Kalpagam, U. - Rule by Numbers - Governmentality in Colonial India-Lexington Books (2014)
Kalpagam, U. - Rule by Numbers - Governmentality in Colonial India-Lexington Books (2014)
Rule by Numbers
U. Kalpagam
LEXINGTON BOOKS
Lanham • Boulder • New York • London
Published by Lexington Books
An imprint of The Rowman & Littlefield Publishing Group, Inc.
4501 Forbes Boulevard, Suite 200, Lanham, Maryland 20706
www.rowman.com
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reproduced in any form or by any
electronic or mechanical means, including information storage and retrieval systems,
without written permission from the publisher, except by a reviewer who may quote
passages in a review.
Kalpagam, U.
Rule by numbers : governmentality in colonial India / U. Kalpagam.
pages cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 978-0-7391-8935-1 (cloth : alkaline paper) -- ISBN 978-0-7391-8936-8 (electronic)
1. India--Politics and government--1765-1947. 2. India--Statistical services--History. 3. Statistics--
Political aspects--India--History. 4. Great Britain--Colonies--Administration--History. 5. Foucault,
Michel, 1926-1984--Political and social views. 6. State, The. I. Title.
JQ231.K35 2014
352.7'509540903--dc23
2014020490
TM
The paper used in this publication meets the minimum requirements of American
National Standard for Information Sciences Permanence of Paper for Printed Library
Materials, ANSI/NISO Z39.48-1992.
v
Preface and Acknowledgments
The “State” has been the subject of interest and curiosity of philosophers,
historians, political scientists, and economists for long. In recent years,
studies on the colonial state in India combining both historical and
anthropological perspectives initiated by American anthropologists and
the Subaltern Studies group received a renewed stimulus as Michel Fou-
cault’s ideas gained popularity in the social sciences. The historian’s
interests on liberalism and empire, the political scientist’s acknowledg-
ment of the potential of Foucault’s idea of governmentality, and the
anthropologists’ interest in studying state-effects at the margins have to-
gether provided new vigor to the study of the state with these perspec-
tives and new questions. This study has been influenced by these cur-
rents of thought in its attempt to understand how governmentality pro-
duced statistical knowledge in colonial India. In the many years that have
gone into this research, I have drawn much inspiration from Talal Asad’s
interest in Foucauldian ideas for anthropological analysis, and his essay
on “statistics and modern power” initiated me into this. His encourage-
ment over the years kept up my interest to complete this work despite
other diversions in my research. Rayna Rapp opened up a whole new
world for me with her enthusiasm and generosity and I have benefitted
much from her comments on this work. My thanks to both Talal Asad
and Rayna Rapp for all they have given me that is beyond measurement.
Deborah Poole evinced interest in this work in its early stages and gave
me her insights. I also thank the anonymous reviewer of this book for the
good suggestions that strengthened sections of some chapters. The edi-
tors and anonymous reviewers of journals that published earlier versions
of some of the chapters, in particular, Time and Society, History of the
Human Sciences, Economy and Society, Journal of Historical Sociology, and
Economic and Political Weekly were generous with their comments thus
helping to clarify many issues. In the initial stages of research, I received
a grant from the Wenner Gren Foundation for Anthropological Research,
New York (Developing Countries Training Fellowship Grant# 4870-4201)
that helped me to pursue this study. A British Academy Fellowship for
another research project took me to London, which facilitated archival
research for the chapter on the public sphere at the India Office in the
British Library. I am thankful to Pat Caplan for hosting me in London.
Much of the reading for this was done over the years at the New York
Public Library and I am ever so thankful to the helpful staff there. Over
vii
viii Preface and Acknowledgments
the course of time I have been on the faculty of several institutions that
have supported this work and I am grateful to the staff of the libraries in
these institutions. A sabbatical leave from my present institution in Alla-
habad, India, helped me to complete this work. Friends and strangers
have helped me access literature that would otherwise have been un-
available to me and I should like to especially offer my thanks to S.
Subbalakshmi, Rama Deb Roy, Joan Mencher, David Scott, and Faisal
Devji. It has been a pleasure to receive all the helpful editorial support of
Sabah Ghulamali and Brian Hill at Lexington Books. My family has sup-
ported me in many ways and I offer my thanks to all of them.
Introduction
The Colonial State and Statistical Knowledge
The modern state in India is of recent origin dating back to British coloni-
al rule of the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries. Despite the prodigious
work of historians of the colonial period that deal with the colonial state,
only a few explicitly analyze the construction of the state that arose out of
a set of contingent factors. The paradigm shift in political studies of the
modern state brought in by the Foucauldian approach of “governmental-
ity” that displaced the earlier approaches that were based either on the
historical evolution of the state or the history of modern political thought,
and the insights bequeathed by recent anthropological studies of state
effects at the margins have cleared the way for critical analyzes of state
constructivism that integrates anthropological and postcolonial perspec-
tives with Foucauldian insights. This book narrates the construction of
the modern colonial state in India through a history of colonial govern-
mentality, focusing on the enumerative rationalities and strategies in the
process of colonial governance and its systems of recordation that gener-
ated vast knowledge even as it constructed the state and the colonial
subjects. New categories of space, time, measurement, classification, and
causality that were integral to the political technologies of colonial
governance constructed “economy” and “society” as domains of govern-
mental intervention and knowledge, and enabled the apprehension of
social phenomenon in modern scientific ways. Drawing on Foucault’s
notion of “episteme,” it is argued that the rise of quantification and
knowledge in colonial India and elsewhere in the colonized world is to be
understood as “the process of a historical practice” of modern govern-
ance, and intimately connected with the construction of the modern state.
For Foucault, the “episteme” is not what may be known at a given peri-
od, but what in the positivity of discursive practices makes possible the
existence of epistemological figures and sciences. 1
Forms of Western dominance over the rest have concerned historians,
anthropologists, sociologists, political economists and those in the hu-
manities for long both in the Western and and in the non-Western world.
But not until Talal Asad’s suggestion of anthropologizing the growth of
Western power that serious and critical reflections began in Western
anthropology of the imbrication of colonial power and knowledge. 2 An
anthropology of Western imperial power, Asad notes, must “try to
1
2 Introduction
distant events, places, and people, it seems possible to retain the catego-
ries of “power” and “knowledge.” Latour acknowledges the role of these
categories when he notes how “immutable and combinable mobiles”
changed cartography from a shaky foundation to a sure path of science,
and that these mobiles “all end up at such scale that a few men or women
can dominate them by sight, at one point or another, they all take the
shape of a flat surface of paper that can be archived, pinned on a wall and
combined with others; they all help to reverse the balance of forces be-
tween those who master and those who are mastered.” 21 Latour’s analy-
sis has contributed to a heightened awareness of how modes of inscrip-
tion and forms of writing and reading have been historically crucial in
the processes of making power and knowledge, and equally how inscrip-
tions construct persons, things, and events at the local or the periphery
and in turn is transformed by the periphery acting upon it. 22 These en-
able a fuller understanding of how both “acting at a distance” and “act-
ing at near” are relevant to an understanding of governance.
Max Weber’s prophecy of modernity that the earlier intimate social
forms would dissolve and be replaced by rational bureaucratic-legal or-
ders governed by the growth of procedure and predictability is most
evident in the procedures of the modern state that ushered in a quantific-
atory episteme. Arthur Bentley in his book The Process of Government first
published in 1908 observed that “quantities” are present in every bit of
political life and there is no political process that is not “a balancing of
quantity against quantity.” “Understanding any of these phenomena
means measuring the elements that have gone into them. . . . If we can get
our social life stated in terms of activity, and of nothing else, we have not
indeed succeeded in measuring it, but we have at least reached a founda-
tion upon which a coherent system of measurements can be built up . . .
we shall cease to be blocked by the intervention of unmeasurable ele-
ments, which claim to be themselves the real causes of all that is happen-
ing, and which by their spook-like arbitrariness make impossible any
progress toward dependable knowledge.” 23
Adapting Manuel Castell’s concept of “information order,” historian
Christopher Bayly has examined the modalities of information gathering
in colonial India through state surveillance and social communication by
drawing the distinction between “knowledge” and “information,” where
knowledge implies socially organized and taxonomized information.
Bayly noted that the evolving information order retained distinctly In-
dian features, even while it was absorbing and responding to the pro-
found influences set in motion by the European rulers, with the gradual
shift from “embodied” knowledge to “institutional” knowledge. 24 While
in the early phase of colonial occupation, the British in India had to gain
access and mastery over prior indigenous information systems which in
turn generated Orientalist knowledge of language, texts, and literature,
the progressive introduction of bureaucratic methods of rule and admin-
Introduction 7
relations that can be discovered, for a given period, between the sci-
ences when one analyses them at the level of discursive regularities. 32
The quantificatory episteme ushered by the colonial state in India was
indeed unique. While precolonial states such as those of the Mughals, the
Mahrattas, or even Tipu Sultan, had streamlined administrative practices
and were indeed noteworthy for systematic record-keeping, none of
them introduced a quantificatory episteme. 33 The pre-colonial reckoning
of worldly affairs were less objectified and quantified. It was only with
the colonial practices of governance that measurement and quantification
assumed predominance; and modern social scientific thought in India is
of colonial origin and in fact traceable to it. What is indeed more interest-
ing is why the nature of governance as well as Indian philosophical
thought in pre-colonial India did not generate and perhaps was not even
capable of generating similar social scientific discourses. No doubt an
examination of the epistemic foundations of pre-modern science in India,
and its contrast with the Baconian ideas of modern inductive and experi-
mental science may provide some explanations. Despite the development
of sciences (sastra) in pre-modern India in fields such as medicine, mathe-
matics, and astronomy, the epistemic foundations for the modern social
sciences did not exist. Although it is often noted that Kautilya’s Arthasas-
tra is a treatise on statecraft and economics, it is only a manual of instruc-
tion written in maxim (sutra) and verse (shloka) form and was meant to be
transmitted orally. 34 While it spells out in detail the organization of
king’s administration including the maintenance of accounts, the only
policy intervention that can be found there is what the king ought to do
as famine measures. The idea of intervening in social processes did not
develop, for the conception of social process itself was lacking. In fact,
this idea is dependent on the development of the notion of social causal-
ity and the apprehension of social phenomenon.
As precise knowledge of society and its laws made it possible to citi-
cize the biases of ordinary obscurantism and the biases created by natural
sciences, Bruno Latour termed the newly founded social sciences of the
nineteenth century as the “second Enlightenment.” 35 The idea of cause
and effect and of the possibility of knowledge of the external world has
been the subject of modern Western philosophy since Descartes. If Ba-
con’s Novum organum in the seventeenth century laid a new foundation
for the entire work of “understanding,” his book The History of Life and
Death highlighted the importance of vital statistics to the broad improve-
ments in the human condition. 36 His call for quantitative studies which
later found reflection in the works of Graunt and Petty led to an emerg-
ing interest in statistical data in the seventeenth century.
Intervention in the external world is possible only when the objects or
events in the world are ordered and necessary connections between them
established. Kantian epistemology no doubt requires a “transcendental”
Introduction 11
subject that constructs from the manifold of appearances objects that are
unities and this unifying act is necessarily subject to the categories. 37
Anthropologists have questioned Kant’s insights on the construction of
objects as unities. Ernest Gellner has argued that whereas Kant thought
that the mind is so constructed that it must bring forth within itself an
orderly knowable Newtonian world, he failed to find out how it was all
instilled in us, and that it was Emile Durkheim who, acknowledging the
pervasive presence of compulsion in our mental life, noted that it was
instilled by “ritual.” Gellner believes that the compulsive ideas of mod-
ern Cartesian man are not linked, in any one-to-one manner, to any spe-
cific ritual but to certain formal properties of ideas, which are socially
induced in more complex ways, and is engendered by a specific historic
experience. 38
In the present anthropological endeavor of grappling with the intro-
duction of new categories of knowledge and new modes of intervention
in colonial society, I suggest that governmentality of the modern colonial
state that made population its object of concern was instrumental in the
generation of social scientific knowledge. These being constituted
through practices meant that the “knowing subject” had exited the field,
and the authorizing power of governing practices became the subject of
knowledge.
If indeed the epistemological domains in colonial India were trans-
formed as a result of new modes of governance thus permitting the pos-
sibility of social scientific discourses, then the representations of the
spatio-temporal world of objects also underwent changes along with the
corresponding changes in collective consciousness. This could only have
been possible with the incorporation of new categories into the epistemo-
logical domains either through a set of new practices or by reconstituting
older ones. This is an aspect surprisingly neglected in anthropology and
in the recent postcolonial critical studies in spite of a great deal of atten-
tion paid to questions of rationality and modernity.
gories constituting the “natives” point of view. What may appear un-
problematically as two mutually exclusive types of social analysis, the
hermeneutical and the explanatory, has been the subject of debates in the
methodology of the social sciences.
I recall here the old debate between Peter Winch and Alasdair MacIn-
tyre on “The Idea of a Social Science.” 51 One of the issues that Winch
brings up for discussion is Weber’s account of “verstehen” and causal
explanation. He notes that for Weber “interpretation” aims at “self-
evidence” only, and cannot claim to be “causally valid.” Statistical laws
based on observations of what happens are necessary to verify such
hypotheses. Thus Winch notes that Weber arrived at a conception of
sociological law as a “statistical regularity, which corresponds to an intel-
ligible intended meaning.” 52 Winch contests Weber’s position and notes
that statistics is not the decisive and ultimate court of appeal for the
validity of sociological interpretation, as sometimes a proffered interpre-
tation could be wrong and what is needed then is a better interpretation.
The problem that Winch tries to grapple with in both Weber’s and Witt-
genstein’s ideas on sociological and philosophical analyses, is the pos-
sibility that categories used in investigations may be different from the
categories that belong to the activity under investigation. So, for Winch,
there is no scope for causal laws. Winch has a double-edged idea of a
social science, one bearing on the individual and the other on the societal
level understanding of regularities and institutions. 53 MacIntyre’s re-
sponse was that there were many phenomena in society that displayed
regularities and there were varieties of systematic regularities and not all
of them were the outcome of rule-governed behavior of the agents. Also
there were many conditions of individuals and societies that had a “logi-
cal character” such as “being unemployed, having kin-relations of a par-
ticular kind, rates of population change,” and these were not all action-
descriptions the way Winch assumed. 54 So for MacIntyre, there existed
scope for causal laws. Since then, of course, MacIntyre has altered his
position recognizing the game-theoretic character of social life with its
systematic unpredictability, and the ways in which predictability and
unpredictability are interlinked. 55
What seems to have been missed in that rather abstract debate was
that the conditions in question—of “being unemployed . . . rates of popu-
lation change”—were changes in the economy, and the “logical charac-
ter” of these conditions is not transparent under capitalist economies and
can only be perceived, deciphered, and predicted through statistically
generated laws. It was after all such a lack of transparency of the value-
creation feature of the “commodity,” the well-known “commodity fetish-
ism,” that prompted Marx to explore the laws of capitalism as well as the
then contemporary originators of the Neo-classical school to search for
laws regarding the price mechanism that could be statistically derived
and verified. This point may appear trivial to economists, though they
16 Introduction
may not all be aware that similar methodological debates have concerned
their fellows such as Friedrich von Hayek’s skepticism of statistical meth-
ods, or Thorstein Veblen’s attempts to draw on the semiotic ideas of
Charles Sanders Peirce to develop the foundations of institutional eco-
nomics as an alternative to the dominant positivist approaches. 56
The reason why I have retrieved this old debate between Peter Winch
and Alasdair MacIntyre is to bring to attention the long-standing issues
in anthropology on questions of rationality, relativism, and commensur-
ability of cultures. 57 An important issue seems to have been missed in
these debates, namely that the “ethnographic sites” have themselves
changed so tremendously in the era of “Late Capitalism,” that it is in-
creasingly being realized by anthropologists that it is not valid to talk
anymore of “cultural wholes.” 58 As “natives” everywhere try to compre-
hend as well as manage the changes taking place in new “languages” and
in new “styles of reasoning” such as the statistical ones, it seems that the
question of commensurability of cultures is not so significant an issue as
the problem of rendering commensurable more and more aspects of the
diverse “social arrangements” across the world. 59
If today in the era of “Late Capitalism” transnational and trans-
regional flows of finance, resources and information, and international
and intra-national disparities in income, wealth, and living standards are
so very obvious through the mass of statistical data, let us remind our-
selves that the significant ontological and epistemological shifts associat-
ed with those enumerative practices in different parts of the world have
not yet been fully comprehended. 60 International data spanning over two
hundred nations around the world are so commonplace today that we
hardly reflect on the ontological status of the nations. Nation-states in the
contemporary world system are similar, yet distinct and separable that
renders possible comparison and the marking out of differences. The
similarity is founded on the territorial boundedness of nations and state
sovereignty irrespective of its political form. Recently, Benedict Ander-
son provided an understanding of comparison across nation-states based
solely on similarity without conceding that it is constitutively linked to
“difference” marked by histories of power and processes of domination,
based on the canonical account of state sovereignty as being of autoch-
thonous European origins which has been universalized, bequeathing to
each nation comparable norms and forms of sovereignty. 61 Anderson
distinguishes two modalities of comparison, namely “bound seriality”
and “unbound seriality” based on the assumption of replicable plurals as
constituting the world. Comparison of cross-sectional and time series
statistical data across nations and regions would be an instance of bound
seriality that operates in and through governmentality. The relationship
between colonialism and the formation of norms of state sovereignty as
one of “inequality structured through the form of equivalence” are only
now being explored. 62
Introduction 17
The advent of colonial rule in India also marked the beginning of a vast
documentation project on a hitherto unknown scale of the activities and
life of the people. Various agencies such as archives, libraries, surveys,
revenue bureaucracies, folklore and ethnographic agencies, censuses, and
museums, and the writings and recordation of colonial administration
provided a context for the surveillance, recording, classifying, and evalu-
ating that was called for by the new order of nineteenth-century nation-
states with their imperializing and disciplining bureaucracies—whether
it concerned colonies abroad or criminals and slums at home. 67 Bernard
Cohn provides a classification of the investigative modalities by which
knowledge of Indian society was generated by British colonial rule that
he grouped as the historiographic, the observational/ travel, the survey
modality, the enumerative, the museological, the surveillance and sani-
tary modalities. 68 Although Cohn refers to the colonial state and “state-
making” as a cultural project, somewhat analogous to the ideas of Corri-
gan and Sayer, and invokes the name of Foucault, his investigative mo-
dalities are insufficiently integrated with the regulatory activities of the
state. 69 Foucault’s conception of governmentality provides a more useful
framework. 70
The techniques of government instituted by the colonial state differed
greatly from pre-colonial states both in the nature of accountability pro-
cedures and in the recording of information, although British administra-
tors sometimes overlooked the available data on India in their discus-
sions on colonial policy. These techniques of government called for the
setting up of new institutions, procedures, calculations, reflections, and
tactics giving rise to both a modern state form and to a modern regime of
power/knowledge, even if as argued the universalist knowledge project
though carried out successfully in the urban slums of England met its
limit in the colonial situation of India. 71
The institution of a fully developed colonial state was a process long
in the making during which colonial governmentality evolved with dif-
ferent political rationalities and technologies that were contingent and
context-related, even if in general colonial governmentality sought to
fuse liberal governmentality with the colonial rule of difference that was
racially marked. In the early years when the East India Company carried
its activities of commerce, the role of governing the population was insig-
nificant. Even then the Company bureaucracy set in its place systems of
accountability that consolidated knowledge of the commercial activities.
Once the company acquired the administration of police, justice and rev-
enue, first in Bengal and then in most other regions, the techniques of
government were progressively instituted. It was from 1818 onward,
after the defeat of the Mahrattas, that regular and centralized forms of
Introduction 19
NOTES
tal doublet. See Michel Foucault, The Order of Things (New York: Vintage Books, 1966/
1973), 340.
41. Homi K. Bhabha, The Location of Culture (London/ New York: Routledge, 1993),
86.
42. Paul Rabinow, “Representations are Social Facts: Modernity and Post-Moder-
nity in Anthropology,” in Writing Culture: the Poetics and Politics of Ethnography, ed.
James Clifford and George E. Marcus (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986),
234–61; and Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1979).
43. Juri Mykkanen, “‘To Methodize and Regulate Them’: William Petty’s Govern-
mental Science of Statistics,” History of the Human Sciences 7, 3 (1994): 65–88. Some
recent works analyzing the role of statistics are The Probabilistic Revolution, volume 1,
ed. L. Kruger, L. J. Daston, and M. Heidelberger(Cambridge: MIT Press, 1987); Ian
Hacking, The Taming of Chance (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990); Theo-
dore M. Porter, The Rise in Statistical Thinking (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1986), and Trust in Numbers: The Pursuit of Objectivity in Science and Public Life (Prince-
ton: Princeton University Press, 1995).
44. Alain Desrosieres,”How Real are Statistics? Four Possible Attitudes,”Social Re-
search68, 2 (Summer 2001): 339–40.
45. Talal Asad, “Ethnographic Representation, Statistics, and Modern Power,” So-
cial Research 61, 1 (1994): 55–88.
46. Sankar Muthu, “Enlightenment Anti-Imperialism,” Social Research 66, 4 (Winter
1999): 959–1007.
47. Lorraine Daston, “Enlightenment Calculations,” Critical Inquiry 21, 1 (Autumn
1994): 191.
48. Fortes reveals that anthropologists have long grappled with how ethnography
and statistics could be combined when he notes, “Our investigation shows that ele-
mentary statistical procedures reduce apparently discrete ‘types’ or ‘forms’ of domes-
tic organization in Ashanti to the differential effects of identical principles in varying
local social contexts. This makes an assessment of the factors underlying the ‘norms’
possible; and it also enables us to relate the ‘norms’ to one another and to the apparent
‘types’ of domestic organization by taking into account the effect of time as an index of
growth.” See Meyer Fortes, “Time and Social Structure: An Ashanti Case Study,” in
Social Structure: Studies Presented to A. R. Radcliffe Brown, ed. Meyer Fortes (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1949), 54–84.
49. Kirstie M. McClure, “Figuring Authority, Statistics, Liberal Narrative and the
Vanishing Subject,” Theory and Event 3, 1 (1999).
50. Raymond Williams, Politics and Letters (London: New Left Books, 1982).
51. Bryan R. Wilson, ed., Rationality (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1970).
52. Peter Winch, “The Idea of a Social Science,” in Rationality, ed. B. R. Wilson
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1970), 7. Winch questions Weber’s implied suggestion that
“verstehen” is something that is logically incomplete and needs complementing by a
different method altogether, namely the collection of statistics.
53. Philip Pettit, “Winch’s Double-Edged Idea of a Social Science,” History of the
Human Sciences 13, 1 (2000): 63–77.
54. Alasdair MacIntyre, “The Idea of a Social Science,” in Rationality ed. B. R. Wilson
(Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1970), 123.
55. Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory (Notre Dame: Univer-
sity of Notre Dame Press, 1981/1984), 88–110.
56. Philip Mirowski, More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as
Nature’s Economics (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989).
57. For a recent discussion on this issue of the controversy over the Hawaiian per-
ception of Captain James Cook between anthropologists Marshall Sahlins and Gana-
nath Obeysekere, see Steven Lukes, “Different Cultures, Different Rationalities?” His-
tory of the Human Sciences 13, 1 (2000): 3–18.
Introduction 25
58. Nicholas Thomas too makes a similar point in his critic of the anthropologists’
ethnographic monograph that privileges both the exotic and the fieldwork as partak-
ing of “alterity.” He notes “A monograph is not about ‘other cultures’ but rather
another culture, and the fact that this must at some level be treated as a bounded and
stable system makes implicit contrast with a home-point almost inevitable even where
there is no explicit one-to-one juxtaposition. . . . Insofar as this is what ethnographic
writing is about, exoticism can only be disposed of by disposing of ethnography, by
breaking from one-to-one presentation into modes that disclose other registers of cul-
tural difference and that replace ‘cultural systems’ with less stable and more deriva-
tive discourses and practices. These have a systemic character, but a dialectical ac-
count must do justice to the transposition of meanings, their local incorporation.” See
Thomas, “Against Ethnography,” 311–12.
59. Asad, “Ethnographic Representation, Statistics, and Modern Power.”
60. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament.
61. Benedict, R. Anderson, The Spectre of Comparisons: Nationalisms, Southeast Asia
and the World (London: Verso, 1998).
62. Radhika V. Mongia, “Historicizing State Sovereignty: Inequality and the Form
of Equivalence,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 49, 2 (2007): 386–87.
63. Peter Pels, “The Anthropology of Colonialism: Culture, History and the Emer-
gence of Western Governmentality,” Annual Review of Anthropology 26 (1997): 175.
64. Williams, Politics and Letters; Silvana Patriarca, Numbers and Nationhood: Writing
Statistics in Nineteenth-Century Italy (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996);
and David Eastwood, “Amplifying the Province of the Legislation: the flow of infor-
mation and the English State in the Early Nineteenth Century,” Historical Research 62,
(1989): 276–94.
65. Asad, “Ethnographic Representation, Statistics, and Modern Power,” 78; and
Talal Asad, “The Concept of Cultural Translation in British Social Anthropology,” in
Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography, ed. James Clifford and George
Marcus (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986), 141–64.
66. A. Abdel Malek, “Orientalism in Crisis,” Diogenes, 11, 44 (December 1963):
103–40; Said, Orientalism; Ian Hacking, Representing and Intervening (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1983).
67. Carol E. Breckenridge, “The Aesthetics and Politics of Colonial Collecting: India
at World Fairs,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 32, 2 (1989): 195–96.
68. Bernard S. Cohn and Nicholas B. Dirks, “Beyond the Fringe: The Nation-State,
Colonialism and the Technologies of Power,” Journal of Historical Sociology 1, 2 (June
1988): 224–29; and Cohn, “Colonialism and its Forms of Knowledge.”
69. Philip Corrigan and Derek Sayer, The Great Arch: English State Formation as Cul-
tural Revolution (London: Basil Blackwell, 1985).
70. David Scott, Refashioning Futures: Criticism after Postcoloniality (New Jersey:
Princeton University Press, 1999); and David Scott, “Colonial Governmentality,” Social
Text 43 (1995): 191–220.
71. Mary Poovey, “The Limits of the Universal Knowledge Project: British India and
the East Indiamen,” Critical Inquiry 31, 1 (2004): 183–202.
72. Eric Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1959/1989), 13.
73. According to Schoolman the “sense of responsibility to act” refers to acting in
the world in justifiable ways, to a moral-prudential obligation to acquire reliable
knowledge, achieve practical ends in a defensible manner, solve problems, realize
certain values, and meet the expectations of other. The “sense of responsibility to
otherness” refers to exposing and rejecting the devaluation and discipline of an “Oth-
er” which is inevitably engendered by the cognitive machinery that underpins the
moral uprightness and pragmatic effectiveness inherent in the sense of responsibility
to act. See Schoolman, “Introduction,” in Stephen K. White, Edmund Burke: Modernity,
Politics and Aesthetics Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 1994/2000).
26 Introduction
74. Javed Majeed, Ungoverned Imaginings: James Mill’s “The History of British India”
and Orientalism (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1992), 16.
75. Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India, 22–23.
76. Cohn and Dirks, “Beyond the Fringe,” and Bayly, Empire and Information.
77. David Ludden, “India’s Development Regime,” in Colonialism and Culture ed.
Nicholas B. Dirks (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1992), 247–87.
78. Appadurai,”Number in the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament, 317.
79. Stoler, Along the Archival Grain.
80. Immanuel Kant, “What is Enlightenment?” in Immanuel Kant: Philosophical Writ-
ings (New York: Continuum, 1784/1986).
ONE
Sovereignty and Governmentality
27
28 Chapter 1
what is “ordered to the end” and thus “correct.” The king’s art is the
science of government, where science as “truth” is a combination of Intel-
lect and Voice. Government was essentially vocal in character.
Coomaraswamy notes that the octad of king-making deities (Savitr,
Agni, Soma, Brhaspati, Indra, Rudra, Mitra, and Varuna) endow the king
with a variety of powers and virtues. Describing the initiatory rites of the
king (abhisekha) translated as “Coronation,” Coomaraswamy argues
with evidence that it is intended to enthrone as king, not a “Varuna” but
a “Mitra” so as to ensure a “Supreme Sovereignty” and to slay all his evil
through the pressing of Soma. This puts the king above the law so that he
can do no harm. When the Sacerdotium and the Regnum (the priest and
the king) act together, then both possess the counseling power. Cooma-
raswamy notes that a king “works” not with his hands but by his fiat or
edicts. The king is the “Voice” that gives effect to the purposes of the
Spiritual authority and thus does the will of God on earth.
The primary work of the god-king and the earthly kings is the perfor-
mance of the Sacrifice. The essential purpose of the Divine Marriage, in
which the priest and king are the representatives of Sky and Earth, is
apotropaic of Death and especially Famine. 17 Death is averted from the
kingdom by means of the Divine Marriage and the Sacrifice, and many
Upanishad texts refer to the marriage as an insurance against the priva-
tion. The king is directly responsible for the fertility of the land and
rainfall at the right season depends upon his righteousness or default,
giving rise to the widespread belief that life and fertility of the realm
depends upon the king.
Coomarawamy notes that the notion of a divine pastor and of an
analogous human pastorate is one of the very many formulae common to
Platonic and Vedic philosophy. There is an art of herding human beings
and the government and care of men is preeminently the sacerdotal func-
tion, but in so far as the royal function is delegated to a king, the latter
can also be called a shepherd of men, as in some of the Indian texts where
the king too is a gopa. 18 Coomaraswamy thus concludes that the tradi-
tional Hindu king in antiquity is not a “constitutional ruler” whose ac-
tions merely reflect the wishes of a majority of his subjects or those of a
secular minister, nor king by virtue of any “social” contract, but a ruler
by divine kingship, and this does not imply that he is an “absolute” ruler,
but on the contrary that he is himself the subject of another king, where
the law (dharma), than which there is nothing higher, is the very princi-
ple of royalty, although the king was not really responsible to anything
like divine law. Thus while the constitutional monarch may be controlled
by his equals or even his inferiors, the ruler by divine kingship is con-
trolled by a superior. Human law reflects divine law and the king was to
link the people with the spiritual order.
With reference to the individual as a subject, the Indian science of
government has three aspects—the cosmic (adhidevatam), the political (ad-
Sovereignty and Governmentality 33
hirajyam), and the self (adhyatmam). The question is not only one of a
universal and a national or civic order, but also one of internal econo-
my—a government of the self wherein the factors of disorder are ruled by
a principle of order, if the goals of wellbeing in this world and the other
are to be reached. It is believed that man has two selves, the one outer
and active, the subject of passions, the other inner, contemplative and
serene. The problem of the internal economy by which the man’s ends
(purusartha) can all be attained is one of the relationship of the psycho-
physical ego to the spiritual person, the outer king to the priest within
oneself. The two selves correspond to those of Mitra-Varuna, Sacerdo-
tium and Regnum. The kingship envisaged by the Indian traditional doc-
trine is thus far removed from “absolute monarchy” or of “individual-
ism.” Arthasastra, the classical Indian text on the science of government
observes that only a ruler who rules himself can long rule others, and that
the whole of this science has to do with a victory over the powers of
perception and action.
A few years after Coomaraswamy’s book was published, Georges
Dumezil published his book Mitra-Varuna in 1948, providing his interpre-
tation of the king-Brahman (king and priest) relationship wherein the
Brahman protected the king against the “magico-religious risks” inherent
in the exercise of the royal function while the king maintained the Brah-
man in a place equal to or above his own. 19 Dumezil also noted that the
sacerdotal early literature pointed to the existence of a brotherhood
formed to “educate heroes,” the Gandharva transposed to the mythical
realm as a band of supernatural beings, and which men may join by
initiation. The juxtaposition of Mitra and Varuna is antithetically asso-
ciated in a way that ensures their collaboration. While Mitra is associated
with the Brahman, Varuna is with the Gandharva.
Dumezil considers the anti-thesis underlying the Brahman-Gandhar-
va opposition as two organs of “magico-religious” sovereignty; Varuna
initiates in violence the religious and/or political order that Mitra devel-
ops in peace. The magical sovereignty of Varuna operates by means of
bonds (nexum) and debts: the violent god or king controls his enemy
with magical ties and his community with obligations. The second, juridi-
cal sovereignty of Mitra employs pacts (mutuum) and faith: the reasoned
legislator preserves society through the validity of contracts and the ful-
fillment of responsibilities. Both the Brahman and the Gandharva share
equally in the task of securing the life and fecundity of society. The two
heavenly sovereigns, Mitra and Varuna, who stand opposed as law and
violence, find place in Indian epic history as two dynasties called the
“sun” dynasty (Surya Vamsam) and the other “moon” dynasty (Chandra
Vamsam), of which one traces its ancestry back to the king-legislator,
Manu, and the other to the king-Gandharva Pururavas. 20 Extant archaeo-
logical evidence in all parts of the country that trace the genealogy of
Hindu kings mention as to which of the two dynasties the king belonged.
34 Chapter 1
where old lineages retained some power, their actions were circum-
scribed by the regulations of the British administration and the lineages
were not recognized as political entities. 45 Using the model of a develop-
mental cycle, Richard Fox has argued that often a strong state that is
locally intrusive could depose the kin order, and when the state was
weak the local corporate kin groups could grow and flourish. 46 In the
absence of territorial states, this dynamics of kinship conditioned the
state order and bound the region together. In the transition to a modern
state in the colonial context, caste, lineage and kinship were sundered
from locality and made to emerge as translocal social entities. 47 The na-
ture of the territoriality/sovereignty relationship was to undergo a funda-
mental change from precolonial to colonial rule.
In looking at the pursuits of any nation, with a view to draw from them
indications of the state of civilization, no mark is so important, as the
nature of the End to which they are directed. . . . Exactly in proportion
as Utility is the object of every pusuit, may we regard a nation as
civilized. Exactly in proportion as its ingenuity is wasted on contempt-
ible and mischievous objects, though it may be, in itself, an ingenuity of
no ordinary kind, the nation may safely be denominated barborous. 59
In his History of British India James Mill noted, “To ascertain the true state
of the Hindus in the scale of civilization, is not only an object of curiosity
in the history of human nature; but to the people of Great Britain,
charged as they are with the government of that great portion of the
human species, it is an object of the highest practical importance.” 60 Re-
viewing the Hindu form of government Mill remarked, “despotism, in
one of its simplest and least artificial shapes was established in Hindu-
stan, and confirmed by laws of Divine authority” and “despotim and
priestcraft taken together, the Hindus, in mind and body, were the most
enslaved portion of the human race.” 61 Mill’s History provided a theoreti-
cal framework as Javed Majeed has noted, for the liberal agenda “to
emancipate India from its own culture.” 62 For James Mill something be-
yond education, namely reform of the form of government, laws, and
taxation was necessary to propel Indian society up the scale of civiliza-
tion.
In a letter written sometime in 1819–1821 James Mill noted, “the
government of India is carried on by correspondence; and that I am the
only man whose business it is, or who has the time to make himself
master of the facts scattered in a most voluminous correspondence, on
which a just decision must rest.” 63 While cultures could be compared
through translation and from at a distance, Mill viewed governance from
a distance as inefficient. The foundations for the administration of law,
revenue and the form of government in India conceived between
1830–1835 in William Bentinck’s time was only fully established by the
1860s.
A later utilitarian conception of the imperialist mission was expressed
by J. S. Mill in On Liberty published in 1859 shortly after the Indian Mu-
tiny of 1857. J. S. Mill observed:
The early difficulties in the way of spontaneous progress are so great,
that there is seldom any choice of means for overcoming them; and a
ruler full of the spirit of improvement is warranted in the use of any
expedients that will attain an end, perhaps otherwise unattainable.
Despotism is a legitimate mode of government in dealing with barbar-
ians, provided the end be their improvement, and the means justified
by actually effecting that end. Liberty, as a principle, has no application
to any state of things anterior to the time when mankind have become
capable of being improved by free and equal discussion. Until then,
44 Chapter 1
vorable, to the next step which it is necessary for them to take in order
to raise themselves to a higher level. 68
Regarding the adaptation of forms of government to states of society, J. S.
Mill was of the view that an ideal must be constructed taking into consid-
eration not only the “next step” that a society has to take but “all the steps
which society has yet to make; both those which can be foreseen, and the
far wider indefinite range which is at present out of sight” so that the
government would promote “not some one improvement, but all forms
and degrees of it.” 69 Having constructed the ideal form of government,
Mill observed that it is necessary to consider “the mental condition of all
sorts necessary to enable this government to realize its tendencies, and
what, therefore, are the various defects by which a people is made inca-
pable of reaping its benefits.” 70 If it be judged not suitable to introduce
the ideal form of government, then some “inferior forms of polity will
best carry those communities through the intermediate stages which they
must traverse before they can become fit for the best form of govern-
ment.” 71 For Mill, non-Europeans were only fit for a “government of
leading-strings.” 72 Their affairs were best run by a body of professionally
trained bureaucrats free from the control of elected politicians upon
whom the influence of shifting public opinion was palpable. He was also
of the view that colonial bureaucracy should not be accountable to the
“second and third class” of elected representatives either in Britain or in
the colonies.
J. S. Mill also believed that just as a civilized society had a right to rule
over a primitive or semi-civilized society, a more civilized group or na-
tionality within a civilized society had a right to “absorb” and dominate
inferior groups. 73 In practice though, J. S. Mill was critical of British impe-
rialism when it violated the norms of good government as in the case of
Jamaica. 74 Differing from John Locke, Mill divided human societies into
“civilized” and “backward.” In civilized societies, human beings were in
the maturity of their faculties and had attained the capacity of being
guided to their own improvement by conviction or persuasion. In his
view most European societies had long since reached that stage. By
contrast all non-European societies were “backward,” and human beings
there were in a state of “nonage” or “infancy.” Such backward societies
were incapable of being improved by free and equal discussion and
lacked the resources for self-regeneration. Like Locke, he argued that the
right to non-intervention, like the right to individual liberty, only be-
longed to those capable of making good use of it, that is, to those “ma-
ture” enough to think and judge for themselves and to develop unaided.
As in Locke, the right to non-intervention only applied to the relations
between civilized societies.
Although as human beings, such backward individuals had equal mo-
ral claims to the pursuit and protection of their interests with the mem-
46 Chapter 1
Strachey, a disciple of Stephen, put it, “the only hope for India was the
long continuance of the benevolent but strong government of English-
men.” 83 Nineteenth-century liberals advocated the colonial project of ra-
tionalizing India, even if that required endorsing an imperial despot-
ism. 84
However, nineteenth-century liberal ideology underwent a change
from the universalist to a culturalist stance from the 1860s after the trans-
fer of authority to the Crown. The earlier transformative agenda of the
civilizing mission also underwent a change to an imperial order on a
more conservative basis, concerned with issues of stability and order, and
in line with the traditional aspects of Indian society. An emphasis on the
insurmountable differences between people replaced the idea of the uni-
versalist project of civilization with its belief in modernizing them. So
marked was the shift in imperial ideology that the liberal agenda of edu-
cating Indians for self-government was almost completely eclipsed until
it was revived by the nationalist movement in the last decades of the
nineteenth century. 85 This indicates, as Henry Maine upheld, that liberal
imperialism was a historical constellation evolving in response to chang-
ing contexts of imperial dilemmas, and the abstract claims of liberalism
were negotiated on the terrain of practical politics under colonial condi-
tions. Maine was of the view that native belief had “a direct bearing on
the structure of government, which it may be possible to the Indian pos-
sessions of this country.” 86 So strong was this view at that time, that
Minto, who had come to India in 1906 as viceroy, was fully convinced
that Western forms of government were unsuited to India and argued
that representative government “could never be akin to the instincts of
the many races composing the population of the Indian Empire,” as it
was a Western importation to a context that for a long time had absolute
rulers. In Minto’s view what was suited for India was a constitutional
autocracy in British hands that invites to its councils “representatives of
all the interests which are capable of being represented.” 87 Yet, Minto’s
creation of special Muslim constituencies in 1906 was his belief that elec-
toral representation in India had to be sensitive to the communities com-
posing the population and which in course of time created a new politi-
cized vision of community.
Curzon also believed that a centralized despotism was best for India,
although he opened the way for a parliamentary system of government
by including the phrase in the Montague-Chelmsford declaration of 1917
of “the gradual development of self-governing institutions, with a view
to the progressive realization of responsible government in India as an
integral part of the British Empire.” He had noted earlier the following in
a letter in 1900 indicating his firm commitment to the civilizing mission
of colonial rule:
Sovereignty and Governmentality 49
Above all I see, oh so clearly, that we can only hold this country by our
superior standards of honour and virtue and by getting the natives to
recognize them as such. . . . On the other hand we cannot take the
natives up into the administration. They are crooked-minded and cor-
rupt. We have got therefore to go on ruling them and we can only do it
with success by being both kindly and virtuous. I dare say I am talking
rather like a schoolmaster; but after all the millions I have to manage
are less than schoolchildren. 88
Understanding liberalism as a historical event means to understand it as
more than just bearer of rights and freedom, but also as structures of
power and dominance, of colonial and others, and that which holds the
“Other” in contempt. 89 Liberalism’s reliance on procedures also leads to a
dehumanization of the world.
Partha Chatterjee has posed the question provocatively as to whether
there is any analytical purpose in distinguishing the colonial state from
other forms of the modern state or whether it is to be regarded simply as
another form of the modern state that generalized itself across the
globe. 90 If rational forms of administration distinguish the modern state,
then clearly colonial rule rendered it possible in India. But as Chatterjee
notes “the more the logic of a modern regime of power pushed the pro-
cesses of government in the direction of a rationalization of administra-
tion and the normalization of the objects of its rule, the more insistently
did the issue of race come up to emphasize the specifically colonial char-
acter of British dominance in India.” 91 Two significant features of a colo-
nial rule are domination by aliens in which material gains of such domi-
nation accrue to the alien rulers, and being such a rule the aliens seek to
shape the conduct of the governed in particular ways. These two features
could vary in their intensity in different colonial contexts. British colonial
rule of Canada and the United States could not have deployed the rule of
colonial difference, in which difference was marked by race and position
in the evolutionary scale as a modern disciplinary power, the way it did
in India and elsewhere. As evident from the debates and opposition to
the Ilbert Bill of 1883 that sought to grant native judicial officers the
powers to try English offenders as also with regard to the freedom of the
press, colonial rule in India differentiated between colonized natives and
the English/foreign residents in the country. 92
The colonial state in India was indeed a modern state that reconsti-
tuted and combined certain aspects of earlier forms of administration
with the modern rational administration introduced by the British, based
in part on the British administrative practices. 93 As a colonial state it
enfolded certain colonial projects such as surplus extraction, and the nev-
er-to-be-completed project of governing the conduct of the colonized sub-
jects as part of its “improvement” or civilizing agenda, which entailed
strategies and tactics of colonial governmentality that were liberal and
50 Chapter 1
of knowledge that the state creates and organizes about the population
that it governs, such as its health, wealth and welfare constitutes and
represents the legitimacy of the state. Until recently, this vast documenta-
tion by the state was not perceived as a totalizing project or as one that
requires a hermeneutic reading of official texts, as these documents were
seen as natural and neutral. 104
Bureaucratic disciplines that emerged with the modern state embod-
ied these principles of panopticism. 105 For Max Weber, discipline is “the
consistently rationalized, methodically trained and exact execution of the
received order,” and this conduct under orders is rationally uniform by a
plurality of men. 106 Michel Foucault has also shown that these panoptic
disciplines became a general formula of domination in an array of institu-
tional settings in modern Europe. For both Weber and Foucault, these
disciplines do not depend for their operation and effects on individual
personalities and the legitimation required is minimal, such that a bu-
reaucracy could implement these based on mere behavioural and proced-
ural regularities. These also exercise control over its subjects by disci-
plines of calculation and classification. 107
Bureaucratic writings such as the “form,” ”memo,” or “report,” collec-
tively called the “document,” are carriers of information which direct
others to act as a command and emerged out of modern managerial
practice expressing the impersonality of bureaucratic authority. 108 Modes
of writing and reading solidify into institutional routines and forms of
rule through processes of inscription and reinscription. 109 Written bu-
reaucratic communications being fixed and context independent have
greater capacity for transmission across space and time, and by separat-
ing communication and observation it enables these separated elements
to be recombined in different ways. 110 The “official secret” is a specific
invention of the bureaucracy. 111 Governmental transactions cause bu-
reaucratic writings to be classified into different categories of “official-
ness,” some marked as public and rendered visible and others classified
as “secret” that is archived away from public visibility even for extremely
long periods of time, removing whole domains of knowledge and in-
creasing the state’s potencies in immeasurable ways. 112
Written rules and regulations of the modern state make the state ap-
pear as an abstract and distant entity and existing as though in a “homog-
enous empty time” in which the past, present and future are always
different and in which the process of “improvement” or “progress”
marks the transition from one to the other. 113 More often, the representa-
tions the modern state creates and embodies in its technologies of
governance take on a life of their own such that the agents who imple-
ment the rules, the bureaucracy, and upon whom the rules seek to act, all
live in divergent moments. The concrete reality is not the ordered and
rational world that the state envisaged to bring forth but one that is
chaotic, in which heterogeneous temporalities characterize everyday life
Sovereignty and Governmentality 53
to connect with the myriad spatially scattered points (as of colonial em-
pires) where the fiscal, organizational, judicial, (un)/constitutional pow-
ers of the state endeavored to manage economic life and govern popula-
tions. According to Nikolas Rose, it is this governmentalization of the
state, which has permitted the state to survive, as it is this tactics of the
government that make possible what is within the competence of the
state and what is not, what is political or not, and the public versus the
private. 123
Liberal rationality of government implies that governing human be-
havior in the framework of, and by means of, state institutions cannot be
an end in itself and so differs with the “reason of state” rationality in
which strengthening the state was the objective. “Society” is both the
precondition and end of liberal rationality. 124 Liberalism can therefore be
found in “different but simultaneous forms as a regulative scheme of
governmental practice and as the theme of a sometimes-radical opposi-
tion.” 125 Foucault suggests that liberalism is to be analyzed as a principle
and a method of rationalizing the exercise of government and obeying
the internal rule of maximum economy.
The perspective of governmentality calls into question the liberal view
of the separation of state and civil society, the latter being autonomous of
the state. 126 The discursive space of government is not homogenous but
intersected by numerous other discourses such as the discourses of sci-
ence and the changing moral rhetorics and ethical vocabularies of the
culture, which histories and problems are independent of those of the
problematics of government but converge and cohere together as transla-
tion at particular moments. Such intersecting discourses both constructed
colonial “difference” and legitimized colonial governmentality. As an in-
creasingly centralized and bureaucratized modern state gets progressive-
ly governmentalized, society both “civil” and “political” and the public
sphere are continuously recreated and reconstituted, becoming the dis-
cursive site in which contestations over entitlements and identities take
place, even as new claims seek to establish themselves. It is through these
“bound serialities” of governmentality and the “unbound serialities,” in
Anderson’s notions that the modern state transforms into the modern
nation-state.
Liberal technology of government sought regulation in the “law,” not
through a legalism but because the law defines forms of general interven-
tion excluding particular, individual or exceptional measures. 127 Statis-
tics was a modality of defining the law or norm. As more and more
arenas of the population's activities come under regulatory mechanisms
they need to be represented appropriately to facilitate the mechanisms of
intervention. These modalities of representing and intervening enabled
the production of knowledge about the population. 128 As an object of
knowledge, population is a statistical artifact as “mundane techniques of
writing, registering and recording attached individuals to new kinds of
56 Chapter 1
From the eighteenth century onward, European states moved away from
ritual performance and display of spectacle as visible manifestations of
power to “officializing procedures” that gradually extended their inter-
ventionary power. 134 The developments in the British Government in the
nineteenth century influenced the administrative system in colonial India
as many of the state building projects of documentation, legitimation,
classification, bounding, and the associated institutions often reflected
ideas, experiences, and practices worked out originally either in Britain,
India and the other colonies of the Empire and then applied to Great
Britain, India and elsewhere. 135
The growth of government refers to both the movement of govern-
ment into new fields, new types of action, and the expansion of numbers
and the organization and standardization of procedures. Up to 1870, it
has been observed that the growth of government in Britain in the nine-
teenth century cannot be described as a single phenomenon or process as
there were differing traditions and patterns of developments in different
departments triggered by a series of impulses toward change and new
developments whose connections were coincidental as much as causal.
After 1870, there was expansion of numbers and elaboration of proce-
dures but much less movement into new fields of action. As the bureau-
cracy began to gently ossify, external initiatives began to increase after
1890. 136 Mary Poovey is of the view that the growth of nineteenth-centu-
ry government was “irrational” in the sense that “it realized no ulterior
logic, whether individual or deep structural,” but one effect of it was a
further “consolidation of the form of subjectivity that both facilitated and
depended on the administrative routines institutionalized by these
changes” signifying the interdependence of the modern forms of individ-
ualism and administration. 137
Nineteenth-century British government was undoubtedly shaped by
the ideas of Bentham and J. S. Mill. Benthamite reforms of the 1830s and
the Northcote-Trevelyan reforms of 1850s together brought about three
major inventions in British governmental machinery in the nineteenth
century, namely, the classified civil service recruited by open, academic,
competitive examination; the elected, multi-purpose local authority; and
the ministerial department. 138 None of these was a sudden or indepen-
dent invention, but their importance is unarguable. In fact the “adminis-
trative revolution” in the British central government is usually dated
from 1780 with the reports of the Statutory Commission for Examining
the Public Accounts (1780–1787) having inspired most of the administra-
tive reforms for the next half-century. The commissioners’ reports tried to
introduce public economy by reducing expenses in the management of
revenue and sought to introduce “more simple, regular, and accordant
58 Chapter 1
system into the internal frame of the office.” 139 As the system of public
economy required speed, precision, impartiality, uniformity and account-
ability, they were in effect evolving a bureaucratic system of organization
along Weberian lines in which official business was completely reduced
to a written routine. Although bureaucracy did exist prior to 1780, it was
in many aspects patrimonial in nature. By progressively bringing an ar-
ray of diverse practices under a few uniform principles, they were able to
recommend uniformity itself as an administrative principle. Urging the
recovery of control over public functions by the government that had
fallen prey to private interests, the commissioners based their arguments
on the doctrine of public trust which by questioning royal prerogatives
and rights opened the way for a utilitarian conception of government. 140
In 1866 the Exchequer and Audit Department (EAD) was created, headed
by the comptroller and auditor general (CAG), which was constitutional-
ly a tool of parliament that controlled the financial regularity of executive
functions.
A crucial and independent factor in nineteenth-century administrative
developments in Britain was the cycle of enforcement-inspection-amend-
ment that was built into and prescribed in Bentham’s scheme. The doc-
trine of annual reports prepared independently linking administration to
parliament emerged from this cycle of enforcement/inspection/amend-
ment, although it was the French rather than the English who first started
the publication of annual reports. 141 By the middle of the nineteenth cen-
tury there was an enormous amount of bureaucratic productions by way
of official reports that some note it as a “peculiar achievement” of the
English state and yet others saw it as a “formidable weapon in the hands
of a predatory government.” 142 The spread of Benthamite ideas involved
the “combining of manipulated inquiry with a manipulated publicity”
using pre-selected witnesses and selective evidence in the compilation of
reports of the Select Committees and Royal Commissions, and the free
distribution of large numbers of Blue Books amid an orchestrated fanfare
of comment. 143 Commissions as “quasi-state” technologies blurred the
boundary between the state and civil society as it called upon outside
experts to author and authorize the reports. Royal Commissions were
used extensively in the Victorian Age as the state became increasingly
interested in investigating every phase of social life, almost as if the Baco-
nian dream of inductivism was being realized in the realm of social af-
fairs. By the late nineteenth-century, commissions as a technology of state
practice spread across the Empire.
A number of features of the mid nineteenth-century interventionist
state, however, departed significantly from the kind of state that Bent-
ham had described and recommended in the Constitutional Code. Victo-
rian governments, experimenting in new forms of regulation, adopted
particular administrative devices that Bentham had vehemently criticized
such as granting to officials very general and loosely defined authorities
Sovereignty and Governmentality 59
est in knowledge from all localities in standardized forms and local agen-
cies were constrained to report to the imperial agencies. As inscriptions
of various kinds reached imperial centers, they were assembled, sorted,
scaled, and organized in ways deemed to be useful for imperial govern-
ance. In Canada, colonial documentary system evolved as a result of
policy-driven demands of the imperial government, for whom the em-
pire was the terrain of comparative investigations of not just policy but a
variety of other scientific researches as well. The documentary system
distinguished between circular enquiries that included printed report
forms and that were likely repeated regularly, and occasional enquiries
wherein the reporting format was left to the colonial initiative. Bruce
Curtis has highlighted that a Canadian colonial governor who requested
for forms to report information sought under the Merchant Shipping Act
was asked to specify what he needed from a list of nineteen books and
sixty-six different forms covering shipping questions alone. 159 The Blue
Book inaugurated in 1817, with printed forms for its completion appear-
ing in 1822, was by 1840 the most extensive, regular, and standardized
imperial inquiry conducted annually of the colonies and territories of the
empire. The Colonial Office in London required the colonies to produce
an annual statistical and informational Blue Book. Prepared printed ta-
bles of contents and pages with the necessary headings were dispatched
to the governors of every colony each year for completion and return to
London. The Blue Books were the forerunners of the modern statistical
yearbooks produced by many colonial governments. After the East India
Company handed over the administration to the Crown in 1858 it was the
India Office that took charge, and the Colonial Office that administered
other colonies did not have influence on Indian administration. The doc-
umentary system continued even after the imperial government lost
much of its sovereignty in information gathering, and with the colonial
governments in place official documentation became an index of state
sovereignty.
Bruno Latour’s ideas of how stable, immutable, and combinable “mo-
biles” that can be inscribed and moved back and forth from the calculat-
ing centers and the peripheries of action could be deployed to act at a
distance on unfamiliar events, places, and people seems to have been
largely successful as a broad strategy in governing colonies through
rules, inscription, and recordation. 160 But it also ran into its limits as the
“graphic artifacts” of state documentation were produced within local
contexts of power, anxiety, and ambivalence. 161 This is evident for in-
stance, in the quest from the 1840s onward to have synchronized and
uniform census of the British Empire for nearly a century.
Following the British lead of the 1801 census, many colonial author-
ities conducted census enumerations based on their needs and the preva-
lent local context including parts of India. On account of the fragmenta-
tion of information, the Colonial Office in London developed the concept
62 Chapter 1
East India Company and lasting up to the middle of the nineteenth centu-
ry is one in which the colonial state acquires its “stateness.” Within a few
years after the Company acquired Bengal in 1765, it set up the only effec-
tive local bureaucracy in the British Empire with a specialized adminis-
trative corps of Company servants posted in “districts” who acted as
collectors of revenue, magistrates, and judges. In this phase, the relation-
ship between territoriality-soverignty-discipline is constituted. While
managing the population has not yet assumed center-stage as it would in
the second phase, here the state-making process entailed the acquisition
of territory through wars and annexations, and the process of making the
territory familiar. The colonial state was not interested in territory per se
but in managing the things contained in the territory, and especially of
things in relation to the people. The Company thus had “its hands on the
levers with which to regulate the lives of millions without their consent.
It assessed and collected taxation, devised new schemes of land tenure,
created a new system of courts applying newly codified laws, fixed the
customs to be levied on trade, regulated currency and founded banks.” 170
Until the mid-nineteenth century, two important state activities name-
ly the revenue settlement process and the codification of law along with
the establishment of the legislative, executive, and judicial branches of
the government, were instrumental in preparing the ground for the ra-
tional governance of the population. These activities no doubt took place
among contending and divergent opinions such as the difference be-
tween the anglicists and the paternalists on the retention and adaptation
of the older institutions of administration in contrast to the wholesale
introduction of the British system; or the settlement of revenue with the
class of aristocratic landlords as envisaged in the Cornwallis settlement
or with the class of peasantry as under Munro's ryotwari system. Despite
these differences, all opinion converged on the idea that private property
in land was necessary for the reconciliation of freedom with order. The
administration of state security and private property yoked sovereignty
to bureaucracy.
Establishing rights on land meant taking cognizance of ownership
and usufruct rights often established through custom and tradition,
transferred along hereditary lines, and backed by complex and confused
evidence of land grants bestowed at different points in time by the ruling
elites. Revenue settlement process meant the comprehension of the enor-
mous diversities in the de-jure and de-facto relationship of people to
land. Settlement records of the early colonial period in many places con-
tained therefore a great deal of information about the population such as
the number of inhabitants and their caste details among others. Land
revenue administration was the single important activity during this
phase of state making. Defining the rights on land with unambiguous
responsibility for revenue payment and collection was in effect a process
that delegitimized the principle of sovereignity that characterized the
Sovereignty and Governmentality 65
lice reforms, and the Railway Board were all implemented through the
same process that entailed
first, the ascertainment from the information at our disposal, from the
representation of the public, and from the known facts, that there was a
case for reform; secondly, the appointment of an influential and repre-
sentative body to go round the country and take evidence; thirdly the
critical examination of their report, accompanied by consultation of
Local Governments and of public opinion.; fourthly, the accomplished
reform. . . . And now I can say that not a single Commission has sat and
reported in my time without its results having been embodied with the
least possible delay in administrative measures or in legislative Acts.
The second and the third principles were to target the population as a
mass rather than any section or class, and “to take them into open confi-
dence as to the views and intentions of Government, to profit by public
opinion instead of ignoring it, never to flatter or cozen and never to
mystify or deceive.” The last principle “has been everywhere to look
ahead; to scrutinize not merely the passing requirements of the hour, but
the abiding needs of the country, and to build not for the present alone
but for the future.” 184 He claimed that the one great fault of Englishmen
in India was that they do not sufficiently look ahead. Cognizant of the
possibility that an efficient staff could be converted into a not so efficient
bureaucracy, Curzon noted that the growth in colonial government, the
creation of new departments and posts, was on account of global tenden-
cies of economic advancement that they were “powerless to resist, but
not powerless to control.” 185
The idea of governmentality targeting population as the tactic of
government was a novel idea as no pre-colonial state in India had devel-
oped the technologies of rule for the rational governance of the popula-
tion, and of the instrumental approach to the economy. Premodern states
that existed in India prior to the colonial state did often have well devel-
oped administrative structures and record-keeping practices but the
states hardly assumed interventionary roles. The collection of land reve-
nue and other taxes constituted the most significant state activity that
was largely performed by intermediaries belonging to kinship structures
that bound the ruling elites with the local units. The direct intervention-
ary roles even when states were strong were at best minimal. Kings rul-
ing under divine authority sought to dispense welfare to their subjects
through the invocation of the moral order, thus rendering moral and
political order as inextricably bound together. This underwent a pro-
found change with the emergence of the modern state, the distinguishing
characteristics of it being the separation of legislative, executive and judi-
cial authority, which did not exist under pre-modern forms of govern-
ance when kingship held the covenant. The political technologies of rule
Sovereignty and Governmentality 69
deployed by the modern state are therefore both different and governed
by different political rationalities.
A question of concern are the similiarities and differences between
metropolitan governmentality and colonial governmentality especially
since new techniques of rule that evolved in Britain found a place in
colonial governmental practices, and new techniques tried out in the col-
onies were deployed in the internal civilizing mission of the newly con-
stituted urban working class in England. No doubt, metropolitan and
colonial governmentality developed together, in mutual fertilization, al-
though the liberalism of colonial governmentality was “highly qualified”
and “ambiguous,” being “inflected by a certain degree of agonism be-
tween authority and liberty,” what has been called a “dislocated liberal-
ism.” 186 Liberal governmentality in the colonial context faced contradic-
tions between the liberal assumption of equality of individuals and the
difference of the colonial “Others.” Equally, the universalism of liberal-
ism predicated on the idea of “progress” consigned “barbarous” India
outside the pale of progress and was a fundamental contradiction of
liberal governmentality as illiberal forms of governance were seen as
necessary for the “Improvement” of conduct of such people. If for some,
colonial governmentality is “structurally different if also intimately relat-
ed,” for others it is “radically discontinuous with the Western norm.” 187
If liberal governance is rule through freedom, the colonial context was
not one of freedom. Modern statecraft was largely a project of internal
colonization, glossed with the imperial rhetoric of “civilizing mission.” 188
fact that it gives a more hopeful and sanguine estimate of the agricultu-
ral prospects. In the nature of things it had to be based in the main
upon the reports of subordinates, and in the absence of statistics fur-
nished by them, it was ex-necessitate to a corresponding degree devoid
of statistics, and was to a very large extent a mere resume of the reports
like its predecessors, I am glad to state that I was able, in consequence
of my personal inspection to afford some information leading to the
inference that their reports were not quite accurate and were unneces-
sarily gloomy. [In this connection, I wish to emphasise that in my com-
ments upon Deputy Collector M.R. Ry. Narrainasaamy Pillai's report, I
had not the slightest intention to question honesty of purpose or good
faith, but merely wished to record for the information of the Board and
Government, facts that had come under my personal observations and
that of another officer of same standing and which seemed to indicate
either that his (Narrainasaamy Pillai's) observation was not acute or
else that language used by him was too general and his opinion such as
could be gathered from his language was open to question]. The fort-
nightly narrative should depict as accurately as possible the facts of the
fortnight. I am entirely in agreement with other officers in the district
that when harvest operations are over in March, it is to be expected that
there will be a considerable increase of workers on relief works. We are
quite prepared for such a contingency if the Public Works Department
officers have a sufficient number of subordinates in readiness. I fear
that there will be some difficulty about their subordinate staff, and
consider that early arrangements should be made to have a sufficient
number of subordinates in readiness.
The Collector of Cuddaph (The Hindu, dated April 10, 1897)
Here is a clear illustration of an ambiguous epistemic space in the realm
of famine administration in colonial south India at the end of the nine-
teenth century. Facts on the ground had to be accurately reported to the
higher authorities for governmental action. Statistics ensures accuracy if
they are accurate and there is no mechanism for checking accuracy in
such cases on the ground. Also in the absence of statistics being for-
warded by the lower level administration, ethnographic authority is sub-
stituted, in which the authority is that of one officer and of another of
“some standing” whose impressions based on such authority (presum-
ably also marked by race though unmentioned) is pitted against the im-
pressions of an obviously “native” officer who though may be honest did
not make an “acute” observation or used unconvincing language, and
whose report was not considered favorably only because his impression-
istic findings presented a gloomy agrarian situation. Even a more opti-
mistic report however is found wanting on account of lack of statistics.
Statistics clearly constructs the truth here.
In a similar vein, Arjun Appadurai calls the revenue documents as a
“prose of cadastral domination” that contained the internal debates of the
revenue bureaucracy on the pragmatics of rule formation and the rhetoric
Sovereignty and Governmentality 73
of utility along with the new technical practices, and were “composed
partly of rules, partly of orders, partly of appendices, and partly of letters
and petitions” whose manifest rhetoric is technical, but whose subtext is
contestatory in regard to superiors, and disciplinary in regard to inferi-
ors. 201
The foregoing substantiates Ann Stoler’s claim that the epistemic
practices of science and colonial governance share a common preoccupa-
tion of taming chance depending as interpretive communities on “rules
of reliability and trust, on an assumed common sense about what was
likely,” and figuring out governing strategies that could work based on
“sound conjecture and expectation.” 202 Conjecture or not, numbers were
more than a part of the colonial “imaginaire” enabling governing at a
distance, conferring a legitimacy to colonial governmentality, measuring
its performance, establishing domains of objectivity, and constituting a
new game of politics of calculation, opinion, and representation. 203 The
chapters that follow inquire into the conditions of the production of sta-
tistical knowledge by colonial governmentality considering the colonial
archive in the process of production, and organized around key epistem-
ic categories of space, time, measurement, classification, and causality.
NOTES
9. Henry Maine even argued that sovereignty was divisible. See “Minute by Sir
Henry Maine dated 22 March 1864 in Sever, Documents, Vol. 1, 251” in Ramusack, The
Indian Princes and Their States, 94.
10. Sen, Distant Sovereignty: National Imperialism and the Origins of British India.
11. Nicholas. B. Dirks, The Scandal of Empire: India and the Creation of Imperial Britain
(Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University, 2006).
12. Bentham defines political society as: “When a number of persons (whom we
may style subjects) are supposed to be in the habit of paying obedience to a person, or
an assemblage of persons, of a known and certain description (whom we may call
governor or governors) such persons altogether (subjects and governors) are said to be
in a state of political society.” See Jeremy Bentham, Fragment on Government in The
Works of Jeremy Bentham, vol. IV, ed. John Bowring (Edinburgh, 1859).
13. Thomas Babbington A. Macaulay, Speech delivered in the House of Commons,
July 10, 1833, reprinted in The Complete Works of Lord Macaulay 19, The Miscellaneous
Works (Philadelphia: The University Library Association, 1910), 162–63.
14. Foucault notes “To say that the problem of sovereignty is the central problem of
right in Western societies means that the essential function of the technique and dis-
course of right is to dissolve the element of domination in power and to replace that
domination, which has to be reduced or masked, with two things: the legitimate rights
of the sovereign on the one hand, and the legal obligation to obey on the other.” See
Foucault, Society Must be Defended, 26.
15. Charles Drekmeier, Kingship and Community in Early India (Stanford: Stanford
University Press, 1962), 251.
16. Ananda K. Coomaraswamy, Spiritual Authority and Temporal Power in the Indian
Theory of Government (New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers, 1978), 3. Origi-
nally published by American Oriental Society, New Haven, Connecticut, 1942.
17. Coomaraswamy, Spiritual Authority and Temporal Power in the Indian Theory of
Government, 63.
18. Coomaraswamy, Spiritual Authority and Temporal Power in the Indian Theory of
Government, 45–46 fn 34.
19. Georges Dumezil, Mitra-Varuna: An Essay on Two Indo-European Representations
of Sovereignty (New York: Zone Books, 1988).
20. For an understanding of the evolution of conceptions of kingship in England
that conceives the prince as possessing two bodies—a body natural and corruptible,
and a body politic and immortal, which is a landmark of Christian political theology,
read Ernst H. Kantorowicz, The King’s Two Bodies: A Study in Medieval Political Theology
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1957/1997).
21. Bhrigupati Singh, “The Headless Horseman of Central India: Sovereignty at
Varying Thresholds of Life,” Cultural Anthropology 27, 2 (2012): 383–407.
22. Varma, cited in Drekmeier, Kingship and Community in Early India, 261.
23. Duncan J. M. Derrett, “Rajadharma,” The Journal of Asian Studies 35, 4 (August
1976): 597–609; and Louis Dumont, “The Conception of Kingship in Ancient India,”
Contribution to Indian Sociology 6, (1962): 61–64.
24. Hartmut Scharfe, The State in Indian Tradition (Leiden/New York: E.J. Brill, 1989),
97.
25. Altekar disagrees with the view that the king is not incapable of doing or think-
ing wrong. He remarks that the king was regarded as being more exposed to errors
and temptations than ordinary human beings, nor was the king’s divinity construed as
necessitating passive obedience even to wicked kings. See A. S. Altekar, State and
Government in Ancient India (Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass, 1949), 94.
26. Muzaffar Alam and Sanjay Subrahmanyam, “Introduction” in The Mughal State
1526–1750, ed. Muzaffar Alam and Sanjay Subrahmanyam (Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 1998), 15.
27. Jyotsna G. Singh, Colonial Narratives/ Cultural Dialogues: “Discoveries” of India in
the Language of Colonialism (London: Routledge, 1996), 32–33.
28. Alam and Subrahmanyam, The Mughal State, 31.
Sovereignty and Governmentality 75
29. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament, 315.
30. John F. Richards, “The Formulation of Imperial Authority under Akbar and
Jahangir,” in The Mughal State 1526–1750, ed. Muzaffar Alam and Sanjay Subrahman-
yam (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998), 126–67.
31. Muzaffar Alam, The Crisis of Empire in Mughal North India: Awadh and the Punjab,
1707–48 (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1997).
32. Sudipta Kaviraj, “Modernity and Politics in India,” Daedalus 129, 1 (Winter
2000): 142.
33. Burton Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India (Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 1980).
34. Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India, 23.
35. Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India, 269.
36. Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India, 264.
37. Chapter VII “The Chola State and the Agrarian Order” in Stein, Peasant State and
Society in Medieval South India.
38. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament, 326.
39. Nicholas. B. Dirks, The Hollow Crown: Ethnohistory of an Indian Kingdom (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1987).
40. Dirks, The Hollow Crown.
41. Pamela G. Price, Kingship and Political Practice in Colonial India (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1996).
42. Wink explains fitna as follows: “As opposed to a purely military operation fitna
was at least a mixture of coercion and conciliation and characteristically implied inter-
vention in and making use of existing local conflicts. Fitna can be equated with the
political expedient of upajapa of the Indian Arthasastra, comprising conciliation, gift-
giving, sowing dissension among and ‘winning over’ of an enemy’s local supporters,
and involving the use of force only secondarily. . . . In India, as in all Islamic states,
sovereignty was primarily a matter of allegiances; the state organized itself around
conflict and remained essentially open-ended instead of becoming territorially circum-
scribed.” Such forms of sovereignty, characterized by dispersal through shifting com-
binations with local powerholders, have become alien to Europe and the modern state
in general, whose sovereignty is always expressed in terms of political territory and
not of allegiances. See Andre Wink, Land and Sovereignty in India: Agrarian Society and
Politics under the Eighteenth-Century Maratha Svarajya (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 1986), 27–28.
43. Wink, Land and Sovereignty in India, 34.
44. Bernard S. Cohn, “Political System in Eighteenth Century India: The Banaras
Region” in An Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays (Delhi: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1987/1990), 483–99.
45. Bernard S. Cohn, “The Initial British Impact on India: A Case Study of the
Benares Region,” The Journal of Asian Studies 19, 4 (Aug 1960): 418–31.
46. Richard G. Fox, Kin, Clan, Raja and Rule: State-Hinterland Relations in Pre-industri-
al India (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1971).
47. Appadurai notes that the unyoking of social groups from the complex and
localized group structures and agrarian practices occurred in two major steps—one
before 1870 in which issues of land settlement and taxation were dominant colonial
projects, and the other in the period of census 1870–1930. See Appadurai, “Number in
the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-Colonial Predicament, 326.
48. Paraphrased by Burke, “Speech in Reply”, (11:195) Cited in Frederick G. Whe-
lan, Edmund Burke and India: Political Morality and Empire (Pittsburgh, PA: University of
Pittsburgh Press, 1996), 233. Also see Edmund Burke, “Speech on Opening of Im-
peachment-1788 on 15th, 16th, 18th, and 19th Feb 1788” in The Writings and Speeches of
Edmund Burke vol. 6, ed. P.J. Marshall (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981), 264–471.
49. Whelan, Edmund Burke and India.
76 Chapter 1
76. Parekh, “Liberalism and Colonialism: A Critique of Locke and Mill” in The
Decolonization of Imagination: Culture, Knowledge and Power, 95–96.
77. Jennifer Pitts, “Legislator of the World? A Rereading of Bentham on Colonies,”
Political Theory 32 (2003): 200–34.
78. Burton Stein, Thomas Munro: The Origins of the Colonial State and His Vision of
Empire (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1989), 293.
79. Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India, 14.
80. Malcolm Political History, Vol II: 143. Cited in Stokes, The English Utilitarians and
India, 23.
81. Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India, 178.
82. James Mill, Testimony before Select Committee, 25 Aug, 1831. Cited in Lynn
Zastoupil, John Stuart Mill and India (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1994), 23.
83. Thomas R. Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj, The New Cambridge History of India III. 4
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 58.
84. Uday Singh Mehta, Liberalism and Empire: India in British Liberal Thought (New
Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1999), 35.
85. Karuna Mantena, Alibis of Empire: Henry Maine and the Ends of Liberal Imperialism
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010).
86. Mantena, Alibis of Empire, 5.
87. Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj, 224–225.
88. Letter of Curzon to Lytton, 29 August 1900. Cited in Robin J. Moore, “Curzon
and Indian Reform,” Modern Asian Studies 27, 4 (October 1993): 723–24.
89. William E. Connolly, “Beyond Good and Evil: The Ethical Sensibility of Michel
Foucault,” Political Theory 21, 3 (August 1993): 365–89.
90. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 14.
91. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 19.
92. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 20.
93. Bayly insists on the continuities between precolonial and colonial administra-
tion noting that the informational needs of precolonial states were directed to specific
rather than general aims. See Bayly, Empire and Information, 20–23.
94. Ranajit Guha, Dominance without Hegemony: History and Power in Colonial India
(Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998). Originally published by Harvard University
Press.
95. Nancy L. Rosenblum, Bentham’s Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1978).
96. L. J. Hume, “Jeremy Bentham and the Nineteenth-Century Revolution in
Government,” in Jeremy Bentham: Critical Assessments vol. 3, ed. Bhikhu Parekh (New
York: Routledge, 1993), 823–25.
97. Hume, “Jeremy Bentham and the Nineteenth-Century Revolution in Govern-
ment,” in Jeremy Bentham: Critical Assessments vol. 3, 826–29.
98. B. B. Schaffer, “The Idea of the Ministerial Department: Bentham, Mill and Bage-
hot,” in Jeremy Bentham: Critical Assessments, vol. 3, ed. Bhikhu Parekh (New York:
Routledge, 1993), 839–40.
99. Bhikhu Parekh, “When Will the State Wither Away?” Alternatives: Global, Local,
Political 15, 3 (Summer 1990): 247–62.
100. Bartelson, A Genealogy of Sovereignty, 188–89.
101. Mark Neocleous, Imagining the State (Maidenhead, Berkshire: Open University
Press, 2003), 5.
102. Corrigan and Sayer, The Great Arch , 6–7. Cited in Cohn and Dirks, “Beyond the
Fringe.”
103. Don Handelman, Models and Mirrors: Towards an Anthropology of Public Events
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1990); and Herzfeld, Anthropology: Theoreti-
cal Practice in Culture and Society, 266–67.
104. Cohn and Dirks, “Beyond the Fringe,” 226.
105. For Don Handelman this panoptic principle renders possible the association of
spectacle and bureaucracy. In the metalogic of presentation, Handelman notes that
78 Chapter 1
124. Foucault has observed that at the end of the eighteenth century, political
thought discovered “society” as a complex and independent reality that has its own
laws and mechanisms of reaction, its regulation as well as its possibilities of distur-
bance and that has to be manipulated by techniques of “government” rather than
being penetrated by “police.” See Michel Foucault, “Space, Knowledge and Power,” in
The Foucault Reader, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: Pantheon Books, 1984), 242.
125. Michel Foucault, “The Birth of Biopolitics,” in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed.
Paul Rabinow (New York: The New Press, 1997), 75.
126. See Chapter 2, “Populations and Political Society” in Partha Chatterjee, The
Politics of the Governed (New York: Columbia University Press, 2004), 27–51.
127. Foucault, “The Birth of Biopolitics,” in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth , 76–77.
128. Bruce Curtis has pointed out that Foucault did not follow the explanatory tactic
of relating population as an object of political government to the development of
large-scale practices of social observation and recording when he became concerned
with governmentality. Instead population was situated in the field of “political rea-
son.” See Curtis, “Foucault on Governmentality and Population: The Impossible Dis-
covery,” 511.
129. Curtis, “Foucault on Governmentality and Population: The Impossible Discov-
ery.”
130. Mary Poovey, Making a Social Body: British Cultural Formation 1830–1864 (Chica-
go: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 3.
131. Thomas Richards, The Imperial Archive: Knowledge and the Fantasy of Empire (Lon-
don: Verso, 1993).
132. John Guillory defines “information” as any given datum of cognitive experience
that can be materially encoded for the purpose of transmission or storage and “knowl-
edge” organizes masses of information or data into complex structures of intelligibility
and uses these structures to discover new relations and new facts. See Guillory, “The
Memo and Modernity,” 110. This notion of “information” is closer to the “modern
fact” of Poovey. See Mary Poovey, A History of the Modern Fact: Problems of Knowledge
in the Sciences of Wealth and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1998). See
also Richards, The Imperial Archive.
133. Stoler, Along the Archival Grain, 20.
134. Cohn, Colonialism and its Forms of Knowledge, 3.
135. Cohn, Colonialism and its Forms of Knowledge, 3–4.
136. G. Sutherland, “Introduction,” in Studies in the Growth of Nineteenth Century
Government, ed. G. Sutherland (London: Routledge, 1972), 6–8.
137. Poovey, Making a Social Body, 114.
138. Schaffer, “The Idea of the Ministerial Department.”
139. John Torrance, “Social Class and Bureaucratic Innovation: The Commissioners
for Examining the Public Accounts 1780–1787,” Past and Present 78 (February 1978):
56–81.
140. Torrance, “Social Class and Bureaucratic Innovation,” 68.
141. Hume, “Jeremy Bentham and the Nineteenth-Century Revolution in Govern-
ment,” 826. Hacking points out that the Swedes too had been compiling annual re-
ports within the framework of the parish and were considered the best available
statistics for late eighteenth century Europe, but it is the French who have to be
credited for their achievement of “secular” numbers, which is a Bonapartic legacy. See
Ian Hacking, “Bio-Power and the Avalanche of Printed Numbers,” Humanities in Soci-
ety 5, 3–4, (1982): 286.
142. Eastwood, “Amplifying the Province of the Legislation,” 276–277. Hugh Mc Dowall
Clokie and William J. Robinson note “Not only did the number, size, and circulation of
parliamentary papers increase many fold in the first third of the nineteenth century,
but by the middle of the century the annual product was far greater than in all the
centuries before 1800.” See Hugh McDowall Clokie and William J. Robinson, Royal
Commissions of Inquiry: The Significance of Investigations in British Politics (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 1937), 54.
80 Chapter 1
189. Bernard S. Cohn, “The Command of Language and the Language of Com-
mand,” in Subaltern Studies IV: Writings on South Asian History and Society, ed. Ranajit
Guha (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1985), 280.
190. Stoler, “Colonial Archives and the Arts of Governance,” 98.
191. Michael T. Clanchy, “Does Writing Construct the State?” Journal of Historical
Sociology 15, 1 (March 2002): 68.
192. Nair observes about the awesome power of the bureaucratic signature in a
postcolonial state—“this fact of signing, and notably signing in all three of Derrida’s
modes, commands a special resonance in any postcolonial society. . . . In any bureau-
cratic culture, such as India’s, a signature carries legendary authority. Signatures are
manifestations not just of personhood, of a singular subjectivity, but the seal of an
absolute and unknowable deified ‘other’.” See Rukmini Bhaya Nair, Lying on the Post-
colonial Couch: The Idea of Indifference (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
2002), 37. In a different vein, Veena Das notes that governance through technologies of
writing institutes the possibility of forgery, imitation, and the mimetic performances
of its power. See Veena Das, “The Signature of the State: The Paradox of Illegibility,”
in Anthropology in the Margins of the State, ed. Veena Das and Deborah Poole (Santa Fe,
NM: School of American Research Press, 2004), 225–52.
193. Stoler, Along the Archival Grain, 33.
194. Stoler, Along the Archival Grain, 48.
195. See “The Statement and the Archive” in Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge,
79–124.
196. Stoler, “Colonial Archives and the Arts of Governance,” 92–99.
197. Stoler, Along the Archival Grain, 43.
198. Richard Saumarez Smith, “Rule by Records and Rule by Reports: Complemen-
tary Aspects of the British Imperial Rule of Law,” Contributions to Indian Sociology 19,1,
(1985): 153–176.
199. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia, 326.
200. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia, 319.
201. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia,321.
202. Stoler, Along the Archival Grain, 42.
203. For the role of numbers in modern government, read chapter 6 “Numbers” in
Nikolas Rose, Powers of Freedom, 197–232. For the role of numbers in colonial imagina-
tion, read Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the
Post-Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia.
TWO
The Production of Space
83
84 Chapter 2
Henri Lefebvre has brought to our awareness that space is not an “aprori
category” or a “mental construct” but is itself produced within social
practices even as it shapes those practices. Thus the state and each of its
constituent institutions call for spaces, which they can organize according
to their specific requirements. 7 The space of the modern state is the ab-
stract space, and although this abstract space is not homogeneous, it has
homogeneity as its goal and hence attempts to reduce all differences
within that space. It is formal and quantitative, erases distinctions, and
functions objectally as a set of things/signs and their formal relationships.
Its abstraction is neither transparent, nor can it be reduced either to a
logic or to a strategy. 8 Abstract space is also universalizable like Fou-
cault’s space of “Utopia,” which are “fundamentally unreal spaces,”
“sites with no places” that are universalized and made abstract, while
heterotopias are real places with unique characteristics that are not “natu-
ral” to them but are products of ideological practices. 9 But abstract space
carries within it the seeds of a new kind of space, a “differential space”
that accentuates differences. The modern notion of space contrasts the
medieval conception of space, which was restricted to “the space of em-
placement” and to “a hierarchic ensemble of places” without any signifi-
The Production of Space 85
Indeed the rational production of abstract space and the rational proce-
dures of modern governance are mutually implicated, as new political
rationalities emerged with the rise of the modern state. Such a space
facilitates governance in modern ways through rules, procedures, bu-
reaucracy, and accountability; and a new set of power relations, with
86 Chapter 2
The processes by which the colonial state organized its spaces of ad-
ministration marked a movement from historical space to abstract space
and the creation of functional sites and spaces of political economy. Ab-
stract spaces that were produced contained their contradictions in the
various functional sites that made the emergence of differential space
imminent; but more remarkable was the resistance to the abstract spaces
and functional sites by those subjected to the authority of the colonial
state and their attempts to reinstate place, which provided them the secur-
ities of emplacement and identity. Such resistance in due course became
subdued as the governance of colonial conduct in an improving direction
rendered the functional sites as loci of knowledge that made apparent the
telos of “progress” and the success of the colonial project.
In the early stages of the formation of the modern colonial state “terri-
tory” became an object of knowledge in order to constitute it as a “reve-
nue state,” and knowing the territory entailed an epistemological con-
quest. As governmentality progressively replaced territoriality, it became
necessary to delineate aggregates of population in demarcated spaces.
Thus the construction and deployment of new political technologies as
part of the new political rationalities introduced by colonial governance
entailed the reconstitution of space. 21
Precolonial states had also produced their spaces by delineating their
territories, measuring lands through techniques they thought would
yield accurate measurements, and even drew maps that fulfilled their
cognitive requirements. For instance, wherever the Mughal emperor Ak-
bar traveled, distances were recorded and superintendents and inspec-
tors audited pole-measurements by surveyors and their calculations. But
mapping culture in the modern sense of a representational instrument
facilitating measurement, inquiry and examination simultaneously did
not exist in India prior to the colonial mapping efforts, even if maps were
produced by both Hindu and Arab geographers. Pre-modern maps were
territorial representations but modern maps could represent populations
as well, and the carto-statistical techniques that evolved along with the
modern maps to facilitate measurement, inquiry and examination simul-
taneously could bring abstract spaces and functional sites within the epis-
temic gaze.
Colonial surveying and mapping was, however, not a one-time effort.
Rather, it evolved over a period of more than a hundred years during
which time, as Mathew Edney has shown, it underwent certain epistemo-
logical shifts in the construction of geographic knowledge. Its discursive
history reveals not merely the burdens of introducing Western scientific
methods that were purportedly more rational but also the complex con-
structions of an imperialist “Self” that was marked out to be very differ-
ent from the colonial “Other.” 22 Partha Chatterjee has noted that colonial
rule was compelled to produce the truth of colonial “difference” within
the “universalist” frameworks of knowledge. 23 The obsessive concern for
88 Chapter 2
Kanara in 1800 was founded upon geometrical certainty and truth, the
standards of accuracy often varied.
Laying the grid of triangles and filling in the triangles with the topo-
graphical details does not complete the process of producing the abstract
space; it merely renders natural space into Euclidean space, which makes
the vastly different lived places commensurable on a uniform grid of
space and capable of being visually represented. To become the locus and
site of state power the visual representation of space has to create an
aggressive visual effect that such a space can be manipulated and con-
trolled, which the Euclidean space affords by erasing the autonomy of
places.
Whereas the rationale of the governing structures of precolonial states
in India sought to retain the significance of place through ties of lineage
and community with kingship, the colonial state in contrast sought to
both create a smooth space of economic exchange and to govern the
conduct of colonial subjects and so set in place structures of governance
to achieve these ends. 40 The spaces and sites shaped by the colonial state
required not just the presence of the state but were to be rendered amen-
able for the measurement of progress.
The colonial state sought to institute itself in its political space primarily
as a revenue state, though it sought to reorganize other spaces such as
urban towns and new functional sites as well. The conduct of the revenue
surveys enabled the colonial state to institute itself most decisively in its
political space and in doing so it completed the production of abstract
space and generated knowledge of village India necessary for administer-
ing it. Since the very inception of their rule, the British imposed a grid of
official categories over the network of agrarian relations as the delinea-
tion of property rights and the constitution of private property in land
along with revenue appropriation were the spatial strategies of colonial
revenue governance. 41 The manner in which a new space of appropria-
tion and knowledge thereof was produced illustrates how colonial
governmentality devised technologies of control through science, objec-
tification and rationality often resulting in a conflict between different
knowledge epistemes in its attempt to reinstate a new regime of power
and knowledge. The rhetoric of accuracy became shrill in the conduct of
the revenue surveys in the debates over the use of survey methods and
the indigenous measurement practices.
The violence of the state represents the intrusive power of the state to
control and manipulate the space to achieve desired ends. Colonial vio-
lence was first expressed in conquering the territory and acquiring the
necessary information to rationalize its extractive procedures. But the
The Production of Space 95
was the first of its kind for procuring the knowledge of the “real value of
any part of the Company’s possessions on the coast.” 45
The reliability of gathering information through surveys and from
drawing information from existing accounts was to become an issue of
contention. Surveys were not accepted as the best principle right from the
beginning. There was a lengthy debate between the Bengal government
and the Court of Directors on this issue when in 1801 the districts of
Oudh and Rohilkhand and in 1803 that of Cuttack came under the Com-
pany’s possessions. The efficacy of survey methods versus reliance on the
existing records of revenue accounts were debated when the Court of
Directors were not in favor of an extension of the permanent settlement
(fixing land revenues in perpetuity with zamindars who acted as revenue
farmers) in these districts as in the case of Bengal and wanted a scrutiny
of individual rights. 46 The directors wanted a “minute and detailed sur-
vey” of the extent, cultivation, and productive powers of the territory
taking into account the local peculiarities. 47 The Bengal government, on
the other hand, felt that revenue assessments were not being fixed merely
by a few years’ experience, but from the accounts of the Zamindars (large
landowners), the Kanungoes (revenue accountants), and the Patwarries
(keeper of village records), and that these native institutions had existed
even prior to the British rule, and that although the village accounts
should be received with circumspection, much greater confidence can be
reposed in them because they are not easily falsified or fabricated than
the accounts of local surveys and valuations made almost exclusively by
the agency of native officers. 48 The Court of Directors refused to accept
these arguments as in their opinion the accounts kept by native revenue
officers were for the most part fallacious and were of the opinion that
only a regular revenue survey can solve the numerous boundary dis-
putes that have arisen on account of the “undefined state of property
with respect to limits.” 49
Soon the instrumentality of survey was accepted as the best method to
verify and collect information on property rights, and the revenue collec-
tors in the Madras Presidency were asked in 1805 to proceed with a
survey of their respective districts. The earlier general district surveys
conducted by the assistant revenue surveyors were considered untrust-
worthy for revenue purposes, which as Bentinck noted had not “been
laid down by men of science,” and being done by the natives were
“equally liable to error from want of honesty and from want of knowl-
edge.” 50 The debate over surveys also highlighted a significant issue of
contention in the shaping of the colonial state that pitted the Burkeans
with the Utilitarians as to the efficacy and desirability of retaining the
older institutions that were already in existence in some form or to dis-
card them altogether and reinstate a new set of institutions for revenue
administration. 51 A few years later Thomas Munro, the architect of the
ryotwari system (revenue settlement directly with the cultivators) while
The Production of Space 97
arguing the case for including natives in the civil administration, who can
supply all the necessary information, noted the importance of collecting
detailed information when he remarked:
We ought, therefore not to be satisfied with a superficial knowledge of
the general state of the country, but make it a part of our system to
obtain the most minute and accurate information concerning its inter-
nal condition, and preserve and accumulate that information in clear
and detailed revenue accounts and statistical statements. 52
Sometimes the enthusiasm for collecting detailed information far ex-
ceeded their utility. For instance, in 1810 Hawkins, who was asked to
survey the Oarts situated in the Bombay and Salsette Islands, received
instructions to “ascertain the number of Coconut, Brab, Date, or Betelnut
trees in each Oart, the proprietors of them, their quantities, and whether
the trees were used for distillation for the sale of the Liquor in the crude
state, or whether the trees were allowed to run to fruit, the average num-
ber of Coconuts produced annually by each Coconut tree, and for how
many years they continue to be productive.” 53 His successor Dickenson
who took over from Hawkins in 1812 submitted a plan that was suppos-
edly comprehensive for every revenue purpose. The plan showed not
only “the exact contents and boundaries of each estate, but every species
of property, and was accompanied by two books, one for registering the
tenures, and containing the rental amounts of every part of the Island
that was let out on lease, and the other book was a census specifying the
number of men, women, and children by caste.” 54 A few years later, the
Bengal Council thought the Bombay system was too elaborate and expen-
sive, and so sought for a simpler procedure.
Surveys not only instituted a panoptic gaze, but also brought different
knowledge practices into conflict that indicates that there were indeed
different ways of imagining land between the colonial and precolonial
rulers. Despite the historical evidence that suggested that different kinds
of rights on land existed though often in an attenuated form depending
on the degree of social control, the colonial administrators assumed as an
almost universal truth the absence of private property in land in the
East. 55 The different ways of imagining land reflected the different mo-
dalities of control over land, and the practices of control over land shaped
in turn the popular imagination. Rulers in the precolonial era made gifts
of revenue-free land, to Brahmans and other subjects in return for various
services of loyalty to the king. Here I illustrate from a particular land
deed the lack of precision in the measurements of such gifted land and
the kind of moral rather than bureaucratic control of such land that was
established. A translation of the land deed notes:
All the land that belongs to us, together with the Yalichi tank, west-
ward from the Arali tree, lying on the east side of the Yalichi tank, as
far as the tamarind tree on the edge of the cultivated ground.
98 Chapter 2
The land deed ends with a Sanskrit verse, which translated as follows:
He who seizes on the wealth yielding land* given either by himself or
by another, shall be born a worm in dung for sixty thousand years--Of
the two acts, giving and protecting that which has been given, protec-
tion excels gift; by gift the lower heaven is obtained, by protecting that
which has been given, an exalted station from there is no descent.
(*Land productive: land allowed to become waste by the negligence or
inability of the holder may be resumed without incurring sin.) 56
In most instances, land was held in common by village communities and
in some areas land rotation was practiced, such that no fixed plot of
cultivable land was assigned to an individual as an alienable or inalien-
able right. The fluidities in land assignments matched with the fluidities
in land classifications that varied seasonally or annually and diverse
measurement practices coexisted.
The conflicts between knowledge practices that colonial control over
land brought forth did not always ensure the victory of European meth-
ods. Particularly with the revenue surveys, the European and indigenous
methods remained juxtaposed rather uneasily, unlike the topographical
and trigonometrical surveys that entailed the application of modern sci-
entific principles and measurements. The ways in which these conflicts
were resolved indicate how differences were erased or remained resilient
in the production of abstract space. If homogeneity is the goal of abstract
space, its production entails unifying divergent spaces, thus leading to
the erasing of many kinds of differences between them, what James Scott
calls as “state simplification” and “legibility.” 57 The differences that the
colonial state encountered in producing its political space were those
relating to diversities in land tenure arrangements and in the practices of
measurement and classification. Scott makes a distinction between state
and nonstate forms of measurement, the latter arising from the logic of
local practice, and scientific surveys became a metaphor for erasing those
differences of local practices. 58
The revenue surveys sought to introduce measurements that were
deemed more rational, and although not fully successful, uniform meas-
ures and standard classifications. Let us consider the case of the adoption
of a standard measure for land. In October 1800, Munro instituted a
survey of some of the ceded districts covering Bellary, Kurnool, Ananta-
pur, and Cuddapah for purposes of revenue assessment. All lands of
whatever kind including roads, sites of towns and villages, bed of tanks
and rivers, and wastes and jungles were for the first time measured using
a standard measure, a chain of thirty-three feet, forty of which made an
“acre.” Out of this survey Munro evolved a Code that was followed
during the introduction of the ryotwari settlements in the 1820s suggest-
ing that the “acre” as the scale of measure be adopted not only in the
English accounts but in all the native village accounts as well. Given the
The Production of Space 99
diversities in measures not only in the various districts but even between
the villages in a district, Munro was of the opinion that it did not really
matter what uniform scale was adopted as the inhabitants would soon
figure out for themselves the difference between their scales and the stan-
dard one. 59 The colonial state thus restructured the fuzziness and vari-
ability in indigenous measurement practices as it sought to institute its
hegemony.
Apart from the question of introducing an English unit of measure in
the village accounts there were other differences as well. While the prin-
ciples of the “native” survey were purely geometrical, those of the Euro-
pean surveys used trigonometrical methods for the calculations of areas.
Not only were the principles of the two kinds of surveys at variance, the
native surveys were always doubted for their reliability. The unreliability
of the native systems and of the natives themselves became a discursive
tactic in the attempt to both assert the superiority of the English methods
and to impose greater control. Although it was felt that surveys under-
taken for revenue purposes should be directed by European surveyors
under the professional control of the surveyor general, the indigenous
system could not be done away with, as it was economical, and the in-
dexation of village plots in the native surveys were far more useful for
revenue purposes. The two surveys needed to be integrated, the village
boundaries generally being done by a professional survey using Euro-
pean methods and by a European surveyor, and the khasrah surveys
which were the field surveys of the village done by indigenous methods
with native measurers. In actual practice, the Khasrah surveys were car-
ried out with little reference to the professional survey that it was later
decided that the professional surveyor was to hold charge of both the
professional control survey and the detailed khasrah, or field survey. A
Khasrah survey was usually done with bamboo rods, nals, or with chains
or ropes, jaribs. Areas were taken out by simple geometry in bighas or
other units and its primary task was an exact survey of the boundaries of
estates or plots, belonging to an owner or a group of owners.It was so
constructed as to enable a person at once to find in it any field. Each field
had a number corresponding to, which was an entry in the khusruh show-
ing the size, the occupant, and the nature of the soil, the crop, and the
rent.
Most of these early surveys proved useless for revenue assessment
and collection for officials from outside the village, as there was a signifi-
cant blockade of information flow from local officials to the headquarter
as the surveys did not define field boundaries. When the settlement sur-
veys were taken up in 1871, the surveys were carried out entirely anew in
the form of cadastral, or field-to-field survey, as it was decided that reve-
nue surveys should be connected by minor triangulation with the trigo-
nometrical survey to ensure accuracy and permanence.
100 Chapter 2
habits meant that the attempts to produce the abstract space contained
within it certain contradictions that signified the emergence of a differen-
tial space. Cognizing such differential space that was bound to the local
idioms and traditions prompted the peasantry in numerous instances to
resist the colonial state and its brutality. 63 Resistance signifies the pres-
ence of power and it suggests that the abstract space serves more than
metaphoric roles of state power, acting especially as a “means of con-
straint.” 64
The space the colonial state sought to produce was the instrumental
space which it can control, manage, regulate, and appropriate according
to its principles of governance. In the evolving imperialist world econo-
my of the nineteenth century in which colonial states were facilitators, the
political space that they sought to produce was one where both the accu-
mulation rationality and the state rationality were conjoined. The produc-
tion of this space entailed demarcating boundaries and locating places in
a grid of scientific precision in an attempt to create a fetishized space
reductive of differences that would increasingly serve important roles in
the evolving world economy of exchange and accumulation. Within this
fetishized space, particular spaces were demarcated and hierarchized,
and made manageable to control and negotiation. The underlying princi-
ple was to reconstitute divergent spaces in homogeneity, so that the state
could hegemonize them under its centralizing control. Hence, local diver-
sities in measurement and classification were rendered uniform. The rev-
enue surveys exemplify how the accumulation rationality was implicated
in the production of abstract space, for the definition of property was at
The Production of Space 105
its core. Further the practices of appropriation of the colonial state were
suffused with the discourses of scientific rationality. Simultaneously, this
same space was fragmented and fractured in accordance with the de-
mands of the division of labor and of the division of needs and functions.
This abstract space is not only quantifiable as geometrical space, but
as a social and administered space too, it is subject to quantitative manip-
ulation. Often the qualitative aspects of social space resist absorption by
the quantitative because social spaces as representational spaces are “di-
rectly lived through its associated images and symbols, and hence the
space of inhabitants.” 84 This was most evident in the sphere of colonial
urban governmentality where “place-making” as resistance were even
incorporated in governmental problematizations. 85 New “norms and
forms” that were introduced as part of urban planning and served as a
technology of social control carried assumptions that were vastly differ-
ent for the British colonial administrators and for the Indians. 86 While
roads were for the colonial administrators a signifier of mobility (espe-
cially for the rapid movement of troops and raw materials), for the In-
dians the street was “a public space with social and recreational func-
tions.” 87
The divergent perceptions of space by the colonial administrators and
the colonial subjects locate the contradictions of abstract space by reveal-
ing two imminent features. One, the reinstitution of place as experienced
by the colonial subjects themselves in the imaginaire of the colonial state,
and secondly a different order of fragmentation and hierarchy of the
abstract space that the colonial subjects felt was less brutal to their experi-
ences. Such contradictions of space were most explicit in the numerous
functional sites of governance created by the colonial state and the norms
and regulations that ordered those sites. No doubt spatial practices resist
being fitted into geometrically rigorous grids and be made homogeneous
especially when the space of inhabitants is filled with images and sym-
bols that bestow meanings to them. The new social spaces created by the
colonial state such as the spaces of sanitary regimes were amenable to
geometric representations in the form of maps even as the population
resisted being circumscribed to those spaces by the colonial strategies of
epidemic and public health management.
Mimetic representations of maps generally attempt to stabilize essen-
tialist views of the world reinforcing the privilege and the dominant
position of the authorizing power. Jose Rabasa has noted that critiques of
colonial cartographic discourse seek a working alliance between “decon-
struction as a process of displacement which registers an attempted dis-
sociation from a dominant discursive system and decolonization as a
process of cultural transformation, which involves the ongoing critique of
colonial discourse.” 88 Such a process of displacement and decolonization
was effected by nationalist imaginations of the nation through the de-
ployment of cartographic images of India by turning maps into body-
106 Chapter 2
NOTES
1. Ainslee T. Embree, “Frontiers into Boundaries: From the Traditional to the Mod-
ern State,” in Realm and Region in Traditional India, ed. Richard G. Fox (New Delhi:
Vikas Publishing House, 1977), 256–57.
2. Matthew H. Edney, Mapping an Empire: The Geographical Construction of British
India, 1765–1843 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1997), 333.
3. Stuart Elden, “Governmentality, Calculation, Territory,” Environment and Plan-
ning D: Society and Space, 25 (2007): 563. Elden thinks it is not a shift in accent but both
a substitution and a change in Foucault’s preoccupation.
4. Latour, Science in Action; and Rose, Powers of Freedom.
5. Benedict R. Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread
of Nationalism. (London: Verso, 1983/ 1991); and Thongchai Winichakul, Siam Mapped:
A History of the Geo-Body of a Nation (Honolulu: University of Hawaii Press, 1994).
6. Edney, Mapping an Empire.
7. Henri Lefebvre, The Production of Space, trans. Donald Nicholson Smith (Cam-
bridge: Basil Blackwell, 1991).
8. Lefebvre clarifies:
Coinciding neither with the abstraction of the sign, nor with that of the
concept, it operates negatively. Abstract space relates negatively to that
which perceives and underpins it—namely, the historical and religio-politi-
cal spheres. It also relates negatively to something which it carries within
itself and which seeks to emerge from it: a differential space-time. It has
nothing of a “subject” about it, yet it acts like a subject in that it transports
and maintains specific social relations, dissolves others and stands opposed
to yet others. It functions positively vis-à-vis its own implications: technolo-
gy, applied sciences, and knowledge bound to power. Abstract space may
even be described as at once, and inseparably, the locus, medium and tool
of this “positivity.”
See Lefebvre, The Production of Space, 50.
9. Michel Foucault, “Of Other Spaces,” Unrevised text of a lecture given in March
1967. Trans. Jay Miskowiee Diacritics 16, 1 (Spring 1986): 22–27.
10. Foucault, “Of Other Spaces,” 22–27.
11. Edward S. Casey, “Smooth Spaces and Rough-Edged Places: The Hidden Histo-
ry of Place,” The Review of Metaphysics 51, 2 (1997): 291.
12. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish (New York: Vintage Books, 1977), 193,
197, 227, 231.
13. Foucault, Discipline and Punish , 204, 205, 243.
14. Poovey, Making a Social Body, 27.
15. David Harvey, The Condition of Postmodernity (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1989).
16. Johannes Fabian, Time and the Other: How Anthropology Makes its Object (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1983).
17. Rose, Powers of Freedom, 32.
The Production of Space 107
18. Michel Foucault, “Security, Territory, and Population” in Ethics: Subjectivity and
Truth, ed. Paul Rabinow (New York: The New Press, 1997), 67–71. Cited in Elden,
“Governmentality, Calculation, Territory,” 565.
19. Cohn, Colonialism and its Forms of Knowledge.
20. Rose, Powers of Freedom, 38–39.
21. Michel Foucault, Technologies of the Self: A Seminar with Michel Foucault, ed. L. H.
Martin, H. Gutman and P. H. Hutton (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press,
1988).
22. Edney, Mapping an Empire, 316–317.
23. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments.
24. Bayly, Empire and Information, 10.
25. Bayly, Empire and Information, 20–21.
26. Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India, 367–368.
27. Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India.
28. Michael Biggs, “Putting the State on the Map: Cartography, Territory and Euro-
pean State Formation,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 41, 2 (April 1999): 374.
29. Chandra Mukerji, From Gravern Images: Patterns of Modern Materialism (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1983); and J. B. Harley, “Maps, Knowledge and
Power,” in The Iconography of Landscape: Essays on the Symbolic Representation, Design
and Use of Past Environments, ed. Denis Cosgrove and Stephen Daniels (New York:
Cambridge University Press, 1988), 277–312.
30. For a lucid account of how the project of geography and information gathering
were linked in colonial India, read Ludden, “Orientalist Empiricism: Transformation
of Colonial Knowledge.” For particular emphasis on the work of Colin Mackenzie,
and the politics associated with the writing of new histories and the denial of historic-
ity and the erasure of the histories of the colonized, read Nicholas B. Dirks, “Colonial
Histories and Native Informants: Biography of an Archive” in Orientalism and the
Postcolonial Predicament, ed. Carol Breckenridge and Peter van der Veer (Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 1993), 279–313.
31. See the chapter on the Akbari Measure of distance called “The Karoh or Kos” in
Abul-Fazl Allami, The A-IN-I Akbari, vol II, trans. H. Blochmann (Delhi: Low Price
Publications, (1927–1949/1988). Original publication date unknown.
32. K. Sivaramakrishnan, “Colonialism and Forestry in India: Imagining the Past in
Present Politics,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 37, 1 (January, 1995): 3–40.
33. R. H. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India vol. 11, 1800 to 1815
(Dehradun: Survey of India, 1950), 251.
34. Sven Widmalm, “Accuracy, Rhetoric, and Technology: The Paris Greenwich
Triangulation, 1784–88,” in The Quantifying Spirit in the 18th Century, ed. Tore Frang-
smyr, J. L. Heilbron, and Robin. E. Rider (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1990), 179–206.
35. Gloria Goodwin Raheja,”The Ajaib-Gher and the Gun Zam-Zammah: Colonial
Ethnography and the Elusive Politics of ‘Tradition’ in the Literature of the Survey of
India,” South Asia Research 19, 1 (1999): 29–51.
36. Bayly, Empire and Information, 56.
37. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11.
38. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 91.
39. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 92.
40. Arjun Appadurai, Worship and Conflict under Colonial Rule (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1980); Alam, The Crisis of Empire in Mughal North India; Alam
and Subrahmanyam, “Introduction” in The Mughal State 1526–1750; Cohn, An Anthro-
pologist among Historians and Other Essays; Dirks, The Hollow Crown: Ethnohistory of an
Indian Kingdom, Fox, Kin, Clan, Raja and Rule: State-Hinterland Relations in Pre-industrial
India; Stein, Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India, and Wink, Land and Sove-
reignty in India among others deal with the nature of precolonial states in India and
their governing rationales and structures.
108 Chapter 2
41. Richard Saumarez Smith, Rule by Records: Land Registration and Village Custom in
Early British Panjab (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1996); and B.H. Baden-Powell,
Administration of Land Revenue and Tenure in British India (New Delhi: Ess Ess Publica-
tions, 1978). Originally published in 1907.
42. Captain Read’s first report of the Colar District dated January 1792. Manuscript,
Madras Records Office.
43. Letter to Governor-general Cornwallis by Alexander Read dated 15th Novem-
ber, 1792. The Baramahal Records, Section I–Management.
44. Report, No. XXVI appended to the letter to David Haliburton, President and
Members of Revenue Board by Alexander Read, dated 10th August 1794. The Barama-
hal Records, Section I–Management.
45. Extract of letter from the Honorable Court of Directors dated 4th October 1797
appended to the letter to Colonel Read by I. Webb, Secretary to Government, Fort St.
George dated 12th May 1798. The Baramahal Records, Section I–Management.
46. Ranajit Guha, A Rule of Property for Bengal: An Essay on the Idea of Permanent
Settlement (Paris: Mouton, 1963).
47. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 178.
48. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 178.
49. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 178.
50. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 179.
51. Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India; Burton Stein, “Idiom and Ideology in
Early Nineteenth Century South India,” in Rural India: Land, Power and Society under
British Rule, ed. Peter Robb (London: Curzon Press, 1983), 23–58; and Stein, Thomas
Munro.
52. Minute of Sir Thomas Munro presented along with Extract Revenue Letter to
Fort St. George dated 29th September 1824. Selections of Papers from the Records at the
East-India House- Revenue, Police, Civil, and Criminal Justice, Company’s Government in
India, Vol. II, 1826.
53. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11, 186.
54. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India, vol. 11,186.
55. Dharma Kumar, “A Note on the Term ‘Land Control,” in Rural India: Land,
Power and Society under British Rule, ed. Peter Robb (London: Curzon Press, 1983),
59–75; Dharma Kumar, Colonialism, Property and the State (Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 1996); Peter Robb, “Land and Society: The British ‘Transformation’ in India” in
Rural India: Land, Power and Society under British Rule, ed.Peter Robb (London: Curzon
Press, 1983), 1–22; and Jacques Pouchepadass, “Land, Power and Market: The Rise of
the Land Market in Gangetic India” in Rural India: Land, Power and Society under British
Rule, ed. Peter Robb (London: Curzon Press, 1983), 76–105.
56. This land deed was contained in the Appendix of Replies from Mr. F.W. Ellis,
Collector of Madras to the Mirasi Questions, dated 30th May, 1816.
57. Scott, Seeing like a State.
58. Scott, Seeing like a State, 25.
59. Minute of Sir Thomas Munro, President, Board of Revenue. Extract Fort St.
George Revenue Consultations dated 14th May 1822. Selections of Papers from the
Records at the East-India House- Revenue, Police, Civil, and Criminal Justice, Company’s
Government in India, Vol. II, 1826.
60. R. H. Phillimore, Historical Records of the Survey of India vol. IV, 1830 to 1843
(Dehradun: Survey of India, 1958), 206.
61. Smith, Rule by Records, 21.
62. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia, 324.
63. Ranajit Guha has shown that the peasantry experienced colonial power and
brutality often not directly as state intervention but by the realignment of the state and
landlord power. Peasant resistances also highlighted peasant notions of territoriality
and indeed alternate conceptions of the state as well. See Ranajit Guha, Elementary
Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983).
The Production of Space 109
RECONSTITUTING CHRONOLOGY
Since gaining control over temporal frameworks that organize social life
is important for achieving dominance, ensuring the comparability of dif-
Temporalities, Routines of Rule, and History 113
ferent eras has always been of concern to the rulers, so as to enable them
to master and govern a new realm of territory, people and things. British
colonial power too had to contend with the issue of chronology to evolve
its regulatory frameworks, as at the beginning of the colonial period there
were thirteen calendrical systems in what was then identified as the In-
dian subcontinent. 8
Chronology is one of the basic aspects of time-consciousness of society
signifying an awareness of the sequential flow of time, the ability to
locate events in a temporal framework, and of the possibility of retrieving
memory into history. Reinhart Koselleck has noted that chronology bor-
rowed from natural time is “indispensable for a historical reality that is to
be redeemed empirically, whether approximation to the absolute exact-
ness of data establishes meaning, or whether the cogency of the relative
before and after, which is unalterable in itself, is the prerequisite for a
meaningful reconstruction of historical events.” 9 The collapse of the short
biblical chronology with the discovery of ancient fossils, what Thomas
Trautman refers as the “revolution in ethnological time,” opened up the
period of pre-history to an infinite period and assigned to anthropology,
in its division of labor with history, the task of reconstructing universal
histories although both history and anthropology in the post-Enlighten-
ment period believed in the idea of “progress” as the telos of mankind. 10
That there was a well-developed notion of Hindu chronology that
enabled the location of events in an epoch is obviously beyond dispute. 11
But this did not lead to a historical consciousness that is familiar to us in
contemporary times. 12 The existence of chronology, although essential, is
not sufficient for a historical consciousness to develop. 13 Reinhart Kosel-
leck has noted that the discovery of subjective historical times is itself a
product of modernity, and such times tied to social and political units of
action, to acting human beings, and to their institutions and organiza-
tions, occurs within the difference between the “space of experience” out
of which one acts and in which the past is present or remembered and the
“horizon of expectations” which serves as a reference to one’s action. 14
With this difference between experience and expectation not clearly con-
ceptualized in premodern times, it is difficult to grasp historical times.
History writing in pre-nineteenth century India was therefore not
common in the form it is known today, although Ashis Nandy argues
that they did have a different way of arriving at the past. 15 A plausible
explanation for the lack of historical consciousness proferred from classi-
cal Indian epistemology is that knowledge claims are based on episodic
experiences and are presentational rather than representational, and also
only those cognitive-episodes are considered knowledge-episodes that
lead to liberatory knowledge. 16 But indigenous texts and traditions did
concern themselves with the past. Nicholas Dirks has suggested from his
analysis of the family histories (Vamcavali) of one South Indian little king,
that these “be classified and analysed in terms and categories that are
114 Chapter 3
were more in the nature of book keeping accounts and are not sufficiently
indicative of the temporalization of economic entities, and no such entity
as the “economy” itself seems to have emerged in the Company dis-
courses at the time.
To have a dynamic conception of the “economy,” the entities used to
construct it have to be temporalized as well. A whole range of statistics
was sought regularly, enabling such a conception of the “economy” to be
realized. Political geographical statistics pertaining to area, population,
the number of villages, the number of judges, magistrates and police, and
gross revenue from land were collected. Population data were gathered
and tabulated by districts in terms of the number of inhabited houses,
and of the classification of population by broad age, sex, religious, and
occupational groups. Fiscal geography provided statistics relating to sur-
vey and settlement. The area surveyed was classified into cultivated, un-
cultivated, and irrigated, and also those assessed for land revenue and
the rate of assessment. This way of temporalizing the entity “land” had
two implications. First it was meant to yield a flow of revenue, a flow that
is not invariant with time. Secondly, it sought to record the varieties of
tenure. Here we see the representation of land as a commodity. Similarly,
all commodities need to be indexed by time for a dynamic conception of
the economy. The time-indexation of stocks and flows of resources and
commodities is an important characteristic of a market economy. The
regulatory practices of the colonial state rendered such indexation pos-
sible.
It is only when the administrative apparatus of the colonial state is
fully developed that administrative accountability becomes streamlined
and pervasive, and this process of temporalization of social and economic
entities takes place on a significant and distinctive scale, thus making it
discursively possible to represent “economy” or “society.”
In 1863 the government appointed a Statistical Committee to recom-
mend ways of compiling the mass of statistics contained in the Adminis-
tration Reports of the local governments on a “uniform” plan so as “to
show the statistics of the Empire” and to “show the progress of India in
such a manner as may be readily understood, and enable a comparison to
be made with the progress of other countries.” 63 The Statistical Commit-
tee also sought to render in tabular details the annual records pertaining
to all other aspects of social and civil existence. Rendering all aspects in a
tabular form and consolidating them district wise for all provinces ena-
bled a representation of “economy” and “society” that was temporal as
well. The Annual Administration Reports that were instruments of regu-
lation and control of the vast bureaucratic edifice of the colonial state also
became the instruments for generating knowledges. Thus the system of
“rule by records” and “rule by reports” contributed in no small way to
the colonial epistemological projects. 64
124 Chapter 3
NOTES
41. See Wagoner, “Precolonial Intellectuals and the Production of Colonial Knowl-
edge.”
42. Some of the important works of history may be noted: Alexander Dow, The
History of Hindostan 2 vols (London, 1770 and 1772); Robert Orme, Historical Fragments
of the Mogul Empire (London, 1805); Wilks and Bruce, Historical Sketches of the South of
India (London, 1810); James Mill, The History of British India (London, 1817); Mountstu-
art Elphinstone, The History of India (London, 1841).
43. Eric Stokes, “The Administrators and Historical Writing on India,” in Historians
of India, Pakistan and Ceylon ed. C. H. Phillips (London, 1961): 385–403.
44. Bhabha, “DissemiNation: Time, Narrative, and the Margins of the Modern Na-
tion,” 308.
45. Foucault dramatizes how when the economy of punishment was redistributed
“the gloomy festival” of public execution was replaced by the timetable. See Foucault,
Discipline and Punish, 3–31.
46. Minute of T.B. Macaulay, dated 14 December 1835, in A.P. Howell—Under Sec-
retary to Government of India—Note on Jails and Jail Discipline, 1. Cited in R. N. Datir,
Prison as a Social System (Bombay: Popular Prakashan, 1978), 75.
47. Foucault, Discipline and Punish.
48. Dipesh Chakrabarty, Rethinking Working Class History: Bengal 1890–1940 (Prince-
ton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1989).
49. Chakrabarty, Rethinking Working Class History: Bengal 1890–1940.
50. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 160.
51. See the chapter “The Nation in Heterogeneous Time” in Chatterjee, The Politics
of the Governed.
52. Wilson, “The Domination of Strangers: Time, Emotion and the Making of the
Modern State in Colonial India,” 46–47. Talal Asad provides a poignant illustration of
this in the administration of French immigration rules on a particular French-Algerian
first generation immigrant. See Talal Asad, “Where are the Margins of the State?” in
Anthropology in the Margins of the State, ed. Veena Das and Deborah Poole (Santa Fe,
NM: School of American Research Press, 2004) 279–88.
53. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 160–61.
54. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Uni-
versity Press, 1979).
55. Chakrabarty further notes “I would suggest that the idea of a godless, continu-
ous, empty, and homogenous time, which history shares with the other social sciences
and modern political philosophy as a basic building block, belongs to this model of a
higher, overarching language. It represents a structure of generality, an aspiration
toward the scientific, that is built into conversations that take the modern historical
consciousness for granted.” See Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe, 73, 75.
56. Chakrabarty notes “Yet historicism carries with it, precisely because of its asso-
ciation with the logic of bureaucratic decision making, an inherent modernist elitism
that silently lodges itself in our everyday consciousness.” See Chakrabarty, Provincial-
izing Europe, 87.
57. Chakrabarty explains how life-world experiences of nonsecular time are trans-
lated into secular time narratives and history such as of religious festivals being fitted
into secular calender time as public holidays. See Chakrabarty, Provincializing Europe.
58. Census of India, 1891: General Report, by J. A.Baines. (London: Eyre and Spotts-
woode, 1893): 274–275.
59. Home (Public Dept) G.O. N0 5274, Letter from Secretary to the Board of Reve-
nue dated 17th August 1864.
60. Martin Heidegger notes “The measurement of time gives it a marked public
character, so that only in this way does what we generally call ‘the time’ become well
known.” Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. John Macquarrie and Edward Rob-
inson (New York: Harper Collins, 1962), 471.
Temporalities, Routines of Rule, and History 135
61. Bruno Latour remarks that temporality is a means of connecting entities and
filing them away, with changes in classification principle giving a different temporal-
ity on the basis of the same events. See Latour, We have Never Been Modern, 75.
62. Latour, We have Never Been Modern, 73.
63. Letter from S.H. Northcote, Secretary of State for India to the Governor General
of India in Council, G.O.N0 89 (Financial), dated India Office, London, the 23rd March
1867 (New Delhi: National Archives of India).
64. Richard Saumarez Smith, “Rule by Records and Rule by Reports: Complemen-
tary Aspects of the British Imperial Rule of Law.”
65. Mary Douglas, How Institutions Think (Syracuse, NY: Syracuse University Press,
1986).
66. Jurgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1990), 311.
67. Read the section “What is Invested in Anachronism” in Chakrabarty, Provincial-
izing Europe, 244–249.
68. Koselleck, Futures Past, 109.
69. Anders Schinkle argues that Koselleck is mistaken in noting that experience and
expectation drift apart in modernity, for they cannot drift apart as imagination con-
nects the two. See Anders Schinkel, “Imagination as a Category of History: An Essay
Concerning Koselleck’s Concepts of Erfahrungsraum and Erwartungshorizont,” History
and Theory 44, (February 2005): 42–54.
70. The “doubling of man” arises because modern thought “moves no longer to-
wards the never-completed formation of Difference, but towards the ever-to-be-ac-
complished unveiling of the Same.” See Foucault, The Order of Things, 340.
71. Koselleck, Futures Past, 17.
72. Koselleck, Futures Past, 17.
73. Fabian, Time and the Other.
74. Immanuel Kant, “Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of
View,” in Philosophical Writings, ed. E. Behler, 249–262. (New York: Continuum, 1784/
1986), 260–261.
75. Kant, “Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View,” 261.
76. Hegel, The Philosophy of History.
77. Paul Veyne, Writing History: Essay on Epistemology, trans. Mina Moore Rinvoluri,
(Connecticut, 1984), 56.
78. Georg Simmel, Essays on Interpretation in Social Science, trans. and ed. Guy Oakes
(New Jersey: Rowman and Littlefield, 1980).
79. Simmel, Georg The Problems of the Philosophy of History: An Epistemological Essay
trans. and ed. Guy Oakes (New York: The Free Press, 1977), 178–84.
80. Using Derrida’s distinction between law (le droit) and justice (la justice), Mark
Jackson argues that writing and naming enframes domains of discursive possibility
producing a supplement, which is excluded from that writing. Justice is the reflexive
attention to both “singularity” and the ways in which the singular or “other” is pro-
duced within any discourse. See Mark Jackson, “The Ethical Space of Historiography,”
Journal of Historical Sociology 14, 4 (December 2001): 467–80.
81. Bhabha, “DissemiNation: Time, Narrative, and the Margins of the Modern Na-
tion,” 308.
82. Bhabha, “DissemiNation: Time, Narrative, and the Margins of the Modern Na-
tion,” 307.
83. Wagoner, “Precolonial Intellectuals and the Production of Colonial Knowl-
edge.”
84. Eugene Irschick, Dialogue and History: Constructing South India 1795–1895 (Berke-
ley: University of California Press, 1994); and Guha, Dominance without Hegemony, 157.
85. MC F/151/135 f. 214. Cited in Stein, Thomas Munro, 208.
86. Guha, Dominance without Hegemony, 3.
87. Majeed, Ungoverned Imaginings, 200.
88. Bhabha, The Location of Culture, 86.
136 Chapter 3
causes and the reasons by which a country’s wealth and riches may be
indefinitely increased. 10
When population emerged as a field of intervention and an object of
governmental techniques, the problem of the “economy” was simultane-
ously reconfigured from the model of the family to one in which the
specific problems of the population relating to the economy provided the
framework for government. This brought a tension between the liberal
and pastoral elements of modern state power, the liberal element con-
cerned with ensuring commercial freedom, and the pastoral element con-
cerned with ensuring the welfare of the population. 11 The new govern-
mental problematic was to ensure that the pursuit of self-interest by indi-
vidual economic actors was compatible with the reproduction and useful
employment of the population. The link between population and nation-
al wealth provided for a greater coordination between different adminis-
trative departments even as it for the first time brought together a whole
ensemble of institutions, procedures, analyses, reflections, calculations,
and tactics.
The colonial career of the modern state in India forces us to rethink the
nature of colonial governmentality, the link between population and na-
tional wealth in the colonial context, and the nature of tensions if any
between the liberal and pastoral elements of power. Colonial governmen-
tality was not merely governance from a distance but was fundamentally
one in which governance by the modern state sought to supplant earlier
forms of pre-modern rule through the autonomous rationality of the
government. 12 In doing so, the colonial state had to contend not only
with extant cognitive frameworks and the practices associated with the
political rationalities of earlier forms of pre-modern rule that rendered
the terrain of governance intelligible, but also encounter the difficulties of
introducing universalistic framework of knowledge into a colonial order
of difference. Hindess notes that Foucault’s idea of the autonomous ra-
tionality of government is predicated on an understanding of the state,
first as a distinctive institution and secondly as containing its own ration-
ality. 13 He further argues that the importance of the idea of an autono-
mous rationality of government for Foucault’s analysis is that it enables
him to develop a perspective on the government of modern states which
is not dominated by discourses of sovereignty and legitimacy; although
he also points out that the idea of the autonomous rationality of the
government seemed to suggest that the population consisted of free indi-
viduals and not of subjects. Clearly the colonial subjects did not perceive
the colonial state as legitimate, nor were colonial subjects free individu-
als. Colonial governmentality with its singular aim of augmenting the
economic strength of the state performed its extractive and regulatory
functions on individual and mass bodies not directly through force,
though that may as well been so in instances, but through modern forms
of regulatory discipline. The liberal and pastoral elements of power did
140 Chapter 4
not exhibit a tension in the colonial context for the nature of pastoral
power complemented the aims of liberal power. Borrowing once again
from Hindess, we note that in Foucault’s representation of pastoral pow-
er as that of the shepherd and his flock, the shepherd as a human being
was “a distinct and superior kind of being” than the flock. 14 The colonial
rulers likewise saw themselves as superior to the colonized subjects,
which implies that the modern colonial state sought to introduce new,
albeit superior, forms of knowledge regimes as part of its governance.
Such knowledge regimes that were constitutive of the technologies of
governance were universally applicable, or so it was assumed.
The colonial order of difference was thus fitted into universalistic
frameworks of knowledge through a process of normalizing the colo-
nized terrain done through the dual techniques of disciplinary power
and risk-based or actuarial power. While disciplinary power entailed the
creation or specification of a general norm in terms of which “individual
uniqueness can be recognized, characterized and then standardized,”
risk-based techniques of normalization sought to set norms by dividing
the “population into statistical and behavioural categories organized
around risk.” 15 These techniques of normalization entailed erasing differ-
ences through a process of constructed uniformity. Standardization of
units of measurement was an important part of the normalizing process.
Also the practices of governance itself rendered accountability and ac-
counting as prerequisites and these made possible the constitution of
calculable and governable selves. Making up “individuals” was an im-
portant agenda of nineteenth century liberalism; but liberalism in the
colonial context did not seek to create the citizen-individual, i.e., the indi-
vidual as bearer of rights, but an individual who by being forced into a
new sphere of commercial exchange would become colonial subjects and
the Homo-economicus of the market economy.
pation to sort the “profits” and “losses” of India engaged some of the
most brilliant minds in the India Office such as James Mill, J. S. Mill, and
J. M. Keynes. Even David Ricardo, whose theories of rent found ready
acceptance and justification in the hands of the colonial administrators in
framing the land revenue policies in India, had on several occasions
made presentations to the Court of Directors, and he being a stockholder
had an immediate interest in the profitability of the Company’s opera-
tions. The British parliament had often witnessed debates on this subject
by such men as Edmund Burke and others.
As early as the seventeenth century, Streynsham Master, an employee
of the East India Company, devised a new system of book-keeping for the
Company’s factories that “had a commanding influence on the public
accounts of the English in India for a long time afterwards.” 18 Master set
in place as part of his task of regulating the accounts of the factories the
following measures. These were two sets of printed rules made in 1667
for “Christian and sober comportment” and for the management of busi-
ness and the accounts that were prominently and publicly displayed in
every factory, established uniform accounting practices in all the facto-
ries, which linked their books into a single accounting system with all the
books being sent to England annually, standardized new methods of
conducting meetings and of keeping records of decisions and discus-
sions, established mechanisms for archiving documentation that bound
all the factories into a single system including the establishment of offices
at each factory where all writing and accounting was to be done and
where all documentation was to be kept as the record of the factory and
not of particular merchants. 19
Master’s regulation is a case of how local inscriptions were transmit-
ted to the centers of calculation. In the excerpt of the regulations given
below, it is evident how the practice of bureaucratic authorization
through signature and attestation emerged from the trade account as it
indicates how accounts were to be maintained ensuring uniformity
across factories and consolidated to render them legible and visible, bear-
ing the imprint of authority within a hierarchy of examination and ac-
countability. It reads:
That in the Titles of the Journall it be expressed who is Chiefe, and by whom
the bookes are kept, and at the end of the Journall and Leidger the person by
whom they are kept doe set his firme [signature] and the Chiefe to signe them
as approved and allowed by him.
For all the moneys paid out of cash, it is thought Convenient that, according to
the custome used at Suratt, the second or book-keeper doe draw a bill upon the
Cashkeeper, in the which he is to express the parties names to whome, and the
accompt upon which the money is payable, which bill the Second is first to
subscribe, leaving place for the Cheife, and the Cheife having signed it, the
money to be paid accordingly, the Cheife or Cashkeeper takeing a receipt for the
same; and if there be money to be sent for Inland Investments, to take attesta-
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 143
tions of two of the Companyes servants of the delivery of the summe, and the
said bills and attestations to be read and passed in Councell every week and
then noted in the Consultation booke.
The accounts were to record place-specific transactions at specified times
as it noted:
if money be remitted from Cassambazar to Pattana, the Cassambazar bookes
must charge Pattana and not Hugly for the same; and the Pattana bookes must
Creditt Cassambazar and cleare that accompt by Hugly accompt Currant
upon the close of their bookes, and the like in other cases.
The Bookes of Accompts of all the respective Factoryes in the Bay, it is agreed
to be most convenient to be balanced the last Aprill yearely, and to be kept in
the method now proposed.
Each ship’s accounts of trade was to be summed up into an annual ac-
count of the factory
One Booke to Comprehend the accompts of Charges Gennerall and Dyett, the
Sloopes and Vessells accompts, and the accompts of stores provided for them,
and what is on board them, and the mens wages belonging to the said Vessells,
which accompts are to be monethly given in to the Second, to be entered in the
Gennerall bookes, and at the end of that booke to make a table of the whole
yeares expence in distinct collumes under the heads entered in the Gennerall
booke, by which the same may be more readily compared. 20
Clearly the genealogy of the accounting and documentary practices of the
colonial bureaucracy in the later period can be traced to these rules of
inscription of early colonial trade. Examining the different forms of writ-
ing in and around the East India Company reveals power and knowledge
in mercantile and imperial worlds as they were in the process of being
made. Miles Ogborn observes that Streynsham Master and the Company
officials at all levels, attempted “to control the responsibility for docu-
ments, the construction and use of archives, the formats of writing, the
ways in which written material was produced, how documents should be
read and by whom, their content, and also their style” and further these
inscriptions and actions shaped the world of the factory in India. 21 Og-
born argues that Streynsham Master’s regulation are to be “understood
as active in the construction of economic and political relationships—of
collectivity, order, and authority—rather than simply being the more or
less practical and mechanical, albeit logistically problematic, means of
representing them to others.” 22 Writing practices in their repeated perfor-
mance and reinscription were intended to constitute a distinction be-
tween the “public” world of the Company’s business and the “private”
actions of its servants even as it solidified into institutional routines and
forms of rule.
Edmund Burke praised the “mercantile constitution” and methods of
the East India Company, as these pertained to its strictly commercial
operations, and especially its system of exact record keeping. 23 He even
144 Chapter 4
argued that the Company’s business methods lent themselves to the de-
velopment, in its hands, of a relatively efficient system of imperial ad-
ministration. 24 The state could learn valuable lessons from businessmen
about procedural regularity, rational accounting, and the like, but it did
not follow that a commercial company should be the state. Burke ob-
served:
It does so happen that there the Counting-house gave lessons to the
State. . . . The regulations made by mercantile men for their mercantile
interest, when they have been able, as in this case, to be applied to the
discipline and order of the State, have produced a discipline and order
which no State should be ashamed to copy. . . . It is perhaps the best
contrivance that ever has been thought of by the wit of men for the
government of a remote, large, disjointed empire. 25
More significantly, the trade accounts of the mercantilist period were to
provide an image of order out of chaos. The underlying mercantilist phi-
losophy was that the wealth of the world was finite, and an increase in
any one nation’s wealth was a zero-sum game. The rationale for the pro-
gram of government in the mercantilist era was the orderly movement of
resources internally and externally, and accounting was linked to prac-
tices of government in such a program through the valorization of order
in commerce that was materialized in its calculative routines. 26
The valuation of goods traded, which included the unit of measure-
ment as well as the price, and the use of money in the transactions, as
well as the manner of accounting form the complex mercantilist dis-
course of early European trade in India. The notion of “wealth” was the
privileged category of mercantilist thinking, and this was represented in
the quantity and quality of precious metals that could be accumulated
through trade. The mercantilist logic of prices made it dependent directly
on the volume of money, and indirectly on the volume of transactions.
The early trade discourses provide insights into the thinking that under-
gird the economic transactions of that period.
As bullion was imported from England and minted into coins in India
for payment transactions, the quality of the metals was an important
issue in the trade discourses. The main accounting problem of mercantil-
ist monetary economics was to ensure equivalence of gold worth, which
also meant the quality of metal content in transactions around the world.
There were frequent occurrences of differences in the assays of imported
gold provided by different merchants, which caused much concern. In
practice, this must not have been an insignificant problem, for even with-
in a region there were so many different varieties of coins circulating.
With transactions being conducted with different varieties of coins, it is
difficult to keep accounts. The Dutch for instance kept their accounts in
an imaginary guilder or florin which was a silver coin weighing 150
grains or five-sixths of a rupee. Measures also varied with the different
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 145
colonial powers, the Dutch pound equaling 1.09 English pounds and
there were other weights such as the “catti” and the “picol” introduced
from the Malayan Archipelago. There were a large number of indigenous
measures as well. For instance, when the Dutch traded on the West coast
of India they confronted the Malabar measures of “candy,” “parra,” and
“palam” for pepper, grains, and cloths and there were local variations in
these as well, as the Travancore “palam” was not exactly equal to the
Madura “palam.” 27
Apart from these issues of measures and money, there was the ques-
tion of ensuring that supplies of the needed goods were forthcoming, as
exchange was purely volitional. A Dutch governor, Stein van Gollenesse,
noted around 1743 that often contracts made with the king and his sub-
jects to supply the Company with pepper were not complied with, and
pepper used to be exported outside of the region by the people when
they considered it profitable. 28 The king, with whom the contract was
signed, could not really enforce the contract, as the king deriving his
power from divine authority could not issue orders that were considered
prejudicial to the interests of the whole community. The volitional char-
acter of exchange was to drastically change into one of forced commerce
as colonial power penetrated and entrenched itself firmly.
The English at the same time competing with their rivals were trying
to make their trade profitable in India. Profitable operations needed accu-
rate accounts as a prerequisite. Book-keeping practices to maintain the
accounts accurately were either constantly devised or were improved
upon. Accounts of goods received and sent by each ship were maintained
through a complex manner of record keeping. The differing systems of
measurement as well as account-keeping practices added no less to the
problems. These early trade discourses provide insights into the issue of
standardization arising out of accounting concerns. Weights and meas-
ures, commodity classifications, and accounting procedures were to all
come within the purview of standardization.
The nature of the Company commerce in India was to undergo a
change once the Company acquired the control over the revenues of
Bengal. A certain proportion of the revenues of Bengal were set aside as
“investment” with which the Company bought its goods for trade. This
new form of trade through the medium of power and public revenue
disrupted the mercantile system by diverting a considerable proportion
of native manufactures to the Company “investment.” In understanding
Company accounts as a proto-macroeconomic account, it has to be noted
that Company “investment” only constituted of mercantile capital rather
than productive capital.
A complex intermeshing of commercial interests with other European
companies meant more of accounts and record keeping, and there was
around this time an awareness of improving the accounts of trade. In
1796 Edward Thomas Jones published in Bristol his Jones’s English System
146 Chapter 4
Some of the Latest Acts of the Legislative Council and a Short Treatise on
Banking in India. It is from the latter half of the nineteenth century and
following the developments in Britain that a rational capitalistic enter-
prise, in the Weberian sense, emerged in India. For Max Weber, a rational
capitalistic enterprise was one that featured “capital accounting,” that is
one in which its income-yielding power is determined by calculation
according to modern methods of book-keeping and the striking of a bal-
ance. 50 Along with this arises the modern notion of capital stock, invest-
ment, depreciation, cash flow, etc., all of which enables the representation
of an enterprise in static and dynamic terms. A distinctly modern under-
standing is that without the anchor of double entry, the analysis of cost-
ing would tend to drift aimlessly. Standard costing was not an isolated
phenomenon but was closely allied to the vast project of standardization
and normalization within the enterprise, and is a key component in the
“ensemble of practices that sought to make actions of individuals visible
in relation to norms and standards.” 51
Britain did have joint-stock companies in the first half of the nine-
teenth century, and shares of these Companies were publicly traded and
exchanged as instruments of investment that resembled contemporary
modern stocks. But in nineteenth-century England there was no statistical
composite index to the shares traded on the stock exchange. Consequent-
ly as Mary Poovey has remarked, it was not possible in the early nine-
teenth century to conceptualize “the market” as a unified and animated
social agent. 52 In the middle of the nineteenth century, people who
bought shares in an individual company could only with difficulty follow
that company’s profits and losses since regular earnings reports were not
widely circulated, but they could not gauge the well-being of the market
as a whole because no representation that could be taken for the market
as a whole circulated in the public sphere. 53 Poovey observes that nine-
teenth-century Britain’s lack of market averages and prices led to concep-
tualizing social agency in individual terms with excessive risk-taking and
speculation being discouraged through an evangelical view of economy
that imbued events in the fiscal domain with moral significance even as it
doubted the significance of economic growth for national prosperity. 54
Only with the passage of new company laws including laws that limited
personal liability for an enterprise’s collapse, and statutes that encour-
aged new company formation between 1855 and 1862 did it become in-
creasingly difficult for clergymen to persuade their parishioners to con-
ceptualize economic transactions primarily as signs of spiritual worth. 55
Simultaneously, from about the 1870s in Europe, the discourse of political
economy was recast to institute the idea of a placeless notion of exchange.
Around that time, new legal measures in colonial India instituted the
market as a public venture, as a supra-local terrain, and as a new object of
sovereign management. Between 1870 and 1930 a slew of foundational
legal measures pertaining to companies law, negotiable instruments, in-
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 153
sources and manufactures located in different regions but also these were
systematized over time in the district, provincial and imperial gazetteers.
As commercialization spread over more and more areas, the classifica-
tory necessity extended as well. With advancing industrialization in Eng-
land the search for raw materials across the Empire also advanced, and
industrial raw materials and minerals came to be made the objects of
knowledge and the Journal of the Asiatic Society of Bengal carried accounts
of many products and resources found in different parts of the country,
even before their systematic compilation in the gazetteers of the Hunter-
ian period. The collection and classification of products became more
vigorous in the latter half of the nineteenth century, as agricultural and
industrial exhibitions became a regular feature at provincial, national,
and international levels. While these exhibitions stressed the principle of
the “function” of knowledge, i.e., to instruct the viewers on improved
methods of production and the use of machinery, these aspects of “func-
tion” grew more important in the growing global commercial world. 72
Exhibitions became the spectacle of the age of commodities, and it could
become possible only by generating a vast body of knowledge about
them. 73
In fact, as “things” move into the status of “commodities” and when
the exchange-value of the thing acquires significance, they also come
within a new regime of knowledge. Their names, functions, methods of
production, measurement, production, consumption, trade patterns all
come together and cohere to form the regime of value. When such a value
regime becomes widespread, more and more “things” acquire the status
of “commodities” and are brought within the fold of exchange, the “econ-
omy” also gets constituted thereby. The knowledge of commodities is
therefore a precondition for constituting knowledge of the economy.
The colonial state played an important role in generating such knowl-
edge. Instructing the local officers to familiarize themselves with the agri-
cultural commodities, the Bengal government for instance, noted quite
clearly in 1874:
Local officers must be able to recognize with precision the various
grains and other products of their districts, to enable them to deal with
agricultural statistics in an intelligent manner. At present it is almost
ludicrous to observe . . . how often the same things are called by differ-
ent names, and different things by same names. 74
Linguistic diversity and local variety would no doubt cause this “ludi-
crous” situation but the above instruction more clearly refracts the anxie-
ty that gripped botanists in 1860s of the “galloping synonymy,” the pro-
liferation of many names for the same plant species which led in 1867 to
institute a series of international codes of nomenclature that sought to
stabilize the names of plants. 75 Such exhortations were to result in the
enthusiastic productions of glossaries and compendiums. William
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 157
Peasants, artisans, and weavers were not merely forced into commerce
and exchange, even the mode of commerce underwent changes. Cowries
(sea shells) used in petty commerce were replaced with copper coins,
metallic money was standardized, paper money was created, and new
financial instruments made their appearance along with the new institu-
tions of the banking system, and new methods of rendering accounts.
Weights and measures and the monetary systems that are crucial in the
reckoning of values entered a new regime of politics, as they were regu-
lated and made uniform in the interest of administering the economy,
once the colonial administration was streamlined. It was not merely one
of diversity, but the measures themselves were deemed not rationally
devised as length was based on bodily parts and distance measured by
the bellow of the cow or similar physical and natural phenomenon. James
Scott has observed that nonstate forms of measurement grew from the
logic of local practice, were tied practically to particular activities, re-
flected variety of local interests and were often “illegible” to the state in
their raw form. 78 This is not something unique to India as even in Britain
diverse weights and measures prevailed until the mid-nineteenth centu-
ry. 79 In Europe too such diversities existed, and it was the Napoleonic
Code of the early nineteenth century that rationalized the linear, capacity,
and weight measures for much of continental Europe.
Such diversities in weights and measures also prevailed in India.
Weights in southern India were deduced originally from the weight of
158 Chapter 4
some stamped or coined piece of metallic money, and since these tokens
have varied in weight according to the mints that produced them, the
scales that combined them similarly fluctuated. 80 The measures of capac-
ity also differed; several measures bearing the same name in the same
place had different struck contents, but all of them often coincided when
heaped. Such enormous diversities posed problems before 1870 when the
provincial governments were asked to submit returns of food prices reg-
ularly to the government of India, for the bimonthly returns submitted
from the district offices showed the number of measures of each com-
modity sold for a rupee but the measures themselves were not strictly
comparable and hence not aggregable. The compilation of agricultural
statistics on a uniform basis for all India that began in 1884 also required
uniform measures to estimate crop yields. Attempts to reform the
weights and measures were taken up on a number of occasions by some
local governments, market legislations did try to regulate them, but the
model laws prescribing standardized weights and measures by district
boards and municipal councils were never put in practice on account of
the strength of local customs and lack of verification; and uniformity
across the country eluded the state for long. Even in 1928, the Royal
Commission on Agriculture in India referred to the hampering effects of
diversities in weights and measures. 81 The colonial State, it must be
noted, was primarily interested in intervening in the ongoing economic
processes rather than the discourse of the economy. The statistical repre-
sentation of regional prices on a longitudinal basis along with an array of
agricultural statistics including area under cultivation, crop yields and
crop forecasts was however an important step in the discursive construc-
tion of the economy.
Along with the standardization of weights and measures, the financial
space of the colonial economy was also homogenized through a new
monetary framework. Money, the medium of exchange, underwent
changes to accommodate the needs of a complexly evolving circuit of
exchange. Although monetary exchange was quite widespread in the
precolonial and early colonial period it was more a patchwork of discrete
currency systems bound together by an overarching credit network of
indigenous merchants with their negotiable instruments and trust based
on kin and caste affiliations. Money’s function as a measure of value
lacked visibility then. As the British consolidated their territorial power,
the imperial coinage system was introduced. Under Act XVII of 1835 gold
coins were no more legal tender and silver coins represented the weight
of pure silver as their value, and were legal tender only if their purity and
weight were maintained. It was with the imperial system that it was
possible to state the value of the total coinage and therefore of money as
measure of value, a crucial first step, in understanding transactions not as
isolated events but within the context of a dynamic national economy.
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 159
which was both superfluous to the local labour market requirements and
biologically and morally incapable of productive labour,” an idea that
was transposed into the colonial setting as part of a myth of the indolent
and lazy native. 90 Even if migrant women were visible in the moral land-
scape of “cooliedom,” their work was rendered invisible in statistics. 91
Governmentality is concerned with the manner in which the link be-
tween population and wealth is translated into policy. While “political
arithmetik” in seventeenth-century Britain calculated the financial worth
of the population, 92 what was central to nineteenth-century governmen-
tality in Britain, was “knowledge of the body through statistical calcula-
tion of the amount of labour various sized and gendered bodies were
capable of and what amount of food was necessary to sustain them.” 93 As
modern industries were established, labor time was regulated in terms of
the working hours. 94 With the passing of the Factories Act from 1881
onwards with periodical amendments, it became obligatory on factory
owners to submit information relating to employment, hours of work,
and accidents in prescribed forms that were compiled annually as pro-
vincial reports, but had little information in it on workers’ wages and
matters relating to their welfare. The Royal Commission on Labour in
1931 noted that as hardly any enquiries had been conducted on the stan-
dard of living of workers, it was impossible for any quantitative analysis
even on such a basic question as to whether workers’ earnings sufficed to
provide for their necessities, clearly revealing the colonial character of the
state for such working class surveys were quite common in England from
the 1830s onward. 95 The colonial state did not consider population itself
to be human capital, and aspects such as education, health, and nutrition
that figure so prominently in contemporary development discourses
were in fact quite marginal till the end of the nineteenth century.
Perhaps the best instance of how colonial governmentality sought to
establish a numerical discourse linking population, resources, and wealth
is to be found in the famine discourses of the colonial government. Indian
rulers had in the past responded to famine situations but evidence is hard
to come by of pre-colonial states responding at the local level in a “secu-
lar” manner through the involvement of a bureaucracy in famine relief on
the basis of impersonal institutional structures. 96 Influenced by the
Smithian idea of laissez faire, the colonial state followed in all the famines
that repeatedly ravaged the country for the greater part of its rule, the
principle of non-intervention in the grain market thereby giving a free
hand to mercantile speculation even as the pastoral element of modern
state power compelled it to show concern for the welfare of the popula-
tion. Even when a policy of non-intervention was followed, there was a
spectacular extension of the colonial state’s material power, and its physi-
cal, statistical and ideological infrastructure in the attempt to administer
famine relief. 97 The administrative discourses on famines are replete with
assessments of costs and benefits. Even in the famine in Bombay presi-
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 163
state. 108 Nutritional and dietary surveys soon caught on, complementing
the surveys of working class budgets especially as scientific authority in
the League of Nations sought to establish norms of universal minimum
needs. Food thus acquired the “character of calculability” in an economy
of equivalences that sought to reduce men, women and children into
standard consumption units that had far reaching implications in wage-
setting policies later. 109 Colonial governmentality’s bureaucratic practices
served the epistemic function of constituting the “economy” in dynamic
terms. This led to the idea of how poverty could be managed, which
became crucial to the later postcolonial problematic of the economy and
the management of poverty. 110
NOTES
tion,” in Accounting as Social and Institutional Practice, ed. Anthony G. Hopwood and
Peter Miller (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 4, 29.
2. Louis Dumont notes: “It should be obvious that there is nothing like an econo-
my out there, unless and until men construct such an object.” See Louis Dumont, From
Mandeville to Marx: The Genesis and Triumph of Economic Ideology (Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1977), 24. Also see Keith Tribe, Land, Labour, and Economic Discourse
(London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978).
3. Karl Marx and Karl Polanyi are some exceptions. For a political genealogy of
political economy, read Denis Meuret, “A Political Genealogy of Political Economy,”
Economy and Society 17, 2 (1988): 225–50.
4. Buck-Morss, “Envisioning Capital: Political Economy on Display.” For more on
how the “science of police” constituted the social and the economic realm in eight-
eenth century Europe, read Pasquale Pasquino, “Theatrum Politicum. The Genealogy
of Capital-Police and the State of Prosperity,” Ideology and Consciousness, 4 (Autumn
1978): 41–54. Also published in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality,ed. Gra-
ham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller, (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press), 105–18.
5. See the chapter “The Character of Calculability” in Timothy Mitchell, Rule of
Experts: Egypt, Techno-Politics, Modernity (Berkeley: University of California Press,
2002).
6. Michel Foucault, “Politics and Reason,” in Politics, Philosophy, Culture: Interviews
and Other Writings 1977–1984, ed. Lawrence D. Kritzman (New York: Routledge, 1988),
57–85. Ritu Birla notes a slippage in Foucault’s use of the term “economy” as it refers
at times to a practice of managing, at others to an abstract arrangement, and even to a
specific sector of reality. See Ritu Birla, Stages of Capital: Law, Culture, and Market
Governance in Late Colonial India (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2009).
7. Ute Tellmann, “The Economic Beyond Governmentality,” in Governmentality:
Current Issues and Future Challenges, ed. Ulrich Brockling, Susanne Krasmann, and
Thomas Lemke (New York: Routledge, 2011), 285–303.
8. Foucault notes “whether it is a question of the physiocrats’ Table or Smith’s
‘invisible hand;’ whether it is a question, therefore, of an analysis aiming to make
visible (in the form of ‘evidence’) the formation of the value and circulation of
wealth—or, on the contrary, an analysis presupposing the intrinsic invisibility of the
connection between individual profit-seeking and the growth of collective wealth—
economics, in any case, shows a basic incompatibility between the optimal develop-
ment of the economic process and a maximization of governmental procedures.” See
Foucault, “The Birth of Biopolitics” in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, 76.
9. Ryan Walter, ‘Governmentality accounts of the economy: a liberal bias?’ Econo-
my and Society 37, 1 (2008): 94–114. Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of
the Wealth of Nations, ed. Edwin Cannan (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976).
10. Lawrence Goldman, “The Origins of British ‘Social Science’, Political Economy,
Natural Science and Statistics, 1830–1835,” The Historical Journal 26, 3 (September
1983): 587–616.
11. Ann Firth, “From Economy to ‘The Economy’: Population and Self-Interest in
Discourses on Government,” History of the Human Sciences 11, 3 (1998): 19–35.
12. Partha Chatterjee poses the question as to whether there is any analytical use in
distinguishing between the colonial state and the forms of the modern state. He makes
the intriguing suggestion that if the colonial state was not in fact distinct, then it is not
a necessary part of the historical narrative of modernity. For Chatterjee, it is the racial
difference between the ruler and the ruled that makes the colonial state distinct. See
Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 14. David Scott has discussed the conceptual
inadequacy of Chatterjee’s formulation. He reinstates in its place a strong foucauldian
formulation of the political rationalities of colonial rule. See Scott, “Colonial Govern-
mentality.”
13. Hindess, “Politics and Governmentality.” A similar idea is expressed by Peter
Miller and Nikolas Rose when they note, “Rather than ‘the State’ giving rise to govern-
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 169
ment, the state becomes a particular form of government that has taken, and one that
does not exhaust the field of calculations and interventions that constitute it.” See
Peter Miller and Nikholas Rose, “Governing Economic Life,” Economy and Society 19, 1
(1990): 3.
14. Hindess, “Politics and Governmentality,” 260.
15. Pat O’Malley, “Risk, Power and Crime Prevention,” Economy and Society 21, 3
(1992): 252, 254.
16. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia, (1993) and Timothy Mitchell, “Statisti-
cal Knowledge and the ‘National Economy,’” paper presented at a seminar in the
Department of Anthropology, Johns Hopkins University, Baltimore, 1997.
17. Mitchell, Rule of Experts; and Manu Goswami, Producing India: From Colonial
Economy to National Space (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2004).
18. Richard Carnac Temple, ed., The Diaries of Streynsham Master-1675–1680 and oth-
er contemporary papers relating thereto vol. II: The First and Second ‘Memorialls’ 1679–1680,
published for the Government of India (London, John Murray, 1911).
19. Miles Ogborn, “Wherein Lay The Late Seventeenth Century State? Charles Dav-
enant Meets Streynsham Master,” Journal of Historical Sociology 16, 1 (March 2002):
96–101.
20. Excerpted from Temple, The Diaries of Streynsham Master-1675–1680 and other
contemporary papers relating thereto.
21. Ogborn, Indian Ink.
22. Ogborn, Indian Ink, 71, 100–101.
23. Whelan, Edmund Burke and India, 96–97.
24. Mary Poovey has argued that it is a historiographical misrepresentation to as-
similate early modern accounting with governmentality, administration and disci-
pline. See Poovey, A History of the Modern Fact.
25. Edmund Burke’s Speech on Opening of Impeachment (1788) in The Writings and
Speeches of Edmund Burke, vol. 6, ed. Paul Langford (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1981).
26. Peter Miller, “On the Interrelations between Accounting and the State,” Account-
ing, Organizations and Society 15, 4 (1990): 333.
27. Keith Thomas has noted the prevalence of different units of measurement for
different commodities in early modern England as well. See Keith Thomas, “Numer-
acy in Early Modern England,” The Prothero Lecture, Transactions of the Royal Histori-
cal Society, London, Fifth Series No. 37 (1987): 103–32. Witold Kula (1986) also deals
with such diversities in Europe. See Witold Kula, Measures and Men (Princeton: Prince-
ton University Press, 1986).
28. “Memorandum on the Administration of the Malabar Coast,” compiled by Ju-
lius Valentijn Stein van Gollenesse in the year 1743 A.D. Records of Fort St. George,
The Dutch in Malabar (Madras: Government Press, 1910).
29. S. K. Sen, ed. Edmund Burke on Indian Economy (Calcutta: Progressive Publishers,
1969), 66.
30. Holden Furber, John Company at Work: A Study of European Expansion in India in
the Late Eighteenth Century (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 1948).
31. Furber, John Company at Work, 207–24.
32. Furber, John Company at Work, 266.
33. James Mill, The History of British India v ol. VI (New York: Chelsea House Pub-
lishers, 1818/1968), 471.
34. Poovey, “The Limits of the Universal Knowledge Project: British India and the
East Indiamen.”
35. Hansard’s Parliamentary Debates, 3d series, 19 (1833), 536. Cited in Poovey, “The
Limits of the Universal Knowledge Project: British India and the East Indiamen.”
36. Thomas B. Macaulay noted “A chest of tea is not necessarily commercial proper-
ty; it may have been bought out of the territorial revenue. Fort is not necessarily
territorial property; it may stand on ground which the Company bought 100 years ago
out of their commercial profits.” Hansard’s Parliamentary Debates, 3rd series, 19 (1833),
170 Chapter 4
508. Cited in Poovey, “The Limits of the Universal Knowledge Project: British India
and the East Indiamen.”
37. Mary Poovey has cautioned that these accounts were more likely to be incom-
plete and inexact simply because in the long journey to and from the East goods often
went missing and unlisted cargo made its way on and off the ships. See Poovey, “The
Limits of the Universal Knowledge Project: British India and the East Indiamen.”
38. J. R. McCulloch presents time series trade data from 1799 to 1846. See J.R.
McCulloch, A Descriptive and Statistical Account of The British Empire, vol. II (London:
Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans, 1847), 18–19.
39. For an insightful analysis of this phenomenon, see Poovey, “The Limits of the
Universal Knowledge Project: British India and the East Indiamen.”
40. Arjo Klammer and Donald McCloskey, “Accounting as the Master Metaphor of
Economics,” European Accounting Review 1, 1 (1992): 145–60. Mary Poovey has noted
that at least since the seventeenth century, British efforts to formulate the new “sci-
ences” of wealth and society was pervaded by the metaphor of accounting and was
made explicit in Hobbes’s Leviathan (1651). See Poovey, A History of the Modern Fact;
and Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1929/1651).
41. Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, 2 vols, ed. G.
Roth and C. Wittlich (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978/1956), 86.
42. Peter Miller, “Governing by Numbers: Why Calculative Practices Matter,” Social
Research 68, 2 (Summer 2001): 379–96.
43. Peter Miller discusses how the emergence of cost accountancy in the early twen-
tieth century made it possible to govern the future actions of the individual according
to prescribed standards and deviations from an economic norm. See Miller, “Govern-
ing by Numbers: Why Calculative Practices Matter.”
44. Jack Goody, The East in the West (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1996); and Bayly, Empire and Information. Mary Poovey has noted that the epistemolog-
ical effects of the double-entry system was to make its formal precision that was
drawn on the rule-bound system of arithmetic to seem to guarantee the accuracy of the
details it recorded. See Poovey, A History of the Modern Fact.
45. Jeremy Bentham, “On Public Account Keeping” in Official Aptitude Maximized
Expense Minimized, The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham, ed. Philip Schofield, (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1993), 293–301.
46. See Bentham, “On Public Account Keeping” in Official Aptitude Maximized Ex-
pense Minimized, 300.
47. Goswami, Producing India.
48. Michel Callon, “Introduction: the Embeddedness of Economic Markets in Eco-
nomics,” in The Laws of the Markets, ed. M. Callon (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 1998),
25–26.
49. David Rudner has examined the accounts maintained by the indigenous bank-
ing community of Chettiars and notes that although some members consider their
accounts to conform to the double-entry system, they do not appear to comply with
the principles of double-entry book-keeping. See David Rudner, “Banker’s Trust and
the Culture of Banking among the Nattukottai Chettiars of Colonial South India,”
Modern Asian Studies 23, 3 (July 1989): 417–58.
50. Max Weber, General Economic History (New York: Collier, 1961), 207.
Also read Richard Colignon and Mark Covaleski, “A Weberian Framework in the
Study of Accounting,” Accounting, Organizations and Society 16, 2 (1991): 141–157.
51. Peter Miller and Ted O’Leary’ “Governing the calculable person,” in Accounting
as social and institutional practice, ed. Anthony G. Hopwood and Peter Miller (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1994), 111.
52. Mary Poovey, “For Everything Else, There’s . . .,” Social Research 68, 2 (Summer
2001): 397–426.
53. Poovey, “For Everything Else, There’s . . .,” 406.
54. See the chapter “Speculation and Virtue in Our Mutual Friend,” in Poovey,
Making a Social Body.
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 171
55. Mary Poovey observes that the desacralization of the economy was achieved in
part by the development of modern science of economics which sought to displace the
logical rationale that persisted in mid-century political economy with the abstract and
apparendy value-free language of mathematics, and the rise of statistics, which made
it possible to think of groups of individuals as statistical populations whose activities
could be tabulated as mathematical regularities. See Poovey, “For Everything Else,
There’s . . .,” 411–12
56. Birla, Stages of Capital, 4–6.
57. Bayly, Empire and Information, 41.
58. Porter, Trust in Numbers, 97.
59. G. P. Kapadia, History of the Accountancy Profession in India (New Delhi: The
Institute of Chartered Accountants of India, 1973).
60. Keith Robson, “On the Arenas of Accounting Change: the Process of Transla-
tion,” Accounting, Organizations and Society 16, 5/6 (1991): 547–70.
61. Hacking, “Bio-Power and the Avalanche of Printed Numbers.”
62. Keith, W. Hoskin and Richard H. Macve, “Accounting as Discipline: The Over-
looked Supplement,” in Knowledges: Historical and Critical Studies in Disciplinarity, ed.
Ellen Messer-Davidow, David R. Shumway and David J. Sylvan (Charlottesville: Uni-
versity of Virginia Press, 1993), 25–53.
63. Poovey, A History of the Modern Fact, 30.
64. Max Weber has noted that even if the decimal system was invented and algebra
was used in India, it was fully utilized only by the developing capitalism in the West
and it did not lead to modern arithmetic, or book–keeping in India. See Max Weber,
“The Uniqueness of Western Civilisation,” in Max Weber: On Capitalism, Bureaucracy
and Religion–A Selection of Texts, ed. Stanislav Andreski (London: George Allen and
Unwin, 1983), 21–29.
65. Michel Callon, “An Essay on Framing and Overflowing: Economic Externalities
Revisited by Sociology” in The Laws of the Markets, ed. M. Callon (Malden, MA: Black-
well, 1998), 250.
66. Bayly, Empire and Information, 46.
67. See the chapter “The Conditions of Emergence of the Economic Category,” in
Dumont From Mandeville to Marx.
68. Siraj Ahmed, “The Theater of the Civilized Self: Edmund Burke and the East
India Trials,” Representations, 78 (Spring 2002): 28–55; Guha, Elementary Aspects of Peas-
ant Insurgency in Colonial India; McCulloch, A Descriptive and Statistical Account of The
British Empire, vol. II; and Thomas R. Metcalfe, “The Struggle Over Land Tenure in
India, 1860–1868,” The Journal of Asian Studies 21, 3 (May 1962): 295–307.
69. Guha, Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India.
70. Arjun Appadurai, “Introduction: Commodities and the Politics of Value,” in The
Social Life of Things ed. Arjun Appadurai (New York: Cambridge University Press,
1986), 4–5.
71. See the seven volume work of George Watt, A Dictionary of the Economic Products
of India (London, 1889–1892); and George Watt, The Commercial Products of India (Lon-
don: John Murray, 1908). Similar works for the different regions were prepared as well
much before Watt’s works, such as the one by B. H. Baden-Powell, Handbook of the
Economic Products of the Punjab, Vol.1and Vol. 2 (Roorkee, 1868–1872).
72. Gyan Prakash, “Science ‘Gone Native’ in Colonial India,” Representations, Special
Issue: Seeing Science 40 (Fall 1992): 153–78.
73. Timothy Mitchell notes that Egypt’s first Bureau de Statistique established in 1870
was done so after the khedive’s visit to the Exposition Universelle in Paris, where the
presentation of statistical data on each country in the world was one of the organizing
principles of the exhibition. See Timothy Mitchell, Rule of Experts.
74. Government of Bengal, Financial Department (Industry and Science), Proceed-
ing no.2.1, May 1874, India Office Library and Records, London (IOLR), p/186. Cited in
Prakash, “Science ‘Gone Native’ in Colonial India.”
172 Chapter 4
75. Lorraine Daston, “Type Specimens and Scientific Memory,” Critical Inquiry 31, 1
(Autumn 2004): 153–182.
76. William Crooke, A Glossary of North Indian Peasant Life, edited Sahid Amin (Del-
hi: Oxford University Press, 1989).
77. Shahid Amin, “Introduction,” in A Glossary of North Indian Peasant Life–William
Crooke.
78. See the chapter “Nature and Space” in Scott, Seeing like a State.
79. Julian Hoppit examines the diversities in weights and measures in Britain from
the mid-seventeenth century to the early nineteenth century and the measures taken to
standardize them. Apparently three Royal Commissions apart from select committees
looked into the matter. See Julian Hoppit, “Reforming Britain’s Weights and Meas-
ures, 1660–1824,” English Historical Review (Jan 1993): 82–104.
80. C. D. Maclean, Manual of the Administration of the Madras Presidency, vol II (Ma-
dras: Government of Madras Press, 1885). Reprint (New Delhi: Asian Educational
Services, 1989).
81. Royal Commission on Agriculture in India Report of the Royal Commission on
Agriculture in India (London: His Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1928), 396.
82. Goswami, Producing India.
83. For the introduction of paper money in the colonial context of Egypt, see Mitch-
ell, Rule of Experts.
84. John Maynard Keynes, The Collected Writings, vol.1: Indian Currency and Finance
(London: Macmillan, 1971, Originally Published in 1913). As member of the Royal
Commission on Indian Currency and Finance of 1913–1914 Keynes reiterated his sup-
port of the sterling exchange standard and which was to become a point of contention
in the nationalist critique of colonial economic policies. See Goswami, Producing India.
85. For more on the colonial influence on Keynes’s conceptualization, read Mitchell,
Rule of Experts.
86. Tellmann, “Catastrophic Populations and the Fear of the Future: Malthus and
the Genealogy of Liberal Economy.”
87. Bernard S. Cohn, “Notes on the History of the Study of Indian Society and
Culture” in An Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays (Delhi: Oxford Univer-
sity Press, 1968/1990), 153; and Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj, 114–15.
88. Hacking, “Bio-Power and the Avalanche of Printed Numbers,” 280–81.
89. Frederick Cooper indicates that a similar phenomenon was taking place in Afri-
ca under the colonial stabilization policy as in the officials’ eyes the industrial worker
was always a man. See Frederick Cooper, “Colonizing Time: Work Rhythms and
Labor Conflict in Colonial Mombasa,” in Colonialism and Culture, ed. Nicholas Dirks
(Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press, 1992), 209–45.
90. M. S. Kumar, “The Census and Women’s Work in Rangoon, 1872–1931,” Journal
of Historical Geography 32, (2006): 383.
91. Jan Breman and E. V. Daniel, “The Making of the Coolie” in Plantations, proletar-
ians, and peasants in colonial Asia, ed. E. Valentine Daniel, Henry Bernstein and Tom
Brass (London: Frank Cass, 1992), 268–95.
92. Charlotte Sussman examines the statistical rhetoric in William Petty’s Political
Arithmetik and his emphasis on the quantifiable value of subaltern bodies that con-
strued such population as transportable. See Charlotte Sussman, “The Colonial After-
life of Political Arithmetic: Swift, Demography and Mobile Populations,” Cultural Cri-
tique 56 (Winter 2004): 96–126.
93. James S. Duncan, In the Shadows of the Tropics: Climate, Race and Bio-power in
Nineteenth Century Ceylon (Hampshire, UK: Ashgate Publishing, 2007), 86, n91.
94. Chakrabarty, Rethinking Working Class History.
95. Royal Commission on Labour in India Report of the Royal Commission on Labour in
India (London: His Majesty’s Stationery Office, 1931), 196.
96. Sanjay Sharma, Famine, Philanthropy and the Colonial State: North India in the early
nineteenth century (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2001), 169.
Colonial Governmentality and the “Economy” 173
97. David Nally observes that in Ireland too the difficulties of superintending a
colonial population during the Irish famine of 1845 became a powerful reason to
expand the pastoral role of the state. The government’s role included administering
aid, managing relief structures, building pauper institutions, directing famished bod-
ies, sanctioning “relief laws,” and mobilizing ideologies and policies to secure particu-
lar outcomes. It involved a high degree of regulation and government intervention in
which the Irish Poor Law was to play a very major role, and these institutions, laws,
and disciplines permitted the colonial state to target the subaltern body in novel and
powerful ways. See David Nally, “‘That Coming Storm’: The Irish Poor Law, Colonial
Biopolitics, and the Great Famine,” Annals of the Association of American Geographers 98,
3 (2008): 714–41.
98. Neil Rabitoy, “The Control of Fate and Fortune: The Origins of the Market
Mentality in British Administrative Thought in South Asia,” Modern Asian Studies 25, 4
(October 1991): 757.
99. William Digby, The famine campaign in southern India (Madras and Bombay presi-
dencies and province of Mysore) 1876–1878, v. 1 (London: Longmans, Green, and Co.,
1878), 8.
100. Peter Gray, “Famine and Land in Ireland and India 1845–1880: James Caird and
the Political Economy of Hunger,” The History Journal 49, 1 (March 2006): 204.
101. In this bureaucratic edifice of “rule by record” and “rule by report” to use
Richard Saumarez Smith’s phrases, selectivity in information retrieval from lower to
higher levels of administration appears to have been prevalent in other departments
such as police and judicial as noted by Bhavani Raman. See Bhavani Raman, “The
Duplicity of Paper: Counterfeit, Discretion, and Bureaucratic Authority in Early Colo-
nial Madras,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 54, 2 (April 2012): 229–250.
102. Digby, The famine campaign in southern India (Madras and Bombay presidencies and
province of Mysore) 1876–1878, v. 1, 92.
103. William Digby, The famine campaign in southern India (Madras and Bombay presi-
dencies and province of Mysore) 1876–1878, v. 2 (London: Longmans, Green, and Co.,
1878), 172.
104. Digby, The famine campaign in southern India (Madras and Bombay presidencies and
province of Mysore) 1876–1878, v. 2, 183.
105. Mitchell Dean, “A Genealogy of the Government of Poverty,” Economy and Soci-
ety 21, 3 (1992): 215–51.
106. The word “self-acting test” used in the Indian Famine Code of 1880 is a replica-
tion of the same phrase used by the English Poor Law Commission of 1832–1834. See
Sabyasachi Bhattacharya, “The Labouring Poor and their Notion of Poverty: Late 19th
and Early 20th Century Bengal,” Labour and Development 3, 1 and 2 (1998): 1–23.
107. A similar point is made in the context of the liberal conception of poverty in
England. Dean notes that the opposition between moral and economic conceptions of
poverty is a result of the transformation in modes of government it seeks to explain.
See Dean, “A Genealogy of the Government of Poverty.”
108. S. S. Amrith, “Food and Welfare in India, c.1900–1950,” Comparative Studies in
Society and History 50, 4 (2008): 1013; and David Arnold, “Discovery of Malnutrition
and Diet in Colonial India,” Indian Economic and Social History Review 31, 1 (1994): 1–26.
109. Amrith, “Food and Welfare in India, c.1900–1950,” 1022–23.
110. For understanding the emergence of the pauper in the discourses of political
economy in Europe, read Giovanna Procacci, “Social Economy and the Government of
Poverty,” Ideology and Consciousness (1978): 55–72. Also published in The Foucault Ef-
fect: Studies in Governmentality, ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller
(Chicago: The University of Chicago Press), 151–168.
111. Robert. A. Horva’th, “The Rise of Macroeconomic Calculations in Economic
Statistics,” in The Probabilistic Revolution vol. 2, ed. Lorenz Kruger, Gerd Gigerenzer,
and Mary Morgan (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1987), 148.
174 Chapter 4
112. Timothy Mitchell, “Origins and Limits of the Idea of the Economy,” Advanced
Study Center, Working Papers Series, no. 12 (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press,
1995).
113. There is a section “Poverty of India” subtitled “Papers read before the Bombay
Branch of the East India Association of London in 1876” in Dadabhai Naoroji’s book
Poverty and Un-British Rule in India in which he states in the first footnote:”These notes
in their original draft were placed before the Select Committee on Indian Finance in
1873. They were taken, but not published with the Report, as they did not suit the
views of the Chairman (Mr. Ayrton), and I was led to suppose, also of Sir Grant Duff,
who was then the Under-Secretary of State for India.” See Dadabhai Naoroji, Poverty
and Un-British Rule in India (New Delhi: Commonwealth Publishers, 1901/1988).
114. John Crawfurd, “A Sketch of the Commercial Resources and Monetary and
Mercantile System of British India, with Suggestions for their Improvements by means
of Banking Establishments, 1837,” in The Economic Development of India under the East
India Company 1814–1858: A Selection of Contemporary Writings, ed. K. N. Chaudhuri
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971). Romesh Chunder Dutt, The Economic
History of India Under Early British Rule 2 vols (New York: Burt Franklin, 1902/ 1970).
115. William Digby, “Prosperous” British India; a revelation from official records (Lon-
don: T. F. Unwin, 1901), 439–40.
116. Alan Heston, “National Income” in The Cambridge Economic History of India, vol.
2: c.1757–c.1970, ed. Dharma Kumar and Meghnad Desai, (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1983), 376–462.
FIVE
Classification and Society
and to tie together the empire abroad in the vernacular usage of the
domestic, ranked social hierarchy, it was as much a replication of same-
ness and similarities originating from Britain as it was an insistence on
difference and dissimilarities originating from elsewhere in the empire.
David Cannadine is of the view that census classification of caste taken in
conjunction with other symbols of “honorific hierarchy” that the British
invented such as the Durbars sought to project the Indian empire as a
“feudal order.” The views of colonial administrators like Henry Maine,
W. W. Hunter, and Alfred Lyall converged on this perspective and their
Burkean agrarian image of Indian society helped to construct a govern-
ment that was “simultaneously direct and indirect, authoritarian and col-
laborationist, but that always took for granted the reinforcement and
preservation of tradition and hierarchy.” 31
Nicholas Dirks has cautioned that the history of the production of
colonial difference does not license all expressions of nativist fundamen-
talism, and by drawing attention to the “wide historical provenance” and
“the deep historical force of colonialism” has shown that caste as it is
known today is not “a residual survival of ancient India but a specifically
colonial form of (that is, substitute for) civil society that both justified and
maintained an Orientalist vision.” 32 As the older political order was re-
placed progressively by colonial rule, caste that had hitherto been em-
bedded into the older structure was disembedded and became amenable
to regulation and administration by the state. In the early colonial sur-
veys of James Buchanan and Colin Mackenzie prior to 1820, the mention
of caste was haphazard and unsystematic, not defining it as India’s dis-
tinctiveness anyway. By 1830s colonial debates came to emphasize caste
as a distinctive feature and much of the mundane reporting in the local-
ities used caste categories although in an ambiguous way by including
occupational and honorific designations. 33 The systematization of caste
was connected with the colonial censuses from 1870s and the develop-
ment of photography from the 1860s. 34 For Cohn, Dirks, and others, the
colonial census enumeration of castes spurred the emergence of this colo-
nial form of civil society as the new political rationalities and technolo-
gies of rule required that individuals be not only counted and classified
but these numerical distributions were to be represented over large blocs
extending across more than one province.
Questioning the views that caste is a colonial invention, an outcome of
the imagination of Western thinkers and their essentializing tendencies
as suggested by Ronald Inden, and that the great Victorian enterprise of
data collection was an one-sided exercise of hegemonic power as Nicho-
las Dirks seemed to suggest, Susan Bayly argues that caste was not an
invention as such but a “meeting ground between Indian reality and
colonial knowledge and strategy,” reshaped or created by colonial ad-
ministrators in different domains of regulation such as the military and
the law. 35 Contradicting the widely-held view that “caste” was the cen-
182 Chapter 5
tral trope in the colonial perception, she argues that it was indeed “race”
nor does she hold that the colonial census of caste was so closely tied to
the colonizers’ need to control and manage the colonized, as believed by
Sudipta Kaviraj and Partha Chatterjee. According to her, the colonial
compilers of caste data were much more concerned with the body of
speculative ethnological scholarship in which biological and moral qual-
ities of “race” were perceived as universal human endowments. From the
late eighteenth century onward, ethnologists sought to classify human
societies based on differential endowments of biological and moral qual-
ities that included European societies as well. Caste was perceived to be
the marker of “race” and caste differences seemed to them to indicate the
differential endowments of “race.” Agreeing partly with Susan Bayly,
Crispin Bates opines that even if the colonial discourse of caste and tribe
was hegemonic, it was not always uncontested and it would therefore not
be quite right to regard it solely as the effect of the colonial project to
normalize society to make it amenable for administrative control. 36 Clear-
ly, Bayly and Bates do not subscribe to Ranajit Guha’s view that the
colonizer could assert dominance without hegemony even under condi-
tions of contestation and resistance. 37
Although each one of these ideas may contain some truth by way of
an explanation, none seem to provide a complete elaboration of the par-
ticular kinds of political rationalities ushered by the colonial state and of
its classificatory needs. The need for controlling an alien population can-
not itself be a sufficient explanation, for even before the systematic census
enumeration from 1871 the people were controlled and governed. Specif-
ic legislations pertaining to castes such as the Caste-Disabilities Removal
Act of 1850 suggest that governing castes did not require their classifica-
tion and enumeration. 38 Although both Kaviraj and Chatterjee have
argued quite correctly that the regime of modern power located in the
institution of the modern state and the discursive needs of such a state
have resulted in classifications and enumerations of population, their
arguments appear to be incomplete for they do not elaborate on the na-
ture and role of such states. It is well known that modern states have been
profoundly interventionist as compared to pre-modern states. The statis-
tical episteme that colonial governmentality instituted provided the
framework of a universal knowledge that was objective, rational, and
scientific. Classification of population became a means of objectification
through the self-identification processes that enumerative practices re-
quired, and generated modal groups that could make normalization pos-
sible through appropriate interventions.
Such normalization of groups was indeed the agenda of the colonial
civilizing mission. If we agree with Foucault that the problem of govern-
ment is best approached, as a rationality of power that directs the con-
duct of individuals and groups, then the governance of “character” or
ethological governance was clearly part of the nineteenth-century liberal
Classification and Society 183
CASTE AS TAXONOMIZER
The early encounters of the British with the local population that pro-
vided the opportunity to record details of caste were the topographical
and revenue surveys. In many of these surveys the category of the popu-
lation was merely enumerated in a manner not very different from other
things such as water works, or religious establishments, or heads of reve-
nue. While castes were enumerated following the broad four-fold varna
classification, within each class they were enumerated just as the survey-
or encountered them in the respective villages, with the particular village
dialect or name. There was not even an attempt to list them alphabetical-
ly. In some instances the occupational association of the caste is given
such as barbers, potters, washermen, toddy drawers, or dancing caste.
There was no attempt to separate tribes except to mention, say for in-
stance “Punchanum” as “five tribes of artificers,” or even for that matter
Muslims from the caste list. 47 However simple-minded this classification
may appear today, it was an early attempt to provide the term jati
(though not used as a term in the listing was nevertheless implied in it)
with a restricted meaning from its very wide semantic coverage. The
term jati can be used in the sense of origin by birth, classes of living
species, varna, lineage or clan, or human collectivities bound by loyalty to
state, nation or province. 48
Well after a hundred years of British presence in India, systematic
caste enumeration on an all-India basis began with the decennial cen-
suses starting from 1871, although a number of surveys and settlement
reports did at times enumerate the castes in the different regions. The
phenomenal nature of caste was not clearly perceived by the British until
the later half of the nineteenth century, and even when it became a con-
186 Chapter 5
cern, they adopted the perspective that castes were relatively discrete
communities with members sharing certain modes of worship, food,
dress, occupation, and an assigned ritual-political standing which deter-
mined their relationships with members of other groups. 49 This led to the
administrative thinking of ordering and counting the castes motivated
perhaps by the objective of ethological governance.
The attempts to fit castes into a rigid classificatory framework of the
censuses had to grapple with numerous issues, as there were a very large
number of jatis in each region. Although not infinite, the problem was
aggravated by the impreciseness and flexibility of caste categories both in
the indigenous nomenclature and in the popular vocabulary. As Rashmi
Pant illustrates, “a Brahman who in Kumaon was a Pant, in Benares
would refer to himself as a Deshashtha Brahman; while a Joshi Brahman of
Kumaon could in Benares call himself by his section and geography as
Kanoujiya Kurmachali, particularly as the Joshis of the plains were consid-
ered very inferior.” 50 Also caste names had to be standardized for pur-
poses of comparison. 51 Because of the large number of jatis emphasis was
placed only on the numerical majorities and selective minorities. 52 The
tabular representation of such majorities and minorities afforded by the
censuses provided a visual numerical display of caste in striking contrast
to the earlier forms of visual display such as portrait sketches found in
Colin Mackenzie’s collections. 53 For instance the 1881 census noted:
The object of the arrangement in the Imperial form was to present to
the eye the distribution of only the major castes by districts, leaving to
the reporter to show in the body of his report either in tabular shape or
otherwise, so much of the information connected with the distribution
and the number of the remaining castes as might be useful. 54
The purpose of a tabular representation is to facilitate comparison for
which uniformity is needed. The 1871–1872 Census sought to classify the
myriad array of jatis by clubbing together the analogous ones and arrang-
ing these hierarchically according to their respective ranks. However,
Henry Waterfield of the Statistics and Commerce Department concluded
that the outcome was “not satisfactory owing partly to the intrinsic diffi-
culties of the subject, and partly to the absence of a uniform plan of
classification, each writer adopting that which seemed to him best suited
for the purpose.” 55 At the 1881 Census, based on the recommendations of
the Census Committee of 1877, a pan-Indian representation of caste struc-
ture was proposed “by aggregating castes, smothering their specific-
ities—hierarchical and interactional, occupational, etc.—and universaliz-
ing certain characteristics on the basis of which castes from disparate
localities could be rendered comparable.” 56 But the envisaged uniformity
was not achieved because of differing principles identified by ethnogra-
phers as underlying the social arrangements, nor could they reject the
Classification and Society 187
four-fold varna model and exclude the influence of the Brahmanical mod-
el from their explanation.
Although J. A. Baines, as the chief Census commissioner of the 1891
Census, had earlier been a protagonist of the view that descent and occu-
pation were the determining criteria of caste status, he directed that the
caste groups be organized within the 1891 imperial tables on a principle
based mainly upon function. What was aimed at in this method, the
Census Commissioner wrote, “was as much uniformity as the nature of
statistics will show, so that the return of each province might be dealt
with on the same basis.” 57 Once again the Census ,ommissioner argued
for uniformity in classifying castes “so that the circumstances of the prov-
inces in respect to sex distribution, education, and marriage customs,
were abstracted, and the prevalence of the selected infirmities . . . may be
accurately compared.” 58 This in turn led first, to the issue of standardiz-
ing names of caste groups and subgroups so that clearly demarcated
categories could emerge, and second to the issue of evolving a hierarchy
of first-order caste names as a series that would have both an all-India
applicability as well as remain stable, that is be unaffected to economic
and political changes of status or to organized lobbying the way the local
variants of caste were subjected to. 59
Although the functional or occupation-based classification of caste
was proposed at the 1891 Census, local officials often used the varna
scheme to hierarchize the castes. The ranking of the Sudra castes posed
particular difficulties. For instance, the relative position of the Gwala caste
in Bihar was fixed by assessing whether customs discouraged by the high
castes such as widow-remarriage were prevalent or not among them; and
by establishing whether Brahmans accepted water from them, and the
other criteria for ranking included whether the caste in question was of
“criminal,” “litigious,” or “peaceful” disposition, the attitude of high
castes towards it, and the period of impurity observed by its members
following the death of a kin. 60
Although right from the beginning there was sensitivity to the issue of
standardizing caste names, the problem never seemed to resolve even
over time. The Commissioner for the 1865 Caste Census of NWP com-
plained that while one collector sent in a return of castes containing more
than 300 different headings, another would condense all the different
castes of his district under half a dozen entries. 61 The Census Commis-
sioner of 1911 for the same region reiterated the same complaint after
more than forty years when he pointed out that respondents often re-
turned names as varied as titles, surnames, the endogamous group, or
the occupation followed when asked to name their caste, which may have
been on account of the flexibility in the indigenous nomenclature, and
being done with the Indian enumerators 62 In order to avoid overlapping
terms and to create unambiguous categories, practical techniques were
evolved for standardizing and hierarchizing caste names.
188 Chapter 5
exogamous group within the caste, and noted further that “no lower unit
than the ‘section’ need be regarded.” That there could be exceptions to
this neat taxonomic structure of species, genus and phylon was recog-
nized by noting that the limits of “caste” and “subcaste” will occasionally
be identical, there being no smaller endogamous groups included under
a common caste name based on occupation. It was also noted that within
the “tribe,” there were many subdivisions, the smallest endogamous
group called the “subtribe,” which will occasionally coincide with the
tribe; and the largest exogamous group within the tribe called the “sept,”
with no lower unit to be taken into consideration. Divisions intermediate
between the “subtribe” and “sept” were to be termed “clans” and “sub-
clans.” 69
Not only would there be exceptions to this hierarchic grouping, it was
noted that even the caste-tribe dichotomy was not that rigid. There could
be cases in which the two types run into each other, “the caste based
upon occupation being made up of tribes or tribal fragments based upon
community of descent.” In these cases, it noted, “the terminology of each
type will be followed so far as the organization stands upon the same
basis as the type, and no further.” The note also explained that in many
cases, the Brahmanical gotras have been adopted or imposed upon castes
and tribes in addition to their proper caste or tribal divisions, and that in
those instances the gotra was not what was wanted but the organic divi-
sions and subdivisions of the caste and tribe, generally called got by the
people themselves as distinguished from gotra in the strict Brahmanical
sense. Here too, there were the exceptions, as occasionally these organic
divisions and the gotras were identical, but where they were distinct,
several gotras ran through the same got division or the same gotra through
several gots, but their identification was not difficult as the people them-
selves often did not know the gotra, their being used only by the officiat-
ing Brahman priests. 70
A set of twenty-seven questions to identify the essential traits of each
of the castes and tribes followed their note of suggestions clarifying the
ethnographic nomenclature. The inquiry ranged from marriage practices,
origin of the caste, whether settled or wandering, admission of outsiders
into the fold, practice of infant and adult marriage, polygamy and poly-
andry, marriage ceremony, widow remarriage, permittance of divorce,
inheritance practices, religion and forms of worship, disposal of dead,
employment of Brahmin priests, propitiation of ancestors, totemism, the
castes’ belief as to their original occupation, details of occupations prac-
ticed, prevalence of prostitution, dietary habits, the relationship with oth-
er castes as to eating, drinking, and smoking. The instructions took care
that the answers to all these questions were properly authorized by “gha-
taks, genealogists, heads of panchayats, or . . . any hereditary official,” it
only took care to establish the authenticity of a custom, tradition or prac-
tice. The more difficult problem of the quantum of information that must
192 Chapter 5
have come forth on the wide range of issues for all the castes would have
dismayed even the most skilled in fitting a taxonomic structure to them.
The other problem was that there were constant changes going on day
by day in the customs of the subdivisions of each caste, and these affected
the social position of the members, even of a caste change, or the emer-
gence of a new caste. The adoption of Brahmanical customs of infant
marriage and vegetarianism by one section of a caste, the phenomenon
popularized by Indian sociologist M. N. Srinivas as “Sanskritization” and
to which ample illustrations are provided in the early census reports, will
in due course raise the status of the caste in the social estimation. New
castes evolve not only through the adoption of the customs of the superi-
or castes, but owing to changes in the occupation as a common occupa-
tion will combine members of different castes into a new caste over time,
even if Molony, the 1911 census commissioner of Madras exaggerated
when he observed, “the idea of innate superiority or inferiority is being
exploded from underneath,” and that “Paraiyan Brahmans” may mani-
fest themselves in a few decades.
If the early censuses exhibited optimism about the possibility of clas-
sifying and enumerating castes, the later censuses recognized the com-
plexity of that task even while attempting to do so. The project of compil-
ing glossaries of castes and tribes evolved out of this difficulty. Risley’s
survey of Bengal published in four volumes as the Tribes and Castes of
Bengal; and subsequent glossaries of communities under the generic title
of Tribes and Castes were published between 1896 and 1916 for North-
Western Provinces, Southern India, Punjab and Noth-Western Provinces,
and the Central Provinces sought to investigate the defining features of
each caste and tribe by which they could be identified as a discrete group
and be enumerated. The 1891 Census report for the Madras Presidency
carried a Caste Index indicating all the recorded subcastes for each of the
main castes. A Tamil cultivating caste group Ambalakkaran had a total of
167,421 members and were divided into twenty-five subcastes. 71 Another
cultivating caste, Agamudaiyan, which though the 1901 glossary indicated
had depleted considerably in the previous thirty years having probably
risen in the social scale and calling themselves as Vellalas, had neverthe-
less 234 subcastes listed under it in the 1891 Caste Index, with the further
problem of a not inconsiderable repetition of subcastes between two ma-
jor caste groups. 72 By the time of the 1911 census the need to contain
them in fewer and fewer subcastes was recognized, and the 1911 chapter
on Caste in the report of the Madras Presidency opened with the state-
ment that there were “479 sets of people, each wearing a distinctive la-
bel,” a not inconsiderable reduction given the fact that the 1891 index had
over 800 subcastes for just Kapus and Vellalas, and noted that this formid-
able total would have “swollen indefinitely, were the titles returned by
each and every person duly recorded.” 73
Classification and Society 193
At least in the later census years, the Census officials were aware of
the effects of their classificatory exercise, as Middleton, the Census Super-
intendent for Punjab, at the 1921 Census noted:
Caste in itself was rigid among the higher castes, but malleable
amongst the lower. We pigeon-holed every one by caste, and if we
could not find a true caste for them, labelled them with the name of an
hereditary occupation. . . . Government’s passion for labels and pigeon-
holes has led to a crystallization of the caste system, which except
amongst the aristocratic castes, was really very fluid under indigenous
rule. 74
THEORIES OF CASTE
oped and perpetuated to an unusual degree; that the four-fold caste clas-
sification of Brahman, Kshatriya, Vaisya, and Sudras was quite anachron-
istic, and that the number of castes which can be classed under any one or
under none of the four heads was almost innumerable, and that nothing
could be “more variable and more difficult to define than caste.” 76
Exploring the origins of caste afforded the opportunity of recasting
the mythic past into a historical one drawing from Orientalist knowledge,
as when Ibbetson noted the two distinct epochs in the post-Vedic history
of Hindu nations. The earlier one of the Brahmanas and the Upanishads
was one in which Hinduism was a single and comparatively simple
creed, during which caste distinctions were primarily based upon occu-
pations but in which there existed considerable flexibility for castes, and
individuals could rise from one caste to another. In the later epoch of the
Puranas and Tantras, the caste system became strict and occupation as-
sumed a cardinal importance. The hereditary nature of occupation be-
came a feature only later when Brahmanism substituted Hinduism, a
phenomenon clarified by Ibbetson in the simple sentence—“In the earlier
epoch the priest was always a Brahman; in the later the Brahman was
always a priest.” Noting that the contemporary period was not very dif-
ferent from the early phase as caste restrictions made change in the up-
ward direction infinitely slow and more difficult, Ibbetson remarked:
As in all other countries and among all other nations, the graduations
of the social scale are fixed; but society is not solid but liquid, and
portions of it are continually rising and sinking and changing their
position as measured by that scale. . . . There cannot be the slightest
doubt that in a few generations the materials for a study of caste as an
institution will be infinitely less complete than they are even now. 77
Colonial knowledge needed to unravel the puzzle of the caste-
occupation nexus not only to explain the origin of caste but also to ensure
the supply of skilled and unskilled labor as new industrial activity was
spurred by the colonial capitalist development in the latter half of the
nineteenth century. Both at the 1871 and 1881 Census castes were clas-
sified under occupational groups under seventeen main and 254 sub-
groups in the Madras Presidency, an arrangement that did not distin-
guish the high castes from the low. Again at the 1891 Census for instance,
the castes were grouped into the functional classes of Agricultural and
Pastoral, Professional, Commercial, Artisans and Village menials, Va-
grants, and Races and Indefinite titles; each of these classes were divided
into many subclasses of occupations. The classifying officers were given
to understand clearly that the occupation to which the caste in question
was to be credited was not necessarily that actually exercised by the caste
in the present day but that which was assigned to it by tradition.
Classification and Society 195
used to typify each race. This was done for the different tribes and castes
in each racial type. The colorful ethnological map indicating the distribu-
tion by physical types divided the subcontinent into seven racial types—
the Mongoloid, Indo-Aryan, Dravidian, Mongolo-Dravidian, Aryo-Dra-
vidian, Scytho-Dravidian, and Turko-Iranian. 90 Risley observed that if a
series of castes were taken in Bengal, Bihar, the United Provinces, or
Madras and arranged them in the order of the average nasal index with
the finest nose at the top, the order corresponded with the accepted order
of social precedence. 91 Risley believed that caste endogamy preserved the
physical differences between various castes, endorsing Dirk’s opinion
that Risley’s views on caste not merely marked his “imperial conceit” but
that he “fashioned a peculiar symbiosis between the racial anxieties of
imperial Britain and the ritual anxieties of the Brahmans and other higher
castes at the turn of the century.” 92
Thirty years later, at the 1931 census, Risley’s conclusions were found
unsatisfactory and open to doubt. The archeological evidence from Mo-
henjodaro had disproved his conception of India as isolated from the rest
of Asia and inhabited by barbarous tribes until the Aryan invasion of
circa 1500 B.C. Also his explanations that brachycephaly in the west of
India was due to Scythian invasion in historic times was called into ques-
tion on the ground that the population so introduced was never so nu-
merous as to make so dramatic a change in the somatic characteristics of
the population, and brachycephaly in Bengal as Mongolian was also
found to be untenable. 93 Not only were some of his conclusions ques-
tioned, but his methods as well. Although he had prepared a book on
Anthropometric Measurements and taught the measurers himself both the
techniques of measurement and the use of instruments, his method of
choosing subjects raised doubts for serious statistical analysis. He had
advised the rejection of men of “very black complexion with broad de-
pressed noses,” and “of very fair complexion with high-caste type of
features” in samples respectively of the upper and lower castes. While it
was felt that a measure of caution was necessary to exclude spurious
cases from the samples, it was felt that there was no justification for
excluding persons on grounds of physical appearance alone, and was
seen as an attempt to set up a preconceived “standard type for each
caste.” 94 Also the number of measurements and what was measured of
each individual in different regions in Risley’s survey was not uniform.
Although the International Agreement of Monaco set standards for meas-
urement based on the system propounded by the French anthropologists
Broca and Topinard, and many of Risley’s techniques of measurement
conformed to that, there were many measurements that were not spec-
ified in it as well. For instance whether the nasal root should be the
deepest point of the nasal depression as Risley took it to be, or whether it
should correspond to the median point in the fronto-nasal stature as
Topinard seemed to indicate, came up for discussion. Above all, Karl
200 Chapter 5
CLASSIFICATION BY RELIGION
marking that “a little red paint smeared over a stone, a lump of clay, or
the stump of a tree converts it into a god worshipped by the lower classes
and saluted by the upper with much apparent devotion.” 102 Many sur-
veyors engaged in the trignometrical surveys in the first half of the nine-
teenth century also made similar observations. According to Ronald In-
den, “Hinduism” became one of the master tropes for understanding and
controlling a mass of population that claimed some shared religious be-
lief and yet followed widely differing practices. 103 Needless to say, this
master trope contained the potential for reification in large-scale surveys
of enumeration and classification such as the census that classifies ac-
cording to discrete religious categories, thus attempting to straitjacket
ecumenical diversity into a unified and rigid framework.
Recently, both Norbert Peabody and Sumit Guha have provided evi-
dence of precolonial and early colonial efforts at enumerating and regu-
lating communities by religion. The Mughal ruler Aurangazeb imposed a
poll tax on non-Muslims that could have been possible only if the com-
munities were enumerated. The Maratha rulers from the mid-eighteenth
century onward sought to maintain the boundaries of communities bas-
ing on the ideals of their founding ruler Shivaji, and a Maratha official in
the late eighteenth century intervened when it was found that there was
intermarriage between the tailors group and indigo-dyers group, who
presumably were Muslims and Hindus. 104 Peabody has shown that
household enumeration by Munhata Nainsi of the towns of Marwar in
1664, though local and segmented, was caste-sensitive in which Muslims
were regarded as one among the castes. The functional requirement of
such a household inventory was attuned to the taxation needs of the time,
wherein hearth taxes and other occupation related taxes like wheel tax,
anvil tax and tax on carded cotton were imposed. Peabody notes that
such castewise listing of households was characteristic of all Khanasumar-
is, the traditional statistical system that was prevalent in most regions.
Comparing Nainsi’s household inventory with a later colonial enumera-
tion of Boileau, the 1835 census of Merta and Pokharana, Peabody has
noted that in Boileau’s census the first-order classification of nonpurify-
ing castes and purifying castes is replaced by an alphabetic listing of all
castes, and the first-order classification for Boileau becomes “Hindus”
and “Muslims.” In the language of taxonomic classification, whereas in
Nainsi’s census, Hindu castes and Muslim castes were made to differ at
the level of species; in the Boileau classification, they were made to differ
at the level of genus. Peabody observes, “through this re-ordering of the
data, Boileau took a very real, but relatively narrow basis of distinction
and made it far wider.” 105 Although it is not clear on what basis he claims
it as a “relatively narrow basis of distinction,” he may be on the mark
when he notes that this move was reproduced countless times in subse-
quent enumerations which would have had some consequences for com-
munal relations in the later period.
Classification and Society 203
At the 1871 Census, the first all-India one, the census officials sought
to collect only eight pieces of information: age, name, caste, religion, type
of dwelling, race or nationality, literacy, and infirmities. Confident that
they would have no difficulties in defining Hinduism, religion was one
among the three questions with pre-coded response categories. Provin-
cial commissioners were instructed that every individual should be
classed into one of the five categories—Buddhist, Christian, Hindu, Mus-
lim, and Other. Several provinces prepared substantive checklists for
each religion so as to enable enumerators to identify the religion of the
respondent. While for Buddhist, Christian, and Muslim there was at least
one unambiguous substantive characteristic such as reverence for Bud-
dha, or Jesus, or Allah, there was no such unique characteristic for the
Hindu. Different provinces had different substantive characteristics on
the checklist such as reading the Vedas, worship of Siva, receiving in-
struction from a Brahman or caste affiliation, but all of these were not
sufficiently discriminatory or inclusive of all Hindus and had to be
dropped. Aware that the definition of the Hindu had to be relaxed to be
more inclusive, the category of “Hindu” in the Madras Presidency in-
cluded “all the aboriginal and mountain tribes, whether they observed
caste distinctions or not.” 106 In Bombay, enumerators were instructed
that “all believers in the Vedas must be entered as Hindoo, and so, too,
must those wild tribes whose original religions are lost, and who now, to
all intents and purposes are Hindoo by religion but not by race.” 107 The
definition of a Hindu used in the Bombay Presidency was even vague as
a Hindu was anyone “who simply worship [s] some god or goddess
without knowing anything of the theology.” 108 In the province of My-
sore, the 1871 census recorded the sub-sects of Hindu whose faith and
practices differ from each other such as “Saivas,” “Lingayets,” “Madh-
vacharis,” “Ramanujas,” “Swami Narayens,” “Wallabhacharyas,” “Kabir
Panthis,” and “Brijmargis.” The Coorg Census of 1871 also listed the
“Jain” and “Coorgs” with other subsects of Hindus.
At the 1881 Census it was resolved that the subsects of Hinduism
would not be recorded though the definition of “Hindu” eluded census
officials for there was no single identifiable characteristic to qualify one
as a Hindu. For every potential Hindu trait, there were groups of popula-
tion that were exceptions. Yet the category “Hinduism” remained even if
many census officials were dissatisfied with it. At the 1891 Census, the
Arya Samaj, a Hindu revivalist organization then in north India, raised
objections to the category “Hinduism” as it felt it to be a negative conno-
tation ascribed by the Muslim rulers of those living beyond the River
Indus, and who did not belong to the Muslim faith. Although its appeal
to reject the term from the census schedule was rejected, it did ask its
followers to identify themselves as “Arya.” By the time of the 1901 Cen-
sus, the category and enumeration of “Hindus” became more politicized
as some among Muslims contested that an overly expansive notion of
204 Chapter 5
“Hindu” included those practicing some form of animistic and other mi-
nor religions that inflated the numbers of the majoritarian group, with a
corresponding decrease in the proportion of Muslims in the population,
which they felt was unfavorable to the Muslims in the context of propor-
tional representation to Legislative Councils that was to take effect as also
in the distribution of educational resources and other privileges. 109 Antic-
ipating an intensification of dissent at the 1911 Census, the Imperial Cen-
sus commissioner E. A. Gait sought to tweak the categories suggesting
first that provincial census commissioners “report as to the criteria which
might be taken to determine whether or not a man is a genuine Hindu in
the popular acceptation of the term” (and that they might consider intro-
ducing a new category “debatable Hindus.” 110 As most provincial com-
missioners were not pleased with the category “debatable Hindus,” it
was withdrawn. Regarding the criteria for determining a genuine “Hin-
du,” some census officials felt that race or the caste test would determine
who is a “Hindu,” while others opined that it was “religious beliefs and
deeds.” The Census commissioner had relative omnipotence to define the
category, as he rejected each of these suggestions but combined them all,
and defined a “Hindu” as one who behaved like a Hindu (worshipping
certain deities or claiming allegiance to a caste), looked like a Hindu (by
being of Aryan descent), or lived among Hindus. Michael Haan observes
that this definition marked the emergence, at least in the census, “of the
idea that being Hindu meant being Indian.” 111 The 1921 Census Commis-
sioner endorsed this definition noting “Hindu is an unsatisfactory cate-
gory in the classification of religion, but one that would remain. In the
first place, Hinduism is not only or essentially a religion. The term also
implies country, race and a social organization.” 112 Noting that an Indian
journal has suggested that all Indians should call themselves Hindu, the
Census commissioner Marten further observed “[T]his extreme territorial
view of the term Hindu emphasizes an underlying feeling that, apart
from those who are definitely assignable to some other religious commu-
nity, every man born into a recognized Indian racial or social group has
an indigenous right to be or become a Hindu of some kind, and it is on
some such vague and almost negative conception as this that the census
classification of Hindus has necessarily to be based.” 113 What for Marten
was an “almost negative conception,” namely “the indigenous right to be
or become a Hindu of some kind” has evolved into a contentious issue of
religious conversion in postcolonial India.
The difficulty in classifying “Hindus” favored the colonial administra-
tion, as granting an autonomous identity to the majority population
would have posed a menacing threat to them, while it was less risky for
them to focus on local customs and castes to make sense of Indian soci-
ety. 114 Such difficulty in classifying a “Hindu” has in recent times led to a
vigourous debate, much like in the case of caste, as to whether “Hindu-
ism” itself is a construct of the colonial censuses. 115 The lack of consensus
Classification and Society 205
OCCUPATIONAL CLASSIFICATION
All intentional acts are acts under a description, and as new modes of
description come into being, it also brings in consequence new possibil-
ities for action. 126 The new possibilities of governance that were rendered
possible by classifying and enumerating Indian society were premised on
the principles of the modern State, which principles in the European
context since Hobbes has meant the end of civil strife, a government of
laws, a dichotomy between sovereign and subject, and between public
policy and private morality. These enabled the state to intervene in both
the sphere of morality and of politics, first by transforming issues of
morality into social phenomenon, postulating social laws governing be-
havior and modifying the latter through techniques of control, planning
208 Chapter 5
and prediction, and bringing more and more of the sphere of morality
into the former sphere by a process of secularization.
In the colonial context, the institution of the colonial state entailed a
redefinition of the spheres of policy and morality. As individuals existed
not under situations of equality and autonomy but with primordial ties
of caste and were subjected to rule-governed behavior, in fact a kind of
social discipline imposed by the caste communities, it was necessary to
first understand the institution of caste as new forms of political rational-
ities were to undergird practices of governance. Bernard Cohn’s view is
that reducing whole demographic groups to their caste characteristics
was especially attractive to the colonial administrator as “it gave the
illusion of knowing the people; he (the administrator) did not have to
differentiate too much among individual Indians—a man was a Brahman
and a Brahman had certain characteristics.” 127 While caste had existed for
long, there were certainly changes in the form and content of that social
discipline as those seemingly “modern solvents” of the system, i.e., the
institutions, practices, and processes of modernization were to take roots.
From the latter half of the nineteenth century, the railways brought peo-
ple of different castes in close proximity, but other institutions such as the
schools and the prisons were for a long time grappling with the issues of
segregation and desegregation. There were many other instances that
modern life posed for the issue of castes. As British administrators, fol-
lowing the then-widely prevalent practice, used caste names as a mode of
description of persons, there were a large number of governmental
records that gave caste details. The police reports gave details of the caste
of the offender, and the railway risk-note had an entry for caste and
expected every sender of parcels to record their caste. Such caste entries
became a quick and easy way to form a rough estimate of the moral
character of the persons, based on typified understanding of caste
groups. 128 In the post-mutiny period, the categories embedded in cen-
suses, gazetteers, and revenue books, became ever more closely tied to
the administrative concerns of the state. 129 But mere enumeration and
classification of population alone was not sufficient as more information
was needed to “interpret” the statistics, indeed as we have well illustrat-
ed, even to constitute the statistics. Detailed ethnographic notes compiled
as glossaries and gazetteers were needed, and group studies were initiat-
ed to identify those likely to be loyal to the British or not.
In 1881, Ibbetson, the Census commissioner of Punjab observed, “Our
ignorance of the customs and beliefs of the people among whom we
dwell is surely in some respects a reproach to us; for not only does that
ignorance deprive European science of material which it greatly needs,
but it also involves a distinct loss of administrative power to our-
selves.” 130 Summarizing the advantages expected to flow from Risley’s
ethnographic survey, C. E. Buckland, officiating secretary to the govern-
ment of Bengal, wrote:
Classification and Society 209
The more Government officers know about the religious and social
customs of the people of their districts, the better able they will be to
deal with either the possible social problems of the future, or with the
practical questions arising in their ordinary work, such as the relations
of different castes to the land, their privileges in respect of rent, their
relations to trade, their status in civil society, their internal organiza-
tion, their rules as to marriage and divorce, and as to the giving and
receiving of famine-relief. 131
The statement in the Government of India Resolution at the time of the
announcement of the ethnographic survey of India indicates the political
importance attached to caste, as it noted:
It is unnecessary to dwell at length upon the obvious advantages to
many branches of the administration in this country of an accurate and
well-arranged record of the customs and the domestic and social rela-
tions of the various castes and tribes. The entire framework of native
life in India is made up of groups of this kind, and the status and
conduct of individuals are largely determined by the rules of the group
to which they belong. For the purposes of legislation, of judicial proce-
dure, of famine relief, of sanitation and dealings with epidemic disease,
and of almost every form of executive action, an ethnographic survey
of India, and a record of the customs of the people is as necessary an
incident of good administration as a cadastral survey of the land and a
record of the rights of its tenants. The census provides the necessary
statistics; it remains to bring out and interpret the facts, which lie be-
hind the statistics. 132
Classification of the population through the Census was by no means the
only instance of classifying population, but the decontextualized enumer-
ation, aggregation and systematization afforded by the censuses along
with the mass of ethnographic information collected in the volumes on
“Castes and Tribes,” District Manuals and Gazetteers provided for the
first time the possibility of discursively articulating “society” and social
change that was necessary to report on the “moral and material
progress.”
The classificatory logic borrowed at times from prevalent European
ideas framed policies of colonial rule and defined the behavior of popula-
tions to suit the administrative ends. For instance, British ideas of native
criminality evolved around race, caste and groups in part because preco-
lonial Indian notion of policing and justice was in tandem with the caste
hierarchy as stipulated in the Code of Manu (Manusmriti) wherein of-
fences were defined and punished according to caste, respectability and
social norms. Instances such as prison administration and the administra-
tion of “Thugee” and the so-called criminal tribes required identification,
classification, and enumeration even though the notion of “Thug” lacked
precision and the defining line between “thugee,” dacoity, and highway
robbery was not so clear. 133 Even so, the notion of communities social-
210 Chapter 5
ized into criminal activities did not emerge suddenly in the 1830s but was
coterminous with the start of judicial activities by the Company in Ben-
gal. Many communities across the length and breadth of the country
were identified as criminal communities. 134 Warren Hastings introduced
Article 35 of 1772 which extended punishment for dacoity from the indi-
vidual offender to his family and village, justifying it on the grounds that
the dacoits of India were not like other criminals, being “robbers by pro-
fession, and even by birth; they are formed into regular communities.” 135
The primary objective of such categorizations was to construe the col-
onized as a population of degenerate type on the basis of social origin in
order to justify conquest and to establish a system of administration. In
order to introduce Western legal systems, native legal systems were
deemed inferior. Malcolm, in his Memoir of Central India, in 1823 classified
the Pindaris (marauder remnants of the Maratha armies who became
predators or robbers) into the “peaceful” and “predatory” with a further
subdivision as those who plundered because of political anarchy and
those “tribes brought into Central India in a military capacity who had
turned mercenaries.” Recognizing that certain “predatory” associations
did not fit into any distinct social class or tribe, he placed the thugs in a
category of “associations of men of all tribes . . . whose object is to live
upon the community.” Criteria such as dietary habits and a wandering
way of life were deployed to lump diverse groups into one social catego-
ry, as for instance under the term “Badhak.” 136
The imprecise definitions of the criminal community and the increas-
ing range of targeted collectivities such as thug gang, dacoit tribe/gang,
and wandering gang meant enfolding a flexible space for prosecutorial
license right within a legal framework. 137 Administration of the Thugee
involved devising appropriate strategies for policing these communities
and of ways of “reclaiming” them to a more settled way of life. Phrenolo-
gy was used to assess the effect of caste and religion on the brain that
causes them to indulge in dacoity and robbery. Henry Spry, medical
officer at Sagar in 1832–1834 sent seven skulls of thug leaders who were
executed to the phrenological society at Edinburgh to contribute to the
knowledge about the influence of caste and religion on the “lower feel-
ings” in the human brain. 138
The colonialist construction of “criminal tribes” resulted in the Crimi-
nal Tribes Act of 1871 with periodic amendments to the Act embodying
the assumptions of inborn criminality that underwent changes in some
instances with the search for “scientific explanations” of crimes in the
later decades. These Acts regulated the movement of certain groups of
wandering and vagrant populations and subjected them to surveillance
thus illustrating the utility of classification. 139
The identification of the criminal castes and tribes was not unlike the
other instances of typification as in one instance, it was noted that the
physique of the criminal castes, when fed properly, differed very little
Classification and Society 211
from that of the other castes as they do not have that flattened head with
ears low down and long, which suggests a criminal. The ethnographic
entry for the caste “Kallan” in the 1901 Census glossary of Madras Presi-
dency introduced the caste with a long paragraph of the incidence of
purported crimes committed by the caste members in the different dis-
tricts from the police records. Attempts to reform the hereditary, habitu-
al, and incorrigible criminals coincided with the need to find easy labor in
the newly established quarries, mines, factories, mills, and tea and coffee
plantations.
Such immediate uses of caste data for administration were probably
not too frequent, leading to the view that a surplus of caste information
was generated. No sooner was the census data on sex ratios cross-
tabulated with caste, it became easy to identify groups that practiced
female infanticide, and the legislation banning such a practice could be
implemented by monitoring those groups. Other categories of caste such
as money lending, agricultural, or “martial” were used as a basis for
legislation controlling land transfers, the grant of proprietary rights, and
the regulation of rents, as well as a basis for distinguishing between the
loyal and the disloyal, and for recruiting to the armed forces. 140 The
attempt to define a social morphology in terms of caste and to under-
stand behavioral patterns in terms of caste groups was derived from the
basic understanding that the “individual” in the strict sense had not
evolved, and it was these caste communities that were made to appear
discrete that could be the units of control.
Even as colonial rule brought, on the one hand, legislations that were
to dissolve the caste principle, such as the Special Marriage Act of 1872
permitting intercaste marriage, there were others, the army and the civil
service, that strengthened the caste principle. After 1857, the colonial
administration diversified the composition of lower castes in the army as
it suspected that upper caste recruits had instigated the rebellion. As
increasing number of Brahmans were recruited in the civil service and
they quickly perceived the benefits of English education, the non-Brah-
man castes began to raise objections. Provincial governments were then
advised to seek the caste and subcastes of the applicants thus becoming
potential sites of ethnic nationalism. 141
The occupational classification was to render itself useful to define the
productive labor force distributed in different sectors, especially for the
newly emerging sectors of production. This suggests that conceptions of
“society” were evolved to promote administration and those of the
“economy” was dictated by logics of the colonial economy.
The most potent effect of classifying and enumerating population was
the formation of collective subjectivities, what Benedict Anderson has
highlighted by consideration of the material, institutional and discursive
bases that generate two contrasting types of seriality—unbound and
bound. 142 For Anderson, “unbound seriality” has its origins in the print
212 Chapter 5
against the mention of castes among Muslims. At the 1941 Census, Jin-
nah, president of the All-India Muslim League sought to do away even
with the “Momins” and “non-Momins” classification. Although the 1931
Census retained the caste column, individuals were given the option of
not recording their caste if they so wished. In March 1939, Indian legisla-
tor S. Satyamurti remarked in the Central Legislative Assembly that the
government must not divide up the country into castes, and should drop
all information about castes considering the public opinion on the issue.
With the emergence of dyarchy and proportional representation caste
consciousness would feed into the representational politics. Language
entries in the census whether Urdu or Hindi or other languages and
dialects also became contentious as communal politics intensified. Even
the classification of “Tribes” has been seen to result in the reduction of
the Hindu and Muslim population with its implications for communal
representation from those parts. 152 As ethnic and nationalist politics
sought to delegitimize colonial rule, caste and religion moved in its func-
tion as the site of control to being a potent weapon of “divide and rule.”
What Hegel saw as inhibiting the development of the State was made
integral to its politics!
colonial census reports would not fail to notice the numerous references
to the lower castes’ emulation of the habits and customs of the higher
castes in order to gain a higher social status. Both Max Weber’s ideas on
the Hinduization process and the thesis of Sanskritization propounded
by sociologist M. N. Srinivas bear the influence of these colonial census
reports. The failure of the censuses to fit a taxonomy to castes that was
applicable at the all-India level generated an interest in doing so at vil-
lage, local, and regional levels, even as it inspired the grand treatise of
“Homo Hierarchicus” by Louis Dumont. McKim Marriott’s successful
attempt at finding hierarchy in the caste structure of a set of villages
based on a transactional matrix, much like Risley’s order of social prece-
dence, was pursued by a number of other non-Indian scholars, even as
some examined both hierarchy and dominance in the rural social struc-
ture. 154 In the shift of focus of caste analysis from the all-India to the
village level, M. N. Srinivas restored to caste its political character in the
sociological analysis, what the census tables and the caste glossaries had
erased. 155 He argued that precolonial political systems placed territorial
limitations on horizontal extension of caste ties which were freed under
colonial rule. The development of roads, railways, posts, telegraph, avail-
ability of cheap paper and printing in regional languages enabled castes
to organize as never before, emphasizing that the availability of cheap
paper enabled caste disputes to be recorded which gave permanent form
to rules and precedents, which till then had depended on the falliable,
and therefore challengeable, memory of the elders. 156
As the unfulfilled aspirations of development, equity, and justice con-
front the postcolonial nation-state, enumerative politics has acquired new
dimensions. 157 The ordering of castes at the country level still remains a
problem for the state as it unrolls its policies of protective discrimination.
In the last two decades, the politics over the Mandal Commission recom-
mendations for reservation of government jobs and seats in educational
institutions to OBCs (Other Backward Classes) has witnessed demands
by communities to be deemed “backward,” in striking contrast to the
earlier colonial census counts where the clamor was to gain higher social
status. 158 As these demands propel a neverending series of like demands,
the state has embarked once again at the 2011 Census to record and
classify castes that was suspended after the 1931 Census. The state initiat-
ed new People of India project that completed its multi-volume ethno-
graphic compedium in the last two decades retained and updated many
characteristics of the colonial classificatory methods much like the earlier
one undertaken by Risley except for its emphasis on national unity and
the linkages between communities. 159 Clearly the classificatory rationales
of the modern state are tied to state projects of simplification, to render
visible and legible the complex space of governance.
Classification and Society 215
NOTES
1. Ian Hacking, “How Should We Do the History of Statistics?” Ideology and Con-
sciousness, 1979. Also published in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, ed.
Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1991), 192.
2. Hacking, “Bio-Power and the Avalanche of Printed Numbers,” 282.
3. Ian Hacking, Historical Ontology (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2002),
189.
4. J. R. Dinwiddy, “Bentham on Invention in Legislation,” in Jeremy Bentham: Criti-
cal Assessments vol. 3, ed. Bhikhu Parekh (New York: Routledge, 1993), 814.
5. Jeremy Bentham, “Chrestomathia,” in The Works of Jeremy Bentham 11 vols, ed.
John Bowring (Edinburgh, 1843), 216.
6. Bentham, The Works of Jeremy Bentham, vol VIII, 278–79.
7. Mary Poovey, “The Social Constitution of ‘Class’: Toward a History of Classifi-
catory Thinking” in Rethinking Class: Literary Studies and Social Formations ed. Wai Chee
Dimock and Michael T. Gilmore (New York: Columbia University Press, 1994), 16.
8. John Herschel Preliminary Discourse on the Study of Natural Philosophy, 1830, cited
in Poovey, A History of the Modern Fact.
9. Bentham, The Works of Jeremy Bentham, vol. IV, 542.
10. F. A. Hayek, “Sociology: Comte and his Successors,” in The Counter-Revolution of
Science: Studies on the Abuse of Reason (Chicago: The Free Press, 1952).
11. Hacking, The Taming of Chance, 4.
12. Hacking, following A. C. Crombie, notes that ordering of variety by comparison
and taxonomy is a style of reasoning like statistical analysis of regularities of popula-
tion. See Hacking, The Taming of Chance, 6.
13. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament, 318.
14. Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj, 114.
15. Sudipta Kaviraj, “On the Construction of Colonial Power: Structure, Discourse,
Hegemony,” Occasional Papers on History and Society (New Delhi: Nehru Memorial
Museum and Library, (February 1991), 29–30.
16. The locus-classicus of this viewpoint is Bernard Cohn, “The Census, Social
Structure and Objectification in South Asia,” in An Anthropologist among Historians and
Other Essays (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1987/1990), 224–54.
17. Anderson, Imagined Communities.
18. Nicholas B. Dirks, “Castes of Mind,” Representations 37 Special Issue, Imperial
Fantasies and Postcolonial Histories (Winter 1992): 60.
19. Nicholas. B. Dirks, Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of Modern India
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001), 79.
20. Kaviraj, “On the Construction of Colonial Power: Structure, Discourse, Hege-
mony,” 29–30.
21. Cohn, “Notes on the History of the Study of Indian Society and Culture,” 154.
For a conceptual understanding of “frame” and “overflow,” see Callon, “An essay on
framing and overflowing: economic externalities revisited by sociology,” 244–69.
22. Hacking, Historical Ontology.
23. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science, trans. Walter Kaufmann (New York: Vin-
tage Books, 1887/1974), Aphorism 58.
24. See Cohn, “The Census, Social Structure and Objectification in South Asia” in
An Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays, 230.
25. G. S. Ghurye, Caste and Race in India (London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner and
Co, 1932).
26. Louis Dumont, Homo Hierarchicus (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).
27. Cohn, An Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays.
28. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination,” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament.
216 Chapter 5
29. See Kaviraj, “On the Construction of Colonial Power: Structure, Discourse, Heg-
emony;” and Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 16–22. The colonial construction
of difference has also been analyzed in Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj.
30. M. Nobles, Shades of Citizenship: Race and the Census in Modern Politics (Stanford:
Stanford University Press, 2000); and Christopher, “The Quest for a Census of the
British Empire c. 1840–1940.”
31. David Cannadine, Ornamentalism: How the British Saw their Empire (New York:
Oxford University Press, 2001), xix, 43–46.
32. Dirks, Castes of Mind, 60.
33. Bayly, Empire and Information, 168.
34. Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj, 116–17.
35. Susan Bayly, “Caste and ‘Race’ in the Colonial Ethnography of India,” in The
Concept of Race in South Asia, ed. Peter Robb (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1997),
166; Nicholas. B. Dirks, “The Invention of Caste: Civil Society in Colonial India,” Social
Analysis 25 (September 1989): 42–51; and Ronald Inden, Imagining India (London:
Blackwell, 1990).
36. Crispin Bates, “Race, Caste, and Tribe in Central India: The Early Origins of
Indian Anthropometry,” in The Concept of Race in South Asia, ed. Peter Robb (Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 1997), 219–59.
37. Sumit Guha, “Lower Strata, Older Races, and Aboriginal Peoples: Racial
Anthropology and Mythical History Past and Present,” The Journal of Asian Studies 57,
2 (May 1998): 423–41.
38. This Act of 1850 did not remove civil disabilities existing between castes but
facilitated the conversion and admission to another religion or caste, by way of pro-
tecting the person’s ordinary property rights. See Ghurye, Caste and Race in India, 152.
39. Melanie White, “The Liberal Character of Ethological Governance,” Economy
and Society 34, 3 (August 2005): 476.
40. John Stuart Mill, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive: Being a connected
view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation (London: Long-
mans, 1843/1974), 457.
41. Mill, A System of Logic Ratiocinative and Inductive, 440–1.
42. White, “The Liberal Character of Ethological Governance.”
43. Stuart Woolf indicates that the structural tie between ethnography and statistics
was a characteristic feature of nineteenth century collection of state-sponsored statis-
tics in France, although not so in Britain. The vast official statistical enquiries would
include the exploration of social customs and practices. See Stuart Woolf, “Statistics
and the Modern State,” Comparative Studies in Society and History 31, 3 (July, 1989):
588–604.
44. Dirks, Castes of Mind, 43.
45. Dirks, “Castes of Mind.”
46. Hegel, The Philosophy of History.
47. These points are made after examining Memoir No 88, (p. 1), (p. 45) p. 45(2),
Survey of India volume no 231 (1825–1830), 45.
48. See the chapter “Communities and the Nation,” in Chatterjee, The Nation and its
Fragments, and note the references to the various dictionaries from which he draws the
multiple senses of the term.
49. Rashmi Pant, “The Cognitive Status of Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Re-
view of some Literature on the North-West Provinces and Oudh,” Indian Economic and
Social History Review 24, 2 (June 1987): 145–62.
50. Pant, “The Cognitive Status of Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of
some Literature on the North-West Provinces and Oudh,” 154.
51. These issues have been succinctly analyzed in Pant, “The Cognitive Status of
Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of some Literature on the North-West Prov-
inces and Oudh.”
52. It appears that even in the first caste census of NWP in 1865, only the most
numerous subcastes of Brahmans, Kshatriyas, Vaishyas and Shudras were recorded in the
Classification and Society 217
report. In the 1872 census again, only the numerically dominant castes were recorded
by “pargana” as the “Great Castes.” Out of 304 separate subdivision names recorded
for the non-twice born castes, the district-wise tabulation was made up of only fifty
subdivisions which comprised “the main body of the persons classed under ‘other
castes.’” The 1881 Census presented tabulations separately for the “Eleven Large
Castes,” “Ten Large Agricultural Castes,” and thirty-seven castes not of the twice-born
category whose numbers exceeded 1,000,000. (See Census NWP & O, 1865, Report, pp.
81–83; Census NWP & O, 1872, Report, pp. 288–95; Census India, 1881, Report, pp. 281–82.
Cited in Pant, “The Cognitive Status of Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of
some Literature on the North-West Provinces and Oudh.”
53. See Dirks, “Castes of Mind;” and Christopher Pinney, “Classification and Fanta-
sy in the Photographic Construction of Caste and Tribe,” Visual Anthropology 3, 2–3
(1990): 259–88.
54. Census of India 1881, Report, p. 277. Cited in Pant, “The Cognitive Status of Caste
in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of some Literature on the North-West Provinces
and Oudh.”
55. H. Waterfield, Memorandum on the Census of British India of 1871–72 (London:
George Edward Eyre and William Spottiswoode, 1875), 20. Cited in Padmanabh Sama-
rendra, “Classifying Caste: Census Surveys in India in the Late Nineteenth and Early
Twentieth Centuries,” South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 26, 2 (2003): 141–64.
56. Samarendra, “Classifying Caste: Census Surveys in India in the Late Nineteenth
and Early Twentieth Centuries,” 146.
57. J. A. Baines, Census of India, 1891, General Report (London: Eyre and Spottis-
woode, 1893), 188–89.
58. Census of India, 1891, Report, p. 188. Cited in Pant, “The Cognitive Status of Caste
in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of some Literature on the North-West Provinces
and Oudh.”
59. Pant, “The Cognitive Status of Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of
some Literature on the North-West Provinces and Oudh.”
60. Samarendra, “Classifying Caste: Census Surveys in India in the Late Nineteenth
and Early Twentieth Centuries.”
61. Census NWP & O, 1865, Report, pp. 6–7. Cited in Pant, “The Cognitive Status of
Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of some Literature on the North-West Prov-
inces and Oudh,” 151.
62. Census NWP & O, 1911, Report, p. 327. Cited in Pant, “The Cognitive Status of
Caste in Colonial Ethnography: A Review of some Literature on the North-West Prov-
inces and Oudh,” 151.
63. Scott Atran, The Cognitive Foundations of Natural History: Towards an Anthropology
of Science (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
64. Chapter VIII, “Caste, Tribe or Race,” in Census of India, 1901, vol XV–Madras, Part
I, Report, W. Francis (Madras: Government Press, 1902): 129.
65. Census of India, 1901, “Caste, Tribe or Race,” 130.
66. Census of India, 1901, “Caste, Tribe or Race,” 131.
67. Stanley Tambiah, “From Varna to Caste through Mixed Unions,” in Culture,
Thought and Social Action: An Anthropological Perspective (Cambridge: Harvard Univer-
sity Press, 1985), 212–51.
68. The Left Hand Castes are Chetties, artisans (also called “Punchaular” and con-
sisting of goldsmiths, ironsmiths, coppersmiths, carpenters, and masons), oilmongers,
weavers, Patnavar, male leatherworkers, and female pullies. The Right Hand Castes
are Vellaular, Cavarays, Comaties, accountants, silk-weavers, male pullies, Pariahs,
and female leatherworkers. See the chapter “Ethnology,” in Maclean, Manual of the
Administration of the Madras Presidency vol. 1, 69. For more on this, also see Niels
Brimnes, Constructing the Colonial Encounter: Right and Left Hand Castes in Colonial South
India (Richmond, UK: Curzon Press, 1999).
218 Chapter 5
10/1901, Subject: ‘Ethnographic Survey of Caste and Tribes in British India’. Cited in
Dirks, “Castes of Mind,”67; and Bates, “Race, Caste, and Tribe in Central India: The
Early Origins of Indian Anthropometry,” in The Concept of Race in South Asia, 259.
133. Radhika Singha, A Despotism of Law: Crime and Justice in Early Colonial India
(Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998).
134. Anand Yang, “Castes and Tribes: The Criminal Tribes Act and the Magahiya
Doms of Northeast India,” in Crime and Criminality in British India, ed. Anand A. Yang
(Tucson, AZ: University of Arizona Press, 1985), 128–39; Sanjay Nigam, “Disciplining
and Policing the ‘Criminals by Birth,’ Part 1: The Making of a Colonial Stereotype–The
Criminal Tribes and Castes of North India,” Indian Economic and Social History Review
27, 2 (1990): 131–164; Sanjay Nigam, “Disciplining and Policing the ‘Criminals by
Birth,’ Part 2: The Development of a Disciplinary System, 1871–1900,” Indian Economic
and Social History Review 27, 3 (1990): 257–87; Sandria B. Freitag, “Crime in the Social
Order of Colonial North India,” Modern Asian Studies 25 (1991): 227–61; and Santhosh
Abraham, “Colonialism and the Making of Criminal Categories in British India,” NAL-
SAR Law Review 6, 1 (2011): 151–65. Andrew Major indicates that at the time of inde-
pendence in 1947 there were 128 tribes and castes deemed as “criminal” numbering
about 3.5 million persons (roughly 1 percent of the population) as part of the colonial
legacy of administering criminal communities. See Andrew J. Major, “State and Crimi-
nal Tribes in Colonial Punjab: Surveillance, Control and Reclamation of the ‘Danger-
ous Classes,’” Modern Asian Studies 33, 3 (July 1999): 657–88.
135. Committee of Circuit to Council at Fort William, 15 August 1772. Cited in Rad-
hika Singha, “‘Providential’ Circumstances: The Thuggee Campaign of the 1830s and
Legal Innovation,” Modern Asian Studies 27, 1 Special Issue: How Social, Political and
Cultural Information is Collected, Defined, Used and Analyzed (February 1993):
83–146.
136. Singha, A Despotism of Law.
137. Singha, A Despotism of Law.
138. Marc Brown has pointed out that ideas about “criminal types” and the develop-
ment of scientific understanding of native criminality in India were based on the
principles and measurement systems of race theory. See Marc Brown, “Race, Science
and the Construction of Native Criminality in Colonial India,” Theoretical Criminology
5, 3 (August 2001): 345–68.
139. Nigam, “Disciplining and Policing the ‘Criminals by Birth,’ Part 1: The Making
of a Colonial Stereotype–The Criminal Tribes and Castes of North India;” and “Disci-
plining and Policing the ‘Criminals by Birth,’ Part 2: The Development of a Discipli-
nary System, 1871–1900.”
140. Bates, “Race, Caste, and Tribe in Central India: The Early Origins of Indian
Anthropometry,” in The Concept of Race in South Asia, 228.
141. Ghurye, Caste and Race in India, 156. Dietrich Reetz has shown how ethnic and
religious parties in Punjab and Tamilnadu evoked solidarity to make their claims for
civil service employment and political representation in the legislative councils. The
recognition of a separate group identity assumed a critical importance both for the
Sikhs in Punjab and the non-Brahmin castes in Tamilnadu during the hearings of the
Public Service Commission of 1913. See Dietrich Reetz, “In Search of the Collective
Self: How Ethnic Group Concepts Were Cast through Conflict in Colonial India,”
Modern Asian Studies 31, 2 (May 1997): 285–315. Dick Kooiman has argued that similar
tendencies of communalism and ethnicity prevailed in the Princely states of Baroda,
Travancore and Hyderabad in the clamour over government employment wherein the
strength of enumerated communities was affirmed. See Dick Kooiman, “The Strength
of Numbers: Enumerating Communities in India’s Princely States,” South Asia: Journal
of South Asian Studies 20, 1 (1997): 81–98.
142. Anderson, The Spectre of Comparisons.
143. Anderson, The Spectre of Comparisons, 38.
144. Anderson, The Spectre of Comparisons, 38.
222 Chapter 5
223
224 Chapter 6
ideas of disease and death and of the means of containing such diseases
leading to what Foucault has described as a “medico-administrative”
knowledge of the society and simultaneously to a “politico-medical” hold
on the population that is now governed by a new set of prescriptions
relating to existence and behavior, and affecting such aspects as food and
drinking habits, dress, habitat and environment.
In his book The Birth of the Clinic, Foucault identified three forms of spa-
tialization. The location of a disease in a family of disease and the body
are the primary and secondary spatialization, and relate to taxonomies of
disease and their concrete manifestations in the organs. The tertiary spa-
tialization is “all the gestures by which in a given society, disease is
circumscribed, medically invested, isolated, divided up into closed, privi-
leged regions, or distributed throughout cure centers, arranged in the
most favorable way,” a place of political struggles, economic constraints,
and social confrontations. 23 Biopolitics is central to the tertiary spatializa-
tion, and all these three forms of medical spatialization are governed by
norms, normality and normalization. “Norm” is the principle that allows
discipline to develop from a simple set of constraints into a mechanism of
regulation, designates both rules and a way of producing them, and a
principle of valorization. 24 Normalization produces procedures that lead
to consensus on the choice of norms and standards. With statistical
norms supplanting the juridical mode of governance, and the “average
man” as a modern way of individualizing members of the population,
the state is increasingly conceived in terms of the actuarial view of society
and becomes a vast system of social insurance that brings in new kinds of
intervention to regulate population.
For Foucault, the rise of a “normalizing society” is bio-power’s central
diacritic for modernity. 25 The emergence of such a “normalizing society”
with modernity also engendered the Comtean project of sociology that
sought to establish a scientific practice of social intervention on a medical
model working with a definition of the field of social pathology. 26 With
the medical discoveries of Broussais, a new field of knowledge was
opened up by statistical applications in the medical and social sciences. 27
The idea that statistics could bridge “the chaos of the particular and the
transparency of the whole” was irresistible. 28 Quetelet’s ideas that hu-
man variation definable in quantitative terms and interpreted as devia-
tions from a norm not only became a legitimate concern of the state but
also effected a fundamental epistemological displacement of absolute de-
terminism that had characterized social science until then. 29 Norms be-
came the objects of a science of sociological abnormality and the idea that
the normal could be conceived statistically became popular. 30
Bio-power and Statistical Causality 229
Since the work of George Canguilhem, the thinking of life and norms
has undergone a major reversal. 31 By questioning the validity of the con-
stancy of norms, the context-free object standards set by these norms, and
also the attempts of medical practice to scientifically establish these
norms, Canguilhem launched a frontal attack on the historical “edifice of
normalization” that were so essential to the procedures of a positivist
science and medicine. Whereas in the 1943 publication, Canguilhem
argued that normality is an activity and not a steady state, he shifted his
position twenty years later from a background normality to an active
normativity, implying that norms were not only active but were histori-
cal and linked to normalization. 32 He also distinguished between social
and organic norms, their modes of regulation and their finalities. Medical
normality tended to support the positivist contention that the normal can
be known and laid down as law prior to the pathological. 33
Inquiring into the ideological aspects of modern medicine in relation
to other disciplines and social practices, Thomas Osborne has suggested
that medical norms have a capacity to “stray beyond themselves, infil-
trating into other forms of rationality.” 34 The very notion of disease in
modern medicine is unstable, and can only figure as an event and not as
an entity, essence, or abstraction. This notion of disease as “event” led to
the proclivity of numerical approaches arising out of the need to identify
consistent regularities and norms as the disease have only a statistical
probability of a certain regularity that would otherwise appear as a sin-
gular mutation in the individual. The world of disease thus entered the
language of mutliplicities and probabilities. When this logic of pathologi-
cal becoming was reterritorialized into other fields of experience, it pro-
moted a new style of reasoning that was not henceforth based on an
understanding of human nature but on normal states, leading to an “in-
surgence of normality” in various spheres. 35
This tended to homogenize the social body even as it played a part in
classification, hierarchization, and in the distribution of rank. Moreover,
a society regulated according to norms mimics both the order and coher-
ence of the organism through a set of interdependent norms. 36 In cases
where there is no single norm to orient normalization, then the several
plausible and different norms do not cohere but exist in tension, suggest-
ing in fact that there are various modes of ordering that diffract and
interfere with each other, as it would in non-singular complex societies.
Medical norms, even if they are those of the organism, become a social
norm that is both set and maintained through a set of social practices as
in the case of colonial public health and sanitary reform that sought to
change conduct and personal habits at the most intimate levels thereby
setting new norms of hygiene and cleanliness. Equally, social norms are
often internalized into medical thought as in the case of the relation be-
tween medicine and insurance. 37 Also, when social and moral demands
are experienced as “determinisms” rather than as “constraints” by the
230 Chapter 6
living being, the organism mistakes it as a vital norm rather than a social
norm. 38 Foucault has shown how normalization, holds up normality as a
norm and an ideal for each and every body to attain, by clarifying the role
of the “norm” in disciplinary and regulatory modes of power as follows:
In more general terms still, we can say that there is one element that
will circulate between the disciplinary and the regulatory, which will
also be applied to body and population alike, which will make it pos-
sible to control both the disciplinary order of the body and the aleatory
events that occur in the biological multiplicity. The element that circu-
lates between the two is the norm. The norm is something that can be
applied to both a body one wishes to discipline and a population one
wishes to regularize. The normalizing society is a society in which the
norm of discipline and the norm of regulation intersect along an or-
thogonal articulation. 39
The emergence of bio-power enabled both individual bodies and mass
bodies to be normalized and pathologized that involved the convergence
of modern medical science, statistical norms, and the disciplinarity of
sanitary administration. The latter entailed a public understanding of
epidemiological terrain and of the means of controlling the terrain such
that diseases are contained and restrained, often entailing populations to
adopt new standards of health and hygiene and new conditions of habi-
tat and environment brought by modern methods of sanitary manage-
ment. The colonial rule of difference constituted the bodies to be normal-
ized and the epidemiological terrain as a vastly different one in the colo-
nized terrain that needed both modern science and modern governance
for its normalization. Famine deaths did not afford the same possibility of
constituting a rule of difference and not surprisingly the state’s concern
was far more in the case of epidemic deaths than famine deaths. These
technologies of power and normalization rendered both the individual
body and the “social” body amenable to observation, intervention, and
manipulation in a manner that was hitherto not available or even at-
tempted before. What occurred was “change of scale and the deployment
of a whole new range of objects” and a “new way of asking questions”
that redrew the “bounds of truth” within medicine and in other disci-
plines. 40
In late nineteenth-century colonial India, disease for the first time con-
fronted the public gaze just as it had done a few decades ago in England.
Until the 1840s, India was not set apart from England by its smell or its
drains, as the early colonialists believed that India was made pestilential
by its climate, not the sewage in its streets. This climate determinism was
first challenged by the Royal Commission on the State of the Army set up
Bio-power and Statistical Causality 231
Unnani and the British were eager to learn the indigenous medical cures
for diseases that were unknown to them. Over time, the rift between the
two widened partly on account of the missionary hostilities to heathen
religious practices which in Hindu India was associated with the huge
gatherings of pilgrims at religious festivals and their perceptions of the
natives’ lack of hygiene on account of the dirt and filth they saw in
pilgrimage centers and the association of disease with it. More important-
ly, both as Western medical knowledge gained strides in pathology, or-
ganic chemistry, and disease classification and causation, and as the Brit-
ish consolidated their power in India, they began to dominate with feel-
ings of superiority. 68 From the mid-1850s onward, sanitary management
and scientific research on diseases gained momentum. What is surpris-
ing, though, is that biopolitics, and by that is implied the discourses and
practices that connect the vital and the political spheres, varied across the
diseases that they sought to control. Thus the biopolitics of cholera,
which includes the production of scientific knowledge and the nature of
state intervention, was in striking contrast with that of the plague as
explained here.
Cholera, considered an indigenous disease endemic to the lower Ben-
gal region, became an epidemic disease in the nineteenth century spread-
ing to regions in India and across the world to Europe and America.
From the early nineteenth century mortality from cholera epidemics was
to disproportionately affect the British troops, the pilgrims in pilgrimage
sites, and the poor. Although statistics on cholera morbidity and mortal-
ity was sparse and irregular, attempts to understand the patterns of the
cholera epidemicity gave rise to a widespread understanding in the early
years that it was caused by climatic or meteorological factors and later to
the view that it was on account of dirt, lack of hygiene, and environmen-
tal factors. Miasmatic and localist theories of the spread of cholera con-
vinced the colonial officials that it was noncontagious and was airborne.
Anti-contagion views were also popular in Britain in the liberalism of the
1830s and the political culture of liberalism served to oppose quarantines
and cordons sanitaires especially after its failure to prevent cholera epi-
demic in the 1830s. 69 James Cunningham as sanitary commissioner of
India from 1866–1884 held steadfast to the localist and environmental
theory of disease causation especially drawing his support from the work
of the German hygienist Pettenkofer who had argued in the 1860s that it
was the soil conditions that caused germs to develop their pathogenic
qualities and that the mere presence of germs would not cause a disease.
This perspective of anti-contagion served Pettenkofer to oppose all meas-
ures of quarantine and cordons sanitaires, a position that appealed to
James Cunningham as quarantines would have affected maritime trade,
and as well, the curtailment of population movement within the country
would have been difficult to enforce as much resistance from the people
was anticipated. This was at a time when international sanitary confer-
238 Chapter 6
interesting conclusion that the upstream waters of the rivers Ganga and
Jamuna had bactericidal properties and was remarkably free from chole-
ra vibrio. 78 His arguable suggestion was that the dangers posed in pil-
grimage sites like Haridwar would disappear if the existing wells nearby
could be closed and the people encouraged to use river water. No doubt
all these experiments under different conditions required vast collection
and analysis of statistical data to draw inferences.
The germ theory shifted the focus from the field to the laboratory,
emphasizing appropriate methods of visualization and controlled experi-
ments. More importantly, identifying the causative agent of cholera was
necessary to find the preventive and curative methods, and the identifica-
tion of comma-bacilli gave hope for the production and testing of a vac-
cine that was to also become contentious. Louis Pasteur had in France
successfully produced vaccines for anthrax and rabies, and once the
comma-bacilli was identified as the causative agent it was hoped that it
would be possible to develop cholera vaccine as well. Jennerian vaccina-
tion that was developed for small pox using live culture of cow pox met
with only mild resistance in India as the Indians already had a similar
procedure of variolation that even the British used in their early years in
India, and they could also seek rationale and justification within a relig-
ious framework as small pox goddesses were worshipped all over the
country. But cholera did not have such a goddess although some ritual
practices were developed in certain regions in the nineteenth century
lending certain cultural meanings to the disease. 79 Early in 1892, D. D.
Cunningham sent a particularly virulent strain of comma-bacilli to Paris,
to aid Waldemar Haffkine, a Russian émigré working at the Pasteur insti-
tute, to aid in the production of an effective vaccine, although Cunning-
ham believed that the vaccine would not be effective in preventing the
occurrence of the disease and would only modify its behavior like the
way hygienic improvements do. 80
When Haffkine came to India in 1893 to test his cholera vaccine that
was “attenuated” rather than live culture, there was no statistical evi-
dence about its efficacy as it was at an experimental stage. While the
government granted him the permission to test his vaccine on the popu-
lation it insisted that it had to be on a voluntary basis with the subjects
being made to understand its effects. Debates ensued between various
officials about granting permission to inoculate on voluntary basis even
after the vaccine was proven to be safe with no harmful effects on native
soldiers, prisoners, school children, emigrants to Assam, coolie workers
in mines, railroads and public works, and in famine camps as it was
debatable if such categories of people could really exercise a choice when
placed in coercive contexts. Even after the colonial government prohibit-
ed the inoculation of prisoners, many prisoners in jails in Gaya, Bilaspur,
and elsewhere where inoculated by Haffkine as the jail authorities
Bio-power and Statistical Causality 241
Not since the Indian mutiny in 1857 had the colonial government been
gripped with such panic as with the outbreak of the plague in 1896.
Known locally as mahamari, plague had supposedly been endemic in the
Himalayan foothills and colonial medical officers had in fact recorded the
years when it erupted, the localities and the mortality. 83 Coupled with
the crisis faced by Western medicine on account of its lack of knowledge
about its causation, cure, and prevention, the plague in 1896 evoked anx-
ieties among the colonial officials of the hidden dangers of the country
that called for struggles “to be waged individually against moral and
physical sickness, collectively against intrigue, conspiracy and rebel-
242 Chapter 6
tices, the authorities tried to enforce the requirement that plague corpses
be wrapped in a sheet soaked in perchloride of lime or covered with
quicklime. The tendency to conceal the dead through stealthy disposal of
corpse compelled the authorities to initially inspect corpses at the homes
and cemeteries to determine the localities and homes of plague victims,
which measures met with fierce resistance. Problems of segregation in
smaller towns and rural areas were no less than in the crowded urban
centers as the unaffected population who on being moved to open-air
camps stealthily went back to their supposedly infected homes under
cover of darkness to retrieve their belongings. With wild rumors circulat-
ing on many different aspects of the epidemic causing panic and resis-
tance at all levels of society and state, epidemic management also had to
contend with managing rumor-induced behavior and action. 107
The authoritatian nature of epidemic management can be surmised
from the evidence given to the Commission as the following.
In Bombay with its immense chawls full of lodgers, who have little kit,
and can shift at any moment, house-house visitation is of comparative-
ly little use, and the only way to discover cases of plague seems to be to
employ spies, and to keep as careful a watch as possible on the cemeter-
ies. Many cases have been discovered in large searches with troops, but
such searches cause great alarm, and I would not use troops until there
is good reason to believe that the area is badly infected and other
means of discovering cases have failed (emphasis mine). 108
To another question on corpse inspection at the cemeteries, another re-
spondent observed, “I do not mean the corpses should be inspected, but
you should see that no body is buried or disposed of at the cemetery until
the fact of the death is known to the authorities in the town. I mean, keep
a watch so that people do not take away corpses and dispose of them
without you knowing where they came from.” 109 Noting that very often
friends give the wrong address of the corpse at the cemeteries, the re-
spondent acknowledged that it was difficult to give any accurate figures
of the proportion of the cases, which he thought must be about 5 percent.
With such authoritarian policy and practices in place and popular
resistance to them, with uncertain scientific knowledge of the cause and
cure of plague, and with pressures heightening on the international front
to stop external trade with India on account of the epidemic, the Indian
Plague Commission played a significant role in retrieving the power of
the state to constitute a liberal governmentality of health and sanitation
even if it had wrongly assumed that its illiberal measures would have
been possible in the colonial context.
Such liberal governmentality of health once again emphasized the
need for statistics. The census of 1901 soon after the plague outbreak, and
the census of 1911 collected for the cities of Bombay and Calcutta detailed
ward-wise and street-wise data on aspects like population by sex, relig-
250 Chapter 6
when that latent claim became manifest. In all instances, the resistance
sought to protect the inviolability of the body, both live and dead, from
intrusive governmental power. The body was perceived to belong to the
community and attempts at individualizing the body by the plague
measures provoked resistance to reclaim the body for the community.
The measures were perceived by all sections of the population both as a
violent intrusion on their cultural practices giving scant regard to matters
of caste and religion in evacuation and segregation, and as an appropria-
tion of their bodies, the intimate space of the family, and even their mean-
ings of life and death. The body became a contested site of colonial
governmentality and the community. Bio-power thus reached its limit
when the colonized body, marked as it was by cultural and religious
differences, refused to be negotiated or trampled for the sake of a univer-
sal science or for modern sanitary technologies.
As a consequence of the resistance, the colonial government in 1898
and 1899 made compromises in its plague policy eschewing compulsion
and the use of troops. Other unpopular measures such as compulsory
segregation and hospitalization, and corpse inspection were abandoned
in favor of voluntary segregation and inoculation, house-cleansing based
on customary beliefs and practices, and the use of “leading men” from
various communities as agents of persuasion. Nowhere is the Foucaul-
dian insight that power can be read off resistance more true than in the
case of resistance to plague measures. While the sanitary power of coloni-
al governmentality sought to normalize the colonial epidemiological ter-
rain, resistances to such normalization were indicative of the limits of
bio-power’s capacity to act on individual and mass bodies. Such limits
were set as much by the resoluteness of colonial “difference” as by the
violent negation of the subject-constituting effects of sanitary power. That
no other colonial medical intervention evoked as much resistance as the
plague measures suggest that colonial “difference” was indeed able to
constitute itself as a resistant “difference” that could in fact negate
governmentality’s subject constituting effects.
The resoluteness of colonial “difference” and the negation of govern-
mentality’s subject-effects resulting in resistance compelled liberal
governmentality at times to acknowledge its failure through violence, to
exercise a form of Clausewitzian power on the people, in which the posi-
tions of attackers and defenders, and guns and bayonet were of strategic
importance than the liberal rationalities of government. The nationalist
response to the excesses of epidemic administration clarified both to the
rulers and the ruled of how governance ought to be, as evident in Tilak’s
comments in his newspaper Kesari on 13 July 1897, that the “policy of
governing by making a parade now and then of the physical power was
unjust. . . . To govern is not to unsheath the sword and to threaten the
people with death and destruction at every moment.” 119 If nationalists
seized the opportunity to let it be known how governance ought to be, it
Bio-power and Statistical Causality 253
was also evident that the colonial state was learning through this epidem-
ic manangement of how to constitute a liberal governmentality of a colo-
nized population, of how much access it can have to individual and mass
bodies, in what ways it can access them, and of where to draw its limits
that exposed in the process the contradictions of a liberal governmental-
ity in the colonial context.
NOTES
According to Joshua Cole, the debates mirrored what Foucault has called as the
“great bipolar technology” of early ninteenth-century medicine, “anatomic and bio-
logical, individualizing and specifying, directed towards the performance of the body,
with attention to the processes of life.” See Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected Inter-
views and Other Writings 1972–1977, 139.
28. Joshua Cole notes on the space of knowledge opened up by Broussais: “A new
order had emerged from the assembled figures and tables, which gave structure and
form to the infinite variety of human experience. When grouped together in series, the
most random events of social life were found to exhibit recognizable and consistent
patterns, hinting at an unsuspected universe of exquisite precision.” See Cole, “The
Chaos of Particular Facts: Statistics, Medicine and the Social Body in Early 19th Centu-
ry France,” 1.
29. Joshua Cole goes further to say that Quetelet’s Physique sociale “marked a rhetor-
ical transition in the treatment of numbers as signs of social phenomena” by eliminat-
ing the one-to-one correspondence between objects in the world and digits in the
statistical table through his averages. Cole, “The Chaos of Particular Facts: Statistics,
Medicine and the Social Body in Early 19th Century France,” 13.
30. Mike Gane has highlighted how Comte took from Broussais the conception of
the relation between normal and pathological phenomenon and regarded him the true
founder of positive pathology. Mike Gane notes, “Progress requires the control of
imagination by observation, says Comte, and the idea that disease is the ‘excess or
deficiency of stimulation . . . either rising above or below the degree which constitutes
the normal condition’ opens the way to the analysis of pathology as a study of ‘inten-
sity in the action of stimulants indispensible for maintaining health.” See Gane, “Can-
guilhem and the Problem of Pathology,” 302.
31. Mike Gane explores Canguilhem’s relation to Comte. Nearly twenty years prior
to the publication of The Normal and the Pathological, Canguilhem wrote a thesis on
Comte’s notion of “order and progess” under Celestin Bougle’s supervision. Bougle
was considered a leading member of the Durkheimian school. See Gane, “Canguilhem
and the Problem of Pathology.”
32. Rabinow, “French Enlightenment: Truth and Life,” 198.
33. George Canguilhem, The Normal and the Pathological (New York: Zone Books,
1989, Originally published in 1943). Canguilhem’s ideas of the normal and the patho-
logical have been discussed in some recent critical writings. Annemarie Mol discusses
how the multiplicity of medical normalities relates to each other. She notes “If multi-
ple normalities come to figure as competing goods, normalization is no longer capable
of providing a coherent order.” Annemarie Mol, “Lived Reality and the Multiplicity of
Norms: A Critical Tribute to George Canguilhem,” Economy and Society 27, 2 and 3
(May 1998): 283.
34. Thomas Osborne, “Medicine and Ideology,” Economy and Society 27, 2 and 3
(May, 1998): 260.
35. Osborne, “Medicine and Ideology,” 269.
36. In the essay “From the Social to the Vital” that George Canguilhem added in the
second edition of The Normal and the Pathological in 1966, he compares the norms of life
with those of society.
37. Rose, “Life, Reason and History: Reading Georges Canguilhem Today,” 165.
38. Monica Greco, “Between Social and Organic Norms: Reading Canguilhem and
Somatization,” Economy and Society 27, 2 and 3 (1998): 234–48.
39. Foucault, Society Must be Defended, Lectures at the Collège de France, 1975–76. For
Foucault’s use of “normalization,” see Foucault, Discipline and Punish.
40. Francois Delaporte, “Foucault, Epistemology and History,” Economy and Society
27, 2 and 3 (1998): 296. Nikolas Rose helps to understand how scale changes lead to
new formulations of a problem, as he shows illustrating with the case of medicine,
how new techniques of visualization changed the scale of clinical vision, such that
“the body” no longer appears as a system, a system of systems, even as an “open
256 Chapter 6
system.” See Rose, “Life, Reason and History: Reading Georges Canguilhem Today,”
162.
41. Samantha Iyer, “Colonial Population and the Idea of Development,” Compara-
tive Studies in Society and History 55, 1 (2013): 71–72.
42. Vijay Prashad, “The Technology of Sanitation in Colonial Delhi,” Modern Asian
Studies 35, 1 (Feb 2001): 116.
43. Metcalfe, Ideologies of the Raj, 172–77.
44. Michel Foucault suggested that a medicine of epidemics could exist only if
partnered by a police, which meant the “ensemble of mechanisms through which
order is ensured, the channeled growth of wealth and the conditions of preservation of
health ‘in general’.” Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic, 25.
45. David Arnold, “Cholera and Colonialism in British India,” Past and Present 113
(Nov 1986):120.
46. Ira Klein, “Death in India, 1871–1921,” The Journal of Asian Studies 32, 4 (August
1973): 639–59.
47. Alison Bashford, “Medicine, Gender and Empire,” in Gender and Empire, The
Oxford History of the British Empire, ed. Phillipa Levine (Oxford University Press, 2004),
112–13.
48. Buck, “Seventeenth-Century Political Arithmetic: Civil Strife and Vital Statis-
tics,” 67.
49. Recent authors have questioned Quetelet’s contribution to understanding social
causality. Gigerenzer and others have noted that Quetelet’s theory was “the purest
form of positivism, requiring no knowledge of actual causes but only the identification
of regularities and, if possible, their antecedents.” See Gerd Gigerenzer, et.al. The
Empire of Chance: How Probability changed Science and Everyday Life (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1989), 42. Stephen Stigler noted that Quetelet’s method ulti-
mately failed to provide an analytically coherent method for distinguishing between
mere regularity and significant evidence of causal influence. See Stephen M. Stigler,
The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before 1900. (Cambridge: Bel-
knap Press of Harvard University Press, 1990), 203–20. Ian Hacking noted that in
Quetelet’s theory of the average man “the mathematics of probability and the meta-
physics of underlying cause were cobbled together by loose argument to bring an
‘understanding’ of the statistical stability of all phenomena.” See Hacking, The Taming
of Chance, 112. Joshua Cole however suggests that Quetelet’s average man “should be
read as an essentially allegorical figure, even as an attempt to assert the power of
statistical allegory as a privileged mode of social description.” See Cole, “The Chaos of
Particular Facts: Statistics, Medicine and the Social Body in Early 19th Century
France,” 12.
50. Mark Harrison, “Tropical Medicine in Nineteenth-Century India,” The British
Journal for the History of Science 25, 3 (Sept 1992): 299–318. Warwick Anderson suggests
that even the American colonial encounter in the Philippines was similar where labor-
atory texts became not merely a medium to inscribe racial differences of colonial and
native “bodies” but in fact as a sign of difference. See Warwick Anderson, “‘Where
Every Prospect Pleases and Only Man is Vile’: Laboratory Medicines as Colonial Dis-
course,” Critical Inquiry 18, 3 (Spring 1992): 506–29.
51. Kumar, Medicine and the Raj, 71–72.
52. Kumar cites the Telugu writer B. G. Devara on this point. See Kumar, Medicine
and the Raj, 72.
53. Mark Harrison, “Medicine and Orientalism: Perspectives on Europe’s Encoun-
ter with Indian Medical Systems,” in Health, Medicine and Empire: Perspectives on Coloni-
al India, ed. Biswamoy Pati and Mark Harrison (Hyderabad: Orient Longman, 2001),
64.
54. Ann Herring and Alan. C. Swedland, “Plagues and Epidemics in Anthropologi-
cal Perspective,” in Plagues and Epidemics: Infected Spaces Past and Present, ed. Ann
Herring and Alan. C. Swedland (New York: Berg Publishers, 2010), 4.
Bio-power and Statistical Causality 257
55. Report of the Commissioners Appointed to Enquire into the Sanitary State of the Army
in India 1859, Vols. I and II (London, 1863).
56. Valeska Huber, “The Unification of the Globe by Disease? The International
Sanitary Conferences on Cholera 1851–1894,” The Historical Journal 49, 2 (June 2006),
453–76.
57. Anil Kumar notes, citing one Sir Pardy Lukis, that plague played a role for
medical research in India like what cholera did for sanitation in England some sixty
years before. See Kumar, Medicine and the Raj, 159–60.
58. Anil Kumar points out that the introduction of the “Bombay System of Vaccina-
tion” by the GOI in 1854 and subsequently to other parts of the country marked the
beginning of the alliance between the public demonstration and the emergence of the
administrative attempt to map the social space of the disease. The salient features of
the Bombay system were the attempt to overcome native prejudice by personally
explaining the disease and to visit hitherto unapproached areas of a district. See Ku-
mar, Medicine and the Raj, 166–67.
59. Anil Kumar notes that the cholera epidemic of Bengal in 1817 spread to many
parts of the world including the United States and Cuba over the next two decades.
See Kumar, Medicine and the Raj, 171.
60. Charles Morehead, Clinical Researches on Diseases in India, Vol. 1 (London, 1856).
61. Sheldon Watts, “British Development Policies and Malaria in India 1897–c1929,”
Past and Present 165 (1999): 141–81.
62. Kumar, Medicine and the Raj, 165.
63. Around 1600 A.D. Francis Bacon distinguished between “ordinary experience”
based on chance observations and therefore subjective, and “ordered experience”
based on methodological investigation and aspiring to a certain form of objectivity.
These new techniques of knowledge fundamentally reconstituted Indian medicine as
well. Bengali intellectuals in the nineteenth century like Akshay Kumar Datta and
Rajendralal Mitra openly declared that India needed a Bacon and Baconian ideas. See
Jayanta Bhattacharya, “The Body: Epistemological Encounters in Colonial India,” in
Making Sense of Health, Illness and Disease, ed. L. Twohig Peter and Vera Kalitzkas
(Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi, 2004), 31–54; and Deepak Kumar, Science and the
Raj (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2006), 60.
64. Alisdaire MacIntyre, “A Mistake about Causality in Social Science,” in Philoso-
phy, Politics and Society, ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman, 48–70. (Oxford: Black-
well, 1962/1972), 48–70.
65. Colin McFarlane, “Governing the Contaminated City: Infrastructure and Sanita-
tion in Colonial and Postcolonial Bombay,” International Journal of Urban and Regional
Research, 32 2, (2008): 415–35.
66. Martin Beattie, “Colonial Space: Health and Modernity in Barabazaar, Kolkata,”
TDSR, XIV, 11 (2003): 7–19.
67. John Chandler Hume, Jr., “Colonialism and Sanitary Medicine: The Develop-
ment of Preventive Health Policy in the Punjab, 1860 to 1900,” Modern Asian Studies 20,
4 (1986): 703–24.
68. Harrison, “Tropical Medicine in Nineteenth-Century India;” and Kavita Misra,
“Productivity of Crises: Disease, Scientific Knowledge and State in India,” Economic
and Political Weekly 35, 43/44 (Oct.21–Nov.3, 2000): 3885–97.
69. Huber, “The Unification of the Globe by Disease? The International Sanitary
Conferences on Cholera 1851–1894,” 456–57.
70. Huber, “The Unification of the Globe by Disease? The International Sanitary
Conferences on Cholera 1851–1894.”
71. Jeremy D. Isaacs, “D. D. Cunningham and the Aetiology of Cholera in British
India, 1869–1897,” Medical History 42 (1998): 279–305.
72. Misra, “Productivity of Crises: Disease, Scientific Knowledge and State in In-
dia,” 3887.
73. Hume, Jr., “Colonialism and Sanitary Medicine: The Development of Preventive
Health Policy in the Punjab, 1860 to 1900.”
258 Chapter 6
74. Isaacs, “D. D. Cunningham and the Aetiology of Cholera in British India,
1869–1897.”
75. Isaacs, “D. D. Cunningham and the Aetiology of Cholera in British India,
1869–1897,” 289.
76. Isaacs, “D. D. Cunningham and the Aetiology of Cholera in British India,
1869–1897.”
77. Isaacs, “D. D. Cunningham and the Aetiology of Cholera in British India,
1869–1897.”
78. M. E. Hankin, “The bactericidal action of the waters of the Jamuna and Ganga
rivers on Cholera microbes,” translated from the original article published in French,
Ann. De I’ Inst. Pasteur, 10.511, (1896).
79. Arnold, “Cholera and Colonialism in British India.”
80. Isaacs, “D. D. Cunningham and the Aetiology of Cholera in British India,
1869–1897,” 298–299.
81. Misra, “Productivity of Crises: Disease, Scientific Knowledge and State in In-
dia,” 3890–91.
82. Misra, “Productivity of Crises: Disease, Scientific Knowledge and State in In-
dia,” 3894.
83. R. Nathan, Plague in India, vol. 2, (Simla: Government Press, 1898), 60–61.
84. Rajnarayan Chandavarkar, “Plague Panic and Epidemic Politics in India
1896–1914,” in Epidemics and Ideas: Essays on the Historical Perception of Pestilence, ed.
Terence Ranger and Paul Slack (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1992), 211.
85. Annual Report of the Public Health Commissioner with the Government of India, 1929,
I (Calcutta, 1932), 69. See also I. J. Catanach, “Plague and the Indian Village,
1896–1914,” in Rural India: Land, Power and Society under British Rule, ed. Peter Robb
(London: Curzon Press, 1983), 216–43.
86. The findings of the Indian Plague Commission in turn informed interpretations
of the European Black death although some hold the view that medieval plague in
Europe could not have been a rat-based bubonic plague. See Herring and Swedland,
“Plagues and Epidemics in Anthropological Perspective,” in Plagues and Epidemics:
Infected Spaces Past and Present.
87. Foucault, The Birth of the Clinic, 22–26.
88. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vols. I–V . . . Indices to the Evidence, Also Glossary, Maps and
Summary of the Report and Appendices (London: His Majesty’s Stationery Office,
1900–1901).
89. David Arnold, Colonizing the Body: State Medicine and Epidemic Disease in Nine-
teenth Century India (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993).
90. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 2.
91. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 1.
92. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 2.
93. The accuracy of plague mortality statistics due to concealment even during the
great plague in Europe has been mentioned by Graunt in his Observations on Bills of
Mortality published in 1662. See Buck, “Seventeenth-Century Political Arithmetic: Civ-
il Strife and Vital Statistics,” 70.
94. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 2.
95. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 4.
96. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 5.
97. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 5.
Bio-power and Statistical Causality 259
98. These questions are numbered from 17487–17496. Indian Plague Commission,
Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Commission, with Appendices Vol. III,
23–24.
99. Kumar (1998), 221.
100. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 11.
101. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 12.
102. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices vol. I, 11.
103. Foucault, Discipline and Punish, 195–225.
104. Stuart Elden, “Plague, Panoptican, Police,” Surveillance and Society 1, 3 (2003):
240–53.
105. David Arnold, “Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague,
1896–1900,” in Selected Subaltern Studies, ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty
Spivak (New York: Oxford University Press, 1988), 395.
106. Although the earlier Military Cantonment Act XXII of 1864 (also Contagious
Diseases Act) was the first comprehensive piece of legislation pertaining to health to
be effected in colonial India, it only targeted Indian prostitutes and English soldiers to
curb the spread of sexually transmitted diseases, and contained a set of codes and
regulations modeled on the British Public Health Acts that instituted sanitary police
under the overall supervision of medical officers and approved the registration of
deaths and recording of observations regarding diseases in the interest of public
health. See Misra, “Productivity of Crises: Disease, Scientific Knowledge and State in
India,” 3886.
107. For the kinds of rumors that circulated about the plague epidemic read Arnold
“Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague, 1896–1900,” in Selected Subal-
tern Studies.
108. Answer to Q#16987, Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by
the Indian Plague Commission, with Appendices Vol. III , 2–3.
109. Answer to Q#16999, Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by
the Indian Plague Commission, with Appendices Vol. III, 3.
110. Richard Harris and Robert Lewis, “Colonial Anxiety Counted: Plague and Cen-
sus in Bombay and Calcutta, 1901,” in Imperial Contagions: Medicine, Hygiene, and Cul-
tures of Planning in Asia, ed. Robert Peckham and David M. Pomfret (Hong Kong:
Hong Kong University Press, 2013), 62–63.
111. Appadurai, “Number in the Colonial Imagination” in Orientalism and the Post-
Colonial Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia.
112. Prashad, “The Technology of Sanitation in Colonial Delhi.”
113. Biswamoy Pati and Mark Harrison, “Introduction,” in Health, Medicine and Em-
pire: Perspectives on Colonial India, ed. Biswamoy Pati and Mark Harrison (Hyderabad:
Orient Longman, 2001), 4–5.
114. For accounts of plague resistance in colonial India, read Arnold, “Touching the
Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague, 1896–1900” in Selected Subaltern Studies; and
Colonizing the Body; and I. J. Catanach, “South Asian Muslims and the Plague
1896–c1911,” South Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies XXII (Special Issue 1999): 87–107.
115. Indian Plague Commission, Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague Com-
mission, with Appendices Vol. III, 2.
116. Catanach, “South Asian Muslims and the Plague 1896–c1911,” 88.
117. For comments on Gyanendra Pandey’s analysis of one such diary, see Catanach,
“South Asian Muslims and the Plague 1896–c1911,” 105.
118. Arnold, “Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague, 1896–1900” in
Selected Subaltern Studies, 393.
119. Arnold, “Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague, 1896–1900” in
Selected Subaltern Studies, 420.
SEVEN
Colonial Governmentality and the
Public Sphere
Surprisingly even in the West, the literature on the public sphere that
followed Jurgen Habermas’s The Structural Transformation of the Public
Sphere ignored the obvious fact that such transformations in the public
sphere were often the effect of the transformation of the State itself and of
the changes in the political rationalities and technologies of governance. 2
This is indeed surprising, for ever since Kant, the rise of public opinion
has been associated with the rise of liberalism. The Kantian doctrine of
freedom as reason is uncompromisingly part of the moral order of liber-
alism, and therefore normatively inscribed in the historical ascendancy of
liberal democracy. For Kant, the actualization of freedom as reason de-
pends not on private autonomy but on public autonomy. In his essay
“What is Enlightenment?” Kant wrote that the promise of self-
261
262 Chapter 7
uments as that just given to the world, every instrument of the kind
should be made public.
For the exercise of modern power, colonial governmentality needed the
edifice of the modern state such as the legislature, executive, and judici-
ary, but precisely because it was the colonial modern, it sought to govern
subjects rather than citizens. Thus colonial governmentality rendered
superfluous the need for representative assemblies, in the sense of repre-
sentatives of the governed, as in the way modern democracy functions,
up until the second decades of the twentieth century. Indeed as J. S. Mill’s
famous quote on Representative Government urged all to believe, the In-
dians must first be constituted as modern subjects before they can be
given a role in representative government. The newspapers sought in
effect to shape a new public sphere that would both generate public
opinion and substitute for the representative assemblies. In the course of
time, this liberal technology of creating public opinion to serve the politi-
cal rationalities of modern colonial power socialized Indian public opin-
ion into increasingly proving the illegitimacy of colonial rule.
The different segments of the newspapers—Anglo-Indian, the Indian-
English, and Vernacular—tried to grapple their role of “an opposition in
representative assemblies,” although they underwent complex changes,
reflecting the complexities of the colonial situation over time. Whereas
bilingual papers such as the Bombay Durpan in the 1830s sought to pro-
vide a symmetrical translation of their publications in English and Mara-
thi, the bilingual papers after the 1860s did not do so but merely allocated
the various issues that were considered appropriate for English or Ver-
nacular publication reflecting the new hierarchies of language and power
established by the colonial education project in the meantime. 36 The ver-
nacular papers too shifted their focus over the period from mere dissemi-
nation of new knowledge to the vernacular readership to consolidating
their presence as authentic representatives of native opinion. Such native
public opinion was needed for colonial governmentality to “cultivate a
good understanding with the people” if its exercise of power was to “rest
as little as possible upon the exhibition of force,” for as the report on “The
Madras Protest” observed, “if the time ever come when the taxes have to
be collected at the point of the bayonet, the days of our empire in India
are numbered” (The Bombay Times and Standard, Original selections, 12 May
12 1860).
More importantly, colonial governmentality needed to reconstitute
the “social” as amenable to its intervention not by any manipulation of
discrete behaviors, but by reshaping the entire social order. Not surpris-
ingly therefore, and despite their identification with colonial interests, the
Anglo-Indian newspapers often assumed a mentoring role to the native
ones, especially on how the “social” issues were to be discursively articu-
lated. Urging the native press to play the role of the “preacher” and the
270 Chapter 7
lar state policies ever subject to such public scrutiny and debate. Indeed,
the notion of public policy as purposive state intervention toward attain-
ment of certain goals and targets is premised on the existence of a mecha-
nism to arrive at a consensus on goals which is generally provided by the
legislative branch of the government, an executive body to transform
legislative desires into executive will and a bureaucracy to implement
them. What is distinctive about the colonial State is that the sovereignty
of the state was independent of the popular will. Colonial governmental-
ity was thus not covered by the covenant of a social contract between the
state and its subjects. 39
ment” so that they “will then cease to desire and aim at independence on
the old Indian footing” proved true when the idea of “progress” interpel-
lated colonial subjects, and obliged them to argue for self-government
from within the discursive site of “progress,” thus compelling them as
participants in a new game of politics. 40
Standard print cultures like the newspapers were powerful forces in
Asian and African contexts in forging national identities among the colo-
nial intelligentsia. 41 As the game of politics became more complex, more
players emerged representing the various streams of the nationalist
movement such as the liberals, revivalists, communists, and socialists,
each with their different perspectives on self-government. Mahatma Gan-
dhi, the most radical anti-modernist was the only one who refused to
play the new game of politics, and conceived his political claims for self-
government not from within the modernist site of “progress” but upon
claims on the collective nostalgia for Ramarajya, a deep-rooted cultural
longing for a Utopia representing a perfect harmony of politics and mo-
rality. 42 Acknowledging that the Indians were compelled to play the new
game of politics having been subjected to modern governmental power,
Gandhi sought to radically overturn colonial governmentality and its
practices of governing colonial conduct through advocating a complete
boycott of courts and government educational institutions, the quintes-
sential institutions of colonial modernity. Gandhi no doubt realized that
colonial governmentality needed the complicity of colonial subjects, for
he once noted “our share in the sins of the Government is not a small
one” (Navajivan, 27 January 1921). 43 Gandhi believed that when public
opinion has become pure and the people have decided to get rid of their
sins, that very day the colonial Government will be defeated. For Gandhi,
the Congress resolution on noncooperation was accepted as a method of
self-purification, for otherwise, it would certainly be a sin.
strain it were as much the result of public opinion as it was of the pro-
claimed British policy itself.
The colonial administrators’ practice of seeking opinions on govern-
mental affairs from the “natural leaders” of communities created condu-
cive conditions for the collaboration between the colonial and the native
elites. In return for extending their support to the colonial government,
the native elites were able to bargain for an inviolable and autonomous
private sphere free from the intrusions of the colonial state. This resulted
in the emergence of a revivalist nationalism among both the Hindus and
the Muslims with far reaching impact on the public sphere that have
reverberated in the contemporary politics of the nation-state. 45
While colonial governmentality set its agenda of transforming coloni-
al conduct, the colonizer’s indifference to the social transformation also
grew out of a sense of being resolutely alien. The Bombay Times and Stan-
dard while reporting of a controversy between reformers and traditional-
ists among the Hindu Vaishnavite sect in Bombay remarked how the
contests between the two groups broke down over their disagreement
over the Shastras as the final appeal; the reformers rejecting the Shastras as
a final appeal, in matters where they manifestly contradict reason. The
report went on to acknowledge the indifference of the English to transfor-
mation in Indian society when it noted:
We have set this community in a ferment by our schools and our news-
papers, our preachings and our literature, and now how many
amongst us have a thought of sympathizing with them, or of identify-
ing ourselves with them in the strife, or even countenancing them in it?
Difference in language, and manners, and customs separates us from
them so completely, that we not merely do not know what is going on
amongst them, but do not care to enquire. (The Bombay Times and Stan-
dard Overland Summary, 11 September 1860, p. 3)
This rather frank admission makes clear that the colonial project of trans-
forming colonial conduct in an improving direction was not really meant
to bring the colonial modern closer to the English, for these relationships
were already over-determined by “race,” euphemistically referred to in
the report as “difference in language, and manners, and customs.” What
the project of colonial modernity sought indeed was the transformation
of desires, wants, and manners that would suit the needs of both a grow-
ing market economy as well as the needs of modern colonial governance.
Such a project of transforming colonial conduct was no doubt mired
in conflicting tendencies. Print languages and literatures that were vital
instruments for crafting social identities in colonial India constituted pro-
cesses of social ordering and social representation, and became the earli-
est sites of struggles among competing social groups, even before these
were played out in the political arena of the modern nation. 46 As society
was divided on the basis of religion, caste, and social position, and there
278 Chapter 7
public sphere and those that did not. The Press Act of India of 1857,
popularly known as the “Gagging Act” drove the wedge between
English-language and Indian-language papers, although Governor-Gen-
eral Canning earned the wrath of the European community for his refusal
to discriminate between the so-called “disloyal native” and the “loyal
British” in the Press Act. 50 The Vernacular Press Act of 1878 that com-
pletely fettered the Indian press in its short reign of three years was
recognized by the Indian press as a penal response by Eden, the lieuten-
ant governor of Bengal, for his inability to make the Indian-owned An-
glo-Vernacular paper the Amrita Bazar Patrika to toe his line. Supporting
the discriminatory Vernacular Press Act of 1878, Eden noted, “What
Government does object to is the sedition, and gross disloyalty of some of
the Vernacular papers, and their attempts to sow the seeds of disaffection
to the British rule in the minds of ignorant people.” 51 For Eden, the licen-
tiousness of the press had, “under false ideas of freedom and indepen-
dence,” been allowed to reach a stage, which “in the interests of the
public at large,” called for interference of the legislature. 52
For Eden, the governing effects of colonial conduct that the liberal
public sphere produced were indeed contrary between the English
papers and the Vernacular papers, as he noted, “The papers published in
this country in the English language are written by a class of writers for a
class of readers whose education and interests would make them natural-
ly intolerant of sedition; they are written under a sense of responsibility
and under a restraint of public opinion which do not and cannot exist in
the case of the ordinary native newspapers.” 53 Although Eden admitted
that the Indian-owned English papers too criticized the government, he
discounted the view that the government showed undue partiality to
papers written in the language of the ruling power.
Clearly, the colonial anxieties were not on account of the incompre-
hension of Vernacular languages but on account of the responses of Ver-
nacular subjects who being perceived as ignorant were seen to be inca-
pable of conducting themselves as autonomous agents and hence likely
to be swayed by sedition. The criminal charge of “sedition” became a
powerful liberal instrument of control to suppress the nationalist move-
ment. Even when sedition targeted the colonial state, it was interpreted
by the colonial authorities as engendering communal riot. In the colonial-
ist discourse, the violence of the “native” was marked by certain Oriental
characteristics as being “helpless, instinctive violence” in the form of con-
vulsions and was almost always related to sectarian strife. 54
Censorship though, was often counterproductive as newspaper edi-
tors in order to evade prosecution resorted to parody, innuendo, and
indirect criticism of the government, contrasting the despotism of coloni-
al rule with the “true” British government in the metropolis, and drawing
analogies between “Mahommedan” and British despotisms. As Bayly has
noted, radical criticism of the state was masked by invoking a broad
280 Chapter 7
Ajay Skaria has recently elaborated the conceptual arguments for Gan-
dhi’s rejection of republican democracy in favor of Ramrajaya through his
interpretive analysis of Gandhi’s Hind Swaraj. Not only did Gandhi op-
pose majority rule as the “major” perpetrated domination and he wanted
a rule that ensured perfect justice for the “minor,” he was also opposed to
the order of general responsibility that relied upon a judge, exemplary of
a sovereign, as a measure of justice as such an order associated with
republican democracy served the purpose of domination. The Ramarajya
reflects Gandhi’s conceptual struggles to think through another order
and responsibility that ensured perfect justice to the minor and is insepa-
rable from Satyagraha or passive resistance. 62
There is an interesting similarity here between the views of Gandhi
and Edmund Burke for Burke also noted that men are qualified for civil
liberty “in exact proportion to their disposition to put moral chains upon
their own appetites; in proportion as their love to justice is above their
rapacity; in proportion as their soundness and sobriety of understanding
is above their vanity and presumption; in proportion as they are more
disposed to listen to the counsels of the wise and good, in preference to
the flattery of knaves.” 63
Gandhi’s critique of liberal public opinion is not merely about the
normalization of majoritarian politics through the transparency of num-
bers in modern democratic governance but is equally a critique of mod-
ern governmental power that in effect creates the liberal public sphere. 64
Uday Singh Mehta has rightly argued that Gandhi’s ambivalence to de-
mocracy was rooted in the links he perceived between violence and mod-
ern politics with its concerns of progress and transformation that “de-
tracted from an attentiveness to the ethical gravity and context of every-
day life” by adopting an instrumentalizing view towards everyday ac-
tions and incorporating them in the collective calculus of benefit, free-
dom and security. 65
It is possible to draw both comparisons and relations between the
critique of colonial governmentality in Gandhi’s Ramarajya and the cri-
tique of bourgeois liberties in Edmund Burke’s reflections on the French
revolution of 1789. Arguing in favor of a state and constitution set up as
part of Britain’s ancient tradition in opposition to the bourgeois revolu-
tion that overthrew the French monarchy, the landed nobility and the
clergy, Burke noted:
Thus, by preserving the method of nature in the conduct of the state, in
what we improve we are never wholly new; in what we retain we are
never wholly obselete. . . . Always acting as if in the presence of canon-
ized forefathers, the spirit of freedom, leading in itself to misrule and
excess, is tempered with an awful gravity. This idea of a liberal descent
inspires us with a sense of habitual native dignity, which prevents that
upstart insolence almost inevitably adhering to and disgracing those
who are the first acquirers of any distinction. By this means our liberty
Colonial Governmentality and the Public Sphere 283
NOTES
that future is invariably expressed through the notion of progress.” Mehta, Liberalism
and Empire, 30.
13. Parliamentary Papers 1852–53, XXX, p. 313. Cited in Ryan, “Utilitarianism and
Bureaucracy: the views of J. S. Mill,” in Studies in the Growth of Nineteenth-century
Government, 49.
14. For an understanding of the “structure” and “project” of colonial power, see
Scott, Refashioning Futures, 31, 41.
15. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, “Teaching for the Times,” in The Decolonization of
Imagination: Culture, Knowledge and Power, ed. Jan Nederveen Pieterse and Bhikhu
Parekh (London: Zed Press, 1995), endnote 12.
16. Scott, Refashioning Futures, 38.
17. Sandria Freitag argues that there are important differences between the Euro-
pean and Indian experiences of the way the transcendence from particular and local
interests to general and supra-local interests was affected. Whereas in both, collective
and symbolic activities provided an enlarging ideological frame of reference by which
popular identification with local “community” became transmuted into identification
with a larger entity, the way in which connections were forged between elite public
opinion and mass collective activity differed. State-focused institutional activities and
collective action of public arenas often remained separate in colonial India. See San-
dria B. Freitag, Collective Action and Community: Public Arenas and the Emergence of
Communalism in North India (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1989).
18. Dirks in The Hollow Crown argues that the introduction of property and bureau-
cracy in nineteenth-century India introduced complexities and contradictions that ulti-
mately reduced the local kings into figureheads through the process of bureaucratic
rationalization and centralization of the state. Cohn in Colonialism and its Forms of
Knowledge: the British in India highlights how the codification of law by the colonial
state in its attempt to base a system of jurisprudence on prevailing Hindu and Muslim
law preferred fixity to regional variations and hence accorded authority to the oldest
extant law as the norm. This in turn contributed to the centralization of disparate and
diffused tendencies prevailing at the local level. Price mentions one such illustration of
transcendence from particular or local to the general or supra-local interest in the shift
from vertical mobilization of castes to horizontal mobilization of castes. See Price,
“Acting in Public versus Forming a Public: Conflict Processing and Political Mobiliza-
tion in Nineteenth Century South India.”
19. Scott, Refashioning Futures, 46.
20. Bayly, Empire and Information, 9.
21. Freitag, Collective Action and Community.
22. Read Douglas Haynes for more on how the Gandhian rhetoric through the use
of metaphors drawn from Hindu and Jain religious experience in the sphere of public
politics forged powerful psychic connections between critical indigenous values and
the notion of nationalism. Douglas Haynes, Rhetoric and Ritual in a Colonial City: The
Shaping of Public Culture in Surat city 1852–1928 (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1991).
23. James Fitzjames Stephen, “The Foundations of the Government of India,” The
Nineteenth Century 14, (October 1883): 562–63. Also cited in Mehta, Liberalism and Em-
pire, 29.
24. Bayly, Empire and Information, 5. Bayly notes “I use the word ‘ecumene’ to de-
scribe the form of cultural and political debate which was typical of north India before
the emergence of the newspaper and public association, yet persisted in conjunction
with the press and new forms of publicity into the age of nationalism. . . . The Indian
ecumene, however, does bear comparison to the modern European public in the sense
that its leaders were able to mount a critical surveillance of government and society.”
Bayly, Empire and Information, 182.
25. Ogborn, Indian Ink.
26. Bayly, Empire and Information; and Haynes, Rhetoric and Ritual in a Colonial City.
286 Chapter 7
27. Michael H. Fisher, “The Office of Akhbar Nawis: The Transition from Mughal to
British Forms,” Modern Asian Studies 27, 1 Special Issue: How Social, Political and
Cultural Information is Collected, Defined, Used and Analyzed, (February 1993):
45–82.
28. Mrinal Kanti Chanda, History of the English Press in Bengal: 1780–1857 (Calcutta:
K. P. Bagchi and Company, 1987), xiii.
29. Freitag, Collective Action and Community; and Haynes, Rhetoric and Ritual in a
Colonial City.
30. Read the chapter “Struggle for the Freedom of the Press” in Chanda, History of
the English Press in Bengal: 1780–1857, 413–51.
31. Stein, Thomas Munro, 284.
32. Stein, Thomas Munro, 285.
33. See Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 22.
34. Anindita Ghosh, Power in Print: Popular Publishing and the Politics of Language and
Culture in a Colonial Society (New Delhi: Oxford University Press, 2006).
35. Chanda, History of the English Press in Bengal: 1780–1857, xxii.
36. Veena Naregal, “Colonial Bilingualism and Hierarchies of Language and Pow-
er: Making of a Vernacular Sphere in Western India,” Economic and Political Weekly 34,
49 (December 4, 1999): 3446–56.
37. Edwin Hirschmann, “Using South Asian Newspapers for Historical Research,”
The Journal of Asian Studies 31, 1 (November 1971): 146.
38. Jawaharlal Nehru, The Discovery of India (New York: John Day, 1946), 293.
39. I use the term “covenant” as a substitute for Locke’s “compact.” The compact
refers to the implicit act of consent and trust whereby men unite together under “one
body politick under one government.” See John Locke, Two Treatises of Government, ed.
Peter Laslett (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960), 332. Peter Laslett notes
“Locke’s insistence that government is defined and limited by the end for which
political society is established, that it can never be arbitrary or a matter of will, can
never be owned, is expressed in a particular and exact application of his doctrine of
natural political virtue—the concept of trust.” See Locke, Two Treatises of Government,
113.
40. Stokes, The English Utilitarians and India, 47; and in Scott, Refashioning Futures, 52.
41. Anderson, Imagined Communities.
42. Partha Chatterjee notes “Gandhi does not even think within the thematic of
nationalism. He seldom writes or speaks in terms of the conceptual frameworks or the
modes of reasoning and inference adopted by the nationalists of his day, and quite
emphatically rejects their rationalism, scientism and historicism.” See Partha Chatter-
jee, “Gandhi and the Critique of Civil Society,” in Subaltern Studies III: Writings on
South Asian History and Society, ed. Ranajit Guha (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1984), 167.
43. M. K. Gandhi, The Collected Works Volume Nineteen (New Delhi: The Publications
Division, Government of India, 1966), 284.
44. Sinha points out the shift in British policies after 1857 from the Anglicist aim of
creating a class of westernized Indians as conceived by Macaulay in his 1835 Minute on
Education to a conscious courting of the traditional and orthodox Indian groups. Mrin-
alini Sinha, Colonial Masculinity: The ‘Manly’ Englishman and the ‘Effeminate’ Bengali in
the Late 19th Century (Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1995).
45. A. Ali, “Evolution of Public Sphere in India,” Economic and Political Weekly 36, 25
(June 30, 2001): 2419–25.
46. Ghosh, Power in Print.
47. For the debates carried in the various newspapers on the Age of Consent Bill,
see Tanika Sarkar, “Rhetoric against Age of Consent: Resisting Colonial Reason and
Death of a Child Wife,”‘ Economic and Political Weekly 28, 36 (September 4, 1993):
1869–78.; and Sinha, Colonial Masculinity.
48. Carroll, “Caste, Social Change, and the Social Scientist: A Note on the Ahistori-
cal Approach to Indian Social History.”
Colonial Governmentality and the Public Sphere 287
49. M. K. Gandhi, The Collected Works Volume Twenty–Seven (New Delhi: The Publi-
cations Division, Government of India, 1968), 347–48.
50. The curbs on the freedom of the native press were many and continued
throughout the colonial period. See Kirti Narain, Press, Politics and Society: Uttar Pra-
desh 1885–1914 (New Delhi: Manohar, 1998).
51. S. Natarajan, Rise of Journalism: A History of the Press in India (Bombay: Asia
Publishing House, 1962), 101.
52. Natarajan, Rise of Journalism, 101.
53. Natarajan, Rise of Journalism, 102.
54. Pandey, The Construction of Communalism in Colonial North India, 65.
55. Christopher A. Bayly, Recovering Liberties: Indian Thought in the Age of Liberalism
and Empire (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 8.
56. Vernacular Newspaper Reports (VNR) of North Western Provinces and Oudh,
Hindustani, Lucknow, 25th July 1894. Narain,Press, Politics and Society, 63, 25.
57. Guha, “Not at Home in Empire,”490; and Barry Hindess, “Not at Home in the
Empire,” Paper presented at the Habitus 2000 seminar, Curtin University, Australia,
2000a.
58. Barry Hindess, “The Liberal Government of Unfreedom,” Alternatives: Global,
Local, Political 26, 2 (April–June 2001): 93–111.
59. Shahid Amin has brilliantly portrayed how the making of the Mahatma entailed
widespread dissemination of his miraculous powers, which often were only rumors.
See Shahid Amin, “Gandhi as Mahatma: Gorakhpur District, Eastern UP, 1921–22,” in
Subaltern Studies III: Writings on South Asian History and Society, ed. Ranajit Guha (Del-
hi: Oxford University Press, 1984), 1–61.
60. Ajay Skaria has observed that for Gandhi Ramarajya is not necessarily Hindu as
Gandhi himself has remarked in the presidential address at Kathiawar Political Con-
ference, “The race of Rama is not extinct. In modern times the first Caliphs may be said
to have established Ramarajya.” See Navjivan, 8 January 1925, Akshardeha, vol. 25, 521;
CWMG, vol. 30, 62. Ajay Skaria, “Relinquishing Republican Democracy: Gandhi’s
Ramarajya,” Postcolonial Studies 14, 2 (2011): 203–229.
61. M. K. Gandhi, The Collected Works, Volume Thirty Five (New Delhi: The Publica-
tions Division, Government of India, 1969), 489–90. It is a moot question as to whether
the use of Hindu religious metaphors in the Gandhian rhetoric did or did not contrib-
ute to suffusing the liberal public sphere with majoritarian values, symbols and
norms.
62. Skaria, “Relinquishing republican democracy: Gandhi’s Ramarajya.”
63. Edmund Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France, ed. L.G. Mitchell (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1993), 289.
64. For a contemporary critique of the numerico-probablistic basis of liberal democ-
racy, read“Community, Number, Ethos of Democracy,” in Scott, Refashioning Futures,
158–89.
65. Uday Singh Mehta, “Gandhi on Democracy, Politics and the Ethics of Everyday
Life,” Modern Intellectual History 7, 2 (2010): 357.
66. Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France, 34.Edmund Burke noted “Each
contract of each particular state is but a clause in the great primaeval contract of
eternal society, linking the lower with the higher natures, connecting the visible and
invisible world, according to a fixed compact sanctioned by the inviolable oath which
holds all physical and all moral natures, each in their appointed place.” See Burke,
Reflections on the Revolution in France, 97.
67. Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France, 126.
68. Faisal Devji argues that the dharma-yuddha of the Bhagawad Gita served as the
arena of moral action for Gandhi to construct his ethical universalism. Faisal Devji,
“Morality in the Shadow of Politics,” Modern Intellectual History 7, 2 (2010): 373–90.
69. Burke, Reflections on the Revolution in France, 126.
70. Partha Chatterjee has noted that Gandhism that was originally a product of
anarchist philosophy of resistance to state oppression itself became a participant in its
288 Chapter 7
imbrication with a nationalist state ideology. See Chatterjee, Nationalist Thought and the
Colonial World.
71. Corinne Enaudeau, “Hannah Arendt: Politics, Opinion, Truth,” Social Research
74, 4 (Winter 2007): 1029–44.
Conclusion
Modern Freedom and Governmentality
INSTRUMENTALIZING FREEDOM
The debates in the Constituent Assembly on rights testify to the fact that
the relationship between “liberty and the shape and form of the economic
structure” preoccupied many of its members. 16 B. R. Ambedkar, the fore-
most leader of the Scheduled Castes, those occupying the lowest rungs of
the Indian caste structure, submitted to the Constituent Assembly as its
member, a social scheme that envisaged an extensive state ownership
and operation of the economic sectors. Although his scheme was rejected,
the Rights sub-committee enthusiastically endorsed positive rights that
included among others the state’s responsibility in securing an adequate
livelihood for all its citizens and its control over the nation’s economy
and material resources in the common interest. Since 1951, planning has
been integral to the nation’s hopes and aspirations and to the state’s
means for realizing them, an important technology of rational govern-
ance that also involved shifts in the plan perspectives over the decades.
While the achievements of planning for over fifty years have preoccupied
economists, few have concerned themselves with the epistemological
project that the nation-state sought to carry forward, which in important
Conclusion 295
that enabled a numerical conception of the poor became the most power-
ful instrumentality by which the techniques of governmentality generat-
ed objective and statistically measurable knowledge of the poor, and
which have been a recurring source of contestation in the public sphere.
Poverty lines helped not only to count the poor but also to know how
poor they were. Such a numerical conception of poverty enabled the state
to devise techniques of government such that a targeted number of the
poor could be lifted above the poverty line within a stipulated time.
Based on a “target approach,” it sought to identify the poor by income
which if supplemented through other income-earning activities could be
lifted above the poverty line, thus making a distinction between the
“worthy poor” who deserved credit and employment assistance and the
“unworthy poor” who did not deserve such assistance. The essence of the
target approach is to define the target in a fixed and discreet way such
that when the techniques act upon the object, they can be made to pro-
duce the desired effects. Even if the poor could be defined in fixed and
discreet ways, the target approach elided the possibility that objective
identification could be at variance with subjectively constituted iden-
tities, for many “non-worthy non-poor” who subjectively identified as
the “worthy poor” could fit themselves into the target group through the
command of social power, thus jostling out many objectively identified as
the “worthy poor.”
In the early phase of planning, the target approach enabled a hitherto
unknown terrain of bio-power and biopolitics inspired by a Malthusian
approach to curtailing population growth. Setting up sterilization camps
and using monetary incentives to persuade people to accept family plan-
ning methods, the vasectomy camps of the 1960s and 1970s gained initial
popularity and subsequent notoriety as the setting of targets for the num-
ber of acceptors propelled an excess of bureaucratic enthusiasm aided by
incentive schemes to transgress bounds of voluntarism to coercion. In the
process, a vast amount of statistical data was generated on population
categorized into “acceptors” and “nonacceptors” and framing target
groups by age, sex, religion, region, habitat, and so on for subsequent
“camp” interventionism. 20
The target approach folded within techniques of government thus
wrapped within it bureaucratic accountability and was on that account
especially amenable to statistical representations. Even as the statistical
bureaucracy enlarged to produce statistical knowledge and to transform
them into policy inputs, it simultaneously popularized the notion that
economic freedom is statistically measurable. Gone are the days when a
simple statistic as real wages or minimum wages signified economic free-
dom. Today, complex measures such as Gender Empowerment Human De-
velopment Index are devised as a measure of economic freedom. By ren-
dering invisible and therefore as insignificant, the social power relations
that circumscribe and constrain agents in the attainment of freedom and
298 Conclusion
which are never directly perceptible from statistical data, these tech-
niques of government are deemed as value-neutral and scientific. Femi-
nist critiques of the notion of justice that underpinned the development
strategies reconstituted the technologies of government by making them
more gender sensitive both to the forms of representations as well as
interventions.
The power of the numerical approach to render objects precise, mea-
surable, and objective meant that the “target approach” became the pre-
ferred tool of postcolonial governmentality in many other realms such as
family planning, public distribution of essential commodities, other in-
come-transfer schemes, rural development and urban planning. Planning
rendered the target approach a preeminent technique of government as it
made it feasible for ex-ante calculations to match with ex-post outcomes,
even if they more often did not match in practice. In turn, the “target
approach” became a convenient tool to evaluate bureaucratic perfor-
mance and more importantly enabled the rise of “political society.” The
“target approach” to delivering publicly supplied goods and government
services often missed the intended targets because the target group was
either not properly specified, unidentified, not properly classified or was
the effect of bureaucratic indifference and corruption. Individuals and
groups by-passed from the targeted programs could mobilize together to
make their claims of entitlements to the state, and under circumstances
could leverage political clout through their democratic voting right. As
the conditions of such mobilization are different from that of civil society,
Partha Chatterjee identifies it as “political society” noting that it could
even encompass survival activities of the poor and marginalized that is in
violation of law. 21 The effects of a governmentality informed by the prin-
ciple of justice has been the rise in demands from the “political society,”
which in turn has spawned yet more measures of enumeration, classifica-
tion, and discipline. Ration cards and voter identification cards that until
now decided the claim of a squatter to occupy an unauthorized squatter
settlement are being replaced with biometric smart cards with unique
identification numbers that would normalize the population of citizens
with varying shades of actually-realized citizenship rights from the non-
citizen refugees from neighboring countries and could as well regulate
movements of population within as an apparatus of security. 22
that proliferate in the media in order to orientate one to face the risks, and
the proliferation of the rights discourse that emphasizes the anguish of
the “multitude” on account of the differentiated nature of risks, chance,
opportunities, and offsets constitute the neoliberal construction of the
citizen-subjects.
However, not all information that is needed to orient one to the risks
is available nor the information required to monitor governance by the
“multitude,” which is crucial to grant some agentic power to the “multi-
tude,” as they seek to be not just subjects of surveillance by agents and
institutions of sovereignty, but would like in turn to be granted the recip-
rocal power to be agents of surveillance themselves of those very same
agents and institutions. 39 The Right to Information (RTI) Act of 2005
passed in the neoliberal era of governance has made it possible for citi-
zens and civil society organizations to monitor governance by the state
through granting access to information that the state and its bureaucracy
had hitherto been reluctant to make public. Bringing to light such laxity
could presumably lead to better statistical data and effective interven-
tions. Extending beyond governance by the nation-state, neoliberal
governmentality includes the supranational agencies of global sovereign-
ty, the civil society organizations that seek to provide a publicness to the
“multitude” and to diffuse the state’s monopoly over decision making,
the strategies of mass media to orientate the subjects to the various risks,
and the techniques of governing the conduct of oneself as well.
NOTES
10. Isaiah Berlin, Two Concepts of Liberty (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961).
11. Austin, The Indian Constitution, 51.
12. Vide Article 37 of the Constitution of India.
13. Andre Beteille, “Distributive Justice and Institutional Well-being,” in Democracy,
Difference and Social Justice, ed. Gurpeet Mahajan (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1998), 463–488.
14. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 203.
15. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 204.
16. B. R. Ambedkar, States and Minorities–What are Their Rights and How to Secure
Them in the Constitution of Free India (Bombay: Thacker and Co, 1947).
17. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 205.
18. Partha Chatterjee has noted that this duality could in practice lead to contradic-
tions. For what the people may express through the representative mechanisms of the
political process as their will may not necessarily be what is good for their economic
well-being, and what the state thought as important for the economic development of
the nation may not be ratified by the representative mechanisms. See Chatterjee, The
Nation and Its Fragments, 203
19. Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 208.
20. Hidam Premananda, “Administration, Statistics and Population: The Sterilisa-
tion Camps in the Early 1970s,” Economic and Political Weekly XLVIII, 12 (March 23,
2013): 69–74.
21. Chatterjee, “On Civil and Political Society in Post-Colonial Democracies” in
Civil Society: History and Possibilities, 177.
22. A newly introduced law in 2012 requires passengers traveling in all reserved
railway compartments to carry government authorized photo idenitification cards!
23. Dipankar Gupta, “Recasting Reservations in the Language of Rights,” in Democ-
racy, Difference and Social Justice, ed. Gurpeet Mahajan (Delhi: Oxford University Press,
1998), 509–26.
24. Gupta, “Recasting Reservations in the Language of Rights,” in Democracy, Differ-
ence and Social Justice, 516.
25. Galanter, Competing Equalities.
26. Scott, Refashioning Futures.
27. Chatterjee, “Beyond the Nation? Or Within?” 56–69.
28. Talal Asad, “What do Human Rights do? An Anthropological Enquiry,” Theory
and Event 4, 4 (December 2000).
29. Rose, Powers of Freedom.
30. Paolo Virno observes that the contemporary multitude is composed neither of
“citizens” nor of “producers” but occupies a middle region between “individual” and
“collective” and for that reason the “public” and “private” too have been decoupled.
Hence it is no longer possible to speak of a people converging into the unity of the
state. See Paolo Virno, A Grammar of the Multitude: For an Analysis of Contemporary
Forms of Life (New York: Semiotext (e), 2004). Michael Hart and Antonio Negri in
Empire note, ‘The “multitude” is a multiplicity, a plane of singularities, an open set of
relations, which is not homogenous or identical with itself and bears an indistinct,
inclusive relation to those outside of it. The “people,” in contrast, tends toward iden-
tity and homogeneity internally while posing its difference from and excluding what
remains outside it. Whereas the “multitude” is an inconclusive constituent relation,
the “people” is a constituted synthesis that is prepared for sovereignty. The “people”
provides a single will and action that is independent of and often in conflict with the
various wills and actions of the “multitude.” Every nation must make the “multitude”
into a “people.” See Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri Empire (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 2000), 103.
31. For explanations of “idle talk” and “curiosity,” see Heidegger Being and Time,
211–17. I have no hesitation in juxtaposing Heidegger with Foucault, as Foucault
himself has acknowledged the determining influence of Heidegger on his philosophi-
cal thought. See Michel Foucault, “Final Interview,” Raritan 5, 1 (Summer 1985).
Conclusion 309
32. Dengue epidemics in Delhi in certain months of the year have been fairly recur-
rent but the newer viral strains have brought it into the vector of the risk society,
although not a global but a localized one. Chickungunya is supposedly from East
Africa, and is a recent disease that in 2006 moved up north from the southern states of
India.
33. Arjun Appadurai, “The Spirit of Calculation,” Cambridge Anthropology 30, 1
(Spring 2012): 3–17.
34. Appadurai, “The Spirit of Calculation,” 9.
35. Appadurai, “The Spirit of Calculation,” 10.
36. A nongovernmental organization’s exposé through the Right To Information
(RTI) Act revealed that information on farmers’ suicides in Bundelkhand in north
India was distorted by the state bureaucracy as out of 1,667 suicides recorded in the
administration reports for the five years preceeding 2006, it had in 1,556 cases re-
corded the reasons for suicide as “unknown.” See Hindustan Times, 3 Nov 2006.
37. Robert Castel notes “A risk does not arise from the presence of particular precise
danger embodied in a concrete individual or group. It is the effect of a combination of
abstract factors which render more or less probable the occurrence of undesirable
modes of behavior. On the basis of the probabilistic and abstract existence of risks,
preventive policies promote a new mode of surveillance called “systematic predetec-
tion.” See Robert Castel, “From Dangerousness to Risk,” in The Foucault Effect: Studies
in Governmentality, ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, 281–98. (Chi-
cago: The University of Chicago Press, 1991), 266–89.
38. Castel, “From Dangerousness to Risk,” in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Govern-
mentality, 266–89.
39. Paolo Virno puts it sharply: “Let us say that the multitude is an amphibian
category: on one hand it speaks to us of social production based on knowledge and
language; on the other hand, it speaks of the crisis of the form-of-State. And perhaps
there is a strong connection between these two things.” See Virno, A Grammar of the
Multitude, 44.
Bibliography
Allami, Abul-Fazl. (1927–1949/1989). The A-IN-I Akbari, vol II, trans. H. Blochmann.
Delhi: Low Price Publications.
Baden-Powell, B. H. 1978. Administration of Land Revenue and Tenure in British India.
New Delhi: Ess Ess Publications. Originally published in 1907.
———. 1868–1872. Handbook of the Economic Products of the Punjab, Vols.1& 2. Roorkee.
Bentham, Jeremy. 1859. Fragment on Government in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Vol.
IV, ed. John Bowring. Edinburgh.
———. 1843. The Works of Jeremy Bentham, 11 Volumes, ed. John Bowring. Edinburgh.
———. 1993. “On Public Account Keeping.” In Official Aptitude Maximized Expense
Minimized, The Collected Works of Jeremy Bentham, ed. Philip Schofield. Oxford: Cla-
rendon Press, 293–301.
Bentley, Arthur Fisher. 1967. The Process of Government, ed. Peter H. Odegard. Cam-
bridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. First published by University of
Chicago Press, 1908.
Burke, Edmund. 1981. “Speech on Fox’s India Bill–1783.” In The Writings and Speeches
of Edmund Burke. Vol. 5, ed. P.J. Marshall. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 378–451.
———. 1981. “Speech on Opening of Impeachment–1788 on 15th, 16th, 18th, and 19th
Feb 1788.” In The Writings and Speeches of Edmund Burke vol. 6, ed. P.J. Marshall.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 264–471.
———. 1993. Reflections on the Revolution in France. Edited with an Introduction by L.G.
Mitchell. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Coomaraswamy, Ananda K. 1978. Spiritual Authority and Temporal Power in the Indian
Theory of Government. New Delhi: Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers. Originally
published by American Oriental Society, New Haven, Connecticut, 1942.
Crawfurd, John. “A Sketch of the Commercial Resources and Monetary and Mercan-
tile System of British India, with Suggestions for their Improvements by means of
Banking Establishments, 1837,” in The Economic Development of India under the East
India Company 1814–1858: A Selection of Contemporary Writings, ed. K. N. Chaudhuri.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971.
Crooke, William. 1989. A Glossary of North Indian Peasant Life. Edited with an Introduc-
tion by Shahid Amin. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Digby, William. 1878. The Famine Campaign in Southern India (Madras and Bombay Presi-
dencies and Province of Mysore) 1876–1878, v. 1. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.
Digby, William. 1878. The Famine Campaign in Southern India (Madras and Bombay Presi-
dencies and Province of Mysore) 1876–1878, v. 2. London: Longmans, Green, and Co.
Digby, William. 1901. “Prosperous” British India; A Revelation from Official Records. Lon-
don: T. F. Unwin,
Dutt, Romesh Chunder. 1970. The Economic History of India Under Early British Rule.
New York: Burt Franklin. First Published in 1902.
Gandhi, M.K. 1966. The Collected Works, volume Nineteen. New Delhi: The Publications
Division, Government of India.
———. 1968. The Collected Works, volume Twenty-Seven. New Delhi: The Publications
Division, Government of India.
311
312 Bibliography
———. 1969. The Collected Works, volume Thirty Five. New Delhi: The Publications
Division, Government of India.
Hankin, M.E. 1896. “The bactericidal action of the waters of the Jamuna and Ganga
rivers on Cholera microbes.” Translated from the original article published in
French, Ann. De I’ Inst. Pasteur 10.511.
Hegel, G. W. F. 1830–1831/1956. The Philosophy of History. New York: Dover Publica-
tions.
———. 1837/1978. Reason in History. Trans. Robert S. Hartman. Indianapolis: Bobbs-
Merrill Educational Publishing.
Hobbes, Thomas. 1929/1651. Leviathan. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Indian Plague Commission. 1900–1901. Minutes of Evidences Taken by the Indian Plague
Commission, with Appendices Vols I–V. . . . Indices to the Evidence, Also Glossary, Maps
and Summary of the Report and Appendices. London: His Majesty’s Stationery Office.
Kant, I. 1781/1965. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St.
Martin’s Press.
———. 1784/1986. “Idea for a Universal History from a Cosmopolitan Point of View.”
In Philosophical Writings, ed. E. Behler. New York: Continuum, 249–62.
———. 1784/1986. “What is Enlightenment?” In Immanuel Kant: Philosophical Writings.
New York: Continuum.
———. 1795/1991. “Perpetual Peace: A Philosophical Sketch.” In Kant’s Political Writ-
ings, ed. Hans Reiss. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1970/1987. Kant’s Political Writings. Ed. Hans Reiss. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Edited by R. P. Karkaria. 1907. Lord Curzon’s Farewell Speeches–Being Speeches delivered
as Viceroy and Governor-General During Sept–Nov 1905. Bombay: Thacker and Co.
Kautilya. The Arthashastra. Ed. L. N. Rangarajan. New Delhi: Penguin Books, 1992.
Keynes, John Maynard. 1971. The Collected Writings, Vol.1: Indian Currency and Finance.
London: Macmillan. Originally Published in 1913.
Locke, John. 1960. Two Treatises of Government. Ed.Peter Laslett. Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press.
———. 1975. An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. London and Glasgow: Wm.
Collins.
Macaulay, Thomas B. 1910. A Speech delivered in the House of Commons, July 10,
1833. In The Complete Works of Lord Macaulay vol. 19, The Miscellaneous Works. Phila-
delphia: The University Library Association, 146–93.
Maclean, C. D. 1885. Manual of the Administration of the Madras Presidency, Vol II. Ma-
dras: Government of Madras Press. Reprinted by Asian Educational Services, New
Delhi, 1989.
Markham, Clements. R. 1871. A Memoir on the Indian Surveys. London: W. H. Allen &
Co.
———. 1895. Major James Rennell and the Rise of Modern English Geography. London:
Cassell and Company Ltd.
McCulloch, J. R. 1847. A Descriptive and Statistical Account of The British Empire vol. II.
London: Longman, Brown, Green and Longmans.
Mill, James. 1817/1968. The History of British India, vols. I & II. New York: Chelsea
House Publishers.
———. 1818/1968. The History of British India v ol. VI. New York: Chelsea House Pub-
lishers.
———.1977. “On Liberty.” In Collected Works of John Stuart Mill vol. 18, ed. J. M. Rob-
son. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
———.1961. “Nature” and “On Liberty.” In Essential Works of John Stuart Mill, ed. Max
Lerner. New York: Bantam Books.
———.1986. On Liberty. New York: Prometheus Books. First published in 1859.
———. 1991. Considerations on Representative Government. New York: Prometheus
Books.
Bibliography 313
Ahmed, Siraj. 2002 “The Theater of the Civilized Self: Edmund Burke and the East
India Trials.” Representations 78: 28–55.
Alam, Muzaffar. 1997. The Crisis of Empire in Mughal North India: Awadh and the Punjab,
1707–48. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Alam, Muzaffar, and Sanjay Subrahmanyam. 1998. “Introduction.” In The Mughal State
1526–1750, ed. M Muzaffar Alam, and Sanjay Subrahmanyam. Delhi: Oxford Uni-
versity Press, 1–71.
Ali, A. 2001. “Evolution of Public Sphere in India.” Economic and Political Weekly 36, 25:
2419–25.
Altekar, A.S. 1949. State and Government in Ancient India. Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.
Ambedkar, B. R. 1947. States and Minorities–What are Their Rights and How to Secure
Them in the Constitution of Free India. Bombay: Thacker and Co.
Amin, Samir. 1989. Eurocentrism. New York: Monthly Review Press.
Amin, Shahid. 1984. “Gandhi as Mahatma: Gorakhpur District, Eastern UP, 1921–22.”
In Subaltern Studies III: Writings on South Asian History and Society, ed. Ranajit Guha.
Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1–61.
———, ed. 1989. A Glossary of North Indian Peasant Life: William Crooke. Delhi: Oxford
University Press.
Amrith, S. S. 2008. “Food and Welfare in India, c. 1900–1950.” Comparative Studies in
Society and History 50,4: 1010–35.
Anderson, Benedict, R. 1998. The Spectre of Comparisons: Nationalisms, Southeast Asia and
the World. New York/London: Verso.
———. 1983/ 1991. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nation-
alism. London: Verso.
Anderson, Warwick. 1992. “‘Where Every Prospect Pleases and Only Man is Vile’:
Laboratory Medicines as Colonial Discourse.” Critical Inquiry 18, 3: 506–29.
Appadurai, Arjun. 2012. “The Spirit of Calculation.” Cambridge Anthropology 30, 1:
3–17.
———. 1993. “Number in the Colonial Imagination.” In Orientalism and the Post-Coloni-
al Predicament: Perspectives on South Asia, ed. Carol Breckenridge and Peter Van der
Veer. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 314–39.
———. 1986. “Introduction: commodities and the politics of value.” In The Social Life of
Things, ed. Arjun Appadurai. New York: Cambridge University Press, 3–63.
———. 1980. Worship and Conflict under Colonial Rule. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Arendt, Hannah. 1958. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Arnold, David. 1993. Colonizing the Body: State Medicine and Epidemic Disease in Nine-
teenth Century India. Berkeley: University of California Press.
———. 1986. “Cholera and Colonialism in British India.” Past and Present, 113: 118–51.
———. 1988. “Touching the Body: Perspectives on the Indian Plague, 1896–1900.” In
Selected Subaltern Studies, ed. Ranajit Guha and Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. New
York: Oxford University Press, 391–426.
———. 1994. “Discovery of Malnutrition and Diet in Colonial India.” Indian Economic
and Social History Review 31, 1: 1–26.
Asad, Talal. 1973. “Two European Images of Non-European Rule.” In Anthropology and
the Colonial Encounter, ed. Talal Asad. London: Ithaca Press, 103–18.
———. 1973. “Introduction.” In Anthropology and the Colonial Encounter, ed. Talal Asad.
London: Ithaca Press, 9–19.
———. 1986. “The Concept of Cultural Translation in British Social Anthropology.” In
Writing Culture: The Poetics and Politics of Ethnography, ed. James Clifford and
George Marcus. Berkeley: University of California Press, 141–64.
———. 1991. “From the History of Colonial Anthropology to the Anthropology of
Western Hegemony.” In Colonial Situations, ed. George W. Stocking. Madison: Uni-
versity of Wisconsin Press, 314–24.
———. 1994. “Ethnographic Representation, Statistics, and Modern Power.” Social
Research 61, 1: 55–88.
Bibliography 315
———. 2000. “What Do Human Rights Do? An Anthropological Enquiry.” Theory and
Event 4, 4.
———. 2004. “Where are the Margins of the State?” In Anthropology in the Margins of
the State, ed. Veena Das and Deborah Poole. Santa Fe: School of American Research
Press, 279–88.
Atran, Scott. 1990. The Cognitive Foundations of Natural History: Towards an Anthropology
of Science. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Aune, Bruce. 1991. Knowledge of the External World. New York: Routledge.
Austin, G. 1966. The Indian Constitution: Cornerstone of a Nation. Bombay: Oxford Uni-
versity Press.
Barrow, Ian. J. 2003. Making History, Drawing Territory: British Mapping in India, c.
1756–1905. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
———. 2003. “From Hindustan to India: Naming Change in Changing Names.” South
Asia: Journal of South Asian Studies 26,1: 37–49.
Bartelson Jens. 1995. .A Genealogy of Sovereignty. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Bashford, Alison. 2004. “Medicine, Gender and Empire.” In Gender and Empire, The
Oxford History of the British Empire, Companion series, ed. Phillipa Levine. Oxford
University Press, 112–33.
Bates, Crispin. 1997. “Race, Caste, and Tribe in Central India: The Early Origins of
Indian Anthropometry.” In The Concept of Race in South Asia, ed. Peter Robb. Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 219–59.
Bayly,Christopher. 1996. Empire and Information: Intelligence Gathering and Social Com-
munication, 1780–1870. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2012. Recovering Liberties: Indian Thought in the Age of Liberalism and Empire.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bayly, Susan. 1997. “Caste and ‘Race’ in the Colonial Ethnography of India.” In The
Concept of Race in South Asia, ed. Peter Robb. Delhi: Oxford University Press,
165–218.
Beattie, Martin. 2003. “Colonial Space: Health and Modernity in Barabazaar, Kolkata.”
TDSR, XIV, 11: 7–19.
Beaud, J.-P. and J.-G. Prévost. 2005. “Statistics as the Science of Government: The
Stillborn British Empire Statistical Bureau, 1918–20.” Journal of Imperial and Common-
wealth History 33, 3: 369–91.
Benhabib, Seyla. 1992. “Models of Public Space: Hannah Arendt, the Liberal Tradition,
and Jurgen Habermas.” In Habermas and the Public Sphere, ed. Craig Calhoun. Cam-
bridge: MIT Press, 73–98.
Berlin, I. 1961. Two Concepts of Liberty. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Beteille, A. 1998. “Distributive Justice and Institutional Well-being.” In Democracy,
Difference and Social Justice, ed. Gurpeet Mahajan. Delhi: Oxford University Press,
463–88.
Bhabha, Homi K. 1990. “DissemiNation: Time, Narrative, and the Margins of the Mod-
ern Nation.” In Nation and Narration, ed. Homi K. Bhabha. London and New York:
Routledge, 291–322.
———. 1993.The Location of Culture. London and New York: Routledge.
Bhattacharya, Durgaprasad, and Rama Deb Roy. 1977. “Khanasumari Records and the
Statistical System of India.” Indian Historical Records Commission, Proceedings of the
Forty-Fifth Session, Mysore 45: 227–37.
Bhattacharya, Jayanta. 2004. “The Body: Epistemological Encounters in Colonial In-
dia.” In Making Sense of Health, Illness and Disease, ed. L. Twohig Peter and Vera
Kalitzkas. Amsterdam and New York: Rodopi, 31–54.
Bhattacharya, Sabyasachi. 1998. “The Labouring Poor and their Notion of Poverty:
Late 19th and Early 20th Century Bengal.” Labour and Development 3, 1 and 2: 1–23.
Biggs, Michael. 1999 “Putting the State on the Map: Cartography, Territory and Euro-
pean State Formation.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 41, 2: 374–405.
316 Bibliography
Birla, Ritu. 2009. Stages of Capital: Law, Culture, and Market Governance in Late Colonial
India. Durham: Duke University Press.
Breckenridge, Carol. 1989. “The Aesthetics and Politics of Colonial Collecting: India at
World Fairs.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 32, 2: 195–216.
Breman, Jan, and E. Valentine Daniel. 1992. “The Making of the Coolie.” In Plantations,
proletarians, and peasants in colonial Asia, ed. E. Valentine Daniel, Henry Bernstein
and Tom Brass. Frank Cass, London, 268–295.
Brimnes, Niels. 1999. Constructing the Colonial Encounter: Right and Left Hand Castes in
Colonial South India. Richmond, UK: Curzon Press.
Brown, Marc. 2001. “Race, Science and the Construction of Native Criminality in Colo-
nial India.” Theoretical Criminology 5, 3: 345–68.
Buck-Morss, Susan. 1995. “Envisioning Capital: Political Economy on Display.” Criti-
cal Inquiry 21, 2: 434–67.
Buck, Peter. 1977. “Seventeenth-Century Political Arithmetic: Civil Strife and Vital
Statistics.” Isis 68, 1: 67–84.
Burke, Peter. 1969. The Renaissance Sense of the Past. London: Edward Arnold.
Calhoun, Craig. 1992. “Introduction: Habermas and the Public Sphere.” In Habermas
and the Public Sphere, ed. Craig Calhoun. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1–48.
Callon, Michel. 1998. “Introduction: The Embeddedness of Economic Markets in Eco-
nomics.” In The Laws of the Markets, ed. Michel Callon. Malden, MA: Blackwell,
1–57.
———. 1998. “An Essay on Framing and Overflowing: Economic Externalities Revisit-
ed by Sociology.” In The Laws of the Markets, ed. Michel Callon. Malden, MA: Black-
well, 244–69.
Canguilhem, G. 1989. The Normal and the Pathological. New York: Zone Books. Original-
ly published in 1943.
Cannadine, David. 2001.Ornamentalism: How the British Saw their Empire. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Carroll, Lucy. 1975. “Caste, Social Change, and the Social Scientist: A Note on the
Ahistorical Approach to Indian Social History.” The Journal of Asian Studies 35, 1:
63–84.
Casey, Edward S. 1997. “Smooth Spaces and Rough-Edged Places: The Hidden Histo-
ry of Place.” The Review of Metaphysics 51, 2: 267–96.
Castel, Robert. 1991. “From Dangerousness to Risk.” In The Foucault Effect: Studies in
Governmentality, ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 281–98.
Catanach, I. J. 1983. “Plague and the Indian Village, 1896–1914.” In Rural India: Land,
Power and Society under British Rule, ed. Peter Robb. London: Curzon Press, 216–43.
———. 1999. “South Asian Muslims and the Plague 1896–c1911.” South Asia: Journal of
South Asian Studies, XXII: 87–107.
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. 1989. Rethinking Working Class History: Bengal 1890–1940. Prince-
ton: Princeton University Press.
———. 1991. “History as Critique and Critique(s) of History.” Economic and Political
Weekly 36, 37: 2162–66.
———. 1992 “Postcoloniality and the Artifice of History: Who Speaks for ‘Indian’
Pasts?” Representations 37: 1–26.
———. 1994. “Modernity and Ethnicity in India.” South Asia, XVII: 143–55.
———. 2000. Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Chanda, Mrinal Kanti. 1987. History of the English Press in Bengal: 1780–1857. Calcutta:
K. P. Bagchi and Company.
Chandavarkar, Rajnarayan. 1992. “Plague Panic and Epidemic Politics in India
1896–1914.” In Epidemics and Ideas: Essays on the Historical Perception of Pestilence, ed.
Terence Ranger and Paul Slack. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 203–40.
Bibliography 317
Chatterjee, Partha. 1984. “Gandhi and the Critique of Civil Society.” In Subaltern Stud-
ies III: Writings on South Asian History and Society, ed. Ranajit Guha. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 153–95.
———. 1986. Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative Discourse? Lon-
don: Zed Press.
———. 1993. The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial Histories. Princeton:
Princeton University Press,
———. 1998. “Beyond the Nation? Or Within?” Social Text 16, 3: 56–69.
———. 1999. “Anderson’s Utopia.” Diacritics 29, 4 Grounds of Comparison: Around
the Work of Benedict Anderson: 128–34.
———. 2001. “On Civil and Political Society in Post-colonial Democracies.” In Civil
Society: History and Possibilities, ed. Sudipta Kaviraj and Sunil Khilnani. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 165–78.
———. 2004. The Politics of the Governed. New York: Columbia University Press.
Chatterjee, Partha, and Gyan Pandey. ed. 1992. Subaltern Studies: Writings on South
Asian History, Vol. 7. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Chaudhuri, K. N. ed. 1971. The Economic Development of India under the East India Com-
pany 1814–1858: A Selection of Contemporary Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press.
Christopher, A. J. 2008 “The Quest for a Census of the British Empire c. 1840–1940.”
Journal of Historical Geography 34: 268–85.
Clanchy, Michael. 2002. “Does Writing Construct the State?” Journal of Historical Sociol-
ogy 15, 1: 68–70.
Clifford, James, and George Marcus. eds. 1986. Writing Culture: the Poetics and Politics of
Ethnography. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Clokie, Hugh Mc Dowall, and William. J. Robinson. 1937. Royal Commissions of Inquiry:
The Significance of Investigations in British Politics. Stanford: Stanford University
Press.
Cohen, Patricia Cline. 1999. A Calculating People: The Spread of Numeracy in Early Ameri-
ca. New York: Routledge.
Cohn, Bernard S. 1960. “The Initial British Impact on India: A Case Study of the
Benares Region.” The Journal of Asian Studies 19, 4: 418–31.
———. 1985. “The Command of Language and the Language of Command.” In Subal-
tern Studies IV: Writings on South Asian History and Society, ed. Ranajit Guha. Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 276–329.
———. 1987/1990. “Political System in Eighteenth Century India: The Banaras Re-
gion.” In An Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays, ed. Bernard S. Cohn.
Delhi: Oxford University Press, 483–99.
———. 1987/1990. “The Census, Social Structure and Objectification in South Asia.” In
An Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays, ed. Bernard S.Cohn. Delhi:
Oxford University Press, 224–54.
———. 1990. “Notes on the History of the Study of Indian Society and Culture.” In An
Anthropologist among Historians and Other Essays, ed. Bernard S. Cohn. Delhi: Oxford
University Press, 136–71.
———. 1996. Colonialism and its Forms of Knowledge: the British in India. New Jersey:
Princeton University Press.
Cohn, Bernard S., and Nicholas Dirks. 1988. “Beyond the Fringe: The Nation-State,
Colonialism and the Technologies of Power.” Journal of Historical Sociology 1, 2:
224–29.
Cole, Joshua. 1994 “The Chaos of Particular Facts: Statistics, Medicine and the Social
Body in Early 19th Century France.” History of the Human Sciences 7, 3: 1–27.
Colignon, Richard, and Mark Covaleski. 1991 “A Weberian Framework in the Study of
Accounting.” Accounting, Organizations and Society 16, 2: 141–57.
Conlon, Frank. 1981. “The Census of India as a Source for the Historical Study of
Religion and Caste.” In The Census in British India: New Perspectives, ed. N. G. Barri-
er. New Delhi: Manohar, 103–17.
318 Bibliography
Connolly, William E. 1993. “Beyond Good and Evil: The Ethical Sensibility of Michel
Foucault.” Political Theory 21, 3: 365–89.
Cooper, Frederick. 1992. “Colonizing Time: Work Rhythms and Labor Conflict in
Colonial Mombasa.” In Colonialism and Culture, ed. Nicholas Dirks. Ann Arbor: The
University of Michigan Press, 209–45.
Corrigan, Philip, and Derek Sayer. 1985. The Great Arch: English State Formation as
Cultural Revolution. London: Basil Blackwell.
Curtis, Bruce. 2002. “Foucault on Governmentality and Population: The Impossible
Discovery.” The Canadian Journal of Sociology 27, 4: 505–33.
———. 1997. “Official Documentary Systems and Colonial Government: From Imperi-
al Sovereignty to Colonial Autonomy in the Canadas, 1841–1867.” Journal of Histori-
cal Sociology, 10, 4: 389–417.
Das, Veena. 2004. “The Signature of the State: The Paradox of Illegibility.” In Anthro-
pology in the Margins of the State, ed. Veena Das and Deborah Poole. Santa Fe: School
of American Research Press, 225–52.
Daston, Lorraine. 1994. “Enlightenment Calculations.” Critical Inquiry 21, 1: 182–202.
———. 2004. “Type Specimens and Scientific Memory.” Critical Inquiry 31, 1: 153–82.
Datir, R. N. 1978. Prison as a Social System. Bombay: Popular Prakashan.
Dean, Mitchell. 1992. “A Genealogy of the Government of Poverty.” Economy and
Society 21, 3: 215–51.
Delaporte, Francois. 1998. “Foucault, Epistemology and History.” Economy and Society
27, 2 and 3: 285–97.
Derrett, Duncan J.M. 1976 “Rajadharma.” The Journal of Asian Studies 35, 4: 597–609.
Desrosieres, Alain. 2001. “How Real are Statistics? Four Possible Attitudes.” Social
Research 68, 2: 339–55.
Devji, Faisal. 2010. “Morality in the Shadow of Politics,” Modern Intellectual History 7, 2:
373–90.
Dinwiddy, J. R. 1993. “Bentham on Invention in Legislation,” In Jeremy Bentham: Criti-
cal Assessments vol. 3, ed. Bhikhu Parekh. New York: Routledge, 803–19.
Dirks, Nicholas. B. 2001. Castes of Mind: Colonialism and the Making of Modern India.
Princeton: Princeton University Press.
———. 1982. “The Pasts of a Palaiyakarar: The Ethnohistory of a South Indian Little
King.” The Journal of Asian Studies 41, 4: 655–83.
———. 1987. The Hollow Crown: Ethnohistory of an Indian Kingdom. New York: Cam-
bridge University Press.
———. 1989. “The Invention of Caste: Civil Society in Colonial India.” Social Analysis
25: 42–51.
———. 1992. “Castes of Mind.” Representations, 37, Special Issue Imperial Fantasies and
Postcolonial Histories: 56–78.
———. 1993. “Colonial Histories and Native Informants: Biography of an Archive.” In
Orientalism and the Postcolonial Predicament, ed. Carol Breckenridge and Peter van
der Veer. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 279–313.
———. 2006. The Scandal of Empire: India and the Creation of Imperial Britain. Cambridge:
Belknap Press of Harvard University.
Douglas, Mary. 1986. How Institutions Think. New York: Syracuse University Press.
Drekmeier, Charles. 1962. Kingship and Community in Early India. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Dumezil, Georges. 1988. Mitra-Varuna: An Essay on Two Indo-European Representations
of Sovereignty. New York: Zone Books.
Dumont, Louis. 1962. “The Conception of Kingship in Ancient India.” Contribution to
Indian Sociology 6, 61–64.
———. 1970. Homo Hierarchicus. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
———. 1977. From Mandeville to Marx: The Genesis and Triumph of Economic Ideology.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Duncan, James. S. 2007. In the Shadows of the Tropics: Climate, Race and Bio-power in
Nineteenth Century Ceylon. Hampshire, UK: Ashgate Publishing.
Bibliography 319
———. 1997. “The Birth of Biopolitics.” In Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth, ed. Paul Ra-
binow. New York: The New Press, 73–79.
———. 2003. Society Must be Defended, Lectures at the Colle`ge de France, 1975–76. Ed.
Bertani and Fontana, trans. David Macey. New York: Picador.
———. 2008. The Birth of Biopolitics, Lectures at the Colle`ge de France, 1978–79. Edited by
Arnold I. Davidson; translated by Graham Burchell. New York: Palgrave Macmil-
lan.
Fox, R.G. Kin, Clan, Raja and Rule: State-Hinterland Relations in Pre-Industrial India.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1971.
Fraser, N. 1992. “Rethinking the Public Sphere: A Contribution to the Critique of
Actually Existing Democracy.”In Habermas and the Public Sphere, ed. Craig Calhoun.
Cambridge: MIT Press, 109–42.
Freitag, Sandria, B. 1990. Collective Action and Community: Public Arenas and the Emer-
gence of Communalism in North India. Delhi: Oxford University Press. Originally
published by University of California Press, Berkeley, 1989.
———. 1991 “Enactments of Ram’s Story and the Changing Nature of ‘The Public’ in
British India.” South Asia 9, 1: 65–90.
———. 1991. “Crime in the Social Order of Colonial North India.” Modern Asian Stud-
ies 25: 227–61.
Furber, Holden. 1948. John Company at Work: A Study of European Expansion in India in
the Late Eighteenth Century. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Galanter, Marc. 1984. Competing Equalities: Law and the Backward Classes in India. Berke-
ley: University of California Press.
Galison, Peter. 2004. “Removing Knowledge.” Critical Inquiry 31, 1: 229–243.
Gane, Mike. 1998. “Canguilhem and the Problem of Pathology.” Economy and Society
27, 2 and 3: 298–312.
Geetha, V. and S. V. Rajadurai. 1995. “One Hundred Years of Brahminitude: Arrival of
Annie Besant.” Economic and Political Weekly 30, 28: 1768–73.
Gellner, Ernest. 1992. Reason and Culture: The Historic Role of Rationality and Rationalism.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Ghertner, Asher, D. 2010. “Calculating Without Numbers: Aesthetic Governmentality
in Delhi’s Slums.” Economy and Society 39, 2: 185–217.
Ghosh, Anindita. 2006. Power in Print: Popular Publishing and the Politics of Language and
Culture in a Colonial Society. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Ghurye, G. S. 1932. Caste and Race in India. London: Kegan, Paul, Trench, Trubner and
Co.
Gigerenzer, Gerd et. al. 1989. The Empire of Chance: How Probability changed Science and
Everyday Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gogate, P. P. and Arunachalam, B. 1998. “Area Maps in Maratha Cartography: A
Study in Native Maps of Western India.” Imago Mundi 50: 126–40.
Goldman, Lawrence. 1983. “The Origins of British ‘Social Science’, Political Economy,
Natural Science and Statistics, 1830–1835.” The Historical Journal 26, 3: 587–616.
———. 1986. “The Social Science Association, 1857–1886: A Context for Mid-Victorian
Liberalism.” The English Historical Review 101, 398: 95–134.
Gole, Susan. 1990. “Size as a Measure of Importance in Indian Cartography.” Imago
Mundi 42: 99–105.
Goody, Jack. 1996. The East in the West. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gordon, Colin. 1991. “Governmental Rationality: An Introduction.” In The Foucault
Effect: Studies in Governmentality, ed. Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter
Miller. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1–51.
Goswami, Manu. 2004. Producing India: From Colonial Economy to National Space. Chica-
go: The University of Chicago Press.
Gray, Peter. 2006. “Famine and Land in Ireland and India 1845–1880: James Caird and
the Political Economy of Hunger.” The History Journal 49, 1: 193–215.
Greco, Monica. 1998. “Between Social and Organic Norms: Reading Canguilhem and
Somatization.” Economy and Society 27, 2 and 3: 234–48.
Bibliography 321
Guha, Ranajit. 1963. A Rule of Property for Bengal: An Essay on the Idea of Permanent
Settlement. Paris: Mouton.
———. 1983. Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonial India. Delhi: Oxford
University Press.
———. 1988. “Preface.” In Selected Writings in Subaltern Studies, ed. Ranajit Guha and
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak. New York: Oxford University Press, 35–43.
———. 1988. An Indian Historiography of India: A Nineteenth-Century Agenda and its
Implications. Calcutta: K. P. Bagchi.
———. 1997. “Not at Home in Empire.” Critical Inquiry Front Lines/ Border Posts 23,
3 : 482–93.
———. 1998. Dominance without Hegemony: History and Power in Colonial India. Delhi:
Oxford University Press. Originally published by Harvard University Press.
Guha, Sumit. 1998. “Lower Strata, Older Races, and Aboriginal Peoples: Racial
Anthropology and Mythical History Past and Present.” The Journal of Asian Studies
57, 2: 423–41.
———. 2003. “The Politics of Identity and Enumeration in India c. 1600–1990.” Com-
parative Studies in Society and History 45, 1: 148–67.
———. 2004. “Speaking Historically: The Changing Voices of Historical Narration in
Western India, 1400–1900.” The American Historical Review 109, 4: 1084–1103.
Guillory, John. 2004. “The Memo and Modernity.” Critical Inquiry 31: 108–132.
Gupta, Akhil. 1992. “The Reincarnation of Souls and the Rebirth of Commodities:
Representations of Time in ‘East’ and ‘West.’” Cultural Critique 22: 187–211.
Gupta, Dipankar. 1998. “Recasting Reservations in the Language of Rights.” In Democ-
racy, Difference and Social Justice, ed. Gurpeet Mahajan. Delhi: Oxford University
Press, 509–26.
Gupta, Narayani. 1981/1998. Delhi Between Two Empires: 1803–1931. Delhi: Oxford Uni-
versity Press.
Haan, Michael. 2005. “Numbers in Nirvana: How the 1872–1921 Indian Censuses
Helped Operationalise ‘Hinduism’.” Religion 35: 13–30.
Habermas, Jurgen. 1989. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere: An Inquiry
into a Category of Bourgeois Society. Trans. Thomas Burger. London: Polity Press. First
published in German in 1962.
———. 1990. The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
———. 1992. “Further Reflections on the Public Sphere.” In Habermas and the Public
Sphere, ed. Craig Calhoun, trans. Thomas Burger. Cambridge: MIT Press, 421–61.
Hacking, Ian. 1979. “How Should We Do the History of Statistics?” Ideology and Con-
sciousness. Also published in The Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, ed. Gra-
ham Burchell, Colin Gordon, and Peter Miller. Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1991, 181–95.
———. 1982. “Bio-Power and the Avalanche of Printed Numbers.” Humanities in Soci-
ety 5, 3–4: 279–95.
———. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1986. “Making Up People.” In Reconstructing Individualism: Autonomy, Individu-
ality, and the Self in Western Thought, ed. Thomas C. Heller, Morton Sosna and David
E. Wellbery. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 222–36.
———. 1990. The Taming of Chance. New York: Cambridge University Press.
———. 2002. Historical Ontology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Halasz, Alexandra. 1997. The Marketplace of Print: Pamphlets and the Public Sphere in
Early Modern England. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Handelman Don. 1990. Models and Mirrors: Towards an Anthropology of Public Events.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Also published by Berghahn, 1998.
Hannah, M. G. 2000. Governmentality and the Mastery of Territory in Nineteenth-Century
America. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. 2000. Empire. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
322 Bibliography
Kula, Witold. 1986. Measures and Men. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Kumar, Anil. 1998. Medicine and the Raj: British Medical Policy in India, 1835–1911. New
Delhi: Sage Publications.
Kumar, Deepak. 2006. Science and the Raj. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Kumar, Dharma. 1983. “A Note on the Term ‘Land Control.’” In Rural India: Land,
Power and Society under British Rule, ed. Peter Robb. London: Curzon Press, 59–75.
———. 1996. Colonialism, Property and the State. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Kumar, M. S. 2006. “The Census and Women’s Work in Rangoon, 1872–1931.” Journal
of Historical Geography 32: 377–97.
Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through
Society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
———. 1993. We Have Never Been Modern. Trans. Catherine Porter. Hertfordshire: Har-
vester Wheatsheaf.
Lefebvre, Henri. 1991. The Production of Space. Trans. Donald Nicholson Smith. Cam-
bridge: Basil Blackwell.
Legg, Stephen. 2007. Spaces of Colonialism: Delhi’s Urban Governmentalities. Oxford:
Blackwell Publishing.
Lorenzen, David N. 1999 “Who Invented Hinduism?” Comparative Studies in Society
and History 41, 4: 630–59.
Ludden, David. 1992. “India’s Development Regime.” In Colonialism and Culture, ed.
Nicholas B. Dirks. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 247–87.
———. 1993. “Orientalist Empiricism: Transformation of Colonial Knowledge.” In
Orientalism and the Post-Colonial Predicament, ed. Carol E. Breckenridge and Peter
Van der Veer. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 250–78.
Lukes, Steven. 2000. “Different Cultures, Different Rationalities?” History of the Human
Sciences 13, 1: 3–18.
Lyotard, J. F. 1984. The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
MacDonagh, Oliver. 1958. “Delegated Legislation and Administrative Discretions in
the 1850’s: A Particular Study.” Victorian Studies 2, 1: 29–44.
MacIntyre, Alasdair. 1962. “A Mistake about Causality in Social Science.” In Philoso-
phy, Politics and Society, ed. Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman. Oxford: Blackwell,
48–70.
———. 1970. “The Idea of a Social Science.” In Rationality, ed. B. R. Wilson. Oxford:
Basil Blackwell, 112–30.
———. 1981/1984. After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory. Notre Dame: University of
Notre Dame Press.
Maheshwari, S.R. 1996. The Census Administration Under the Raj and After. New Delhi:
Concept Publishing.
Majeed, Javed. 1992. Ungoverned Imaginings: James Mill’s “The History of British India”
and Orientalism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
———. 1999. “James Mill’s ‘The History of British India: A Reevaluation.’” In J. S.
Mill’s Encounter with India, ed. Martin I. Moir, Douglas M. Peers, and Lynn Zastou-
pil. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 53–71.
Major, Andrew J. 1999. “State and Criminal Tribes in Colonial Punjab: Surveillance,
Control and Reclamation of the “Dangerous Classes.” Modern Asian Studies 33, 3:
657–88.
Mantena, Rama. 2007. “The Question of History in Precolonial India.” History and
Theory 46, 3: 396–408.
Mantena, Karuna. 2010. Alibis of Empire: Henry Maine and the Ends of Liberal Imperialism.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Marriott, McKim. 1958. Caste Ranking and Community Structure in Five Regions of India
and Pakistan. Poona: Bulletin Deccan College Research Institute.
Marshall, P.J. 1987. “Empire and Authority in the Late Eighteenth Century.” Journal of
Imperial and Commonwealth History 15: 105–22.
Bibliography 325
McClure, Kirstie M. 1999. “Figuring Authority, Statistics, Liberal Narrative and the
Vanishing Subject.” Theory and Event 3, 1.
McFarlane, Colin. 2008. “Governing the Contaminated City: Infrastructure and Sanita-
tion in Colonial and Postcolonial Bombay.” International Journal of Urban and Region-
al Research, 32, 2: 415–35.
Mehta, Uday Singh. 2010. “Gandhi on Democracy, Politics and the Ethics of Everyday
Life.” Modern Intellectual History 7, 2: 355–71.
Mehta, Uday Singh. 1999. Liberalism and Empire: India in British Liberal Thought. New
Delhi: Oxford University Press. Originally published by University of Chicago
Press, 1999.
Metcalfe, Thomas R. 1962. “The Struggle Over Land Tenure in India, 1860–1868.” The
Journal of Asian Studies 21, 3: 295–307.
———. 1994. Ideologies of the Raj. The New Cambridge History of India, III. 4. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Meuret, Denis. 1988. “A Political Genealogy of Political Economy.” Economy and Soci-
ety 17, 2: 225–50.
Miller, Peter. 1990. “On the Interrelations between Accounting and the State.” Account-
ing, Organizations and Society 15, 4: 315–38.
———. 1994. “Accounting as Social and Institutional Practice: An Introduction.” In
Accounting as Social and Institutional Practice, ed. Anthony G. Hopwood and Peter
Miller. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1–39.
———. 2001. “Governing by Numbers: Why Calculative Practices Matter.” Social Re-
search 68, 2: 379–96.
Miller, Peter, and Ted O’Leary. 1994. “Governing the Calculable Person.” In Account-
ing as Social and Institutional Practice, ed. Anthony G. Hopwood and Peter Miller.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 98–115.
Miller, Peter, and Nikholas Rose. 1990: “Governing Economic Life.” Economy and Soci-
ety 19, 1: 1–31.
Mirowski, Philip. 1989. More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics, Physics as
Nature’s Economics. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Misra, Kavita. 2000. “Productivity of Crises: Disease, Scientific Knowledge and State in
India.” Economic and Political Weekly 35, 43/44: 3885–97.
Mitchell, Timothy. 1989. Colonizing Egypt. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1995. “Origins and Limits of the Idea of the Economy.” Advanced Study
Center, Working Papers Series 12. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan.
———. 1997. “Statistical Knowledge and the ‘National Economy’.” Paper presented at
seminar, Anthropology Department. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University.
———. 2002. Rule of Experts: Egypt, Techno-Politics, Modernity. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Mohanty, J. N. 1992. Reason and Tradition in Indian Thought: An Essay on the Nature of
Indian Philosophical Thinking. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Moir, Martin. 1983. “Kaghazi Raj: Notes on the Documentary Basis of Company Rule
1783–1858.” Indo-British Review 21, 2: 185–93.
Moir, Martin, Peers, Douglas M., and Lynn Zastoupil. 1999. J. S . Mill’s Encounter with
India. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.
Mol, Annemarie. 1998. “Lived Reality and the Multiplicity of Norms: A Critical Trib-
ute to George Canguilhem.” Economy and Society 27, 2 and 3: 274–84.
Mongia, Radhika V. 2007. “Historicizing State Sovereignty: Inequality and the Form of
Equivalence.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 49, 2: 384–411.
Moore, Robin J. 1993. “Curzon and Indian Reform.” Modern Asian Studies 27, 4: 719–40.
Mukerji, Chandra. 1983. From Gravern Images: Patterns of Modern Materialism. New
York: Columbia University Press.
Munz, Peter. 1989. “Review of `The Measure of Times Past: Pre-Newtonian Chronolo-
gies and the Rhetoric of Relative Time’, by D. J. Wilcox.” History and Theory 28, 2:
292.
326 Bibliography
———. 1990. “When Will the State Wither Away?” Alternatives: Global, Local, Political
15, 3: 247–62.
Pasquino, Pasquale. 1978. “Theatrum Politicum: The Genealogy of Capital-Police and
the State of Prosperity.” Ideology and Consciousness, 4: 41–54. Also published in The
Foucault Effect: Studies in Governmentality, edited by G. Burchell, C. Gordon, and P.
Miller. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1991, 105–118.
Pati, Biswamoy, and Mark Harrison. 2001. “Introduction,” In Health, Medicine and
Empire: Perspectives on Colonial India, ed. Biswamoy Pati and Mark Harrison. Hyder-
abad: Orient Longman, 1–36.
Patriarca, Silvana. 1996. Numbers and Nationhood: Writing Statistics in Nineteenth-
Century Italy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Peabody, Norbert. 1996. “Tod’s Rajast’han and the Boundaries of Imperial Rule in
Nineteenth-Century India.” Modern Asian Studies 30, 1: 185–220.
———. 2001. “Cents, Sense, Census: Human Inventories in Late Precolonial and Early
Colonial India.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 43, 4: 819–50.
Pels, Peter. 1997. “The Anthropology of Colonialism: Culture, History and the Emer-
gence of Western Governmentality.” Annual Review of Anthropology 26: 163–83.
Perrett, Roy W. 1999. “History, Time and Knowledge in Ancient India.” History and
Theory 38, 3: 307–21.
Pettit, Philip. 2000. “Winch’s Double-Edged Idea of a Social Science.” History of the
Human Sciences 13, 1: 63–77.
Pinney, Christopher. 1990. “Classification and Fantasy in the Photographic Construc-
tion of Caste and Tribe.” Visual Anthropology 3, 2–3: 259–88.
Pitts, Jennifer. 2003. “Legislator of the World? A Rereading of Bentham on Colonies.”
Political Theory 32: 200–34.
Poovey, Mary. 2004. “The Limits of the Universal Knowledge Project: British India and
the East Indiamen.” Critical Inquiry 31, 1: 183–202.
———. 2001. “For Everything Else, There’s . . . ,” Social Research 68, 2: 397–426.
———. 1998. A History of the Modern Fact: Problems of Knowledge in the Sciences of Wealth
and Society. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
———. 1995. Making a Social Body: British Cultural Formation 1830–1864. Chicago: Uni-
versity of Chicago Press.
———. 1994. “The Social Constitution of ‘Class’: Toward a History of Classificatory
Thinking.” In Rethinking Class: Literary Studies and Social Formations, ed. Wai Chee
Dimock and Michael T. Gilmore. New York: Columbia University Press, 15–56.
———. 1993. “Figures of Arithmetic, Figures of Speech: The Discourse of Statistics in
the 1830s.” Critical Inquiry 18, 2: 256–76.
Porter, Theodore M. 1986. The Rise in Statistical Thinking. Princeton: Princeton Univer-
sity Press.
———. 1995. Trust in Numbers: The Pursuit of Objectivity in Science and Public Life.
Princeton: Princeton University Press,
Pouchepadass, Jacques. 1983. “Land, Power and Market: The Rise of the Land Market
in Gangetic India.” In Rural India: Land, Power and Society under British Rule, ed. Peter
Robb. London: Curzon Press, 76–105.
Power, Michael. 1997. The Audit Society: Rituals of Verification. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Prakash, Gyan. 2002. “The Colonial Genealogy of Society: Community and Political
Modernity in India.” In The Social in Question: New Bearings in History and the Social
sciences, ed. Patrick Joyce. London: Routledge, 81–96.
———. 1999. Another Reason: Science and the Imagination of Modern India. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
———. 1997. “The Modern Nation’s Return in the Archaic.” Critical Inquiry, Front
Lines/ Border Posts 23, 2: 536–56.
———. 1992. “Science ‘Gone Native’ in Colonial India.” Representations, Special Issue:
Seeing Science 40: 153–78.
328 Bibliography
Roberts, David. 1993. “Jeremy Bentham and the Victorian Administrative State.” In
Jeremy Bentham: Critical Assessments vol.3, ed Bhikhu Parekh. New York: Routledge,
879–94.
Rocher, Rosane. 1993. “British Orientalism in the Eighteenth Century: The Dialectics of
Knowledge and Government.” In Orientalism and the Post-Colonial Predicament, ed.
Carol E. Breckenridge and Peter Van der Veer. Philadelphia: University of Pennsyl-
vania Press, 215–49.
Rorty, Richard. 1979. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature.. Princeton: Princeton Univer-
sity Press.
Rose, Nikolas. 1994. “Expertise and the Government of Conduct.” Studies in Law,
Politics and Society 14: 359–97.
———. 1996. Powers of Freedom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1998. “Life, Reason and History: Reading Georges Canguilhem Today.” Econo-
my and Society 27, 2: 154–170.
Rose, Nikolas, and Peter Miller. 1992. “Political Power beyond the State: Problematics
of Government.” The British Journal of Sociology 43, 2: 173–205.
Rosenblum, Nancy L. 1978. Bentham’s Theory of the Modern State. Cambridge, Mass:
Harvard University Press.
Rudner, David. 1989. “Banker’s Trust and the Culture of Banking among the Nattukot-
tai Chettiars of Colonial South India.” Modern Asian Studies 23, 3: 417–58.
Rudolph, Lloyd. I., and Susanne Hoeber Rudolph. 1967. The Modernity of Tradition.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Ryan, Alan. 1972. “Utilitarianism and Bureaucracy: The Views of J. S. Mill.” In Studies
in the Growth of Nineteenth-Century Government, ed. G. Sutherland. London: Rout-
ledge and Kegan Paul, 33–62.
Saar, Martin. 2011. “Relocating the Modern State: Governmentality and the History of
Political Ideas.” In Governmentality: Current Issues and Future Challenges, ed. Ulrich
Brockling, Susanne Krasmann, and Thomas Lemke. New York: Routledge, 34–55.
Said, Edward. 1979/1995. Orientalism: Western Conceptions of the Orient. New York:
Vintage.
———. 1985. “Orientalism Reconsidered.” Cultural Critique 1: 89–107.
Samarendra, Padmanabh. 2003. “Classifying Caste: Census Surveys in India in the
Late Nineteenth and Early Twentieth Century.” South Asia: Journal of South Asian
Studies 26, 2 :141–64.
Sarkar, Tanika. 1993. “Rhetoric against Age of Consent: Resisting Colonial Reason and
Death of a Child Wife.” Economic and Political Weekly 28, 36: 1869–78.
Schaffer, B. B. 1993. “The Idea of the Ministerial Department: Bentham, Mill and Bage-
hot.” In Jeremy Bentham: Critical Assessments vol.3, ed. Bhikhu Parekh. New York:
Routledge, 836–57.
Scharfe, Hartmut. 1989. The State in Indian Tradition. Leiden/New York, E.J. Brill.
Schinkel, Anders. 2005 “Imagination as a Category of History: An Essay Concerning
Koselleck’s Concepts of Erfahrungsraum and Erwartungshorizont.” History and Theory
44 : 42–54.
Schwarz, Henry. 1997. “Laissez-Faire Linguistics: Grammar and the Codes of Empire.”
Critical Inquiry, Front Lines/ Border Posts 23, 2: 509–35.
Scott, David. 1995. “Colonial Governmentality.” Social Text 43: 191–220.
———. 1999. Refashioning Futures: Criticism after Postcoloniality. Princeton, NJ: Prince-
ton University Press.
Scott, James C. 1998. Seeing like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human
Condition Have Failed. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Sen, S. K., ed. 1969. Edmund Burke on Indian Economy. Calcutta: Progressive Publishers.
Sen, Sudipta. 2002. Distant Sovereignty: National Imperialism and the Origins of British
India. London: Routledge.
Sharma, Sanjay. 2001. Famine, Philanthropy and the Colonial State: North India in the Early
Nineteenth Century. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.
330 Bibliography
Shinkle, Eugenie. 1996. “The Troping of (the) Landscape: Nature and the Politics of
Representation.” Cultural Dynamics 8, 3: 219–49.
Singh, Bhrigupati. 2012. “The Headless Horseman of Central India: Sovereignty at
Varying Thresholds of Life.” Cultural Anthropology 27, 2: 383–407.
Singh, Jyotsna G. 1996. Colonial Narratives/Cultural Dialogues: “Discoveries” of India in
the Language of Colonialism. London: Routledge.
Singha, Radhika. 1993. “‘Providential’ Circumstances: The Thuggee Campaign of the
1830s and Legal Innovation.” Modern Asian Studies, Special Issue: How Social, Political
and Cultural Information is Collected, Defined, Used and Analyzed 27: 83–146.
Singha, Radhika. 1998. A Despotism of Law: Crime and Justice in Early Colonial India.
Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Sinha, Mrinalini. 1995. Colonial Masculinity: The ‘Manly’ Englishman and the ‘Effeminate’
Bengali in the Late 19th Century. Manchester: Manchester University Press.
Sivaramakrishnan, K. 1995. “Colonialism and Forestry in India: Imagining the Past in
Present Politics.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 37, 1: 3–40.
Skaria, Ajay. 2011. “Relinquishing republican democracy: Gandhi’s Ramarajya.” Postco-
lonial Studies 14, 2: 203–29.
Skinner, Quentin. 1999. “Hobbes and the Purely Artificial Person of the State.” The
Journal of Political Philosophy 7, 1: 1–29.
Smith, Richard Saumarez. 1985 . “Rule by Records and Rule by Reports: Complemen-
tary Aspects of the British Imperial Rule of Law.” Contributions to Indian Sociology
19, 1: 153–76.
Smith, Richard Saumarez. 1996. Rule by Records: Land Registration and Village Custom in
Early British Panjab. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty. 1988. “Can the Subaltern Speak?” In Marxism and the
Interpretation of Culture, ed. Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg. Urbana: Univer-
sity of Illinois Press, 271–313.
———. 1993. Outside in the Teaching Machine. London: Routledge.
———. 1995. “Teaching for the Times.” In The Decolonization of Imagination: Culture,
Knowledge and Power, ed. Jan Nederveen Pieterse and Bhikhu Parekh. London: Zed
Press, 177–202.
Srinivas, M. N. 1957. “Caste in Modern India.” The Journal of Asian Studies 16, 4: 529–48.
———. 1987. The Dominant Caste and Other Essays. Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Stein, Burton. 1980. Peasant State and Society in Medieval South India. Delhi: Oxford
University Press.
———. 1983. “Idiom and Ideology in Early Nineteenth Century South India.” In Rural
India: Land, Power and Society under British Rule, ed. Peter Robb. London: Curzon
Press, 23–58.
———. 1989. Thomas Munro: The Origins of the Colonial State and His Vision of Empire.
Delhi: Oxford University Press.
Stern, Philip. 2011. The Company-State: Corporate Sovereignty and the Early Modern Foun-
dations of the British Empire in India. New York: Oxford University Press.
Stigler, Stephen M. 1990. The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty before
1900. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.
Stocking, G. W. 1987. Victorian Anthropology. New York: The Free Press.
Stokes, Eric. 1959/1989. The English Utilitarians and India. Delhi: Oxford University
Press.
———. 1961. “The Administrators and Historical Writing on India.” In Historians of
India, Pakistan and Ceylon, ed. C.H. Phillips. London, 385–403.
———. 1973. “The First Century of British Colonial Rule in India: Social Revolution or
Social Stagnation?” Past and Present 58: 136–60.
Stoler, Ann Laura. 2002. “Colonial Archives and the Arts of Governance.” Archival
Science 2: 87–109.
———. 2009. Along the Archival Grain: Epistemic Anxieties and Colonial Common Sense.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Bibliography 331
Sussman, Charlotte. 2004. “The Colonial Afterlife of Political Arithmetic: Swift, De-
mography and Mobile Populations.” Cultural Critique 56: 96–126.
Sutherland. G. 1972. “Introduction.” In Studies in the Growth of Nineteenth Century
Government, ed. G. Sutherland. London: Routledge, 1–10.
Talbot, Cynthia. 1995. “Inscribing the Other, Inscribing the Self: Hindu-Muslim Iden-
tities in Pre-Colonial India.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 37, 4: 692–722.
Tambiah, Stanley. 1985. “From Varna to Caste through Mixed Unions.” In Culture,
Thought and Social Action: An Anthropological Perspective. Cambridge: Harvard Uni-
versity Press, 212–51.
Tellmann, Ute. 2013. “Catastrophic Populations and the Fear of the Future: Malthus
and the Genealogy of Liberal Economy.” Theory, Culture and Society 30: 135–55.
———. 2011. “The Economic Beyond Governmentality.” In Governmentality: Current
Issues and Future Challenges, ed. Ulrich Brockling, Susanne Krasmann, and Thomas
Lemke. New York: Routledge, 285–303.
Thapar, Romila. 2002. “Cyclic and Linear Time in Early India.” In Time, ed. Katinka
Ridderbos. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 27–45.
Thomas, Keith. 1987. “Numeracy in Early Modern England.” The Prothero Lecture,
Transactions of the Royal Historical Society London, Fifth Series, 37: 103–32.
Thomas, Nicholas. 1991. “Against Ethnography.” Cultural Anthropology 6, 3: 306–22.
Thomson, Janice E. 1994.Mercenaries, Pirates and Sovereigns: State-Building and Extrater-
ritorial Violence in Early Modern Europe. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Thrower, Norman. J. W. 1972. Maps and Man: An Examination of Cartography in Relation
to Culture and Civilization. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Tilly, Charles. 1994. “The Time of States.” Social Research 61, 2: 269–95.
Torrance, John. 1978. “Social Class and Bureaucratic Innovation: The Commissioners
for Examining the Public Accounts 1780–1787.” Past and Present 78: 56–81.
Trautmann, Thomas R. 1992. “The Revolution in Ethnological Time.” Man, New Series
27, 2: 379–97.
Trautmann, Thomas R. 2009. The Clash of Chronologies: Ancient India in
the Modern World. New Delhi: Yoda Press.
Tribe, Keith. 1978. Land, Labour, and Economic Discourse. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul.
Trivedi Lisa N. 2003. “Visually Mapping the ‘Nation’: Swadeshi Politics in Nationalist
India, 1920–1930.” The Journal of Asian Studies 62, 1: 11–41.
Turnbull, David. 1996. “Cartography and Science in Early Modern Europe: Mapping
the Construction of Knowledge Spaces.” Imago Mundi 48: 5–24.
Turner, Bryan S. 1992. Max Weber: From History to Modernity. London: Routledge.
Venturi, Franco. 1963. “Oriental Despotism.” Journal of the History of Ideas 24: 133–42.
Veyne Paul. 1984. Writing History: Essay on Epistemology. Trans. Mina Moore Rinvoluri.
Middleton, CT: Wesleyan University Press.
Virno, Paolo. 2004. A Grammar of the Multitude: For an Analysis of Contemporary Forms of
Life. New York: Semiotext (e).
Wagoner, Phillip. 2003. “Precolonial Intellectuals and the Production of Colonial
Knowledge.” Comparative Studies in Society and History 45, 4: 783–814.
Walter, Ryan. 2008. “Governmentality Accounts of the Economy: A Liberal Bias?”
Economy and Society 37, 1: 94–114.
Watts, Sheldon. 1999. “British Development Policies and Malaria in India 1897–c1929.”
Past and Present 165: 141–81.
Whelan, Frederick G. 1996. Edmund Burke and India: political morality and empire. Pitts-
burgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
White, Melanie. 2005. “The Liberal Character of Ethological Governance.” Economy and
Society 34, 3: 474–94.
White, Stephen K. 1994/2000. Edmund Burke: Modernity, Politics and Aesthetics. Lanham,
MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Widmalm, Sven. 1990. “Accuracy, Rhetoric, and Technology: The Paris‑Greenwich
Triangulation, 1784–88.” In The Quantifying Spirit in the 18th Century, ed. Tore
332 Bibliography
333
334 Name Index
Clemon, Frank G., 236 Dumont, Louis, 34, 137, 155, 168n2,
Clokie, Hugh Mc Dowall, 79n142 180, 214
Cohen, Patricia Cline, 80n147, 80n148 Dundas, Henry, 147
Cohn, Bernard, 1, 3, 18, 39, 69, 178, 180, Duperron, Anquetil A. H., 114
181, 208, 285n18 Durkheim, Emile, 11
Cole, Joshua, 254n27, 255n28, 255n29,
256n49 Eastwood, David, 59
Comte, Auguste, 255n30, 255n31 Eden, 279
Conybeare, Henry, 235 Edney, Mathew, 87
Cook, James, 24n57 Everest, George, 91, 93
Cooke, Charles Northcote, 151 Evola, Julius, 31
Coomaraswamy, Ananda, 31, 32, 33
Cooper, Frederick, 172n89 Fabre-Tonnerre, 236
Cornish, 165 Farr, William, 161, 205, 238
Cornwallis, Charles, 19, 65, 95 Filmer, Robert, 30
Corrigan, Philip, 18, 51, 262 Fortes, Meyer, 24n48
Crawfurd, John, 166 Foucault, Michel, 1, 2, 8, 9, 12, 18,
Crombie, A. C., 215n12 23n40, 27, 52, 53, 54, 55, 70, 74n14,
Cromwell, 29 79n124, 79n128, 83, 84, 85, 101, 111,
Crooke, William, 156, 198 120, 131n2, 134n45, 137, 138, 139,
Cullen, William, 176 140, 168n6, 168n8, 182, 223, 225, 228,
Cunningham, D. D., 238, 239, 240 230, 242, 248, 253n1, 253n2, 254n27,
Cunningham, James, 237, 238, 239 255n39, 256n44, 262, 289, 306, 307n6,
Curtis, Bruce, 61, 79n128 308n31
Curzon, George Nathaniel, 48, 67, 68, Fox, Charles James, 41
166 Fox, Richard, 40
Francis, W, 219n97
D’Anville, 102 Fraser, T. R., 242
Dalhousie, James Andrew B. R., 29 Freitag, Sandria, 285n17
Dalton, Edward T., 198
Das, Veena, 82n192 Gait, E. A., 204
Datta, Akshay Kumar, 257n63 Gandhi, M. K., 106, 276, 278, 280, 281,
De Renzy, A. C. C., 238 282, 283, 286n42, 287n60, 287n68,
De Tocqueville, Alex, 281 299
Dean, Mitchell, 165, 173n107 Gane, Mike, 255n30, 255n31
Derrett, Duncan J. M., 34 Geddes, Patrick, 236
Derrida, Jacques, 2, 70, 82n192, 135n80 Gellner, Ernest, 11
Descartes, René, 10 Ghertner, Asher D., 109n86
Devji, Faisal, 287n68 Ghurye, G. S., 178, 180, 213
Dickenson, 97 Giegerenzer, Gerd, 256n49
Diderot, Denis, 13 Gordon, Colin, 138, 307n6
Digby, William, 166 Grant, James, 42, 127
Dirks, Nicholas, 38, 70, 113, 178, 181, Graunt, John, 10, 60, 225, 232, 258n93
184, 199, 285n18 Guha, Ranajit, 63, 70, 71, 108n63, 115,
Dow, Alexander, 128 127, 128, 133n39, 136n94, 182, 262
Dr. Mayr, 245 Guha, Sumit, 114, 202, 218n80, 219n98
Dufferin, 201 Guillory, John, 79n132
Dumezil, Georges, 33, 34 Gupta, Akhil, 131n5
Gupta, Dipankar, 299
Name Index 335
absolute, 30, 32, 67, 82n192; monarchy, 157; classification, 301; concerns,
33; time, 120, 122 208; controls, 91, 182; Corps, 64;
absolutism, 30 department, 50, 139; developments,
abstract, 84, 85; regularities, 63; space, 58; devices, 58; discourses, 5, 7, 8,
83, 84, 85, 86, 87, 88, 94, 98, 101, 102, 17, 103, 162; domain, 223, 224;
104, 105, 106n8 efficiency, 60; ends, 209; hierarchy,
account books, 146, 150, 153 275; interests, 197; machine, 67;
accountability, 7, 8, 9, 18, 41, 51, 58, 65, management, 235; measures, 62, 68;
70, 71, 85, 120, 140, 141, 142, 148, modalities, 103, 115, 175; necessity,
149, 153, 154, 159, 163, 175; 180; power, 208; practices, 8, 10, 196;
procedures, 112, 166 principle, 58; procedures, 20, 150;
accounting, 9, 137, 140, 141, 142, 143, process, 80n157; record, 140, 234,
144, 145, 149, 150, 153, 154, 155, 166, 241; reforms, 57; reports, 166;
167n1, 170n40; discourses, 141, 149, revolution, 57; routines, 57; state, 54,
154; framework, 148; logic, 147; 176; strategies, 248; structures, 68;
methods, 146; practices, 145, 146, system, 141; techniques, 88;
150; principle, 147; problem, 146; thinking, 186; triplicate, 70; unit, 88
procedures, 145; system, 142, 151 aetiology of bubonic plague, 242
accounts, 10, 65, 95, 96, 98, 99, 122, 141, aetiology of cholera, 238
142, 144, 145, 146, 147, 148, 150, 151, aggregate of individuals, 266
153, 154, 155, 157, 166, 170n37, aggregate of population, 87, 160, 205
170n49; of commerce, 153 agricultural statistics, 156, 158
accumulation rationality, 104 aim of government, 47
act at a distance, 5, 6, 22n16, 61 Aini-i-Akbari, 36
acting at near, 6 Akbar Nama, 36
administered space, 105 Aligarh Institute Gazette, 278
administration, 9, 43, 49, 51, 57, 58, 61, All-India budget, 151
62, 64, 66, 67, 86, 102, 117, 127, ambiguous epistemic space, 71, 72
134n52, 149, 150, 154, 155, 165, 166, ambivalence, 61, 129, 130, 281, 282; of
169n24, 173n101, 181, 185, 201, 209, colonial discourse, 111
210, 211, 230, 234, 244, 267, 268, 272, Amrita Bazar Patrika , 279
274, 275, 292; of health, 250; of anachronism, 124, 129
justice, 50; of relief works, 164; of analytic reason, 14
state security, 64; of the Thugee, analytics of government, 56
210; reports, 123, 166, 309n36 anatomo-politics, 225
administrative, 63, 148, 175, 195, 247, Anglo-Indian, 266, 267, 268, 269, 270,
251, 274; accountability, 14, 123, 166; 271
actions, 148, 163, 233; apparatus, 28, annual account, 143
123, 159; areas, 66; attempt, 257n58; annual budget, 151
blueprint, 291; boundaries, 91, 93, annual records, 123
339
340 Subject Index
annual reports, 51, 58, 79n141, 124, 183, autonomous, 280, 306
201 agency, 284n4; agents, 262, 279;
anthropological capacities, 263 identity, 204; rationality, 139;
anthropological data, 197 sphere, 273, 277
Anthropometric Measurements, 199 autonomy, 208
anthropometry, 195, 197, 198, 200; avalanche of numbers, 12, 154, 175,
measurements, 188, 198; methods, 176, 177
188, 198; research, 197, 201 average man, 104, 228, 256n49
anti-colonialist nationalist discourse, 8
anti-contagion, 237 BAAS. See British Association for the
anti-modernist, 276 Advancement of Science
anxieties of colonial rule, 249 backward societies, 45
anxiety, 61, 63, 201 Baconian: ideas, 10, 257n63;
apparatuses: of power, 9; of security, inductivism, 58; methods, 138
53, 83, 298; of surveillance, 306 bacteriology, 232, 233, 239, 247
arbitrary legislation, 294 balance sheet, 146, 153
arbitrary power, 41 barbarian(s), 43, 44, 69, 183
Archaeological Survey of India, 201 Barthesian image, 70
archeological evidence, 218n80 Battle of Plassey 1757, 29
archival collections, 70 Being and Time, 308n31
archival forms, 56 Bengal Atlas 1781, 89
Archival power, 70 Bengal Herald, 268
archive, 56, 70, 115, 143 Bengal Hurkaru, 267, 270, 271
archives of governance, 20 Benthamite, 60, 63; ideas, 46, 58; ideas
archives of information, 63 on government, 50; panopticon, 119;
archiving documentation, 142 principle, 71; reforms, 57
Aristotelian, 85 Bhagavat Gita, 31
art of government, 30, 53, 138 Biblical chronology, 113, 116
Arthasastra , 10, 31, 33, 34, 75n42 biography of the archive, 70
Aryan, 130, 195, 196, 197, 199, 200, 201, biological, 254n27; multiplicity, 230;
204 normativity, 227; processes, 253n1
Aryanist perspective, 130 biopolitics, 223, 228, 236, 237, 241, 243,
Asiatic Research, 114 297, 303, 305; of cholera, 237; of the
assemblage of persons, 74n12 population, 225
assemblages, 70 bio-power, 53, 160, 224, 228, 230, 252,
attributes of sites, 85 297
audit culture, 66 bi-polar sovereignty, 34
authoritarian, 181, 249, 280 bi-polar technology, 254n27
authoritarian liberalism, 47 The Birth of the Clinic, 228, 253n2
authoritarian rule, 280 Blue books, 58, 61, 163, 226
authoritative, 243, 261, 280 body natural, 74n20
authoritative agent, 274 body politic, 74n20
authoritative bearer, 266 body-organism, 253n1
authority, 30, 68, 69, 72, 111, 119, 129, body-scapes, 105
142, 143, 189, 190, 249, 250, 279, Bombay Durpan , 269
285n18; grants of, 41; nature and The Bombay Times and Standard, 268,
degree of, 44 269, 270, 277
authorized, 101, 191, 248 book-keeping, 142, 150, 151, 152, 154,
authorizing power, 105, 242, 246 171n64, 224; accounts, 123;
Subject Index 341
categories, 140; practices, 145, 146 calculating rationality, 20, 86, 137, 154
bound seriality, 16, 55, 212; effect, 212 calculation, 18, 54, 59, 60, 73, 87, 90,
bourgeois : liberties, 282; public sphere, 118, 121, 137, 139, 140, 142, 151, 152,
268; revolution, 282 154, 166, 168n13, 199, 235, 298; and
brahmanical model, 187 tactics, 9
Brief View of the Caste System of the calculative : action, 306; ethos, 305;
N.W.Provinces and Oudh, 193 practice, 109n86, 137, 167n1;
British: administration, 40, 49; Census routines, 144
of 1861, 161; British censuses, 201, calculus of benefit, 282
205; Empire, 29, 48, 61, 62, 64, capital accounting, 149, 152
133n28; government, 57; capital budgeting, 146
governmental machinery, 57; capitalist enterprise, 150, 152
governmental practices, 27; imperial Cartesian man, 11
enterprise, 180; imperialism, 42, 45, cartographic images, 105
47, 262, 296; state, 62, 63; statistical cartographic representations, 84
movement, 60 cartography, 6, 86, 90, 102, 104
British Association for the carto-statistical techniques, 87, 103,
Advancement of Science, 60, 165, 104, 234
197, 198 caste, 40, 54, 64, 90, 159, 160, 175, 178,
bureaucracy, 35, 51, 52, 57, 58, 60, 64, 179, 180, 181, 182, 184, 185, 187, 188,
66–67, 68, 71, 77n105, 85, 143, 190, 191, 192, 193, 194, 195, 197, 199,
162–163, 274, 285n18, 295, 307, 200, 201, 204, 206, 208, 209, 210, 211,
309n36 212, 213, 216n51, 216n52, 219n97,
bureaucratic, 65, 67, 88, 123, 165; 241, 247, 252, 277, 285n18, 298, 299,
accountability, 297; action, 295; 300, 301, 303; associations, 212;
administration, 243; authority, 52; categories, 181, 186; classification,
authorization, 142; 194, 195, 201, 212; communities, 178,
communications, 52; control, 20, 97; 208, 211; consciousness, 212, 213;
culture, 82n192; decision-making, data, 182, 184, 211; distinctions, 194,
134n56, 163; disciplines, 52; 203; endogamy, 199; enumeration,
discourses, 141; edifice, 173n101; 180, 185, 213; functional theory of,
enthusiasm, 297; exactitude, 77n105; 205; glossaries, 214; groups, 187,
frameworks, 121; hierarchy, 71; 208, 211; hierarchy, 209; identity,
indifference, 298; intervention, 296; 178; list, 185; names, 186, 187, 208;
knowledge, 231; manipulation, 296; origins of, 193, 194; principle, 211;
performance, 298; practices, 56, 103, racial origins of, 193, 195; ranking,
118, 120, 121, 126, 166; procedures, 212; and religion, 203; segregation,
166; procedures of writing, 27; 119; status, 187; structure, 186, 294;
productions, 58; rationality, 165, system, 37, 38, 179, 180, 188, 189,
285n18; regulation, 38; rules, 120; 193, 194, 195, 197, 200, 201; theories
signature, 82n192; structures, 67, of caste, 193, 198; and tribes, 190
295; system, 58; writings, 51, 52, 70 Caste and Race in India, 213
bureaucratic-legal order, 6 Caste Census of North Western Provinces
bureaucratized modern state, 55 1865, 187
Burkean, 96; agrarian image, 181; caste-occupation nexus, 194, 205
phrase, 19; thinking, 19 causal, 231, 256n49; laws, 15;
relationship, 104
cadastral, 99; surveys, 86, 209 causality, 1, 7, 8, 20, 21, 73, 224, 233,
calculable man, 85 234, 237, 241, 242, 247, 248, 249,
342 Subject Index
242; bureaucracy, 45, 242, 295; 162, 165, 166, 175, 178, 182, 185, 227,
capitalism, 153; cartography, 89, 92, 231, 233, 235, 236, 242, 252, 261, 264,
103, 105; categories, 70; census 266, 268, 269, 270, 271, 273, 274, 275,
enumeration, 181; censuses, 160, 276, 277, 278, 280, 282, 283, 289, 290,
181, 182, 204, 212; character, 254n20; 291, 292, 293, 294, 298
civilizing agenda, 114, 182, 302; Colonialism and its forms of Knowledge:
comparison, 235, 236; conduct, 227, the British in India, 285n18
263, 265, 268, 277, 278, 279, 290, 294, colonialist historiography, 127, 128,
298; covenant, 274, 275; difference, 129, 130
55, 87, 128, 181, 250, 252, 271; colonized population, 253
discourse, 5, 12, 17, 105, 111, 124, colonized society, 263
180; discourse of caste, 182; colonized terrain, 140
documentary system, 61; combinable mobiles, 61
documents, 70; domination, 106; commensurability of cultures, 16
economy, 137, 140, 149, 151, 154, commercial accounts, 146
159, 211; education project, 265, 269; Commercial and Political Atlas, 104
empire, 54, 84; epidemiological commissions, 58, 59, 66, 68
terrain, 224; epistemological project, communal politics, 213
295; financial system, 159; form of communal representation, 213
civil society, 181; historiography, communalism, 221n141, 264
130; indifference, 276; invention, communicable diseases, 224, 231
181; liberalism, 264, 292, 293; communicative action, 284n3
medical intervention, 231, 252; communities, 179, 180, 184
mimcry, 111, 128, 129; modality of compact, 286n39
knowledge, 184; modernity, 227, comparable groups, 241
269, 276, 277; office, 61; official comparative observations, 248
sociology/anthropology, 213; order, comparative statistics, 12
80n162, 109n85; order of difference, Comptroller and Auditor General, 58
236; power, 84, 113, 264; practices, Comrade, 278
141; project, 49, 63, 87, 270, 277; Comtean ideas, 177
public health, 229; public sphere, Comtean project, 228
262; rationality, 292; rule, 128; rule Comtean sociology, 177
of difference, 18, 230; sanitary conceptions of kingship, 74n20
policy, 239; society, 232; sociology, condensation of regulative functions,
175, 213; spidemiological terrain, 51
252; stabilization policy, 172n89; Congress of Orientalists, 197
state, 7, 8, 10, 17, 18, 20, 23n33, 49, consciousness, 134n56, 220n115
56, 62, 64, 65, 68, 69, 70, 71, 87, 94, constative, 130
96, 98, 99, 104, 105, 112, 118, 119, Constituent Assembly, 294
121, 123, 126, 136n94, 139, 141, 150, constitution, 42, 291, 292, 293, 299
154, 156, 158, 159, 162, 165, 166, Constitution of India, 291, 312
168n12, 173n97, 182, 184, 195, 208, Constitutional Code, 50, 58, 150
251, 252, 263, 265, 266, 272, 274, 275, construction of modern power, 17
279, 285n18, 292; temporality, 66, 70; constructivism, 12
truth claims, 70; violence, 94; wars, contagion theory, 224
49 contextual document, 179
colonial governmentality, 1, 18, 21, 27, contingencies of chance, 13
49, 53, 55, 69, 70, 73, 87, 88, 94, 100, contingent, 241
104, 105, 115, 128, 137, 139, 140, 160, contradictions of abstract space, 105
344 Subject Index
248, 253n2, 255n30, 259n106; empire, 36, 41, 42, 56, 57, 60, 61, 62, 84,
causation, 233, 237; classification, 89, 144, 153, 156, 161, 181, 206, 231,
237; control, 224, 239 233, 262, 269, 284n12
dislocated liberalism, 69 Empire , 308n30
disposition, 125, 183, 187, 196, 263, 282 empirical laws, 183
dividing practices, 183, 184 empirico-transcendental doublet,
divine authority, 145 23n40, 131n2
divine kingship, 31, 32 end of government, 47
divine pastor, 32 English: newspapers, 267; Poor Law
divine right, 30 Commission 1832-1834, 173n106;
divinely illumined right, 36 press, 267, 268; sanitary statistics,
division of labor, 188, 193, 263, 270 235; state, 58, 60
doctrine of lapse, 29 Enlightenment, 10, 85, 114, 116, 126,
doctrine of natural political virtue, 132n15, 232, 261, 290, 294; anti-
286n39 imperialist thinkers, 12; knowledge,
doctrine of public trust, 58 11, 12; rationalism, 180
document, 52, 69 ensemble of population, 225, 226
documentary evidence, 114, 116, 148 enterprises, 149, 151, 152, 153, 154
documentary practices, 52, 143 enterprise accounts, 150, 151, 154
documentary system, 61 enumerable, 177, 184
documentation, 56, 57, 66, 70 enumerable groups, 184
documentation by the state, 51 enumerate communities, 178, 179, 180,
documentation record, 142 221n141
documents, 56, 59, 72, 80n147, 143, 268 enumerating population, 211
domain of strategies, 54 enumeration, 36, 62, 90, 137, 160, 175,
domains of administration, 86 177, 178, 179, 180, 182, 184, 185, 202,
Dominance without Hegemony, 133n39 204, 208, 209, 296, 298; of caste, 184,
dominance without hegemony, 182 192, 213
domination of strangers, 267 enumerative, 1, 18, 195
double-entry, 145, 152; book-keeping, enumerative inductivism, 232
150, 151, 170n49; system, 150, 154, enumerative moment, 213
170n44, 170n49 enumerative politics, 214
doubling of man, 12, 111, 124, 126, enumerative practices, 13, 14, 182
135n70 environmental norms, 227, 231
Dravidian, 195, 196, 198 environmental regulation, 227
Durkheimian, 255n31, 300 epidemic, 66, 67, 103, 105, 122, 223, 230,
dynamic nominalism, 206 233, 234, 242, 243, 245, 246, 247, 248,
249; administration, 252; areas, 233;
East India Bill, 41 cholera, 236; conditions, 239;
East India Company, 28, 29, 36, 40, 41, control, 121, 234; disease, 209, 224,
42, 61, 64, 67, 122, 141, 142, 143, 147, 231, 234, 236, 237, 238; Diseases Act
148 1897, 248; intensity, 243;
economy, 8, 21, 53, 120, 122, 123, 124, management, 236, 241, 249, 253
137, 138, 139, 141, 148, 150, 152, 154, epidemiological terrain, 230, 242
156, 157, 158, 159, 160, 166, 167n1, episteme, 1, 7, 9, 70, 89, 94, 129, 242, 306
168n2, 168n6, 211, 226, 254n21, 264, epistemic, 54, 166, 224, 294; agendas,
273; of equivalences, 166 89; categories, 73; concerns, 69;
ecumene, 285n24 discontinuities, 27; domain, 122;
embodied knowledge, 6, 63 foundation, 10; function, 160, 166;
346 Subject Index
functional identities, 179 83, 85, 87, 104, 109n85, 111, 138, 160,
functional sites, 83, 85, 86, 87, 88, 89, 91, 162, 169n24, 207, 212, 223, 235, 250,
94; of governance 105 252, 262, 271, 278, 280, 289, 290, 293,
Fundamental Rights, 291, 292, 299, 300 296, 298, 302, 304; framework, 224;
future-oriented projects, 63 effects, 104; history of, 54; theorists,
fuzzy communities, 178, 179 138
governmentalization, 223
game of politics, 276 governmentalization of the state, 9, 14,
gazetteers, 155, 156, 208, 209 35, 54
Gemeinschaft, 153 governmentalized rule, 53
genealogy, 141, 143, 165, 166; of gradations of morality, 59
calculation, 137; method, 179; of gradations of unfreedom, 59
poverty, 296 Grammatology, 70
geographic archive, 84, 89, 90 graphic artifacts, 52, 61
germ theory, 224, 239, 240 Great Trigonometrical Survey (GTS),
Gesellschaft, 153 92
Glas, 70
global risks, 304 Harijanbandhu, 280
global sovereignty, 307 health statistics, 231
Glossaries, 156, 157, 192, 197, 208 Hegelian, 111
good government, 44, 45 Heideggerian, 303
goodness of a government, 44 heterogeneity: of beliefs, 201; of spaces,
govern conduct, 303 91, 101; of temporalities, 52; of time,
govern the conduct, 94, 300 120
governable space, 86 heterotopias, 84–85
governance, 83, 85, 86, 88, 118, 230, 289; hierarchization, 229, 248
from a distance, 43, 73; of castes, Hind Swaraj , 282
182; of character, 182; of colonial Hindoo Patriot , 267
conduct, 87, 276; of conduct, 86, 175, Hindu Castes and Sects , 213
184, 303; effects, 227, 263, 279; of Hindu Janabhooshany , 274
health, 227; of human conduct, 55; Hinduization, 214
of populations, 9; practices, 118; of Hinduism, 202, 203, 204; chronology,
spaces, 84; strategies, 73, 88; 113, 114, 132n11; kingship, 30, 31
structures, 94 historical: consciousness, 113, 132n13,
government, 41, 46, 50, 83; accounts, 134n55; contingency, 54; deeds, 111;
150, 154; action, 72, 271; of disease, epistemologies, 56; events, 113;
227; of economic life, 167n1; of food, knowledge, 89, 116, 117; maps, 89;
165; growth of, 57; interventions, modernity, 124; narratives, 111, 114,
295, 303; of leading strings, 45; of 117, 168n12; nominalism, 54;
modern states, 54; of poverty, 165, practice, 7; reality, 113; records, 115;
227; power, 252, 281; practice, 55, science, 133n27; time, 113, 114,
159, 166, 307n6; problematics of, 55, 220n115; truth, 133n27;
105; procedures, 138, 168n8; understanding, 114
rationalities, 160, 243, 302; of record, historicism, 134n56, 286n42
65; signature, 70; sites, 242; historicist memory, 127
statistics, 166; techniques, 9, 53, 139, historicity, 107n30, 127
302; technologies, 54, 302 historiography, 114, 128, 130, 136n101,
governmentality, 1, 8, 9, 11, 14, 18, 53, 136n109, 136n94, 169n24
54, 55, 56, 62, 63, 67, 68, 73, 79n128,
348 Subject Index
legal norms, 38 liberalism, 19, 27, 40, 46, 48, 53, 55, 69,
legal-political sovereignty, 295 129, 140, 164, 237, 261, 262, 263, 275,
legibility, 98 278, 280, 284n3, 291, 300, 301; as a
legible, 142 historical event, 49; in practice, 272;
legislation, 50 anxieties, 280
legislative, 50, 64, 68, 265, 266, 269, 274, liberatory knowledge, 113
279, 293 libertarian project, 293
Legislative Councils, 275 liberty, 43, 46, 47, 69, 180, 280, 282, 292,
legitimacy, 29, 30, 39, 54, 73, 73n6, 139, 294
262, 265, 293, 295; of the state, 51 limited government, 41
legitimate mode of government, 43 lineage, 39, 40, 94, 185
legitimate sphere of government lineage control, 39
functions, 44 lineage segments, 178
legitimate subjects, 272 lineage system, 38
legitimized powers, 51 linear time, 119, 131n5, 132n22
Leviathan, 45, 170n40 linguistic surveys, 90
liberal, 44, 49, 55, 63, 139, 163, 167n1, “little” public spheres, 265
173n107, 196, 225, 226, 240, 262, 263, local contingencies, 224
275, 278, 280, 282, 289, 291, 304, 306; localist theories, 238
agency, 138; agenda of education, localistic response, 239
48; democracy, 261, 287n64; localization, 232
democratic project, 300; The Location of Culture, 3
governance, 69; government, 59, Lockean imagery, 13
183; contradictions of, 242; Logic , 183
governmentality, 17, 18, 69, 103, 138, logical-linguistic forms, 306
177, 226, 246, 250, 252, 253, 280, 281, London Statistical Society, 13, 60
283, 289, 303, 304; governmentality long-distance colonial governance, 141
of health, 249; idea, 289; ideals, 291; long-distance governance, 102, 112
imperialism, 48; justice, 301, 302; lower castes, 188, 211
political rationalities, 227, 254n15;
political reason, 59; public opinion, Machiavellism, 50
282; public sphere, 264, 267, 278, magical sovereignty, 33
279, 281, 282, 283, 287n61; magico-religious risks, 33
rationalities, 55, 138; rationalities of magico-religious sovereignty, 33
government, 55, 183, 225, 226, 252; Magna Carta, 41, 42
rationalities of rule, 183; rationality Mahratta, 274, 278
of ethological governance, 196; majoritarian group, 204
rationality of numbers, 301; reason, majoritarian politics, 282
283, 291; security, 226; strategies of majoritarian values, 287n61
government, 289; technique of majority, 204, 205, 281, 283, 300
normalization, 301; techniques of malaria, 231, 233, 234
government, 301, 302; technologies, Malayalam Manorama, 273
85, 269, 295; technologies of Malthusian approach, 297
government, 55, 266, 301; Manual of the Administration of the
technologies of rule, 290, 293; Madras Presidency, 117, 195
technology of governance, 84; manufacture subjects, 27
technology of governmentality, 91, Manusmriti, 34
101, 104; technology of justice, 301; map(s), 52, 84, 87, 89, 90, 91, 92, 95, 101,
universalism, 263 102, 103, 104, 105, 106, 178, 198, 243,
Subject Index 351
modern state, 1, 4, 6, 7, 8, 9, 12, 13, 18, identities, 90, 276; income, 166;
30, 49, 50, 51, 52, 54, 55, 56, 62, 68, Income Accounts, 155; society, 293;
75n42, 86, 88, 91, 103, 111, 120, 121, space, 129; temporality, 118
126, 128, 129, 130, 138, 139, 160, nationalism, 268, 285n22, 285n24;
168n12, 179, 180, 182, 184, 207, 223, discourse, 21, 129, 166; histories,
224, 269; as subject, 51; formation, 130; historiography, 127, 129, 130;
51; space, 84; regulations of, 52; imagination of history, 127;
representations of, 52 movement, 48, 264, 267, 276, 279,
modern subject, 85 280; sociology/anthropology, 213;
modern temporality, 122 thought, 261
modern thought, 175 nationhood, 90, 289
modernist site of progress, 276 nations, 194, 237
modernity, 130 nation-state, 214, 277, 290, 292, 293, 294
modes of inscription, 6 native classification, 157
modes of signing, 82n192 native criminality, 209
monarchical absolutism, 30 native knowledges, 263, 264
Moral and Material Progress, 8, 160, 183, native newspapers, 266, 274, 279
209 native press, 269, 270, 280, 287n50
moral improvement, 47, 278 native subjectivity, 270
moral liberalism, 265 native survey, 99
moral scale, 42 natural history, 176, 238
moral sovereignty, 284n3 natural law, 42
morbidity, 232, 247 natural rights, 27, 41
mortality, 231, 232, 233, 236, 237, 241, naturalization, 254n16
243, 247 naturalization of poverty, 227
Mother India, 106 Naturall Person, 46
Mughal: administration, 35, 69; Navajivan, 276, 280
authority, 36; charters, 29; Empire, negative freedom, 291, 294
39; power, 65; state, 35, 36, 69; neoliberal, 306, 307
system of government, 40 neoliberal governmentality, 302, 303,
multiform tactics, 53 304, 306, 307
multiplicities, 229 neoliberal rationality, 305
multitude, 303, 304, 306, 307, 308n30, neoliberal subject(s), 303, 304, 305
309n39 neoliberalism, 290, 302
Muslim(s), 185, 189, 202, 204, 205, 212, new game of politics, 73, 264, 276
213, 219n101, 250, 251, 277, 278 newspaper, 261, 264, 265, 266, 267, 268,
Muslim League, 205, 212 269, 270, 271, 272, 274, 275, 276, 277,
mythic history, 218n80 278, 279, 285n24
mythographies, 116 Newtonian, 11, 116; anthropology, 11,
mythology, 233 12
Nietzschean idea, 179
Napoleonic Code, 157 Ninth International Congress of
narrative authority, 130 Orientalists, 197
narrative framework, 284n3 nominalist assumptions, 232
nation, 105, 106, 124, 127, 129, 130, nonage, 45
136n109, 161, 179, 185, 201, 205, non-Brahman castes, 211
221n138, 274, 275, 291, 292, 294, 295; non-contagious, 233, 237, 239
economy, 140, 159; fraternity, 299, non-purifying castes, 202
300; freedom, 299; history, 130, 301; non-secular time, 134n57
Subject Index 353
discourses, 289; discussion, 284n3; regulation, 58, 79n124, 118, 120, 128,
forms of administration, 49; 142, 143, 161, 173n97, 181, 226, 227,
governance, 64; governance of the 230, 273; of life, 226; of
population, 68; history(s), 116, 117, mercantilism, 80n148; domains of,
126, 129; ordering of spaces, 85; 181
techniques, 88; thinking, 283; regulations, 105, 119, 142, 144, 253n1,
universality, 293 259n106, 266
rationale for government, 226 regulative practices, 154
rationalist historiography, 129 regulative scheme, 55
rationalist history, 130 regulatory, 230; activities, 18; controls,
rationalist paradigm, 8 225; discipline, 139; framework, 113,
rationalities, 1, 263, 283, 303, 307n6; of 302; functions, 139; injunctions, 153;
calculation, 27; of governance, 196, measures, 119, 165; mechanisms, 55,
281; of government, 223; of power, 160, 166, 253n1; practices, 8, 17, 120,
182; principles of, 53 121, 123, 138, 140, 141, 165, 175, 271,
rationalization, 95, 121, 141, 154; of 306; site, 175; techniques, 17
administration, 49, 254n20 Reflections on the Revolution in France,
Rawlsian, 299 287n66
real space, 102 relief works, 163, 164, 165
reason of state, 30, 50, 55, 138 religion, 160, 175, 185, 201, 202, 203,
reconstructing histories, 90 204, 205, 210, 213, 216n38, 220n115,
record, 71, 115, 143, 185, 206, 214, 233, 232, 241, 247, 249, 252, 277, 291, 297,
245 299, 303; categories, 185, 201, 202;
recordation, 1, 18, 27, 61, 70 communities, 205; histories, 117;
righteousness of Recordation, 66 identity, 205, 219n101, 220n115
recording of information, 18, 20 The Religion of India, 133n27
recording of observations, 259n106 Renaissance, 89, 114
record-keeping, 10, 38, 143, 145, 149; Report of the Sanitary State and Sanitary
activities, 120; practices, 68 Requirements of Bombay, 235
records, 65, 69, 71, 95, 96, 116, 247 Report on the Census of the British Empire
reform commissions, 60 1901, 62
reform discourses, 276 Report upon the Sanitary Condition of
Reformer, 268 Ward VII (Burra Bazar), Calcutta
regime of knowledge, 156 1899, 236
regimentation, 112 report(s), 50, 52, 56, 58, 59, 61, 62, 65,
regimes of modern power, 121 66, 67, 71, 184, 186, 224, 226, 238,
regimes of truth, 56 251, 266, 272, 277
regional histories, 127, 128 representation, 73, 85, 86, 101, 116, 122,
regional surveys, 234 123, 137, 138, 152, 180, 188, 295, 298,
Registrar General, 62 299; of objects, 104; politics, 213, 275;
registration of deaths, 259n106 practices, 137
Regnum, 31, 33 representative: assemblies, 268, 269;
regular accounts, 150 government(s), 47, 48, 264, 269, 295;
regularity(s), 125, 141, 149, 167n1, sample, 14, 196
215n12, 226, 229, 232, 256n49; of Representative Government , 269
disease, 224; of observation, 51 representing, 55, 133n27, 143, 166
regulating the accounts, 142 republican democracy, 282
regulating weights, 159 revenue accounts, 97
revenue administration, 96
Subject Index 357
segmentary forms of state, 39 265, 270, 277, 281, 285n24, 290, 291
segmentary state, 37, 38 sovereign, 74n14, 207, 282
segmentary state framework, 38 sovereign powers, 28, 30
segmentary system, 39 sovereign ruler, 29
segmentation, 248 sovereign subject(s), 129, 265
segmented, 85 single and indivisible sovereignty, 50
segments, 37, 265, 269 single sovereignty, 36
segregation, 248, 249, 250, 251, 252 sovereignty, 9, 27, 28, 29, 30, 31, 35, 36,
Select Committee(s), 58, 59, 65, 172n79; 37, 39, 40, 41, 53, 54, 61, 63, 64, 65,
Select Committee on Indian Famine 67, 74n14, 75n42, 88, 130, 139, 184,
(1873), 174n113 223, 274, 293, 295, 302, 303, 307,
seriality(s), 211, 212 308n30; gradations of, 34; divisible,
series, 187, 199, 227, 253n1, 255n28 74n9; indivisible, 51; of a territory,
series of events, 227 254n15; nature of sovereignty, 88;
settlement reports, 185 norms and forms of, 16; thematics
sign of difference, 256n50 of, 53; theory of, 31, 138
signature, 70, 82n192, 142 sovereignty-governmentality-
signification of concepts, 124 discipline, 9
similarities, 69, 86, 177, 181, 207 sovereignty-territoriality-discipline, 9
single sovereign, 41 space(s), 1, 7, 8, 21, 73, 83, 85, 86, 88, 89,
singular, 135n80 90, 91, 94, 100, 101, 103, 104, 236,
singular subjectivity, 82n192 242, 278, 284n4, 304; of
singularity(s), 130, 135n80, 308n30; of administration, 87, 104; of
fever, 227 appropriation, 94, 100; of
site(s), 9, 85, 91, 94, 129; of legitimation, domination, 85; of experience, 113,
280; of public opinion, 281; with no 114; of governance, 214; of the
places, 85; space, 85 modern state, 84; nature of, 88; of
sly civility, 70 political economy, 87; of sanitary
small-area statistics, 249 regime, 105; of risk, 306; of Utopia,
Smithian: idea, 162; principles, 271 84
social, 224, 225, 262, 263, 265, 269, 276, spatial: control, 236; distribution, 224;
294, 298; causality, 10, 232, 256n49; knowledge, 83; mapping, 227;
classifications, 175, 185, 198; practices, 105; strategies, 94
contract theory, 53; discipline, 208; spectacularization, 101
freedom, 298, 299; groups, 277, 296; sphere of morality, 207
histories, 200; identity(s), 178, 212, spheres of administration, 67
277; justice, 299; morphology, 188, Spiritual Authority and Temporal Power
211; norm(s), 59, 209, 229, 230; in the Indian Theory of Government, 31
order, 269; phenomenon, 10; splitting of colonial discourse, 111
physics, 177; practices, 84, 229; standard(s), 152, 170n43, 190, 228, 246,
precedence, 188; reform(s), 276, 278, 276; classifications, 98; consumption
294, 298, 299; space(s), 85, 105, 106, units, 166; deviation, 200; of living,
234, 257n58 160, 162; type, 199
Social Science Association, 60 standardization, 70, 101, 140, 141, 145,
sociality, 154 152, 159, 248; of caste names, 187; of
society(s), 8, 21, 55, 79n124, 120, 121, conduct, 183; of names, 187; of
122, 123, 124, 125, 127, 137, 175, 177, procedures, 57
178, 188, 194, 209, 211, 213, 223, 225, standardized: classifications, 62; forms,
228, 229, 232, 255n36, 261, 263, 264, 61; teloses, 124; time, 118
Subject Index 359
state: apparatuses, 9; of civil society, statistics, 11, 14, 17, 20, 24n48, 55, 59,
54; documentation, 61; formation, 60, 62, 66, 69, 71, 72, 79n141, 80n162,
53; forms, 54; identifications, 212; 88, 123, 138, 160, 162, 163, 165, 166,
medicine, 242; of civilization, 43; 171n55, 185, 187, 205, 208, 209,
order, 40; practices, 120; projects of 216n43, 226, 227, 228, 237, 238, 241,
simplification, 214; rationality, 104; 242, 243, 249, 254n27, 258n93, 295,
reason, 225; simplification, 98; 304, 306; of birth, 225; of mortality,
sovereignty, 14, 16, 61, 63; 233; of the Empire, 123; on crime,
surveillance, 6; technology, 66; 163; worship of, 59
temporality, 112 stochastic: methods, 13; thinking, 14
statecraft, 39, 54, 59, 242 stranger, 63
state-economy relation, 54 strategies, 27, 49, 56, 84, 105, 289; of
state-idea, 73n5 government, 289; of security, 226
state-like actions, 29 strong languages, 17
state-like conduct, 29 structure: of a state, 50; of governance,
state-like function, 29 38, 94; of government, 48; of power,
state-making, 18, 64, 67 49, 114
statistical, 20, 61, 103, 140, 152, 159, 162, The Structural Transformation of the
235; abstracts, 166; aggregates, 13; Public Sphere, 261
analysis, 14, 199, 215n12, 235; styles: of reasoning, 16, 176, 215n12,
categories, 14, 256n49; causality, 229; of language, 12
230, 235; Committee, 123; subaltern: signification, 130; studies,
correlation, 104, 235; corroboration, 23n27, 136n109
235; data, 10, 13, 14, 166, 171n73, subject, 106n8, 207
231, 234, 238, 240, 295, 297, 298, 306, subject of narration, 130
307; discourse(s), 13, 175; enquiries, subject-constituting effect(s), 252, 278,
216n43; enumeration, 5; episteme, 283
182; epistemology, 238; estimates, subject-effects, 252
223; evidence, 232, 240, 247; facts, subjecthood, 129
13, 166; forms, 159; frequencies, 232; subjectivity(s), 54, 57, 175, 184, 243, 276,
index numbers, 166; inference, 166, 284n4, 303
235, 247; information, 7, 20, 60, 93; subjectivity effects, 175
knowledge, 8, 12, 18, 70, 140, 242, subjectivity of the state, 51
297; laws, 15, 177; medical norms, supreme sovereignty, 32
245; methods, 20, 200, 219n98; surrogate statehood, 29
modes, 14, 17; movement, 60; surveillance, 9, 18, 88, 93, 100, 112, 119,
narratives, 13; norms, 104, 228, 230; 141, 155, 210, 224, 237, 238, 248, 265,
practices, 21, 271; probability, 229; 272, 273, 285n24, 303, 307, 309n37
procedures, 24n48; reasoning, 234; survey(s), 20, 46, 63, 89, 91, 92, 93, 95,
regularity(s), 15, 177; repetition, 13; 96, 97, 98, 99, 102, 104, 117, 123, 155,
reports, 155; representation, 12, 13, 175, 179, 181, 184, 185, 199, 236, 247
158, 159, 161, 297; rhetoric, 172n92; survey(s): methods, 94, 96; modality,
survey(s), 20, 56, 59; table(s), 59, 238, 18; of territories, 20
255n29; tests, 200; time-series, 124; Swadeshabhimani, 272
universe(s), 13, 244; world-view, 9 Swadeshamitran, 274
Statistical Account of Sealkote District, synchronized census, 62
102 synoptic table, 176
statistically generated laws, 15 system of enunciabilities, 70
system of recordation, 65, 66
360 Subject Index
systematic classification, 176 temporality, 111, 112, 118, 119, 120, 121,
systematic predetection, 306, 309n37 125, 126, 135n61
systematic regularities, 15 temporalization, 112, 122; of economic
systematization of caste, 181 entities, 123; of entities, 124; of
systems of verification, 66 social and economic entities, 123
temporally standardized, 149, 151
table(s), 143, 148, 190, 243, 255n28 territorial, 38, 88, 157, 190; accounts,
tabular representation, 186 148; representations, 87;
tabular shape, 186 sovereignty, 29, 37; state(s), 40, 83
tactic of government, 68 territoriality, 9, 37, 38, 40, 64, 67, 83, 87
tactics, 49, 54, 55, 139 territory(s), 47, 64, 83, 87, 90, 93, 94,
taming chance, 71, 73 101, 103, 113, 114, 127, 147, 149, 155,
target approach, 297, 298, 299 178, 188, 190, 201, 225, 226
taxonomic, 177, 185, 198, 214, 215n12, time, 1, 7, 8, 21, 47, 73, 85, 100, 101, 118,
228; classifications, 202; structure, 119, 120, 122, 123, 131n5, 133n25,
191, 192 133n31, 134n60, 143, 165, 166, 176,
technique: of government, 8, 18, 242; contestation, 118; discipline,
79n124, 295, 297, 298, 301; of 118, 119; series, 14, 149, 151; series
autopsy, 227; of calculability, 305; of data, 124; self-awareness of, 121
character formation, 183; of colonial time-indexation, 123
governmentality, 268, 293; of time-measurement, 118
control, 119, 207; of governance, 9, time-table, 118, 119, 134n45
128; of governmentality, 17, 89, 297, topographical, 91, 92, 98, 103, 117, 185,
299, 301, 306; of knowledge, 257n63; 238
of measurement, 199; of topographical survey(s), 91, 93
normalization, 140; of postcolonial totalizing, 91, 225, 226, 253n2, 280
governmentality, 299; of rule, 69; of trade accounts, 122, 142, 144, 148, 149,
security, 84; of subjection, 120; of 154
surveillance, 303; of visualization, trade statistics, 148, 149
255n40; of writing, 55 traditional communities, 179, 183
technologies: of colonial governance, transcendence, 263, 285n17, 285n18
86; of colonial rule, 227; of control, transcendental, 262; domain, 225;
94; of governance, 5, 8, 52, 83, 86, 88, subject, 7, 10
140, 261, 294, 303; of government, triangualation, 92, 99
86, 223, 226, 290, 298, 302; of tribe(s), 178, 182, 184, 185, 189, 191, 192,
inscription, 166; of power, 223, 230; 195, 197, 198, 203, 209, 210, 218n80,
of postcolonial governmentality, 221n134, 301
296; of rule, 27, 56, 68, 181, 271, 278; Tribes and Castes of Bengal, 192, 197, 198
of security, 254n15; of state trigonometical survey, 91
formation, 89 trigonometrical surveys, 92, 98, 99, 202
temporal: calendar, 118; categories, 20; tropical epidemiology, 242
consciousness, 118; continuity, 124; tropical medicine, 232
difference, 85; disciplinary methods, trust, 71, 73, 159, 286n39
120; discourse, 111; framework(s), truth: claims, 70; of colonial difference,
112, 113, 116, 117; grid, 116; 180; as reaon, 283; regime, 42
knowledge, 120; nature, 122; typification, 188, 210; of castes, 200
regularities, 112, 118; regulation, tyranny of majority, 281
123; sequences, 126, 141, 148, 159;
standardization, 119, 120 unbound seriality(s), 16, 55, 211, 304
Subject Index 361
363