
to accomplish anything valuable, it must go more radically to work. It must
—at least in a measure—discard from its preliminary view the data of
common and current distinctions, and try to get at something more primary
or ultimate as its starting-point. And this it may do in [pg lvii] two ways. It
may, in the one case, follow the example of the physical sciences. In these it
is the universal practice to assume that the explanation of complex and
concrete facts is to be attained by (a) postulating certain simple elements
(which we may call atoms, molecules, and perhaps units or monads), which
are supposed to be clearly conceivable and to justify themselves by intrinsic
intelligibility, and by (b) assuming that these elements are compounded and
combined according to laws which again are in the last resort self-evident,
or such that they seem to have an obvious and palpable lucidity. Further,
such laws being always axioms or plain postulates of mechanics (for these
alone possess this feature of self-evident intelligibility), they are subject to
and invite all the aids and refinements of the higher mathematical calculus.
What the primary and self-explicative bits of psychical reality may be, is a
further question on which there may be some dispute. They may be, so to
say, taken in a more physical or in a more metaphysical way: i.e. more as
units of nerve-function or more as elements of ideative-function. And there
may be differences as to how far and in what provinces the mathematical
calculus may be applicable. But, in any case, there will be a strong tendency
in psychology, worked on this plan, to follow, mutatis mutandis, and at
some distance perhaps, the analogy of material physics. In both the
justification of the postulated units and laws will be their ability to describe
and systematise the observed phenomena in a uniform and consistent way.
The other way in which psychology gets a foundation and ulterior certainty
is different, and goes deeper. After all, the “scientific” method is only a way
in which the facts of a given sphere are presented in thoroughgoing
interconnexion, each reduced to an exact multiple [pg lviii] or fraction of
some other, by an inimitably continued subtraction and addition of an
assumed homogeneous element, found or assumed to be perfectly
imaginable (conceivable). But we may also consider the province in relation
to the whole sphere of reality, may ask what is its place and meaning in the
whole, what reality is in the end driving at or coming to be, and how far this
special province contributes to that end. If we do this, we attach psychology
to philosophy, or, if we prefer so to call it, to metaphysics, as in the former
way we established it on the principles generally received as governing the
method of the physical sciences.
Such a collected and united theory of reality (it is what Hegel has
designated the Idea) is what is understood by a natural metaphysic. It has
nothing necessarily to do with a supersensible or a supernatural, if these
words mean a ghostly, materialised, but super-finely-materialised nature,
above and beyond the present. But that there is a persistent tendency to
conceive the unity and coherence, the theoretic idea of reality, [pg lx] in this
pseudo-sensuous (i.e. super-sensuous) form, is of course a well-known fact.
For the present, however, this aberration—this idol of the tribe—may be left
out of sight. By a metaphysic or fundamental philosophy, is, in the present
instance, meant a system of first principles—a secular and cosmic creed: a
belief in ends and values, a belief in truth—again premising that the system
in question is, for most, a rudely organised and almost inarticulate mass of
belief and hope, conviction and impression. It is, in short, a natural
metaphysic: a metaphysic, that is, which has but an imperfect coherence,
which imperfectly realises both its nature and its limits.
In certain parts, however, it is more and better than this crude background
of belief. Each science—or at least every group of sciences—has a more
definite system or aggregate of first principles, axioms, and conceptions
belonging to it. It has, that is,—and here in a much distincter way—its
special standard of reality, its peculiar forms of conceiving things, its
distinctions between the actual and the apparent, &c. Here again it will
probably be found that the scientific specialist is hardly conscious that these
are principles and concepts: on the contrary, they will be supposed self-
evident and ultimate facts, foundations of being. Instead of being treated as
modes of conception, more or less justified by their use and their results,
these categories will be regarded as fundamental facts, essential conditions
of all reality. Like popular thought in its ingrained categories, the specialist
cannot understand the possibility of any limitation to his radical ideas of
reality. To him they are not hypotheses, but principles. The scientific
specialist may be as convinced of the universal application of his peculiar
categories, as the Chinese or the Eskimo that his standards are natural and
final.
[pg lxi]
Under such metaphysical or extra-empirical presuppositions all
investigation, whether it be crudely empirical or (in the physical sense)
scientific, is carried on. And when so carried on, it is said to be prosecuted
apart from any interference from metaphysic. Such a naïve or natural
metaphysic, not raised to explicit consciousness, not followed as an
imposed rule, but governing with the strength of an immanent faith, does
not count for those who live under it as a metaphysic at all. M. Jourdain was
amazed suddenly to learn he had been speaking prose for forty years
without knowing it. But in the present case there is something worse than
amazement sure to be excited by the news. For the critic who thus reveals
the secrets of the scientist's heart is pretty sure to go on to say that a good
deal of this naïve unconscious metaphysic is incoherent, contradictory, even
bad: that it requires correction, revision, and readjustment, and has by
criticism to be made one and harmonious. That readjustment or criticism
which shall eliminate contradiction and produce unity, is the aim of the
science of metaphysic—the science of the meta-physical element in
physical knowledge: what Hegel has chosen to call the Science of Logic (in
the wide sense of the term). This higher Logic, this science of metaphysic,
is the process to revise and harmonise in systematic completeness the
imperfect or misleading and partial estimates of reality which are to be
found in popular and scientific thought.
In the case of the run of physical sciences this revision is less necessary;
and for no very recondite reason. Every science by its very nature deals
with a special, a limited topic. It is confined to a part or aspect of reality. Its
propositions are not complete truths; they apply to an artificial world, to a
part expressly cut off from the concrete reality. Its principles [pg lxii] are
generally cut according to their cloth,—according to the range in which
they apply. The only danger that can well arise is if these categories are
transplanted without due reservations, and made of universal application,
i.e. if the scientist elects on his speciality to pronounce de omnibus rebus.
But in the case of psychology and ethics the harmlessness of natural
metaphysics will be less certain. Here a general human or universal interest
is almost an inevitable coefficient: especially if they really rise to the full
sweep of the subject. For as such they both seem to deal not with a part of
reality, but with the very centre and purpose of all reality. In them we are
not dealing with topics of secondary interest, but with the very heart of the
human problem. Here the questions of reality and ideals, of unity and
diversity, and of the evaluation of existence, come distinctly to the fore. If
psychology is to answer the question, What am I? and ethics the question,
What ought I to do? they can hardly work without some formulated creed of
metaphysical character, without some preliminary criticisms of current first
principles.
(ii.) Herbart.
The German thinker, who has given perhaps the most fruitful stimulus to
the scientific study of psychology in modern times—Johann Friedrich
Herbart—is after all essentially a philosopher, and not a mere scientist, even
in his psychology. His psychological inquiry, that is, stands in intimate
connexion with the last questions of all intelligence, with metaphysics and
[pg lxiii] ethics. The business of philosophy, says Herbart, is to touch up
and finish off conceptions (Bearbeitung der Begriffe)22. It finds, as it
supervenes upon the unphilosophical world, that mere and pure facts (if
there ever are or were such purisms) have been enveloped in a cloud of
theory, have been construed into some form of unity, but have been
imperfectly, inadequately construed: and that the existing concepts in
current use need to be corrected, supplemented and readjusted. It has,
accordingly, for its work to “reconcile experience with itself23,” and to elicit
“the hidden pre-suppositions without which the fact of experience is
unthinkable.” Psychology, then, as a branch of this philosophic enterprise,
has to readjust the facts discovered in inner experience. For mere uncritical
experience or merely empirical knowledge only offers problems; it suggests
gaps, which indeed further reflection serves at first only to deepen into
contradictions. Such a psychology is “speculative”: i.e. it is not content to
accept the mere given, but goes forward and backward to find something
that will make the fact intelligible. It employs totally different methods
from the “classification, induction, analogy” familiar to the logic of the
empirical sciences. Its “principles,” therefore, are not given facts: but facts
which have been manipulated and adjusted so as to lose their self-
contradictory quality: they are facts “reduced,” by introducing the omitted
relationships which they postulate if they are to be true and self-consistent24.
While it is far from rejecting or ignoring experience, therefore, psychology
cannot strictly be said to build upon it alone. It uses experimental fact as an
unfinished datum,—or it sees in [pg lxiv] experience a torso which betrays
its imperfection, and suggests completing.
The place of the conception of the Ego in Kant's and Fichte's theory of
knowledge is well known. Equally well known is Kant's treatment of the
soul-reality or soul-substance in his examination of Rational Psychology.
Whereas the (logical) unity of consciousness, or “synthetic unity of
apperception,” is assumed as a fundamental starting-point in explanation of
our objective judgments, or of our knowledge of objective existence, its real
(as opposed to its formal) foundation in a “substantial” soul is set aside as
an illegitimate [pg lxv] interpretation of, or inference from, the facts of
inner experience. The belief in the separate unity and persistence of the
soul, said Kant, is not a scientifically-warranted conclusion. Its true place is
as an ineffaceable postulate of the faith which inspires human life and
action. Herbart did not rest content with either of these—as he believed—
dogmatic assumptions of his master. He did not fall in cheerfully with the
idealism which seemed ready to dispense with a soul, or which justified its
acceptance of empirical reality by referring to the fundamental unity of the
function of judgment. With a strong bent towards fully-differentiated and
individualised experience Herbart conjoined a conviction of the need of
logical analysis to prevent us being carried away by the first-come and
inadequate generalities. The Ego which, in its extremest abstraction, he
found defined as the unity of subject and object, did not seem to him to
offer the proper guarantees of reality: it was itself a problem, full of
contradictions, waiting for solution. On the other hand, the real Ego, or self
of concrete experience, is very much more than this logical abstract, and
differs widely from individual to individual, and apparently from time to
time even in the same individual. Our self, of which we talk so fluently, as
one and the self-same—how far does it really possess the continuity and
identity with which we credit it? Does it not rather seem to be an ideal
which we gradually form and set before ourselves as the standard for
measuring our attainments of the moment,—the perfect fulfilment of that
oneness of being and purpose and knowledge which we never reach?
Sometimes even it seems no better than a name which we move along the
varying phenomena of our inner life, at one time identifying it with the
power which has gained the victory in a moral struggle, at another with that
which [pg lxvi] has been defeated26, according as the attitude of the moment
makes us throw now one, now another, aspect of mental activity in the
foreground.
That the unity of the Self as an intelligent and moral being, that the Ego of
self-consciousness was an ideal and a product of development, was what
Herbart soon became convinced of. The unity of Self is even as given in
mature experience an imperfect fact. It is a fact, that is, which does not
come up to what it promised, and which requires to be supplemented, or
philosophically justified. Here and everywhere the custom of life carries us
over gaps which yawn deep to the eye of [pg lxvii] philosophic reflection:
even though accident and illness force them not unfrequently even upon the
blindest. To trace the process of unification towards this unity—to trace, if
you like, even the formation of the concept of such unity, as a governing
and guiding principle in life and conduct, comes to be the problem of the
psychologist, in the largest sense of that problem. From Soul (Seele) to
Mind or Spirit (Geist) is for Herbart, as for Hegel, the course of
psychology27. The growth and development of mind, the formation of a self,
the realisation of a personality, is for both the theme which psychology has
to expound. And Herbart, not less than Hegel, had to bear the censure that
such a conception of mental reality as a growth would destroy personality28.
But with so much common in the general plan, the two thinkers differ
profoundly in their special mode of carrying out the task. Or, rather, they
turn their strength on different departments of the whole. Herbart's great
practical interest had been the theory of education: “paedagogic” is the
subject of his first important writings. The inner history of ideas—the
processes which are based on the interaction of elements in the individual
soul—are what he specially traces. Hegel's interests, on the contrary, are
more towards the greater process, the unities of historical life, and the
correlations of the powers of art, religion, and philosophy that work therein.
He turns to the macrocosm, almost as naturally as Herbart does to the
microcosm. Thus, even in Ethics, while Herbart gives a delicate analysis of
the distinct aspects or elements in the Ethical idea,—the diverse headings
under which the disinterested spectator within the breast measures with
purely aesthetic [pg lxviii] eye his approach to unity and strength of
purpose, Hegel seems to hurry away from the field of moral sense or
conscience to throw himself on the social and political organisation of the
moral life. The General Paedagogic of Herbart has its pendant in Hegel's
Philosophy of Law and of History.
Psychology then deals with a real, which exhibits [pg lxix] phenomena
analogous in several respects to those discussed by statics and mechanics.
Its foundation is a statics and mechanics of the Soul,—as this real is called.
We begin by presupposing as the ultimate reality, underlying the factitious
and generally imperfect unity of self-consciousness and mind, an essential
and primary unity—the unity of an absolutely simple or individual point of
being—a real point which amongst other points asserts itself, maintains
itself. It has a character of its own, but that character it only shows in and
through a development conditioned by external influences. The specific
nature of the soul-reality is to be representative, to produce, or manifest
itself in, ideas (Vorstellungen). But the character only emerges into actuality
in the conflict of the soul-atom with other ultimate realities in the
congregation of things. A soul per se or isolated is not possessed of ideas. It
is merely blank, undeveloped, formal unity, of which nothing can be said.
But like other realities it defines and characterises itself by antithesis, by
resistance: it shows what it is by its behaviour in the struggle for existence.
It acts in self-defence: and its peculiar style or weapon of self-defence is an
idea or representation. The way the Soul maintains itself is by turning the
assailant into an idea32: and each idea is therefore a Selbsterhaltung of the
Soul. The Soul is thus enriched—to appearance or incidentally: and the
assailant is annexed. In this way the one Soul may develop or evolve or
express an innumerable variety of ideas: for in response to whatever it
meets, the living and active Soul ideates, or gives rise to a representation.
Thus, while the soul is [pg lxx] one, its ideas or representations are many.
Taken separately, they each express the psychic self-conservation. But
brought in relation with each other, as so many acts or self-affirmations of
the one soul, they behave as forces, and tend to thwart or check each other.
It is as forces, as reciprocally arresting or fostering each other, that ideas are
objects of science. When a representation is thus held in check, it is reduced
to a mere endeavour or active tendency to represent. Thus there arises a
distinction between representations proper, and those imperfect states or
acts which are partly or wholly held in abeyance. But the latent phase of an
idea is as essential to a thorough understanding of it as what appears. It is
the great blunder of empirical psychology to ignore what is sunk below the
surface of consciousness. And to Herbart consciousness is not the condition
but rather the product of ideas, which are primarily forces.
What Herbart (as well as Hegel) finds perpetual ground for objecting to is
the talk about mental faculties. This objection is part of a general
characteristic of all the higher philosophy; and the recurrence of it gives an
illustration of how hard it is for any class of men to see themselves as others
see them. If there be anything the vulgar believe to be true of philosophy, it
is that it deals in distant and abstruse generalities, that it neglects the shades
of individuality and reality, and launches out into unsubstantial general
ideas. But it would be easy to gather from the great thinkers an anthology of
passages in which they hold it forth as the great work of philosophy to
rescue our conceptions from the indefiniteness and generality of popular
conception, and to give them real, as opposed to a merely nominal,
individuality.
The Wolffian school, which Herbart (not less than Kant) found in
possession of the field, and which in Germany may be taken to represent
only a slight variant of the half-and-half attitude of vulgar thought, [pg
lxxiv] was entrenched in the psychology of faculties. Empirical psychology,
said Wolff35, tells the number and character of the soul's faculties: rational
psychology will tell what they “properly” are, and how they subsist in soul.
It is assumed that there are general receptacles or tendencies of mental
operation which in course of time get filled or qualified in a certain way:
and that when this question is disposed of, it still remains to fix on the
metaphysical bases of these facts.
That a doctrine of faculties should fix itself in psychology is not so
wonderful. In the non-psychical world objects are easily discriminated in
space, and the individual thing lasts through a time. But a phase of mind is
as such fleeting and indeterminate: its individual features which come from
its “object” tend soon to vanish in memory: all freshness of definite
characters wears off, and there is left behind only a vague “recept” of the
one and same in many, a sort of hypostatised representative, faint but
persistent, of what in experience was an ever-varying succession. We
generalise here as elsewhere: but elsewhere the many singulars remain to
confront us more effectually. But in Mind the immense variety of real
imagination, memory, judgment is forgotten, and the name in each case
reduced to a meagre abstract. Thus the identity in character and operation,
having been cut off from the changing elements in its real action, is
transmuted into a substantial somewhat, a subsistent faculty. The
relationship of one to another of the powers thus by abstraction and fancy
created becomes a problem of considerable moment, their causal relations
in particular: till in the end they stand outside and independent of each
other, engaged, as Herbart says, in a veritable bellum omnium contra omnes.
[pg lxxv]
But this hypostatising of faculties becomes a source of still further
difficulties when it is taken in connexion with the hypostasis of the Soul or
Self or Ego. To Aristotle the Soul in its general aspect is Energy or Essence;
and its individual phases are energies. But in the hands of the untrained
these conceptions came to be considerably displaced. Essence or Substance
came to be understood (as may be seen in Locke, and still more in loose
talk) as a something,—a substratum,—or peculiar nature—(of which in
itself nothing further could be said36 but which notwithstanding was
permanent and perhaps imperishable): this something subsistent exhibited
certain properties or activities. There thus arose, on one hand, the Soul-
thing,—a substance misunderstood and sensualised with a supernatural
sensuousness,—a denizen of the transcendental or even of the transcendent
world: and, on the other hand, stood the actual manifestations, the several
exhibitions of this force, the assignable and describable psychic facts. We
are accordingly brought before the problem of how this one substance or
essence stands to the several entities or hypostases known as faculties. And
we still have in the rear the further problem of how these abstract entities
stand to the real and concrete single acts and states of soul and mind.
Leibniz speaks no less distinctly and sanely in this direction. “True powers
are never mere possibilities: they are always tendency and action.” The
“Monad”—that is the quasi-intelligent unit of existence,—is essentially
activity, and its actions are perceptions and appetitions, i.e. tendencies to
pass from one perceptive state or act to another. It is out of the variety, the
complication, and relations of these miniature or little perceptions and
appetitions, that the conspicuous phenomena of consciousness are to be
explained, and not by supposing them due to one or other faculty. The soul
is a unity, a self-developing unity, a unity which at each stage of its
existence shows itself in a perception or idea,—each such perception
however being, to repeat the oft quoted phrase, plein de l'avenir et chargé
du passé:—each, in other words, is not stationary, but active and urgent, a
progressive force, as well as a representative element. Above all, Leibniz
has the view that the soul gives rise to all its ideas from itself: that its life is
its own production, not a mere inheritance of ideas which it has from birth
and nature, nor [pg lxxviii] a mere importation into an empty room from
without, but a necessary result of its own constitution acting in necessary
(predetermined) reciprocity and harmony with the rest of the universe.
But Hobbes, Spinoza, and Leibniz, were most attentively heard in the
passages where they favoured or combatted the dominant social and
theological prepossessions. Their glimpses of truer insight and even their
palpable contributions in the line of a true psychology were ignored or
forgotten. More attention, perhaps, was attracted by an attempt of a very
different style. This was the system of Condillac, who, as Hegel says (p.
61), made an unmistakable attempt to show the necessary interconnexion of
the several modes of mental activity. In his Traité des Sensations (1754),
following on his Essai sur l'origine des connaissances humaines (1746), he
tried to carry out systematically the deduction or derivation of all our ideas
from sense, or to trace the filiation of all our faculties from sensation. Given
a mind with no other power than sensibility, the problem is to show how it
acquires all its other faculties. Let us then suppose a sentient animal to
which is offered a single sensation, or one sensation standing out above the
others. In such circumstances the sensation “becomes” (devient) attention:
or a sensation “is” (est) attention, either because it is alone, or because it is
more lively than all the rest. Again: before such a being, let us set two
sensations: to perceive or feel (apercevoir ou sentir) the two sensations is
the same thing (c'est la même chose). If one of the sensations is not present,
but a sensation made already, then to perceive it is memory. Memory, then,
is only “transformed sensation” (sensation transformée). Further, suppose
we attend to both ideas, this is “the same thing” as to compare them. [pg
lxxix] And to compare them we must see difference or resemblance. This is
judgment. “Thus sensation becomes successively attention, comparison,
judgment.” And—by further steps of the equating process—it appears that
sensation again “becomes” an act of reflection. And the same may be said
of imagination and reasoning: all are transformed sensations.
If this is so with the intelligence, it is equally the case with the Will. To feel
and not feel well or ill is impossible. Coupling then this feeling of pleasure
or pain with the sensation and its transformations, we get the series of
phases ranging from desire, to passion, hope, will. “Desire is only the action
of the same faculties as are attributed to the understanding.” A lively desire
is a passion: a desire, accompanied with a belief that nothing stands in its
way, is a volition. But combine these affective with the intellectual
processes already noticed, and you have thinking (penser)40. Thus thought in
its entirety is, only and always, transformed sensation.
These large hopes may have a certain fulfilment. They may lead to the
withdrawal of some of the fictitious mental processes which are still
described in works of psychology. But on the whole they can only have a
negative and auxiliary value. The value, that is, of helping to confute
feigned connexions and to suggest truer. They will be valid against the
mode of thought which, when Psyché fails us for an explanation, turns to
body, and interpolates soul between the states of body: the mode which, in
an older phraseology, jumps from final causes to physical, and from
physical (or efficient) to final. Here, as elsewhere, the physical has its place:
and here, more than in many places, the physical has been unfairly treated.
But the whole subject requires a discussion of the so-called “relations” of
soul and body: a subject on which popular conceptions and so-called
science are radically obscure.
“This must be all changed, if we are not to drift into the barrenest
scholastic.... Everywhere out of the correct perception that problems of
principle demand the investigation of detailed phenomena, and that the
latter investigation must proceed in comparative independence of the
question of principles, there has grown the false belief that the description
of detail phenomena is the ultimate aim of science. And so, side by side
with details which are of importance to principles, we have others, utterly
indifferent and theoretically worthless, treated with the same zeal. To the
solution of their barren problems the old Schoolmen applied a certain
acuteness; but in order to turn out [pg lxxxv] masses of numbers from
barren experiments, all that is needed is a certain insensibility to fits of
ennui. Let numbers be less collected for their own sake: and instead, let the
problems be so brought to a point that the answers may possess the
character of principles. Let each experiment be founded on far more
theoretical considerations, then the number of the experiments may be
largely diminished44.”
“The human being of the psychologist,” says Herbart45, “is the social and
civilised human being who stands on the apex of the whole history through
which his race has passed. In him is found visibly together all the
multiplicity of elements, which, under the name of [pg lxxxvi] mental
faculties, are regarded as a universal inheritance of humanity. Whether they
are originally in conjunction, whether they are originally a multiplicity, is a
point on which the facts are silent. The savage and the new-born child give
us far less occasion to admire the range of their mind than do the nobler
animals. But the psychologists get out of this difficulty by the unwarranted
assumption that all the higher mental activities exist potentially in children
and savages—though not in the animals—as a rudimentary predisposition
or psychical endowment. Of such a nascent intellect, a nascent reason, and
nascent moral sense, they find recognisable traces in the scanty similarities
which the behaviour of child or savage offers to those of civilised man. We
cannot fail to note that in their descriptions they have before them a special
state of man, and one which, far from accurately defined, merely follows
the general impression made upon us by those beings we name civilised. An
extremely fluctuating character inevitably marks this total impression. For
there are no general facts:—the genuine psychological documents lie in the
momentary states of individuals: and there is an immeasurably long way
from these to the height of the universal concept of man in general.”
But that is only one way of looking at the matter—and one which, perhaps,
is more becoming to the pathologist and the cynic, than to the psychologist.
Each of these stages of psychical development, even if that development be
obviously describable as degeneration, has something which, duly adjusted,
has its place and function in the theory of the normally-complete human
mind. The animal, the savage, and [pg lxxxviii] the child,—each has its part
there. It is a mutilated, one-sided and superficial advance in socialisation
which cuts off the civilised creature from the natural stem of his ancestry,
from the large freedom, the immense insouciance, the childlikeness of his
first estate. There is something, again, wanting in the man who utterly lacks
the individualising realism and tenderness of the woman, as in the woman
who can show no comprehension of view or bravery of enterprise. Even
pathological states of mind are not mere anomalies and mere degenerations.
Nature perhaps knows no proper degenerations, but only by-ways and
intricacies in the course of development. Still less is the vast enormity or
irregularity of genius to be ignored. It is all—to the philosophic mind—a
question of degree and proportion,—though often the proportion seems to
exceed the scale of our customary denominators. If an element is latent or
quiescent (in arrest), that is no index to its absolute amount: “we know not
what's resisted.” Let us by all means keep proudly to our happy mediocrity
of faculty, and step clear of insanity or idiotcy on one hand, and from
genius or heroism on the other. But the careful observer will
notwithstanding note how delicately graded and how intricately combined
are the steps which connect extremes so terribly disparate. It is only vulgar
ignorance which turns away in hostility or contempt from the imbecile and
the deranged, and only a worse than vulgar sciolism which sees in genius
and the hero nothing but an aberration from its much-prized average.
Criminalistic anthropology, or the psychology of the criminal, may have
indulged in much frantic exaggeration as to the doom which nature and
heredity have pronounced over the fruit of the womb even before it entered
the shores of light: yet they have at least [pg lxxxix] served to discredit the
free and easy assumption of the abstract averagist, and shown how little the
penalties of an unbending law meet the requirements of social well-being.
Yet, if psychology be willing to learn in all these and other provinces of the
estate of man, it must remember that, once it goes beyond the narrow range
in which the interpretations of symbol and expression have become
familiar, it is constantly liable to blunder in the inevitable effort to translate
observation into theory. The happy mean between making too much of
palpable differences and hurrying on to a similar rendering of similar signs
is the rarest of gifts. Or, perhaps, it were truer to say it is the latest and most
hardly won of acquirements. To learn to observe—observe with mind—is
not a small thing. There are rules for it—both rules of general scope and,
above all, rules in each special department. But like all “major premisses”
in practice, everything depends on the power of judgment, the tact, the skill,
the “gift” of applying them. They work not as mere rules to be conned by
rote, but as principles assimilated into constituents of the mental life-blood:
rules which serve only as condensed reminders and hints of habits of
thought and methods of research which have grown up in action and
reflection. To observe we must comprehend: yet we can only comprehend
by observing. We all know how unintelligible—save for epochs of ampler
reciprocity, and it may be even of acquired unity of interest—the two sexes
are for each other. Parents can remember how mysteriously minded they
found their own elders; and in most cases they have to experience the depth
of the gulf which in certain directions parts them from their children's
hearts. Even in civilised Europe, the ordinary member of each nation has an
underlying [pg xc] conviction (which at moments of passion or surprise will
rise and find harsh utterance) that the foreigner is queer, irrational, and
absurd. If the foreigner, further, be so far removed as a Chinaman (or an
Australian “black”), there is hardly anything too vile, meaningless, or
inhuman which the European will not readily believe in the case of one
who, it may be, in turn describes him as a “foreign devil.” It can only be in
a fit of noble chivalry that the British rank and file can so far temporise with
its insular prejudice as to admit of “Fuzzy-wuzzy” that
Not every one is an observer who chooses to dub himself so, nor is it in a
short lapse of time and with condescension for foreign habits, that any
observer whatever can become a trustworthy reporter of the ideas some
barbarian tribe holds concerning the things of earth and air, and the hidden
things of spirits and gods. The “interviewer” no doubt is a useful being
when it is necessary to find “copy,” or when sharp-drawn characters and
picturesque incidents are needed to stimulate an inert public, ever open to
be interested in some new thing. But he is a poor contributor to the stored
materials of science.
It is of other stuff that true science is made. And if even years of nominal
intercourse and spatial juxtaposition sometimes leave human beings, as
regards their inner selves, in the position of strangers still, what shall be
said of the attempt to discern the psychic life of animals? Will the touch of
curiosity which prompts us to watch the proceedings of the strange
creatures,—will a course of experimentation on their behaviour under
artificial conditions,—justify us in drawing liberal conclusions as to why
they so behaved, [pg xci] and what they thought and felt about it? It is
necessary in the first place to know what to observe, and how, and above all
what for. But that presumed, we must further live with the animals not only
as their masters and their examiners, but as their friends and fellow-
creatures; we must be able—and so lightly that no effort is discernable—to
lay aside the burden and garb of civilisation; we must possess that stamp of
sympathy and similarity which invites confidence, and breaks down the
reserve which our poor relations, whether human or others, offer to the first
approaches of a strange superior. It is probable that in that case we should
have less occasion to wonder at their oddities or to admire their sagacity.
But a higher and more philosophical wonder might, as in other cases when
we get inside the heart of our subject, take the place of the cheap and
childish love of marvels, or of the vulgar straining after comic traits.
Of all this mass of materials the psychologist proper can directly make only
a sparing use. Even as illustrations, his data must not be presented too often
in all their crude and undigested individuality, or he runs the risk of leaving
one-sided impressions. Every single instance, individualised and historical,
—unless it be exhibited by that true art of genius which we cannot expect in
the average psychologist—narrows, even though it be but slightly, the
complete and all-sided truth. Anecdotes are good, and to the wise they
convey a world of meaning, but to lesser minds they sometimes suggest
anything but the points they should accentuate. Without the detail of
individual realistic study there is no psychology worth the name. History,
story, we must have: but at the same time, with the philosopher, we must
say, I don't give much weight to stories. And this is what will always—
except in rare instances where [pg xcii] something like genius is conjoined
with it—make esoteric science hard and unpopular. It dare not—if it is true
to its idea—rest on any amount of mere instances, as isolated, unreduced
facts. Yet it can only have real power so far as it concentrates into itself the
life-blood of many instances, and indeed extracts the pith and unity of all
instances.
Nor, on the other hand, can it turn itself too directly and intently towards
practical applications. All this theory of mental progress from the animate
soul to the fullness of religion and science deals solely with the universal
process of education: “the education of humanity” we may call it: the way
in which mind is made true and real46. It is therefore a question of intricacy
and of time how to carry over this general theory into the arena of education
as artificially directed and planned. To try to do so at a single step would be
to repeat the mistake of Plato, if Plato may be taken to suppose (which
seems incredible) that a theoretical study of the dialectics of truth and
goodness would enable his rulers, without the training of special
experience, to undertake the supreme tasks of legislation or administration.
All politics, like all education, rests on these principles of the means and
conditions of mental growth: but the schooling of concrete life, though it
may not develop the faculty of formulating general laws, will often train
better for the management of the relative than a mere logical Scholastic in
first or absolute principles.
In conclusion, there are one or two points which seem of cardinal
importance for the progress of psychology. (1) Its difference from the
physical sciences has to be set out: in other words, the peculiarity of
psychical fact. It will not do merely to say that experience marks [pg xciii]
out these boundaries with sufficient clearness. On the contrary, the terms
consciousness, feeling, mind, &c., are evidently to many psychologists
mere names. In particular, the habits of physical research when introduced
into mental study lead to a good deal of what can only be called mythology.
(2) There should be a clearer recognition of the problem of the relations of
mental unity to mental elements. But to get that, a more thorough logical
and metaphysical preparation is needed than is usually supposed necessary.
The doctrine of identity and necessity, of universal and individual, has to be
faced, however tedious. (3) The distinction between first-grade and second-
grade elements and factors in the mental life has to be realised. The mere
idea as presentative or immediate has to be kept clear of the more logico-
reflective, or normative ideas, which belong to judgment and reasoning.
And the number of these grades in mental development seems endless. (4)
But, also, a separation is required—were it but temporary—between what
may be called principles, and what is detail. At present, in psychology,
“principles” is a word almost without meaning. A complete all-explaining
system is of course impossible at present and may always be so. Yet if an
effort of thought could be concentrated on cardinal issues, and less padding
of conventional and traditional detail were foisted in, much might thereby
be done to make detailed research fruitful. (5) And finally, perhaps, if
psychology be a philosophical study, some hint as to its purpose and
problem would be desirable. If it is only an abstract branch of science, of
course, no such hint is in place.
[pg xciv]
Essay III. On Some Psychological Aspects Of Ethics.
Allusion has already been made to the question of the boundaries between
logic and psychology, between logic and ethics, ethics and psychology, and
psychology and epistemology. Each of these occasionally comes to cover
ground that seems more appropriate to the others. Logic is sometimes
restricted to denote the study of the conditions of derivative knowledge, of
the canons of inference and the modes of proof. If taken more widely as the
science of thought-form, it is supposed to imply a world of fixed or
stereotyped relations between ideas, a system of stable thoughts governed
by inflexible laws in an absolute order of immemorial or eternal truth. As
against such fixity, psychology is supposed to deal with these same ideas as
products—as growing out of a living process of thought—having a history
behind them and perhaps a prospect of further change. The genesis so given
may be either a mere chronicle-history, or it may be a philosophical
development. In the former case, it would note the occasions of incident
and circumstance, the reactions of mind and environment, under which the
ideas were formed. Such [pg xcv] a psychological genesis of several ideas
is found in the Second Book of Locke's Essay. In the latter case, the account
would be more concerned with the inner movement, the action and reaction
in ideas themselves, considered not as due to casual occurrences, but as
self-developing by an organic growth. But in either case, ideas would be
shown not to be ready-made and independently existing kinds in a world of
idea-things, and not to form an unchanging diagram or framework, but to be
a growth, to have a history, and a development. Psychology in this sense
would be a dynamical, as opposed to the supposed statical, treatment of
ideas and concepts in logic. But it may be doubted how far it is well to call
this psychology: unless psychology deals with the contents of the mental
life, in their meaning and purpose, instead of, as seems proper, merely in
their character of psychic events. Such psychology is rather an evolutionist
logic,—a dialectic process more than an analytic of a datum.
In the same way, ethics may be brought into one kind of contact with
psychology. Ethics, like logic, may be supposed to presuppose and to deal
with a certain inflexible scheme of requirements, a world of moral order
governed by invariable or universal law; an eternal kingdom of right,
existing independently of human wills, but to be learned and followed out
in uncompromising obedience. As against this supposed absolute order,
psychology may be said to show the genesis of the idea of obligation and
duty, the growth of the authority of conscience, the formation of ideals, the
relativity of moral ideas. Here also it may reach this conclusion, by a more
external or a more internal mode of argument. It may try to show, in other
words, that circumstances give rise to these forms of estimating conduct, or
it may argue that they are a necessary [pg xcvi] development in the human
being, constituted as he is. It may again be doubted whether this is properly
called psychology. Yet its purport seems ultimately to be that the objective
order is misconceived when it is regarded as an external or quasi-physical
order: as a law written up and sanctioned with an external authority—as, in
Kant's words, a heteronomy. If that order is objective, it is so because it is
also in a sense subjective: if it is above the mere individuality of the
individual, it is still in a way identical with his true or universal self-hood.
Thus “psychological” here means the recognition that the logical and the
moral law is an autonomy: that it is not given, but though necessary,
necessary by the inward movement of the mind. The metaphor of law is, in
brief, misleading. For, according to a common, though probably an
erroneous, analysis of that term, the essence of a law in the political sphere
is to be a species of command. And that is rather a one-sidedly practical or
aesthetic way of looking at it. The essence of law in general, and the
precondition of every law in special, is rather uniformity and universality,
self-consistency and absence of contradiction: or, in other words,
rationality. Its essential opposite—or its contradiction in essence—is a
privilege, an attempt at isolating a case from others. It need not indeed
always require bare uniformity—require i.e. the same act to be done by
different people: but it must always require that every thing within its
operation shall be treated on principles of utter and thorough harmony and
consistency. It requires each thing to be treated on public principles and
with publicity: nothing apart and mere singular, as a mere incident or as a
world by itself. Differently it may be treated, but always on grounds of
common well-being, as part of an embracing system.
There is probably another sense, however, in which [pg xcvii] psychology
comes into close relation with ethics. If we look on man as a microcosm,
his inner system will more or less reproduce the system of the larger world.
The older psychology used to distinguish an upper or superior order of
faculties from a lower or inferior. Thus in the intellectual sphere, the
intellect, judgment, and reason were set above the senses, imagination, and
memory. Among the active powers, reasonable will, practical reason and
conscience were ranked as paramount over the appetites and desires and
emotions. And this use of the word “faculty” is as old as Plato, who regards
science as a superior faculty to opinion or imagination. But this application
—which seems a perfectly legitimate one—does not, in the first instance,
belong to psychology at all. No doubt it is psychically presented: but it has
an other source. It springs from an appreciation, a judgment of the
comparative truth or reality of what the so-called psychical act means or
expresses. Such faculties are powers in a hierarchy of means and ends and
presuppose a normative or critical function which has classified reality.
Psychically, the elements which enter into knowledge are not other than
those which belong to opinion: but they are nearer an adequate rendering of
reality, they are truer, or nearer the Idea. And in the main we may say, that
is truer or more real which succeeds in more completely organising and
unifying elements—which rises more and more above the selfish or isolated
part into the thorough unity of all parts.
[pg xcix]
When this line is once fixed upon, it seems inevitable to go farther. Comte
was inclined to treat psychology [pg c] as falling between two stools: it
must, he thought, draw all its content either from physiology on the one
hand, or from social factors on the other. The dominant or experimental
psychology of the present day seems inclined, without however formulating
any very definite statement, to pronounce for the former alternative. It does
not indeed adopt the materialistic view that mind is only a function of
matter. Its standpoint rather is that the psychical presents itself even to
unskilled observation as dependent on (i.e. not independent of) or as
concomitant with certain physical or corporeal facts. It adds that the more
accurately trained the observer becomes, the more he comes to discover a
corporeal aspect even where originally he had not surmised its existence,
and to conclude that the two cycles of psychical and physical event never
interfere with each other: that soul does not intervene in bodily process, nor
body take up and carry on psychical. If it is said that the will moves the
limbs, he replies that the will which moves is really certain formerly
unnoticed movements of nerve and muscle which are felt or interpreted as a
discharge of power. If the ocular impression is said to cause an impression
on the mind, he replies that any fact hidden under that phrase refers to a
change in the molecules of the brain. He will therefore conclude that for the
study of psychical phenomena the physical basis, as it may be called, is all
important. Only so can observation really deal with fact capable of
description and measurement. Thus psychology, it may be said, tends to
become a department of physiology. From another standpoint, biology may
be said to receive its completion in psychology. How much either phrase
means, however, will depend on the estimate we form of biology. If biology
is only the study of mechanical and chemical phenomena on the peculiar
field known as [pg ci] an organism, and if that organism is only treated as
an environment which may be ignored, then psychology, put on the same
level, is not the full science of mind, any more than the other is the full
study of life. They both have narrowed their subject to suit the abstract
scheme of the laboratory, where the victim of experiment is either altered
by mutilation and artificial restrictions, or is dead. If, on the contrary,
biology has a substantial unity of its own to which mechanical and chemical
considerations are subordinate and instrumental, psychology may even take
part with physiology without losing its essential rank. But in that case, we
must, as Spinoza said47, think less mechanically of the animal frame, and
recognise (after the example of Schelling) something truly inward (i.e. not
merely locally inside the skin) as the supreme phase or characteristic of life.
We must, in short, recognise sensibility as the culmination of the
physiological and the beginning of the psychological.
With this distinction we are brought across the problem sometimes called
Epistemological. Strictly speaking, it is really part of a larger problem: the
problem of what—if Greek compounds must be used—may be styled
Aletheiology—the theory of truth and reality: what Hegel called Logic, and
what many others have called Metaphysics. As it is ordinarily taken up,
“ideas” are believed to be something in us which is representative or
symbolical of something truly real outside us. This inward something is
said to be the first and immediate object of knowledge48, and gives us—in a
mysterious way we need not here discuss—the mediate knowledge of the
reality, which is sometimes said to cause it. Ideas in the Mind, or in the
Subject, or in us, bear witness to something outside the mind,—trans-
subjective—beyond us. The Mind, Subject, or Ego, in this parallelism is
evidently in some way identified with our corporeal organism: perhaps even
located, and provided with a “seat,” in some defined space of that [pg civ]
organism. It is, however, the starting-point of the whole distinction that
ideas do not, no less than they do, conform or correspond to this supra-
conscious or extra-conscious world of real things. Truth or falsehood arises,
according to these assumptions, according as psychical image or idea
corresponds or not to physical fact. But how, unless by some miraculous
second-sight, where the supreme consciousness, directly contemplating by
intuition the true and independent reality, turns to compare with this
immediate vision the results of the mediate processes conducted along the
organs of sense,—how this agreement or disagreement of copy and original,
of idea and reality, can be detected, it is impossible to say.
As has been already noted, the mischief lies in the hypostatisation of ideas
as something existing in abstraction from things—and, of things, in
abstraction from ideas. They are two abstractions, the first by the realist, the
second by the idealist called subjective and psychological. To the realist,
things exist by themselves, and they manage to produce a copy of
themselves (more or less exact, or symbolical) in our mind, i.e. in a
materialistically-spiritual or a spiritualistically-material locus which holds
“images” and ideas. To the psychological idealist, ideas have a substantive
and primary right to existence, them alone do we really know, and from
them we more or less legitimately are said (but probably no one takes this
seriously) to infer or postulate a world of permanent things. Now ideas have
no substantive existence as a sort of things, or even images of things
anywhere. All this is pure mythology. It is said by comparative
mythologists that in some cases the epithet or quality of some deity has
been substantialised (hypostatised) into a separate god, who, however (so
still to keep up the unity), is regarded [pg cv] as a relative, a son, or
daughter, of the original. So the phrase “ideas of things” has been taken
literally as if it was double. But to have an idea of a thing merely means that
we know it, or think it. An idea is not given: it is a thing which is given in
the idea. An idea is not an additional and intervening object of our
knowledge or supposed knowledge. That a thing is our object of thought is
another word for its being our idea, and that means we know it.
Kant's central idea is that truth, beauty, goodness, are not dependent on
some qualities of the object, but on the universal nature or law of
consciousness. Beauty is not an attribute of things in their abstractness: but
of things as ideas of a subject, and depends on the proportion and symmetry
in the play of human faculty. Goodness is not conformity to an outward law,
but is obligatory on us through that higher nature which is our truer being.
Truth is not conformity of ideas with supposed trans-subjective things, but
coherence and stability in the system of ideas. The really infinite world is
not out there, but in here—in consciousness in general, which is the denial
of all limitation, of all finality, of all isolation. God is the essential and
inherent unity and unifier of spirit and nature—the surety that the world in
all its differentiations is one. The Soul is not an essential entity, but the
infinite fruitfulness and freshness of mental life, which forbids us stopping
at anything short of complete continuity and unity. The Kingdom of God—
the Soul—the moral law—is within us: within us, as supreme, supra-
personal and infinite intelligences, even amid all our littleness and finitude.
Even happiness which we stretch our arms after is not really beyond us, but
is the essential self which indeed we can only reach in detail. It is so both in
knowledge and in action. Each knowledge and enjoyment in reality is
limited and partial, but it is made stable, and it gets a touch of infinitude, by
the larger idea which it helps to realise. Only indeed in that antithesis
between the finite and the infinite does the real live. Every piece of
knowledge is real, only because it assumes pro tempore certain premisses
which are given: every actual beauty is set in some defect of aesthetic [pg
cix] completeness: every actually good deed has to get its foil in
surrounding badness. The real is always partial and incomplete. But it has
the basis or condition of its reality in an idea—in a transcendental unity of
consciousness, which is so to say a law, or a system and an order, which
imposes upon it the condition of conformity and coherence; but a
conformity which is essential and implicit in it.
Kant had brought into use the term Deduction, and Fichte follows him. The
term leads to some confusion: for in English, by its modern antithesis to
induction, it suggests a priori methods in all their iniquity. It means a kind
of jugglery which brings an endless series [pg cxi] out of one small term.
Kant has explained that he uses it in the lawyer's sense in which a claim is
justified by being traced step by step back to some acknowledged and
accepted right50. It is a regressive method which shows us that if the original
datum is to be accepted it carries along with it the legitimation of the
consequence. This method Fichte applies to psychology. Begin, he says like
Condillac, with the barest nucleus of soul-life; the mere sentiency, or
feeling: the contact, as it were, with being, at a single point. But such a
mere point is unthinkable. You find, as Mr. Spencer says, that “Thought”
(or Consciousness) “cannot be framed out of one term only.” “Every
sensation to be known as one must be perceived.” Such is the nature of the
Ego—a subject which insists on each part being qualified by the whole and
so transformed. As Mr. Spencer, again, puts it, the mind not merely tends to
revive, to associate, to assimilate, to represent its own presentations, but it
carries on this process infinitely and in ever higher multiples. Ideas as it
were are growing in complexity by re-presenting: i.e. by embracing and
enveloping elements which cannot be found existing in separation. In the
mind there is no mere presentation, no bare sensation. Such a unit is a
fiction or hypothesis we employ, like the atom, for purposes of explanation.
The pure sensation therefore—which you admit because you must have
something to begin with, not a mere nothing, but something so simple that it
seems to stand out clear and indisputable—this pure sensation, when you
think of it, forces you to go a good deal further. Even to be itself, it must be
more than itself. It is like the pure or mere being of the logicians. Admit the
simple [pg cxii] sensation—and you have admitted everything which is
required to make sensation a possible reality. But you do not—in the sense
of vulgar logic—deduce what follows out of the beginning. From that,
taken by itself, you will get only itself: mere being will give you only
nothing, to the end of the chapter. But, as the phrase is, sensation is an
element in a consciousness: it is, when you think of it, always more than
you called it: there is a curious “continuity” about the phenomena, which
makes real isolation impossible.
Hence, in Fichte, the absence of the ascetic element so often stamping its
character on ethics, and representing the moral life as the enemy of the
natural, or as mainly a struggle to subdue the sensibility and the flesh. With
Kant,—as becomes his position of mere inquirer—the sensibility has the
place of a predominant and permanent foreground. Reason, to his way of
talking, is always something of an intruder, a stranger from a far-off world,
to be feared even when obeyed: sublime, rather than beautiful. From the
land of sense which we habitually occupy, the land of reason is a country
we can only behold from afar: or if we can be said to have a standpoint in it,
that is only a figurative way of saying that though it is really over the
border, we can act—it would sometimes seem by a sort of make-believe—
as if we were already there. But these moments of high enthusiasm are rare;
and Kant commends sobriety and warns against high-minded Schwärmerei,
or over-strained Mysticism. For us it is reserved to struggle with a
recalcitrant selfhood, a grovelling sensibility: it were only fantastic
extravagance, fit for “fair souls” who unfortunately often lapse into “fair
sinners,” should we fancy ourselves already anchored in the haven of
untempted rest and peace.
What have been called “formal duties59” seem to fall under this range—the
province of a philosophical psychology which unveils the conditions of
personality. Under that heading may be put self-control, consistency,
resolution, energy, forethought, prudence, and the like. The due proportion
of faculty, the correspondence of head and heart, the vivacity and quickness
of sympathy, [pg cxx] the ease and simplicity of mental tone, the due vigour
of memory and the grace of imagination, sweetness of temper, and the like,
are parts of the same group60. They are lovely, and of good report: they are
praise and virtue. If it be urged that they are only natural gifts and graces,
that objection cuts two ways. The objector may of course be reminded that
religion tones down the self-complacency of morality. Yet, first, even apart
from that, it may be said that of virtues, which stand independent of natural
conditions—of external supply of means (as Aristotle would say)—nothing
can be known and nothing need be said. And secondly, none of these
qualities are mere gifts;—all require exercise, habituation, energising, to get
and keep them. How much and how little in each case is nature's and how
much ours is a problem which has some personal interest—due perhaps to a
rather selfish and envious curiosity. But on the broad field of experience
and history we may perhaps accept the—apparently one-sided—proverb
that “Each man is the architect of his own fortune.” Be this as it may, it will
not do to deny the ethical character of these “formal duties” on the ground
e.g. that self-control, prudence, and even sweetness of temper may be used
for evil ends,—that one may smile and smile, and yet be a villain. That—let
us reply,—on one hand, is a fault (if fault it be) incidental to all virtues in
detail (for every single quality has its defect): nay it may be a limitation
attaching to the whole ethical sphere: and, secondly, its inevitable limitation
does not render the virtue in any case one whit less genuine so far as it goes.
And yet of such virtues it may be said, as Hume61 would say (who calls
them “natural,” as opposed to the more artificial merits [pg cxxi] of justice
and its kin), that they please in themselves, or in the mere contemplation,
and without any regard to their social effects. But they please as entering
into our idea of complete human nature, of mind and spirit as will and
intellect.
It is not very satisfactory, either, as Aristotle and others have pointed out, to
speak of man's duties to himself. The phrase is analogical, like the other.
But it has the merit, like that of duty to God, of reminding us that the
ordinary latitude occupied by morality is not all that comes under the larger
scope of ethics. The “ethics of individual life” is a subject which Mr.
Spencer has touched upon: and by this title, he means that, besides his
general relationship to others, a human being has to mind his own health,
food, and amusement, and has duties as husband and parent. But, after all,
these are not matters of peculiarly individual interest. They rather refer to
points which society at certain epochs leaves to the common sense of the
agent,—apparently on an assumption that he is the person chiefly
interested. And these points—as the Greeks taught long ago—are of
fundamental importance: they are the very bases of life. Yet the
comparative neglect [pg cxxiv] in which so-called civilised societies64 hold
the precepts of wisdom in relation to bodily health and vigour, in regard to
marriage and progeny, serve to illustrate the doctrine of the ancient Stoics
that πάντα ὑπόληψις, or the modern idealist utterance that the World is my
idea. More and more as civilisation succeeds in its disruption of man from
nature, it shows him governed not by bare facts and isolated experiences,
but by the systematic idea under which all things are subsumed. He loses
the naïveté of the natural man, which takes each fact as it came, all alike
good: he becomes sentimental, and artificial, sees things under a
conventional point of view, and would rather die than not be in the fashion.
And this tendency is apparently irresistible. Yet the mistake lies in the one-
sidedness of sentiment and convention. Not the domination of the idea is
evil; but the domination of a partial and fragmentary idea: and this is what
constitutes the evil of artificiality. And the correction must lie not in a
return to nature, but in the reconstruction of a wider and more
comprehensive idea: an idea which shall be the unity and system of all
nature; not a fantastic idealism, but an attempt to do justice to the more
realist as well as the idealist sides of life.
the healthy mind in a healthy body. Ethics is only too apt to suppose that
will and intelligence are assumptions which need no special justification.
But the truth is that they vary from individual to individual in degree and
[pg cxxv] structure. It is the business of ethical psychology to give to these
vague attributions the definiteness of a normal standard: to show what
proportions are required to justify the proper title of reason and will—to
show what reason and will really are if they do what they are encouraged or
expected to do. It talks of the diseases of will and personality: it must also
set forth their educational ideal. The first problem of Ethics, it may be said,
is the question of the will and its freedom. But to say this is of course not to
say that, unless freedom of will be understood in some special sense, ethics
becomes impossible. If the moral law is the ratio cognoscendi of freedom,
then must our conception of morality and of freedom hang together. And it
will clearly be indispensable to begin by some attempt to discover in what
sense man may be in the most general way described as a moral agent—as
an intelligent will, or (more briefly, yet synonymously) as a will. “The soil
of law and morality,” says Hegel65, “is the intelligent life: and its more
precise place and starting-point the will, which is free, in the sense that
freedom is its substance and characteristic, and the system of law the realm
of freedom realised, the world of intelligence produced out of itself as a
second nature.” Such a freedom is a freedom made and acquired, the work
of the mind's self-realisation, not to be taken as a given fact of
consciousness which must be believed66. To have a will—in other words, to
have freedom, is the consummation—and let us add, only the formal or
ideal consummation—of a process by which man raises himself out of his
absorption in sensation and impulse, establishes within himself a mental
realm, an organism of ideas, a self-consciousness, and a self.
[pg cxxvi]
The vulgar apprehension of these things seems to assume that we have by
nature, or are born with, a general faculty or set of general faculties, which
we subsequently fill up and embody by the aid of experience. We possess—
they seem to imply—so many “forms” and “categories” latent in our minds
ready to hold and contain the raw materials supplied from without.
According to this view we have all a will and an intelligence: the difference
only is that some put more into them, and some put less. But such a
separation of the general form from its contents is a piece of pure
mythology. It is perhaps true and safe to say that the human being is of such
a character that will and intelligence are in the ordinary course inevitably
produced. But the forms which grow up are the more and more definite and
systematic organisation of a graded experience, of series of ideas, working
themselves up again and again in representative and re-representative
degree, till they constitute a mental or inner world of their own. The will is
thus the title appropriate to the final stage of a process, by which sensation
and impulse have polished and perfected themselves by union and
opposition, by differentiation and accompanying redintegration, till they
assume characters quite unsurmised in their earliest aspects, and yet only
the consolidation or self-realisation of implications. Thus the mental
faculties are essentially acquired powers,—acquired not from without, but
by action which generates the faculties it seems to imply. The process of
mind is a process which creates individual centres, raises them to completer
independence;—which produces an inner life more and more self-centered
and also more and more equal to the universe which it has embodied. And
will and intelligence are an important stage in that process.
Herbart (as was briefly hinted at in the first essay) [pg cxxvii] has analysed
ethical appreciation (which may or may not be accompanied by
approbation) into five distinct standard ideas. These are the ideas of inward
liberty, of perfection, of right, benevolence, and equity. Like Hume, he
regards the moral judgment as in its purity a kind of aesthetic
pronouncement on the agreement or proportion of certain activities in
relations to each other. Two of these standard ideas,—that of inward liberty
and of perfection—seem to belong to the sphere at present under review.
They emerge as conditions determining the normal development of human
nature to an intelligent and matured personality. By inward freedom Herbart
means the harmony between the will and the intellect: what Aristotle has
named “practical truth or reality,” and what he describes in his conception
of wisdom or moral intelligence,—the power of discerning the right path
and of pursuing it with will and temper: the unity, clear but indissoluble, of
will and discernment. By the idea of perfection Herbart means the sense of
proportion and of propriety which is awakened by comparing a progress in
development or an increase in strength with its earlier stages of promise and
imperfection. The pleasure such perception affords works in two ways: it is
a satisfaction in achievement past, and a stimulus to achievement yet to
come.
It is in these regions that Greek ethics loves to linger; on the duty of the
individual to himself, to be perfectly lucid and true, and to rise to ever
higher heights of achievement. Ceteris paribus, there is felt to be something
meritorious in superiority, something good:—even were it that you are
master, and another is slave. Thus naïvely speaks Aristotle69. To a modern,
set amid so many conflicting ideals, perhaps, the immense possibilities of
yet further growth might suggest themselves with overpowering force. To
him the idea of perfection takes the form of an idea of perfectibility: and
sometimes it smites down his conceit in what he has actually done, and
impresses a sense of humility in comparison with what yet remains
unaccomplished. An ancient Greek apparently was little haunted by these
vistas of possibilities of progress through worlds beyond worlds. A
comparatively simple environment, a fixed and definite mental horizon, had
its plain and definite standards, or at least seemed to have such. There were
fewer cases of the man, unattached or faintly attached to any [pg cxxx]
definite profession—moving about in worlds half realised—who has grown
so common in a more developed civilisation. The ideals of the Greek were
clearly descried: each man had his definite function or work to perform: and
to do it better than the average, or than he himself habitually had done, that
was perfection, excellence, virtue. For virtue to the Greek is essentially
ability and respectability: promise of excellent performance: capacity to do
better than others. Virtue is praiseworthy or meritorious character and
quality: it is achievement at a higher rate, as set against one's past and
against others' average.
The four cardinal virtues of Plato's list are the qualities which go to make a
healthy, normal, natural human soul, fit for all activity, equipped with all
arms for the battle of life. They tell us what such a soul is, not [pg cxxxiii]
what it does. They are the qualities which unless a soul has, and has them
each perfect, yet all co-operant, its mere outward and single acts have no
virtue or merit, but are only lucky accidents at the best. On the other hand,
if a man has these constitutive qualities, he will act in the social world, and
act well. Plato has said scornful things of mere outward and verbal
truthfulness, and has set at the very lowest pitch of degradation the “lie in
the soul.” His “temperance” or “self-restraint,” if it be far from breathing
any suggestion of self-suppression or self-assertion, is still farther from any
suspicion of asceticism, or war against the flesh. It is the noble harmony of
the ruling and the ruled, which makes the latter a partner of the sovereign,
and takes from the dictates of the ruler any touch of coercion. It is literally
sanity of soul, integrity and purity of spirit; it is what has been sometimes
called the beautiful soul—the indiscerptible unity of reason and impulse.
Plato's bravery, again, is fortitude and consistency of soul, the full-blooded
heart which is fixed in reason, the zeal which is according to knowledge,
unflinching loyalty to the idea, the spirit which burns in the martyrs to truth
and humanity: yet withal with gentleness and courtesy and noble urbanity in
its immediate train. And his truthfulness is that inner lucidity which cannot
be self-deceived, the spirit which is a safeguard against fanaticism and
hypocrisy, the sunlike warmth of intelligence without which the heart is a
darkness full of unclean things.
The full development and crowning grace of such a manly nature Aristotle
has tried to present in the character of the Great-souled man—him whom
Plato has called the true king by divine right, or the autocrat by the patent of
nature. Like all such attempts to delineate a type in the terms necessarily
single and [pg cxxxiv] successive of abstract analysis, it tends occasionally
to run into caricature, and to give partial aspects an absurd prominency.
Only the greatest of artists could cope with such a task, though that artist
may be found perhaps classed among the historians. Yet it is possible to
form some conception of the ideal which Aristotle would set before us. The
Great-souled man is great, and he dare not deny the witness of his spirit. He
is one who does not quail before the anger and seek the applause of popular
opinion: he holds his head as his own, and as high as his undimmed self-
consciousness shows it is worth. There has been said to him by the reason
within him the word that Virgil erewhile addressed to Dante:
He is his own Emperor and his own Pope. He is the perfected man, in
whom is no darkness, whose soul is utter clearness, and complete harmony.
Calm in self-possessed majesty, he stands, if need be, contra mundum: but
rather, with the world beneath his feet. The chatter of personality has no
interest for him. Bent upon the best, lesser competitions for distinction have
no attraction for him. To the vulgar he will seem cold, self-confined: in his
apartness and distinction they will see the signs of a “prig.” His look will be
that of one who pities men—rather than loves them: and should he speak ill
of a foe, it is rather out of pride of heart and unbroken spirit than because
these things touch him. Such an one, in many ways, was the Florentine poet
himself.
If the Greek world in general thus conceived ἀρετή as the full bloom of
manly excellence (we all know how slightly—witness the remarks in the
Periclean oration—Greeks, [pg cxxxv] in their public and official
utterances, rated womanliness), the philosophers had a further point to
emphasise. That was what they variously called knowledge, prudence,
reason, insight, intelligence, wisdom, truth. From Socrates to Aristotle,
from Aristotle to the Stoics and Epicureans, and from the Stoics to the Neo-
Platonists, this is the common theme: the supremacy of knowledge, its
central and essential relation to virtue. They may differ—perhaps not so
widely as current prejudice would suppose—as to how this knowledge is to
be defined, what kind of knowledge it is, how acquired and maintained, and
so on. But in essentials they are at one. None of them, of course, mean that
in order to right conduct nothing more is needed than to learn and
remember what is right, the precepts and commandments of ordinary
morality. Memory is not knowledge, especially when it is out of mind. Even
an ancient philosopher was not wholly devoid of common sense. They held
—what they supposed was a fact of observation and reflection—that all
action was prompted by feelings of the values of things, by a desire of
something good or pleasing to self, and aimed at self-satisfaction and self-
realisation, but that there was great mistake in what thus afforded
satisfaction. People chose to act wrongly or erroneously, because they were,
first, mistaken about themselves and what they wanted, and, secondly,
mistaken in the means which would give them satisfaction. But this second
point was secondary. The main thing was to know yourself, what you really
were; in Plato's words, to “see the soul as it is, and know whether it have
one form only or many, or what its nature is; to look upon it with the eye of
reason in its original purity.” Self-deception, confusion, that worst
ignorance which is unaware of itself, false estimation—these are the radical
[pg cxxxvi] evils of the natural man. To these critics the testimony of
consciousness was worthless, unless corroborated. To cure this mental
confusion, this blindness of will and judgment, is the task set for
philosophy: to give inward light, to teach true self-measurement. In one
passage, much misunderstood, Plato has called this philosophic art the due
measurement of pleasures and pains. It should scarcely have been possible
to mistake the meaning. But, with the catchwords of Utilitarianism ringing
in their ears, the commentators ran straight contrary to the true teaching of
the Protagoras, consentient as it is with that of the Phaedo and the
Philebus. To measure, one must have a standard: and if Plato has one lesson
always for us, it is that a sure standard the multitude have not, but only
confusion. The so-called pleasures and pains of the world's experiences are
so entitled for different reasons, for contrary aims, and with no unity or
harmony of judgment. They are—not a fact to be accepted, but—a problem
for investigation: their reality is in question, their genuineness, solidity and
purity: and till you have settled that, you cannot measure, for you may be
measuring vacuity under the idea that there is substance. You have still to
get at the unit—i.e. the reality of pleasure. It was not Plato's view that
pleasure was a separate and independent entity: that it was exactly as it was
felt. Each pleasure is dependent for its pleasurable quality on the
consciousness it belongs to, and has only a relative truth and reality.
Bentham has written about computing the value of a “lot” of pleasures and
pains. But Plato had his mind on an earlier and more fundamental problem,
what is the truth and reality of pleasure; and his fullest but not his only
essay towards determining the value or estimating the meaning of pleasure
in the scale of being is that given in the Philebus.
[pg cxxxvii]
This then is the knowledge which Greek philosophy meant: not mere
intellect—though, of course, there is always a danger of theoretical inquiry
degenerating into abstract and formal dogma. But of the meaning there can
be no serious doubt. It is a knowledge, says Plato, to which the method of
mathematical science—the most perfect he can find acknowledged—is only
an ouverture, or perhaps, only the preliminary tuning of the strings. It is a
knowledge not eternally hypothetical—a system of sequences which have
no sure foundation. It is a knowledge which rests upon the conviction and
belief of the “idea of good”: a kind of knowledge which does not come by
direct teaching, which is not mere theory, but implies a lively conviction, a
personal apprehension, a crisis which is a kind of “conversion,” or
“inspiration.” It is as it were the prize of a great contest, in which the sword
that conquers is the sword of dialectic: a sword whereof the property is, like
that of Ithuriel's spear, to lay bare all deceptions and illusions of life. Or, to
vary the metaphor: the son of man is like the prince in the fairy tale who
goes forth to win the true queen; but there are many false pretenders decked
out to deceive his unwary eyes and foolish heart. Yet in himself there is a
power of discernment: there is something kindred with the truth:—the
witness of the Spirit—and all that education and discipline can do is to
remove obstacles, especially the obstacles within the self which perturb the
sight and mislead the judgment. Were not the soul originally possessed of
and dominated by the idea of good, it could never discern it elsewhere. On
this original kindred depends all the process of education; the influence of
which therefore is primarily negative or auxiliary. Thus the process of
history and experience,—which the work of education only reproduces in
an accelerated tempo—serves but to bring out [pg cxxxviii] the implicit
reason within into explicit conformity with the rationality of the world.
Whether therefore we agree or not with Plato's reduction of Right and Duty
to self-actualisation, we may at least admit that in the idea of perfection or
excellence, combined with the idea of knowledge or inward lucidity, he has
got the fundamental ideas on which further ethical development must build.
Self-control, self-knowledge, internal harmony, are good: and so are the
development of our several faculties and of the totality of them to the fullest
pitch of excellence. But their value does not lie entirely in themselves, or
rather there is implicit in them a reference to something beyond themselves.
They take for granted something which, because it is so taken, may also be
ignored and neglected, just because it seems so obvious. And that
implication is the social humanity in which they are the spirits of light and
leading.
To lay the stress on ἀρετή or excellence tends to leave out of sight the force
of duty; and to emphasise knowledge is allowed to disparage the heart and
feelings. The mind—even of a philosopher—finds a difficulty in holding
very different points of view in one, and where it is forced from one to
another, tends to forget the earlier altogether. Thus when the ethical
philosopher, presupposing as an absolute or unquestionable fact that man
the individual was rooted in the community, proceeded to discuss the
problem of the best and completest individual estate, he was easily led to
lose sight of the fundamental and governing condition altogether. [pg cxl]
From the moment that Aristotle lays down the thesis that man is naturally
social, to the moment when he asks how the bare ideal of excellence in
character and life can become an actuality, the community in which man
lives has retired out of sight away into the background. And it only comes
in, as it first appears, as the paedagogue to bring us to morality. And Plato,
though professedly he is speaking of the community, and is well aware that
the individual can only be saved by the salvation of the community, is
constantly falling back into another problem—the development of an
individual soul. He feels the strength of the egoistic effort after perfection,
and his essay in the end tends to lose sight altogether of its second theme.
Instead of a man he gives us a mere philosopher, a man, that is, not living
with his country's life, instinct with the heart and feeling of humanity,
inspired by art and religion, but a being set apart and exalted above his
fellows,—charged no doubt in theory with the duty of saving them, of
acting vicariously as the mediator between them and the absolute truth—but
really tending more and more to seclude himself on the edita templa of the
world, on the high-towers of speculation.
And what Plato and Aristotle did, so to speak, against their express purpose
and effort, yet did, because the force of contemporary tendency was
irresistible—that the Stoa and Epicurus did more openly and professedly.
With a difference in theory, it is true, owing to the difference in the
surroundings. Virtue in the older day of the free and glorious
commonwealth had meant physical and intellectual achievement, acts done
in the public eye, and of course for the public good—a good with which the
agent was identified at least in heart and soul, if not in his explicit
consciousness. In later and worse days, when the political [pg cxli] world,
with the world divine, had withdrawn from actual identity with the central
heart of the individual, and stood over-against him as a strange power and
little better than a nuisance, virtue came to be counted as endurance,
indifference, negative independence against a cold and a perplexing world.
But even still, virtue is excellence: it is to rise above the ignoble level: to
assert self-liberty against accident and circumstance—to attain self-
controlled, self-satisfying independence—and to become God-like in its
seclusion. Yet in two directions even it had to acknowledge something
beyond the individual. The Epicurean—following out a suggestion of
Aristotle—recognised the help which the free society of friends gave to the
full development of the single seeker after a self-satisfying and complete
life. The Stoic, not altogether refusing such help, tended rather to rest his
single self on a fellowship of ideal sort, on the great city of gods and men,
the civitas Dei. Thus, in separate halves, the two schools, into which Greek
ethics was divided, gave expression to the sense that a new and higher
community was needed—to the sense that the visible actual community no
longer realised its latent idea. The Stoic emphasised the all-embracing
necessity, the absolute comprehensiveness of the moral kingdom. The
Epicurean saw more clearly that, if the everlasting city came from heaven,
it could only visibly arise by initiation upon the earth. Christianity—in its
best work—was a conjunction of the liberty with the necessity, of the
human with the divine.
And, above all, intelligence is only half itself when it is not also will. And
both are more than mere consciousness. Plato—whom we refer to, because
he is the coryphaeus of all the diverse host of Greek philosophy—seems to
overestimate or rather to misconceive the place of knowledge. That it is the
supreme and crowning grace of the soul, he sees. But he tends to identify it
with the supreme or higher soul:—as Aristotle did after him, to be followed
by the Stoics and Neo-Platonists. For them the supreme, or almost supreme
reality is the intelligence or reason: the soul is only on a second grade of
reality, on the borders of the natural or physical world. When Plato takes
that line, he turns towards the path of asceticism, and treats the philosophic
life as a preparation for that truer life when intelligence shall be all in all,
for that better land where “divine dialogues” shall form the staple and
substance of spiritual existence. Aristotle,—who less often treads these
solitudes,—still extols the theoretic life, when the body and its needs
trouble no more, when the activity of reason—the theory of theory—is
attained at least as entirely as mortal conditions allow man to be deified. Of
the “apathy” and the reasonable conformity of the Stoics, or of the purely
negative character of Epicurean happiness (the excision of all that pained)
[pg cxliv] we need not here speak. And in Plotinus and Proclus the
deification of mere reason is at any rate the dominant note; whatever
protests the larger Greek nature in the former may from time to time offer.
The truth which philosophy should have taught was that Mind or
intelligence was the element where the inner life culminated and expanded
and flourished: the error which it often tended to spread was that
intelligence was the higher life of which all other was a degenerate
shortcoming, and something valuable on its own account.
“The key,” says Carus, “for the ascertainment of the nature of the conscious
psychical life lies in the region of the unconscious71.” The view which these
words take is at least as old as the days of Leibniz. It means that the mental
world does not abruptly emerge a full-grown intelligence, but has a genesis,
and follows a law of development: that its life may be described as the
differentiation (with integration) of a simple or indifferentiated mass. The
terms conscious and unconscious, indeed, with their lax popular uses, leave
the door wide open for misconception. But they may serve to mark that the
mind is to be understood only in a certain relation (partly of antithesis) to
nature, and the soul only in reference to the body. The so-called “superior
faculties”—specially characteristic of humanity—are founded upon, and do
not abruptly supersede, the lower powers which are supposed to be
specially obvious in the animals72. The individual and specific phenomena
of consciousness, which the psychologist is generally supposed to study,
rest upon a deeper, less explicated, more indefinite, life of sensibility, which
in its turn fades away by immeasurable gradations into something
irresponsive to the ordinary tests for sensation and life.
[pg cxlvii]
And yet the moment we attempt to leave the daylight of consciousness for
the darker sides of sub-conscious life, the risks of misinterpretation
multiply. The problem is to some extent the same as confronts the student
of the ideas and principles of primitive races. There, the temptation of
seeing things through the “spectacles of civilisation” is almost irresistible.
So in psychology we are apt to import into the life of sensation and feeling
the distinctions and relations of subsequent intellection. Nor is the difficulty
lessened by Hegel's method which deals with soul, sentiency, and
consciousness as grades or general characteristics in a developmental
advance. He borrows his illustrations from many quarters, from morbid and
anomalous states of consciousness,—less from the cases of savages,
children and animals. These illustrations may be called a loose induction.
But it requires a much more powerful instrument than mere induction to
build up a scientific system; a framework of general principle or theory is
the only basis on which to build theory by the allegation of facts, however
numerous. Yet in philosophic science, which is systematised knowledge, all
facts strictly so described will find their place and be estimated at their
proper value.
Psychology (with Hegel) takes up the work of science from biology. The
mind comes before it as the supreme product of the natural world, the finest
flower of organic life, the “truth” of the physical process. As such it is
called by the time-honoured name of Soul. If we further go on to say that
the soul is the principle of life, [pg cxlviii] we must not understand this vital
principle to be something over and above the life of which it is the
principle. Such a locally-separable principle is an addition which is due to
the analogy of mechanical movement, where a detached agent sets in
motion and directs the machinery. But in the organism the principle is not
thus detachable as a thing or agent. By calling Soul the principle of life we
rather mean that in the vital organism, so far as it lives, all the real variety,
separation, and discontinuity of parts must be reduced to unity and identity,
or as Hegel would say, to ideality. To live is thus to keep all differences
fluid and permeable in the fire of the life-process. Or to use a familiar term
of logic, the Soul is the concept or intelligible unity of the organic body. But
to call it a concept might suggest that it is only the conception through
which we represent to ourselves the variety in unity of the organism. The
soul, however, is more than a mere concept: and life is more than a mere
mode of description for a group of movements forming an objective unity.
It is a unity, subjective and objective. The organism is one life, controlling
difference: and it is also one by our effort to comprehend it. The Soul
therefore is in Hegelian language described as the Idea rather than the
concept of the organic body. Life is the generic title for this subject-object:
but the life may be merely physical, or it may be intellectual and practical,
or it may be absolute, i.e. will and know all that it is, and be all that it
knows and wills.
Up to this point the world is what is called an external, which is here taken
to mean (not a world external to the individual, but) a self-externalised
world. That is to say, it is the observer who has hitherto by his interpretation
of his perceptions supplied the “Spirit in Nature.” In itself the external
world has no inside, [pg cxlix] no centre: it is we who read into it the
conception of a life-history. We are led to believe that a principle of unity is
always at work throughout the physical world—even in the mathematical
laws of natural operation. It is only intelligible and credible to us as a
system, a continuous and regular development. But that system is only a
hypothetical idea, though it is held to be a conclusion to which all the
evidence seems unequivocally to point. And, even in organic life, the unity,
though more perfect and palpable than in the mechanical and inorganic
world, is only a perception, a vision,—a necessary mode of realising the
unity of the facts. The phenomenon of life reveals as in a picture and an
ocular demonstration the conformity of inward and outward, the identity of
whole and parts, of power and utterance. But it is still outside the observer.
In the function of sensibility and sentiency, however, we stand as it were on
the border-line between biology and psychology. At one step we have been
brought within the harmony, and are no longer mere observers and
reflecters. The sentient not merely is, but is aware that it is. Hitherto as life,
it only is the unity in diversity, and diversity in unity, for the outsider, i.e.
only implicitly: now it is so for itself, or consciously. And in the first stage
it does not know, but feels or is sentient. Here, for the first time, is created
the distinction of inward and outward. Loosely indeed we may, like Mr.
Spencer, speak of outward and inward in physiology: but strictly speaking,
what Goethe says is true, Natur hat weder Kern noch Schaale73. Nature in
the narrower sense knows no distinction of the inward and outward in its
phenomena: it is a purely superficial order and succession of appearance
and event. The Idea which has been visible to an intelligent [pg cl]
percipient in the types and laws of the natural world, now is, actually is—is
in and for itself—but at first in a minimum of content, a mere point of light,
or rather the dawn which has yet to expand into the full day.
Spinoza has asserted that “all individual bodies are animate, though in
different degrees74.” Now it is to a great extent this diversity of degree on
which the main interest turns. Yet it is well to remember that the abrupt and
trenchant separations which popular practice loves are overridden to a
deeper view by an essential unity of idea, reducing them to indifference. If,
that is, we take seriously the Spinozist unity of Substance, and the continual
correlation (to call it no more) of extension and consciousness therein, we
cannot avoid the conclusion which even Bacon would admit of something
describable as attraction and perception, something subduing diversity to
unity. But whether it be well to name this soul or life is a different matter. It
may indeed only be taken to mean that all true being must be looked on as a
real unity and individuality, must, that is, be conceived as manifesting itself
in organisation, must be referred to a self-centred and self-developing
activity. But this—which is the fundamental thesis of idealism—is hardly
all that is meant. Rather Spinoza would imply that all things which form a
real unity must have life—must have inner principle and unifying reality:
and what he teaches is closely akin to the Leibnitian doctrine that every
substantial existence reposes upon a monad, a unity which is at once both a
force and a cognition, a “representation” and an appetite or nisus to act. [pg
cli] When Fechner in a series of works75 expounds and defends the
hypothesis that plants and planets are not destitute of soul, any more than
man and animals, he only gives a more pronounced expression to this
idealisation or spiritualisation of the natural world. But for the moment the
point to be noted is that all of this idealistic doctrine is an inference, or a
development which finds its point d'appui in the fact of sensation. And the
problem of the Philosophy of Mind is just to trace the process whereby a
mere shock of sensation has grown into a conception and a faith in the
goodness, beauty and intelligence of the world.
Schopenhauer has put the point with his usual picturesqueness. Outward
nature presents nothing but a play of forces. At first, however, this force
shows merely the mechanical phenomena of pressure and impact, and its
theory is sufficiently described by mathematical physics. But in the process
of nature force assumes higher types, types where it loses a certain amount
of its externality76, till in the organic world it acquires a peculiar phase
which Schopenhauer calls Will, meaning by that, however, an organising
and controlling power, a tendency or nisus to be and live, which is
persistent and potent, but without consciousness. This blind force, which
however has a certain coherence and purposiveness, is in the animal
organism endowed with a new character, in consequence of the emergence
of a new organ. This organ, the brain and nervous system, causes the
evolution into clear day of an element which has been growing more and
more urgent. The gathering tendency of force to return into itself is now
complete: the cycle of operation is [pg clii] formed: and the junction of the
two currents issues in the spark of sensation. The blind force now becomes
seeing.
Soul, says Hegel, is not a separate and additional something over and above
the rest of nature: it is rather nature's “'universal immaterialism, and simple
ideal life77.” There were ancient philosophers who spoke of the soul as a
self-adjusting number,—as a harmony, or equilibrium78—and the moderns
have added considerably to the list of these analogical definitions. As
definitions they obviously fall short. Yet these things give, as it were, by
anticipation, an image of soul, as the “ideality,” which reduces the manifold
to [pg cliii] unity. The adhesions and cohesions of matter, its gravitating
attractions, its chemical affinities and electrical polarities, the intricate out-
and-in of organic structure, are all preludes to the true incorporating unity
which is the ever-immanent supersession of the endless self-externalism
and successionalism of physical reality. But in sentiency, feeling, or
sensibility, the unity which all of these imply without reaching, is explicitly
present. It is implicitly an all-embracing unity: an infinite,—which has no
doors and no windows, for the good reason that it needs none, because it
has nothing outside it, because it “expresses” and “envelopes” (however
confusedly at first) the whole universe. Thus, even if, with localising
phraseology, we may describe mind, where it appears emerging in the
natural world, as a mere feeble and incidental outburst,—a rebellion
breaking out as in some petty province or isolated region against the great
law of the physical realm—we are in so speaking taking only an external
standpoint. But with the rise of mind in nature the bond of externalism is
implicitly overcome. To it, and where it really is, there is nothing outside,
nothing transcendent. Everything which is said to be outside mind is only
outside a localised and limited mind—outside a mind which is imperfectly
and abstractly realised—not outside mind absolutely. Mind is the absolute
negation of externality: not a mere relative negative, as the organism may
be biologically described as inner in respect of the environment. To
accomplish this negation in actuality, to bring the multiplicity and
externality of things into the unity and identity of one Idea, is the process of
development of mind from animal sensibility to philosophic knowledge,
from appetite to art,—the process of culture through the social state under
the influence of religion.
The step by which the universality or unity of the self is realised in the
variety of its sensation is Habit. Habit gives us a definite standing-ground in
the flux of single impressions: it is the identification of ourselves with what
is most customary and familiar: an identification which takes place by
practice and repetition. If it circumscribes us to one little province of being,
it on the other frees us from the vague indeterminateness where we are at
the mercy of every passing mood. It makes thus much of our potential
selves our very own, our acquisition and permanent possession. It, above
all, makes us free and at one with our bodily part, so that henceforth we
start as a subjective unit of body and soul. We have now as the result of the
anthropological process a self or ego, an individual consciousness able to
reflect and compare, setting itself on one side (a soul [pg clix] in bodily
organisation), and on the other setting an object of consciousness, or
external world, a world of other things. All this presupposes that the soul
has actualised itself by appropriating and acquiring as its expression and
organ the physical sensibility which is its body. By restricting and
establishing itself, it has gained a fixed standpoint. No doubt it has localised
and confined itself, but it is no longer at the disposal of externals and
accident: it has laid the foundation for higher developments.
Interest in these questions went naturally with the new conception of the
place of Man in Nature, and of Nature as the matrix of mind84. But it had
been acutely stimulated by the performances and professions of Mesmer at
Vienna and Paris in the last quarter of the eighteenth century. These—
though by no means [pg clxii] really novel—had forced the artificial world
of science and fashion to discuss the claim advanced for a new force which,
amongst other things, could cure ailments that baffled the ordinary
practitioner. This new force—mainly because of the recent interest in the
remarkable advances of magnetic and electrical research—was conceived
as a fluid, and called Animal Magnetism. At one time indeed Mesmer
actually employed a magnet in the manipulation by which he induced the
peculiar condition in his patients. The accompaniments of his procedure
were in many respects those of the quack-doctor; and with the quack indeed
he was often classed. A French commission of inquiry appointed to
examine into his performances reported in 1784 that, while there was no
doubt as to the reality of many of the phenomena, and even of the cures,
there was no evidence for the alleged new physical force, and declared the
effects to be mainly attributable to the influence of imagination. And with
the mention of this familiar phrase, further explanation was supposed to be
rendered superfluous.
It cannot be said that the net results of these observations and hypotheses
are of a very definitive character. While a large amount of controversy has
been waged on the comparative importance of the several methods and
instruments by which the hypnotic or mesmeric trance may be induced, and
a scarcely less wide range of divergence prevails with regard to the
physiological and pathological conditions in connexion with which it has
been most conspicuously manifested, there has been less anxiety shown to
determine its precise psychical nature, or its significance in mental
development. And yet the better understanding of these aspects may throw
light on several points connected with primitive religion and the history of
early civilisation, indeed over the whole range of what is called
Völkerpsychologie. Indeed this is one of the points which may be said to
emerge out of the confusion of dispute. Phenomena at least analogous to
those styled hypnotic have a wide range in the anthropological sphere87: and
the proper characters which belong to them will only be caught by an
observer who examines them in the widest variety of examples. Another
feature which has been put in prominence is what has been called
“psychological automatism.” And in this name two points [pg clxvi] seem
to deserve note. The first is the spontaneous and as it were mechanical
consecution of mental states in the soul whence the interfering effect of
voluntary consciousness has been removed. And the second is the unfailing
or accurate regularity, so contrary to the hesitating and uncertain procedure
of our conscious and reasoned action, which so often is seen in the
unreflecting and unreasoned movements. To this invariable sequence of
psychical movement the superior control and direction by the intelligent
self has to adapt itself, just as it respects the order of physical laws.
What Hegel chiefly sees in these phenomena is their indication, even on the
natural side of man, of that ideality of the material, which it is the work of
intelligence to produce in the more spiritual life, in the fully-developed
mind. The latter is the supreme over-soul, that Absolute Mind which in our
highest moods, aesthetic and religious, we approximate to. But mind, as it
tends towards the higher end to “merge itself in light,” to identify itself yet
not wholly lost, but retained, in the fullness of undivided intellectual being,
so at the lower end it springs from a natural and underlying unity, the
immense solidarity of nether-soul, the great Soul of Nature—the
“Substance” which is to be raised into the “Subject” which is true divinity.
Between these two unities, the nature-given nether-soul and the spirit-won
over-soul, lies the conscious life of man: a process of differentiation which
narrows and of redintegration which enlarges,—which alternately builds up
an isolated personality and dissolves it in a common intelligence and
sympathy. It is because [pg clxix] mental or tacit “suggestion”88 (i.e. will-
influence exercised without word or sign, or other sensible mode of
connexion), thought-transference, or thought-reading (which is more than
dexterous apprehension of delicate muscular signs), exteriorisation or
transposition of sensibility into objects primarily non-sensitive,
clairvoyance (i.e. the power of describing, as if from direct perception,
objects or events removed in space beyond the recognised limits of
sensation), and somnambulism, so far as it implies lucid vision with sealed
eyes,—it is because these things seem to show the essential ideality of
matter, that Hegel is interested in them. The ordinary conditions of
consciousness and even of practical life in society are a derivative and
secondary state; a product of processes of individualism, which however are
never completed, and leave a large margin for idealising intelligence to
fulfil. From a state which is not yet personality to a state which is more than
can be described as personality—lies the mental movement. So Fichte, too,
had regarded the power of the somnambulist as laying open a world
underlying the development of egoity and self-consciousness89: “the merely
sensuous man is still in somnambulism,” only a somnambulism of waking
hours: “the true waking is the life in God, to be free in him, all else is sleep
and dream.” “Egoity,” he adds, “is a merely formal principle, utterly, and
never qualitative (i.e. the essence and universal force).” For Schopenhauer,
too, the experiences of animal magnetism had seemed to prove the [pg clxx]
absolute supernatural power of the radical will in its superiority to the
intellectual categories of space, time, and causal sequence: to prove the
reality of the metaphysical which is at the basis of all conscious divisions.
Thus, for the third time, but now on a higher plane, that of intelligence and
rationality, is traced the process of development or realisation by which
reason becomes reasoned knowledge and rational will, a free or
autonomous intelligence. And, as before, the starting-point, alike in
theoretical and practical mind, is feeling—or immediate knowledge and
immediate sense of Ought. The basis of thought is an immediate perception
—a sensuous affection or given something, and the basis of the idea of a
general satisfaction is the natural claim to determine the outward existence
conformably to individual feeling. In intelligent perception or intuition the
important factor is attention, which raises it above mere passive acceptance
and awareness of a given fact. Attention thus involves on one hand the
externality of its object, and on the other affirms its dependence on the act
of the subject: it sets the objects before and out of itself, in space and time,
but yet in so doing it shows itself master of the objects. If perception
presuppose attention, in short, they cease to be wholly outward: we make
them ours, and the space and time they fill are projected by us. So attended
to, they are appropriated, [pg clxxiv] inwardised and recollected: they take
their place in a mental place and mental time: they receive a general or de-
individualised character in the memory-image. These are retained as mental
property, but retained actually only in so far they are revivable and revived.
Such revival is the work of imagination working by the so-called laws of
association. But the possession of its ideas thus inwardised and recollected
by the mind is largely a matter of chance. The mind is not really fully
master of them until it has been able to give them a certain objectivity, by
replacing the mental image by a vocal, i.e. a sensible sign. By means of
words, intelligence turns its ideas or representations into quasi-realities: it
creates a sort of superior sense-world, the world of language, where ideas
live a potential, which is also an actual, life. Words are sensibles, but they
are sensibles which completely lose themselves in their meaning. As
sensibles, they render possible that verbal memory which is the handmaid
of thought: but which also as merely mechanical can leave thought
altogether out of account. It is through words that thought is made possible:
for it alone permits the movement through ideas without being distracted
through a multitude of associations. In them thought has an instrument
completely at its own level, but still only a machine, and in memory the
working of that machine. We think in names, not in general images, but in
terms which only serve as vehicles for mental synthesis and analysis.
[pg clxxvi]
Essay V. Ethics And Politics.
“In dealing,” says Hegel, “with the Idea of the State, we must not have
before our eyes a particular state, or a particular institution: we must rather
study the Idea, this actual God, on his own account. Every State, however
bad we may find it according to our principles, however defective we may
discover this or that feature to be, still contains, particularly if it belongs to
the mature states of our time, all the essential factors of its existence. But as
it is easier to discover faults than to comprehend the affirmative, people
easily fall into the mistake of letting individual aspects obscure the intrinsic
organism of the State itself. The State is no ideal work of art: it stands in the
everyday world, in the sphere, that is, of arbitrary act, accident, and error,
and a variety of faults may mar the regularity of its traits. But the ugliest
man, the criminal, a sick man and a cripple, is after all a living man; the
affirmative, Life, subsists in spite of the defect: and this affirmative is here
the theme93.” “It is the theme of philosophy,” he adds, “to ascertain the
substance which is immanent in the show of the temporal and transient, and
the eternal which is present.”
[pg clxxvii]
But if this is true, it is also to be remembered that the philosopher is, like
other men, the son of his age, and estimates the value of reality from
preconceptions and aspirations due to his generation. The historical
circumstances of his nation as well as the personal experiences of his life
help to determine his horizon, even in the effort to discover the hidden pulse
and movement of the social organism. This is specially obvious in political
philosophy. The conception of ethics and politics which is presented in the
Encyclopaedia was in 1820 produced with more detail as the Grundlinien
der Philosophie des Rechts. Appearing, as it did, two years after his
appointment to a professorship at Berlin, and in the midst of a political
struggle between the various revolutionary and conservative powers and
parties of Germany, the book became, and long remained, a target for
embittered criticism. The so-called War of Liberation or national movement
to shake off the French yoke was due to a coalition of parties, and had
naturally been in part supported by tendencies and aims which went far
beyond the ostensive purpose either of leaders or of combatants.
Aspirations after a freer state were entwined with radical and socialistic
designs to reform the political hierarchy of the Fatherland: high ideals and
low vulgarities were closely intermixed: and the noble enthusiasm of youth
was occasionally played on by criminal and anarchic intriguers. In a strong
and wise and united Germany some of these schemes might have been
tolerated. But strength, wisdom, and unity were absent. In the existing
tension between Austria and Prussia for the leadership, in the ill-adapted
and effete constitutions of the several principalities which were yet
expected to realise the [pg clxxviii] advance which had taken place in
society and ideas during the last thirty years, the outlook on every hand
seemed darker and more threatening than it might have otherwise done.
Governments, which had lost touch with their peoples, suspected
conspiracy and treason: and a party in the nation credited their rulers with
gratuitous designs against private liberty and rights. There was a vast but
ill-defined enthusiasm in the breasts of the younger world, and it was shared
by many of their teachers. It seemed to their immense aspirations that the
war of liberation had failed of its true object and left things much as they
were. The volunteers had not fought for the political systems of Austria or
Prussia, or for the three-and-thirty princes of Germany: but for ideas, vague,
beautiful, stimulating. To such a mood the continuance of the old system
was felt as a cruel deception and a reaction. The governments on their part
had not realised the full importance of the spirit that had been aroused, and
could not at a moment's notice set their house in order, even had there been
a clearer outlook for reform than was offered. They too had suffered, and
had realised their insecurity: and were hardly in a mood to open their gates
to the enemy.
Coming on such a situation of affairs, Hegel's book would have been likely
in any case to provoke criticism. For it took up a line of political theory
which was little in accord with the temper of the age. The conception of the
state which it expounded is not far removed in essentials from the
conception which now dominates the political life of the chief European
nations. But in his own time it came upon ears which were naturally
disposed to misconceive it. It was unacceptable to the adherents of the
ancien régime, as much as to the liberals. It was declared by one party to be
a glorification [pg clxxix] of the Prussian state: by another to rationalise the
sanctities of authority. It was pointed out that the new professor was a
favourite of the leading minister, that his influence was dominant in
scholastic appointments, and that occasional gratuities from the crown
proved his acceptability. A contemporary professor, Fries, remarked that
Hegel's theory of the state had grown “not in the gardens of science but on
the dung-hill of servility.” Hegel himself was aware that he had planted a
blow in the face of a “shallow and pretentious sect,” and that his book had
“given great offence to the demagogic folk.” Alike in religious and political
life he was impatient of sentimentalism, of rhetorical feeling, of wordy
enthusiasm. A positive storm of scorn burst from him at much-promising
and little-containing declamation that appealed to the pathos of ideas,
without sense of the complex work of construction and the system of
principles which were needed to give them reality. His impatience of
demagogic gush led him (in the preface) into a tactless attack on Fries, who
was at the moment in disgrace for his participation in the demonstration at
the Wartburg. It led him to an attack on the bumptiousness of those who
held that conscientious conviction was ample justification for any
proceeding:—an attack which opponents were not unwilling to represent as
directed against the principle of conscience itself.
Yet Hegel's views on the nature of political unity were not new. Their
nucleus had been formed nearly twenty years before. In the years that
immediately followed the French revolution he had gone through the usual
anarchic stage of intelligent youth. He had wondered whether humanity
might not have had a nobler destiny, had fate given supremacy to some
heresy rather than the orthodox creed of Christendom. He had [pg clxxx]
seen religion in the past “teaching what despotism wished,—contempt of
the human race, its incapacity for anything good94.” But his earliest
reflections on political power belong to a later date, and are inspired, not so
much by the vague ideals of humanitarianism, as by the spirit of national
patriotism. They are found in a “Criticism of the German Constitution”
apparently dating from the year 180295. It is written after the peace of
Lunéville had sealed for Germany the loss of her provinces west of the
Rhine, and subsequent to the disasters of the German arms at Hohenlinden
and Marengo. It is almost contemporaneous with the measures of 1803 and
1804, which affirmed the dissolution of the “Holy Roman Empire” of
German name. The writer of this unpublished pamphlet sees his country in
a situation almost identical with that which Macchiavelli saw around him in
Italy. It is abused by petty despots, distracted by mean particularist
ambitions, at the mercy of every foreign power. It was such a scene which,
as Hegel recalls, had prompted and justified the drastic measures proposed
in the Prince,—measures which have been ill-judged by the closet moralist,
but evince the high statesmanship of the Florentine. In the Prince, an
intelligent reader can see “the enthusiasm of patriotism underlying the cold
and dispassionate doctrines.” Macchiavelli dared to declare that Italy must
become a state, and to assert that “there is no higher duty for a state than to
maintain itself, and to punish relentlessly every author of anarchy,—the
supreme, and perhaps sole political crime.” And [pg clxxxi] like teaching,
Hegel adds, is needed for Germany. Only, he concludes, no mere
demonstration of the insanity of utter separation of the particular from his
kin will ever succeed in converting the particularists from their conviction
of the absoluteness of personal and private rights. “Insight and intelligence
always excite so much distrust that force alone avails to justify them; then
man yields them obedience96.”
“The German political edifice,” says the writer, “is nothing else but the sum
of the rights which the single parts have withdrawn from the whole; and this
justice, which is ever on the watch to prevent the state having any power
left, is the essence of the constitution.” The Peace of Westphalia had but
served to constitute or stereotype anarchy: the German empire had by that
instrument divested itself of all rights of political unity, and thrown itself on
the goodwill of its members. What then, it may be asked, is, in Hegel's
view, the indispensable minimum essential to a state? And the answer will
be, organised strength,—a central and united force. “The strength of a
country lies neither in the multitude of its inhabitants and fighting men, nor
in its fertility, nor in its size, but solely in the way its parts are by reasonable
combination made a single political force enabling everything to be used for
the common defence.” Hegel speaks scornfully of “the philanthropists and
moralists who decry politics as an endeavour and an art to seek private
utility at the cost of right”: he tells them that “it is foolish to oppose the
interest or (as it is expressed by the more morally-obnoxious word) the
utility of the state to its right”: that the “rights of a state are the utility of the
state as established and recognised by compacts”: and that “war” (which
they [pg clxxxii] would fain abolish or moralise) “has to decide not which
of the rights asserted by either party is the true right (—for both parties
have a true right), but which right has to give way to the other.”
It is evident from these propositions that Hegel takes that view of political
supremacy which has been associated with the name of Hobbes. But his
views also reproduce the Platonic king of men, “who can rule and dare not
lie.” “All states,” he declares, “are founded by the sublime force of great
men, not by physical strength. The great man has something in his features
which others would gladly call their lord. They obey him against their will.
Their immediate will is his will, but their conscious will is otherwise.... This
is the prerogative of the great man to ascertain and to express the absolute
will. All gather round his banner. He is their God.” “The state,” he says
again, “is the self-certain absolute mind which recognises no definite
authority but its own: which acknowledges no abstract rules of good and
bad, shameful and mean, craft and deception.” So also Hobbes describes the
prerogatives of the sovereign Leviathan. But the Hegelian God immanent in
the state is a higher power than Hobbes knows: he is no mortal, but in his
truth an immortal God. He speaks by (what in this early essay is called) the
Absolute Government97: the government of the Law—the true impersonal
sovereign,—distinct alike from the single ruler and the multitude of the
ruled. “It is absolutely only universality as against particular. As this
absolute, ideal, universal, compared to which everything else is a particular,
it is the phenomenon of God. Its words are his decision, and it can appear
[pg clxxxiii] and exist under no other form.... The Absolute government is
divine, self-sanctioned and not made98.” The real strength—the real
connecting-mean which gives life to sovereign and to subject—is
intelligence free and entire, independent both of what individuals feel and
believe and of the quality of the ruler. “The spiritual bond,” he says in a
lower form of speech, “is public opinion: it is the true legislative body,
national assembly, declaration of the universal will which lives in the
execution of all commands.” This still small voice of public opinion is the
true and real parliament: not literally making laws, but revealing them. If
we ask, where does this public opinion appear and how does it disengage
itself from the masses of partisan judgment? Hegel answers,—and to the
surprise of those who have not entered into the spirit of his age99—it is
embodied in the Aged and the Priests. Both of these have ceased to live in
the real world: they are by nature and function disengaged from the
struggles of particular existence, have risen above the divergencies of social
classes. They breathe the ether of pure contemplation. “The sunset of life
gives them mystical lore,” or at least removes from old age the distraction
of selfishness: while the priest is by function set apart from the divisions of
human interest. Understood in a large sense, Hegel's view is that the real
voice of experience is elicited through those who have attained indifference
to the distorting influence of human parties, and who see life steadily and
whole.
If this utterance shows the little belief Hegel had in the ordinary methods of
legislation through “representative” bodies, and hints that the real substance
of political [pg clxxxiv] life is deeper than the overt machinery of political
operation, it is evident that this theory of “divine right” is of a different
stamp from what used to go under that name. And, again, though the power
of the central state is indispensable, he is far from agreeing with the so-
called bureaucratic view that “a state is a machine with a single spring
which sets in motion all the rest of the machinery.” “Everything,” he says,
“which is not directly required to organise and maintain the force for giving
security without and within must be left by the central government to the
freedom of the citizens. Nothing ought to be so sacred in the eyes of a
government as to leave alone and to protect, without regard to utilities, the
free action of the citizens in such matters as do not affect its fundamental
aim: for this freedom is itself sacred100.” He is no friend of paternal
bureaucracy. “The pedantic craving to settle every detail, the mean jealousy
against estates and corporations administrating and directing their own
affairs, the base fault-finding with all independent action on the part of the
citizens, even when it has no immediate bearing on the main political
interest, has been decked out with reasons to show that no penny of public
expenditure, made for a country of twenty or thirty millions' population, can
be laid out, without first being, not permitted, but commanded, controlled
and revised by the supreme government.” You can see, he remarks, in the
first village after you enter Prussian territory the lifeless and wooden
routine which prevails. The whole country suffers also from the way
religion has been mixed up with political rights, and a particular creed
pronounced by law indispensable both for sovereign and full-privileged
subject. In a word, the unity and vigour of the state is quite compatible with
considerable latitude [pg clxxxv] and divergence in laws and judicature, in
the imposition and levying of taxes, in language, manners, civilisation and
religion. Equality in all these points is desirable for social unity: but it is not
indispensable for political strength.
This decided preference for the unity of the state against the system of
checks and counterchecks, which sometimes goes by the name of a
constitution, came out clearly in Hegel's attitude in discussing the dispute
between the Würtembergers and their sovereign in 1815-16. Würtemberg,
with its complicated aggregation of local laws, had always been a paradise
of lawyers, and the feudal rights or privileges of the local oligarchies—the
so-called “good old law”—were the boast of the country. All this had
however been aggravated by the increase of territory received in 1805: and
the king, following the examples set by France and even by Bavaria,
promulgated of his own grace a “constitution” remodelling the electoral
system of the country. Immediately an outcry burst out against the attempt
to destroy the ancient liberties. Uhland tuned his lyre to the popular cry:
Rückert sang on the king's side. To Hegel the contest presented itself as a
struggle between the attachment to traditional rights, merely because they
are old, and the resolution to carry out reasonable reform whether it be
agreeable to the reformed or not: or rather he saw in it resistance of
particularism, of separation, clinging to use and wont, and basing itself on
formal pettifogging objections, against the spirit of organisation. Anything
more he declined to see. And probably he was right in ascribing a large part
of the opposition to inertia, to vanity and self-interest, combined with the
want of political perception of the needs of Würtemberg and Germany. But
on the other hand, he failed to remember the insecurity and danger of such
[pg clxxxvi] “gifts of the Danai”: he forgot the sense of free-born men that a
constitution is not something to be granted (octroyé) as a grace, but
something that must come by the spontaneous act of the innermost self of
the community. He dealt rather with the formal arguments which were used
to refuse progress, than with the underlying spirit which prompted the
opposition101.
The philosopher lives (as Plato has well reminded us) too exclusively
within the ideal. Bent on the essential nucleus of institutions, he attaches
but slight importance to the variety of externals, and fails to realise the
practice of the law-courts. He forgets that what weighs lightly in logic, may
turn the scale in real life and experience. For feeling and sentiment he has
but scant respect: he is brusque and uncompromising: and cannot realise all
the difficulties and dangers that beset the Idea in the mazes of the world,
and may ultimately quite alter a plan which at first seemed independent of
petty details. Better than other men perhaps he recognises in theory how the
mere universal only exists complete in an individual shape: but more than
other men he forgets these truths of insight, when the business of life calls
for action or for judgment. He cannot at a moment's notice remember that
he is, if not, as Cicero says, in faece Romuli, the member of a degenerate
commonwealth, at least living in a world where good and evil are not, as
logic presupposes, sharply divided but intricately intertwined.
[pg clxxxvii]
In the essay already referred to, Hegel has designated something analogous
to this as Natural or Physical Ethics, or as Ethics in its relative or
comparative stage. Here Man first shows his superiority to nature, or enters
on his properly ethical function, by transforming the physical world into his
possession. He makes himself the lord of natural objects—stamping them as
his, and not their own, making them his permanent property, his tools, his
instruments of exchange [pg cxci] and production. The fundamental ethical
act is appropriation by labour, and the first ethical world is the creation of
an economic system, the institution of property. For property, or at least
possession and appropriation, is the dominant idea, with its collateral and
sequent principles. And at first, even human beings are treated on the same
method as other things: as objects in a world of objects or aggregate of
things: as things to be used and acquired, as means and instruments,—not in
any sense as ends in themselves. It is a world in which the relation of
master and slave is dominant,—where owner and employer is set in
antithesis against his tools and chattels. But the Nemesis of his act issues in
making the individual the servant of his so-called property. He has become
an objective power by submitting himself to objectivity: he has literally put
himself into the object he has wrought, and is now a thing among things: for
what he owns, what he has appropriated, determines what he is. The real
powers in the world thus established are the laws of possession-holding: the
laws dominate man: and he is only freed from dependence on casual
externals, by making himself thoroughly the servant of his possessions.
The only salvation, and it is but imperfect, that can be reached on this stage
is by the family union. The sexual tie, is at first entirely on a level with the
other arrangements of the sphere. The man or woman is but a chattel and a
tool; a casual appropriation which gradually is transformed into a
permanent possession and a permanent bond104. But, as the family
constituted itself, it helped to afford a promise of better things. An ideal
interest—the religion of the household—extending [pg cxcii] beyond the
individual, and beyond the moment,—binding past and present, and parents
to offspring, gave a new character to the relation of property. Parents and
children form a unity, which overrides and essentially permeates their
“difference” from each other: there is no exchange, no contract, nor, in the
stricter sense, property between the members. In the property-idea they are
lifted out of their isolation, and in the continuity of family life there is a
certain analogue of immortality. But, says Hegel, “though the family be the
highest totality of which Nature is capable, the absolute identity is in it still
inward, and is not instituted in absolute form; and hence, too, the
reproduction of the totality is an appearance, the appearance of the
children105.” “The power and the intelligence, the ‘difference’ of the parents,
stands in inverse proportion to the youth and vigour of the child: and these
two sides of life flee from and are sequent on each other, and are
reciprocally external106.” Or, as we may put it, the god of the family is a
departed ancestor, a ghost in the land of the dead: it has not really a
continuous and unified life. In such a state of society—a state of nature—
and in its supreme form, the family, there is no adequate principle which
though real shall still give ideality and unity to the self-isolating aspects of
life. There is wanted something which shall give expression to its
“indifference,” which shall control the tendency of this partial moralisation
to sink at every moment into individuality, and lift it from its immersion in
nature. Family life and economic groups (—for these two, which Hegel
subsequently separates, are here kept close together) need an ampler and
wider [pg cxciii] life to keep them from stagnating in their several
selfishnesses.
This freshening and corrective influence they get in the first instance from
deeds of violence and crime. Here is the “negative unsettling” of the narrow
fixities, of the determinate conditions or relationships into which the
preceding processes of labour and acquisition have tended to stereotype life.
The harsh restriction brings about its own undoing. Man may subject
natural objects to his formative power, but the wild rage of senseless
devastation again and again bursts forth to restore the original formlessness.
He may build up his own pile of wealth, store up his private goods, but the
thief and the robber with the instincts of barbarian socialism tread on his
steps: and every stage of appropriation has for its sequel a crop of acts of
dispossession. He may secure by accumulation his future life; but the
murderer for gain's sake cuts it short. And out of all this as a necessary
consequence stands avenging justice. And in the natural world of ethics—
where true moral life has not yet arisen—this is mere retaliation or the lex
talionis;—the beginning of an endless series of vengeance and counter-
vengeance, the blood-feud. Punishment, in the stricter sense of the term,—
which looks both to antecedents and effects in character—cannot yet come
into existence; for to punish there must be something superior to
individualities, an ethical idea embodied in an institution, to which the
injurer and the injured alike belong. But as yet punishment is only
vengeance, the personal and natural equivalent, the physical reaction
against injury, perhaps regulated and formulated by custom and usage, but
not essentially altered from its purely retaliatory character. These crimes—
or transgressions—are thus by Hegel quaintly conceived as storms which
clear the air—which shake the individualist [pg cxciv] out of his slumber.
The scene in which transgression thus acts is that of the so-called state of
nature, where particularism was rampant: where moral right was not, but
only the right of nature, of pre-occupation, of the stronger, of the first maker
and discoverer. Crime is thus the “dialectic” which shakes the fixity of
practical arrangements, and calls for something in which the idea of a
higher unity, a permanent substance of life, shall find realisation.
Of the peasant order Hegel has less to say. On one side the “country” as
opposed to the “town” has a closer natural sympathy with the common and
general interest: and the peasantry is the undifferentiated, solid and sound,
basis of the national life. It forms the submerged mass, out of which the best
soldiers are made, and which out of the depths of earth brings forward
nourishment as well as all the materials of elementary necessity.
Faithfulness and loyalty are its virtues: but it is personal allegiance to a
commanding superior,—not to a law or a general view—for the peasant is
[pg ccii] weak in comprehensive intelligence, though shrewd in detailed
observation.
Of the purely political function of the state Hegel in this sketch says almost
nothing. But under the head of the general government of the state he deals
with its social functions. For a moment he refers to the well-known
distinction of the legislative, judicial and executive powers. But it is only to
remark that “in every governmental act all three are conjoined. They are
abstractions, none of which can get a reality of its own,—which, in other
words, cannot be constituted and organised as powers. Legislation,
judicature, and executive are something completely formal, empty, and
contentless.... Whether the others are or are not bare abstractions, empty
activities, depends entirely on the executive power; and this is absolutely
the government116.” Treating government as the organic movement by which
the universal and the particular in the commonwealth come into relations,
he finds that it presents three forms, or gives rise to three systems. The
highest and last of these is the “educational” system. By this he understands
all that activity by which the intelligence of the state tries directly to mould
and guide the character and fortunes of its members: all the means of
culture and discipline, whether in general or for individuals, all training to
public function, to truthfulness, to good manners. Under the same head
come conquest and colonisation as state agencies. The second system is the
judicial, which instead of, like the former, aiming at the formation or
reformation of its members is satisfied by subjecting individual
transgression to a process of rectification by the general principle. With
regard to the system of judicature, Hegel argues for a variety of procedure
to suit different ranks, and for a corresponding [pg cciii] modification of
penalties. “Formal rigid equality is just what does not spare the character.
The same penalty which in one estate brings no infamy causes in another a
deep and irremediable hurt.” And with regard to the after life of the
transgressor who has borne his penalty: “Punishment is the reconciliation of
the law with itself. No further reproach for his crime can be addressed to the
person who has undergone his punishment. He is restored to membership of
his estate117.”
In the first of the three systems, the economic system, or “System of
wants,” the state seems at first hardly to appear in its universal and
controlling function at all. Here the individual depends for the satisfaction
of his physical needs on a blind, unconscious destiny, on the obscure and
incalculable properties of supply and demand in the whole interconnexion
of commodities. But even this is not all. With the accumulation of wealth in
inequality, and the growth of vast capitals, there is substituted for the
dependence of the individual on the general resultant of a vast number of
agencies a dependence on one enormously rich individual, who can control
the physical destinies of a nation. But a nation, truly speaking, is there no
more. The industrial order has parted into a mere abstract workman on one
hand, and the grande richesse on the other. “It has lost its capacity of an
organic absolute intuition and of respect for the divine—external though its
divinity be: and there sets in the bestiality of contempt for all that is noble.
The mere wisdomless universal, the mass of wealth, is the essential: and the
ethical principle, the absolute bond of the nation, is vanished; and the nation
is dissolved118.”
It would be a long and complicated task to sift, in [pg cciv] these ill-
digested but profound suggestions, the real meaning from the formal
statement. They are, like Utopia, beyond the range of practical politics. The
modern reader, whose political conceptions are limited by contemporary
circumstance, may find them archaic, medieval, quixotic. But for those who
behind the words and forms can see the substance and the idea, they will
perhaps come nearer the conception of ideal commonwealth than many
reforming programmes. Compared with the maturer statements of the
Philosophy of Law, they have the faults of the Romantic age to which their
inception belongs. Yet even in that later exposition there is upheld the
doctrine of the supremacy of the eternal State against everything particular,
class-like, and temporary; a doctrine which has made Hegel—as it made
Fichte—a voice in that “professorial socialism” which is at least as old as
Plato.
[pg 003]
Introduction.
§ 377. The knowledge of Mind is the highest and hardest, just because it is
the most “concrete” of sciences. The significance of that “absolute”
commandment, Know thyself—whether we look at it in itself or under the
historical circumstances of its first utterance—is not to promote mere self-
knowledge in respect of the particular capacities, character, propensities,
and foibles of the single self. The knowledge it commands means that of
man's genuine reality—of what is essentially and ultimately true and real—
of mind as the true and essential being. Equally little is it the purport of
mental philosophy to teach what is called knowledge of men—the
knowledge whose aim is to detect the peculiarities, passions, and foibles of
other men, and lay bare what are called the recesses of the human heart.
Information of this kind is, for one thing, meaningless, unless on the
assumption that we know the universal—man as man, and, that always
must be, as mind. And for another, being only engaged with casual,
insignificant and untrue aspects of mental life, it fails to reach the
underlying essence of them all—the mind itself.
[pg 004]
§ 378. Pneumatology, or, as it was also called, Rational Psychology, has
been already alluded to in the Introduction to the Logic as an abstract and
generalising metaphysic of the subject. Empirical (or inductive)
psychology, on the other hand, deals with the “concrete” mind: and, after
the revival of the sciences, when observation and experience had been made
the distinctive methods for the study of concrete reality, such psychology
was worked on the same lines as other sciences. In this way it came about
that the metaphysical theory was kept outside the inductive science, and so
prevented from getting any concrete embodiment or detail: whilst at the
same time the inductive science clung to the conventional common-sense
metaphysic, with its analysis into forces, various activities, &c., and
rejected any attempt at a “speculative” treatment.
The books of Aristotle on the Soul, along with his discussions on its special
aspects and states, are for this reason still by far the most admirable,
perhaps even the sole, work of philosophical value on this topic. The main
aim of a philosophy of mind can only be to re-introduce unity of idea and
principle into the theory of mind, and so re-interpret the lesson of those
Aristotelian books.
§ 379. Even our own sense of the mind's living unity naturally protests
against any attempt to break it up into different faculties, forces, or, what
comes to the same thing, activities, conceived as independent of each other.
But the craving for a comprehension of the unity is still further stimulated,
as we soon come across distinctions between mental freedom and mental
determinism, antitheses between free psychic agency and the corporeity that
lies external to it, whilst we equally note the intimate interdependence of
the one upon the [pg 005] other. In modern times especially the phenomena
of animal magnetism have given, even in experience, a lively and visible
confirmation of the underlying unity of soul, and of the power of its
“ideality.” Before these facts, the rigid distinctions of practical common
sense were struck with confusion; and the necessity of a “speculative”
examination with a view to the removal of difficulties was more directly
forced upon the student.
§ 380. The “concrete” nature of mind involves for the observer the peculiar
difficulty that the several grades and special types which develop its
intelligible unity in detail are not left standing as so many separate
existences confronting its more advanced aspects. It is otherwise in external
nature. There, matter and movement, for example, have a manifestation all
their own—it is the solar system; and similarly the differentiae of sense-
perception have a sort of earlier existence in the properties of bodies, and
still more independently in the four elements. The species and grades of
mental evolution, on the contrary, lose their separate existence and become
factors, states and features in the higher grades of development. As a
consequence of this, a lower and more abstract aspect of mind betrays the
presence in it, even to experience, of a higher grade. Under the guise of
sensation, e.g., we may find the very highest mental life as its modification
or its embodiment. And so sensation, which is but a mere form and vehicle,
may to the superficial glance seem to be the proper seat and, as it were, the
source of those moral and religious principles with which it is charged; and
the moral and religious principles thus modified may seem to call for
treatment as species of sensation. But at the same time, when lower grades
of mental life are under examination, it becomes necessary, if we desire [pg
006] to point to actual cases of them in experience, to direct attention to
more advanced grades for which they are mere forms. In this way subjects
will be treated of by anticipation which properly belong to later stages of
development (e.g. in dealing with natural awaking from sleep we speak by
anticipation of consciousness, or in dealing with mental derangement we
must speak of intellect).
What Mind (or Spirit) is.
§ 381. From our point of view Mind has for its presupposition Nature, of
which it is the truth, and for that reason its absolute prius. In this its truth
Nature is vanished, and mind has resulted as the “Idea” entered on
possession of itself. Here the subject and object of the Idea are one—either
is the intelligent unity, the notion. This identity is absolute negativity—for
whereas in Nature the intelligent unity has its objectivity perfect but
externalised, this self-externalisation has been nullified and the unity in that
way been made one and the same with itself. Thus at the same time it is this
identity only so far as it is a return out of nature.
§ 382. For this reason the essential, but formally essential, feature of mind
is Liberty: i.e. it is the notion's absolute negativity or self-identity.
Considered as this formal aspect, it may withdraw itself from everything
external and from its own externality, its very existence; it can thus submit
to infinite pain, the negation of its individual immediacy: in other words, it
can keep itself affirmative in this negativity and possess its own identity.
All this is possible so long as it is considered in its abstract self-contained
universality.
§ 383. This universality is also its determinate sphere [pg 007] of being.
Having a being of its own, the universal is self-particularising, whilst it still
remains self-identical. Hence the special mode of mental being is
“manifestation.” The spirit is not some one mode or meaning which finds
utterance or externality only in a form distinct from itself: it does not
manifest or reveal something, but its very mode and meaning is this
revelation. And thus in its mere possibility Mind is at the same moment an
infinite, “absolute,” actuality.
[pg 008]
Subdivision.
(1) In the form of self-relation: within it it has the ideal totality of the Idea
—i.e. it has before it all that its notion contains: its being is to be self-
contained and free. This is Mind Subjective.
(3) In that unity of mind as objectivity and, of mind as ideality and concept,
which essentially and actually is and for ever produces itself, mind in its
absolute truth. This is Mind Absolute.
§ 386. The two first parts of the doctrine of Mind embrace the finite mind.
Mind is the infinite Idea; thus finitude here means the disproportion
between the concept and the reality—but with the qualification that it is a
shadow cast by the mind's own light—a show or illusion which the mind
implicitly imposes as a barrier to itself, in order, by its removal, actually to
realise and become conscious of freedom as its very being, i.e. to be fully
manifested. The several steps of this activity, on each of which, with their
semblance of being, it is the function of the finite mind to linger, and
through which it has to pass, are steps in its liberation. In the full truth of
that liberation is given the identification of the three stages—finding a
world presupposed before us, generating a world as our own creation, and
gaining freedom from it and in it. To the infinite form of this truth the show
purifies itself till it becomes a consciousness of it.
[pg 010]
Section I. Mind Subjective.
(B) Mediate or explicit: still as identical reflection into itself and into other
things: mind in correlation or particularisation: consciousness—the object
treated by the Phenomenology of Mind.
We must, however, distinguish and keep apart from the progress here
studied what we call education and instruction. The sphere of education is
the individual's only: and its aim is to bring the universal mind to exist in
them. But in the philosophic theory of mind, mind is studied as self-
instruction and self-education in very essence; and its acts and utterances
are stages in the process which brings it forward to itself, links it in unity
with itself, and so makes it actual mind.
[pg 012]
Sub-Section A. Anthropology. The Soul.
§ 388. Spirit (Mind) came into being as the truth of Nature. But not merely
is it, as such a result, to be held the true and real first of what went before:
this becoming or transition bears in the sphere of the notion the special
meaning of “free judgment.” Mind, thus come into being, means therefore
that Nature in its own self realises its untruth and sets itself aside: it means
that Mind presupposes itself no longer as the universality which in corporal
individuality is always self-externalised, but as a universality which in its
concretion and totality is one and simple. At such a stage it is not yet mind,
but soul.
The question of the immateriality of the soul has no interest, except where,
on the one hand, matter is [pg 013] regarded as something true, and mind
conceived as a thing, on the other. But in modern times even the physicists
have found matters grow thinner in their hands: they have come upon
imponderable matters, like heat, light, &c., to which they might perhaps
add space and time. These “imponderables,” which have lost the property
(peculiar to matter) of gravity and, in a sense, even the capacity of offering
resistance, have still, however, a sensible existence and outness of part to
part; whereas the “vital” matter, which may also be found enumerated
among them, not merely lacks gravity, but even every other aspect of
existence which might lead us to treat it as material. The fact is that in the
Idea of Life the self-externalism of nature is implicitly at an end:
subjectivity is the very substance and conception of life—with this proviso,
however, that its existence or objectivity is still at the same time forfeited to
the sway of self-externalism. It is otherwise with Mind. There, in the
intelligible unity which exists as freedom, as absolute negativity, and not as
the immediate or natural individual, the object or the reality of the
intelligible unity is the unity itself; and so the self-externalism, which is the
fundamental feature of matter, has been completely dissipated and
transmuted into universality, or the subjective ideality of the conceptual
unity. Mind is the existent truth of matter—the truth that matter itself has no
truth.
(a) In its immediate natural mode—the natural soul, which only is.
(b) Secondly, it is a soul which feels, as individualised, enters into
correlation with its immediate being, and, in the modes of that being, retains
an abstract independence.
(c) Thirdly, its immediate being—or corporeity—is moulded into it, and
with that corporeity it exists as actual soul.
§ 392. While still a “substance” (i.e. a physical soul) the mind (1) takes part
in the general planetary life, feels the difference of climates, the changes of
the seasons and the periods of the day, &c. This life of nature for the main
shows itself only in occasional strain or disturbance of mental tone.
In recent times a good deal has been said of the cosmical, sidereal, and
telluric life of man. In such a sympathy with nature the animals essentially
live: their specific characters and their particular phases of growth depend,
in many cases completely, and always more or less, upon it. In the case of
man these points of dependence lose importance, just in proportion to his
civilisation, and the more his whole frame of soul is based upon a
substructure of mental freedom. The history of the world is not bound up
with revolutions in the solar system, any more than the destinies of
individuals with the positions of the planets.
The difference of climate has a more solid and vigorous influence. But the
response to the changes of the seasons and hours of the day is found only in
faint changes of mood, which come expressly to the [pg 016] fore only in
morbid states (including insanity) and at periods when the self-conscious
life suffers depression.
§ 393. (2) According to the concrete differences of the terrestrial globe, the
general planetary life of the nature-governed mind specialises itself and
breaks up into the several nature-governed minds which, on the whole, give
expression to the nature of the geographical continents and constitute the
diversities of race.
The contrast between the earth's poles, the land towards the north pole
being more aggregated and preponderant over sea, whereas in the southern
hemisphere it runs out in sharp points, widely distant from each other,
introduces into the differences of continents a further modification which
Treviranus (Biology, Part II) has exhibited in the case of the flora and fauna.
§ 394. This diversity descends into specialities, that may be termed local
minds—shown in the outward modes of life and occupation, bodily
structure and disposition, but still more in the inner tendency and capacity
of the intellectual and moral character of the several peoples.
Back to the very beginnings of national history we see the several nations
each possessing a persistent type of its own.
[pg 017]
§ 395. (3) The soul is further de-universalised into the individualised
subject. But this subjectivity is here only considered as a differentiation and
singling out of the modes which nature gives; we find it as the special
temperament, talent, character, physiognomy, or other disposition and
idiosyncrasy, of families or single individuals.
The (1) first of these is the natural lapse of the ages in man's life. He begins
with Childhood—mind wrapt up in itself. His next step is the fully-
developed antithesis, the strain and struggle of a universality which is still
subjective (as seen in ideals, fancies, hopes, ambitions) against his
immediate individuality. And that individuality marks both the world
which, as it exists, fails to meet his ideal requirements, and the position of
the individual himself, who is still short of independence and not fully
equipped for the part he has to play (Youth). Thirdly, we see man in his true
relation to his environment, recognising the objective necessity and
reasonableness of the world as he finds it,—a world no longer incomplete,
but able in the work which it collectively achieves to afford the individual a
place and a security for his performance. By his share in this collective
work he first is really somebody, gaining an effective existence and an
objective value (Manhood). Last of all comes the finishing touch to [pg
018] this unity with objectivity: a unity which, while on its realist side it
passes into the inertia of deadening habit, on its idealist side gains freedom
from the limited interests and entanglements of the outward present (Old
Age).
§ 397. (2) Next we find the individual subject to a real antithesis, leading it
to seek and find itself in another individual. This—the sexual relation—on
a physical basis, shows, on its one side, subjectivity remaining in an
instinctive and emotional harmony of moral life and love, and not pushing
these tendencies to an extreme universal phase, in purposes political,
scientific or artistic; and on the other, shows an active half, where the
individual is the vehicle of a struggle of universal and objective interests
with the given conditions (both of his own existence and of that of the
external world), carrying out these universal principles into a unity with the
world which is his own work. The sexual tie acquires its moral and spiritual
significance and function in the family.
The distinction between sleep and waking is one of those posers, as they
may be called, which are often addressed to philosophy:—Napoleon, e.g.,
on a visit to the University of Pavia, put this question to the class of
ideology. The characterisation given in the section is abstract; it primarily
treats waking merely as a natural fact, containing the mental element
implicite but not yet as invested with a special being of its own. If we are to
speak more concretely of this distinction (in fundamentals it remains the
same), we must take the self-existence of the individual soul in its higher
aspects as the Ego of consciousness and as intelligent mind. The difficulty
raised anent the distinction of the two states properly arises, only when we
also take into account the dreams in sleep and describe these dreams, as
well as the mental representations in the sober waking consciousness, under
one and the same title of mental representations. Thus superficially
classified as states of mental representation the two coincide, because we
have lost sight of the difference; and in the case of any assignable
distinction of waking consciousness, we can always return to the trivial
remark that all this is nothing more than mental idea. But the concrete
theory of the waking soul in its realised being views it as consciousness and
intellect: and the world of intelligent consciousness is something quite
different from a picture of mere ideas and images. The latter are in the main
only externally conjoined, in an unintelligent way, by the laws of the so-
called Association of Ideas; though here and there of course logical
principles may also be operative. But in the waking state man behaves [pg
020] essentially as a concrete ego, an intelligence: and because of this
intelligence his sense-perception stands before him as a concrete totality of
features in which each member, each point, takes up its place as at the same
time determined through and with all the rest. Thus the facts embodied in
his sensation are authenticated, not by his mere subjective representation
and distinction of the facts as something external from the person, but by
virtue of the concrete interconnexion in which each part stands with all
parts of this complex. The waking state is the concrete consciousness of this
mutual corroboration of each single factor of its content by all the others in
the picture as perceived. The consciousness of this interdependence need
not be explicit and distinct. Still this general setting to all sensations is
implicitly present in the concrete feeling of self.—In order to see the
difference of dreaming and waking we need only keep in view the Kantian
distinction between subjectivity and objectivity of mental representation
(the latter depending upon determination through categories): remembering,
as already noted, that what is actually present in mind need not be therefore
explicitly realised in consciousness, just as little as the exaltation of the
intellectual sense to God need stand before consciousness in the shape of
proofs of God's existence, although, as before explained, these proofs only
serve to express the net worth and content of that feeling.
(γ) Sensibility121.
§ 399. Sleep and waking are, primarily, it is true, not mere alterations, but
alternating conditions (a progression in infinitum). This is their formal and
negative relationship: but in it the affirmative relationship [pg 021] is also
involved. In the self-certified existence of waking soul its mere existence is
implicit as an “ideal” factor: the features which make up its sleeping nature,
where they are implicitly as in their substance, are found by the waking
soul, in its own self, and, be it noted, for itself. The fact that these
particulars, though as a mode of mind they are distinguished from the self-
identity of our self-centred being, are yet simply contained in its simplicity,
is what we call sensibility.
§ 400. Sensibility (feeling) is the form of the dull stirring, the inarticulate
breathing, of the spirit through its unconscious and unintelligent
individuality, where every definite feature is still “immediate,”—neither
specially developed in its content nor set in distinction as objective to
subject, but treated as belonging to its most special, its natural peculiarity.
The content of sensation is thus limited and transient, belonging as it does
to natural, immediate being,—to what is therefore qualitative and finite.
§ 401. What the sentient soul finds within it is, on one hand, the naturally
immediate, as “ideally” in it and made its own. On the other hand and
conversely, what originally belongs to the central individuality (which as
further deepened and enlarged is the conscious ego and free mind) get the
features of the natural corporeity, and is so felt. In this way we have two
spheres of feeling. One, where what at first is a corporeal affection (e.g. of
the eye or of any bodily part whatever) is made [pg 023] feeling (sensation)
by being driven inward, memorised in the soul's self-centred part. Another,
where affections originating in the mind and belonging to it, are in order to
be felt, and to be as if found, invested with corporeity. Thus the mode or
affection gets a place in the subject: it is felt in the soul. The detailed
specification of the former branch of sensibility is seen in the system of the
senses. But the other or inwardly originated modes of feeling no less
necessarily systematise themselves; and their corporisation, as put in the
living and concretely developed natural being, works itself out, following
the special character of the mental mode, in a special system of bodily
organs.
The system by which the internal sensation comes to give itself specific
bodily forms would deserve to be treated in detail in a peculiar science—a
psychical physiology. Somewhat pointing to such a system is implied in the
feeling of the appropriateness or inappropriateness of an immediate
sensation to the persistent tone of internal sensibility (the pleasant and
unpleasant): as also in the distinct parallelism which underlies the
symbolical employment of sensations, e.g. of colours, tones, smells. [pg
024] But the most interesting side of a psychical physiology would lie in
studying not the mere sympathy, but more definitely the bodily form
adopted by certain mental modifications, especially the passions or
emotions. We should have, e.g., to explain the line of connexion by which
anger and courage are felt in the breast, the blood, the “irritable” system,
just as thinking and mental occupation are felt in the head, the centre of the
'sensible' system. We should want a more satisfactory explanation than
hitherto of the most familiar connexions by which tears, and voice in
general, with its varieties of language, laughter, sighs, with many other
specialisations lying in the line of pathognomy and physiognomy, are
formed from their mental source. In physiology the viscera and the organs
are treated merely as parts subservient to the animal organism; but they
form at the same time a physical system for the expression of mental states,
and in this way they get quite another interpretation.
§ 402. Sensations, just because they are immediate and are found existing,
are single and transient aspects of psychic life,—alterations in the
substantiality of the soul, set in its self-centred life, with which that
substance is one. But this self-centred being is not merely a formal factor of
sensation: the soul is virtually a reflected totality of sensations—it feels in
itself the total substantiality which it virtually is—it is a soul which feels.
In the usage of ordinary language, sensation and feeling are not clearly
distinguished: still we do not speak of the sensation,—but of the feeling
(sense) of right, of self; sentimentality (sensibility) is connected with
sensation: we may therefore say sensation emphasises rather the side of
passivity—the fact that we find ourselves feeling, i.e. the immediacy of
mode in [pg 025] feeling—whereas feeling at the same time rather notes the
fact that it is we ourselves who feel.
Nowhere so much as in the case of the soul (and still more of the mind) if
we are to understand it, must that feature of “ideality” be kept in view,
which represents it as the negation of the real, but a negation, where the real
is put past, virtually retained, although it does not exist. The feature is one
with which we are familiar in regard to our mental ideas or to memory.
Every individual is an infinite treasury of sensations, ideas, acquired lore,
thoughts, &c.; and yet the ego is one and uncompounded, a deep featureless
characterless mine, in which all this is stored up, without existing. It is only
when I call to mind an idea, that I bring it out of that interior to existence
before consciousness. Sometimes, in sickness, ideas and information,
supposed to have been forgotten years ago, because for so long they had not
been brought into consciousness, once more come to light. They were not in
our possession, nor by such reproduction as occurs in sickness do they for
the future come into our possession; and yet they [pg 026] were in us and
continue to be in us still. Thus a person can never know how much of things
he once learned he really has in him, should he have once forgotten them:
they belong not to his actuality or subjectivity as such, but only to his
implicit self. And under all the superstructure of specialised and
instrumental consciousness that may subsequently be added to it, the
individuality always remains this single-souled inner life. At the present
stage this singleness is, primarily, to be defined as one of feeling—as
embracing the corporeal in itself: thus denying the view that this body is
something material, with parts outside parts and outside the soul. Just as the
number and variety of mental representations is no argument for an
extended and real multeity in the ego; so the “real” outness of parts in the
body has no truth for the sentient soul. As sentient, the soul is characterised
as immediate, and so as natural and corporeal: but the outness of parts and
sensible multiplicity of this corporeal counts for the soul (as it counts for
the intelligible unity) not as anything real, and therefore not as a barrier: the
soul is this intelligible unity in existence,—the existent speculative
principle. Thus in the body it is one simple, omnipresent unity. As to the
representative faculty the body is but one representation, and the infinite
variety of its material structure and organisation is reduced to the simplicity
of one definite conception: so in the sentient soul, the corporeity, and all
that outness of parts to parts which belongs to it, is reduced to ideality (the
truth of the natural multiplicity). The soul is virtually the totality of nature:
as an individual soul it is a monad: it is itself the explicitly put totality of its
particular world,—that world being included in it and filling it up; and to
that world it stands but as to itself.
§ 404. As individual, the soul is exclusive and always [pg 027] exclusive:
any difference there is, it brings within itself. What is differentiated from it
is as yet no external object (as in consciousness), but only the aspects of its
own sentient totality, &c. In this partition (judgment) of itself it is always
subject: its object is its substance, which is at the same time its predicate.
This substance is still the content of its natural life, but turned into the
content of the individual sensation-laden soul; yet as the soul is in that
content still particular, the content is its particular world, so far as that is, in
an implicit mode, included in the ideality of the subject.
By itself, this stage of mind is the stage of its darkness: its features are not
developed to conscious and intelligent content: so far it is formal and only
formal. It acquires a peculiar interest in cases where it is as a form and
appears as a special state of mind (§ 350), to which the soul, which has
already advanced to consciousness and intelligence, may again sink down.
But when a truer phase of mind thus exists in a more subordinate and
abstract one, it implies a want of adaptation, which is disease. In the present
stage we must treat, first, of the abstract psychical modifications by
themselves, secondly, as morbid states of mind: the latter being only
explicable by means of the former.
In the ordinary course of nature this is the condition of the child in its
mother's womb:—a condition neither merely bodily nor merely mental, but
psychical—a correlation of soul to soul. Here are two individuals, yet in
undivided psychic unity: the one as yet no self, as yet nothing impenetrable,
incapable of resistance: the other is its actuating subject, the single self of
the two. The mother is the genius of the child; for by genius we commonly
mean the total mental self-hood, as it has existence of its own, and
constitutes the subjective substantiality of some one else who is only
externally treated as an individual and has only a nominal independence.
The underlying essence of the genius is the sum total of existence, of life,
and of character, not as a mere possibility, or capacity, or virtuality, but as
efficiency and realised activity, as concrete subjectivity.
If we look only to the spatial and material aspects of the child's existence as
an embryo in its special integuments, and as connected with the mother by
means of umbilical cord, placenta, &c., all that is presented to the senses
and reflection are certain anatomical and physiological facts—externalities
and instrumentalities in the sensible and material which are insignificant as
regards the main point, the psychical relationship. What ought to be noted
as regards this psychical tie are not merely the striking effects
communicated to and stamped upon the child by violent emotions, injuries,
&c. of the mother, but the whole psychical judgment (partition) of the
underlying nature, by which the female (like the monocotyledons among
vegetables) can suffer disruption in twain, so that the child has not [pg 029]
merely got communicated to it, but has originally received morbid
dispositions as well as other pre-dispositions of shape, temper, character,
talent, idiosyncrasies, &c.
Sporadic examples and traces of this magic tie appear elsewhere in the
range of self-possessed conscious life, say between friends, especially
female friends with delicate nerves (a tie which may go so far as to show
“magnetic” phenomena), between husband and wife and between members
of the same family.
The total sensitivity has its self here in a separate subjectivity, which, in the
case cited of this sentient life in the ordinary course of nature, is visibly
present as another and a different individual. But this sensitive totality is
meant to elevate its self-hood out of itself to subjectivity in one and the
same individual: which is then its indwelling consciousness, self-possessed,
intelligent, and reasonable. For such a consciousness the merely sentient
life serves as an underlying and only implicitly existent material; and the
self-possessed subjectivity is the rational, self-conscious, controlling genius
thereof. But this sensitive nucleus includes not merely the purely
unconscious, congenital disposition and temperament, but within its
enveloping simplicity it acquires and retains also (in habit, as to which see
later) all further ties and essential relationships, fortunes, principles—
everything in short belonging to the character, and in whose elaboration
self-conscious activity has most effectively participated. The sensitivity is
thus a soul in which the whole mental life is condensed. The total individual
under this concentrated aspect is distinct from the existing and actual play
of his consciousness, his secular ideas, developed interests, inclinations,
&c. As contrasted with this looser aggregate of means and methods the
more intensive form of [pg 030] individuality is termed the genius, whose
decision is ultimate whatever may be the show of reasons, intentions,
means, of which the more public consciousness is so liberal. This
concentrated individuality also reveals itself under the aspect of what is
called the heart and soul of feeling. A man is said to be heartless and
unfeeling when he looks at things with self-possession and acts according to
his permanent purposes, be they great substantial aims or petty and unjust
interests: a good-hearted man, on the other hand, means rather one who is at
the mercy of his individual sentiment, even when it is of narrow range and
is wholly made up of particularities. Of such good nature or goodness of
heart it may be said that it is less the genius itself than the indulgere genio.
§ 406. (ββ) The sensitive life, when it becomes a form or state of the self-
conscious, educated, self-possessed human being is a disease. The
individual in such a morbid state stands in direct contact with the concrete
contents of his own self, whilst he keeps his self-possessed consciousness
of self and of the causal order of things apart as a distinct state of mind.
This morbid condition is seen in magnetic somnambulism and cognate
states.
(α) To the concrete existence of the individual belongs the aggregate of his
fundamental interests, both the essential and the particular empirical ties
which connect him with other men and the world at large. This totality
forms his actuality, in the sense that it lies in fact immanent in him; it has
already been called his genius. This genius is not the free mind which wills
and thinks: the form of sensitivity, in which the individual here appears
immersed, is, on the contrary, a surrender of his self-possessed intelligent
existence. The first conclusion to which these considerations lead, with
reference to the contents of consciousness in the somnambulist stage, is that
it is only the range of his individually moulded world (of his private
interests and narrow relationships) which appear there. Scientific theories
and philosophic conceptions or general truths require a different soil,—
require an intelligence which has risen out of the inarticulate mass of mere
sensitivity to free consciousness. It is foolish therefore to expect revelations
about the higher ideas from the somnambulist state.
(β) Where a human being's senses and intellect are [pg 032] sound, he is
fully and intelligently alive to that reality of his which gives concrete filling
to his individuality: but he is awake to it in the form of interconnexion
between himself and the features of that reality conceived as an external
and a separate world, and he is aware that this world is in itself also a
complex of interconnexions of a practically intelligible kind. In his
subjective ideas and plans he has also before him this causally connected
scheme of things he calls his world and the series of means which bring his
ideas and his purposes into adjustment with the objective existences, which
are also means and ends to each other. At the same time, this world which is
outside him has its threads in him to such a degree that it is these threads
which make him what he really is: he too would become extinct if these
externalities were to disappear, unless by the aid of religion, subjective
reason, and character, he is in a remarkable degree self-supporting and
independent of them. But, then, in the latter case he is less susceptible of the
psychical state here spoken of.—As an illustration of that identity with the
surroundings may be noted the effect produced by the death of beloved
relatives, friends, &c. on those left behind, so that the one dies or pines
away with the loss of the other. (Thus Cato, after the downfall of the Roman
republic, could live no longer: his inner reality was neither wider than
higher than it.) Compare home-sickness, and the like.
(γ) But when all that occupies the waking consciousness, the world outside
it and its relationship to that world is under a veil, and the soul is thus sunk
in sleep (in magnetic sleep, in catalepsy, and other diseases, e.g. those
connected with female development, or at the approach of death, &c.), then
that immanent actuality of the individual remains the same substantial total
[pg 033] as before, but now as a purely sensitive life with an inward vision
and an inward consciousness. And because it is the adult, formed, and
developed consciousness which is degraded into this state of sensitivity, it
retains along with its content a certain nominal self-hood, a formal vision
and awareness, which however does not go so far as the conscious
judgment or discernment by which its contents, when it is healthy and
awake, exist for it as an outward objectivity. The individual is thus a monad
which is inwardly aware of its actuality—a genius which beholds itself. The
characteristic point in such knowledge is that the very same facts (which for
the healthy consciousness are an objective practical reality, and to know
which, in its sober moods, it needs the intelligent chain of means and
conditions in all their real expansion) are now immediately known and
perceived in this immanence. This perception is a sort of clairvoyance; for
it is a consciousness living in the undivided substantiality of the genius, and
finding itself in the very heart of the interconnexion, and so can dispense
with the series of conditions, external one to another, which lead up to the
result,—conditions which cool reflection has in succession to traverse and
in so doing feels the limits of its own individual externality. But such
clairvoyance—just because its dim and turbid vision does not present the
facts in a rational interconnexion—is for that very reason at the mercy of
every private contingency of feeling and fancy, &c.—not to mention that
foreign suggestions (see later) intrude into its vision. It is thus impossible to
make out whether what the clairvoyants really see preponderates over what
they deceive themselves in.—But it is absurd to treat this visionary state as
a sublime mental phase and as a truer state, capable of conveying general
truths123.
[pg 034]
(δ) An essential feature of this sensitivity, with its absence of intelligent and
volitional personality, is this, that it is a state of passivity, like that of the
child in the womb. The patient in this condition is accordingly made, and
continues to be, subject to the power of another person, the magnetiser; so
that when the two are thus in psychical rapport, the selfless individual, not
really a “person,” has for his subjective consciousness the consciousness of
the other. This latter self-possessed individual is thus the effective
subjective soul of the former, and the genius which may even supply him
with a train of ideas. That the somnambulist perceives in himself tastes and
smells which are present in the person with whom he stands en rapport, and
that he is aware of the other inner ideas and present perceptions of the latter
as if they were his own, shows the substantial identity which the soul
(which even in its concreteness is also truly immaterial) is capable of
holding with another. When the substance of both is thus made one, there is
only one subjectivity of consciousness: the patient has a sort of
individuality, but it is empty, not on the spot, not actual: and this nominal
self accordingly derives its whole stock of ideas [pg 035] from the
sensations and ideas of the other, in whom it sees, smells, tastes, reads, and
hears. It is further to be noted on this point that the somnambulist is thus
brought into rapport with two genii and a twofold set of ideas, his own and
that of the magnetiser. But it is impossible to say precisely which sensations
and which visions he, in this nominal perception, receives, beholds and
brings to knowledge from his own inward self, and which from the
suggestions of the person with whom he stands in relation. This uncertainty
may be the source of many deceptions, and accounts among other things for
the diversity that inevitably shows itself among somnambulists from
different countries and under rapport with persons of different education, as
regards their views on morbid states and the methods of cure, or medicines
for them, as well as on scientific and intellectual topics.
§ 407. (αα) The sensitive totality is, in its capacity of individual, essentially
the tendency to distinguish itself in itself, and to wake up to the judgment in
itself, in virtue of which it has particular feelings and stands as a subject in
respect of these aspects of itself. The subject as such gives these feelings a
place as its own in itself. In these private and personal sensations it is
immersed, and at the same time, because of the “ideality” of the particulars,
it combines itself in them with itself as a subjective unit. In this way it is
self-feeling, and is so at the same time only in the particular feeling.
§ 408. (ββ) In consequence of the immediacy, which still marks the self-
feeling, i.e. in consequence of the element of corporeality which is still
undetached from the mental life, and as the feeling too is itself particular
and bound up with a special corporeal form, it follows that although the
subject has been brought to acquire intelligent consciousness, it is still
susceptible of disease, so far as to remain fast in a special phase of its self-
feeling, unable to refine it to “ideality” and get the better of it. The fully-
furnished self of intelligent consciousness is a conscious subject, which is
consistent in itself [pg 037] according to an order and behaviour which
follows from its individual position and its connexion with the external
world, which is no less a world of law. But when it is engrossed with a
single phase of feeling, it fails to assign that phase its proper place and due
subordination in the individual system of the world which a conscious
subject is. In this way the subject finds itself in contradiction between the
totality systematised in its consciousness, and the single phase or fixed idea
which is not reduced to its proper place and rank. This is Insanity or mental
Derangement.
In considering insanity we must, as in other cases, anticipate the full-grown
and intelligent conscious subject, which is at the same time the natural self
of self-feeling. In such a phase the self can be liable to the contradiction
between its own free subjectivity and a particularity which, instead of being
“idealised” in the former, remains as a fixed element in self-feeling. Mind
as such is free, and therefore not susceptible of this malady. But in older
metaphysics mind was treated as a soul, as a thing; and it is only as a thing,
i.e. as something natural and existent, that it is liable to insanity—the settled
fixture of some finite element in it. Insanity is therefore a psychical disease,
i.e. a disease of body and mind alike: the commencement may appear to
start from one more than other, and so also may the cure.
(γ) Habit125.
But this abstract realisation of the soul in its corporeal vehicle is not yet the
self—not the existence of the [pg 040] universal which is for the universal.
It is the corporeity reduced to its mere ideality; and so far only does
corporeity belong to the soul as such. That is to say, as space and time—the
abstract one-outside-another, as, in short, empty space and empty time—are
only subjective form—pure act of intuition; so that pure being (which
through the supersession in it of the particularity of the corporeity, or of the
immediate corporeity as such has realised itself) is mere intuition and no
more, lacking consciousness, but the basis of consciousness. And
consciousness it becomes, when the corporeity, of which it is the subjective
substance, and which still continues to exist, and that as a barrier for it, has
been absorbed by it, and it has been invested with the character of self-
centred subject.
§ 410. The soul's making itself an abstract universal being, and reducing the
particulars of feelings (and of consciousness) to a mere feature of its being
is Habit. In this manner the soul has the contents in possession, and contains
them in such manner that in these features it is not as sentient, nor does it
stand in relationship with them as distinguishing itself from them, nor is
absorbed in them, but has them and moves in them, without feeling or
consciousness of the fact. The soul is freed from them, so far as it is not
interested in or occupied with them: and whilst existing in these forms as its
possession, it is at the same time open to be otherwise occupied and
engaged—say with feeling and with mental consciousness in general.
In habit the human being's mode of existence is “natural,” and for that
reason not free; but still free, so far as the merely natural phase of feeling is
by habit reduced to a mere being of his, and he is no longer involuntarily
attracted or repelled by it, and so no longer interested, occupied, or
dependent in regard to it. The want of freedom in habit is partly merely
formal, as habit merely attaches to the being of the soul; partly only
relative, so far as it strictly speaking arises only in the case of bad habits, or
so far as a habit is opposed by another purpose: whereas the habit of right
and goodness is an embodiment of liberty. The main point about Habit is
that by its means man gets emancipated from the feelings, even in being
affected by them. The different forms of this may be described as follows:
(α) The immediate feeling is negated and treated as indifferent. One who
gets inured against external sensations (frost, heat, weariness of the limbs,
[pg 042] &c., sweet tastes, &c.), and who hardens the heart against
misfortune, acquires a strength which consists in this, that although the
frost, &c.—or the misfortune—is felt, the affection is deposed to a mere
externality and immediacy; the universal psychical life keeps its own
abstract independence in it, and the self-feeling as such, consciousness,
reflection, and any other purposes and activity, are no longer bothered with
it. (β) There is indifference towards the satisfaction: the desires and
impulses are by the habit of their satisfaction deadened. This is the rational
liberation from them; whereas monastic renunciation and forcible
interference do not free from them, nor are they in conception rational. Of
course in all this it is assumed that the impulses are kept as the finite modes
they naturally are, and that they, like their satisfaction, are subordinated as
partial factors to the reasonable will. (γ) In habit regarded as aptitude, or
skill, not merely has the abstract psychical life to be kept intact per se, but it
has to be imposed as a subjective aim, to be made a power in the bodily
part, which is rendered subject and thoroughly pervious to it. Conceived as
having the inward purpose of the subjective soul thus imposed upon it, the
body is treated as an immediate externality and a barrier. Thus comes out
the more decided rupture between the soul as simple self-concentration, and
its earlier naturalness and immediacy; it has lost its original and immediate
identity with the bodily nature, and as external has first to be reduced to that
position. Specific feelings can only get bodily shape in a perfectly specific
way (§ 401); and the immediate portion of body is a particular possibility
for a specific aim (a particular aspect of its differentiated structure, a
particular organ of its organic system). To mould such an aim in the organic
body is to bring out and express the “ideality” [pg 043] which is implicit in
matter always, and especially so in the specific bodily part, and thus to
enable the soul, under its volitional and conceptual characters, to exist as
substance in its corporeity. In this way an aptitude shows the corporeity
rendered completely pervious, made into an instrument, so that when the
conception (e.g. a series of musical notes) is in me, then without resistance
and with ease the body gives them correct utterance.
The form of habit applies to all kinds and grades of mental action. The most
external of them, i.e. the spatial direction of an individual, viz. his upright
posture, has been by will made a habit—a position taken without
adjustment and without consciousness—which continues to be an affair of
his persistent will; for the man stands only because and in so far as he wills
to stand, and only so long as he wills it without consciousness. Similarly
our eyesight is the concrete habit which, without an express adjustment,
combines in a single act the several modifications of sensation,
consciousness, intuition, intelligence, &c., which make it up. Thinking, too,
however free and active in its own pure element it becomes, no less requires
habit and familiarity (this impromptuity or form of immediacy), by which it
is the property of my single self where I can freely and in all directions
range. It is through this habit that I come to realise my existence as a
thinking being. Even here, in this spontaneity of self-centred thought, there
is a partnership of soul and body (hence, want of habit and too-long-
continued thinking cause headache); habit diminishes this feeling, by
making the natural function an immediacy of the soul. Habit on an ampler
scale, and carried out in the strictly intellectual range, is recollection and
memory, whereof we shall speak later.
[pg 044]
Habit is often spoken of disparagingly and called lifeless, casual and
particular. And it is true that the form of habit, like any other, is open to
anything we chance to put into it; and it is habit of living which brings on
death, or, if quite abstract, is death itself: and yet habit is indispensable for
the existence of all intellectual life in the individual, enabling the subject to
be a concrete immediacy, an “ideality” of soul—enabling the matter of
consciousness, religious, moral, &c., to be his as this self, this soul, and no
other, and be neither a mere latent possibility, nor a transient emotion or
idea, nor an abstract inwardness, cut off from action and reality, but part and
parcel of his being. In scientific studies of the soul and the mind, habit is
usually passed over—either as something contemptible—or rather for the
further reason that it is one of the most difficult questions of psychology.
§ 411. The Soul, when its corporeity has been moulded and made
thoroughly its own, finds itself there a single subject; and the corporeity is
an externality which stands as a predicate, in being related to which, it is
related to itself. This externality, in other words, represents not itself, but
the soul, of which it is the sign. In this identity of interior and exterior, the
latter subject to the former, the soul is actual: in its corporeity it has its free
shape, in which it feels itself and makes itself felt, and which as the Soul's
work of art has human pathognomic and physiognomic expression.
Under the head of human expression are included, e.g., the upright figure in
general, and the formation of the limbs, especially the hand, as the absolute
instrument, [pg 045] of the mouth—laughter, weeping, &c., and the note of
mentality diffused over the whole, which at once announces the body at the
externality of a higher nature. This note is so slight, indefinite, and
inexpressible a modification, because the figure in its externality is
something immediate and natural, and can therefore only be an indefinite
and quite imperfect sign for the mind, unable to represent it in its actual
universality. Seen from the animal world, the human figure is the supreme
phase in which mind makes an appearance. But for the mind it is only its
first appearance, while language is its perfect expression. And the human
figure, though its proximate phase of existence, is at the same time in its
physiognomic and pathognomic quality something contingent to it. To try to
raise physiognomy and above all cranioscopy (phrenology) to the rank of
sciences, was therefore one of the vainest fancies, still vainer than a
signatura rerum, which supposed the shape of a plant to afford indication of
its medicinal virtue.
§ 412. Implicitly the soul shows the untruth and unreality of matter; for the
soul, in its concentrated self, cuts itself off from its immediate being,
placing the latter over against it as a corporeity incapable of offering
resistance to its moulding influence. The soul, thus setting in opposition its
being to its (conscious) self, absorbing it, and making it its own, has lost the
meaning of mere soul, or the “immediacy” of mind. The actual soul with its
sensation and its concrete self-feeling turned into habit, has implicitly
realised the 'ideality' of its qualities; in this externality it has recollected and
inwardised itself, and is infinite self-relation. This free universality thus
made explicit shows the soul awaking to the higher stage of the ego, or
abstract universality in so far as it is for the abstract universality. In this [pg
046] way it gains the position of thinker and subject—specially a subject of
the judgment in which the ego excludes from itself the sum total of its
merely natural features as an object, a world external to it,—but with such
respect to that object that in it it is immediately reflected into itself. Thus
soul rises to become Consciousness.
[pg 047]
Sub-Section B. Phenomenology Of Mind.
Consciousness.
§ 414. The self-identity of the mind, thus first made [pg 048] explicit as the
Ego, is only its abstract formal identity. As soul it was under the phase of
substantial universality; now, as subjective reflection in itself, it is referred
to this substantiality as to its negative, something dark and beyond it. Hence
consciousness, like reciprocal dependence in general, is the contradiction
between the independence of the two sides and their identity in which they
are merged into one. The mind as ego is essence; but since reality, in the
sphere of essence, is represented as in immediate being and at the same
time as “ideal,” it is as consciousness only the appearance (phenomenon)
of mind.
§ 416. The aim of conscious mind is to make its appearance identical with
its essence, to raise its self-certainty to truth. The existence of mind in the
stage of consciousness is finite, because it is merely a nominal self-relation,
or mere certainty. The object is only abstractly characterised as its; in other
words, in the object it is only as an abstract ego that the mind is reflected
into itself: hence its existence there has still a content, which is not as its
own.
§ 417. The grades of this elevation of certainty to truth are three in number:
first (a) consciousness in general, with an object set against it; (b) self-
consciousness, for which ego is the object; (c) unity of consciousness and
self-consciousness, where the mind sees itself embodied in the object and
sees itself as implicitly and explicitly determinate, as Reason, the notion of
mind.
[pg 050]
(β) Sense-perception128.
§ 429. But on the inner side, or implicitly, the sense of self which the ego
gets in the satisfaction does not remain in abstract self-concentration or in
mere individuality; on the contrary,—as negation of immediacy and
individuality the result involves a character of universality and of the
identity of self-consciousness [pg 055] with its object. The judgment or
diremption of this self-consciousness is the consciousness of a “free”
object, in which ego is aware of itself as an ego, which however is also still
outside it.
§ 432. The fight of recognition is a life and death struggle: either self-
consciousness imperils the other's like, and incurs a like peril for its own—
but only peril, for either is no less bent on maintaining his life, as the
existence of his freedom. Thus the death of one, [pg 056] though by the
abstract, therefore rude, negation of immediacy, it, from one point of view,
solves the contradiction, is yet, from the essential point of view (i.e. the
outward and visible recognition), a new contradiction (for that recognition
is at the same time undone by the other's death) and a greater than the other.
§ 433. But because life is as requisite as liberty to the solution, the fight
ends in the first instance as a one-sided negation with inequality. While the
one combatant prefers life, retains his single self-consciousness, but
surrenders his claim for recognition, the other holds fast to his self-assertion
and is recognised by the former as his superior. Thus arises the status of
master and slave.
In the battle for recognition and the subjugation under a master, we see, on
their phenomenal side, the emergence of man's social life and the
commencement of political union. Force, which is the basis of this
phenomenon, is not on that account a basis of right, but only the necessary
and legitimate factor in the passage from the state of self-consciousness
sunk in appetite and selfish isolation into the state of universal self-
consciousness. Force, then, is the external or phenomenal commencement
of states, not their underlying and essential principle.
§ 434. This status, in the first place, implies common wants and common
concern for their satisfaction,—for the means of mastery, the slave, must
likewise be kept in life. In place of the rude destruction of the immediate
object there ensues acquisition, preservation, and formation of it, as the
instrumentality in which the two extremes of independence and non-
independence are welded together. The form of universality thus arising in
satisfying the want, creates a permanent means and a provision which takes
care for and secures the future.
[pg 057]
§ 435. But secondly, when we look to the distinction of the two, the master
beholds in the slave and his servitude the supremacy of his single self-hood,
and that by the suppression of immediate self-hood, a suppression,
however, which falls on another. This other, the slave, however, in the
service of the master, works off his individualist self-will, overcomes the
inner immediacy of appetite, and in this divestment of self and in “the fear
of his lord” makes “the beginning of wisdom”—the passage to universal
self-consciousness.
§ 438. The essential and actual truth which reason is, lies in the simple
identity of the subjectivity of the notion, with its objectivity and
universality. The universality of reason, therefore, whilst it signifies that the
object, which was only given in consciousness quâ consciousness, is now
itself universal, permeating and encompassing the ego, also signifies that
the pure ego is the pure form which overlaps the object, and encompasses it
without it.
[pg 059]
Sub-Section C. Psychology. Mind . 134
§ 440. Mind has defined itself as the truth of soul and consciousness,—the
former a simple immediate totality, the latter now an infinite form which is
not, like consciousness, restricted by that content, and does not stand in
mere correlation to it as to its object, but is an awareness of this substantial
totality, neither subjective nor objective. Mind, therefore, starts only from
its own being and is in correlation only with its own features.
§ 441. The soul is finite, so far as its features are immediate or con-natural.
Consciousness is finite, in so far as it has an object. Mind is finite, in so far
as, though it no longer has an object, it has a mode in its knowledge; i.e., it
is finite by means of its immediacy, or, what is the same thing, by being
subjective or only a notion. And it is a matter of no consequence, which is
defined as its notion, and which as the reality of that notion. Say that its
notion is the utterly infinite objective reason, then its reality is knowledge
or intelligence: say that knowledge is its notion, then its reality is that
reason, and the realisation of knowledge consists in appropriating reason.
Hence the finitude of mind is to be placed in the (temporary) failure of
knowledge to get hold of the full reality of its reason, or, equally, in the
(temporary) failure of reason to attain full manifestation in knowledge.
Reason at the same time is only infinite so far as it is “absolute” freedom;
so far, that is, as presupposing itself for its knowledge to work upon, it
thereby reduces itself to finitude, and appears as everlasting movement of
superseding this immediacy, of comprehending itself, and being a rational
knowledge.
The development here meant is not that of the individual (which has a
certain anthropological character), where faculties and forces are regarded
as successively emerging and presenting themselves in external existence—
a series of steps, on the ascertainment on which there was for a long time
great stress laid (by the system of Condillac), as if a conjectural natural
emergence could exhibit the origin of these faculties and explain them. In
Condillac's method there is an unmistakable intention to show how the
several modes of mental activity could be made intelligible without losing
sight of mental unity, and to exhibit their necessary interconnexion. But the
categories employed in doing so are of a wretched sort. Their ruling
principle is that the sensible is taken (and with justice) as the prius or the
initial basis, but that the later phases that follow this starting-point present
themselves as emerging in a solely affirmative manner, and the negative
aspect of mental activity, by which this material is transmuted into mind
and destroyed as a sensible, is misconceived and overlooked. As the theory
of Condillac states it, the sensible is not merely the empirical first, but is
left as if it were the true and essential foundation.
Similarly, if the activities of mind are treated as mere manifestations, forces,
perhaps in terms stating their utility or suitability for some other interest of
head or heart, there is no indication of the true final aim of the whole
business. That can only be the intelligible unity of mind, and its activity can
only have itself as aim; i.e. [pg 062] its aim can only be to get rid of the
form of immediacy or subjectivity, to reach and get hold of itself, and to
liberate itself to itself. In this way the so-called faculties of mind as thus
distinguished are only to be treated as steps of this liberation. And this is the
only rational mode of studying the mind and its various activities.
§ 443. As consciousness has for its object the stage which preceded it, viz.
the natural soul (§ 413), so mind has or rather makes consciousness its
object: i.e. whereas consciousness is only the virtual identity of the ego with
its other (§ 415), the mind realises that identity as the concrete unity which
it and it only knows. Its productions are governed by the principle of all
reason that the contents are at once potentially existent, and are the mind's
own, in freedom. Thus, if we consider the initial aspect of mind, that aspect
is twofold—as being and as its own: by the one, the mind finds in itself
something which is, by the other it affirms it to be only its own. The way of
mind is therefore
(b) Will: practical mind, which in the first place is likewise formal—i.e. its
content is at first only its own, and is immediately willed; and it proceeds
next to liberate its volition from its subjectivity, which is the one-sided form
of its contents, so that it
(c) confronts itself as free mind and thus gets rid of both its defects of one-
sidedness.
[pg 063]
§ 444. The theoretical as well as the practical mind still fall under the
general range of Mind Subjective. They are not to be distinguished as active
and passive. Subjective mind is productive: but it is a merely nominal
productivity. Inwards, the theoretical mind produces only its “ideal” world,
and gains abstract autonomy within; while the practical, while it has to do
with autonomous products, with a material which is its own, has a material
which is only nominally such, and therefore a restricted content, for which
it gains the form of universality. Outwards, the subjective mind (which as a
unity of soul and consciousness, is thus also a reality,—a reality at once
anthropological and conformable to consciousness) has for its products, in
the theoretical range, the word, and in the practical (not yet deed and action,
but) enjoyment.
Psychology, like logic, is one of those sciences which in modern times have
yet derived least profit from the more general mental culture and the deeper
conception of reason. It is still extremely ill off. The turn which the Kantian
philosophy has taken has given it greater importance: it has, and that in its
empirical condition, been claimed as the basis of metaphysics, which is to
consist of nothing but the empirical apprehension and the analysis of the
facts of human consciousness, merely as facts, just as they are given. This
position of psychology, mixing it up with forms belonging to the range of
consciousness and with anthropology, has led to no improvement in its own
condition: but it has had the further effect that, both for the mind as such,
and for metaphysics and philosophy generally, all attempts have been
abandoned to ascertain the necessity of essential and actual reality, to get at
the notion and the truth.
[pg 064]
§ 445. Intelligence135 finds itself determined: this is its apparent aspect from
which in its immediacy it starts. But as knowledge, intelligence consists in
treating what is found as its own. Its activity has to do with the empty form
—the pretence of finding reason: and its aim is to realise its concept or to be
reason actual, along with which the content is realised as rational. This
activity is cognition. The nominal knowledge, which is only certitude,
elevates itself, as reason is concrete, to definite and conceptual knowledge.
The course of this elevation is itself rational, and consists in a necessary
passage (governed by the concept) of one grade or term of intelligent
activity (a so-called faculty of mind) into another. The refutation which
such cognition gives of the semblance that the rational is found, starts from
the certitude or the faith of intelligence in its capability of rational
knowledge, and in the possibility of being able to appropriate the reason,
which it and the content virtually is.
It is commonly enough assumed that mind has in its feeling the material of
its ideas, but the statement [pg 068] is more usually understood in a sense
the opposite of that which it has here. In contrast with the simplicity of
feeling it is usual rather to assume that the primary mental phase is
judgment generally, or the distinction of consciousness into subject and
object; and the special quality of sensation is derived from an independent
object, external or internal. With us, in the truth of mind, the mere
consciousness point of view, as opposed to true mental “idealism,” is
swallowed up, and the matter of feeling has rather been supposed already as
immanent in the mind.—It is commonly taken for granted that as regards
content there is more in feeling than in thought: this being specially
affirmed of moral and religious feelings. Now the material, which the mind
as it feels is to itself, is here the result and the mature result of a fully
organised reason: hence under the head of feeling is comprised all rational
and indeed all spiritual content whatever. But the form of selfish singleness
to which feeling reduces the mind is the lowest and worst vehicle it can
have—one in which it is not found as a free and infinitely universal
principle, but rather as subjective and private, in content and value entirely
contingent. Trained and sterling feeling is the feeling of an educated mind
which has acquired the consciousness of the true differences of things, of
their essential relationships and real characters; and it is with such a mind
that this rectified material enters into its feeling and receives this form.
Feeling is the immediate, as it were the closest, contact in which the
thinking subject can stand to a given content. Against that content the
subject re-acts first of all with its particular self-feeling, which though it
may be of more sterling value and of wider range than a onesided
intellectual standpoint, may just as likely be narrow and poor; and in any
case is the form of the particular [pg 069] and subjective. If a man on any
topic appeals not to the nature and notion of the thing, or at least to reasons
—to the generalities of common sense—but to his feeling, the only thing to
do is to let him alone, because by his behaviour he refuses to have any lot or
part in common rationality, and shuts himself up in his own isolated
subjectivity—his private and particular self.
§ 449. (3) When intelligence reaches a concrete unity of the two factors,
that is to say, when it is at once self-collected in this externally existing
material, and yet in this self-collectedness sunk in the out-of-selfness, it is
Intuition or Mental Vision.
(αα) Recollection138.
§ 452. Intelligence, as it at first recollects the intuition, places the content of
feeling in its own inwardness—in a space and a time of its own. In this way
that content is (1) an image or picture, liberated from its original immediacy
and abstract singleness amongst other things, and received into the
universality of the ego. The [pg 071] image loses the full complement of
features proper to intuition, and is arbitrary or contingent, isolated, we may
say, from the external place, time, and immediate context in which the
intuition stood.
(ββ) Imagination139.
The so-called laws of the association of ideas were objects of great interest,
especially during that outburst of empirical psychology which was
contemporaneous with the decline of philosophy. In the first place, it is not
Ideas (properly so called) which are associated. Secondly, these modes of
relation are not laws, just for the reason that there are so many laws about
the same thing, as to suggest a caprice and a contingency opposed to the
very nature of law. It is a matter of chance whether the link of association is
something pictorial, or an intellectual category, such as likeness and
contrast, reason and consequence. The train of images and representations
suggested by association is the sport of vacant-minded ideation, where,
though intelligence shows itself by a certain formal universality, the matter
is entirely pictorial.—Image and idea, if we leave out of account the more
precise definition of those forms given above, present also a distinction in
content. The former is the more consciously-concrete idea, whereas the idea
(representation), whatever be its content (from image, notion, or idea), has
always the peculiarity, though belonging to intelligence, of being in respect
of its content given and immediate. It is still [pg 074] true of this idea or
representation, as of all intelligence, that it finds its material, as a matter of
fact, to be so and so; and the universality which the aforesaid material
receives by ideation is still abstract. Mental representation is the mean in
the syllogism of the elevation of intelligence, the link between the two
significations of self-relatedness—viz. being and universality, which in
consciousness receive the title of object and subject. Intelligence
complements what is merely found by the attribution of universality, and
the internal and its own by the attribution of being, but a being of its own
institution. (On the distinction of representations and thoughts, see Introd.
to the Logic, § 20 note.)
Productive imagination is the centre in which the universal and being, one's
own and what is picked up, internal and external, are completely welded
into one. The preceding “syntheses” of intuition, recollection, &c., are
unifications of the same factors, but they are “syntheses”; it is not till
creative imagination that intelligence ceases to be the vague mine and the
universal, [pg 076] and becomes an individuality, a concrete subjectivity, in
which the self-reference is defined both to being and to universality. The
creations of imagination are on all hands recognised as such combinations
of the mind's own and inward with the matter of intuition; what further and
more definite aspects they have is a matter for other departments. For the
present this internal studio of intelligence is only to be looked at in these
abstract aspects.—Imagination, when regarded as the agency of this
unification, is reason, but only a nominal reason, because the matter or
theme it embodies is to imagination quâ imagination a matter of
indifference; whilst reason quâ reason also insists upon the truth of its
content.
Another point calling for special notice is that, when imagination elevates
the internal meaning to an image and intuition, and this is expressed by
saying that it gives the former the character of an existent, the phrase must
not seem surprising that intelligence makes itself be as a thing; for its ideal
import is itself, and so is the aspect which it imposes upon it. The image
produced by imagination of an object is a bare mental or subjective
intuition: in the sign or symbol it adds intuitability proper; and in
mechanical memory it completes, so far as it is concerned, this form of
being.
[pg 077]
The sign is some immediate intuition, representing a totally different import
from what naturally belongs to it; it is the pyramid into which a foreign soul
has been conveyed, and where it is conserved. The sign is different from the
symbol: for in the symbol the original characters (in essence and
conception) of the visible object are more or less identical with the import
which it bears as symbol; whereas in the sign, strictly so-called, the natural
attributes of the intuition, and the connotation of which it is a sign, have
nothing to do with each other. Intelligence therefore gives proof of wider
choice and ampler authority in the use of intuitions when it treats them as
designatory (significative) rather than as symbolical.
§ 459. The intuition—in its natural phase a something given and given in
space—acquires, when employed as [pg 078] a sign, the peculiar
characteristic of existing only as superseded and sublimated. Such is the
negativity of intelligence; and thus the truer phase of the intuition used as a
sign is existence in time (but its existence vanishes in the moment of being),
and if we consider the rest of its external psychical quality, its institution by
intelligence, but an institution growing out of its (anthropological) own
naturalness. This institution of the natural is the vocal note, where the
inward idea manifests itself in adequate utterance. The vocal note which
receives further articulation to express specific ideas—speech and, its
system, language—gives to sensations, intuitions, conceptions, a second
and higher existence than they naturally possess,—invests them with the
right of existence in the ideational realm.
What has been said shows the inestimable and not sufficiently appreciated
educational value of learning to read and write an alphabetic character. It
leads the mind from the sensibly concrete image to attend to the more
formal structure of the vocal word and its abstract elements, and contributes
much to give stability and independence to the inward realm of mental life.
Acquired habit subsequently effaces the peculiarity by which alphabetic
writing appears, in the interest of vision, as a roundabout way to ideas by
means of audibility; it makes them a sort of hieroglyphic to us, so that in
using them we need not consciously realise them by means of tones,
whereas people unpractised in reading utter aloud what they read in order to
catch its meaning in the sound. Thus, while (with the faculty which
transformed alphabetic writing into hieroglyphics) the capacity of
abstraction gained by the first practice remains, hieroglyphic reading is of
itself a deaf reading and a dumb writing. It is true that the audible (which
[pg 084] is in time) and the visible (which is in space), each have their own
basis, one no less authoritative than the other. But in the case of alphabetic
writing there is only a single basis: the two aspects occupy their rightful
relation to each other: the visible language is related to the vocal only as a
sign, and intelligence expresses itself immediately and unconditionally by
speaking.—The instrumental function of the comparatively non-sensuous
element of tone for all ideational work shows itself further as peculiarly
important in memory which forms the passage from representation to
thought.
§ 460. The name, combining the intuition (an intellectual production) with
its signification, is primarily a single transient product; and conjunction of
the idea (which is inward) with the intuition (which is outward) is itself
outward. The reduction of this outwardness to inwardness is (verbal)
Memory.
(γγ) Memory141.
§ 461. Under the shape of memory the course of intelligence passes through
the same inwardising (recollecting) functions, as regards the intuition of the
word, as representation in general does in dealing with the first immediate
intuition (§ 451). (1) Making its own the synthesis achieved in the sign,
intelligence, by this inwardising (memorising) elevates the single synthesis
to a universal, i.e. permanent, synthesis, in which name and meaning are for
it objectively united, and renders the intuition (which the name originally
is) a representation. Thus the import (connotation) and sign, being
identified, form one representation: the representation in its inwardness is
rendered concrete and gets existence for its import: all this being the work
of memory which retains names (retentive Memory).
[pg 085]
§ 462. The name is thus the thing so far as it exists and counts in the
ideational realm. (2) In the name, Reproductive memory has and recognises
the thing, and with the thing it has the name, apart from intuition and image.
The name, as giving an existence to the content in intelligence, is the
externality of intelligence to itself; and the inwardising or recollection of
the name, i.e. of an intuition of intellectual origin, is at the same time a self-
externalisation to which intelligence reduces itself on its own ground. The
association of the particular names lies in the meaning of the features
sensitive, representative, or cogitant,—series of which the intelligence
traverses as it feels, represents, or thinks.
Given the name lion, we need neither the actual vision of the animal, nor its
image even: the name alone, if we understand it, is the unimaged simple
representation. We think in names.
§ 463. (3) As the interconnexion of the names lies in the meaning, the
conjunction of their meaning with the reality as names is still an (external)
synthesis; and intelligence in this its externality has not made a complete
and simple return into self. But intelligence is the universal,—the single
plain truth of its particular self-divestments; and its consummated
appropriation of them abolishes that distinction between meaning and
name. This extreme inwardising of representation is the supreme self-
divestment of intelligence, in which it renders itself the mere being, the
universal space of names as such, i.e. of meaningless words. The ego,
which is this abstract being, is, because subjectivity, at the same time the
power over the different names,—the link which, having nothing in itself,
fixes in itself series of them and keeps them in stable order. So far as they
merely are, and intelligence is here itself this being of theirs, its power is a
merely abstract subjectivity,—memory; which, on account of the complete
[pg 087] externality in which the members of such series stand to one
another, and because it is itself this externality (subjective though that be),
is called mechanical (§ 195).
[pg 089]
(γ) Thinking144.
§ 466. But cognition by thought is still in the first instance formal: the
universality and its being is the plain subjectivity of intelligence. The
thoughts therefore are not yet fully and freely determinate, and the
representations which have been inwardised to thoughts are so far still the
given content.
§ 467. As dealing with this given content, thought is (α) understanding with
its formal identity, working up the representations, that have been
memorised, into species, genera, laws, forces, &c., in short into categories,
—thus indicating that the raw material does not get the truth of its being
save in these thought-forms. As intrinsically infinite negativity, thought is
(β) essentially an act of partition,—judgment, which however does not
break up the concept again into the old antithesis of universality and being,
but distinguishes on the lines supplied by the interconnexions peculiar to
the concept. Thirdly (γ), thought supersedes the formal distinction and [pg
090] institutes at the same time an identity of the differences,—thus being
nominal reason or inferential understanding. Intelligence, as the act of
thought, cognises. And (α) understanding out of its generalities (the
categories) explains the individual, and is then said to comprehend or
understand itself: (β) in the judgment it explains the individual to be an
universal (species, genus). In these forms the content appears as given: (γ)
but in inference (syllogism) it characterises a content from itself, by
superseding that form-difference. With the perception of the necessity, the
last immediacy still attaching to formal thought has vanished.
In Logic there was thought, but in its implicitness, and as reason develops
itself in this distinction-lacking medium. So in consciousness thought
occurs as a stage (§ 437 note). Here reason is as the truth of the antithetical
distinction, as it had taken shape within the mind's own limits. Thought thus
recurs again and again in these different parts of philosophy, because these
parts are different only through the medium they are in and the antithesis
they imply; while thought is this one and the same centre, to which as to
their truth the antithesis return.
[pg 091]
(b) Mind Practical . 145
§ 469. As will, the mind is aware that it is the author of its own conclusions,
the origin of its self-fulfilment. Thus fulfilled, this independency or
individuality form the side of existence or of reality for the Idea of mind.
As will, the mind steps into actuality; whereas as cognition it is on the soil
of notional generality. Supplying its own content, the will is self-possessed,
and in the widest sense free: this is its characteristic trait. Its finitude lies in
the formalism that the spontaneity of its self-fulfilment means no more than
a general and abstract ownness, not yet identified with matured reason. It is
the function of the essential will to bring liberty to exist in the formal will,
and it is therefore the aim of that formal will to fill itself with its essential
nature, i.e. to make liberty its pervading character, content, and aim, as well
as its sphere of existence. The essential freedom of will is, and must always
be, a thought: hence the way by which will can make itself objective mind
is to rise to be a thinking will,—to give itself the content which it can only
have as it thinks itself.
True liberty, in the shape of moral life, consists in the will finding its
purpose in a universal content, not in subjective or selfish interests. But
such a content is only possible in thought and through thought: it is nothing
short of absurd to seek to banish thought from the moral, religious, and law-
abiding life.
Thus it is on the one hand silly to suppose that in the passage from feeling
to law and duty there is any loss of import and excellence; it is this passage
which lets feeling first reach its truth. It is equally silly to consider intellect
as superfluous or even harmful to feeling, heart, and will; the truth and,
what is the same thing, the actual rationality of the heart and will can only
be at home in the universality of intellect, and not in the singleness of
feeling as feeling. If feelings are of the right sort, it is because of their
quality or content,—which is right only so far as it is intrinsically universal
or has its source in the thinking mind. The difficulty for the logical intellect
consists in throwing off the separation it has arbitrarily imposed between
the several faculties of feeling and thinking mind, and coming to see that in
the human being there is only one reason, in feeling, volition, and thought.
Another difficulty connected with this is found in the fact that the Ideas
which are the special property of the thinking mind, viz. God, law and
morality, can also be felt. But feeling is only the form of the immediate and
peculiar individuality of the subject, in which these facts, like any other
objective facts (which consciousness also sets over against itself), may be
placed.
Delight, joy, grief, &c., shame, repentance, contentment, &c., are partly
only modifications of the formal “practical feeling” in general, but are
partly different in the features that give the special tone and character mode
to their “Ought.”
The celebrated question as to the origin of evil in the world, so far at least
as evil is understood to mean what is disagreeable and painful merely, arises
on this stage of the formal practical feeling. Evil is nothing but the
incompatibility between what is and what ought to be. “Ought” is an
ambiguous term,—indeed infinitely so, considering that casual aims may
also come under the form of Ought. But where the objects sought are thus
casual, evil only executes what is rightfully due to the vanity and nullity of
their planning: for they themselves were radically evil. The finitude of life
and mind is seen in their judgment: the contrary which is separated from
them they also have as a negative in them, and thus they are the
contradiction called evil. In the dead there is neither evil nor pain: for in
inorganic [pg 095] nature the intelligible unity (concept) does not confront
its existence and does not in the difference at the same time remain its
permanent subject. Whereas in life, and still more in mind, we have this
immanent distinction present: hence arises the Ought: and this negativity,
subjectivity, ego, freedom are the principles of evil and pain. Jacob Böhme
viewed egoity (selfhood) as pain and torment, and as the fountain of nature
and of spirit.
[pg 096]
The special note in passion is its restriction to one special mode of volition,
in which the whole subjectivity of the individual is merged, be the value of
that mode what it may. In consequence of this formalism, passion is neither
good nor bad; the title only states that a subject has thrown his whole soul,
—his interests of intellect, talent, character, enjoyment,—on one aim and
object. Nothing great has been and nothing great can be accomplished
without passion. It is only a dead, too often, indeed, a hypocritical
moralising which inveighs against the form of passion as such.
But with regard to the inclinations, the question is directly raised, Which
are good and bad?—Up to what degree the good continue good;—and (as
there are many, each with its private range) In what way have they, being all
in one subject and hardly all, as experience shows, admitting of
gratification, to suffer at least reciprocal restriction? And, first of all, as
regards the numbers of these impulses and propensities, the case is much
the same as with the psychical powers, whose aggregate is to form the mind
theoretical,—an aggregate which is now increased by the host of impulses.
The nominal rationality of impulse and propensity lies merely in their
general impulse not to be subjective merely, but to get realised, overcoming
the subjectivity by the subject's own agency. Their genuine rationality
cannot reveal its secret to a method of outer reflection which pre-supposes a
number of independent innate tendencies and immediate instincts, and
therefore is wanting in a single principle and final purpose for them. But the
immanent “reflection” of mind itself carries it beyond their particularity and
their natural immediacy, and gives their contents a rationality and
objectivity, in which they exist as necessary ties of social relation, as rights
and duties. It is this objectification which [pg 097] evinces their real value,
their mutual connexions, and their truth. And thus it was a true perception
when Plato (especially including as he did the mind's whole nature under its
right) showed that the full reality of justice could be exhibited only in the
objective phase of justice, viz. in the construction of the State as the ethical
life.
The answer to the question, therefore, What are the good and rational
propensities, and how they are to be co-ordinated with each other? resolves
itself into an exposition of the laws and forms of common life produced by
the mind when developing itself as objective mind—a development in
which the content of autonomous action loses its contingency and
optionality. The discussion of the true intrinsic worth of the impulses,
inclinations, and passions is thus essentially the theory of legal, moral, and
social duties.
§ 475. The subject is the act of satisfying impulses, an act of (at least)
formal rationality, as it translates them from the subjectivity of content
(which so far is purpose) into objectivity, where the subject is made to close
with itself. If the content of the impulse is distinguished as the thing or
business from this act of carrying it out, and we regard the thing which has
been brought to pass as containing the element of subjective individuality
and its action, this is what is called the interest. Nothing therefore is
brought about without interest.
An action is an aim of the subject, and it is his agency too which executes
this aim: unless the subject were in this way in the most disinterested
action, i.e. unless he had an interest in it, there would be no action at all.—
The impulses and inclinations are sometimes depreciated by being
contrasted with the baseless chimera of a happiness, the free gift of nature,
where [pg 098] wants are supposed to find their satisfaction without the
agent doing anything to produce a conformity between immediate existence
and his own inner requirements. They are sometimes contrasted, on the
whole to their disadvantage, with the morality of duty for duty's sake. But
impulse and passion are the very life-blood of all action: they are needed if
the agent is really to be in his aim and the execution thereof. The morality
concerns the content of the aim, which as such is the universal, an inactive
thing, that finds its actualising in the agent; and finds it only when the aim
is immanent in the agent, is his interest and—should it claim to engross his
whole efficient subjectivity—his passion.
§ 476. The will, as thinking and implicitly free, distinguishes itself from the
particularity of the impulses, and places itself as simple subjectivity of
thought above their diversified content. It is thus “reflecting” will.
§ 477. Such a particularity of impulse has thus ceased to be a mere datum:
the reflective will now sees it as its own, because it closes with it and thus
gives itself specific individuality and actuality. It is now on the standpoint
of choosing between inclinations, and is option or choice.
§ 478. Will as choice claims to be free, reflected into itself as the negativity
of its merely immediate autonomy. However, as the content, in which its
former universality concludes itself to actuality, is nothing but the content
of the impulses and appetites, it is actual only as a subjective and contingent
will. It realises itself in a particularity, which it regards at the same time as a
nullity, and finds a satisfaction in what it has at the same time emerged
from. As thus contradictory, it is the process of distracting and suspending
[pg 099] one desire or enjoyment by another,—and one satisfaction, which
is just as much no satisfaction, by another, without end. But the truth of the
particular satisfactions is the universal, which under the name of happiness
the thinking will makes its aim.
(γ) Happiness148.
[pg 100]
§ 481. Actual free will is the unity of theoretical and practical mind: a free
will, which realises its own freedom of will now that the formalism,
fortuitousness, and contractedness of the practical content up to this point
have been superseded. By superseding the adjustments of means therein
contained, the will is the immediate individuality self-instituted,—an
individuality, however, also purified of all that interferes with its
universalism, i.e. with freedom itself. This universalism the will has as its
object and aim, only so far as it thinks itself, knows this its concept, and is
will as free intelligence.
§ 482. The mind which knows itself as free and wills itself as this its object,
i.e. which has its true being for characteristic and aim, is in the first instance
the rational will in general, or implicit Idea, and because implicit only the
notion of absolute mind. As abstract Idea again, it is existent only in the
immediate will—it is the existential side of reason,—the single will as
aware of this its universality constituting its contents and aim, and of which
it is only the formal activity. If the will, therefore, in which the Idea thus
appears is only finite, that will is also the act of developing the Idea, and of
investing its self-unfolding content with an existence which, as realising the
idea, is actuality. It is thus “Objective” Mind.
If to be aware of the idea—to be aware, i.e. that men are aware of freedom
as their essence, aim, and object—is matter of speculation, still this very
idea itself is the actuality of men—not something which they have, as men,
but which they are. Christianity in its adherents has realised an ever-present
sense that they are not and cannot be slaves; if they are made slaves, if the
decision as regards their property rests with an arbitrary [pg 102] will, not
with laws or courts of justice, they would find the very substance of their
life outraged. This will to liberty is no longer an impulse which demands its
satisfaction, but the permanent character—the spiritual consciousness
grown into a non-impulsive nature. But this freedom, which the content and
aim of freedom has, is itself only a notion—a principle of the mind and
heart, intended to develope into an objective phase, into legal, moral,
religious, and not less into scientific actuality.
[pg 103]
Section II. Mind Objective.
§ 483. The objective Mind is the absolute Idea, but only existing in posse:
and as it is thus on the territory of finitude, its actual rationality retains the
aspect of external apparency. The free will finds itself immediately
confronted by differences which arise from the circumstance that freedom is
its inward function and aim, and is in relation to an external and already
subsisting objectivity, which splits up into different heads: viz.
anthropological data (i.e. private and personal needs), external things of
nature which exist for consciousness, and the ties of relation between
individual wills which are conscious of their own diversity and particularity.
These aspects constitute the external material for the embodiment of the
will.
§ 484. But the purposive action of this will is to realise its concept, Liberty,
in these externally-objective aspects, making the latter a world moulded by
the former, which in it is thus at home with itself, locked together with it:
the concept accordingly perfected to the Idea. Liberty, shaped into the
actuality of a world, receives the form of Necessity the deeper substantial
nexus of which is the system or organisation of the principles of liberty,
whilst its phenomenal nexus is power or authority, [pg 104] and the
sentiment of obedience awakened in consciousness.
§ 485. This unity of the rational will with the single will (this being the
peculiar and immediate medium in which the former is actualised)
constitutes the simple actuality of liberty. As it (and its content) belongs to
thought, and is the virtual universal, the content has its right and true
character only in the form of universality. When invested with this character
for the intelligent consciousness, or instituted as an authoritative power, it is
a Law150. When, on the other hand, the content is freed from the mixedness
and fortuitousness, attaching to it in the practical feeling and in impulse,
and is set and grafted in the individual will, not in the form of impulse, but
in its universality, so as to become its habit, temper and character, it exists
as manner and custom, or Usage151.
§ 486. This “reality,” in general, where free will has existence, is the Law
(Right),—the term being taken in a comprehensive sense not merely as the
limited juristic law, but as the actual body of all the conditions of freedom.
These conditions, in relation to the subjective will, where they, being
universal, ought to have and can only have their existence, are its Duties;
whereas as its temper and habit they are Manners. What is a right is also a
duty, and what is a duty, is also a right. For a mode of existence is a right,
only as a consequence of the free substantial will: and the same content of
fact, when referred to the will distinguished as subjective and individual, is
a duty. It is the same content which the subjective consciousness recognises
as a duty, and brings into existence in these several wills. The finitude of
the objective will thus creates the semblance of a distinction between rights
and duties.
[pg 105]
In the phenomenal range right and duty are correlata, at least in the sense
that to a right on my part corresponds a duty in some one else. But, in the
light of the concept, my right to a thing is not merely possession, but as
possession by a person it is property, or legal possession, and it is a duty to
possess things as property, i.e. to be as a person. Translated into the
phenomenal relationship, viz. relation to another person—this grows into
the duty of some one else to respect my right. In the morality of the
conscience, duty in general is in me—a free subject—at the same time a
right of my subjective will or disposition. But in this individualist moral
sphere, there arises the division between what is only inward purpose
(disposition or intention), which only has its being in me and is merely
subjective duty, and the actualisation of that purpose: and with this division
a contingency and imperfection which makes the inadequacy of mere
individualistic morality. In social ethics these two parts have reached their
truth, their absolute unity; although even right and duty return to one
another and combine by means of certain adjustments and under the guise
of necessity. The rights of the father of the family over its members are
equally duties towards them; just as the children's duty of obedience is their
right to be educated to the liberty of manhood. The penal judicature of a
government, its rights of administration, &c., are no less its duties to
punish, to administer, &c.; as the services of the members of the State in
dues, military services, &c., are duties and yet their right to the protection
of their private property and of the general substantial life in which they
have their root. All the aims of society and the State are the private aim of
the individuals. But the set of adjustments, by which their duties come back
to them as the exercise and enjoyment of right, [pg 106] produces an
appearance of diversity: and this diversity is increased by the variety of
shapes which value assumes in the course of exchange, though it remains
intrinsically the same. Still it holds fundamentally good that he who has no
rights has no duties and vice versa.
Distribution.
B. When the will is reflected into self, so as to have its existence inside it,
and to be thus at the same time characterised as a particular, it is the right
of the subjective will, morality of the individual conscience.
C. When the free will is the substantial will, made actual in the subject and
conformable to its concept and rendered a totality of necessity,—it is the
ethics of actual life in family, civil society, and state.
[pg 107]
Sub-Section A. Law. 152
(a) Property.
§ 490. In his property the person is brought into union with itself. But the
thing is an abstractly external thing, and the I in it is abstractly external. The
concrete return of me into me in the externality is [pg 108] that I, the
infinite self-relation, am as a person the repulsion of me from myself, and
have the existence of my personality in the being of other persons, in my
relation to them and in my recognition by them, which is thus mutual.
§ 491. The thing is the mean by which the extremes meet in one. These
extremes are the persons who, in the knowledge of their identity as free, are
simultaneously mutually independent. For them my will has its definite
recognisable existence in the thing by the immediate bodily act of taking
possession, or by the formation of the thing or, it may be, by mere
designation of it.
§ 492. The casual aspect of property is that I place my will in this thing: so
far my will is arbitrary, I can just as well put it in it as not,—just as well
withdraw it as not. But so far as my will lies in a thing, it is only I who can
withdraw it: it is only with my will that the thing can pass to another, whose
property it similarly becomes only with his will:—Contract.
(b) Contract.
§ 493. The two wills and their agreement in the contract are as an internal
state of mind different from its realisation in the performance. The
comparatively “ideal” utterance (of contract) in the stipulation contains the
actual surrender of a property by the one, its changing hands, and its
acceptance by the other will. The contract is thus thoroughly binding: it
does not need the performance of the one or the other to become so—
otherwise we should have an infinite regress or infinite division of thing,
labour, and time. The utterance in the stipulation is complete and
exhaustive. The inwardness of the will which surrenders and the will which
accepts the property is in the realm of ideation, [pg 109] and in that realm
the word is deed and thing (§ 462)—the full and complete deed, since here
the conscientiousness of the will does not come under consideration (as to
whether the thing is meant in earnest or is a deception), and the will refers
only to the external thing.
§ 494. Thus in the stipulation we have the substantial being of the contract
standing out in distinction from its real utterance in the performance, which
is brought down to a mere sequel. In this way there is put into the thing or
performance a distinction between its immediate specific quality and its
substantial being or value, meaning by value the quantitative terms into
which that qualitative feature has been translated. One piece of property is
thus made comparable with another, and may be made equivalent to a thing
which is (in quality) wholly heterogeneous. It is thus treated in general as
an abstract, universal thing or commodity.
§ 495. The contract, as an agreement which has a voluntary origin and deals
with a casual commodity, involves at the same time the giving to this
“accidental” will a positive fixity. This will may just as well not be
conformable to law (right), and, in that case, produces a wrong: by which
however the absolute law (right) is not superseded, but only a relationship
originated of right to wrong.
§ 497. Now so long as (compared against this show) the one intrinsically
right, still presumed identical with the several titles, is affirmed, willed, and
recognised, the only diversity lies in this, that the special thing is subsumed
under the one law or right by the particular will of these several persons.
This is naïve, non-malicious wrong. Such wrong in the several claimants is
a simple negative judgment, expressing the civil suit. To settle it there is
required a third judgment, which, as the judgment of the intrinsically right,
is disinterested, and a power of giving the one right existence as against that
semblance.
§ 498. But (2) if the semblance of right is willed as such against right
intrinsical by the particular will, which thus becomes wicked, then the
external recognition of right is separated from the right's true value; and
while the former only is respected, the latter is violated. This gives the
wrong of fraud—the infinite judgment as identical (§ 173),—where the
nominal relation is retained, but the sterling value is let slip.
§ 499. (3) Finally, the particular will sets itself in opposition to the intrinsic
right by negating that right itself as well as its recognition or semblance.
[Here there is a negatively infinite judgment (§ 173) in which there is
denied the class as a whole, and not merely the particular mode—in this
case the apparent recognition.] Thus the will is violently wicked, and
commits a crime.
§ 502. A distinction has thus emerged between the law (right) and the
subjective will. The “reality” of right, which the personal will in the first
instance gives itself in immediate wise, is seen to be due to the [pg 112]
instrumentality of the subjective will,—whose influence as on one hand it
gives existence to the essential right, so may on the other cut itself off from
and oppose itself to it. Conversely, the claim of the subjective will to be in
this abstraction a power over the law of right is null and empty of itself: it
gets truth and reality essentially only so far as that will in itself realises the
reasonable will. As such it is morality153 proper.
The phrase “Law of Nature,” or Natural Right154, in use for the philosophy
of law involves the ambiguity that it may mean either right as something
existing ready-formed in nature, or right as governed by the nature of
things, i.e. by the notion. The former used to be the common meaning,
accompanied with the fiction of a state of nature, in which the law of nature
should hold sway; whereas the social and political state rather required and
implied a restriction of liberty and a sacrifice of natural rights. The real fact
is that the whole law and its every article are based on free personality
alone,—on self-determination or autonomy, which is the very contrary of
determination by nature. The law of nature—strictly so called—is for that
reason the predominance of the strong and the reign of force, and a state of
nature a state of violence and wrong, of which nothing truer can be said
than that one ought to depart from it. The social state, on the other hand, is
the condition in which alone right has its actuality: what is to be restricted
and sacrificed is just the wilfulness and violence of the state of nature.
[pg 113]
Sub-Section B. The Morality Of Conscience . 155
§ 503. The free individual, who, in mere law, counts only as a person, is
now characterised as a subject, a will reflected into itself so that, be its
affection what it may, it is distinguished (as existing in it) as its own from
the existence of freedom in an external thing. Because the affection of the
will is thus inwardised, the will is at the same time made a particular, and
there arise further particularisations of it and relations of these to one
another. This affection is partly the essential and implicit will, the reason of
the will, the essential basis of law and moral life: partly it is the existent
volition, which is before us and throws itself into actual deeds, and thus
comes into relationship with the former. The subjective will is morally free,
so far as these features are its inward institution, its own, and willed by it.
Its utterance in deed with this freedom is an action, in the externality of
which it only admits as its own, and allows to be imputed to it, so much as
it has consciously willed.
The “moral” must be taken in the wider sense in which it does not signify
the morally good merely. In French le moral is opposed to le physique, and
means the mental or intellectual in general. But here the moral signifies
volitional mode, so far as it is in the interior of the will in general; it thus
includes purpose and intention,—and also moral wickedness.
a. Purpose .156
§ 504. So far as the action comes into immediate touch with existence, my
part in it is to this extent formal, that external existence is also independent
of the agent. This externality can pervert his action and bring to light
something else than lay in it. Now, though any alteration as such, which is
set on foot by the subject's action, is its deed157, still the subject does not for
that reason recognise it as its action158, but only admits as its own that
existence in the deed which lay in its knowledge and will, which was its
purpose. Only for that does it hold itself responsible.
§ 505. As regards its empirically concrete content (1) the action has a
variety of particular aspects and connexions. In point of form, the agent
must have known and willed the action in its essential feature, embracing
these individual points. This is the right of [pg 115] intention. While
purpose affects only the immediate fact of existence, intention regards the
underlying essence and aim thereof. (2) The agent has no less the right to
see that the particularity of content in the action, in point of its matter, is not
something external to him, but is a particularity of his own,—that it
contains his needs, interests, and aims. These aims, when similarly
comprehended in a single aim, as in happiness (§ 479), constitute his well-
being. This is the right to well-being. Happiness (good fortune) is
distinguished from well-being only in this, that happiness implies no more
than some sort of immediate existence, whereas well-being regards it as
also justified as regards morality.
§ 506. But the essentiality of the intention is in the first instance the abstract
form of generality. Reflection can put in this form this and that particular
aspect in the empirically-concrete action, thus making it essential to the
intention or restricting the intention to it. In this way the supposed
essentiality of the intention and the real essentiality of the action may be
brought into the greatest contradiction—e.g. a good intention in case of a
crime. Similarly well-being is abstract and may be set on this or that: as
appertaining to this single agent, it is always something particular.
§ 507. The truth of these particularities and the concrete unity of their
formalism is the content of the universal, essential and actual, will,—the
law and underlying essence of every phase of volition, the essential and
actual good. It is thus the absolute final aim of the world, and duty for the
agent who ought [pg 116] to have insight into the good, make it his
intention and bring it about by his activity.
§ 508. But though the good is the universal of will—a universal determined
in itself,—and thus including in it particularity,—still so far as this
particularity is in the first instance still abstract, there is no principle at hand
to determine it. Such determination therefore starts up also outside that
universal; and as heteronomy or determinance of a will which is free and
has rights of its own, there awakes here the deepest contradiction. (α) In
consequence of the indeterminate determinism of the good, there are always
several sorts of good and many kinds of duties, the variety of which is a
dialectic of one against another and brings them into collision. At the same
time because good is one, they ought to stand in harmony; and yet each of
them, though it is a particular duty, is as good and as duty absolute. It falls
upon the agent to be the dialectic which, superseding this absolute claim of
each, concludes such a combination of them as excludes the rest.
§ 509. (β) To the agent, who in his existent sphere of liberty is essentially as
a particular, his interest and welfare must, on account of that existent
sphere of liberty, be essentially an aim and therefore a duty. But at the same
time in aiming at the good, which is the not-particular but only universal of
the will, the particular interest ought not to be a constituent motive. On
account of this independency of the two principles of action, it is likewise
an accident whether they harmonise. And yet they ought to harmonise,
because the agent, as individual and universal, is always fundamentally one
identity.
(γ) But the agent is not only a mere particular in his existence; it is also a
form of his existence to be an abstract self-certainty, an abstract reflection
of freedom [pg 117] into himself. He is thus distinct from the reason in the
will, and capable of making the universal itself a particular and in that way
a semblance. The good is thus reduced to the level of a mere “may happen”
for the agent, who can therefore resolve itself to somewhat opposite to the
good, can be wicked.
§ 510. (δ) The external objectivity, following the distinction which has
arisen in the subjective will (§ 503), constitutes a peculiar world of its own,
—another extreme which stands in no rapport with the internal will-
determination. It is thus a matter of chance, whether it harmonises with the
subjective aims, whether the good is realised, and the wicked, an aim
essentially and actually null, nullified in it: it is no less matter of chance
whether the agent finds in it his well-being, and more precisely whether in
the world the good agent is happy and the wicked unhappy. But at the same
time the world ought to allow the good action, the essential thing, to be
carried out in it; it ought to grant the good agent the satisfaction of his
particular interest, and refuse it to the wicked; just as it ought also to make
the wicked itself null and void.
[pg 119]
Sub-Section C. The Moral Life, Or Social Ethics . 161
§ 513. The moral life is the perfection of spirit objective—the truth of the
subjective and objective spirit itself. The failure of the latter consists—
partly in having its freedom immediately in reality, in something external
therefore, in a thing,—partly in the abstract universality of its goodness.
The failure of spirit subjective similarly consists in this, that it is, as against
the universal, abstractly self-determinant in its inward individuality. When
these two imperfections are suppressed, subjective freedom exists as the
covertly and overtly universal rational will, which is sensible of itself and
actively disposed in the consciousness of the individual subject, whilst its
practical operation and immediate universal actuality at the same time exist
as moral usage, manner and custom,—where self-conscious liberty has
become nature.
[pg 121]
§ 517. The ethical substance is
§ 518. The ethical spirit, in its immediacy, contains the natural factor that
the individual has its substantial existence in its natural universal, i.e. in its
kind. This is the sexual tie, elevated however to a spiritual significance,—
the unanimity of love and the temper of trust. In the shape of the family,
mind appears as feeling.
§ 519. (1) The physical difference of sex thus appears at the same time as a
difference of intellectual and moral type. With their exclusive
individualities these personalities combine to form a single person: the
subjective union of hearts, becoming a “substantial” unity, makes this union
an ethical tie—Marriage. The 'substantial' union of hearts makes marriage
an indivisible personal bond—monogamic marriage: the bodily conjunction
is a sequel to the moral attachment. A further sequel is community of
personal and private interests.
§ 520. (2) By the community in which the various members constituting the
family stand in reference to property, that property of the one person
(representing the family) acquires an ethical interest, as do also its industry,
labour, and care for the future.
§ 521. The ethical principle which is conjoined with the natural generation
of the children, and which was assumed to have primary importance in first
forming the marriage union, is actually realised in the second or [pg 122]
spiritual birth of the children,—in educating them to independent
personality.
§ 522. (3) The children, thus invested with independence, leave the concrete
life and action of the family to which they primarily belong, acquire an
existence of their own, destined however to found anew such an actual
family. Marriage is of course broken up by the natural element contained in
it, the death of husband and wife: but even their union of hearts, as it is a
mere “substantiality” of feeling, contains the germ of liability to chance and
decay. In virtue of such fortuitousness, the members of the family take up to
each other the status of persons; and it is thus that the family finds
introduced into it for the first time the element, originally foreign to it, of
legal regulation.
§ 524. (α) The particularity of the persons includes in [pg 123] the first
instance their wants. The possibility of satisfying these wants is here laid on
the social fabric, the general stock from which all derive their satisfaction.
In the condition of things in which this method of satisfaction by indirect
adjustment is realised, immediate seizure (§ 488) of external objects as
means thereto exists barely or not at all: the objects are already property. To
acquire them is only possible by the intervention, on one hand, of the
possessors' will, which as particular has in view the satisfaction of their
variously defined interests; while on the other hand it is conditioned by the
ever continued production of fresh means of exchange by the exchangers'
own labour. This instrument, by which the labour of all facilitates
satisfaction of wants, constitutes the general stock.
§ 526. The labour which thus becomes more abstract tends on one hand by
its uniformity to make labour easier and to increase production,—on
another to limit each person to a single kind of technical skill, and thus
produce more unconditional dependence on the social system. The skill
itself becomes in this way mechanical, and gets the capability of letting the
machine take the place of human labour.
§ 527. (γ) But the concrete division of the general [pg 124] stock—which is
also a general business (of the whole society)—into particular masses
determined by the factors of the notion,—masses each of which possesses
its own basis of subsistence, and a corresponding mode of labour, of needs,
and of means for satisfying them, besides of aims and interests, as well as
of mental culture and habit—constitutes the difference of Estates (orders or
ranks). Individuals apportion themselves to these according to natural
talent, skill, option and accident. As belonging to such a definite and stable
sphere, they have their actual existence, which as existence is essentially a
particular; and in it they have their social morality, which is honesty, their
recognition and their honour.
Where civil society, and with it the State, exists, there arise the several
estates in their difference: for the universal substance, as vital, exists only so
far as it organically particularises itself. The history of constitutions is the
history of the growth of these estates, of the legal relationships of
individuals to them, and of these estates to one another and to their centre.
§ 528. To the “substantial,” natural estate the fruitful soil and ground supply
a natural and stable capital; its action gets direction and content through
natural features, and its moral life is founded on faith and trust. The second,
the “reflected” estate has as its allotment the social capital, the medium
created by the action of middlemen, of mere agents, and an ensemble of
contingencies, where the individual has to depend on his subjective skill,
talent, intelligence and industry. The third, “thinking” estate has for its
business the general interests; like the second it has a subsistence procured
by means of its own skill, and like the first a certain subsistence, certain
however because guaranteed through the whole society.
[pg 125]
b. Administration of Justice164.
§ 529. When matured through the operation of natural need and free option
into a system of universal relationships and a regular course of external
necessity, the principle of casual particularity gets that stable articulation
which liberty requires in the shape of formal right. (1) The actualisation
which right gets in this sphere of mere practical intelligence is that it be
brought to consciousness as the stable universal, that it be known and stated
in its specificality with the voice of authority—the Law165.
The positive element in laws concerns only their form of publicity and
authority—which makes it possible for them to be known by all in a
customary and external way. Their content per se may be reasonable—or it
may be unreasonable and so wrong. But when right, in the course of
definite manifestation, is developed in detail, and its content analyses itself
to gain definiteness, this analysis, because of the finitude of its materials,
falls into the falsely infinite progress: the final definiteness, which is
absolutely essential and causes a break in this progress of unreality, can in
this sphere of finitude be attained only in a way that savours of contingency
and arbitrariness. Thus whether three years, ten thalers, or only 2-1/2, 2-3/4,
2-4/5 years, and so on ad infinitum, be the right and just thing, can by no
means be decided on intelligible principles,—and yet it should be decided.
Hence, though of course only at the final points of deciding, on the side of
external existence, the “positive” principle naturally enters law as
contingency and arbitrariness. This happens and has from of old happened
in all legislations: [pg 126] the only thing wanted is clearly to be aware of
it, and not be misled by the talk and the pretence as if the ideal of law were,
or could be, to be, at every point, determined through reason or legal
intelligence, on purely reasonable and intelligent grounds. It is a futile
perfectionism to have such expectations and to make such requirements in
the sphere of the finite.
There are some who look upon laws as an evil and a profanity, and who
regard governing and being governed from natural love, hereditary, divinity
or nobility, by faith and trust, as the genuine order of life, while the reign of
law is held an order of corruption and injustice. These people forget that the
stars—and the cattle too—are governed and well governed too by laws;—
laws however which are only internally in these objects, not for them, not as
laws set to them:—whereas it is man's privilege to know his law. They
forget therefore that he can truly obey only such known law,—even as his
law can only be a just law, as it is a known law;—though in other respects it
must be in its essential content contingency and caprice, or at least be
mixed and polluted with such elements.
§ 530. (2) The positive form of Laws—to be promulgated and made known
as laws—is a condition of the external obligation to obey them; inasmuch
as, being laws of strict right, they touch only the abstract will,—itself at
bottom external—not the moral or ethical will. The subjectivity to which
the will has in this direction a right is here only publicity. This subjective
existence is as existence of the essential and developed truth in this sphere
of Right at the same time an externally objective existence, as universal
authority and necessity.
§ 531. (3) Legal forms get the necessity, to which objective existence
determines itself, in the judicial [pg 128]system. Abstract right has to
exhibit itself to the court—to the individualised right—as proven:—a
process in which there may be a difference between what is abstractly right
and what is provably right. The court takes cognisance and action in the
interest of right as such, deprives the existence of right of its contingency,
and in particular transforms this existence,—as this exists as revenge—into
punishment (§ 500).
The comparison of the two species, or rather two elements in the judicial
conviction, bearing on the actual state of the case in relation to the accused,
—(1) according as that conviction is based on mere circumstances and other
people's witness alone,—or (2) in addition requires the confession of the
accused, constitutes the main point in the question of the so-called jury-
courts. It is an essential point that the two ingredients of a judicial
cognisance, the judgment as to the state of the fact, and the judgment as
application of the law to it, should, as at bottom different sides, be exercised
as different functions. By the said institution they are allotted even to bodies
differently qualified,—from the one of which individuals belonging to the
official judiciary are expressly excluded. To carry this separation of
functions up to this separation in the courts rests rather on extra-essential
considerations: the main point remains only the separate performance of
these essentially different functions.—It is a more important point whether
the confession of the accused is or is not to be made a condition of penal
judgment. The institution of the jury-court loses sight of this condition. The
point is that on this ground certainty is completely inseparable from truth:
but the confession is to be regarded as the very acmé of certainty-giving
which in its nature is subjective. The final decision therefore lies with the
confession. To this therefore the accused [pg 129] has an absolute right, if
the proof is to be made final and the judges to be convinced. No doubt this
factor is incomplete, because it is only one factor; but still more incomplete
is the other when no less abstractly taken,—viz. mere circumstantial
evidence. The jurors are essentially judges and pronounce a judgment. In so
far, then, as all they have to go on are such objective proofs, whilst at the
same time their defect of certainty (incomplete in so far as it is only in
them) is admitted, the jury-court shows traces of its barbaric origin in a
confusion and admixture between objective proofs and subjective or so-
called “moral” conviction.—It is easy to call extraordinary punishments an
absurdity; but the fault lies rather with the shallowness which takes offence
at a mere name. Materially the principle involves the difference of objective
probation according as it goes with or without the factor of absolute
certification which lies in confession.
§ 534. To keep in view this general end, to ascertain the way in which the
powers composing that social necessity act, and their variable ingredients,
and to maintain that end in them and against them, is the work of an
institution which assumes on one hand, to the concrete of civil society, the
position of an external universality. Such an order acts with the power of an
external state, which, in so far as it is rooted in the higher or substantial
state, appears as state “police.” On the other hand, in this sphere of
particularity the only recognition of the aim of substantial universality and
the only carrying of it out is restricted to the business of particular branches
and interests. Thus we have the corporation, in which the particular citizen
in his private capacity finds the securing of his stock, whilst at the same
time he in it emerges from his single private interest, and has a conscious
[pg 131] activity for a comparatively universal end, just as in his legal and
professional duties he has his social morality.
CC. The State.
α. Constitutional Law167.
§ 537. The essence of the state is the universal, self-originated and self-
developed,—the reasonable spirit of will; but, as self-knowing and self-
actualising, sheer subjectivity, and—as an actuality—one individual. Its
work generally—in relation to the extreme of individuality as the multitude
of individuals—consists in a double function. First it maintains them as
persons, thus making right a necessary actuality, then it promotes their
welfare, which each originally takes care of for himself, but which has a
thoroughly general side; it protects the [pg 132] family and guides civil
society. Secondly, it carries back both, and the whole disposition and action
of the individual—whose tendency is to become a centre of his own—into
the life of the universal substance; and, in this direction, as a free power it
interferes with those subordinate spheres and retains them in substantial
immanence.
§ 538. The laws express the special provisions for objective freedom. First,
to the immediate agent, his independent self-will and particular interest,
they are restrictions. But, secondly, they are an absolute final end and the
universal work: hence they are a product of the “functions” of the various
orders which parcel themselves more and more out of the general
particularising, and are a fruit of all the acts and private concerns of
individuals. Thirdly, they are the substance of the volition of individuals—
which volition is thereby free—and of their disposition: being as such
exhibited as current usage.
[pg 133]
Liberty and Equality are the simple rubrics into which is frequently
concentrated what should form the fundamental principle, the final aim and
result of the constitution. However true this is, the defect of these terms is
their utter abstractness: if stuck to in this abstract form, they are principles
which either prevent the rise of the concreteness of the state, i.e. its
articulation into a constitution and a government in general, or destroy
them. With the state there arises inequality, the difference of governing
powers and of governed, magistracies, authorities, directories, &c. The
principle of equality, logically carried out, rejects all differences, and thus
allows no sort of political condition to exist. Liberty and equality are indeed
the foundation of the state, but as the most abstract also the most
superficial, and for that very reason naturally the most familiar. It is
important therefore to study them closer.
As regards, first, Equality, the familiar proposition, All men are by nature
equal, blunders by confusing the “natural” with the “notion.” It ought rather
to read: By nature men are only unequal. But the notion of liberty, as it
exists as such, without further specification and development, is abstract
subjectivity, as a person capable of property (§ 488). This single abstract
feature of personality constitutes the actual equality of human beings. But
that this freedom should exist, that it should be man (and not as in Greece,
Rome, &c. some men) that is recognised and legally regarded as a person, is
so little by nature, that it is rather only a result and product of the
consciousness of the deepest principle of mind, and of the universality and
expansion of this consciousness. That the citizens are equal before the law
contains a great truth, but which so expressed is a tautology: it only states
that the legal status in general exists, that the laws rule. But, as [pg 134]
regards the concrete, the citizens—besides their personality—are equal
before the law only in these points when they are otherwise equal outside
the law. Only that equality which (in whatever way it be) they, as it
happens, otherwise have in property, age, physical strength, talent, skill, &c.
—or even in crime, can and ought to make them deserve equal treatment
before the law:—only it can make them—as regards taxation, military
service, eligibility to office, &c.—punishment, &c.—equal in the concrete.
The laws themselves, except in so far as they concern that narrow circle of
personality, presuppose unequal conditions, and provide for the unequal
legal duties and appurtenances resulting therefrom.
§ 540. The guarantee of a constitution (i.e. the necessity that the laws be
reasonable, and their actualisation secured) lies in the collective spirit of the
nation,—especially in the specific way in which it is itself conscious of its
reason. (Religion is that consciousness in its absolute substantiality.) But
the guarantee lies also at the same time in the actual organisation or
development of that principle in suitable institutions. The constitution
presupposes that consciousness [pg 137] of the collective spirit, and
conversely that spirit presupposes the constitution: for the actual spirit only
has a definite consciousness of its principles, in so far as it has them
actually existent before it.
The question—To whom (to what authority and how organised) belongs the
power to make a constitution? is the same as the question, Who has to make
the spirit of a nation? Separate our idea of a constitution from that of the
collective spirit, as if the latter exists or has existed without a constitution,
and your fancy only proves how superficially you have apprehended the
nexus between the spirit in its self-consciousness and in its actuality. What
is thus called “making” a “constitution,” is—just because of this
inseparability—a thing that has never happened in history, just as little as
the making of a code of laws. A constitution only develops from the
national spirit identically with that spirit's own development, and runs
through at the same time with it the grades of formation and the alterations
required by its concept. It is the indwelling spirit and the history of the
nation (and, be it added, the history is only that spirit's history) by which
constitutions have been and are made.
As the most obvious categories of the notion are those of universality and
individuality and their relationship that of subsumption of individual under
universal, it has come about that in the state the legislative and executive
power have been so distinguished as to make the former exist apart as the
absolute superior, and to subdivide the latter again into administrative
(government) power and judicial power, according as the laws are applied
to public or private affairs. The division of these powers has been treated as
the condition of political equilibrium, meaning by division their
independence one of another in existence,—subject always however to the
above-mentioned subsumption of the powers of the individual under the
power of the general. The theory of such “division” unmistakably implies
the elements of the notion, but so combined by “understanding” as to result
in an absurd collocation, instead of the self-redintegration of the living
spirit. The one essential canon to make liberty deep and real is to give every
business belonging to the general interests of the state a separate
organisation wherever they are essentially distinct. Such real division must
be: for liberty is only deep when it is differentiated in all its fullness and
these differences manifested in existence. But to make the business of
legislation an independent power—to make it the first power, with the
further proviso that all citizens shall have part therein, and the government
be merely executive and dependent, presupposes ignorance that the true
idea, and therefore the living and spiritual actuality, is the self-
redintegrating notion, in other words, the subjectivity which contains in it
universality as only one of its moments. (A mistake still greater, if it goes
with the fancy that the constitution and the fundamental [pg 139] laws were
still one day to make,—in a state of society, which includes an already
existing development of differences.) Individuality is the first and supreme
principle which makes itself fall through the state's organisation. Only
through the government, and by its embracing in itself the particular
businesses (including the abstract legislative business, which taken apart is
also particular), is the state one. These, as always, are the terms on which
the different elements essentially and alone truly stand towards each other
in the logic of “reason,” as opposed to the external footing they stand on in
'understanding,' which never gets beyond subsuming the individual and
particular under the universal. What disorganises the unity of logical reason,
equally disorganises actuality.
§ 546. This state of war shows the omnipotence of the state in its
individuality—an individuality that goes even to abstract negativity.
Country and fatherland then appear as the power by which the particular
independence of individuals and their absorption in the external existence
of possession and in natural life is convicted of its own nullity,—as the
power which procures the maintenance of the general substance by the [pg
147] patriotic sacrifice on the part of these individuals of this natural and
particular existence,—so making nugatory the nugatoriness that confronts
it.
§ 547. In the game of war the independence of States is at stake. In one case
the result may be the mutual recognition of free national individualities (§
430): and by peace-conventions supposed to be for ever, both this general
recognition, and the special claims of nations on one another, are settled and
fixed. External state-rights rest partly on these positive treaties, but to that
extent contain only rights falling short of true actuality (§ 545): partly on
so-called international law, the general principle of which is its
presupposed recognition by the several States. It thus restricts their
otherwise unchecked action against one another in such a way that the
possibility of peace is left; and distinguishes individuals as private persons
(non-belligerents) from the state. In general, international law rests on
social usage.
γ. Universal History169.
§ 548. As the mind of a special nation is actual and its liberty is under
natural conditions, it admits on this nature-side the influence of
geographical and climatic qualities. It is in time; and as regards its range
and scope, has essentially a particular principle on the lines of which it
must run through a development of its consciousness and its actuality. It
has, in short, a history of its own. But as a restricted mind its independence
is something secondary; it passes into universal world-history, the events of
which exhibit the dialectic of the several national minds,—the judgment of
the world.
[pg 148]
§ 549. This movement is the path of liberation for the spiritual substance,
the deed by which the absolute final aim of the world is realised in it, and
the merely implicit mind achieves consciousness and self-consciousness. It
is thus the revelation and actuality of its essential and completed essence,
whereby it becomes to the outward eye a universal spirit—a world-mind.
As this development is in time and in real existence, as it is a history, its
several stages and steps are the national minds, each of which, as single and
endued by nature with a specific character, is appointed to occupy only one
grade, and accomplish one task in the whole deed.
The presupposition that history has an essential and actual end, from the
principles of which certain characteristic results logically flow, is called an
a priori view of it, and philosophy is reproached with a priori history-
writing. On this point, and on history-writing in general, this note must go
into further detail. That history, and above all universal history, is founded
on an essential and actual aim, which actually is and will be realised in it—
the plan of Providence; that, in short, there is Reason in history, must be
decided on strictly philosophical ground, and thus shown to be essentially
and in fact necessary. To presuppose such aim is blameworthy only when
the assumed conceptions or thoughts are arbitrarily adopted, and when a
determined attempt is made to force events and actions into conformity with
such conceptions. For such a priori methods of treatment at the present day,
however, those are chiefly to blame who profess to be purely historical, and
who at the same time take opportunity expressly to raise their voice against
the habit of philosophising, first in general, and then in history. Philosophy
is to them a troublesome neighbour: for it is an enemy of all arbitrariness
and hasty suggestions. Such a priori [pg 149] history-writing has
sometimes burst out in quarters where one would least have expected it,
especially on the philological side, and in Germany more than in France and
England, where the art of historical writing has gone through a process of
purification to a firmer and maturer character. Fictions, like that of a
primitive age and its primitive people, possessed from the first of the true
knowledge of God and all the sciences,—of sacerdotal races,—and, when
we come to minutiae, of a Roman epic, supposed to be the source of the
legends which pass current for the history of ancient Rome, &c., have taken
the place of the pragmatising which detected psychological motives and
associations. There is a wide circle of persons who seem to consider it
incumbent on a learned and ingenious historian drawing from the original
sources to concoct such baseless fancies, and form bold combinations of
them from a learned rubbish-heap of out-of-the-way and trivial facts, in
defiance of the best-accredited history.
[pg 154]
§ 552. The national spirit contains nature-necessity, and stands in external
existence (§ 423): the ethical substance, potentially infinite, is actually a
particular and limited substance (§§ 549, 550); on its subjective side it
labours under contingency, in the shape of its unreflective natural usages,
and its content is presented to it as something existing in time and tied to an
external nature and external world. The spirit, however, (which thinks in
this moral organism) overrides and absorbs within itself the finitude
attaching to it as national spirit in its state and the state's temporal interests,
in the system of laws and usages. It rises to apprehend itself in its
essentiality. Such apprehension, however, still has the immanent limitedness
of the national spirit. But the spirit which thinks in universal history,
stripping off at the same time those limitations of the several national minds
and its own temporal restrictions, lays hold of its concrete universality, and
rises to apprehend the absolute mind, as the eternally actual truth in which
the contemplative reason enjoys freedom, while the necessity of nature and
the necessity of history are only ministrant to its revelation and the vessels
of its honour.
The strictly technical aspects of the Mind's elevation to God have been
spoken of in the Introduction to the Logic (cf. especially § 51, note). As
regards the starting-point of that elevation, Kant has on the whole adopted
the most correct, when he treats belief in God as proceeding from the
practical Reason. For that starting-point contains the material or content
which constitutes the content of the notion of God. But the true concrete
material is neither Being (as in the cosmological) nor mere action by design
(as in the physico-theological proof) but the Mind, the absolute
characteristic and function of which is effective reason, i.e. the self-
determining [pg 155] and self-realising notion itself,—Liberty. That the
elevation of subjective mind to God which these considerations give is by
Kant again deposed to a postulate—a mere “ought”—is the peculiar
perversity, formerly noticed, of calmly and simply reinstating as true and
valid that very antithesis of finitude, the supersession of which into truth is
the essence of that elevation.
As regards the “mediation” which, as it has been already shown (§ 192, cf.
§ 204 note), that elevation to God really involves, the point specially calling
for note is the “moment” of negation through which the essential content of
the starting-point is purged of its finitude so as to come forth free. This
factor, abstract in the formal treatment of logic, now gets its most concrete
interpretation. The finite, from which the start is now made, is the real
ethical self-consciousness. The negation through which that consciousness
raises its spirit to its truth, is the purification, actually accomplished in the
ethical world, whereby its conscience is purged of subjective opinion and its
will freed from the selfishness of desire. Genuine religion and genuine
religiosity only issue from the moral life: religion is that life rising to think,
i.e. becoming aware of the free universality of its concrete essence. Only
from the moral life and by the moral life is the Idea of God seen to be free
spirit: outside the ethical spirit therefore it is vain to seek for true religion
and religiosity.
Here then is the place to go more deeply into the reciprocal relations
between the state and religion, and [pg 156] in doing so to elucidate the
terminology which is familiar and current on the topic. It is evident and
apparent from what has preceded that moral life is the state retracted into its
inner heart and substance, while the state is the organisation and
actualisation of moral life; and that religion is the very substance of the
moral life itself and of the state. At this rate, the state rests on the ethical
sentiment, and that on the religious. If religion then is the consciousness of
“absolute” truth, then whatever is to rank as right and justice, as law and
duty, i.e. as true in the world of free will, can be so esteemed only as it is
participant in that truth, as it is subsumed under it and is its sequel. But if
the truly moral life is to be a sequel of religion, then perforce religion must
have the genuine content; i.e. the idea of God it knows must be the true and
real. The ethical life is the divine spirit as indwelling in self-consciousness,
as it is actually present in a nation and its individual members. This self-
consciousness retiring upon itself out of its empirical actuality and bringing
its truth to consciousness, has in its faith and in its conscience only what it
has consciously secured in its spiritual actuality. The two are inseparable:
there cannot be two kinds of conscience, one religious and another ethical,
differing from the former in body and value of truth. But in point of form,
i.e. for thought and knowledge—(and religion and ethical life belong to
intelligence and are a thinking and knowing)—the body of religious truth,
as the pure self-subsisting and therefore supreme truth, exercises a sanction
over the moral life which lies in empirical actuality. Thus for self-
consciousness religion is the “basis” of moral life and of the state. It has
been the monstrous blunder of our times to try to look upon these
inseparables as separable from one another, and even as mutually [pg 157]
indifferent. The view taken of the relationship of religion and the state has
been that, whereas the state had an independent existence of its own,
springing from some force and power, religion was a later addition,
something desirable perhaps for strengthening the political bulwarks, but
purely subjective in individuals:—or it may be, religion is treated as
something without effect on the moral life of the state, i.e. its reasonable
law and constitution which are based on a ground of their own.
As the inseparability of the two sides has been indicated, it may be worth
while to note the separation as it appears on the side of religion. It is
primarily a point of form: the attitude which self-consciousness takes to the
body of truth. So long as this body of truth is the very substance or
indwelling spirit of self-consciousness in its actuality, then self-
consciousness in this content has the certainty of itself and is free. But if
this present self-consciousness is lacking, then there may be created, in
point of form, a condition of spiritual slavery, even though the implicit
content of religion is absolute spirit. This great difference (to cite a specific
case) comes out within the Christian religion itself, even though here it is
not the nature-element in which the idea of God is embodied, and though
nothing of the sort even enters as a factor into its central dogma and sole
theme of a God who is known in spirit and in truth. And yet in Catholicism
this spirit of all truth is in actuality set in rigid opposition to the self-
conscious spirit. And, first of all, God is in the “host” presented to religious
adoration as an external thing. (In the Lutheran Church, on the contrary, the
host as such is not at first consecrated, but in the moment of enjoyment, i.e.
in the annihilation of its externality, and in the act of faith, i.e. in the free
self-certain spirit: only then is it consecrated and exalted [pg 158] to be
present God.) From that first and supreme status of externalisation flows
every other phase of externality,—of bondage, non-spirituality, and
superstition. It leads to a laity, receiving its knowledge of divine truth, as
well as the direction of its will and conscience from without and from
another order—which order again does not get possession of that
knowledge in a spiritual way only, but to that end essentially requires an
external consecration. It leads to the non-spiritual style of praying—partly
as mere moving of the lips, partly in the way that the subject foregoes his
right of directly addressing God, and prays others to pray—addressing his
devotion to miracle-working images, even to bones, and expecting miracles
from them. It leads, generally, to justification by external works, a merit
which is supposed to be gained by acts, and even to be capable of being
transferred to others. All this binds the spirit under an externalism by which
the very meaning of spirit is perverted and misconceived at its source, and
law and justice, morality and conscience, responsibility and duty are
corrupted at their root.
Thus set free, the content of religion assumes quite another shape. So long
as the form, i.e. our consciousness and subjectivity, lacked liberty, it
followed necessarily that self-consciousness was conceived as not
immanent in the ethical principles which religion embodies, and these
principles were set at such a distance as to seem to have true being only as
negative to actual self-consciousness. In this unreality ethical content gets
the name of Holiness. But once the divine spirit introduces itself into
actuality, and actuality emancipates itself to spirit, then what in the world
was a postulate of holiness is supplanted by the actuality of moral life.
Instead of the vow of chastity, marriage now ranks as the ethical relation;
and, therefore, as the highest on this side of humanity stands the family.
Instead of the vow of poverty (muddled up into a contradiction of assigning
merit to whosoever gives away goods to the poor, i.e. whosoever enriches
them) is the precept of action to acquire goods through one's own
intelligence [pg 160] and industry,—of honesty in commercial dealing, and
in the use of property,—in short moral life in the socio-economic sphere.
And instead of the vow of obedience, true religion sanctions obedience to
the law and the legal arrangements of the state—an obedience which is
itself the true freedom, because the state is a self-possessed, self-realising
reason—in short, moral life in the state. Thus, and thus only, can law and
morality exist. The precept of religion, “Give to Caesar what is Caesar's and
to God what is God's” is not enough: the question is to settle what is
Caesar's, what belongs to the secular authority: and it is sufficiently
notorious that the secular no less than the ecclesiastical authority have
claimed almost everything as their own. The divine spirit must
interpenetrate the entire secular life: whereby wisdom is concrete within it,
and it carries the terms of its own justification. But that concrete indwelling
is only the aforesaid ethical organisations. It is the morality of marriage as
against the sanctity of a celibate order;—the morality of economic and
industrial action against the sanctity of poverty and its indolence;—the
morality of an obedience dedicated to the law of the state as against the
sanctity of an obedience from which law and duty are absent and where
conscience is enslaved. With the growing need for law and morality and the
sense of the spirit's essential liberty, there sets in a conflict of spirit with the
religion of unfreedom. It is no use to organise political laws and
arrangements on principles of equity and reason, so long as in religion the
principle of unfreedom is not abandoned. A free state and a slavish religion
are incompatible. It is silly to suppose that we may try to allot them separate
spheres, under the impression that their diverse natures will maintain an
attitude of tranquillity one to another [pg 161] and not break out in
contradiction and battle. Principles of civil freedom can be but abstract and
superficial, and political institutions deduced from them must be, if taken
alone, untenable, so long as those principles in their wisdom mistake
religion so much as not to know that the maxims of the reason in actuality
have their last and supreme sanction in the religious conscience in
subsumption under the consciousness of “absolute” truth. Let us suppose
even that, no matter how, a code of law should arise, so to speak a priori,
founded on principles of reason, but in contradiction with an established
religion based on principles of spiritual unfreedom; still, as the duty of
carrying out the laws lies in the hands of individual members of the
government, and of the various classes of the administrative personnel, it is
vain to delude ourselves with the abstract and empty assumption that the
individuals will act only according to the letter or meaning of the law, and
not in the spirit of their religion where their inmost conscience and supreme
obligation lies. Opposed to what religion pronounces holy, the laws appear
something made by human hands: even though backed by penalties and
externally introduced, they could offer no lasting resistance to the
contradiction and attacks of the religious spirit. Such laws, however sound
their provisions may be, thus founder on the conscience, whose spirit is
different from the spirit of the laws and refuses to sanction them. It is
nothing but a modern folly to try to alter a corrupt moral organisation by
altering its political constitution and code of laws without changing the
religion,—to make a revolution without having made a reformation, to
suppose that a political constitution opposed to the old religion could live in
peace and harmony with it and its sanctities, and that stability could be
procured for the laws by external guarantees, [pg 162] e.g. so-called
“chambers,” and the power given them to fix the budget, &c. (cf. § 544
note). At best it is only a temporary expedient—when it is obviously too
great a task to descend into the depths of the religious spirit and to raise that
same spirit to its truth—to seek to separate law and justice from religion.
Those guarantees are but rotten bulwarks against the consciences of the
persons charged with administering the laws—among which laws these
guarantees are included. It is indeed the height and profanity of
contradiction to seek to bind and subject to the secular code the religious
conscience to which mere human law is a thing profane.
The perception had dawned upon Plato with great clearness of the gulf
which in his day had commenced to divide the established religion and the
political constitution, on one hand, from those deeper requirements which,
on the other hand, were made upon religion and politics by liberty which
had learnt to recognise its inner life. Plato gets hold of the thought that a
genuine constitution and a sound political life have their deeper foundation
on the Idea,—on the essentially and actually universal and genuine
principles of eternal righteousness. Now to see and ascertain what these are
is certainly the function and the business of philosophy. It is from this point
of view that Plato breaks out into the celebrated or notorious passage where
he makes Socrates emphatically state that philosophy and political power
must coincide, that the Idea must be regent, if the distress of nations is to
see its end. What Plato thus definitely set before his mind was that the Idea
—which implicitly indeed is the free self-determining thought—could not
get into consciousness save only in the form of a thought; that the substance
of the thought could only be true when set forth as a universal, and [pg 163]
as such brought to consciousness under its most abstract form.
To compare the Platonic standpoint in all its definiteness with the point of
view from which the relationship of state and religion is here regarded, the
notional differences on which everything turns must be recalled to mind.
The first of these is that in natural things their substance or genus is
different from their existence in which that substance is as subject: further
that this subjective existence of the genus is distinct from that which it gets,
when specially set in relief as genus, or, to put it simply, as the universal in
a mental concept or idea. This additional “individuality”—the soil on which
the universal and underlying principle freely and expressly exists,—is the
intellectual and thinking self. In the case of natural things their truth and
reality does not get the form of universality and essentiality through
themselves, and their “individuality” is not itself the form: the form is only
found in subjective thinking, which in philosophy gives that universal truth
and reality an existence of its own. In man's case it is otherwise: his truth
and reality is the free mind itself, and it comes to existence in his self-
consciousness. This absolute nucleus of man—mind intrinsically concrete
—is just this—to have the form (to have thinking) itself for a content. To
the height of the thinking consciousness of this principle Aristotle ascended
in his notion of the entelechy of thought, (which is νοῆσις τῆς νοήσεως),
thus surmounting the Platonic Idea (the genus, or essential being). But
thought always—and that on account of this very principle—contains the
immediate self-subsistence of subjectivity no less than it contains
universality; the genuine Idea of the intrinsically concrete mind is just as
essentially under the one of its terms (subjective consciousness) as under
the other [pg 164] (universality): and in the one as in the other it is the same
substantial content. Under the subjective form, however, fall feeling,
intuition, pictorial representation: and it is in fact necessary that in point of
time the consciousness of the absolute Idea should be first reached and
apprehended in this form: in other words, it must exist in its immediate
reality as religion, earlier than it does as philosophy. Philosophy is a later
development from this basis (just as Greek philosophy itself is later than
Greek religion), and in fact reaches its completion by catching and
comprehending in all its definite essentiality that principle of spirit which
first manifests itself in religion. But Greek philosophy could set itself up
only in opposition to Greek religion: the unity of thought and the
substantiality of the Idea could take up none but a hostile attitude to an
imaginative polytheism, and to the gladsome and frivolous humours of its
poetic creations. The form in its infinite truth, the subjectivity of mind,
broke forth at first only as a subjective free thinking, which was not yet
identical with the substantiality itself,—and thus this underlying principle
was not yet apprehended as absolute mind. Thus religion might appear as
first purified only through philosophy,—through pure self-existent thought:
but the form pervading this underlying principle—the form which
philosophy attacked—was that creative imagination.
§ 553. The notion of mind has its reality in the mind. If this reality in
identity with that notion is to exist as the consciousness of the absolute
Idea, then the necessary aspect is that the implicitly free intelligence be in
its actuality liberated to its notion, if that actuality is to be a vehicle worthy
of it. The subjective and the objective spirit are to be looked on as the road
on which this aspect of reality or existence rises to maturity.
[pg 169]
Sub-Section A. Art.
§ 558. For the objects of contemplation it has to produce, Art requires not
only an external given material—(under which are also included subjective
images and ideas), but—for the expression of spiritual truth—must use the
given forms of nature with a significance which art must divine and possess
(cf. § 411). Of all such forms the human is the highest and the true, because
only in it can the spirit have its corporeity and thus its visible expression.
§ 559. In such single shapes the “absolute” mind cannot be made explicit:
in and to art therefore the spirit is a limited natural spirit whose implicit
universality, when steps are taken to specify its fullness in detail, breaks up
into an indeterminate polytheism. With the essential restrictedness of its
content, Beauty in general goes no further than a penetration of the vision
or image by the spiritual principle,—something formal, so that the thought
embodied, or the idea, can, like the material which it uses to work in, be of
the most diverse and unessential kind, and still the work be something
beautiful and a work of art.
[pg 171]
§ 560. The one-sidedness of immediacy on the part of the Ideal involves the
opposite one-sidedness (§ 556) that it is something made by the artist. The
subject or agent is the mere technical activity: and the work of art is only
then an expression of the God, when there is no sign of subjective
particularity in it, and the net power of the indwelling spirit is conceived
and born into the world, without admixture and unspotted from its
contingency. But as liberty only goes as far as there is thought, the action
inspired with the fullness of this indwelling power, the artist's enthusiasm,
is like a foreign force under which he is bound and passive; the artistic
production has on its part the form of natural immediacy, it belongs to the
genius or particular endowment of the artist,—and is at the same time a
labour concerned with technical cleverness and mechanical externalities.
The work of art therefore is just as much a work due to free option, and the
artist is the master of the God.
§ 562. In another way the Idea and the sensuous figure it appears in are
incompatible; and that is where the infinite form, subjectivity, is not as in
the first extreme a mere superficial personality, but its inmost depth, and
God is known not as only seeking his form or satisfying himself in an
external form, but as only finding himself in himself, and thus giving
himself his adequate figure in the spiritual world alone. Romantic art gives
up the task of showing him as such in external form and by means of
beauty: it presents him as only condescending to appearance, and the divine
as the heart of hearts in an externality from which it always disengages
itself. Thus the external can here appear as contingent towards its
significance.
But with a further and deeper study, we see that the advent of art, in a
religion still in the bonds of sensuous externality, shows that such religion is
on the decline. At the very time it seems to give religion the supreme
glorification, expression and brilliancy, it has lifted the religion away over
its limitation. In the sublime divinity to which the work of art succeeds in
giving expression the artistic genius and the spectator find themselves at
home, with their personal sense and feeling, satisfied and liberated: to them
the vision and the consciousness of free spirit has been vouchsafed and
attained. Beautiful art, from its side, has thus performed the same service as
philosophy: it has purified the spirit from its thraldom. The older religion in
which the [pg 174] need of fine art, and just for that reason, is first
generated, looks up in its principle to an other-world which is sensuous and
unmeaning: the images adored by its devotees are hideous idols regarded as
wonder-working talismans, which point to the unspiritual objectivity of that
other world,—and bones perform a similar or even a better service than
such images. But even fine art is only a grade of liberation, not the supreme
liberation itself.—The genuine objectivity, which is only in the medium of
thought,—the medium in which alone the pure spirit is for the spirit, and
where the liberation is accompanied with reverence,—is still absent in the
sensuous beauty of the work of art, still more in that external, unbeautiful
sensuousness.
§ 563. Beautiful Art, like the religion peculiar to it, has its future in true
religion. The restricted value of the Idea passes utterly and naturally into the
universality identical with the infinite form;—the vision in which
consciousness has to depend upon the senses passes into a self-mediating
knowledge, into an existence which is itself knowledge,—into revelation.
Thus the principle which gives the Idea its content is that it embody free
intelligence, and as “absolute” spirit it is for the spirit.
[pg 175]
Sub-Section B. Revealed Religion . 172
If we recollect how intricate is the knowledge of the divine Mind for those
who are not content with the homely pictures of faith but proceed to
thought,—at first only “rationalising” reflection, but afterwards, as in duty
bound, to speculative comprehension, it may almost create surprise that so
many, and especially theologians whose vocation it is to deal with these
Ideas, have tried to get off their task by gladly accepting anything offered
them for this behoof. And nothing serves better to shirk it than to adopt the
conclusion that man knows nothing of God. To know what God as spirit is
—to apprehend this accurately and distinctly in thoughts—requires careful
and thorough speculation. It includes, in its fore-front, the propositions:
God is God only so far as he knows himself: his self-knowledge is, further,
his self-consciousness in man, and man's knowledge of God, which
proceeds to man's self-knowledge in God.—See the profound elucidation of
these propositions in the work from which they are taken: Aphorisms on
Knowing and Not-knowing, &c., by C. F. G—l.: Berlin 1829.
§ 566. In this separating, the form parts from the content: and in the form
the different functions of the notion part off into special spheres or media,
in each of which the absolute spirit exhibits itself; (α) as eternal content,
abiding self-centred, even in its manifestation; (β) as distinction of the
eternal essence from its manifestation, which by this difference becomes the
phenomenal world into which the content enters; (γ) as infinite return, and
reconciliation with the eternal being, of the world it gave away—the
withdrawal of the eternal from the phenomenal into the unity of its fullness.
§ 570. (2) This objective totality of the divine man who is the Idea of the
spirit is the implicit presupposition for the finite immediacy of the single
subject. For such subject therefore it is at first an Other, an object [pg 179]
of contemplating vision,—but the vision of implicit truth, through which
witness of the spirit in him, he, on account of his immediate nature, at first
characterised himself as nought and wicked. But, secondly, after the
example of his truth, by means of the faith on the unity (in that example
implicitly accomplished) of universal and individual essence, he is also the
movement to throw off his immediacy, his natural man and self-will, to
close himself in unity with that example (who is his implicit life) in the pain
of negativity, and thus to know himself made one with the essential Being.
Thus the Being of Beings (3) through this mediation brings about its own
indwelling in self-consciousness, and is the actual presence of the essential
and self-subsisting spirit who is all in all.
§ 572. This science is the unity of Art and Religion. Whereas the vision-
method of Art, external in point of form, is but subjective production and
shivers the substantial content into many separate shapes, and whereas
Religion, with its separation into parts, opens it out in mental picture, and
mediates what is thus opened out; Philosophy not merely keeps them
together to make a total, but even unifies them into the simple spiritual
vision, and then in that raises them to self-conscious thought. Such
consciousness is thus the intelligible unity (cognised by thought) of art and
religion, in which the diverse elements in the content are cognised as
necessary, and this necessary as free.
But if those who give out that a certain philosophy is Pantheism, are unable
and unwilling to see this—for it is just to see the notion that they refuse—
they should before everything have verified the alleged fact that any one
philosopher, or any one man, had really ascribed substantial or objective
and inherent reality to all things and regarded them as God:—that such an
idea had ever come into the hand of any body but themselves. This
allegation I will further elucidate in this exoteric discussion: and the only
way to do so is to set down the evidence. If we want to take so-called
Pantheism [pg 186] in its most poetical, most sublime, or if you will, its
grossest shape, we must, as is well known, consult the oriental poets: and
the most copious delineations of it are found in Hindoo literature. Amongst
the abundant resources open to our disposal on this topic, I select—as the
most authentic statement accessible—the Bhagavat-Gita, and amongst its
effusions, prolix and reiterative ad nauseam, some of the most telling
passages. In the 10th Lesson (in Schlegel, p. 162) Krishna says of himself173:
—“I am the self, seated in the hearts of all beings. I am the beginning and
the middle and the end also of all beings ... I am the beaming sun amongst
the shining ones, and the moon among the lunar mansions.... Amongst the
Vedas I am the Sâma-Veda: I am mind amongst the senses: I am
consciousness in living beings. And I am Sankara (Siva) among the Rudras,
... Meru among the high-topped mountains, ... the Himalaya among the
firmly-fixed (mountains).... Among beasts I am the lord of beasts.... Among
letters I am the letter A.... I am the spring among the seasons.... I am also
that which is the seed of all things: there is nothing moveable or
immoveable which can exist without me.”
Even in these totally sensuous delineations, Krishna (and we must not
suppose there is, besides Krishna, still God, or a God besides; as he said
before he was Siva, or Indra, so it is afterwards said that Brahma too is in
him) makes himself out to be—not everything, but only—the most
excellent of everything. Everywhere there is a distinction drawn between
external, unessential existences, and one essential amongst them, which he
is. Even when, at the beginning [pg 187] of the passage, he is said to be the
beginning, middle, and end of living things, this totality is distinguished
from the living things themselves as single existences. Even such a picture
which extends deity far and wide in its existence cannot be called
pantheism: we must rather say that in the infinitely multiple empirical
world, everything is reduced to a limited number of essential existences, to
a polytheism. But even what has been quoted shows that these very
substantialities of the externally-existent do not retain the independence
entitling them to be named Gods; even Siva, Indra, &c. melt into the one
Krishna.
This reduction is more expressly made in the following scene (7th Lesson,
p. 7 sqq.). Krishna says: “I am the producer and the destroyer of the whole
universe. There is nothing else higher than myself; all this is woven upon
me, like numbers of pearls upon a thread. I am the taste in water;... I am the
light of the sun and the moon; I am ‘Om’ in all the Vedas.... I am life in all
beings.... I am the discernment of the discerning ones.... I am also the
strength of the strong.” Then he adds: “The whole universe deluded by
these three states of mind developed from the qualities [sc. goodness,
passion, darkness] does not know me who am beyond them and
inexhaustible: for this delusion of mine,” [even the Maya is his, nothing
independent], “developed from the qualities is divine and difficult to
transcend. Those cross beyond this delusion who resort to me alone.” Then
the picture gathers itself up in a simple expression: “At the end of many
lives, the man possessed of knowledge approaches me, (believing) that
Vasudeva is everything. Such a high-souled mind is very hard to find.
Those who are deprived of knowledge by various desires approach other
divinities... Whichever form of deity one worships with [pg 188] faith, from
it he obtains the beneficial things he desires really given by me. But the
fruit thus obtained by those of little judgment is perishable.... The
undiscerning ones, not knowing my transcendent and inexhaustible essence,
than which there is nothing higher, think me who am unperceived to have
become perceptible.”
This “All,” which Krishna calls himself, is not, any more than the Eleatic
One, and the Spinozan Substance, the Every-thing. This every-thing, rather,
the infinitely-manifold sensuous manifold of the finite is in all these
pictures, but defined as the “accidental,” without essential being of its very
own, but having its truth in the substance, the One which, as different from
that accidental, is alone the divine and God. Hindooism however has the
higher conception of Brahma, the pure unity of thought in itself, where the
empirical everything of the world, as also those proximate substantialities,
called Gods, vanish. On that account Colebrooke and many others have
described the Hindoo religion as at bottom a Monotheism. That this
description is not incorrect is clear from these short citations. But so little
concrete is this divine unity—spiritual as its idea of God is—so powerless
its grip, so to speak—that Hindooism, with a monstrous inconsistency, is
also the maddest of polytheisms. But the idolatry of the wretched Hindoo,
when he adores the ape, or other creature, is still a long way from that
wretched fancy of a Pantheism, to which everything is God, and God
everything. Hindoo monotheism moreover is itself an example how little
comes of mere monotheism, if the Idea of God is not deeply determinate in
itself. For that unity, if it be intrinsically abstract and therefore empty, tends
of itself to let whatever is concrete, outside it—be it as a lot of Gods or as
secular, empirical individuals—keep its independence. That pantheism [pg
189] indeed—on the shallow conception of it—might with a show of logic
as well be called a monotheism: for if God, as it says, is identical with the
world, then as there is only one world there would be in that pantheism only
one God. Perhaps the empty numerical unity must be predicated of the
world: but such abstract predication of it has no further special interest; on
the contrary, a mere numerical unity just means that its content is an infinite
multeity and variety of finitudes. But it is that delusion with the empty
unity, which alone makes possible and induces the wrong idea of
pantheism. It is only the picture—floating in the indefinite blue—of the
world as one thing, the all, that could ever be considered capable of
combining with God: only on that assumption could philosophy be
supposed to teach that God is the world: for if the world were taken as it is,
as everything, as the endless lot of empirical existence, then it would hardly
have been even held possible to suppose a pantheism which asserted of
such stuff that it is God.
[pg 190]
I refrain from accumulating further examples of the religious and poetic
conceptions which it is customary to call pantheistic. Of the philosophies to
which that name is given, the Eleatic, or Spinozist, it has been [pg 191]
remarked earlier (§ 50, note) that so far are they from identifying God with
the world and making him finite, that in these systems this “everything” has
no truth, and that we should rather call them monotheistic, or, in relation to
the popular idea of the world, acosmical. [pg 192] They are most accurately
called systems which apprehend the Absolute only as substance. Of the
oriental, especially the Mohammedan, modes of envisaging God, we may
rather say that they represent the Absolute as the utterly universal genus
which dwells in the species or existences, but dwells so potently that these
existences have no actual reality. The fault of all these modes of thought
and systems is that they stop short of defining substance as subject and as
mind.
These systems and modes of pictorial conception originate from the one
need common to all philosophies and all religions of getting an idea of God,
and, secondly, of the relationship of God and the world. (In philosophy it is
specially made out that the determination of God's nature determines his
relations with the world.) The “reflective” understanding begins by
rejecting all systems and modes of conception, which, whether they spring
from heart, imagination or speculation, express the interconnexion of God
and the world: and in order to have God pure in faith or consciousness, he is
as essence parted from appearance, as infinite from the finite. But, after this
partition, the conviction arises also that the appearance has a relation to the
essence, the finite to the infinite, and so on: and thus arises the question of
reflection as to the nature of this relation. It is in the reflective form that the
whole difficulty of the affair lies, and that causes this relation to be called
incomprehensible by the agnostic. The close of philosophy is not the place,
even in a general exoteric discussion, to waste a word on what a “notion”
means. But as the view taken of this relation is closely connected with the
view taken of philosophy generally and with all imputations against it, we
may still add the remark that though philosophy certainly has to do with
unity in general, it is not however [pg 193] with abstract unity, mere
identity, and the empty absolute, but with concrete unity (the notion), and
that in its whole course it has to do with nothing else;—that each step in its
advance is a peculiar term or phase of this concrete unity, and that the
deepest and last expression of unity is the unity of absolute mind itself.
Would-be judges and critics of philosophy might be recommended to
familiarise themselves with these phases of unity and to take the trouble to
get acquainted with them, at least to know so much that of these terms there
are a great many, and that amongst them there is great variety. But they
show so little acquaintance with them—and still less take trouble about it—
that, when they hear of unity—and relation ipso facto implies unity—they
rather stick fast at quite abstract indeterminate unity, and lose sight of the
chief point of interest—the special mode in which the unity is qualified.
Hence all they can say about philosophy is that dry identity is its principle
and result, and that it is the system of identity. Sticking fast to the
undigested thought of identity, they have laid hands on, not the concrete
unity, the notion and content of philosophy, but rather its reverse. In the
philosophical field they proceed, as in the physical field the physicist; who
also is well aware that he has before him a variety of sensuous properties
and matters—or usually matters alone, (for the properties get transformed
into matters also for the physicist)—and that these matters (elements) also
stand in relation to one another. But the question is, Of what kind is this
relation? Every peculiarity and the whole difference of natural things,
inorganic and living, depend solely on the different modes of this unity. But
instead of ascertaining these different modes, the ordinary physicist
(chemist included) takes up only one, the most external and the worst, viz.
[pg 194] composition, applies only it in the whole range of natural
structures, which he thus renders for ever inexplicable.
§ 574. This notion of philosophy is the self-thinking Idea, the truth aware of
itself (§ 236),—the logical system, but with the signification that it is
universality approved and certified in concrete content as in its actuality. In
this way the science has gone back to its beginning: its result is the logical
system but as a spiritual principle: out of the presupposing judgment, in
which the notion was only implicit and the beginning an immediate,—and
thus out of the appearance which it had there—it has risen into its pure
principle and thus also into its proper medium.
§ 575. It is this appearing which originally gives the motive of the further
development. The first appearance is formed by the syllogism, which is
based on the Logical system as starting-point, with Nature for the middle
term which couples the Mind with it. The Logical principle turns to Nature
and Nature to Mind. Nature, standing between the Mind and its essence,
sunders itself, not indeed to extremes of finite abstraction, nor itself to
something away from them and independent,—which, as other than they,
only serves as a link between them: for the syllogism is in the Idea and
Nature is essentially defined as a transition-point and negative factor, and as
implicitly the Idea. Still the mediation of the notion has the external form of
transition, and the science of Nature presents itself as the course of
necessity, so that it is only in the one extreme that the liberty of the notion is
explicit as a self-amalgamation.
§ 577. The third syllogism is the Idea of philosophy, which has self-
knowing reason, the absolutely-universal, for its middle term: a middle,
which divides itself into Mind and Nature, making the former its
presupposition, as process of the Idea's subjective activity, and the latter its
universal extreme, as process of the objectively and implicitly existing Idea.
The self-judging of the Idea into its two appearances (§§ 575, 576)
characterises both as its (the self-knowing reason's) manifestations: and in it
there is a unification of the two aspects:—it is the nature of the fact, the
notion, which causes the movement and development, yet this same
movement is equally the action of cognition. The eternal Idea, in full
fruition of its essence, eternally sets itself to work, engenders and enjoys
itself as absolute Mind.
Ἡ δὲ νόησις ἡ καθ᾽ αὑτὴν τοῦ καθ᾽ αὑτὸ ἀρίστου, καὶ ἡ μάλιστα τοῦ μάλιστα.
Αὑτὸν δὲ νοεῖ ὁ νοῦς κατὰ μετάληψιν τοῦ νοητοῦ νοητὸς γὰρ γίγνεται θιγγάνων καὶ
νοῶν, ὥστε ταὐτὸν νοῦς καὶ νοητόν. Τὸ γὰρ δεκτικὸν τοῦ νοητοῦ καὶ τῆς οὐσίας
νοῦς. Ἐνεργεῖ δὲ ἔχων. Ὥστ᾽ ἐκεῖνο μᾶλλον τούτου ὂ δοκεῖ ὁ νοῦς θεῖον ἔχειν, καὶ
ἡ θεωρία τὸ ἥδιστον καὶ ἄριστον. Εἰ οὖν οὕτως εὖ ἔχει, ὡς ἡμεῖς ποτέ, ὁ θεὸς ἀεί,
θαυμαστόν; εἰ δὲ μᾶλλον, ἔτι θαυμασιώτερον. Ἔχει δὲ ὡδί. Καὶ ζωὴ δέ γε ὑπάρχει; ἡ
γὰρ νοῦ ἐνέργεια ζωή, ἐκεῖνος δὲ ἡ ἐνέργεια; ἐνέργεια δὲ ἡ καθ᾽ αὑτὴν ἐκείνου ζωὴ
ἀρίστη καὶ ἀΐδιος. Φαμὲν δὲ τὸν θεὸν εἶναι ζῷον ἀΐδιον ἄριστον, ὥστε ζωὴ αἰὼν
συνεχὴς καὶ ἀΐδιος ὑπάρχει τῷ θεῷ; τοῦτο γὰρ ὁ θεός. (ARIST. Met. XI. 7.)
[pg 199]
Index.
Abstraction, 74.
Alphabets, 81.
Altruism, 57.
Appetite, 53.
Atheism, 183.
Athens, cxxx.
Beauty, 169.
Biography, 151.
Boëthius, l.
Bravery, cxcix.
Budget, 144.
Categories, lx.
Catholicism, 157.
Choice, 98.
Cognition, 64.
Contract, 108.
Corporation, 130.
Dante, cxxxiv.
Democracy, 141.
Development, 60.
Duty, cxiv, cxix, cxxi seqq., cxxxi, cxxxix, 97, 104, 116.
Economics, 122.
Education, xcii, cxxxvii, 11.
Egoism, 55.
Eleaticism, 190.
England, 143.
Epistemology, ciii.
Equity, xxxi.
[pg 200]
Estates, 123.
Ethics, xv, xix, xxx seqq., xcv, cxiii seqq., cxc seqq., 113 seqq.
Experience, 51.
Faith, cvii.
Fame, 153.
Finance, 144.
Finitude, 8.
Fraud, 110.
Fries, clxxix.
Goodness, 115.
Government, 137;
forms of, 141.
Happiness, 99.
Holiness, 159.
Honour, 124.
Imagination, 72.
Immaterialism, clii, 12, 45.
Impulse, 95.
Insanity, 37.
Intention, 114.
Intuition, 67.
Irony, 179.
Jelaleddin-Rumi, 189.
Judgment, 89.
Jung-Stilling, clxii.
Juries, 128.
Kant (I.), xv, lxiv, lxxi, xcvi, cvii, cxxviii, clxxxviii, 20, 48, 51, 63, 154.
Kieser, clxiii.
Knowledge, cv, cxxxv, cxli, 64.
Labour, 123.
Laplace, clxiv.
Legislation, 125.
Life, 13.
Lutheranism, 157.
Macchiavelli, clxxx.
Manifestation, 7.
Manners, 104.
Mesmer, clxi.
[pg 201]
Mnemonics, 85.
Monarchy, 139.
Monasticism, 159.
Monotheism, 188.
Napoleon, 19.
Nemesis, 174.
Observation, lxxxix.
Pain, 6, 94.
Parliament, 142.
Passion, 95.
Peasantry, cci.
Perception, 67.
Phrenology, 35.
Physiology, lxxxi, c.
Pinel, 39.
Police, 130.
Porphyry, xx.
Practice, 92.
Protestantism, 166.
Psychiatry, 33.
Psychology, xxii, xxiv, lii seqq., lxiii, lxxxvi, xcv, cxvii, 4, 58, 63.
Races, 16.
Recollection, 70.
Reinhold, 49.
Responsibility, 114.
Revelation, 7, 175.
Romances, 151:
romantic art, 172.
Schelling, clxi.
Schindler, clxiii.
Sex, 18.
Sleep, 18.
Sociology, xxiii.
Somnambulism, 30.
Spiritualism, clxii.
State, xxxii seqq., clxxvi, clxxxiii, 131 seqq.
[pg 202]
Superstition, 158.
Syllogism, 90.
Sympathy, clv.
Theology, 155.
Tholuck, 191.
Universalising, cxxviii.
Utilitarianism, cxxxvi.
Value, 109.
Virtues, cxxxi, cxcviii, 120.
Wartburg, clxxix.
Welfare, 114.
Wolff, lxxiii.
Wrong, 109.
Würtemberg, clxxxv.
Footnotes
1.
Plato, Rep. 527.
2.
The prospectus of the System of Synthetic Philosophy is dated
1860. Darwin's Origin of Species is 1859. But such ideas, both in
Mr. Spencer and others, are earlier than Darwin's book.
3.
Hegel's Verhältniss, the supreme category of what is called
actuality: where object is necessitated by outside object.
4.
Cf. Herbart, Werke (ed. Kehrbach), iv. 372. This consciousness
proper is what Leibniz called « Apperception, » la connaissance
réflexive de l'état intérieur (Nouveaux Essais).
5.
Herbart, Werke, vi. 55 (ed. Kehrbach).
6.
p. 59 (§ 440).
7.
p. 63 (§ 440).
8.
These remarks refer to four out of the five Herbartian ethical
ideas. See also Leibniz, who (in 1693, De Notionibus juris et
justitiae) had given the following definitions: “Caritas est
benevolentia universalis. Justitia est caritas sapientis. Sapientia
est scientia felicitatis.” The jus naturae has three grades: the
lowest, jus strictum; the second, aequitas (or caritas, in the
narrower sense); and the highest, pietas, which is honeste, i.e. pie
vivere.
9.
To which the Greek πόλις, the Latin civitas or respublica, were
only approximations. Hegel is not writing a history. If he were, it
would be necessary for him to point out how far the individual
instance, e.g. Rome, or Prussia, corresponded to its Idea.
10.
Shakespeare's phrase, as in Othello, iii. 2; Lover's Complaint, v.
24.
11.
Iliad, xii. 243.
12.
See Hegel's Logic, pp. 257 seq.
13.
See p. 153 (§ 550).
14.
Cf. Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel, chaps. xviii, xxvi.
15.
As stated in p. 167 (Encycl. § 554). Cf. Phenom. d. Geistes, cap.
vii, which includes the Religion of Art, and the same point of
view is explicit in the first edition of the Encyclopaedia.
16.
Philosophie der Religion (Werke, xi. 5).
17.
Hegel, Phenomenologie des Geistes (Werke, ii. 545). The
meeting-ground of the Greek spirit, as it passed through Rome,
with Christianity.
18.
Ib., p. 584.
19.
Phenomenologie des Geistes (Werke, ii. 572). Thus Hegelian
idealism claims to be the philosophical counterpart of the central
dogma of Christianity.
20.
From the old Provençal Lay of Boëthius.
21.
It is the doctrine of the intellectus agens, or in actu; the actus
purus of the Schoolmen.
22.
Einleitung in die Philosophie, §§ 1, 2.
23.
Psychologie als Wissenschaft, Vorrede.
24.
Einleitung in die Philosophie, §§ 11, 12.
25.
Einleitung in die Philosophie, § 18: cf. Werke, ed. Kehrbach, v.
108.
26.
Cf. Plato's remarks on the problem in the word Self-control.
Republ. 430-1.
27.
Lehrbuch der Psychologie, §§ 202, 203.
28.
Allgemeine Metaphysik, Vorrede.
29.
Hauptpunkte der Metaphysik (1806), § 13.
30.
Werke, ed. Kehrbach (Ueber die Möglichkeit, &c), v. 96.
31.
Ibid., p. 100.
32.
One might almost fancy Herbart was translating into a general
philosophic thesis the words in which Goethe has described how
he overcame a real trouble by transmuting it into an ideal shape,
e.g. Wahrheit und Dichtung, cap. xii.
33.
Herbart's language is almost identical with Hegel's: Encycl. § 389
(p. 12). Cf. Spencer, Psychology, i. 192. “Feelings are in all cases
the materials out of which the superior tracts of consciousness
and intellect are evolved.”
34.
Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel, ch. xvii.
35.
Psychologia Empirica, § 29.
36.
As is also the case with Herbart's metaphysical reality of the Soul.
37.
Human Nature, vii. 2. “Pleasure, Love, and appetite, which is also
called desire, are divers names for divers considerations of the
same thing....” Deliberation is (ch. xii. 1) the “alternate succession
of appetite and fears.”
38.
Eth. ii. 48 Schol.
39.
Eth. ii. 43 Schol.: cf. 49 Schol.
40.
This wide scope of thinking (cogitatio, penser) is at least as old as
the Cartesian school: and should be kept in view, as against a
tendency to narrow its range to the mere intellect.
41.
e.g. Analysis of the Human Mind, ch. xxiv. “Attention is but
another name for the interesting character of the idea;” ch. xix.
“Desire and the idea of a pleasurable sensation are convertible
terms.”
42.
As Mr. Spencer says (Psychology, i. 141), “Objective psychology
can have no existence as such without borrowing its data from
subjective psychology.”
43.
The same failure to note that experiment is valuable only where
general points of view are defined, is a common fault in biology.
44.
Münsterberg, Aufgaben und Methoden der Psychologie, p. 144.
45.
Lehrbuch der Psychologie, § 54 (2nd ed.), or § 11 (1st ed.).
46.
See p. 11 (§ 387).
47.
Cf. Nietzsche, Also sprach Zarathustra, i. 43. “There is more
reason in thy body than in thy best wisdom.”
48.
This language is very characteristic of the physicists who dabble
in psychology and imagine they are treading in the steps of Kant,
if not even verifying what they call his guesswork: cf. Ziehen,
Physiol. Psychologie, 2nd ed. p. 212. “In every case there is given
us only the psychical series of sensations and their memory-
images, and it is only a universal hypothesis if we assume beside
this psychical series a material series standing in causal relation to
it.... The material series is not given equally originally with the
psychical.”
49.
It is the same radical feature of consciousness which is thus noted
by Mr. Spencer, Psychology, i. 475. “Perception and sensation are
ever tending to exclude each other but never succeed.”
“Cognition and feeling are antithetical and inseparable.”
“Consciousness continues only in virtue of this conflict.” Cf.
Plato's resolution in the Philebus of the contest between
intelligence and feeling (pleasure).
50.
It is the quasi-Aristotelian ἀπαγωγή, defined as the step from one
proposition to another, the knowledge of which will set the first
proposition in a full light.
51.
Grundlage des Naturrechts, § 5.
52.
System der Sittenlehre, § 8, iv.
53.
Even though religion (according to Kant) conceive them as divine
commands.
54.
Cf. Hegel's Werke, vii. 2, p. 236 (Lecture-note on § 410). “We
must treat as utterly empty the fancy of those who suppose that
properly man should have no organic body,” &c.; and see p. 159
of the present work.
55.
Criticism of Pure Reason, Architectonic.
56.
Spencer, Psychology, i. 291: “Mind can be understood only by
observing how mind is evolved.”
57.
Cf. Spencer, Principles of Ethics, i. 339: “The ethical sentiment
proper is, in the great mass of cases, scarcely discernible.”
58.
Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel, p. 143.
59.
Windelband (W.), Präludien (1884), p. 288.
60.
Cf. Plato, Republic, p. 486.
61.
Human Nature: Morals, Part III.
62.
Emotion and Will, ch. xv. § 23.
63.
It is characteristic of the Kantian doctrine to absolutise the
conception of Duty and make it express the essence of the whole
ethical idea.
64.
Which are still, as the Socialist Fourier says, states of social
incoherence, specially favourable to falsehood.
65.
Rechtsphilosophie, § 4.
66.
Cf. Schelling, ii. 12: “There are no born sons of freedom.”
67.
Simmel (G.), Einleitung in die Moralwissenschaft, i. 184.
68.
Jenseits von Gut und Böse, p. 225.
69.
Aristot. Polit. i. 6.
70.
Plato, Phaedo.
71.
Carus, Psyche, p. 1.
72.
See Arist., Anal. Post. ii. 19 (ed. Berl. 100, a. 10).
73.
Cf. The Logic of Hegel, notes &c., p. 421.
74.
“Omnia individua corpora quamvis diversis gradibus animata
sunt.” Eth. ii. 13. schol.
75.
Nanna (1848): Zendavesta (1851): Ueber die Seelenfrage (1861).
76.
Described by S. as the rise from mere physical cause to
physiological stimulus (Reiz), to psychical motive.
77.
Infra, p. 12.
78.
Aristot., De Anima, i. c. 4, 5.
79.
Wilhelm Meister's Wanderjahre, i. 10.
80.
Wilhelm Meister's Wanderjahre, iv. 18.
81.
Works like Preyer's Seele des Kindes illustrate this aspect of
mental evolution; its acquirement of definite and correlated
functions.
82.
Cf. the end of Caleb Balderstone (in The Bride of Lammermoor):
“With a fidelity sometimes displayed by the canine race, but
seldom by human beings, he pined and died.”
83.
See Windischmann's letters in Briefe von und an Hegel.
84.
Cf. Prolegomena to the Study of Hegel, chaps. xii-xiv.
85.
Kieser's Tellurismus is, according to Schopenhauer, “the fullest
and most thorough text-book of Animal Magnetism.”
86.
Cf. Fichte, Nachgelassene Werke, iii. 295 (Tagebuch über den
animalischen Magnetismus, 1813), and Schopenhauer, Der Wille
in der Natur.
87.
Bernheim: La suggestion domine toute l'histoire de l'humanité.
88.
An instance from an unexpected quarter, in Eckermann's
conversations with Goethe: “In my young days I have
experienced cases enough, where on lonely walks there came
over me a powerful yearning for a beloved girl, and I thought of
her so long till she actually came to meet me.” (Conversation of
Oct. 7, 1827.)
89.
Gleichsam in einer Vorwelt, einer diese Welt schaffenden Welt
(Nachgelassene Werke, iii. 321).
90.
Selbst-bewusstsein is not self-consciousness, in the vulgar sense
of brooding over feelings and self: but consciousness which is
active and outgoing, rather than receptive and passive. It is
practical, as opposed to theoretical.
91.
The more detailed exposition of this Phenomenology of Mind is
given in the book with that title: Hegel's Werke, ii. pp. 71-316.
92.
System der Sittlichkeit, p. 15 (see Essay V).
93.
Hegel's Werke, viii. 313, and cf. the passage quoted in my Logic
of Hegel, notes, pp. 384, 385.
94.
Hegel's Briefe, i. 15.
95.
Kritik der Verfassung Deutschlands, edited by G. Mollat (1893).
Parts of this were already given by Haym and Rosenkranz. The
same editor has also in this year published, though not quite in
full, Hegel's System der Sittlichkeit, to which reference is made in
what follows.
96.
In which some may find a prophecy of the effects of “blood and
iron” in 1866.
97.
Die Absolute Regierung: in the System der Sittlichkeit, p. 32: cf.
p. 55. Hegel himself compares it to Fichte's Ephorate.
98.
Die Absolute Regierung, l.c. pp. 37, 38.
99.
Some idea of his meaning may perhaps be gathered by
comparison with passages in Wilhelm Meister's Wanderjahre, ii.
1, 2.
100.
Kritik der Verfassung, p. 20.
101.
In some respects Bacon's attitude in the struggle between royalty
and parliament may be compared.
102.
Just as Schopenhauer, on the contrary, always says moralisch—
never sittlich.
103.
Grey (G.), Journals of two Expeditions of Discovery in North-
West and Western Australia, ii. 220.
104.
With some variation of ownership, perhaps, according to the
prevalence of so-called matriarchal or patriarchal households.
105.
Cf. the custom in certain tribes which names the father after his
child: as if the son first gave his father legitimate position in
society.
106.
System der Sittlichkeit, p. 8.
107.
Aufhebung (positive) as given in absolute Sittlichkeit.
108.
System der Sittlichkeit, p. 15.
109.
This phraseology shows the influence of Schelling, with whom he
was at this epoch associated. See Prolegomena to the Study of
Hegel, ch. xiv.
110.
Cf. the intermediate function assigned (see above, p. clxxxiii) to
the priests and the aged.
111.
System der Sittlichkeit, p. 19.
112.
See infra, p. 156.
113.
Wordsworth's Laodamia.
114.
“For it's Tommy this, an' Tommy that, an' ‘Chuck him out, the
brute!’
But it's ‘Saviour of 'is country’ when the guns begin to shoot.”
115.
“I can assure you,” said Werner (the merchant), “that I never
reflected on the State in my life. My tolls, charges and dues I have
paid for no other reason than that it was established usage.” (Wilh.
Meisters Lehrjahre, viii. 2.)
116.
System der Sittlichkeit, p. 40.
117.
System der Sittlichkeit, p. 65.
118.
Ibid. p. 46.
119.
Natürliche Seele.
120.
Natürliche Qualitäten.
121.
Empfindung.
122.
Die fühlende Seele.
123.
Plato had a better idea of the relation of prophecy generally to the
state of sober consciousness than many moderns, who supposed
that the Platonic language on the subject of enthusiasm authorised
their belief in the sublimity of the revelations of somnambulistic
vision. Plato says in the Timaeus (p. 71), “The author of our being
so ordered our inferior parts that they too might obtain a measure
of truth, and in the liver placed their oracle (the power of
divination by dreams). And herein is a proof that God has given
the art of divination, not to the wisdom, but, to the foolishness of
man; for no man when in his wits attains prophetic truth and
inspiration; but when he receives the inspired word, either his
intelligence is enthralled by sleep, or he is demented by some
distemper or possession (enthusiasm).” Plato very correctly notes
not merely the bodily conditions on which such visionary
knowledge depends, and the possibility of the truth of the dreams,
but also the inferiority of them to the reasonable frame of mind.
124.
Selbstgefühl.
125.
Gewohnheit.
126.
Die wirkliche Seele.
127.
Das Bewußtsein als solches: (a) Das sinnliche Bewußtsein.
128.
Wahrnehmung.
129.
Der Verstand.
130.
Selbstbewußtsein.
131.
Die Begierde.
132.
Das anerkennende Selbstbewußtsein.
133.
Die Vernunft.
134.
Der Geist.
135.
Die Intelligenz.
136.
Anschauung.
137.
Vorstellung.
138.
Die Erinnerung.
139.
Die Einbildungskraft.
140.
Phantasie.
141.
Gedächtniß.
142.
Auswendiges.
143.
Inwendiges.
144.
Das Denken.
145.
Der praktische Geist.
146.
Der praktische Gefühl.
147.
Der Triebe und die Willkühr.
148.
Die Glückseligkeit.
149.
Der freie Geist.
150.
Gesess.
151.
Sitte.
152.
Das Recht.
153.
Moralität.
154.
Naturrecht.
155.
Moralität.
156.
Der Vorsatz.
157.
That.
158.
Handlung.
159.
Die Absicht und das Wohl.
160.
Das Gute und das Böse.
161.
Die Sittlichkeit.
162.
Die bürgerliche Gesellschaft.
163.
Das System der Bedürfnisse.
164.
Die Rechtspflege.
165.
Geseß.
166.
Die Polizei und die Corporation.
167.
Inneres Staatsrecht.
168.
Das äußere Staatsrecht.
169.
Die Weltgeschichte.
170.
Weltweisheit.
171.
Der absolute Geist.
172.
Die geoffenbarte Religion.
173.
[The citation given by Hegel from Schlegel's translation is here
replaced by the version (in one or two points different) in the
Sacred Books of the East, vol. viii.]
174.
In order to give a clearer impression of it, I cannot refrain from
quoting a few passages, which may at the same time give some
indication of the marvellous skill of Rückert, from whom they are
taken, as a translator. [For Rückert's verses a version is here
substituted in which I have been kindly helped by Miss May
Kendall.]
III.
V.
IX.
I'll tell thee how from out the dust God moulded man,—
Because the breath of Love He breathed into his clay:
I'll tell thee why the spheres their whirling paths began,—
They mirror to God's throne Love's glory day by day:
I'll tell thee why the morning winds blow o'er the grove,—
It is to bid Love's roses bloom abundantly:
I'll tell thee why the night broods deep the earth above,—
Love's bridal tent to deck with sacred canopy:
All riddles of the earth dost thou desire to prove?—
To every earthly riddle is Love alone the key.
XV.
In this poetry, which soars over all that is external and sensuous,
who would recognise the prosaic ideas current about so-called
pantheism—ideas which let the divine sink to the external and the
sensuous? The copious extracts which Tholuck, in his work
Anthology from the Eastern Mystics, gives us from the poems of
Jelaleddin and others, are made from the very point of view now
under discussion. In his Introduction, Herr Tholuck proves how
profoundly his soul has caught the note of mysticism; and there,
too, he points out the characteristic traits of its oriental phase, in
distinction from that of the West and Christendom. With all their
divergence, however, they have in common the mystical
character. The conjunction of Mysticism with so-called
Pantheism, as he says (p. 53), implies that inward quickening of
soul and spirit which inevitably tends to annihilate that external
Everything, which Pantheism is usually held to adore. But beyond
that, Herr Tholuck leaves matters standing at the usual indistinct
conception of Pantheism; a profounder discussion of it would
have had, for the author's emotional Christianity, no direct
interest; but we see that personally he is carried away by
remarkable enthusiasm for a mysticism which, in the ordinary
phrase, entirely deserves the epithet Pantheistic. Where, however,
he tries philosophising (p. 12), he does not get beyond the
standpoint of the “rationalist” metaphysic with its uncritical
categories.
***END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY OF MIND***
Credits
March 5, 2012
This and all associated files of various formats will be found in:
http://www.gutenberg.org/dirs/3/9/0/6/39064/
Updated editions will replace the previous one — the old editions will be
renamed.
Creating the works from public domain print editions means that no one
owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and
you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and
without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General
Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the Project Gutenberg™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be
used if you charge for the eBooks, unless you receive specific permission. If
you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the
rules is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. They may
be modified and printed and given away — you may do practically
anything with public domain eBooks. Redistribution is subject to the
trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.
The Full Project Gutenberg License
1.A.
1.B.
1.C.
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the Foundation” or
PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the
collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual
work is in the public domain in the United States and you are located in the
United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying,
distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on
the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of
promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project
Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for
keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name associated with the work. You can
easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the
same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you
share it without charge with others.
1.D.
The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you
can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant
state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of your
country in addition to the terms of this agreement before downloading,
copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works
based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation
makes no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country outside the United States.
1.E.
1.E.1.
The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access to,
the full Project Gutenberg™ License must appear prominently whenever
any copy of a Project Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase
“Project Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg”
is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or
distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere at no cost and with almost no restrictions
whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project
Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at http://www.gutenberg.org
1.E.2.
1.E.3.
1.E.4.
Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg™ License
terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any
other work associated with Project Gutenberg™.
1.E.5.
1.E.6.
You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed,
marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word
processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or
distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work in a format other than
“Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in the official version posted on
the official Project Gutenberg™ web site (http://www.gutenberg.org), you
must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a
means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of
the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate
format must include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in
paragraph 1.E.1.
1.E.7.
Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing, copying
or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works unless you comply with
paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
1.E.8.
You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or
distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works provided that
You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from the
use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the method you
already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the
owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has agreed to
donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg Literary
• Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60 days
following each date on which you prepare (or are legally required to
prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly
marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information about
donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation.”
You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies you
in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he does not
agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™ License. You must
•
require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed
in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all access to other
copies of Project Gutenberg™ works.
You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any
money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the
•
electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of
receipt of the work.
You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free distribution
•
of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.E.9.
1.F.1.
1.F.2.
1.F.3.
LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND — If you discover
a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can
receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written
explanation to the person you received the work from. If you received the
work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with your written
explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the defective work
may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received
the work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose
to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu
of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund
in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem.
1.F.4.
Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in paragraph
1.F.3, this work is provided to you 'AS-IS,' WITH NO OTHER
WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED, INCLUDING
BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTIBILITY OR
FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
1.F.5.
1.F.6.
INDEMNITY — You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the
trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone
providing copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in accordance
with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production,
promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works,
harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that
arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause
to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.
Section 2.
Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without wide spread
public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the
number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed
in machine readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment
including outdated equipment. Many small donations ($1 to $5,000) are
particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.
While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have
not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against
accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us
with offers to donate.
Please check the Project Gutenberg Web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways
including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate,
please visit: http://www.gutenberg.org/fundraising/donate
Section 5.
General Information About Project Gutenberg™ electronic works.
Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed editions,
all of which are confirmed as Public Domain in the U.S. unless a copyright
notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance
with any particular paper edition.
Corrected editions of our eBooks replace the old file and take over the old
filename and etext number. The replaced older file is renamed. Versions
based on separate sources are treated as new eBooks receiving new
filenames and etext numbers.
Most people start at our Web site which has the main PG search facility:
http://www.gutenberg.org