Zlib - Pub A History of Psychology in Ten Questions
Zlib - Pub A History of Psychology in Ten Questions
in Ten Questions
This student-friendly book on the history of psychology covers the key historical
developments and controversies in all areas of psychology, linking history to the
present by focusing on ten conceptual issues that are relevant today.
How did psychology become a science, and what kind of science did it
become? How do psychologists measure and explain the fact that in some
ways everyone is unique? Is psychoanalysis scientific? Why did cognitive
science replace behaviorism? This book addresses all these questions and
more, covering the whole range of psychology, from neuroscience and artificial
intelligence to hermeneutics and qualitative research in the process. Drawing
on the author’s experience of how to make the subject interesting for students,
the book is structured around ten key questions that engage with all the core
areas of psychology and the main schools of thought. Showing how each of
the different approaches or paradigms within psychology differ not based on
data but on assumptions, Michael Hyland provides an engaging introduction
to debates from history and in contemporary society.
Including boxed material on hot topics, historical figures, studies/
experiments, and quirky facts, this is the ideal book for undergraduate students
of psychology taking CHIPS and other history of psychology modules.
Michael Hyland
First published 2020
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
52 Vanderbilt Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2020 Michael Hyland
The right of Michael Hyland to be identified as author of this work has been
asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright,
Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or
utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now
known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording, or in
any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in writing
from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record for this book has been requested
ISBN: 978-0-8153-6507-5 (hbk)
ISBN: 978-0-8153-8487-8 (pbk)
ISBN: 978-1-351-20303-6 (ebk)
Typeset in Sabon
by Apex CoVantage, LLC
Illustrations by Kate Hyland
To Orin and Theo
Contents
Preface���������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������������� ix
Student satisfaction ratings are now an important part of university life. They
were not used when I started teaching 40 years ago, but if they had my ratings
would have been poor. I had no interest in history, and my own recent experi-
ence as a student had been entirely negative. The course taught by a young
lecturer when I was an undergraduate went something like this:
There was Fechner, yeah, and he was early and then there was Wundt.
Wundt was important. Yeah, yeah, really, really important. Then there
was Watson, he was also important. He started behaviourism, like . . .
I am sure it wasn’t that bad, but that is how I remember it. My early courses
were only a little better. I taught history from a respected textbook on the his-
tory of psychology, but I had no love for the subject. Over time, things changed.
In the year I retired from the University of Plymouth, the average overall satis-
faction for my course was 4.7 out of 5, with an interest rating of 4.6. Freetext
comments from students showed that many anticipated the course to be boring
because of its title only to be surprised by how interesting they found it.
Some people find history interesting. The majority of psychology students
do not. They have come to study modern psychology. They have not come to
study history. When presented with the term ‘conceptual issues,’ most students
don’t know what it means and lack interest. However, students will find these
topics interesting if they are presented in a way that is relevant to their under-
standing of modern psychology. To be successful in teaching historical and
conceptual issues in psychology (CHIPS), the topic must be linked to existing
concepts that students find interesting. This educational principle is not new!
There are two ways of teaching CHIPS. One way is to provide a historical
introduction to each topic that makes up a psychology course. For example,
social psychology courses start with a historical introduction to social psychol-
ogy, and developmental psychology courses start with a historical introduction
to development psychology. The advantage of this approach is that it avoids the
negative ratings that can accompany CHIPS courses. There are two disadvan-
tages. One is that students continue to perceive psychology as a set of discon-
nected topics rather than a whole that has evolved over time. A second is that
this approach neglects the broader conceptual issues.
An alternative is to teach CHIPS as a separate course. If not done well,
students will find it uninteresting, but if done well, this approach can cover the
broader conceptual issues and provide a sense of psychology as a whole. In this
x ◆ Preface
book, conceptual issues are presented in the form of questions. This technique
enables students to learn with a purpose – an idea that predates the founding
of academic psychology in Leipzig (Parsons, 1873). Each chapter deals with a
different conceptual issue, with a historical introduction, and then shows how
that issue is relevant today. Many of these conceptual issues have to do with
the different assumptions of different groups of psychologists, assumptions that
have changed over time.
In writing this book I have been mindful of the fact that many students have
studied psychology, including the history of psychology, at school or in some
introductory course. Students find repetition tedious. The content of this book
is selected to avoid repetition. For example, students will have a basic under-
standing of behaviourism and cognitive psychology but be unaware that each
answers a different type of question using a different type of theory. Students
will have been introduced to some of Freud’s ideas but not know why some
are true, some are false, and some are unfalsifiable. Students will know about
the heredity-environment controversy but not that modern epigenetics shows
that it is based on a false premise, nor will they know how it is informed by the
person-situation debate. Students will know about neuroscience but have little
understanding of biopsychosocial interactionism. Students will know about
qualitative methods but not know the different assumptions of those who use
qualitative methods in different ways.
The book is also suitable for anyone wanting to gain an overall understand-
ing of the conceptual issues in psychology, and in particular for undergraduates
taking a CHIPS course on a psychology degree. There is some advantage in
having some experience of psychology before reading this book, for example
having studied psychology at an advanced level in school or equivalent. The dis-
cipline of psychology is like a jigsaw puzzle made out of many pieces, and it is
good to have at least some understanding of the pieces in order to see the picture
as a whole. Some of the conceptual ideas are more challenging than others, but
there is enough in each chapter to be of interest to all students.
This book does not provide the kind of historical detail that is more suited
for a specialist course on the history of psychology. I have selected some per-
sonal historical detail, but only where it is useful or interesting for students. I
refer to events in William James’ life to show that even famous psychologists
can have mental health problems. I refer to Watson’s sacking from his uni-
versity for the less good reason that students will find the gossip interesting. I
mention that Wundt was a nice guy, because I like nice guys. I refer to racism
in psychology because it tends to be airbrushed out, but it is relevant to the
heredity-environment controversy. I refer to personal details if it is relevant to a
person’s theory or research or because it is pertinent in some other way. There is
some historical detail along with the conceptual issues, but the historical details
are not as thorough as will be found in proper histories of psychology, written
by proper historians. I don’t mention where Wundt was born, nor reports of his
performance at school – interesting as those may be.
Preface ◆ xi
Any book reflects the personal interests of the author. My PhD was theoreti-
cal, and as a young lecturer I was instrumental in setting up the International
Society for Theoretical psychology. However, I have spent most of my working
life as a health psychologist trying to solve practical problems by using new
theories or new applications of old theories. I developed an interest in the his-
tory of psychology through teaching the subject. Readers may detect a sympa-
thy with applied psychology, a fascination with theory, and an interest in the
quirkier aspects of history.
This book is written for a specific purpose: to show how conceptual issues
that are relevant today have developed over the history of academic psychol-
ogy. My hope is that this book will help other lecturers provide interesting
and inspiring lectures, and for students to enjoy a subject that can inform
their understanding of the subject they have chosen to study: the discipline of
psychology.
1
What is science and what do
scientists do?
2 ◆ What is science and what do scientists do?
This chapter covers two topics: the philosophy of science and the psychology
of science.
How do you know if something is true? That question is particularly
pertinent in a world where news is sometimes described as ‘fake news.’ To
know whether something is true it is necessary to have criterion, a crite-
rion that can distinguish truth from falsity. But how can you tell whether
the criterion is true? The answer is that you cannot tell, because if there is
a criterion for the criterion, then you don’t know whether that criterion is
true. Knowing whether a criterion is true or not is called the problem of the
criterion. Although philosophers have discussed the problem of the criterion
for at least two thousand years, in this book two criteria for knowledge
will be assumed to be true. These are the logical criterion and the empirical
criterion.
The science of psychology, like any other science, is based on the empirical
criterion. However, the empirical criterion has a logical basis, so this chapter
starts with a brief discussion of logic.
Logic
Imagine you have a pack of cards face down in front of you. You take the first
card from the pack, and you find that it is the ace of hearts. Let me explain,
in case there is any doubt, that this is an ordinary pack of cards, and there is
only one ace of hearts in the whole pack. Now, consider the two following
statements
You, the student, will know straight away that the first sentence is false and
the second sentence true, and you know this without having to look. You
know this without empirical evidence. The reason is that you are applying a
logical rule. The logical rule is this: Something cannot be in two places at the
same time.
Logic is based on the application of rules, the rules of logic. There are
many different logical rules and few will be discussed here. However, students
will already have come across logical rules in statistics. Null hypothesis testing
is based on the assumption that a hypothesis is either true or false – but not
both true and false at the same time. Statistical tests give the probability that
a hypothesis is not true (e.g., two groups are not equal); statistical tests apply
the rule that a hypothesis can be either true or false, but not true and false. The
process of science is a logical one; it is based on following certain accepted rules
of practice.
What is science and what do scientists do? ◆ 3
If something has been observed to occur regularly in the past, the same
will occur in the future.
Inductive rules are therefore useful for predicting and controlling the world in
which we live. Inductive rules make practical sense.
In the example of the swans, induction has produced the statement ‘all
swans are white,’ but is this statement true? In any group of psychology stu-
dents, there will be some who know that not all swans are white – swans in (or
originating from) Australia are black. So, after observing some black swans, it
is possible to conclude that the original law – all swans are white – is false; it is
now possible to write a new statement:
Again, it is possible to ask, is it possible to prove this statement true, in the sense
that is known to be 100% true? The answer is no. It can never be proved with
100% certainty that all swans are either black or white as there may be some
hiding away somewhere in the undergrowth that are not black or white. You
may be interested to learn that the statement ‘all swans are black or white’ is
in fact false. The reason is that in a far-away galaxy, on the planet Zog, there
Naughty green swan hiding from scientists on planet Zog.
What is science and what do scientists do? ◆ 5
are a group of swans that are pink with blue spots. You don’t believe me? You
cannot be sure that there are no pink and blue swans any more than I can be
sure that there are.
OK, so now it is possible to generate another rule:
This rule can be proved true, but it cannot be proved false. The same applies to
the following statement:
It is always possible that there are some green swans hiding away somewhere –
not necessarily on the planet Zog, so this statement can never be shown to be
false.
From a psychological perspective, the statement that ‘some swans are white’
is a lot less interesting than the statement ‘all swans are white.’ Imagine being
told this:
This conclusion would be true, but it is also obvious and therefore uninterest-
ing. Thus, the type of inductive generalisation is important. One criticism of
the assumption that science is based on induction is that scientists do not col-
lect facts randomly. They collect the facts on the basis of ‘ideas’ about what is
interesting. The collected facts should be important or interesting in some way.
Some swans are white is a lot less informative than all swans are white – even
though the latter is false.
Has the simple fact of my dropping the keys proved the theory of gravity? The
answer is no. Even if I keep dropping my keys and collect a sizeable pool of
data supporting the theory, the theory of gravity can never be proved to be true,
because there is an alternative explanation. The reason that keys keep falling
to earth is nothing to do with this strange thing called gravity. There is a much
simpler explanation. It is caused by a gravity monster who sits at the centre
of the earth and waves its tail. Whenever the gravity monster waves its tail, it
attracts objects to its tail. That is the real reason why things fall to earth. And
the gravity monster is always waving its tail. Or is it?
The reality is that when data confirm a theory – i.e., when singular occur-
rences are consistent with the prediction of a theory – it is always possible that
the same data can be explained by another theory. It is always possible that
some data will be found in the future that cannot be explained by the theory.
Therefore, theories can be confirmed but never proved to be true. Data do not
prove theories. Scientists try to rule out competing hypotheses by setting up
experiments where the competing hypotheses make different predictions. In
principle, it takes only one observation that cannot be explained by the theory
to show that a theory is false. Of course, as more and more data of different
kinds are found to support the theory, the more the theory is corroborated
by those data. So, some theories can be well confirmed, but they can never be
proved to be true.
Popper suggested that science proceeds through a series of ‘conjectures and
refutations’ – which is the title of one his books (Popper, 1963). Scientists have
a hypothesis or conjecture. They test the hypothesis and for a while the data
What is science and what do scientists do? ◆ 7
confirm (but never prove) the theory. Eventually data are found that falsify the
theory and so it is necessary to develop a new conjecture or hypothesis. Science
proceeds by a series of conjectures and refutations; each time the conjecture
becomes more ‘true’ than the conjecture before. In practice, scientific advance
is not quite the elegant process suggested by Popper. Disconfirming evidence
usually leads to changes rather than the rejection of a theory, or simply rejection
of the disconfirming evidence.
The key difference between the earlier inductive view of science and the
deductive/falsification model proposed by Popper is that the latter involves
theories, and theories provide explanations as well as predictions. The theory
provides an explanation of why something happens. The explanations have one
key advantage over predictions based on inductive generalisations. They allow
novel predictions. The ability of theories to make novel predictions is not some-
thing that is automatic. Humans are needed to make novel predictions. Science
is a creative activity involving the insight of people.
God exists.
What kind of evidence is there that God does not exist? It is possible to cite
miracles and other kinds of evidence suggesting that God exists, but there is no
type of evidence that could prove – i.e., show with 100% certainty – that God
does not exist. So, the statement that ‘God exists’ is therefore unfalsifiable, and
the statement is metaphysical rather than scientific. It is also, note, impossible
to falsify the statement that ‘somewhere there are swans with pink spots on a
green background.’ Statements that, on logical grounds, cannot be shown to be
false are not scientific.
it rains a lot) and you want to do your washing and hang it on the line to dry.
Consider the following two statements:
It will be dry on one day and only one day next week.
It will be dry on Wednesday and only on Wednesday next week.
Both statements are falsifiable. If it doesn’t rain or if it rains on more than one
day, then both statements are false. Both are scientific rather than metaphysi-
cal. Both show that washing is possible on one day next week. But the second
sentence is a lot more useful in helping you decide when to do your washing.
The second sentence is also more falsifiable, in the sense that it is more likely
to be wrong if weather is random. The second sentence gives a more powerful
prediction.
Popper distinguishes between strong theories that are highly falsifiable
and weak theories that are falsifiable in principle, but difficult to show wrong.
Note that the degree of falsifiability has nothing to do with whether the theory
is actually false or not, which is something that is determined through obser-
vation. The strength of a theory is something that can be evaluated without
observation. The degree of falsifiability or strength of the theory is an ‘internal’
property of a theory and not an ‘external’ property, which is a theory strength
that can be determined independently of the observation that tests. Strong
theories are easily shown to be false, but if they are not shown false then they
provide more useful information than weak theories that are less likely to be
shown false.
Some theories are falsifiable but so weak – so difficult to show false – that
they are not very useful. The strength and therefore usefulness of psychological
theories is something that will be discussed later in this book. One of the criti-
cisms against Freud’s theory is that it is almost completely unfalsifiable. Others
have argued that his theory is in fact unfalsifiable, and therefore metaphysical.
Both arguments cannot be true, but they certainly need consideration in relation
to both psychoanalytic and other theories in psychology.
next so long as it has happened in the past. Theories enable prediction of things
that have not happened in the past.
One way in which theories differ is whether they make quantitative predic-
tions. Compare the following two statements
Effect size
The degree of difference is indicated by the statistic called effect size. A small
effect size between two groups is more likely to be found to be statistically
significant if the sample size is large than if it is small. Hence, studies that
employ very large samples will reveal effects that are statistically significant,
but may have little practical significance. Guidelines for psychological jour-
nals increasingly require authors to quote effect size along with statistical sig-
nificance. This information is useful as it provides quantitative information.
What is science and what do scientists do? ◆ 11
randomly assigned to receive the drug or a placebo and their performance com-
pared, statistically, to see if the probability of the drug and placebo having the
same effect is sufficiently low (e.g., p < 0.05%) for the alternative hypothesis to
be accepted. Statistics are used to test whether a difference occurs or not, not to
test the degree of difference.
The story of the discovery of penicillin provides one possible insight into the creative
process of hypothesis formation and the relationship between theory and data.
Alexander Fleming, a Scottish researcher, was growing bacteria on a petri
dish. He came back from a two week holiday in 1928 to find that one of his
dishes had been contaminated with what looked like mould, and no bacteria
were growing where the mould had contaminated the petri dish. One pos-
sible reaction would be to say “bother, my petri dish has been contaminated.”
12 ◆ What is science and what do scientists do?
will die. Common sense tells us that before the box is opened, the cat must
be either dead or alive. The principle of superposition says that before the
box is opened the cat is both dead and alive. Neils Bohr, one of the fathers
of quantum mechanics, said “If you are not shocked by quantum mechan-
ics, you don’t understand it.” If we experienced the world like it is in the
quantum world, perhaps our logical rules would be different! So logical
rules are based on observations about the universe in which we live. Sci-
ence is based on observation but the rules of science come, ultimately, from
observation as well.
Falsification in psychology
Students reading this book might like to ask themselves what psychologi-
cal theories have been shown to be false. The issue of falsification is related
to the crisis of replication described later in this chapter.
However, when it comes to research paradigms, scientists are even more protec-
tive of what they have assumed in the past to be true. No one wants to find that
they have invested years of their careers carrying out research – or practice –
based on assumptions that are incorrect. So when paradigm shifts are proposed,
there can be strong resistance from scientists working in the older paradigm.
New paradigms are met with two kinds of response: enthusiasm from those
who believe that the new paradigm provides a novel solution, and hostility from
those who don’t. If the latter camp is stronger, the new paradigm takes longer
to become established.
What is science and what do scientists do? ◆ 17
There are two points to note about Parisano’s criticism of what is now uni-
versally accepted as true – the heart does actually pump blood. The first is
that the critics of the new paradigm deny that a pulse can be heard there. This
point illustrates a general principle known in the philosophy of science as
18 ◆ What is science and what do scientists do?
Here are two examples that illustrate this point. Both examples come from
theories that inform current practice:
In both cases there is evidence that throws doubt against accepted and domi-
nant paradigms. The serotoninergic hypothesis is the basis for a multi-million-
pound drugs industry and CBT provides the accepted rationale for the funding
of talking therapies. This is not the place to provide evidence for or against the
various positions – which are robustly supported by both sides. Students may
wish to do this independently. The argument presented here is simply that the
issue of evidence and falsification of scientific theories is by no means a simple
logical process. Science involves humans. Humans are messy.
psychology is that associated with the eminent British psychologist, Cyril Burt.
Burt published data supporting the idea that there was a substantial heredity
component to intelligence. In a study of 53 monozygotic twins reared apart,
Burt reported a correlation of 0.77 between the intelligence scores of twins
(Burt, 1966). These results were interpreted to support the view that intelligence
was largely inherited. Shortly after Burt’s death in 1971, Kamin (1974) and then
others (e.g., Hearnshaw, 1979) published critiques, arguing that the data had
been made up and that the research assistants Burt had cited as co-authors did
not exist.
Others came to the defence of Burt, the ‘missing’ research assistants were
found, and it was pointed out that data supporting similar correlations to those
reported by Burt were replicated by independent researchers (Rushton, 2002).
In 1980 the British Psychological Society condemned Burt as a fraud, but in
1992 revised this judgement, writing:
To his defenders, Burt was a good scientist who did not fake his data. Others
take a different view.
Burt is not the only famous psychologist subsequently accused of creating
fraudulent data. Hans Eysenck was a famous psychologist, best known for his
work on personality – he developed the Eysenck Personality Inventory. Eysenck
argued that personality was a major cause of fatal diseases such as cancer and
that the link between smoking and cancer was not because smoking caused
cancer, but because both correlated with a cancer-prone personality. Eysenck
collaborated with another researcher, Grossarth-Maticek, and together they
published cohort data showing an extraordinarily high association between the
cancer-prone personality and cancer, and published experimental data show-
ing that psychological therapy, either delivered through a therapist or through
bibliotherapy, had a substantial effect of reducing cancers in those with a
cancer-prone personality. That this research was funded by the tobacco industry
was an early indicator that it might be flawed and at worst fraudulent. Criti-
cisms and analysis of this case have recently been made public (Marks, 2019;
Pelosi, 2019). The story has further to go.
Burt and Eysenck were senior scientists. For junior scientists, personal
ambition can be a motivator for fraudulent activity (Steen, 2011). There is
increasing competitiveness in science between researchers competing for scarce
jobs and scarce research grants. University appointment policies and tenure are
often linked to publications. In a profession where time is often scarce, there
can be a temptation to short circuit the arduous business of collecting data
22 ◆ What is science and what do scientists do?
Essay questions
1 What is the logic of induction and deduction and how are they used in
scientific enquiry?
2 What is a paradigm and what is a paradigm shift? Illustrate your answer
with examples with particular reference to the attitudes of those involved.
3 Focussing on just one of these two individuals, did Burt or Eysenck
commit scientific misconduct?
2
How did psychology become
a science and what kind of science
did it become?
26 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
When asked, most people today would say that psychology is a science, and, by
implication, a science like any other natural science. Psychology certainly fulfils
the logical criterion of science, that of falsifiability, described in the last chapter.
However, in the distant past psychology was not viewed as a science like any
other, and even in the recent past it was viewed with some suspicion. When I
was considering which degree to study in 1967, I was advised to study a ‘proper
science’ like physiology rather than psychology – advice I ignored. Going back
150 years, psychology was not considered a science at all. Why was this and
how did these changes come about? Not all psychologists think that psychology
should be a science like any other natural science, and these other approaches
will be described in Chapter 9.
with the paranormal was associated, at least in the mind of the general public,
with non-science rather than science.
The society for psychical research was formed in Cambridge, England, in 1882
to investigate claims of the paranormal. The British Psychological Society was
formed in London in 1901.
The first psychology laboratory, given the name ‘new psychology’ by Wundt
to distinguish it from the old, came about from an integration of three strands
of thinking – it is too much to call them research programmes. These are
(a) developments from sensory physiology that provided a scientific approach
to the study of sensation, (b) contributions from the philosophy of mind that
showed that higher mental processes could be studied, and (c) medical findings
that higher or cognitive processes were linked in some way to the brain.
Weber systematically measured the sensitivity of the skin across the whole of the
body, using an adjustable compass, which was given the rather dignified name
of an aesthesiometer (Weber, 1834/1978). He made a number of interesting
30 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
observations, for example, that we are less sensitive if the two compass points
are placed in the direction of the limb rather than across it. Having started with
the sensation of touch, Weber then went on to study the two-point threshold in
other sensory modalities, including weights, lengths of lines, and pitches.
In studying the sensory modality of weight Weber asked a person to com-
pare the weight of two objects (he got people to do this sequentially using the
same hand) and tell him if they seemed the same or one was heavier than the
other. The just noticeable difference (JND) was the smallest difference in weight
between the two objects that led to a person saying they were different.
Weber found that, irrespective of the sensory modality tested, there was a
relationship between a ‘just noticeable difference’ (or JND) between two stimuli
and the magnitude of the stimuli. Imagine a kilo bag of sugar, and another bag
that is 1.5 kilos. It is easy to tell the bags of sugar are different from their heavi-
ness (note they weigh different amounts and the sensation is also different).
Now imagine a 50 kilo sack of sugar, and another sack 50.5 kilos in weight.
It is now impossible to tell the sacks apart – they appear equally heavy. Weber
noticed that the ratio of the JND to the stimulus intensity was approximately
constant, irrespective of the stimulus intensity. So, for example, if the JND is 0.2
kg when the stimulus intensity is 1 kg (0.2/1 = 0.2) then the JND for a stimulus
intensity of 50 kg is likely to be 1 kg (1/50 = 0.2).
Weber studied the JNDs in other sensory modalities and found that the ratio
of JND to stimulus intensity was always approximately constant, though the
ratio differed between sensory modalities. Although the constants were differ-
ent all sensory modalities could be described by an equation
Weber’s family
Weber came from an academic family. His younger brother was a famous
professor of physics. Measurement was a family business!
S = k log R,
Which do you find most beautiful? Make a decision before going on to read
the next sentence. The underlying hypothesis of ‘the golden ratio’ or ‘golden
section’ is that rectangles where the ratio of the short to long side is 1 to 1.62
32 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
are considered most beautiful. Did you find the middle square above the most
beautiful?
Fechner developed methods used in psychophysics by asking people to
compare two rectangles and say which they thought more beautiful. His results
confirmed that the golden ratio is indeed 1 to 1.62. Later researchers, however,
showed that Fechner’s results were anomalous and that preference for a par-
ticular ratio depends on the method used (Höge, 1997). Despite later criticism,
Fechner is looked on as the father of experimental aesthetics.
There is one final point which is important to note in relation to Weber’s law
and Fechner’s law. Both of these laws make quantitative predictions. That is,
they present a theory where the prediction is not qualitative, but quantitative.
The theories do not only assert that a JND increases with the magnitude of the
stimulus. The theories predict precisely how much the JND should increase.
Weber and Fechner did not use statistical testing. (They did not have to attend
stats classes as students!) It is only later that statistics were used in psychology
to test qualitative predictions (see Chapter 1). Why did Weber and Fechner
propose quantitative theories? The answer is they were simply copying what
was done in physics at the time. Weber’s brother was a physicist. The theories
of physics in the 19th century were based on mathematical equations that
provided quantitative prediction. Weber and Fechner created theories just as
physicists were doing at the time.
worked on philosophy in his spare time. His ‘day job’ was that of a practising
physician. Although medicine was still at an early stage, Hartley would have
been well aware of the study of anatomy and pathology and the findings that
the body functioned as a kind of mechanical system (see Chapter 1). Hartley
was one of the earliest people to suggest that the brain and nervous system were
connected to thought. In earlier years, the brain had been dismissed as at best
some kind of cooling device as the soul or mind was assumed to reside in the
heart, not the brain.
Hartley believed that the brain, spinal cord, and nerves contained particles
that vibrated. He suggested that moderate vibration caused pleasure and large
vibration pain. Hartley’s assumption that the brain contained vibrating particles
arose from his observation of positive after-images. Hartley had noticed that if
he looked fixedly at a candle, and then closed his eyes, the image of the candle
remained. He assumed that this was because the vibrating particles continued
to vibrate for a short while after the cessation of a stimulus (Hartley, 1749).
Although Hartley’s theory is wrong, it adopts the correct metatheory that men-
tal events are the consequence of physical events. Theories can be wrong, even
though the metatheory is correct.
Hartley also believed, like others before him, that the mind of the newborn
baby was blank and ideas came from experience. Much of his writing is about
‘the association of ideas.’ He believed that ideas became associated with other
ideas to form new ideas. The result is that the ideas a person has are not just
the result of the experiences the person has, but from how the thoughts com-
bine. This emphasis on combination of ideas is given the label ‘associationist
philosophy.’
A blank sheet
The idea that the mind of the newborn baby is a blank sheet – or tabula
rasa – was first suggested by the philosopher John Locke (1631–1704).
The alternative view is that certain ideas – such as fear of spiders – are
‘programmed’ into the body. Thus, the tabula rasa hypothesis is relevant
to the hereditary-environment controversy (see Chapter 7). Those sup-
porting a tabula rasa interpretation place emphasis on the environment,
not heredity.
The idea that thoughts combine to form new thoughts was not accepted by all
philosophers. James Mill (1773–1836), best known at the time as a historian,
suggested an alternative in his book, Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human
Mind, in 1829. Mill suggested that the mind was a kind of machine and ideas
came into that machine and were fixed in that machine. Note that whereas
34 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
Hartley was using a biological model to inform his understanding, Mill used
mechanism.
There were therefore two positions being presented by associationist phi-
losophers. Hartley’s view that thoughts combined to form novel thoughts was
called the ‘coalescence’ hypothesis. Mill’s view that thoughts always remained
separate was called the ‘brick wall hypothesis.’
James Mill’s son John Stuart Mill (1806–1873) (named after James Mill’s
benefactor, Sir John Stuart) agreed with his father’s brick wall hypothesis, but
changed his mind, largely because of evidence from chemistry. The science of
chemistry showed that, when combined, chemical substances could produce
entirely new chemical substances. Copper and zinc are both soft metals, neither
as strong as bronze, which is formed when zinc and copper are combined.
The coalescence and brick wall hypotheses reappear in several different forms
in the history of psychology. The gestalt movement is based on assumptions of
coalescence. Behaviourism is based on the atomistic assumption of the brick
wall hypothesis. Like many opposed views, the truth is neither exclusively one
nor exclusively the other.
differences in the 19th century – were used to define disease. Each disease had a
different abnormality or pathophysiology. It was therefore natural for doctors
to also look for differences in the brains between patients and those who died
of natural causes.
Pierre Broca (1824–1880), who was chief of surgery at a hospital near
Paris, had a 51-year-old patient who could understand everything said to him,
but could never speak beyond saying “tan, tan” or when frustrated “Sacré
nom de Dieu” (Sacred name of God). When the patient died, Broca carried out
an autopsy and found an area missing (a lesion) in the frontal lobe – a part of
the brain subsequently called Broca’s area – which is responsible for language
(Sagan, 1979).
About ten years after Broca’s discovery, the German neurologist Carl Wer-
nicke (1848–1904) reported a patient fluent but with meaningless speech. Wer-
nicke found, on autopsy, damage to the top part of the left temporal lobe, the
part of the brain that connects speech with meaning. Broca and Wernicke had
both demonstrated localisation of function, i.e., the idea that different parts of
the brain do different things. These findings provided detail to the increasingly
accepted view that the brain was responsible for thought. If mental life is caused
by the brain, and the brain can be studied through natural science, then it fol-
lows that mental life can also be studied through the methods of natural science.
There is one other case that is so famous that it appears in many introduc-
tory psychology texts. Wundt also referred to this case in one of his early text-
books, and that is the case of Phineas Gage. The case is shown in the box here
for those who have not come across it.
Later beginnings
Many textbooks on the history of psychology, as well as sources on the inter-
net, state that Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) was the founding father of modern
psychology. Why is that? After all, Weber had been conducting psychological
experiments many years earlier and Wundt was a student of Herman Ludwig
von Helmholtz (1821–1894) who, like Weber, conducted studies in the physi-
ology of sensation. Furthermore, as will become clear later, the discipline of
scientific psychology envisaged by Wundt is very different from that of today.
There are two explanations.
Students should decide for themselves whether Wundt should be considered the
father of psychology at the end of this chapter.
Helmholtz
Herman Ludwig von Helmholtz (1821–1894), like Weber before him,
studied sensory psychophysiology. One of his achievements was to mea-
sure the speed of conduction of nerve impulses, both for motor nerves and
for sensory nerves. Helmholtz made significant contributions to the field
of vision, developing an early theory of colour perception. He believed
that illusions occur when visual conditions are not normal, but that these
illusions can provide insight into the normal functioning of the eye, an
idea adopted by much later researchers in the field of perception(Gregory,
2007). Helmholtz developed some interesting optical instruments such
as optometers, ophthalmometers, and ophthalmoscopes that are used by
scientists today to investigate the function of the eye (Pearce, 2009; Wade,
1994; Wade & Finger, 2001).
Wundt developed an interest in the link between physiology and sensory percep-
tion while at Heidelberg (Bringmann, 1975). He published a short monograph
on sense perception in 1862 (Wundt, 1862), publishing his book Principles
of Physiological Psychology in 1874 (Wundt, 1874/1996). It should be noted
that although this book includes the term psychology in the title, most of it is
about the physiology of sensory nerves, but with a section at the end devoted to
conation – i.e., to higher mental thought. Wundt showed how the experimental
method used in the study of physiology could be applied to psychology.
Although Wundt was developing a career in medicine and physiology linked
to psychology, he was also interested in philosophy. His skill and understanding
of philosophy developed independently of his employment in Heidelberg.
In 1874, Wundt accepted the post of professor in inductive philosophy at
the University of Zurich (note the term induction – see Chapter 1). He remained
at Zurich for only one year, because in 1875 he accepted the post of Professor
of Philosophy at Leipzig. As a professor of philosophy, Wundt published an
important work on Logic (Wundt, 1880–1883) followed in 1886 by a work on
38 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
Ethics (Wundt, 1886). At Leipzig, Wundt was at the same university as Weber
and Fechner, and was able to put his plan for a discipline of scientific psychol-
ogy into practice.
We know about Wundt as a person from the writings of others. Elwood
Worcester attended Wundt’s lectures in Leipzig and provided this description
in his own autobiography (Worcester, 1932). He describes Wundt as follows:
So, Wundt was an excellent lecturer, and he was an excellent lecturer not only
in psychology but also philosophy.
or folk psychology that studied culture, rituals, religion, and so on, and which
did not use scientific methods – i.e., the experiment.
Note that Wundt’s belief that there should be two different kinds of psychol-
ogy is a metatheoretical assumption (see Chapter 1). No evidence is presented
and there can be none. Wundt is suggesting that there are two entirely different
paradigms of psychology. In one paradigm, there is active manipulation of a
variable by an experimenter. The psychologist makes something happen and
observes the result. In the other paradigm, the psychologist simply observes
what happens and thinks about what is seen. The former is defined as experi-
mental psychology. The latter is not.
Wundt promoted the discipline of scientific (i.e., experimental) psychol-
ogy at the University of Leipzig. One thing he insisted upon was that study
of the paranormal was outside the field of his new psychology, because the
paranormal was associated with non-science. The paranormal was not stud-
ied in his institute for experimental psychology. He started a journal with
the title (translated from the original German) of Psychological Research,
because there was an existing journal with the title Journal of Psychology,
that was devoted to parapsychology. Wundt also defined psychology as a
pure rather than applied science for reasons that will become clear in the
next chapter.
natural sciences in that there was access to immediate experience, not just medi-
ate experience as in the case of natural sciences (Bringmann & Tweney, 1980).
As the historian Van Rappard (2004, p. 146) has pointed out:
The natural sciences study the objects of experience abstracting from the
subject and, since their perspective is mediated by this abstraction they
are called mediate. The significance of psychology may be seen in the
fact that that it nullifies this abstraction and thus studies experience in
its non-mediated reality.
(Van Rappard, 2004, p. 146)
Immediate experience
A good way of characterising the difference between mediate and immedi-
ate experience is by examining the technique used by artists to paint repre-
sentational paintings. Suppose an artist wants to paint a yellow brick just
as it would look like in a photograph. The artist has to look at the brick
not as a brick but as a series of yellow rectangular shapes of slightly dif-
ferent colours. The artist then creates the impression of a brick by drawing
exactly what the eye sees. The artist does not say “I am drawing the feel-
ing of brickness” – at least not for representational art. The artist just has
to draw the immediate experience of the colours and shapes without any
interpretation of what those colours and shapes mean. However, artists
often do not just try to represent things as they appear visually. They also
want to draw the feeling of ‘brickness’ – something about the way a brick
feels rather just looks – and they do this either with abstract art or art that
differs from the photograph in some way. It is the difference between the
photograph and what the artist draws that captures the mediated experi-
ence of the brick, rather than immediate experience that is found in the
photography.
How did psychology become a science? ◆ 41
Goals of psychology
Wundt used his form of introspection to achieve three goals of psychology.
First, to analyse the contents of consciousness into their basic elements; second,
to discover how these elements are connected; and, third, to determine the
laws that underlie the connections between elements (Boring, 1929). Wundt’s
approach to psychology was consistent with the 19th-century view that science
should be data driven. This purely inductive approach to hypothesis generation
does not generate explanatory theories. For Wundt, scientific psychology was a
matter of observing and cataloguing the contents of the mind. Wundt promoted
the idea of psychology as a science in a world where psychology and science
were viewed differently from what they are today.
Völkerpsychologie
One mistake often made in describing Wundt was that his interest was lim-
ited to the rather narrow confines of what he called experimental psychology,
44 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
namely, the study of low level perceptual processes. This mistake arose from
using Tichtener’s account of Wundt. Edward Tichtener (1867–1927) was a stu-
dent of Wundt who moved to America, and did not agree with Völkerpsycholo-
gie; he therefore didn’t report this aspect of Wundt’s work. Some of the earlier
histories of psychology relied on Tichtener’s account of Wundt. In fact, Wundt
had wide-ranging interests in other aspects of psychology, but he believed that
higher mental processes could not be studied experimentally – i.e., from his
perspective, scientifically. Evidence for his interest in this ‘other’ psychology
is provided by work carried out in the last two decades of his life, when he
wrote the ten-volume Völkerpsychologie (Wundt, 1904) The content of these
volumes illustrates the topics Wundt studied. They consisted of two volumes on
language, two on myth or religion, two on society, and one each on art, culture
and law. Wundt’s Völkerpsychologie would now be recognised as more similar
to anthropology or ethnography than to psychology.
Wundt believed that, when trying to understand the subject matter of Völk-
erpsychologie, the most basic unit of thought could not be expressed by a word
or linguistic term but was a “general impression”(Gesamtvorstelling). That is,
this subject matter could not be explored with the scientific method because
it required an element of intuitive insight (Sabat, 1979). It was the intuitive
insight that Wundt rejected as unscientific (Greenwood, 2003). Later psycholo-
gists, including those using qualitative methods (Chapter 8) and humanistic
psychologists (Chapter 9) showed how it is indeed possible to study intuitive
insight scientifically. Although Wundt is often described as the founding father
of experimental psychology, in his autobiography, published in 1920, Wundt
wrote that Völkerpsychologie was the most satisfying part of his academic life
(Wong, 2009).
Russia. Most universities now have psychology departments, though the psy-
chology taught today is very different from that taught 100 years ago. The staff
are also different. Then psychology was dominated by men. Now psychology
is predominantly a female discipline – look around you during the next lecture.
Psyche was a female Greek goddess, so perhaps we shouldn’t be surprised.
Summary
In the 19th century, the term psychology was not associated with science. Psy-
chology, the study of the soul, was associated with the paranormal. Measure-
ment was a feature of 19th-century science. During the middle of that century,
sensation was measured in a variety of ways and called sensory psychophysiol-
ogy or psychophysics. Advances in medicine and earlier work in philosophy was
combined by Wundt with the emerging psychophysics to create what he called
the new psychology. Wundt’s goal was to make the new psychology a respect-
able science, and he therefore restricted psychology in ways that were consistent
with views of science at the time, rejecting the study of higher mental processes
as unscientific. Wundt wrote books on what he considered non-scientific, folk
psychology whose subject matter is consistent with the broader remit of some
of psychology today but is now treated scientifically. Students from around
the world studied psychology with Wundt in Germany, though many rejected
Wundt’s view of psychology and went on to study higher mental processes and
behaviour. Wundt made psychology a respectable subject for scientists to study
by being aware of what would be perceived as scientific or not in Europe at the
time. He was an excellent and much respected lecturer, but psychology today is
very different from what he proposed.
Should Wundt be considered the father of psychology? All the reports given
by Wundt’s students are of a very kind and generous human being. It is nice to
have people like that as the father of a discipline. But might that be a reinter-
pretation of history imposed by people looking for a good story?
46 ◆ How did psychology become a science?
Essay questions
1 How did 19th-century science influence the way Wundt defined his new
psychology?
2 Discuss arguments for and against the statement that Wundt was the
founding father of psychology.
3 What is the difference between association and apperception? Illustrate
your answer with examples that are relevant to modern psychology.
3
How did psychology become an applied
science and what is the relationship
between applied and non-applied
psychology today?
48 ◆ Becoming an applied science
Let us begin with terminology: pure science versus applied science; basic science
versus applied science, fundamental science versus applied science. These words
have different connotations. Pure science is noble and good. If applied is the
opposite of pure, then applied must be dirty and bad. Basic science implies that
this is something that must be done first – something that is done before applied
science. Fundamental science implies the research deals with more general or
important issues than the (potentially dirty) applied science. Pure, basic, and
fundamental. All three words reflect different attitudes of those who want to
make this distinction.
from colleges, schools and technical institutes to within the university system.
Art colleges, colleges of agriculture, nursing schools, physiotherapy schools etc.
are now departments or schools within universities. Physiotherapy became an
all graduate entry profession in the UK in 1992, and nursing training became
degree level in 2000.
Wundt insisted that psychology should be a pure rather than an applied
topic because, by doing so, it would form part of the higher status university
life, rather than the lower status technical college life. If Wundt had suggested
that psychology should be studied in order to solve problems, his psychology
would not have fitted the ethos needed for a university science.
The first undergraduate course with the title Psychology was taught at
Harvard University in 1872 as part of a philosophy degree (Coon, 2000) –
note, this was five years before Wundt started teaching psychology at Leipzig.
However, that early psychology course at Harvard was not scientific psychol-
ogy. James had the same problem as Wundt in trying to make psychology a
scientific discipline, but his approach to the problem was different. In Amer-
ica, science solved problems. Psychology was a science because it too could
solve problems.
William James came from a wealthy liberal, intellectual, and artistic fam-
ily who travelled widely. James was educated at schools in Europe and in
the USA. His younger brother became a famous novelist (Henry James). The
young James was skilled in drawing and painting and, when young, decided to
be an artist. For unknown reasons (possibly parental pressure) he gave up this
career. Instead, he enrolled in a course in science and then studied medicine,
graduating with an MD in 1869. Throughout his schooling James suffered
from bouts of depression, gastric problems, and what was described at the
time as neurasthenia – now known as ME/CFS or chronic fatigue syndrome.
He considered suicide on many occasions. After being awarded his MD, he
lived at home due to illness for three years, taking up a lecturing post in 1872
at Harvard (Myers, 2001).
James was an excellent university teacher; he enjoyed the process of helping
a student develop, and his interest in psychology developed based on his own
personal experience and the experience of teaching others (Croce, 1999). James’
liberal education included philosophy. He was appointed assistant professor in
philosophy in 1880 at Harvard University, and full professor in philosophy in
1885. By 1889 he had changed his title to professor of psychology, changing it
back to professor of philosophy again in 1897. The 1926 Encyclopaedia Bri-
tannica describes James as a philosopher, though later interpretation is that he
remained a psychologist throughout his career (Taylor, 1996). James’ personal
life almost certainly influenced his view of psychology. He suffered illness even
when he was well established as an academic and published a paper in 1895
with the title “Is life worth living?” (James, 1895).
Throughout his life James was plagued with self-doubt (see James,
1895) and felt that his ability to write was poor. In fact, an internet search
of ‘quotes of William James’ will show how many well-written and sensible
suggestions he makes. James’ best known work is his The Principles of Psy-
chology, published in 1890. This book summarises much of what was known
of psychology at the time. However, James noted that people he talked to
were particularly interested in how psychology could be applied to problems
in life, and he wrote a much shorter book focussing on application that was
published in 1899. This book is based on lectures he gave to teachers, and
has the title Talks to Teachers on Psychology. Much of the early practical
application of psychology in America was on education and James was a
pioneer in this regard.
Becoming an applied science ◆ 51
Our sensations are here to attract us or deter us, our memories to warn
or encourage us, our feelings to impel, and our thoughts to restrain our
behaviour, so that on the whole we may prosper and our days be long
in the land.
(James, 1899/1922, p. 24)
(Note the biblical ring to this quote – James’ father was an eccentric
theologian.)
You may take a horse to water, but you cannot make him drink; and so
you may take a child to the schoolroom, but you cannot make him learn
the new things you wish to impart, except by soliciting him in the first
instance by something which natively makes him react.
(James, 1899/1922, p. 39)
James provides some practical suggestions about how to go about this. Chil-
dren have a ‘native reaction’ to movement and change. So the teacher should
move about and introduce novelty into the lesson. James states that voluntary
attention is of short duration, so the teacher should engage with the pupil by
introducing new ideas that are of interest.
What ideas are of interest to the child? James believed that learning was
based on the association of new ideas with ideas that are already established.
Therefore, learning is most effective if the new material can be linked with
the old. This idea of learning by association has been part of the earlier the-
ory of the German educationalist Johann Herbart (1776–1841), which was
Becoming an applied science ◆ 53
acknowledged by James – note that Herbart does not feature in the early Ger-
man psychology as education was separate from psychology.
When we wish to fix a new thing in either our own mind or a pupil’s,
our conscious effort should not be so much to impress and retain as to
connect it with something else already there.
(James, 1899/1922, p. 143, emphasis in original)
James argues against ‘cramming’ as a way of teaching children. New ideas are
most effectively retained if they are associated with many rather than few ideas.
Therefore the most effective learning is that which is done gradually and where
numerous connections are made with the new material. This principle is now
accepted in modern educational theory and has been developed in several ways,
for example, problem-based learning.
Quoting experimental work by Herman Ebbinghaus (1850–1909), James
shows that forgetting occurs more rapidly at first, but the rate of forgetting
decreases with time. James used words such as ‘recency’ and ‘immediate mem-
ory,’ both of which will be familiar to modern students of cognitive psychology.
James showed that although a pupil may not be able to recall something, the
memory trace was not completely absent as memorisation would be faster the
second time. Recognition can occur even if recall does not – which is why exam-
inations (James points out) may not be the most effective form of assessment.
Finally, James provided advice about the will. If a child wants to do some-
thing that the adult disapproves of, then rather than inhibit the ‘native reaction’
of the child, the adult should find a substitution for that native reaction. This
substitute should be something else that the child is interested in. Modern child
rearing advice is similar – distraction is a very effective technique for managing
young children as parents soon find out.
From where did James get the advice he gives to teachers? Part of it is based
on his theory of habit, which he developed from the observation of people. Some
is based on a theory of memory, partially supported by research carried out by
others. What James does not do is test whether his recommendations actually
work. James’ recommendation that teachers should move around when teach-
ing was not based on any evidence and is not supported by any subsequent
research – even though teachers’ non-verbal behaviour is important (Gorham,
1988). James did not test his theory on children. His recommendations are
based on theoretical speculation, albeit sensible theoretical speculation. His rec-
ommendations are based on deduction from theory but without the subsequent
testing that is required in scientific research.
the time it was founded in 1889. While still at John Hopkins University, Hall
founded the American Journal of Psychology in 1887 and after moving to Clark
University founded the American Psychological Association in 1892.
All our prejudices and all our convictions work as such suggestions.
(Münsterberg, 1908, p. 190)
As part of his study into detecting lies, Münsterberg showed that safe words
tended to produce the same association when repeated, dangerous words pro-
duced associations that tended to change.
Münsterberg concluded his studies with principles that remain true in
forensic psychology today:
Scott made two contributions to industrial psychology, the first being that
he was one of the pioneers of advertising (Scott, 1911). Scott believed that
“consumers are not rational beings and can be easily influenced” and so set
about finding ways of influencing consumers. Part of this was through adver-
tisements that provide a direct suggestion to purchase a product. For example,
he developed a successful advertisement that had a picture of Pears Soap, and
under which was written in large letters “Use Pears Soap.” He also introduced
advertisements aimed at women that had an emotional component as he felt
that feelings of sympathy were more likely to be responded to by women.
Finally, he introduced the idea of return coupons. Consumers were able to
return a coupon for a small free sample. Scott argued that this required positive
action on the part of the consumer, and so was likely to generate a positive pur-
chase at a future date. The idea of return coupons became particularly popular
in the 1960s – Green Shield stamps were introduced in 1958, and unused ones
are now collectors’ items.
The second contribution Scott made to industrial psychology was in the
field of personnel testing. Scott was interested in finding ways of distinguishing
good from bad employees, and developed his own way of researching this ques-
tion. He asked businessmen to rate their employees in terms of their usefulness,
and then gave the employees questionnaire-based tests. The tests were similar
to intelligence tests, except that they were administered in groups. Scott found
that some of the items in his tests distinguished the good from bad employees
(as rated by the employers), and then employed these items for his tests of
personnel selection. Like James, Scott used psychological theory to make rec-
ommendations without testing them, but like Witmer, he developed methods
of assessment. Psychological assessment was to become a major factor in the
development of psychology as a science in the early 20th century.
The first test produced by Binet and Simon was produced in 1905 with
revisions in 1908 and 1911, the year Binet died (Binet, 1903, 1909/1975).
Binet introduced about 30 different tests to measure mental faculties, and these
included a kind of testing of higher mental facilities that are now recognised
as standard in intelligence tests. His tests enabled him to compare the ‘mental
faculties’ of different pupils. Binet assumed that there were many different
mental faculties, and that it was possible to be high on one and low on another.
So Binet was not measuring intelligence as a single concept. The concept of
general intelligence or g was introduced some 20 years later by Charles Spear-
man (Spearman, 1927). Binet believed that his tests could not “make us know
the totality of an intelligence.” Instead, Binet’s aim was to measure the many
mental faculties that he thought were important to guide the selection of pupils
through an educational system. Spearman used the finding that the scores on
the different mental faculties correlate (he used the method of factor analysis) to
infer there was an underlying construct of general intelligence that affected all
mental faculties. Spearman’s idea of general intelligence was used later to allo-
cate children to different schools in the UK – in contrast to Binet’s assumption
that differences in specific intelligence were important for allocating students to
different classes within schools.
When the author was young, intelligence tests were used to allocate pupils
to three classes of school in the UK: grammar school, technical school, and
secondary modern – this tripartite system was introduced in the education act
of 1944. The arguments for the early allocation of pupils to different types
of school was later condemned as discriminatory as well as being having sig-
nificant disadvantages in terms of the underlying assumption that intelligence
remains constant as children grow older. Comprehensive schools (i.e., schools
that were non-selective) were introduced in 1965 by the Labour government.
Some grammar schools still exist and have both supporters and detractors. The
several factors that inform this debate are beyond the scope of this book but
may be interesting for students.
make one more and very important requirement for impact: It must be based on
research. There must be a research paper or papers that provide a justification
or rationale for the change in practice.
According to these guidelines, neither William James nor Stanley Hall cre-
ated impact. It is certainly true that they influenced practice, and did so to a
large degree. However, the change in practice was not based on research, but
on observation-based theory. They developed theories on the basis of observa-
tion of people around them, but did not test those theories with independent
data. By contrast Münsterberg did carry out experiments, and his recom-
mendations for practice were supported by the evidence of his experiments.
Other psychologists (Witmer, Scott, Binet) developed methods of assessment
that were used where the method of assessment was based on research meth-
odology. If the criteria of impact are used, then applied psychology requires
underpinning by research.
What kind of research leads to impact? Chapter 1 provided an account of
two types of research and research programme. In one, theory is developed
inductively by collecting data relevant to a particular problem. This type of
research is data-led. In the other, speculative theory is tested using deduction to
provide tests of the theory. This type of research is theory-led. Data-led versus
theory-led is a continuum rather than a binary classification, though for sim-
plicity it is treated as such.
If research is data-led, then impact must come from research in an applied
field. Research in clinical psychology, health psychology, educational psychol-
ogy, occupational psychology, counselling psychology, and forensic psychology
need to be conducted with, respectively, people with mental illness, people with
somatic illness, children or students, workers, people with problems of varying
kinds, and perpetrators or staff involved in crime. Applied research in these
different areas of application is well established with journals specific to each
different type of application.
By contrast, if research is theory-led, then impact can come from a variety
of sources. One of the arguments for those carrying out or supporting pure or
non-applied research is that their research may have practical applications in
the future. The history of science provides examples of how research that had
no apparent use at first turned out to have use in the long run. When quantum
mechanics was first envisaged, none of the theoretical physicists thought that
their invention would be used in mobile phones almost a century later. However,
although mobile phones use quantum technology, other research was needed to
translate the original theory and fundamental research into something practical.
This ‘other’ research, research that develops an application from non-applied
research, is called ‘translational research.’ So, although the argument that ‘pure’
research can lead in due to course to applications, those applications require
the addition of another type of research, translational research. What happens
in the laboratory may not happen in real life. Translational research is needed
Becoming an applied science ◆ 65
Both applied and non-applied research have value. As a science develops and
becomes more theoretical, the distinction becomes less important because there
is nothing so practical as a good theory. However, the distinction remains
important from a political perspective. If research is mostly funded, as it is
in the UK, by tax payers’ money, then tax payers expect their scientists to do
something more useful than extract sunbeams from cucumbers.
66 ◆ Becoming an applied science
Summary
Wundt presented psychology as a pure, non-applied subject in order to gain
intellectual acceptance in European society where applied subjects were valued
less. Psychologists developed psychology as an applied discipline in America.
William James and Stanley Hall developed theories based on observation and
used these theories to make recommendations in education, but did not attempt
to test their theories or the validity of their recommendations. Münsterberg
made an explicit distinction between applied and non-applied psychology
research, defining the former in terms of the intention of the researchers. Mün-
sterberg carried out experiments in applied settings and his recommendations
for forensic psychology were based on evidence, not only on theory. Other
applied psychologists also made empirical contributions to their fields. Witmer
developed the first clinical psychology clinics in America, focussing on measure-
ment and improved environmental conditions for the mentally ill. Scott pio-
neered organisational psychology, developing tests for personnel selection and
advertisements based on psychological principles. In France, Binet developed
the first intelligence tests, intelligence tests that exist with little modification
today.
The UK government has increased the status of applied research by intro-
ducing impact as a criterion for competitive university funding. Impact is
achieved most often when researchers have the intention of solving a practical
problem. However, impact can result from non-applied research with the addi-
tion of translational research.
Essay questions
1 How did Münsterberg define applied psychology and what was his
contribution?
2 William James provided advice to teachers about education. Evaluate
that advice in terms of modern theory and practice.
3 Imagine that you are in charge of all psychology research funding
in the UK. There is not enough money to fund all the good quality
research applications which divide into two main groups, those that
are primarily applied and those that are not. What proportion of that
funding would you allocate to applied psychology versus non-applied
psychology research topics? Justify the reason for your decision and
describe how you would assess impact.
4
Why did behaviourism occur, what
forms did it take, and why and how was
it replaced by cognitive psychology as
the dominant paradigm in psychology?
68 ◆ Why did the behaviourism story occur?
This is a long chapter, the longest in this book. It covers a number of inter-
related concepts: Why introspection was rejected as a method by psychologists,
the assumptions and different forms of behaviourism, why cognitive psychol-
ogy replaced behaviourism as the dominant paradigm, and how cognitive psy-
chology differs from or is related to behaviourism.
From 1920 to 1950 most psychologists working in university departments
would have considered themselves behaviourists. Research psychologists wore
white coats and they worked in laboratories with cages of white rats. Psychol-
ogy was the psychology of the white rat. Behaviourism did more than anything
else to convert public opinion to the view that psychology was a science. When
a member of the general public evaluates whether something is a science, they
seldom use Popper’s criterion of falsifiability. If something looked like science –
and scientists wear white coats – then it must be a science. Even by the 1960s,
when the height of behaviourism was well and truly gone, rat psychology was
still an important part of the student curriculum. When the author was an under-
graduate in Bristol (1968–1971), the top floor of the three storey psychology
department (a converted Georgian house) was devoted entirely to animals – and
students were expected to get used to handling rats. I still remember the smell of
rat urine on sawdust that greeted you when entering the front door – entering a
pet shop brings back the memory of long ago.
Paradigms in psychology are based on assumptions, untested metatheoreti-
cal assumptions. Behaviourism was one of those paradigms. It is based on a
set of assumptions, the primary one being that human behaviour has the same
causes as that of rat behaviour. However, the assumptions of behaviourism
changed slightly as time went on, so although it is perfectly possible to write
about ‘behaviourism’ as a single ‘thing,’ this chapter tells the story of a series of
ideas that developed between the beginning of the 20th century till about 1950.
This chapter tells the story from the time before behaviourism started until after
it was no longer the dominant paradigm.
Behaviourism started as an explicit rejection of an earlier paradigm of psy-
chology. That earlier paradigm was psychology based on introspection. Wilhem
Wundt and his students defined psychology as the study of the structure of the
mind. William James and his students defined psychology as the study of the
function of the mind, including what the mind could tell us about behaviour.
The problem was that introspection, as practised in several laboratories across
the world, did not easily provide the answers that scientific psychologists (call-
ing themselves experimental psychologists) were looking for. Behaviourism
arose as an explicit rejection of introspection. That rejection was based on
evidence not prejudice.
There were two kinds of problem that arose using introspection as a method
of experimental psychology. One was that introspection as a method failed to
explain certain types of psychological problem. The second was that labora-
tories were coming to different conclusions using introspection and one of the
characteristics of a science is that the findings must be replicable. These two
problems are described before the description of behaviourism itself.
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 69
or divide. The word presented before the task had an effect on the associated
number without conscious awareness. For example, when Ach presented the
numbers 6 and 2, if he had said ‘add,’ the associated number was invariably 8,
whereas if he said ‘divide’ the associated number would be 3. People’s behav-
iour was determined independently of introspection. Exactly the same phenom-
enon is sometimes used by magicians when they perform magic tricks of mind
reading.
Precursors to behaviourism
Before the term behaviourism was coined, psychologists had started to do ani-
mal experiments. One of these psychologists was Edward Thorndike (1874–1949).
For reasons that are not entirely clear, Thorndike wanted to study animal
behaviour for his PhD at Harvard University – where William James was a
professor. The only problem was that psychologists didn’t study animals, and
biologists didn’t study behaviour. In the end Thorndike carried out his experi-
ments in William James’ basement – James was a generous person.
Although Thorndike is remembered for his animal research (1899, 1905),
he only spent a few years on it, as he soon “followed the path of least resis-
tance” as he put it and turned to research in educational psychology (Thorn-
dike, 1921, 1932). Educational psychology at the time was an important and
respected field of psychology (see Chapter 3).
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 71
As part of his research, Thorndike set out to discover how kittens or young
cats could open a ‘puzzle box’ (Burnham, 1972). There were various types of
puzzle boxes, each requiring a different solution to how it was opened. For
example, Thorndike would place a hungry cat in the box with food outside
and then time how long the cat took to open the puzzle box. What he found
was that over repeated exposure to this situation, the length of time to escape
decreased. That the animals appeared to learn gradually led to Thorndike for-
mulating his famous laws.
Thorndike suggested two laws, the law of effect and the law of exercise.
Thorndike defined the law of effect as follows:
When students read these laws nowadays, common reactions are incompre-
hension and boredom. In fact, what they are saying is very simple. The law of
effect means that animals do more of the things they enjoy and less of the things
they find unpleasant. This is hardly a novel idea. However, what was novel
was the quasi-scientific way in which this simple idea was expressed. Calling
it ‘the law of effect’ meant psychology had its own laws, just as Newton had
invented the laws of physics. Well, almost! The law of exercise is an equally
unsurprising idea. The basic idea had already been expressed by William James
in his analysis of habit. Put simply, the law of exercise says that animals tend to
repeat behaviours that they have done before. Nevertheless, Thorndike’s laws
are important in that he expressed ideas that are self-evident in humans if one
focusses on consciousness, but may not be self-evident in animals. At the same
time, these laws must be contenders for the first prize for ‘The psychology of
the bleedin’ obvious.’
Student rat revising.
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 73
Thorndike’s law of effect has one other feature that is worth noting. Thorndike
used the term satisfaction but without clearly defining what satisfaction is. In
fact, Thorndike’s approach to satisfaction was circular. If the probably of an
action increases, this indicates that the action was satisfying; satisfaction is
therefore defined in terms of its effect. However, the idea of ‘satisfaction’ does
imply some form of motivation, and this motivational aspect was developed by
later behaviourists.
Watson’s ideas developed over time, but central to his theory was the idea of the
stimulus-response bond. The stimulus-response bond was responsible for hab-
its. Habits developed over the lifetime were responsible for much of behaviour.
The idea of a stimulus-response bond has clear links with Thorndike’s law of
effect and James’ concept of habit. However, Watson also linked his use of the
term habit with the phenomenon of conditioning that had been discovered by
Ivan Pavlov (1849–1936) in Russia. In his well-known studies of dogs, Pavlov
showed that it was possible to form associations between stimuli – between an
unconditioned stimulus (e.g., food) and a conditioned stimulus (e.g., a bell).
Watson thought that habits could be conditioned by environmental circum-
stances, as these circumstances and consequent habits led either to a well-
adjusted person or a neurotic person. His strong belief in the environmental
determination of behaviour is summed up in his claim, made in 1924.
Why did Watson think this possible? Although he did not use this modern termi-
nology, Watson thought that animals and humans were adaptive systems. That
is, it would be possible to mould people into different types of specialist because
they would adapt to the environmental characteristics of those specialists.
Watson gained psychiatric experience by working at the Hopkins’ Phipps
psychiatric clinic and it was there that he began to apply his ideas of condition-
ing to the development of neuroses. Watson demonstrated a conditioned fear
response in a young child. Watson’s study on the conditioning of fear was car-
ried out with Rosalie Rayner and published in 1920 (Watson & Rayner, 1920) –
the study would not obtain ethical approval these days, and it is referred to as
the study of Little Albert. Watson selected a ‘solid and unemotional’ child for
his experiment, Little Albert, who was about nine months old. Little Albert was
76 ◆ Why did the behaviourism story occur?
afraid only of a sudden loud noise, which is a normal fear response for children.
Two months later Little Albert started training. Training involved placing a
white rat in front of Little Albert, who showed no fear of the rat. Then, when
Little Albert reached out to touch the rat, as soon as he touched the rat, the
experimenters made a loud noise by striking a steel bar with a hammer. Little
Albert jumped at the loud noise. This was then repeated. A week later, there
were five more presentations of the rat and noise at which point Little Albert
was clearly afraid of the rat and would cry and crawl away. Five days later,
when the rat was presented and without the loud noise, Little Albert was still
afraid of the rat. Watson believed that this showed that neurotic responses in
patients were also caused by conditioning.
The reporting of the Little Albert story has become elaborated over time like
a game of Chinese whispers (British English) or game of telephone (American
English). In fact, the conditioning effect was weak, and on subsequent occasions
Watson had to ‘freshen up’ (Watson & Rayner, 1920, p. 9) the original response
by repeating the loud noise. Watson and Rayner were able to show that the
fear did generalise – for example to a white rabbit, dog, fur coat, cotton wool,
and a Father Christmas. In later accounts of the experiment, fear was reported
as generalising to other objects not mentioned in the original paper. Watson
(1928/1972) mentions a rug, and inventions in textbooks include a furry glove
and even a teddy bear (Harris, 1979). Harris (1979) suggests that these addi-
tions were probably invented to make the story more acceptable and believable
to students and other readers.
Watson and Rayner not only collaborated on research together, but they
also became lovers. Watson’s marriage had not been good for several years, and
Watson found in Rayner the romance that he was lacking at home. In1920 he
divorced he wife and married Rayner. This action scandalised the authorities at
Johns Hopkins University, particularly as Rayner came from a family who had
given large sums of money to the University. Watson was dismissed from his
post. From then on Watson never obtained a good academic job, but for a short
time he continued to publish on his work on child rearing (Watson 1928/1972).
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 77
Invented history
Those interested in Watson’s personal life might like to note that Watson
was, in 1919, voted the most attractive male professor by female students
(Benjamin, Whitaker, Ramsey & Zeve, 2007). There is an interesting
postscript to Watson’s story. It was suggested that the real reason he was
sacked was not because of his affair with Rosalie Rayner, but because
he was conducting experiments investigating the physiological effects
of sexual intercourse – using himself and Rosalie as subjects. This story,
however, has been shown to be nothing more than that – just a story (Ben-
jamin et al., 2007), but the fact that the story is told shows how history
is elaborated to fulfil the perceptions of the teller – perhaps more so for
Watson than for others.
Mothers just don’t know, when they kiss their children and pick them
up and rock them, caress them and jiggle them upon their knee, that
they are slowly building up a human being totally unable to cope with
the world it must later live in.
(Watson, 1928/1972, p. 44)
they received or influenced by the early death of their mother when she was 35
is unknown.
In summary, Watson introduced a new type of psychology that entirely
rejected the idea of the introspection as a method. Some of his ideas still have
currency today, such as the idea of a conditioned fear response, but others, such
as his beliefs about childrearing, are now rejected. His legacy is controversial.
Some considering him second in influence only to Freud whereas others see him
as just a footnote in the development of modern psychology (Weyant, 1968).
Explanatory fictions
The content of scientific explanations is made from two different types of term:
observation terms and theoretical terms. Observation terms refer to things that
can be seen (e.g., tables, chairs, dials, levers). Theoretical terms refer to things
that cannot be seen (e.g., electrons, atoms). The purpose of scientific explana-
tion (or one purpose of scientific explanation) is to predict cause and effect
relationships between observation terms. After all, it is the observation terms
that really matter in terms of everyday life. No one will worry if an electron is
misplaced, but they do if their car won’t start. For many explanations, theoreti-
cal terms intervene between the observation terms:
Or
S→O→R
S→O→R
Then, once the connections between stimulus, organism, and response are
known, this relationship can be simplified to
S→R
In other words, if the organism variable does what it is supposed to do, then it
can be ignored.
Skinner argued that psychology should restrict itself to S-R links and
ignore psychological theoretical terms irrespective of their nature. Thus, Skin-
ner rejected physiological explanations just as he rejected mentalistic explana-
tions in psychology.
Skinner’s argument for a strict S-R psychology included a damning criticism
of the way organism terms are used in psychology, a criticism that theoretical
terms in psychology were ‘explanatory fictions.’
To illustrate the case of an explanatory fiction, let us return to the example
given previously:
Let us suppose that John sees a lion, becomes afraid, and so runs away. How
do we know that John is afraid? Because he runs away. If John approached
and stroked the lion, we wouldn’t suppose that John was afraid. John’s fear is
inferred from his behaviour, the same behaviour which the fear is being used
to explain.
To give a slightly more banal example, let us suppose that we observe John
smiling. We infer from this that John is happy. Because John is happy, therefore
he smiles. But we only know that he is happy because he smiles.
Skinner points out that the organism variable in psychology is an explana-
tory fiction. It masquerades as an explanation. It cons us into thinking that an
explanation is provided, when all it does is redescribe the behaviour. While
Skinner’s argument has merits, a later section in this chapter will explain what
it takes to make an organism variable not an explanatory fiction.
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 81
Skinner’s contribution
Burrhus Frederic Skinner, or B.F. Skinner (1904–1990) originally planned to
be an author, but after reading works by Watson and Pavlov he enrolled in
a graduate programme of psychology at Harvard in 1928 (Catania, 1992).
His career as a behaviourist psychologist lasted six decades and included not
only academic books and papers, but also many non-technical books written
for the general population, so that his original aim of being an author was in
fact realised (Bjork, 1993). Skinner’s book The Behavior of Organisms (1938)
was his major work. Although focussing on the behaviour of the white rat,
Skinner believed that humans were organisms just as the rat was. By organism
he meant a unified system of stimulus-response connections (Catania, 1992).
Skinner investigated the rat’s behaviour with an invention of his that is now
known as the Skinner box. The Skinner box consists of a box in which the rat
is placed with a lever on which the rat can press. The rat’s lever presses are the
response – and various stimuli, such as food or electric shock, can be applied
by the researcher.
Skinner’s main academic contribution to behaviourism was that he estab-
lished the idea of operant conditioning in contrast to respondent conditioning –
respondent conditioning was the form of conditioning studied by Pavlov.
Operant conditioning involved the shaping of behaviour through reinforce-
ment, and this idea is directly linked to Thorndike’s law of effect. That is, organ-
isms tend to do more of an action that is reinforced (i.e., creates satisfaction)
and less of one that does not. Behaviour is controlled by its consequences. The
astute student may query whether the idea of satisfaction is an explanatory fic-
tion. Skinner avoided this problem by simply identifying those conditions that
were reinforcing – i.e., led to an increase of a particular behaviour. However, in
contrast to Thorndike, Skinner believed that reinforcement was better able to
shape behaviour than punishment and so advocated the use of encouragement
rather than punishment for modifying human behaviour.
Skinner’s contributions were not only in the academic sphere (e.g., Skinner,
1935, 1957, 1984a), he also made contributions in three other ways. First, he
wrote a number of books and articles that provided a blueprint for a ‘better way
of life’ based on behaviourist principles (Skinner, 1938, 1953, 1974). His novel
Walden Two published in 1948 describes a happy society based on principles
82 ◆ Why did the behaviourism story occur?
was taken up initially by physicians (it was renamed the tautophone), but again,
never really caught on (Rutherford, 2003).
Skinner was a multi-faceted person. His contribution included a philosophi-
cal perspective on psychological theory, the application of psychological theory in
the form of operant conditioning and several applications of behavioural princi-
ples to real life situations. That these applications were not particularly successful
were a great disappointment to Skinner. Why they were not successful is a matter
of speculation and a useful topic for discussion. Despite his earlier popularity, by
the 1960s popular opinion was moving away from a mechanistic view of people
as mindless machines to one that was more in line with the liberalism of the time –
where flower power and free love were the new idiom (see Chapter 9). Skinner’s
interpretation of psychology was criticised in the popular press (Rutherford,
2000). Nevertheless, he has had an immense influence on psychology with the
central belief that people are the product of their environments. At the age of 86
he was still working on the final correction on a paper entitled “Can Psychology
Be a Science of Mind?” the evening before he died (Fowler, 1990).
Now, imagine what happens if non-naïve rats, rats who have learned where the
goal box is, are used instead. The non-naïve rat will run straight to the goal box
where a reward of food is waiting. The prior history of the rat makes a differ-
ence. Equally, if a rat is hungry because it has not been fed, this rat will behave
differently to one that is satiated because it has just been fed. Again, prior his-
tory makes a difference. It seems that any explanation of the behaviour of a rat
must take into account prior history.
The radical behaviourist solution to the effect of history on present behav-
iour was to incorporate the historical stimuli into the explanation of stimulus
and response. The stimulus-response links of the non-naïve rats on the occa-
sions before the test period become part of the explanation.
84 ◆ Why did the behaviourism story occur?
SER
Mathematical psychology
Hull was one of the first psychologists to introduce quantitative theory
into psychology in a way that mimics the quantitative theories of physics
and chemistry (but see also Weber’s fraction and Fechner’s law, Chap-
ter 2). Although a fraction of psychological theories are quantitative, the
Journal of Mathematical Psychology was first published in 1964 and con-
tinues publishing articles to this day. Although some papers relate to rein-
forcement, others describe human behaviour. For example, Luce’s choice
axiom (Luce, 1977) provides quantitative predictions about choice. If,
for example, the proportion of people choosing chicken over beef in a
restaurant is X/Y, then, if pork is added to the menu, although the abso-
lute number of people choosing chicken and beef reduces, the proportion,
X/Y, remains the same. The theory is tested not with statistical hypothesis
testing but by a quantitative estimate of the extent to which that propor-
tion, X/Y, remains the same under different conditions of choice.
The second of Hull’s organism variables is called drive, and given the
expression
D or drive is operationally defined in terms of the number of hours the rat has
been without food. Hull thought that there was one central drive, D, that moti-
vated all behaviour, and that when D was high the rat was more likely to engage
in behaviour, any behaviour.
The third of Hull’s organism variables is called habit, and given the
expression
SER = D × H
of behaviour (i.e., what they actually do) is determined by habit. That is, drive
energises behaviour and habit directs behaviour.
Notice that Hull’s three organism variables are operationally defined in
terms of external observable variables. Drive is not some internal physiologi-
cal state, and habit is not a pathway in the brain. These concepts are entirely
described in terms of objective external conditions. Notice that this form of
description of organism variables is not very different from Skinner’s proposal
that there should be no organism variables at all. Because drive is only the num-
ber of hours without food, it would be possible to dispense with the concept
of drive and rely only on the number of hours without food. That is, it would
be possible to include the historical stimuli (number of hours without food)
with the present stimulus of the maze in order to explain the rat’s behaviour.
Hull’s organism variables are simply a convenient summary of the external,
objective stimulus. He does not make the error criticised by Skinner of creating
an explanatory fiction by supposing that there is an internal state, called drive,
that ‘makes’ the rat run. Drives are simply convenient summaries of the external
objective data.
In a typical behaviourist experiment conducted by Hull, a rat would be
placed at the beginning of a maze. There was food at the goal box at the end
of the maze. The behaviour of the rat would be observed. It was found that the
rat ran faster if it was deprived of food, and it would be more likely to go to the
correct goal box if it had received food there in the past. However, over time
Hull found that other variables would affect the rat’s behaviour. For example,
the attractiveness of the reward would make a difference, as well as the amount
of effort needed by the rat to achieve the goal. These additional variables could
not be explained by his initial theory of
SER = D × H
them. However, as Hull’s theory grew it became less good at simplifying and
making sense. The more comprehensive the theory became – and Hull wanted
to explain all behaviour – the more unwieldy it became. As a theory for explain-
ing a limited number of events in a restricted setup, the theory was very suc-
cessful. But as a theory of all behaviour, Hull’s approach failed to be successful.
There is a reason for focussing on Hull’s theory. The historian Imre Lakatos
observed that research programmes that are driven by data are less successful
than those driven by theory (see Chapter 1). Lakatos used the term ‘degenerat-
ing problem shift’ to describe research where theory lags behind data. Lakatos
did not refer to Hull’s theory as an example of a degenerating problem shift, but
it is an excellent example of what happens. Theoretical terms were introduced
to explain behaviours of the rat that were observed and could not be explained
by the existing theoretical terms. To be successful, a theory needs to be able to
simplify behaviour, not just redescribe each behaviour using a different theo-
retical concept. Despite its influence in its day, nowadays Hull’s mathematical
theory is largely forgotten (Mills, 1978).
know – there is no point in between. Tolman had worked with Koffka, and
Koffka had worked with Köhler who had demonstrated that apes could learn
through insight learning (see Chapter 10). So, Tolman was maintaining the
tradition started by the Gestalt psychologists (see Chapter 10) whose theories
focussed on wholes rather than on parts. By contrast, Hull was maintaining
the tradition started by Wundt of associationism. In Hull’s case, association
is a gradual process. The all-or-nothing versus associative or gradual learning
controversy was a major point of discussion at that time (Bruce, 1998).
The difference between Hull and Tolman about incremental versus all or
nothing learning lasted for many years. Each side found that ‘their’ rats per-
formed in the way their theory predicted. When placed in a maze Tolman’s rats
looked around, and (according to Tolman) formed a cognitive map of their
environment, and once they had formed that cognitive map, then they always
went straight to the goal. Note the term cognitive map – Tolman’s theory
anticipates cognitive psychology. By contrast, Hull’s learned gradually, making
progressively fewer and fewer errors. Just as the debate was becoming irrelevant
(with the advent of cognitive psychology) a possible reason for these different
results emerged. Hull and Tolman were using different strains of rats. Hull’s rats
had been selectively bred to be unemotional. Tolman’s rats were more closely
related to the emotional rats that are found in the wild. Tolman’s rats were
more afraid, and more hesitant and so went to the goal box only when they had
learned where they were (Jones, 2003).
Like Hull, Tolman introduced organism variables, and these organism variables
included expectancy, purposes, cognitions, hypotheses, and appetite. To illus-
trate what is meant by expectancy, Tolman suggested that when a response is
rewarded, then rats develop an expectancy that the response is going to lead to
another response. Although this idea of expectancy may appear to be mentalis-
tic, in fact Tolman was careful to avoid treating organism variables in that way.
At least he was careful to make sure his concepts were operationally defined,
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 89
The key point made by MacCorquodale and Meehl is that if there is nothing
more to an organism variable than its procedures for measurement, then the
organism variable should be treated as an intervening variable – i.e., a short-
hand summary of that measurement procedure. However, if the organism
variable has properties beyond that of measurement because the organism
variable is hypothesised to exist, then the organism should be called a hypo-
thetical construct. The crucial issue is the hypothesis that something exists
independently of its measurement procedures. Hypothetical constructs are
organism variables that are hypothesised to exist independently of measure-
ment. They are there whether or not you measure them. Intervening variables
are only there if you measure them. They exist only because of the measure-
ment procedures.
Hypothetical constructs are assumed to exist as entities. The technical term
is that hypothetical constructs have ontological status – there is something
‘there.’ What exactly it is that is there can be disputed, but the assumption is
that there is something there. By contrast, intervening variables do not require
the assumption of an entity and they do not have ontological status – there is
nothing there other than the measurement procedure.
There are two additional features that distinguish hypothetical constructs
and intervening variables. First, the description of an intervening variable is
precise in that it is defined exactly by its operations. There is nothing more to
add than the operational description. Hypothetical constructs are not precisely
defined by describing what they do. Hypothetical constructs have ‘surplus
meaning.’ Surplus meaning refers to ways of describing the hypothetical con-
struct without referring to what it does. So, for example, if we were to say
that there is a motive, a hypothetical construct, called achievement motivation
which motivates people to achieve, the implication is that achievement motiva-
tion does things other than motivate people to achieve – for example, it may
make them more prone to write stories about achievement. The surplus of the
hypothetical construct acts as a heuristic that guides future research, and in
particular is a source of inspiration for developing new empirical predictions
(Hyland, 1981, 1985)
There is yet one more difference between hypothetical constructs and inter-
vening variables. The measurement of the intervening variable is precise; in
the case of the hypothetical construct it is only approximate. If it is said that
intelligence is what intelligence tests measure, then the measure of intelligence
tests provides an exact account of a person’s level of intelligence, because that
is exactly what intelligence is. There is no measurement error. However, if it is
said that intelligence tests measure intelligence, then it is assumed that intelli-
gence exists independently of the test, and the test will never be able to provide
a perfect description of that independently existing entity of intelligence.
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 91
The controversy between Skinner and Chomsky was over the explanation for
the development of language. Skinner took an environmentalist position that all
that was needed were principles of reinforcement and the right circumstances.
Chomsky argued that there is a genetic difference between humans and animals,
humans having a ‘language acquisition device’ that enabled the formation of
language. Skinner’s view was not as simplistic as it is often made out to be
(Skinner, 1984a, 1984b), and he did provide a way of explaining language using
behaviourist principles. The problem is that just because a theory can explain
something does not make that theory true (see Chapter 1). The difficulty Skin-
ner’s theory faced was not why humans had language but why other animals,
when given all the advantages of language development that humans have
(e.g., dogs reared in domestic household), do not develop language. The theory
explains some but not all parts of the phenomenon of language.
Given the dominance of behaviourism, given the ubiquity of psychology labs
full of rats, is it really likely that the empire of behaviourism was demolished by
one theoretical controversy? There are two other good reasons for the demise of
behaviourism, one cultural and the other related to types of explanation.
needed little cognitive input when working. If one is interested in simple repeti-
tive movements, then the assumptions of behaviourist theories make sense. A
modern and more familiar example of a simple repetitive movement is that
needed when gambling with a slot machine. Research using rats shows that a
variable reinforcement schedule produces the most amount of work without
reinforcement. So, if a gambling machine is set up to pay out on a random
basis, then this is more likely to produce compulsive gambling than one with a
fixed reinforcement schedule. Gambling machines are based on reinforcement
principles. Reinforcement does work. Furthermore, as the behaviourists found
with rats, reinforcement is a better way of controlling behaviour than punish-
ment for humans.
Computers were being developed in the 1950s and 1960s. Computers
process information, information that cannot be represented in the form of
stimulus-response bonds. A computer stores information that can then be
combined with the input to make an output, an output that corresponds to a
solution of some problem. The development of computers coincided with the
development of cognitive psychology. The technological developments led to
a new kind of question that was asked: How do people process information?
How do they remember things? The principles of association – the bedrock
of behaviourist theory – could not explain information processing. Cognitive
psychology differed from behaviourism in that it explained a type of behaviour
that behaviourism did not explain.
Types of explanation
A second reason for the demise of behaviourism was mentioned previously in
the evaluation of Hull’s theory. The behaviourists did not try to understand
underlying mechanisms. By limiting theoretical terms to those that were opera-
tionally defined, research took the form of observation followed by explana-
tion. Research was data-led rather than theory-led. Lakatos (see Chapter 1)
provides a description of research where theory lags behind data. He described
these as having a degenerating problem shift, in contrast to the progressive
problem shift where theory precedes data. Cognitive psychology arose from an
attempt to try to understand the mechanisms that were responsible for informa-
tion processing. They speculated about mechanisms.
The idea for a new type of mechanism or a new type of explanation for
cognitive science predates Broadbent’s (1958) publication by 15 years. Kenneth
Craik (1943) provided an elegant argument, which goes like this: The brain
controls behaviour, but it is difficult to understand what is happening in the
brain. The brain is able to manipulate structures in the outside world through
its effect on behaviour. Because events in the brain parallel those external struc-
tures, it should be possible to use the structures themselves as the elements of
a theory without having to understand the minute details of what is happening
in the brain. It is this idea that Broadbent adopts in his book Perception and
Learning but citing Craik (1948) only in relation to Craik’s description of a
self-correcting or control system.
Control systems
The idea of a control system is a good example of the application of a mechanical
concept to psychology. The feedback loop, the basis of a common thermostat,
has been used in several different ways, including motor control (Todorov &
94 ◆ Why did the behaviourism story occur?
Stimulus, Environment
sensory input
FIGURE 4.1
This figure shows how psychological concepts can be ‘modelled’ onto the form of a
control system.
Jordan, 2002); social, personality, and health psychology (Carver & Scheier,
1982, 1990); and depression (Hyland, 1987). The set point in the thermostat
corresponds to a person’s goal. The thermometer in the thermostat corresponds
to the sensory input. The central heating boiler corresponds to behaviour, and
the room temperature to the environment (see Figure 4.1).
Unlike behaviourists, the new cognitive psychologists were comfortable
with terms that were not operationally defined, and which MacCorquodale and
Meehl (1948) would have been classified as hypothetical constructs but were
later referred to as ‘person variables’ (Hyland, 1985). The hypothesis of, for
example, working memory, is based on the assumption that people really do
have working memories. Working memory is a structure that has ontological
status and is an idea that is derived from computers. The acceptance of person
variables soon spread to the rest of psychology. Personality theorists assume
that personality constructs really do exist. The term personality construct
derives from the word hypothetical construct. One of the authors in the Mac-
Corquodale and Meehl (1948) paper provided an early definition of construct
validity (Cronbach & Meehl, 1955). The theoretical terms that come after the
behaviourist era are not just a description of data; they provide an explanation
in terms of a hypothesised mechanism.
The introduction of the new hypothetical constructs used by cognitive
psychologists coincided with the introduction of a new term, psychological
model. The term psychological model is rare before 1950. What does the term
psychological model mean?
A model car has four wheels like a proper car. The relationship between the
four wheels is the same, as is the relationship of the wheels to the rest of the car.
Almost everything in the model car looks the same as a proper car, except that
the model car is smaller. The relationship between the parts remains the same
but the parts themselves are different.
The word model is used as a synonym for theory, when the theory is ‘modelled’
on something else, such as a physical structure. The cognitive theory has the same
form as the physical technology (i.e., the same relationship between the parts), but
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 95
different content (i.e., the parts are actually different). The word psychological
model therefore refers to the similarity in form between the psychological theory
and something else. In the case of the control theory examples, the psychological
theories have the same form as a thermostatic control system, but the content of
the theories is different because they refer to the control of psychological phenom-
ena rather than temperature control. The hallmark of cognitive psychology and
the new theories that replaced behaviourism was that they used technology as a
heuristic for understanding human behaviour (i.e., for modelling theories) and,
specifically, information processing (Miller, Galanter & Pribram, 1960).
Although cognitive psychology has not provided a focus on how people adapt
to their environments, the theoretical approach initially developed by cogni-
tive psychologists provided the impetus of doing just that, under the heading
of deep learning that forms part of artificial intelligence (see Chapter 10). The
mechanical analogy can be used as a way of understanding adaptation, but it
took the invention of robots for a technology to develop that was capable of
behavioural adaptation.
Final thoughts
Behaviourism was an important stage in the development of psychology. It lost its
position of dominance because it was no longer seen to be relevant to questions
that were being asked as psychology developed. It was a research programme
that ran out of steam. Behaviourism was never ‘proved wrong’ – only shown to
be irrelevant to some important questions in psychology, but it developed ideas
that are relevant today, and may be relevant for the future. To conclude, here is
a quotation from Tolman. Students should interpret it as they wish.
Rats live in cages; they do not go on binges the night before one has
planned an experiment; they do not kill each other off in wars; they do
not invent engines of destruction, and, if they did, they would not be so
inept about controlling such engines; they do not go in for either class
conflicts or race conflicts; they avoid politics, economics, and papers
on psychology. They are marvelous, pure, and delightful. And, as soon
as I possibly can, I am going to climb back again out on that good old
philogenetic limb and sit there, this time right side up and unashamed,
wiggling my whiskers at all the silly, yet at the same time far too com-
plicated, specimens of homo sapiens whom I shall see strutting and
fighting and messing things up, down there on the ground below me.
(Tolman, 1945, p. 166)
Summary
Behaviourism arose because of a failure of the introspective method to explain
behaviour. Behaviourists shared the common assumption that animal and
human behaviour had the same causes, and so the study of rats could be used
to develop explanations of human behaviour. Methodological behaviourism,
radical behaviourism, and neobehaviourism are based on different assump-
tions. These assumptions relate to the type of the theoretical term, if any, used
to explain behaviour. Behaviourism was superseded by cognitive psychology
because the former failed to adequately account for information processing,
an aspect of human behaviour that became increasingly important after the
development of computers and because the operational definition of theoretical
Why did the behaviourism story occur? ◆ 97
Essay questions
1 Why did Skinner reject theoretical terms? What were the advantages
and disadvantages of doing so?
2 Compare and contrast methodological behaviourism, radical behav
iourism, and neobehaviourism.
3 Why did cognitive psychology arise, and how and what does it explain?
5
Is psychoanalysis scientific, what
are its assumptions, why is therapy
effective, and what is the legacy of
psychoanalysis today?
100 ◆ Is psychoanalysis scientific or effective?
To many members of the general public, Freud is the most famous psychologist
of all time. Yet, Freud was not a psychologist, and some academic psycholo-
gists have a very low opinion of Freud. This chapter examines the concepts that
underpin psychoanalysis and describes their origins and relevance today.
Paradigms of medicine
Freud’s significance in the history of science is that he initiated a paradigm shift.
It was a paradigm shift within the discipline of medicine, not within psychol-
ogy. Freud trained as a medical doctor: He received no training in psychology.
To understand what this paradigm shift was and why it was so significant, it is
necessary to know about the medical paradigm that Freud rejected.
The paradigm of modern western medicine is based on the assumption that
the body is a kind of biological machine. Like any other machine, the body
develops faults, and these faults can be corrected by doctors. The faults are
referred to as pathophysiology. Diseases are defined by different types of fault,
each disease having its own, unique and specific pathophysiology. The theories
of medicine are biological theories, each theory showing how different parts of
the body can go wrong to create disease.
The paradigm of modern western medicine developed gradually, starting in
the 17th century. Early support for the paradigm came from the observation
that there were anatomical differences between people who were healthy and
those with disease. Later, tissue differences and eventually, with the develop-
ment of powerful microscopes, cellular differences were discovered between
those with and without disease.
Before the 20th century, the main alternative to modern western medicine
was Hippocratic medicine. Hippocratic medicine assumes that to be healthy
it was necessary to balance the four bodily humours, black bile, yellow bile,
phlegm, and blood, and that the same imbalance can create many different
diseases. Hippocratic medicine had lost favour by the end of the 19th century
when Freud was working. The pathologist Rudolf Virchow (1821–1902) was
famous for his declaration that there was no such thing as a non-specific illness
(the basis for Hippocratic medicine) only specific illness (the basis of modern
western medicine).
Nearly all diseases known today had been identified by the end of the 19th
century. However, there was a group of diseases where, despite best endeavours,
there was no evidence of pathophysiology. This group of diseases was given the
collective name of ‘nervous diseases’ because it was assumed that they were
diseases of the nervous system. Nervous diseases included melancholia (i.e.,
depression), mania, hysterical paralysis, and lunacy. Only one nervous disease
had its pathophysiology identified – the one named after its discoverer, Alois
Alzheimer – and that discovery was published in 1906, a short while after Freud
had presented his new ideas.
Is psychoanalysis scientific or effective? ◆ 101
Hippocratic medicine
According to those working in the Hippocratic tradition of the early 19th
century, madness was caused by excessive phlegm. So were respiratory
problems. Madness and respiratory problems were treated by the same
‘cure,’ the vomiting cure, where the patient was made to vomit. If some-
one was made to vomit every time they exhibited mad behaviour, it is not
too surprising that this ‘cure’ sometimes worked. As for respiratory com-
plaints, there is no possible reason why vomiting could help.
Poles and Jews, came to Vienna for the same reasons immigrants travel today: a
mix of economic opportunity and escaping from danger. It was more dangerous
to be Jewish in the East than in Vienna in the 19th century (in Russia, Jews were
massacred through pogroms). Freud was born in Czechoslovakia and his family
arrived when Freud was four years old. The immigrants brought with them new
energy and creative ideas in art. These immigrants included Gustav Klimt and
his student Egon Schiele. Klimt shocked Viennese society by his art, which was
modern and sexually explicit in a way that had not been seen before. Schiele also
painted pictures that were at the time considered pornographic.
There was therefore a mix of two societies in 19th-century Vienna. One
respectable, rule following, and sexually inhibited, and the other rule breaking
and sexually liberated. It will immediately strike the student of psychology that
there is a parallel between this society and Freud’s concepts of the id and super-
ego. The conflict between sexual energy and repression was all around him. There
is also an interesting development in Freud’s concept of the id. The id is a kind of
instinct: It makes you want to do things. Freud originally thought there was one
desire called the Libido. The Libido is the sexual instinct. Later (after 1921) Freud
thought there were two instincts, Eros and Thanatos. Eros is similar to the Libido
in that it drives people to sexual activity. Thanatos is the death instinct – it drives
people to kill others. Thanatos as a concept arose after the First World War, a
war when people killed each other but in greater numbers than before. It would
appear that Freud’s theories mirrored his experience of society.
Later authors working within the psychoanalytic tradition accepted the idea
that there was a ‘bad’ element to people, but did not assume the over-arching
connection with sex. For example, Jung proposed that each person had a
‘shadow.’ The shadow was bad in the sense that it encouraged bad desires that
were not necessarily sexual. Jung proposed that recognition of these desires
(‘confronting the shadow’) is important for well-being.
Where Freud got his concept of the id from is unclear. A similar idea had
been proposed shortly before by the philosopher Schopenhauer, though Freud
reported that he had not read Schopenhauer. However the idea of ‘the bad
within all of us’ is repeated many times in literature and philosophy. In book
9 of Plato’s republic (Plato, 380 BCE approximately) there is a description of
desires that occur when people dream.
When the rest of the soul, the reasoning, gentle and ruling part of it is
asleep, then the bestial and savage part . . . begins to leap about, pushes
sleep aside, and tries to go and gratify its instincts. . . . It does not shrink
from attempting incestual intercourse in its dream, with a mother or
with any man or god or beast. It is ready for any deed of blood, and
there is no unhallowed food it will not eat.
(Plato, book IX)
The relationship with the Oedipus complex is clear from this quote, and
Freud reported that he based his concept of sexuality on Plato’s concept of
106 ◆ Is psychoanalysis scientific or effective?
Eros – though there are clear differences (Sandford, 2006). The idea of the ‘bad
within’ is also a feature of Buddhist philosophy which presents the idea that
people have bad desires and that controlling these desires is important to hap-
piness: Desire is the root of sorrow (Rahula, 1959)
In addition to philosophers who recognise that people have a ‘dark side,’ this
idea appears in literature. The short novel The Strange Case of Dr Jekyll and Mr
Hyde was published by Robert Louis Stevenson in 1886 (Stevenson, 1886) and
anticipates Freud’s ideas. The story tells of a good man, Dr Jekyll, who, with a
mysterious medicine, is transferred into a very bad man, Mr Hyde. The assump-
tion that humans are basically bad assumes a degree of genetic determinism that
may not (or may) be entirely justified, but it is clear that the idea of a bad part of
the psyche, which is a characteristic of both Freud and Jung, has a long history.
It is easy to dismiss Freud’s preoccupation with sex as a reflection on his own
life and society, but the evidence suggests that Freud did find references to sex in his
sessions with patients. Among the more controversial of these references was that
young women would report sexual contact with adults when they were children.
Freud interpreted this child-adult sexual contact as damaging to the child, and the
idea became referred to as the seduction hypothesis. Freud later changed his mind
suggesting that women imagined sexual abuse rather than experiencing it.
Historians have disagreed as to why Freud changed his mind. Masson
(1984), in a book entitled The Assault on Truth: Freud’s Suppression of the
Seduction Theory, argues that Freud abandoned the idea because of social pres-
sure from his colleagues who were unwilling to countenance the possibility of
sexual exploitation of children. Freud certainly refers to negative reactions in
some of his letters. More recently Esterson (2002a, 2002b) argued that child
sexual exploitation was recognised at the time but that Freud’s colleagues
rejected it as a cause of mental illness. According to Esterson, Freud’s change
of mind reflected Freud’s own conviction that his original interpretation was
wrong. Whatever the reason, Freud changed his mind on this point, but the
association between sexual abuse of children and mental health problems
had been established. In the novel written by F. Scott Fitzgerald, Tender Is
the Night, published in 1934, part of the story concerns a young psychiatrist
who treats a young woman who has been sexually molested by her father with
resulting mental illness. Thus, although Freud may have retracted his theory, he
drew attention to something that eventually became recognised as true and is
reflected in the literature on child abuse today.
For we found to our great surprise at first, that each individual hysteri-
cal symptom immediately and permanently disappeared when we had
succeeded in bringing clearly to light the memory of the event by which
it was provoked and in arousing the companying affect, and when the
patient had described that event in the greatest possible detail and had
put the affect into words.
(Breuer and Freud, 1893/1955, pp. 6–7)
Ellenberger (1972) however, suggests that although some symptoms did sub-
side, the overall treatment of Bertha by Breuer was not successful. There are
three factors that lead to this conclusion. First, although notes were taken dur-
ing consultation, the case was written up many years after Breuer and Freud
had stopped treating Bertha. Second, Bertha was prescribed morphine and chlo-
ral hydrate (probably by Breuer) and she was maintained on these drugs till she
108 ◆ Is psychoanalysis scientific or effective?
recovered. Third, despite starting treatment with Breuer in 1880, she was hos-
pitalised in 1881 – her name appears in the register of patients in a hospital
in Vienna. It was only in 1882 when she was in hospital that any attempt was
made to wean her off the drugs – which may have been contributing to the
worsening of her symptoms in the first place.
De Paula Ramos (2003) says “After a review of Bertha’s clinical picture, it is
clear that the vast majority of her symptoms . . . are compatible with dependence
on a nonbarbiturate sedative and narcotics” (p. 46).
Despite later evidence that Bertha’s treatment was not as successful as
Breuer had suggested, this early case provided the impetus for Freud to develop
his later theories and treatment. It is significant, however, that Breuer notes in
this case study that “the element of sexuality was astonishingly undeveloped.”
The emphasis on sexuality, which forms an important part of Freud’s later case
studies, is missing in this first case study.
interpretation was that the source of Sergei’s problems was his relationship with
his father, who Sergei admired because he believed him to be a perfect gentle-
man. Freud believed that in reality Sergei suffered from castration anxiety, was
frightened of his father and interpreted this dream as being caused by Sergei
seeing his parents having sexual intercourse – though he later suggested that
Sergei might have witnessed copulation between animals that then generalised
to his parents. Sergei was not impressed by this interpretation. After all, young
children in well-off families did not sleep in the room of their parents but with
a nanny. Freud treated Sergei over a period of four years (1910–1914) and
claimed to have cured him, but the evidence suggests that Sergei was in and out
of treatment throughout his long life – he lived until he was 92 years old (May,
1990).
and well-adjusted young man. So, if a child of yours develops an interest in his
widdler, there is nothing to worry about.
Freud concludes his case study with this postscript that was added to the
original case study:
Whereas Freud interpreted this as amnesia associated with the case, students
might like to come to their own conclusion.
Frank and Frank (1991) argue that the narrative or conceptual scheme does not
have to be true. It just has to be accepted as true by the patients. It is clear from
Freud’s case studies that Freud provided all of the above. Patients describe their
dreams. Freud provides a conceptual scheme for analysing the dreams that is
then discussed with the patients. Freud undoubtedly helped patients with his
talking cure and at the very least spared them some of the more harmful forms
of biological therapy – vomiting therapy, nasal operations, strong psychoactive
substances etc. – that came from a biological explanation of nervous diseases.
Freud introduced the idea of a ‘talking cure’ to the world of medicine. Talking
therapies are now an accepted part of treatment for people with mental illness,
but exactly why talking cures help is a matter of considerable debate even today
and is beyond the scope of this book.
One of the lasting contributions of that Freud introduced were the concepts
of transference and counter-transference (see the case of Anna O). Modern
psychotherapists and counsellors are taught to recognise that patients can
develop emotional feelings towards their therapists, and that therapists can
develop emotional feelings towards their clients. Freud’s recognition of this
Is psychoanalysis scientific or effective? ◆ 113
History of catharsis
The idea of catharsis stems from the days of Ancient Rome. The rulers of
Rome believed that the common people were happy fighting wars and if
there were no wars, the people would become restless. The assumption of
the Roman Games was that if the common people saw something aggres-
sive happening, then they would be less likely to be restless and aggressive.
Seeing Christians thrown to the lions would make the common people
more docile and more easily managed by their rulers
behaviour therapy (CBT) is sometimes described as the most tested and vali-
dated of all psychotherapies. This is perfectly true. More studies have been con-
ducted showing that CBT is effective than the number of studies showing that
other types of psychotherapy are effective. What the data do not show convinc-
ingly is that CBT is more effective than any other psychotherapy (Wampold,
2013). The finding that therapy is effective provides only weak corroborating
evidence for both psychoanalysis and CBT.
A possible conclusion about the scientific status of Freud’s ideas is that some
of them are true, some of them are untrue, and some of them are unfalsifiable.
Freud did not test his ideas with independent data, but he was writing at a time
before the scientific criterion of falsifiability was proposed and accepted. Freud
followed the science of the time in making observations and then providing a the-
ory that was consistent with those observations. The need to test that theory, the
hallmark of modern science, came later. With the hindsight of history, it is pos-
sible to say that Freud was a good scientist in developing speculative theory. His
failure was in assuming that theory was correct. It is the ability to speculate, to
test, to find lacking and then to start again or modify that makes a good scientist.
If ever you should rid yourself entirely of your complexes and stop
playing the father to your sons, and instead of aiming continually at
their weak spots take a good look at your own for a change, then I will
mend my ways and at one stroke uproot the vice of being in two minds
about you.
(Jung on December 18, 1912)
116 ◆ Is psychoanalysis scientific or effective?
Freud and Jung both developed theories of personality that were in some ways
similar and some ways very different. Both theories were type theories. Both are
inventions by their respective authors on the basis of their personal experience,
but without independent data. Freud’s types were the oral type, the anal type,
and the phallic type (see the previous section). Type theories can be contrasted
with trait theories. Modern theories of personality are trait theories. In a type
theory a person is either the type or not the type – it is a binary classification.
For example, a person either has the oral personality or doesn’t have the oral
personality, but cannot be somewhere in between. In the case of modern per-
sonality theories (e.g., the Big Five personality theory), a person varies along
a dimension such as extraversion-introversion. Type theories reflect a medical
tradition of diagnosis. A person either has a disease or does not have a disease.
In fact, for some diseases (e.g., asthma) it is possible to be have ‘a little of the
disease’ whereas others are clearly binary (e.g., Type 1 diabetes), but neverthe-
less the medical tradition is one that puts people into categories. Where there
is a physiological continuum (as in the case of asthma) medical doctors apply a
cut-off point to determine whether or not the person has the disease.
Jung’s personality types are different from Freud’s in that there is no attempt
to explain them in terms of developmental stages. Jung distinguishes four types
of mental function, Thought (i.e., rational judgement, true or false), the oppo-
site of which is Feeling (i.e., emotional judgement, nice or nasty), and Sensation
(i.e., understanding the detail of things), the opposite of which is Intuition (i.e.,
understanding the inner potential of things).
Jung suggested that whatever function occurs in the conscious, the opposite
occurs in the unconscious. So the personality type of a person who is dreaming
is different from the personality type of a person when awake. In addition to his
four psychological functions, Jung proposed two mental attitudes (again, these
are types not traits). The mental attitudes were extraversion (i.e., a tendency
to respond positively in uncertainty) versus introversion (i.e., a tendency to
respond negatively in uncertainty).
Jung’s theory has a number of other differences from Freud’s. Jung was
interested in similarities between different cultures and hypothesised the
existence of a ‘collective unconscious’ which he distinguished from the
‘personal unconscious.’ The collective unconscious is responsible for sym-
bols that are universal to all people. The idea of a collective unconscious is
dismissed by most psychologists today, though a minority claim empirical
evidence in support of the concept (e.g., Ivonin et al., 2015; Rosen, Smith,
Huston, & Gonzalez, 1991).
widely used personality questionnaire used in industry. Few of those using this
questionnaire realise that it is based on the theories of Jung.
What is the greatest impact of Freud and Jung today? Is it the continuation
of psychoanalysis as a form of therapy, is it the concept of mental illness, is it
the talking cure that is now used in one form or another in all psychotherapies,
or is it the Myers-Briggs inventory? Students should decide for themselves.
Summary
Sigmund Freud qualified as a doctor of medicine and at first accepted the
dominant paradigm that ‘nervous diseases’ could be explained in terms of the
pathology of nerves. He developed an alternative paradigm, hypothesising that
‘mental illness,’ as it came to be known, could be explained in terms of psycho-
logical pathology. This psychological paradigm forms the basis of all modern
psychotherapies. Freud treated patients with ‘the talking therapy’ and reported
how this helped patients. Later evidence shows that some of Freud’s claims of
treatment success were over-optimistic. There are two possible explanations
why psychoanalysis is helpful – the theory of psychoanalysis and the common
factors model. The possibility that common factors are responsible for thera-
peutic benefit is a potential criticism of all psychotherapies, including cognitive
behaviour therapy. Carl Jung was influenced by Freud but developed a different
kind of psychodynamic theory and theory of personality. Jung’s theory of per-
sonality influenced the development of the Myers-Briggs scale, a scale that is in
general use today but criticised by modern personality theorists.
Essay questions
1 How did Freud’s personal experience shape the theory he proposed?
2 Is Freudian theory falsifiable?
3 To what extent are concepts used in psychoanalysis shared with later
psychologies? Give examples and justify the reasons for your choice.
6
What is the relationship between
psychology and physiology, will
neuroscience replace psychology, and
what is biopsychosocial interactionism?
122 ◆ Psychology and physiology
Wilhelm Wundt trained in physiology and had a medical degree. His early
books described the physiology of the sensory nervous system (see Chapter 2).
How did Wundt view the relationship between physiology and his new experi-
mental psychology?
Wundt assumed that mental content was the result of the body’s physiology,
but could not be described in terms of physiology. For example, the image of a
chair is represented somewhere in the brain, but that biological representation
does not describe what a chair actually looked like. Wundt’s approach to the
mind-body problem is referred to as psychophysical parallelism. Mental events
occur in parallel with physiological events. Psychophysical parallelism is a phi-
losophy of science based on materialism (also called physicalism), a philosophy
that assumes that only the physical world exists. Although mental events occur
in parallel with physiological events, the material world is the only ‘stuff’ that
exists. There is no ‘mind stuff.’ The experience of mind is a consequence of the
physical world.
Materialism is not the only philosophy of science. The philosopher Des-
cartes had suggested some years before that mind stuff and body stuff both
exist, and that the mind – or soul – exists after the body is dead (see Chapter 2).
Although several of the early psychologists were sympathetic to the idea of an
independent soul, this hypothesis will not be explored here, though most reli-
gions assume some form of independence of the soul or mind from the body.
If the soul exists independently of the body (and can exist after death) then
theories about the body will not be able to explain the phenomena associated
with the soul. Although religious views and dualism are accepted as true by
many people, the examination of how psychology relates to physiology in this
chapter is limited and based on one simple assumption: Minds do not exist
without bodies.
Like Wundt, Sigmund Freud had a degree in medicine and was trained in physi-
ology. Freud initially assumed, like everyone else, that nervous diseases, as they
were then called, were the result of nerves. Because no abnormality of nerves
could be discovered, Freud adopted a psychological explanation for nervous
diseases (see Chapter 5). The psychological explanation led to a new way of
thinking about and describing symptoms. The term and concept of mental ill-
ness replaced the earlier term and concept of nervous diseases. The first effective
psychoactive drugs were developed in the 1950s, providing clear evidence that
nervous diseases/mental illness was indeed due to something wrong with the
nerves. One might imagine, therefore, that if mental illness is due to something
wrong with nerves – as it must be if one assumes materialism – then mental
illness should be treatable through biology and one can forget about talking
therapies. This has not happened. Will it happen in the future? These and other
questions are explored in this chapter.
position of the electrodes gives some information about the activity of different
parts of the brain, because of the way electrical signals travel through the brain,
it is not a very accurate measure of the localisation of function (Haas, 2003).
In 1990 a new technique for investigating the brain was published, called
functional magnetic resonance imaging or fMRI. This technique enables
researchers to measure blood flow through the brain. This is possible because
the water molecules in the brain act as very weak magnets. By briefly disturb-
ing the magnetic field in the brain, the water molecules shift, and the energy
released as they regain their original position is detected. fMRI can be used
to generate pictures of brain activity and can provide accurate localisation of
function. fMRI gives a time-based picture of the activity of different parts of
the brain.
What do EEG and fMRI tell us? They tell us where things are happening in
the brain when certain sorts of mental activity are taking place. Knowing the
position of a book in a library catalogue will give some information about the
content of a book. For example, if the book is in the poetry section, then it is
likely to contain poems. However, the location of a book in a library does not
provide information about the detailed contents of the book (it does not tell
what poems are in the book or whether they are beautiful). The same can be
said about the EEG and fMRI. They provide information about which parts of
the brain are active, but they do not provide the fine detail of description, nor do
they provide the kind of psychological account that Wundt believed psychology
was able to provide.
There are two reasons why psychophysiology is important despite its limita-
tions. The first is that the demonstration that brain and psychological phenom-
ena are correlated has had a substantial impact on the perception of psychology
by the general public. The reader will recall from earlier chapters that the his-
tory of psychology is one where psychologists have felt the need to present what
they are doing as a science. The demonstration that there are correlates between
mental events and physiology shows that psychological phenomena are ‘real’
in the minds of those who believe that the only reality is physical. Of course,
students will be aware that there must be correlates of physiological events with
psychological events. Minds do not occur without bodies. So the impact of
what is now referred to as ‘neuroscience’ on how psychology is perceived by the
public may seem surprising, but it would be wrong to underestimate the social
impact neuroscience has had on the perception of psychology. Psychologists are
sometimes described as ‘cognitive neuroscientists’ when they do not even take
physiological measurements.
The second reason why psychophysiology – or neuroscience – is important
is that measurement techniques are improving. As techniques improve, more
and more detail is provided about what happens in the brain when thoughts or
tasks take place. Knowing where something happens in the brain is like know-
ing where a book is in a library. However, as the detail gets finer and finer, the
position of the book gets more and more accurate so that not only do we know
Psychology and physiology ◆ 125
that a book is in the poetry section, but which poet it is, and eventually which
poem it is. Some believe that eventually, with increasing accuracy of measure-
ment, it should be possible to associate particular thoughts with particular
events in the brain so that thoughts and indeed the whole of psychology can be
explained by physiology. The contribution of psychophysiology to psychology
and whether it is possible in practice or in principle to replace psychology with
physiology will be examined later in this chapter.
were lithium salts, chlorpromazine, and reserpine. There was still no biological
explanation for psychosis, and the antipsychotic effects of these drugs were dis-
covered by accident. For example, chlorpromazine comes from a class of drugs
originally developed for the dyeing industry. These dyes were used to stain spec-
imens that were examined under a microscope. Evidence from these specimens
seemed to indicate that the stains also had anti-microbial effects, though this
was later not confirmed. So chlorpromazine had biological effects, but it was
a drug looking for a treatment. Experimentation showed it had antipsychotic
effects (López-Muñoz et al., 2005).
Reserpine was another drug that was discovered as part of that pharma-
cological revolution, and again its discovery occurred without any theoretical
rationale as to why it should have antipsychotic effects. The chemical property
of reserpine is such that it depletes mono-amines and this was known by chem-
ists at the time. Because the experimental use of reserpine for psychosis also
seemed to cause depression – though the depressive effect of reserpine has been
questioned (Baumeister, Hawkins, & Uzelac, 2003), a theory was proposed that
depression was caused by lack of serotonin and dopamine. This hypothesis,
called the serotoninergic theory, led to the first serotonin-enhancing drugs for
treating depression in the 1960s. New types of serotonin-enhancing drugs were
developed over the years. So, unlike antipsychotics, antidepressants were devel-
oped on the basis of a theory of a biological cause of depression (Hillhouse &
Porter, 2015).
Serotonin-enhancing antidepressants are widely used today. Is the sero-
toninergic theory of depression correct? Certainly undergraduate students are
often taught that it is correct. However, several authors have questioned this
theory, in part because increases in levels of serotonin have a relatively small
effect on depression – at least 80% of the effectiveness of antidepressants is
due to the placebo effect (Kirsch, Moore, Scoboria, & Nicholls, 2002; Kirsch,
2014). Perhaps if depression were just a lack of serotonin, depression would
be less of a problem than it is today (see Chapter 1). So, like antipsychotics,
antidepressants affect the mind but the underlying theory remains less secure
than many believe.
Since the 1950s many different pharmacological agents have been developed
that alter the chemistry of the brain and hence alter a person’s p sychology –
including new recreational drugs. What does this demonstrate? It shows that
psychological phenomena have a biological basis. This demonstration is hardly
new. The biological basis for mental phenomena was assumed by Wundt.
Despite continuing problems, the fact that drugs do have effects on mental life
opens the possibility that mental illness could one day be treated successfully
with drugs and talking therapies would become a thing of the past. Equally,
some might argue that the failure to determine the chemical basis of mental
illness and find a definitive form of treatment, despite more than a century of
looking, might suggest that another type of theory and therapy, i.e., psychology,
is needed.
Psychology and physiology ◆ 127
Psychoneuroimmunology
The term psychoimmunology was coined by the psychiatrist George Solomon
(Shubla, Solomon, & Dosli, 1979), but the term soon changed to psychoneuro-
immunology – a change that reflects the status given to the term neuro but also
because the link between the brain and immune system was now included in
investigations. Whereas physiological psychology examined the effects of drugs
on the brain – and the effect of behaviour on chemicals in the brain – psycho-
neuroimmunology examined the relationship between the mind, the brain, and
the immune system. Amongst other things, the research shows the effect of stress
on the immune system and the effects of the immune system on the psychologi-
cal state. Research shows, for example, that stress increases inflammation in part
through an increase in pro-inflammatory cytokines (Segerstrom & Miller, 2004).
Cytokines are the messengers in the immune system that tell other parts of the
immune system that there is infection. The inflammatory effects of pro-inflamma-
tory cytokines exacerbate a number of disease processes, (e.g., cancer, heart dis-
ease, asthma, multiple sclerosis) with the result that there is now a well-established
relationship between stress and disease (Cohen, Janicki-Deverts, & Miller, 2007).
The pro-inflammatory cytokines also have effects on the brain and hence psy-
chological state, causing, amongst other things, fatigue and depression. One
might imagine that there should be a one-to-one relationship between particular
cytokines and particular mental states, but this has not been found to be the
case. It is not possible to say, for example, that depression is caused by one
pro-inflammatory cytokine and fatigue with another. What seems to happen is
that all pro-inflammatory cytokines increase with fatigue and depression, but
in a way that is not consistent across people. As with physiological psychology,
there is a relationship between physiology and psychology, but not one that is
very precise, and certainly not one that allows a one-to-one linking of psychol-
ogy with physiology.
Psychoneuroimmunology has played an important role in the story of phys-
iology of psychology, and has had an effect on the way psychology is viewed
by those outside the discipline of psychology. It showed that psychology was
relevant to the cause and mechanisms of somatic diseases, and not only men-
tal illness. Whereas psychophysiology and physiological psychology focussed
on the relation between the brain and psychology, psychoneuroimmunology
showed that the immune system was also part of the equation when trying to
understand the physiology that underpins psychology. The relevance of psy-
chology to the body therefore increased. Clinical psychology as a sub-discipline
dates from the early 20th century. The sub-discipline of health psychology is a
new kid on the block and developed in the 1980s.
Psychoneuroimmunology added the immune system to the psychology-
physiological relationship. Yet later research focussed on other parts of the
128 ◆ Psychology and physiology
body, such as the gut. The gut has been described as the ‘second brain’ as the gut
contains more nerves than the spinal cord, and the gut is also the primary site
of immune learning. A happy gut makes a happy mind and vice versa. Because
the health of the gut is associated with the gut biome (the gut microflora) the
gut biome of bacteria and viruses also has an effect on psychological state
(Ridaura & Belkaid, 2015). Other mind-body interactions such as kinaesthetic
feedback also feature in modern thinking so that the overall effect of these new
developments is that the psychology-physiology relationship should be consid-
ered in terms of the mind and body, not the mind and brain.
Reductionism
If one had perfect understanding of the physiology of the whole of the body,
would it then be possible to explain psychology in terms of physiology? And
if so, is it possible to replace psychology with physiology? Can psychology be
reduced to physiology? Reductionism is a type of relationship between two sci-
ences. The most commonly accepted definition of reductionism is that provided
by Nagel:
In practical terms, this means that reductionism is not about finding correla-
tions between physiological and psychological events. It is not about finding
that drugs have psychological effects. Reductionism concerns the relationship
between theories from two different disciplines, what Nagel refers to as the
primary and secondary science. Finding that a particular part of the brain
lights up when a person has a particular thought does not constitute reduc-
tionism. However, if all the theories of psychology can be shown to be the
logical consequences of theories of physiology, with the addition of some
‘bridging theories,’ then psychology can be reduced to physiology. Note that
the requirement for reduction is not that psychological theories should be the
logical consequence of physiological theories, but rather that they should be
the logical consequence with the addition of some additional theories that link
them together. For reduction to occur psychological theories must be capable
of deduction from physiological theories with the addition of a few extra
bridging theories (Nagel, 1998).
Reductionism is a metatheoretical assumption, an assumption that, when
applied to all science, is referred to as ‘the unity of science’ (Kemeny & Oppen-
heim, 1956). The unity of science concept is based on the assumption that
People as biological machines.
130 ◆ Psychology and physiology
Complementarity
Complementarity is a philosophical principle that owes its origins to quantum
mechanics. The basic idea is that it is the nature of reality that phenomena can
be explained only by using more than one incompatible theory. This principle
has been demonstrated in quantum mechanics in several ways that need not
concern us, but one that can be accepted as true. It is also possible to apply
the same principle of complementarity to the relationship between psychology
and physiology – even though neither are quantum theories. Methodologi-
cal complementarity was proposed by Kirsch and Hyland (1987) as a way of
understanding the relationship between biological and psychological theories.
Methodological complementarity is based on the following argument. When
discussing reductionism, what matters is the relationship between the two types
of theory. The exact nature of consciousness and of physical reality can be put
on one side. Psychological theories and biological theories describe different
types of entities, entities that have a different ontological status. ‘Ontological
status’ refers to the way something exists. So mind states and physiological
states exist in different ways.
Multiple uses of the same word can lead to confusion. The word cause
is used in more than one way. When used informally, the word cause simply
refers to the temporal sequence of events. If A is always preceded by B, then it
is possible to say that B causes A. This informal sense is used when events are
described as opposed to explained (as in inductive generalisations, see Chap-
ter 1). By contrast, if cause is used in an explanatory sense (i.e., in terms of a
theoretical mechanism that explains the observed events), then the term cause
also has the requirement of connectivity. Connectivity means that there is some
sort of connection that links the two events. For example, if ball A hits ball B so
that ball B rolls away, then it is the physical contact between the two balls that
is the connection. In the case of mental events, ideas can be connected in content
when one idea leads to another. So both physiological and psychological mecha-
nisms involve connectivity, though each has a different kind of connectivity.
When used as part of an explanatory mechanism, causal relationships can exist
only between entities that have the same ontological status – because causality
requires some form of connection between the causally connected events.
The conclusion from this is that, if the term cause is used in a formal
explanatory sense, then minds do not cause bodies nor bodies cause minds.
Although mind states and physiological status exist in different ways and can-
not cause each other, they can be identified with each other. That is, whenever
132 ◆ Psychology and physiology
there is a mind state there is a unique and corresponding body state (note the
opposite does not always occur – variation in physiology does not require varia-
tion in psychology). The statement that stress causes inflammation which then
causes disease (as suggested earlier) is a description of a causal sequence, not
an explanation. From a formal, explanatory perspective, psychological stress
is identified with a biological state that causes biological illness. The authors
of methodological complementarity argue that although ‘mind causing body’
and vice versa statements are commonplace, they confuse two different ways of
using the word cause – cause used in the informal and formal senses.
Methodological complementarity paints a picture of the relationship
between psychology and physiology that is very similar to Wundt’s idea of psy-
chophysical parallelism. Psychological events and physiological events occur in
parallel. Methodological complementarity adds the idea of identity relations
that occur from time to time in the mutual causal sequence of events. Every
psychological event must, in principle, be identified with a physiological event
as otherwise the assumption of materialism is broken. However, there may
be physiological events that are not represented psychologically, so not every
physiological event is identified with a psychological event.
Methodological complementarity (Kirsch & Hyland, 1987) was a simplifi-
cation of an earlier proposal of complementarity (Hyland, 1985) where there
were three parallel levels of explanation: physiological, mentalistic, and mecha-
nistic. The mentalistic and mechanistic levels provide a distinction between two
types of psychological explanation. The mechanistic level corresponds to the
type of constructs used in cognitive psychology (see Chapter 4), whereas the
mentalistic constructs are those used in humanistic psychology (see Chapter 8).
Methodological complementarity focussed on the mentalistic and physiological
relationship rather than considering the mechanistic concepts that were pro-
posed originally by Craik (1943).
Kirsch and Hyland argue that psychological description (i.e., mentalistic
description) cannot be reduced to physiological description, even if there is a
one-to-one relationship between psychological events and physiological events.
The reason is that a one-to-one relationship requires a bridging theory. A reduc-
tion is effected if the theories of the secondary science can be deduced from the
primary science with the addition of bridging theories. Although one cannot
Psychological level: X1 X3 X5
Physiological level Y1 Y2 Y3 Y4 Y5
A causal sequence of five events shown at the psychological (X) and physiological (Y) level with
identity relationship between three of the events. Not all physiological states can be identified
with a psychological state.
Psychology and physiology ◆ 133
know what bridging theories are going to be discovered in the future, there are
several possible reasons why bridging theories can never provide a logical (i.e.,
one-to-one) link between concepts in psychology and physiology. Two of these
reasons are described in the next section.
The word computer is revealing in this quote. The modularity approach to the
mind is one that treats humans as a kind of information processing system.
Computers are information processing systems. The underlying assumption
of the modularity approach is that an understanding of the function of a com-
puter aids the understanding of human cognitive function. It is not unusual for
new theories to be influenced by new technology. Desktop computers started
appearing in universities in the late 1970s and early 1980s, just at the time that
Fodor developed his theory of modularity. Fodor’s theory is influenced by the
structure and function of a computer. A computer’s hardware is related to its
software, but the hardware of a computer is not logically related to its software.
If physiology is equated with the hardware of a computer, psychology can be
equated with its software. The importance of computers in the emergence of
cognitive psychology was described in Chapter 4.
that emergent property did not have a ‘downward’ effect on the properties
of the lower level system. Sperry argued that emergent properties did have a
downward effect. The consequence was that mind could ‘cause the body,’ even
though the mind is not independent from the body.
Sperry illustrates this argument with the case of a wheel. A wheel has sev-
eral parts – there are the spokes, the hub, and the rim. When all these parts are
assembled in the correct way, then the wheel can roll along the ground. The
property of ‘rolling’ is an emergent property of the parts of the wheel that is
achieved only when the parts are in the right places. However, when the wheel
rolls along, the position of the individual spokes are determined by the emer-
gent property of rolling. The position of the parts is determined by the whole.
Sperry argues that emergent properties such as the mind can have a downward
effect on the physiology of the brain. Sperry’s argument seems to make sense. If
people engage in positive mental activities, such as meditation, then this leads
to positive physiological changes, such as a reduction in stress.
Sperry’s argument of cause between a higher and lower level – and more
generally, between levels – is inconsistent with the argument, presented in
methodological complementarity (see earlier) that, to avoid confusion, the
term cause should be used in only in the formal sense, the sense where there is
connectivity between events. In Sperry’s example of a wheel, if the term cause
is used in the formal sense, then the spokes of the wheel are caused to move by
their two attachment points. In methodological complementarity, the idea that
‘mind causes brain’ is represented as identity relations, and this form of repre-
sentation can easily accommodate the idea of emergent properties. The brain
has emergent properties that are identified with psychological states. The state
of the brain that generates those emergent properties has a causal effect within
the brain. In summary, there is a compelling argument for treating emergent
states at different levels as causally independent but connected by identify rela-
tions, even though the state at the lower level creates the emergent property that
may defy description.
Explanation explained
There is a difference between description and explanation (see Chapter 1). A
description of events is provided when an account of those events is given only
by observation terms and words describing how those observations are related.
136 ◆ Psychology and physiology
Biopsychosocial interactionism
The term biopsychosocial was introduced by George Engel in 1978 (Engel,
1978). Engel’s use of the term was purely practical and was aimed at medical
education. Medical doctors are trained in biomedicine – also referred to as the
medical model. Disease is understood and treated in terms of pathophysiology.
Engel worked within that medical model but wanted to alert physicians and
138 ◆ Psychology and physiology
surgeons to the psychological needs of patients. Put simply, his message was
this: Think also about patients as people and think about their psychological
and social circumstances. Engel suggested several levels that were relevant to
treating the patient – levels that are different from but bear some relation to
the levels cited in the unity of science hypothesis. Engel’s levels were commu-
nity, family, two-person, person, nervous system, organ system, tissue, cell, and
molecule.
Psychological care has always featured in good treatment by doctors and
nurses, but its recognition was certainly stimulated by Engel’s use of a catchy
word. Subsequent to Engel, the term biopsychosocial interactionism has been
used to describe a theory where psychosocial and biological elements are
included. Several biopsychosocial theories have been proposed, and in each case
the end state, typically some form of health variable, is affected by both biologi-
cal and psychological variables.
This idea of applying different types of theory to the same context is also
not new. It is an application of the idea of methodological complementarity
described earlier in this chapter. Using this approach, there are two separate
types of theory, one biological and one psychological, and each provides infor-
mation about the treatment of the patient. One of the criticisms of biopsycho-
social interaction is that it is not a theory (Pilgrim, 2015). It does not integrate
biology and psychology at a theoretical level. It is simply the combination of
two different theories in the same context. In biopsychosocial interactionist
theories, psychological and biological processes add, they do not interact.
Biopsychosocial interactionism suffers from a theoretical problem. At an
empirical level, it is clear that mind variables and body variables interact sta-
tistically. The effect of psychological stress on the body depends on the state of
the body. A body that is stressed (high autonomic arousal) will exhibit a greater
reaction to stress than a body that is not stressed. So, at an empirical level,
minds and bodies are interactive rather than additive. However, if mind states
do not cause body states or vice versa then it is not possible to represent the
observed statistical interaction in terms of theory.
The solution to this problem is to propose another theoretical level, a level
that intervenes between the biological and psychological levels of description
(Hyland, 2017). This intervening level can be described in different ways but
most usefully as a level of information. Both psychological and biological events
can be identified with the events in the information level. So, events that cannot
be causally connected because they are different levels of description and exist
in different ways, can be connected once those events are represented in a com-
mon level of description.
The intermediary level in Figure 6.2 is similar in many respects to the type
of theoretical construct that is characteristic of cognitive psychology, that
is, the mechanistic level of person variables (see Chapter 4) (Hyland, 1985).
There are, however, two differences between the way mechanistic concepts
are commonly used in cognitive psychology and how they should be used in
Psychology and physiology ◆ 139
Psychological level: X1 X2 X5
Intermediary level Z1 Z3 Z4 Z5
Physiological level Y1 Y2 Y4 Y5
FIGURE 6.2
The intermediary or computational level of information that is between the
psychological and physiological levels. The intermediary level provides theoretical
concepts (Z3) that are unique to that level.
Summary
Physiology plays an important part in the history of psychology. Modern psy-
chology emerged from individuals who were trained in physiology, and the
relationship between these two disciplines has continued and expanded to the
present day. Scientists working on the relationship between psychology and
physiology can focus on different aspects of this relationship. Some focus on
measurement, some on intervention, some on only the brain, and some on the
brain, immune system, and other parts of the body.
140 ◆ Psychology and physiology
Essay questions
1 What does neuroscience add to psychology?
2 What evidence is there for and against the claim that drugs will one day
replace the need for psychotherapy for mental illness?
3 Compare and contrast the different meanings of the term biopsychosocial
interactionism.
7
How has the heredity-environment
controversy been represented in the
history of psychology and how is it
informed by the person-situation
debate and modern understanding
of epigenetics?
142 ◆ The heredity-environment controversy
Nature
The idea of heredity is not new. Since recorded history, people have noted that
children resemble their parents, as do the offspring of cattle, dogs, and cats.
It takes only a small leap of imagination from the observation that body type
is inherited to the conclusion that psychological characteristics are inher-
ited. Madness is a psychological characteristic. The concept of madness as a
hereditary characteristic appears in several works of literature. For example,
in Charlotte Brontë’s novel, Jane Eyre, Mr Rochester marries Bertha Mason
but is unaware that there was ‘madness in the family.’ Bertha becomes mad
and is hidden away and confined to her room. The story revolves round this
hidden secret of Mr Rochester – that he is married but wants to marry Jane.
Madness in families was often hidden because it affected the marriage pros-
pects of other family members. It comes as no surprise that scientists in the
19th century assumed that psychological characteristics were influenced by
heredity.
Francis Galton (1822–1911) was born in Birmingham, England, and
was related to Charles Darwin – his mother was the half-sister of Charles
Darwin’s father. Like William James, Galton was profoundly influenced by
Darwin’s The Origin of Species (Pearson, 1914, 1924). Darwin’s theory
is based on an assumption of heredity. Natural selection occurs because
offspring resemble their parents. Galton wrote a book entitled Hereditary
Genius in 1869 (Galton, 1869), some ten years after Darwin had published
his Origin of Species. Galton put forward the argument that genius, like
any other human or animal characteristic, was inherited. Consequently, if
genius was an inherited characteristic, then genius should run in families.
In order to demonstrate that genius was inherited Galton showed that the
people who achieved eminence (i.e., whose contributions were recognised
by others) tended to come from about 300 families. Galton established an
anthropometric laboratory in 1884 at the International Health Exhibition
in London where, for a small fee, people could have their ability measured.
This very early type of intelligence test relied on some simple tests such as
reaction time and sensory acuity, as Galton assumed a simple physiological
basis underlying all ability.
Paying participants
Nowadays, psychologist pay the participants or provide some other form
of inducement for participants to take part in studies. Galton actually
charged people. Why did that work then and would it work now?
144 ◆ The heredity-environment controversy
Racism in psychology
Racism was commonplace in the 19th century. Slavery was abolished in Britain
in 1833 and in the USA in 1865, but this does not prevent assumptions about
racial differences. Racism is based on the assumption of genetic differences
between races which confers superiority of one race over another. In Europe
and America, racist beliefs were applied in particular to Jews and people of
African heritage. Winston (1998, p. 28) writes that “The widespread antisemi-
tism in the United States between the world wars is well documented . . . as are
the discriminatory practices of universities in admissions and hiring.” Edward
G Boring (1889–1968) was one of a small number of people who helped place
Jewish students and academics (not always successfully) into American Univer-
sities when the Nazi party in Germany banned Jews from universities. Boring
had to certify that the Jews did not have ‘Jewish characteristics’ (Winston,
1998). However, feelings towards African Americans were considerably more
negative to the extent that black psychologists were more or less non-existent
until the 1960s. African Americans were segregated from European Americans
in parts of the USA until the 1960s, and were subject to unequal treatment in
many other ways.
The heredity-environment controversy ◆ 145
assumptions about humanity and biases that are sometime implicit rather than
explicit. It should be said, however, that the current consensus amongst psycholo-
gists is that there is no genetically conferred difference in intelligence between
races of humans.
Nurture
Although some psychologists had racist views, many others took an entirely
different approach and emphasised the importance of nurture. The stron-
gest environmentalist view (i.e., supporting the nurture position) came from
behaviourists.
The following quotation from J. B. Watson is repeated from Chapter 4.
Watson and other behaviourists assumed there was no dividing line in terms
of psychological processes between animals and humans. If there are no
differences between animals and humans, then there can certainly be no
differences between different humans, whether or not they come from dif-
ferent races.
Although behaviourists took an extreme nurture position, other early psy-
chologists also favoured the effects of the environment over heredity. Witmer
(1907) first assumed that mental illness was due to heredity, as did others at that
time, but changed his mind, believing that mental illness had an environmental
cause (see Chapter 3). The switch from a nature to nurture interpretation of
mental illness had an impact on the way mentally ill patients were treated. If
it is the nature of some people that they are mentally ill, then nothing can be
done about it. However, if mental illness is caused by nurture, then there is the
possibility that nurture can cure it.
What is inherited?
If a puff of air is blown into a person’s eye, the person blinks. This is a reflex
response. Everyone does it. It is inherited. Non-human animals inherit many
complex patterns of behaviour, and these are called instinctive behaviours.
The heredity-environment controversy ◆ 147
For example, when ducklings hatch out of the egg, they become imprinted on
the first moving object. That is instinct. Every duckling behaves in this way.
Humans differ from animals. Apart from reflexes, they do not exhibit instinc-
tive stereotypical behaviour.
Rather than inheriting stereotypical behaviours, humans inherit capacities to
behave in particular ways. Inherited capacities have evolutionary advantages in that
they enhance the ability to adapt to changing environments – and humans evolved
in a changing environment caused by periods of glaciation (the ice ages that started
about six million years ago). Human capacities can be treated in two ways: capaci-
ties that are shared between all people and capacities that differ between people.
A problem
The following statement was in an earlier paragraph: People who have the
capacity to learn faster will develop into people who are different from
those who learn slower. Dig a little deeper and you will see that this state-
ment is an over-simplification. People with different capacities to learn
will develop into people who are different in a learning-rich environment.
But what about a learning-poor environment? In a learning-poor environ-
ment, the ability of the genetic capacity to affect outcome will be reduced.
Heredity and environment interact. The relative contribution of heredity
and environment depends on the type of environment. More detail about
this interaction will be provided later in this chapter under the topic of
epigenetics.
Behaviour
It can be seen from Figure 7.1 that behaviour is affected by the situation (or
environment) in two ways. The situation affects behaviour indirectly through
its past contribution to personality and the situation affects behaviour directly
by its present influence on behaviour. It follows that the more behaviour is
determined by events in the present, the less it can be affected by heredity,
irrespective of the relative contributions of heredity and environment to dispo-
sitional factors such as personality or intelligence.
In 1957, Lee Cronbach (1957) wrote a paper with the title “The Two Dis-
ciplines of Scientific Psychology” in which he drew attention to a split between
two types of psychological research. One type used correlational methods to
examine differences in people’s behaviour that were (assumed) consistent across
situations. The other type used experimental methods to examine differences
across situations that were (assumed) consistent across people. One focussed on
the person; the other on the situation. This distinction remains to today. Social
psychologists research the effects of different social environments on people and
publish the research in social psychology journals. Personality psychologists
research how people differ in the same environment and publish in personality
journals.
Cronbach argued that this split in psychology was unhelpful and that
a combination of the experimental and correlational methods was needed.
For example, experimental methods will reveal that one treatment is better
than another when people are considered as a group. However, it may be
that some people respond better to one treatment and other people better
to the other treatment. Cronbach – and others – argued the concept of the
‘best treatment’ was based on a false assumption and suggested instead that
it is necessary to determine which treatment is best for whom. Cronbach’s
suggestion that correlational and experimental methods should be combined
reflects earlier theoretical work by Kurt Lewin (1943a) who interpreted
behaviour resulting from an interaction between the person and situation.
The idea of integrating personality psychology and social psychology eventu-
ally became accepted. The Journal of Personality and Social Psychology was
first published in 1965.
The heredity-environment controversy ◆ 151
Personalised medicine
Despite Cronbach’s logical argument against ‘the best treatment’ concept,
that idea still dominates medicine, and to some extent clinical psychology.
Recently, ‘personalised medicine’ provides an alternative to the assump-
tion that there is a best treatment for any disease. Personalised medicine
is defined as “treatments targeted to the needs of individual patients on
the basis of genetic, biomarker, phenotypic, or psychosocial characteristics
that distinguish a given patient from other patients with similar clinical
presentations” (Agusti et al., 2016, p. 410).
If behaviour is influenced by both the situation and personality, then this leads
to an obvious question: Which is more important? The person-situation debate
arose over this question. Initially, there was an absence of consensus with per-
sonality theorists claiming that personality was more important, and social and
experimental psychologists suggesting that the situation was more important.
Consensus was reached by a position known as ‘interactionism.’ Behaviour is
the result of an interaction between the person and the situation (Magnusson &
Endler, 1977; Epstein & O’brien, 1985).
The consensus that persons and situations interacted – i.e., interactionism –
has implications for the heredity-environment controversy. In both debates
there is ambiguity about what exactly is being explained. In both debates it is
behaviour that is being explained, but behaviour can be described in different
ways. The behaviour under consideration is crucial to both debates.
The conclusion from the person-situation debate is that both the personality
and psychologists and social psychologists were correct, but they were claim-
ing different things and are therefore correct in different ways. They are cor-
rect depending on what is meant by behaviour. Does the word behaviour refer
to a single instance of behaviour, or is it an aggregation of many behaviours?
The consensus reached was that if one tries to explain a single behaviour, then
in most cases that single behaviour is explained entirely by the situation, and
personality plays only a minor role. However, if one tries to explain an aver-
age of several different behaviours across different situations, then personality
does indeed explain that behaviour. So personality explains general trends in
behaviour but is very poor at explaining individual behaviours. The situation
explains individual behaviours but is poor at explaining trends in behaviour. If
one considers that personality traits are defined in terms of ‘behaviours that are
consistent across situations and time’ then it is not surprising that this is exactly
what personality does. Some behaviours are consistent across situations and
time, some are not. Those behaviours that are consistent across situations and
time make up personality.
152 ◆ The heredity-environment controversy
Not only does the answer to the person-situation debate depend on whether
the behaviour is an aggregation or not, the result also depends on the particu-
lar behaviour. Consider how people respond when driving and they see traffic
lights. Everyone stops at red, and goes at green. The behaviour at traffic lights
is not determined by personality or intelligence. However, the results from a
maths test result will differ between people as a function of mathematical abil-
ity, and behaviour at parties will differ as a function of sociability.
The non-linear interaction of person and situation (NIPS) model provides
a theoretical framework for understanding whether situations and persons
play a greater or lesser role in determining behaviour (Blum, Rauthmann,
Göllner, Lischetzke, & Schmitt, 2018). According to this model, situations
can be described as either strong or weak, where strong or weak refers to the
affordance of the situation. In common sense language, the term affordance
means the situation is ‘telling’ the person something. For example, a red traffic
light has a strong affordance – it signals that you should stop. There is only one
behaviour associated with the red traffic light, namely stopping. The red traffic
light is a strong situation. A mouse that appears suddenly in front of you, on
the other hand, can lead to a number of behavioural responses. You could jump
on a chair, run away, try and catch it, or simply stand still and watch what it
does. The mouse is a weak situation. According to the NIPS model, in strong
situations, personality is unimportant in determining behaviour. Everyone stops
at a traffic light irrespective of their personality. And if a person does not stop –
for example, a bank robber fleeing from police – then it is not personality that
is determining their behaviour at that particular moment in time. However, in
weak situations, personality plays a much greater role. People high in neuroti-
cism may behave differently to the mouse compared to those low in neuroticism.
The NIPS model also makes a distinction between strong and weak persons.
Strong persons tend to behave in the same way irrespective of the situation. For
example, some people are always aggressive or always non-aggressive what-
ever the situation. Such persons are described as strong. Others are sometimes
aggressive or not depending on the situation. Such persons are described as
weak. So, if a person exhibits cross-situationally consistent behaviour, then they
are described as strong and for such people personality has a greater impact on
behaviour that those weak persons whose behaviour varies with the situation.
The conclusion from NIPS therefore is that it is meaningless to talk about the
relative contribution of persons and situations to behaviour because it depends
on the person and situation.
There is one more piece to the jigsaw that needs putting in place, and that
is an explanation of the word interactionism. Interactionism is the resolution
of the person-situation debate. The person and situation do not add to produce
behaviour: They interact. What this means in practice can be illustrated by the
following example of the interaction between neuroticism and stressors. A per-
son high in neuroticism shows a large autonomic response to a mild stressor,
but shows no autonomic response in the absence of any stressor. A person low
The heredity-environment controversy ◆ 153
they eat – has a cumulative effect on their body mass. However, in the case of
intelligence, the contribution of heredity increases with age. Results using twin
studies show that the heritability of intelligence at age 5 years is estimated as
0.22, by age 16 it is 0.62, and at age 50 years it is 0.80 (Sauce & Matzel, 2018).
The reason is that people high in cognitive ability seek situations of cognitive
stimulation over the lifespan, and as they do so, more and more cognitively ori-
ented genes become switched on. The environment is not random. People seek
environments that are consistent with their genes, so the environment becomes
more matched to their particular genotype. Gene-environment interactions are
not only passive; they also are the consequence of an active process of behav-
ioural choice.
Trans-generational effects
One final factor must be added to the heredity-environment debate. There is evi-
dence from animal models, and to some extent humans, that epigenetic effects –
i.e., the switching on of genes – can be passed from one generation to the next.
These effects are called trans-generational epigenetic effects. There is growing
evidence that environmental influences can be passed from one generation to
156 ◆ The heredity-environment controversy
Summary
The heredity-environment controversy has been motivated by values and debate
about the advantages or disadvantages of different political and social systems,
and in particular privileges provided by inheritance.
How much is behaviour determined by heredity and how much by the
environment? Percentage estimates of the relative contribution of heredity and
environment to intelligence are based on twin studies, where the methodology
creates a bias in favour of heredity. However, the main problem with hered-
ity-environment controversy is not empirical but conceptual. The controversy
is based on the assumption that a certain percentage of variance of behaviour
is due to heredity and the remainder to the environment. This assumption is
untrue as the relative contribution of heredity and environment depends on a
variety of different factors. The correct conclusion of the heredity-environment
controversy is that ‘it depends’ (Sauce & Matzel, 2018).
Essay questions
1 What is the person-debate and what are its implications for the heredity-
environment controversy?
2 What are the advantages and disadvantages of twin studies in studying
heritability?
3 What is epigenetics and what is its relevance to the heredity-environment
controversy?
8
How do psychologists measure and
explain the fact that in some ways
everyone is unique?
160 ◆ Everyone is unique
In some ways everyone is the same. In some ways everyone is different but like
some other people. In some ways everyone is unique.
Social and experimental psychology and many other branches of psychol-
ogy provide an account of why people behave in the same way in different
situations. Personality psychology and the psychology of individual differences
provide an account of why people behave differently in the same situation. It is
a self-evident truth that in some ways everyone is unique. Uniqueness is one of
the ideas explored in humanistic psychology. Humanistic psychology developed
in the late 1940s and 1950s (i.e., in the dying days of the empire of behaviour-
ism and before the dominance of cognitive psychology) describing itself as
‘the third force in psychology’ – the other two forces being behaviourism and
psychoanalysis. This chapter describes the methodology used by humanistic
psychologists, some of their achievements, and its relevance today.
may fall at different places on that scale, given a large enough sample, some
people must be at the same point on that scale as other people.
Windelband contrasted nomothetic science with idiographic science. Like
nomothetic science, idiographic science has laws or theories, but different theo-
ries are needed for different situations. The idiographic approach lacks the uni-
versality of laws that is a feature of nomothetic science. Each event in history is
unique, so it is possible to treat history idiographically as well as nomothetically
where the latter describes general trends (Lyman & O’Brien, 2004). Equally,
each person is unique so it is possible to treat psychology idiographically as
well as nomothetically. Each person requires a unique form of description and
explanation, but it is an explanation or theory that follows the rules of science
in being falsifiable.
Humanistic psychology is not the only approach within psychology that
assumes the uniqueness of the individual. Hermeneutical psychology is also
predicated on the assumption that each person is unique. However, hermeneuti-
cal psychology rejects the scientific rational that is accepted by humanistic psy-
chologists. The hermeneutical approach to uniqueness is discussed in Chapter 9.
Measuring uniqueness
The concept of a trait forms the basis of modern personality theories – hence the
term personality trait. Neuroticism, extraversion, openness, conscientiousness
and agreeableness are all traits. So are the traits of aggression, silliness, and lazi-
ness. Traits are almost invariably treated as a nomothetic concept in the sense
that every trait applies to everyone. For example, everyone can be placed some-
where along a dimension of neuroticism. Everyone can be placed somewhere
along a trait of aggression. Each trait dimension applies to everyone.
each person can be described by an array of traits that may differ from the array
of traits used to describe someone else. Each person has their own unique (or
reasonably unique) array of traits. When a trait applies to a person, then that
person can be represented on that trait with a number. So Allport’s approach is
both idiographic and quantitative.
The idiographic approach to traits is based on the assumption that some-
times it is the situation rather than a trait that determines behaviour. A similar
idea is found in the non-linear interaction of person and situation (NIPS) model
that was described in Chapter 7. According to NIPS, strong people exhibit the
same trait in different situations. Weak people vary their behaviour according
to the situation. However, there is a difference between Allport’s idiographic
traits and NIPS. In the case of NIPS, the terms strong or weak people refer to
a tendency that occurs across traits; it is a nomothetic concept. By contrast, in
Allport’s idiographic trait theory, a person can be weak in regard to one trait
but strong with regard to another.
Despite being theoretically plausible, Allport’s idiographic approach to
traits never caught on. It is so much easier to explain personality in terms of
dimensions shared by everyone rather than dimensions that are unique to each
individual. In addition, personality theorists argue that people are in fact rea-
sonably consistent across situations for the higher order traits, such as the big
five traits of neuroticism, extraversion, openness, conscientiousness, and agree-
ableness, so it is meaningful to treat them nomothetically. Of course, they would
say that wouldn’t they! Personality theory is based on a nomothetic assumption.
The NIPS model would suggest that consistency of behaviour across situations
applies only to some people, namely, strong people. Perhaps both are correct to
some degree. Students should come to their own conclusions.
A whale
A rat
A trout
In what way are two of these objects similar and one different? There are several
possible answers, but suppose you replied with this:
In this example, ‘mammal’ is the similarity pole of the construct and ‘fish’ the
contrast pole. The construct is mammal versus fish.
However another possible answer is this:
In this second example, ‘lives in water’ is the similarity pole and ‘lives on land’
the contrast pole. The construct is lives on water versus lives on land.’
If students are asked to compare a whale, rat and trout, they usually create
many more constructs, e.g.,
A construct is like a theory. It has a focus in the sense that it applies to a par-
ticular kind of context. For example, the construct mammal versus fish applies
only to animals. When you see an animal, it is reasonable to classify it in terms
of whether it is a mammal or not. When you see a plant, you are unlikely to ask
yourself the question, “is this a mammal or not?”
Kelly’s theory suggests that
◆◆ Finding out about someone’s constructs tell us what that person is like
and how they will respond to different situations.
Kelly provided a counselling service to students and school children, and to help
in this he developed a method for understanding a person’s construct system.
He called this method the ‘repertory grid test’ or ‘rep test’ for short. Because
many student problems arise from their interactions with others, constructs
relating to the way a person views other people are particularly important.
1 Write down a list of six people you know (i.e., six real people such as
friends and relatives). For example, this might be Bob, Mary, Peter, Sue,
Alison, and Roger.
2 Take the first three people in the list, and ask yourself in what way two
are similar and one different? For example, you might say that Bob and
Mary have a sense of humour and Peter hasn’t.
3 Write down the similarity pole (the way two are similar) and the contrast
pole (the way the third person is different). For example, this would be
‘sense of humour versus no sense of humour.’
4 Now take another three people from the list. For example, this might be
Peter, Sue, and Alison.
5 Ask yourself again, in what way are two similar and one different? You
might say that Peter and Sue are old and Alison is young.
6 Write down the poles of the construct again, for example, ‘old versus
young.’
7 Now take a further three people and repeat the process. It doesn’t matter
which three people you compare as long as it is a different combination.
Continue doing this until you have made at least ten comparisons, or
until you are generating no new constructs.
Having created your list of constructs, now change roles and imagine you are
the examining psychologist. The examining psychologist gains insight into the
constructs that lie behind the words used by the client. The examining psy-
chologist uses this insight to advise the client. If you are continuing with this
exercise, you will be able to give yourself some sound advice.
First, the examining psychologist needs to find out how many constructs
the client has. Sometimes the client uses different words for constructs that
have similar meanings. For example, a client might present three sets of
similarity and contrast poles: ‘intelligent versus not intelligent’ and ‘educated
versus not educated’ and ‘thick versus bright.’ A moment’s reflection will show
Everyone is unique ◆ 165
that these different words refer to one underlying construct dealing with
intelligence, so the examining psychologist should interpret these as one. The
more constructs the person has, the more adaptable the person is in a complex
world, so people who have many constructs usually do better in social contexts
than those who have few.
Second, the examining psychologist interprets how the person construes the
world in order to give advice. This involves the psychologist trying to interpret
how the client views the world the world about them from the constructs that
have been produced. Again, it is easiest to understand this with an example.
Imagine you are an examining psychologist and have been presented by the
following constructs of a client:
The client’s constructs relate to issues of perceived criticism and being criticised
by others. The client has issues concerning self-confidence. The psychologist
will also note that a therapist will be judged using exactly the same constructs
as the client uses for other people. The psychologist will have to make a special
effort not to appear critical and provide a way of helping the client become less
defensive.
Kelly helped clients by advising them to try using other constructs. In prac-
tice, this meant asking clients to pretend to be someone else in a therapy session
and try out what it feels like to take the role of someone else – hence, the name
of his therapy, fixed role therapy. Kelly’s method and theory show that it is
possible to measure the mind, but at the same time accept there is an aspect of
uniqueness to every person.
(Bourne & Jankowicz, 2018). The rep test has been used to find out what
constructs people use when they come to a museum, to help in the design
and management of museums (Caldwell & Coshall, 2002). In these cases, the
researchers refer to the ‘rich meaning’ that the technique provides, and in each
case people, ordinary people, are presented with three buildings, three organisa-
tions, three museums, or whatever is the focus, and asked in what way two are
similar and one different.
The use of the rep test in applied contexts can be contrasted with the equiva-
lent use of the semantic differential (Osgood, Suci, & Tannenbaum, 1967). The
semantic differential is based on the assumption that everyone uses the same
dimensions of judgement. These dimensions are:
The semantic differential is based on the assumption that everyone uses the
same constructs when judging objects, and uses the same constructs irrespective
of the object being judged. Personal construct theory is based on the assumption
that people use different constructs when judging objects. To some extent both
views are true. To some extent people have common characteristics when judg-
ing objects. However, the ability of the rep test to find out how different types
of constructs are used in different situations enables the technique to provide
a more situation specific analysis of the attribution of meaning. It is the situ-
ational specificity of the rep test that makes it most attractive to those working
in applied contexts. Furthermore, if different people use similar constructs to
judge a particular type of object, then it is perfectly possible to use those con-
structs to develop a scale that is used nomothetically. Idiographic research can
inform nomothetic research.
Origins of self-actualisation
Maslow was born in Brooklyn, New York, and was the eldest child in a
large family of immigrant Russian Jews who lived close to the border with
Poland. The following story is told of Rabbi Zusya (unknown–1800) of
Hanipol, Poland: When he was dying he expressed concern about meeting
God and said to those about him “When I reach the next world, God will
not ask me, ‘Why were you not Moses?’ Instead, he will ask me, ‘Why
were you not Zusya?’” Why were you not the person you were meant to
be? It is highly likely that Maslow would have known about Rabbi Zusya
as well as the Hasidic tradition that Zusya represented. Hassidism includes
two ideas that are common in humanistic psychology. One is the joy of
living; the other is the acceptance of suffering.
Frankl suggested that the human super-ordinate goal was to find meaning in
life. For him, self-actualisation meant meaning in life. Frankl distinguished
three categories of the meaning of life.
170 ◆ Everyone is unique
Rogers believed that humans are basically good. They are good when they
are free or mature and they are only bad when they are neurotic. This idea of
the fundamental goodness of Rogers’ approach can be contrasted with that of
Freud who thought people were driven by fundamentally bad instincts and only
good because they were constrained to be good by society.
Rogers adopted the idea, proposed by Maslow, that people strive towards
self-actualisation and believed that self-actualisation always manifested itself
positively in one way or another. It is only when people are neurotic that they
deviate from this pattern of goodness. Unkindness and cruelty are a deviation
from the natural human state, not part of it.
Rogers noticed from his clinical practice that clients often referred to them-
selves. They would say things like, “I have not been feeling myself recently” or
“I am not happy with the way I am.” Rogers inferred that the self is something
that is perceived. The self is an organised conceptual gestalt. It is not made
up from lots of different bits and pieces, but is organised as a whole. Further-
more, this whole that is the self can grow and change and yet retain the same
identity. The student applying to go to university is the same person when they
graduate. The phenomenal field of the self remains the same.
172 ◆ Everyone is unique
The self, also known as the actual self or the real self, refers to the way cli-
ents describe themselves as they are now.
The ideal self refers to the self clients would like to be.
One aim of Rogerian therapy is to reduce the discrepancy between the self and
ideal self. The therapy is linked to the idea of uniqueness of people: The self that
is right for one individual may be different from the self that is right for another.
Rogers’ aim in providing therapy was to help a person become the person they
really are and be satisfied with the person they really are.
Measuring self-ideal–self-discrepancy
The Q-sort technique, used by Rogers, is based on 100 statements that
describe a person, for example, the statements might be ‘am generally
happy’ or ‘get upset easily.’ The statements are written on cards. The client
is first asked to sort the statements into two piles, those that are ‘like me’
and those that are ‘unlike me.’ The cards are then shuffled and the client
is asked to sort the statements into two more piles, those that are ‘like the
ideal me’ and those that are ‘unlike the ideal me.’ The number of differ-
ences in the card allocations between the first sorting and second sorting
determines the discrepancy between the self and ideal self.
Everyone is unique ◆ 173
Self-consistency or congruence
Rogers adds one more idea to the distinction of the self versus the ideal self.
The client develops the concept of self on the basis of experiences about the
self. For example, if whenever you met someone, they said to you ‘you are
amazingly beautiful,’ you would begin to believe that you are amazingly
beautiful. The concept of congruence is about the relationship between the
perception of yourself, and the objective data with which you are presented.
So, for example, if everyone says ‘you are amazingly beautiful’ and you
believe that you are beautiful, then that is congruence. But if everyone says
‘you are amazingly beautiful’ and you believe that you are ugly, then that
is incongruence. A modern and more easily understood example of incon-
gruence is provided by anorexia. People with anorexia think they are fat,
whereas the objective data – and what everyone else is saying – is that they
are very thin.
Rogers believed that incongruence resulted from childhood experiences and
was unhealthy because it creates a distorted sense of reality, a distorted sense that
can lead to anxiety and depression. Rogers distinguished two ways of bringing
up children: with unconditional positive regard and with conditional positive
regard.
Children brought up with conditional positive regard are disciplined with
the withdrawal of love as a means of punishment. That is, when the child is
naughty, the parent becomes distant and unloving. Children brought up with
unconditional positive regard are not disciplined with withdrawal of love as a
means of punishment. When the children are naughty the children are disci-
plined in one way or another, but the children always believe that they as indi-
viduals are loved – it is the behaviour not the individual that is being punished.
Rogers believed that conditional positive regard was very damaging as children
brought up in this way would learn to believe a reality – the parent’s reality –
that is not their own. That is, in order to regain the parent’s regard, the child
learns to distort reality.
Other selves
Later authors have developed Rogers’ theory further with additional self-related
concepts. Higgins (1987) introduced the distinction between the ideal self (what
you would like to be) and the ought self (what others would like you to be). The
ought self is particularly relevant to feelings of dissatisfaction a person has that
comes from social comparison. Higgins suggests that the discrepancy between
the self and ideal self leads to depression whereas discrepancy between the self
and ought self leads to anxiety. Another approach taken by Markus and Nurius
(1986) is that there are several possible selves, including the past self and future
self. Although people are free to create many sorts of possible self, the self they
create is bound by their circumstances. Later authors have emphasised the mal-
leability of the self concept. This idea of malleability is also found in the fixed
174 ◆ Everyone is unique
role therapy of George Kelly (see earlier in this chapter). A person can become
a different person by choosing to become a different person.
Therapy
Rogers (1957) suggested that six conditions were needed for therapy to be effec-
tive. This is how Rogers defined them:
Note how Rogers’ definition uses jargon in a way that gives the impression of
a science. ‘Two persons in psychological contact’ simply means that two people
are communicating in some way. Although Rogers presents his theory as scien-
tific, he was aware of the tension between being scientific and a purely human
sense of understanding other people, a tension he discussed in 1955 (Rogers,
1955). During its history, psychology has needed to present itself as a science
in order to gain acceptability within a culture that is dominated by science.
Humanistic psychologists maintained the scientific status of psychology despite
the fact that each person is unique. The tension, between the purely intuitive
and the scientific, is discussed in Chapter 9 in the context of hermeneutical psy-
chology, an approach that rejects the scientific model entirely.
Rogers originally called his therapy non-directive therapy because he wanted
to emphasise the fact that the therapist is not directing the client to a particular
fixed goal. However, he found that other therapists were not as successful as he
was, the reason being that non-directive was being interpreted as disinterested
or even stand-offish. So, in his later writing, Rogers called his therapy client
centred therapy to emphasise the unconditional positive regard and empathic
understanding that was central to his therapy.
Rogers’ client centred approach underpins the common factors or contex-
tual model of psychotherapy (see Chapter 5). The description given by Rogers
Everyone is unique ◆ 175
earlier about what is needed for effective psychotherapy is very similar to that
described by Frank and Frank (1991) and quoted in Chapter 5. The underlying
assumption shared by Rogers as well as the common factors model is that it
is the therapeutic context that is therapeutic rather than anything specific that
happens in the therapy session. Rogers stresses the importance of the relation-
ship in psychotherapy. The common factors model includes other components,
including the cognitive component of expectancy.
Given the evidence supporting the common factors or contextual model
in contrast to specific models of psychotherapy (Wampold, 2013), one might
wonder why specific models of psychotherapy, such as cognitive behaviour
therapy (Beck, 1967) are more popular and more respected than contextual
models. The reason has to do with one of the weaknesses of the contextual
model, namely that it does not provide an explanation consistent with the
dominant paradigm that symptoms are caused by faults and removed by the
correction of faults.
The dominant paradigm owes its origins to modern western medicine,
which is based on the assumption that symptoms are caused by diseases that
are caused by specific faults (pathophysiology) in the body (see Chapter 5). The
contextual model has difficulty answering this question: What is wrong with
the client and how does the context help? Rogers explains that unconditional
regard might have been lacking in the client’s life, and that the therapist’s
unconditional positive regard helps. But why positive regard has this thera-
peutic function is never fully explained. In the case of response expectancy
theory (Kirsch, 1985), which is one of the other components of the contextual
model, expectancy fails to explain the underlying pathology even though it
provides an explanation of benefit. The components of the contextual model
provide only a partial account of fault and the correction of fault. By contrast,
cognitive behaviour theory (Beck, 1967) explains symptoms as resulting from
erroneous cognitions and that it is the change in these cognitions that then
produces therapeutic benefit. The cognitive behaviour model is based on the
assumption of a specific form of fault that is corrected by a specific interven-
tion, and in this regard is consistent with the assumptions of modern western
medicine, as are psychoanalytic explanations of psychopathology (see Chap-
ter 5). The weakness of the contextual model, the model most associated with
Rogers, is not that it doesn’t work nor that it is inconsistent with the evidence.
Its weakness – if it is a weakness – is that is inconsistent with the assumptions
of a dominant paradigm.
Summary
Nomothetic science explains the generality of people and events. Idiographic
science is the science of the uniqueness of people and events. Most of psychol-
ogy is nomothetic. Experimental, social, developmental, health, and many other
176 ◆ Everyone is unique
Essay questions
1 How have psychologists assessed people from an idiographic perspec
tive and what are the advantages and disadvantages compared with
nomothetic assessment of individual differences?
2 What is self-actualisation, how can it be measured, and what are the
consequences of achieving or not achieving self-actualisation?
3 How has Rogers contributed to the contextual model of psychotherapy
and what are its advantages and disadvantages?
9
What are the assumptions of
psychologists who use qualitative
research methodology and what
are the alternatives to treating
psychology as a natural science?
178 ◆ Qualitative methods
The Romantics
The idea that there is a form of non-numeric meaning in the world is a fea-
ture of 19th-century German Romanticism exemplified in Goethean Sci-
ence (Steiner, 1883/1988). Goethean science involves examining objects as
they are and trying to intuit their essence. The essence cannot be ascribed
a number. It is a purely intuitive process of feeling. In Goethean science,
the colour white is a colour which has its own properties and ‘feels’ differ-
ent from other colours. In Newtonian science, the colour white is simply
a combination of all the colours of the rainbow and does not exist as a
distinct colour.
Dichter and other market researchers not only tried to understand the moti-
vational basis for consumer objects, they also came up with slogans and strat-
egies for improving sales. When he first moved to America, Dichter advised
Proctor and Gamble on how to sell their soap. He came up with the slogan
“wash your troubles away.” A Proctor and Gamble executive acknowledged
his creativity by writing “You s.o.b., you are really a copy writer” (Stern,
2004, p. 166).
Qualitative methods ◆ 181
research. In fact, many medical grant giving bodies require that patients should
be involved in the design of the research. The technical term for this is patient
public involvement, or PPI. However, psychologists who specialise in qualita-
tive methods would draw a clear a distinction between this kind of informal
use of qualitative research, such as PPI, and their own methodologically more
rigorous use.
When used in questionnaire design there is no attempt to find hidden mean-
ing in words. The term thematic analysis is used to describe an analysis of dis-
course that focusses on the surface meaning of words (Clark & Braun, 2013).
The methodology of thematic analysis involves attention to detail and to coding
of the detail. As the name suggests, thematic analysis is an analysis of themes
in discourse, but without any a priori theoretical assumptions. Words reveal
nothing more than the literal interpretation of what is said. Thematic analysis
could also be described as an application of common sense to understanding
the discourse of others.
Qualitative research can be used to develop methodology, as shown in
the earlier example, but it can also be used in hypothesis generation. Talking
to people can provide information that stimulates hypothesis generation. Of
course, hypothesis generation comes not just from observation but also from
the person doing the observation (see Chapter 1). The really difficult and
important skill of scientific research, the skill that makes an immense differ-
ence to reputation, is in getting the right question. It takes experience to know
what right questions to ask. The most impactful research questions are often
not those that are being asked now, but those that will be important in a year
or two when the data are collected, analysed, and the paper submitted. There
is a purely intuitive process in developing research questions that depends on
the person. Quantitative science depends on an intuitive process that involves
qualitative understanding.
Qualitative methods ◆ 183
by virtue of the social interactions between people. Edley argues that many of
the criticisms of social constructionism are based on the assumption that social
constructionists support the ontological form whereas he argues that few actu-
ally do. He writes:
21 Kath: chicken.
22 Vic: ((leans back)) yeh ((nods))
23 Kath: °okay:° ((turns away from Vic)
This text illustrates three features of conversational analysis. The first is that
this form of analysis provides the kind of methodological rigour one would
expect from a science. The second is that discourse is being treated as a form
of data without any attempt to find hidden meaning in the minds of those tak-
ing part. The third is that meaning can be found in the discourse itself that was
not apparent to those taking part. The meaning that this analysis reveals is in
the conversation, not in the minds of those taking part. The conclusions drawn
by the researchers will be clear to anyone reading that extract. Although Kath
wants to make sure Vic is making an informed choice, Vic is having difficulty
negotiating what he is being asked to do because of the way it is being asked.
And
Rogers’ description of the therapeutic process in this paper is the same as that
found in hermeneutics – and is at odds with his earlier descriptions of the pro-
cess of psychotherapy as a scientific endeavour. A unity of experiencing does
not produce falsifiable theories. Rogers’ recognition of the tension between
the scientific and non-scientific was made possible because he inhabited both
worlds, a world where psychology was justified to others in terms of science and
an intuitive world of trying to understand the minds of his clients.
relationship is found between men and women, and this forms part of the focus
of criticism in feminist psychology (Wilkinson, 1996). Feminist psychology also
draws attention to other gender imbalances in psychology – for example, that
whereas the majority of psychology students are female, the lecturing staff in
some universities are (or used to be) predominantly male. Feminist psychol-
ogy is not only critical of the male bias in academic psychology, but also of a
male bias in society which, as in the case of critical psychology, emphasises the
unequal power between two groups of people.
The second consequence of psychology’s failure to recognise its political
role means that that political role is not properly studied. Critical psycholo-
gists therefore aim to remedy this deficit by providing an academic study of the
political role psychologists play. The first issue of the journal Annual Review of
Critical Psychology was published in 1999, and contains a manifesto for what
critical psychology should do (Parker, 1999). The manifesto draws attention to
four components that could be considered to form the subject matter of critical
psychology:
Critical psychology can itself be analysed from a political, cultural, and his-
torical perspective. Critical psychology is primarily a UK and to a lesser extent
European phenomenon. It became a recognised contributor to psychological
thought at a time in history when there was a new type of political development
in the UK, called Thacherism. Thacherism was named after the British Prime
Minister 1979–1990, Margaret Thatcher who famously said “There is no such
thing as society.” Margaret Thatcher espoused a form of individualism that
many, including the critical psychologists, felt was wrong. Some undergraduate
psychology courses do not cover critical psychology, though the argument that
psychologists are part of a political and historical context is as true now as it
was in the past.
Summary
Qualitative research methods were first used by psychologists working in
applied settings, not academia, who conducted motivational research to exam-
ine people’s buying habits. Qualitative research can be used by academic psy-
chologists in several ways with different types of assumptions. First, qualitative
studies are used within the context of quantitative science where researchers
use it for hypothesis generation and the refinement of the quantitative research
192 ◆ Qualitative methods
process. When used in this way, i.e., as help in natural science, most researchers
do not search for deep meaning in what people say.
Second, qualitative research is used as an end in itself to answer theoreti-
cal or practical questions. There are several different methodologies that can
be adopted for this purpose, but they all rely on analysing the meaning of
discourse rather than on quantitative assessment. The methodology selected is
carefully selected and followed, and researchers provide a scientific study that is
replicable by others. Discourse is analysed to discover meaning using a process
of inference and hypothesis generation. Qualitative research used in this way
meets the requirements of falsifiability and replicability that are the hallmarks
of a science, but it is a different type of science to natural science. One difference
between qualitative researchers is whether or not the discourse reveals hidden
meanings in the minds of the participants, or whether the meaning of discourse
when used in natural conversation can be inferred from detailed analysis of the
words themselves.
Third, there are those whose approach to qualitative research is explic-
itly non-scientific and who rely on human intuition, using a hermeneutical
approach that is not restricted to the discipline of psychology. In hermeneutic
psychology there is an explicit recognition that their understanding of people
should not be considered a science.
Finally, there are those whose qualitative methodology is part of a rejection
of mainstream psychology in favour of a distinctly political agenda.
This chapter has provided examples to show that qualitative methods, how-
ever they are used, can provide information that cannot be obtained through
quantitative methods. The inner meaning of soup is not revealed by a question-
naire asking people how much they like soup. The words of a questionnaire do
not write themselves. Conversations can create problems of understanding that
are not apparent to those taking part in the conversation. Quantitative research
answers some types of questions; qualitative research answers other types of
questions. Both are useful methods used in psychology.
Essay questions
1 When might it be useful to search for the hidden meaning in discourse
and when might this not be useful?
2 In what ways is qualitative research useful?
3 What is the role of intuition in human understanding and research?
10
Is the whole greater than the sum
of its parts? From gestalt psychology
to artificial intelligence
194 ◆ From gestalt psychology to AI
The question addressed in this chapter, the last chapter in this book, is in some
ways the most important question in psychology. It is important because an
answer ‘yes’ can be used to justify the existence of psychology as a discipline
separate from physiology. It is important because the difference between those
assuming yes and those assuming no fuels a controversy that runs throughout
the history of psychology. It is important because artificial intelligence and
therefore the future of humans is linked to the assumption of ‘yes.’ It is impor-
tant because artificial intelligence can act as heuristic for a new type of theory
in psychology, a type of theory that would create a paradigm shift from the
current neurocognitive paradigm – assuming that this is the current paradigm,
which by now the reader will realise is not assumed by all psychologists!
There are two ways of understanding the world: analysis and synthesis. The
process of analysis examines the different parts of something. After analysing
something into its separate ‘bits,’ the whole is found by adding the separate
bits together to make a whole. In the physical sciences this often involves
micro-analysis – i.e., finding the smaller and smaller parts, for example, the
genes in biology or fundamental particles in physics.
The process synthesis shows how the different parts of something interact
and combine such that the whole cannot be understood by the separate contri-
butions of the individual parts. Throughout the history of science, and in sev-
eral different disciplines, there is a tension between those who want to analyse
yet smaller and smaller parts of the jigsaw that is knowledge, and those who
want to see the meaning of the jigsaw as a whole.
The coalescence versus brick wall hypothesis was introduced in Chapter 2.
If the taste of lemonade can be understood as the combination of two separate
tastes, lemon and sugar, then the sensation of lemonade can be analysed into
its separate components. If, on the other hand, lemonade is a unique taste, dif-
ferent from lemon and sugar, then lemonade is a synthesis of sugar and lemon
and must be understood as such. The brick wall versus coalescence controversy
was a debate amongst philosophers in the 19th century, and it is a precursor to
a much more important movement in psychology, the gestalt movement.
A
B
FIGURE 10.1 Line A appears and then disappears and is replaced by line B, then vice versa.
196 ◆ From gestalt psychology to AI
Wertheimer was able to vary the rate of alternation between line A and B. He
found that as the rate increased, there came a point when it appeared that a line
was moving between A and B and something was actually visible between them.
The line appears to be rotating around the point where the two lines meet. In
fact, the same experiment is more easily demonstrated by two lights in a dark
room that are separated by a short distance. If the light alternates between A
and B, it appears that the light is moving between A and B and something is
visible between A and B. The demonstration of apparent motion is interesting
but was not novel. Wertheimer’s important contribution, which was published
in 1912 (Wertheimer, 1912), was a modification of this type of phi experiment.
Wertheimer used three lines, two of which are called A, and one B
(Figure 10.2).
B
A
A
FIGURE 10.2 Line B appears then disappears and is followed by lines A and vice versa.
As before, the A and B lines alternate on the screen, but in this case the two
A lines appear at the same time. The B line appears, then the two A lines appear
as the B line disappears, then the A lines appear again and the B line disappears.
This arrangement creates the peculiar impression that the B line moves in two
directions at once – it looks as though the B line splits and moves outwards.
Wertheimer realised that this impression could not be caused by eye movement,
because the eyes cannot move in two directions at the same time. His demon-
stration therefore showed that Wundt’s explanation of how we perceive motion
was false. Motion is not perceived because of the way the eye moves, but is due
the overall pattern of what we see. Why do we see movement from the overall
pattern? The answer is that perception follows certain rules, so that when a
pattern of a particular kind appears, then we perceive according to that rule.
The idea that perception follows rules or principles led over a short period
of time to the discovery of several gestalt principles. Students studying psy-
chology will already be familiar with these principles from the study of visual
perception. They include:
Continuity: There is an assumption that lines that are interrupted are con-
tinuous (a principle exploited in the ‘three rope trick’ (search online and
you will find videos showing you how to do this).
Proximity: Objects close together are assumed to be connected.
Similarity: Objects that are similar are assumed to be connected.
Gestalt principles also are used in colour perception. The colours of the rain-
bow are well known: red, orange, yellow, green, blue, and violet. So where is
brown? Where is gold? Where is silver? Gold and silver are the easiest ones to
explain. Gold is yellow and silver is light grey with particularly bright highlights
(highlights are the reflections that come off shiny objects). If you examine a
painting of a gold shield, you will see that from a distance the shield really looks
gold, but when you come up close it is simply yellow. The trick is that artists
puts in more highlights than are in the surrounding objects so that you assume
that the object must be shiny gold. Colours such as gold and silver show that
people infer colour not only from the colour impinging on the eye but from the
whole of the visual array.
Brown is a little more difficult to understand. If you have paints that are
red, orange, yellow, green, and blue next to each other, they look like those
colours – i.e., red orange, yellow, etc. However, if you take a colour such as yel-
low, and reduce the amount of light that is emerging relative to its surroundings,
then this ‘yellow’ looks brown. Brown (there are lots of different browns) is the
colour that we infer from knowing that relatively little light is being reflected –
of course, when no light is reflected, then we assume the colour is black. Colour
perception shows that colour is not just a matter of an addition of signals from
the cones in the eye but is an inference that is made from the total array of the
visual image.
stick and hook the banana inside. Repeated study shows, for example, that the
chimpanzee picks up the stick faster if the stick is between the chimpanzee and
the banana rather than at the other end of the cage. The significance of Köhler’s
studies was to show that learning happened in an ‘all-or-nothing’ fashion. At
one point in time the chimpanzee did not know what to do and at the next point
it did. This finding was important because it contradicted the more atomistic
theories of learning that were being developed by animal psychologists working
within the behaviourist tradition (see Chapter 4) where learning was believed to
be a gradual process of the strengthening of stimulus-response bonds. Köhler’s
research showed that learning could be all or nothing.
America
Koffka moved to America in 1924. Wertheimer, who was Jewish, moved
to America in 1933 when the German National Socialists dismissed all
Jewish professors from German Universities – including Nobel prize win-
ners such as Albert Einstein. Köhler published an article in 1933 strongly
criticising German discrimination against Jews (Henle, 1978). Köhler left
Germany for America in 1935. The three men were friends throughout
their academic lives (Brett & Wertheimer, 2005).
Kurt Koffka moved to America before his German friends. He was proficient
in English before he left (Koffka, 1922, 1924, 1935) and his proficiency in
English enabled him to promote gestalt principles in the English-speaking
world (Gibson, 1979). He influenced Tolman (see Chapter 4) and befriended
James J. Gibson (1904–1979), whose book The Ecological Approach to Visual
Perception, published in 1979, is viewed as an important culmination of the
gestalt approach. One of Gibson’s many ideas was that, when people look at a
visual array, they immediately register what objects are for. So, for example, if
a person sees something that has the structure of a path, that person will know
that the path is for walking on. The shape of a hammer will indicate that the
object is for hitting things with. Gibson described these ‘what things are for’ as
affordances.
Field theories
Many theories in psychology take the logical form of A causes B. The experi-
mental method is suited for assessing such causal statements. Causal statements
are important because they have practical implications. Does spaced learning
help a student revise more than massed learning? Do adverse childhood expe-
riences affect behaviour in later life? Does drinking alcohol on a regular basis
lead to greater happiness? Causal theories of this kind take the form of
S→O→R
Or more generally
However, any causal relationship is just one of many, many different causal
relations that are happening at any one time. The assumption of the gestalt
movement is that the whole is greater than the sum of its parts. That being the
case, it also makes sense to consider how all the many, many different causal
relations that are happening at one time interact to produce some kind of out-
come. Not only is perception and learning holistic, it also may be that one needs
holistic theories. Field theories are based on the assumption that theories should
explore how all the different causal relations occur together. In this section two
field theories are examined, the field theory of Lewin and inter-behaviourism.
Lewin (1890–1947) was Jewish and like Kofka moved to America in 1933,
as did other Jews who had university careers and had to leave Germany. Lewin
was familiar with gestalt psychology and refers to this in his field theory. The
following quote sums up the essence of Lewin’s field theory:
Lewin suggests that behaviour is the result of different forces that result from a
person’s “life space” where life space consists of all the different experiences and
motives that make up a person. Lewin suggests that behaviour can be consid-
ered a path through this life space, and he gives a name to this space, hodologi-
cal space. Lewin was influenced by newly developed mathematics of topology
and he invented symbols to represent the various concepts in hodological space.
In his most detailed publication of his theory (Lewin, 1938), he provides four
200 ◆ From gestalt psychology to AI
pages of symbols that are used in the diagrams which he created to represent
hodological space. This type of representation looks very scientific!
Although field theory naturally stems from gestalt principles, field theory
was also developed by a behaviourist, Jacob Kantor (1888–1984). Kantor
had worked with Skinner (see Chapter 4) whom he admired, but felt that the
interactional nature of behaviourism was not sufficiently developed (Morris,
1984). Kantor proposed a form of behaviourism called inter-behaviourism
(Kantor, 1970). Kantor suggested there was a bidirectional causal connec-
tion between stimulus and response, instead of the single-directional, stimu-
lus-causes-response approach taken by other behaviourists. Kantor’s approach
is described as ecological behaviourism. He suggested that the stimulus-response
interaction takes place in a context and it is the context that is neglected in other
behaviourist approaches to understanding behaviour.
What these different field theories have in common is the idea that it is not
possible to isolate the organism and study it separately from its natural environ-
ment. It is the interaction with the natural environment that is important. The
idea of understanding behaviour in terms of a number of simultaneous causal
interactions is found not only in field theories of psychology, it is the most basic
assumption in the study of ecology. Ecologists study the mutual interactions of
species in the total environment. Some argue that experimental studies fail to
provide a true picture of the mechanism’s underlying behaviour because they
lack ecological validity. The term ecological validity is based on the assumption
that a valid – i.e., true – account of human behaviour requires investigation in
its natural setting, not in the laboratory
Field theories can be considered an extension of ideas first proposed by the
gestalt psychologists. Sharps and Wertheimer sum up the contribution of the
gestalt movement to modern psychology as follows:
Several points for modern psychology emerge from the Gestalt perspec-
tive. Phenomena should be studied within their full context; there is a
need to acknowledge the domain specificity of principles in experimen-
tal psychology; it is wise to study phenomena that either exist in the real
world or have close real-world analogues; psychology must recognize
interchanges between organisms and surroundings as determinants of
behaviour.
(Sharps & Wertheimer, 2000, p. 315)
Field theories in psychology are intuitively plausible. So why are they practically
unknown? Students reading this book could ask fellow students whether they
have heard of either Lewin or Kantor. Lewin and Kantor suggested how psy-
chology theory should be constructed. The problem is they never demonstrated
that this type of theory was able to solve problems that could not be solved by
other existing theories – despite Lewin being committed to the practical use
of psychology. The history of psychology is one where different people have
From gestalt psychology to AI ◆ 201
Hebb showed that networks can adapt or learn if they follow rules. Several
other rules were later developed to show how networks could learn.
McCulloch and Pitts developed their ideas through the inter-disciplinary collab-
oration of neuroscience and mathematics (Abraham, 2002). Inter-disciplinary
developments can be some of the most important in the development of sci-
ence. The McCulloch-Pitts model is based a simple assumption (McCulloch &
Pitts, 1943). Suppose there is a network of neurones that are either ‘on’ or ‘off.’
Then assume that this on-off state of a neurone corresponds to true-false in a
logical argument. McCulloch and Pitts showed that variation in the connection
strengths between the neurones in a network could produce on-off or true-false
states that followed the rules of logic. The contribution of their approach was to
show that networks could solve problems, simply by the connection strengths
of the neurones.
204 ◆ From gestalt psychology to AI
The two pieces of the jigsaw, from Hebb and from McCulloch-Pitts, were
put together in what become known as connectionist psychology (Ellis & Hum-
phreys, 1999). A network system can learn and in doing so solve problems. In
adapting to their inputs, networks can learn to function better in their envi-
ronment. Connectionist psychology and artificial intelligence are based on the
same assumption. The assumption is that in order to understand or mimic the
intelligence of a human, it is necessary to have a structure of a network where
multiple, simultaneous causal connections occur. Pattern recognition is one of
the achievements of AI, and the way an AI system recognises a pattern provides
an answer to the question that the gestalt psychologists were never able to
answer, how patterns are recognised.
How is a pattern recognised? How do we recognise the letter A when hand-
writing differs so much between people? One way would be to have a series of
templates, of different kinds of A. For example, the following are the letter A
using different fonts
A A A A A
Any new letter could be compared with a storage bank of letters A to see
whether or not the letter was an A. The problem with the template approach is
that it will recognise the letter A only if it has been seen in that format before.
The templates here would fail to recognise a letter A that has never been written
before, but which you, the student, will recognise as a letter A.
Humans – and machines that mimic humans – are able to recognise the letter
A in a format that has not been seen before. Pattern recognition requires an
understanding of the relationship between the elements of the pattern – the
relationship between the lines that make up a letter A, for example.
Pattern recognition devices, i.e., devices capable of recognising a letter even
if that form of the letter has not been seen before – use neural network structure
similar to that shown in the Figure 10.3.
FIGURE 10.3 In this figure, there are three layers of neurones, input, hidden, and output.
From gestalt psychology to AI ◆ 205
The input layer receives inputs from the external environment. Each input
node is either on or off depending on its input from the external environment.
Figure 10.3 shows only five input nodes, but there can be many more. The input
nodes could also be arranged in a two-dimensional array connected to detectors
that detect whether a point in a pattern is either black (i.e., a line passes through
that point) or white (a line does not pass through that point). Just one input
layer is shown in the figure, but additional hidden layers can be added one after
another, all connecting with each other.
The neurones in the output layer – just one is shown in the Figure 10.3,
but there could be more – provide the answer, for example whether the
pattern is an A or not. Figure 10.3 shows that information is processed in
parallel – hence a parallel distributed processing system, rather than a lin-
ear system where one logical process is followed by another. The perceptive
student will ask, “but how exactly does this parallel distributed processing
system provide the correct answer?” It does it by getting the correct strengths
of connection between the all three layers, input, hidden, and output. The
strengths of connection can vary and once they are exactly right, then the
system will correctly recognise patterns such as the letter A. The perceptive
student will point out, “yes, but how do you get the connection strengths
exactly correct? The diagram looks incredibly complicated and it looks
like an impossible task.” The answer is that a human does not work it out.
Instead the answer is provided from a type of machine learning, called super-
vised learning.
Supervised learning occurs when a network adapts on the basis of feedback.
First, the network needs to be trained. Training is achieved by presenting the
network with letters of the alphabet in different fonts, some of them being As,
and providing the network with information about whether the letter is an A
or not. Then, if the network adapts using a ‘supervised learning rule’ or algo-
rithm, then the connection strengths will gradually change so that eventually
they are just right to be able to detect whether a letter is an A or not. There are
several different possible supervised learning rules, but they all provide a way
of gradually changing the connection weights until they provide the correct
solution. So long as the network adapts – i.e., the connection strengths change –
in accordance with the learning rule, then, after training, the network will be
able to correctly identify the letter A, whatever form that A takes. This form of
learning is also referred to as ‘deep learning.’
Supervised learning or deep learning shows an important feature of artificial
intelligence. After training, a machine will be able to perform tasks that it has
not been programmed to perform. The human does not have to write the rules
for task performance. The machine learns those rules by itself. The machine is
capable of learning something that the human has not been able to make. The
science of artificial intelligence was motivated by a desire to create a machine
to do what humans are capable of doing. However, in creating artificial intel-
ligence, scientists have been able to demonstrate how humans do what they are
capable of doing.
206 ◆ From gestalt psychology to AI
then the robots of the future will not be alive. If, however, it becomes possible
to make a truly parallel processing machine in the way that humans are parallel
processing, then one can certainly raise the question as to whether the machine
is alive and should be granted the rights of ‘wet’ organisms. Who knows what
the future will bring? As a student watching episodes of Star Trek, I thought
the communication devices were an impossibility. Mobile phones are now
taken for granted.
The novel part of the adaptive network theory is the proposal that the body
adapts when symptoms fail to have their intended function, and it adapts by
increasing the intensity of the symptom. If a person doesn’t listen and respond
to what the body is trying to tell them, then the body shouts louder. A simi-
lar idea had been presented some 30 years previously. The control theory of
depression suggests that failing to disengage from unattainable goals leads to
depression (Carver & Scheier, 1990; Hyland, 1987). The weakness of the con-
trol theory explanation of depression is that it did not explain why persistence
210 ◆ From gestalt psychology to AI
FIGURE 10.4
Schematic representation of the adaptive network theory. Stop signals encode the
instruction to ‘stop doing whatever it is that you are doing at the moment.’ The stop
programme encodes the instruction to ‘stop everything that you are doing.’
From gestalt psychology to AI ◆ 211
Treatment
‘Body reprogramming’ is the name given to the educational intervention
based on the adaptive network theory (Hyland et al., 2016). The aim is
to explain to patients why they became ill and how they can help them-
selves by engaging in behaviours that do not create stop signals, see www.
bodyreprogramming.org. Patients are taught how to teach their bodies
that the world is a safe and rewarding place using evidence-based lifestyle
change such as relaxation, stress avoidance, positive experiences, exercise,
and nutrition.
There is evidence consistent with the predictions of the adaptive network theory
that is separate from effectiveness of therapy (Hyland, Lanario, Wei, Jones, &
Masoli, 2019; Melidis, Denham, & Hyland, 2018), but evidence merely cor-
roborates and never proves a theory. The existing data may be explainable by
another theory, and future data may falsify the theory. The adaptive network
theory is an example of a theory being used to solve an applied problem (see
Chapter 3), but its relative usefulness compared to other theories is yet to be
evaluated. The theory combines the idea of adaptation and information pro-
cessing (see Chapter 4) and provides a paradigm where humans are understood
in terms of a mechanism similar to that found in robots. Some may argue that
this paradigm is a travesty of what it means to be human, where humans have
spiritual needs (Chapter 8) and where deep learning is no substitute for deep
meaning (Chapter 9). Others may argue that in the long run developments
in neuroscience will provide a better understanding (in what sense better?)
of the phenomena explained by the adaptive network theory. The theory is a
biopsychosocial theory in that symptoms result from an interaction between
have psychological and biological causes. That interaction taking place in an
information level consistent with the mechanistic explanations of cognitive psy-
chology (see Chapters 4 and 6), but the usefulness of this approach in contrast
to a purely physiological or purely psychological one may prove in the long
term to be deceptive. The original hypothesis was informed by observation and
qualitative information from patients (see Chapter 8), but failure to do a proper
qualitative analysis is a shortcoming in any understanding of the phenomenon
of functional disorders. Finally, any theory, however ardently supported by its
inventor (as this one is) has a good potential for being wrong. Science advances
only when conjectures are found to be false and new conjectures proposed.
Exam anxiety
Many students experience exam anxiety. According to the adaptive net-
work theory, exam anxiety is caused by a history of exam taking. Each
time a child takes an exam, they are engaging in a behaviour that creates
anxiety. Their bodies are telling them to stop doing things that signal dan-
ger, but they keep on putting themselves in (what the body interprets as)
danger by taking exams. Social and other pressures cause people to ignore
what their bodies are telling them to do. The adaptive network theory
predicts that the degree of exam anxiety in students should be correlated
with the number of exams taken previously – a prediction consistent with
observation (McDonald, 2001).
The history of psychology shows that new technologies can provide the oppor-
tunity for new paradigms in psychology. The original aim of AI was to create
From gestalt psychology to AI ◆ 213
Summary
The idea that ‘the whole is greater than the sum of its parts’ was suggested by
gestalt psychologists using perception as an example of this phenomenon. Later
the idea was applied to learning to show that learning was (or could be) all or
none rather than incremental. This idea of holism influences field theorists and
underpins the idea of ecological validity. What happens in the laboratory may
not happen in real life. Finally, the emergence of network theory in the 1940s
and 1950s led to connectionist psychology in the 1980s and the start of the new
technological revolution, that of artificial intelligence.
The development of factory production lines coincided with rise of behav-
iourism. The sequential processing computer coincided with the rise of cogni-
tive psychology. Parallel processing, the basis of AI, is a new technology that
could be more revolutionary than the other two technological revolutions. Con-
nectionist psychology is based on the assumption that concepts form the nodes
of a network and the psychological processes reflect an underlying network
architecture. The adaptive network theory is based on the assumption that the
body is a network with emergent properties and that particular patterns of life-
style lead to adaptations that create symptoms.
The discipline of psychology has changed over the 150 years of its history,
and will continue to change. When historians of psychology look back in 50
years’ time, what will they see?
Essay questions
1 What were the main achievements of the gestalt movement?
2 What is machine learning and how has machine learning and artificial
intelligence contributed to psychology?
3 Scientific paradigms change. Behaviourism lasted about 50 years, and
cognitive psychology and humanistic psychology about the same length
of time. What do you think the discipline of psychology will be like 50
years from now?
11
The changing assumptions
of psychology
216 ◆ The changing assumptions of psychology
Types of research
Humans are fundamentally the same as animals and so animal research advances
our understanding of human psychology.
There are significant differences between humans and animals so animals
cannot form a substitute for people in the study of psychology.
Psychology is a pure science whose aim is to understand basic processes.
Psychology is an applied and non-applied science where non-applied theo-
ries can have application following translational research.
Psychological research conducted in laboratories and on undergraduates
generalises to the general population and everyday life.
Psychological research conducted in laboratories lacks ecological validity;
to be valid, research needs to be carried out in the context to which it is being
applied.
Aims of psychology
The aim of psychology is to document the elements of consciousness and the
connections between those elements.
The aim of psychology is to explain how associations (operant and classical
conditioning) lead to changes in behaviour and so enable humans to predict and
control behaviour.
The changing assumptions of psychology ◆ 217
Essay question
1 What assumptions do you support and why?
References
Abraham, T. H. (2002). (Physio) logical circuits: The intellectual origins of the McCulloch-
Pitts neural networks. Journal of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 38(1), 3–25.
Abramson, L. Y., Seligman, M. E., & Teasdale, J. D. (1978). Learned helplessness in humans:
Critique and reformulation. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 87(1), 49–74.
Ach, N. (1910a). Über den Willen (On volition). Leipzig, Germany: Verlag von Quelle &
Meyer.
Ach, N. (1910b). Über den Willensakt und das Temperament (On will and temperament).
Leipzig, Germany: Verlag von Quelle & Meyer.
Adelman, E. M. (2006). Mind-body intelligence: A new perspective integrating Eastern
and Western healing traditions. Holistic Nursing Practice, 20(3), 147–151.
Agusti, A., Bel, E., Thomas, M., Vogelmeier, C., Brusselle, G., Holgate, S., . . . Beasley, R.
(2016). Treatable traits: Toward precision medicine of chronic airway diseases.
European Respiratory Journal, 47(2), 410–419.
Albu, A. (1980). British attitudes to engineering education: A historical perspective.
In Technical innovation and British economic performance (pp. 67–87). London,
England: Palgrave Macmillan.
Allport, G. W. (1962). The general and the unique in psychological science 1. Journal of
Personality, 30(3), 405–422.
Antaki, C., Finlay, W., Walton, C., & Pate, L. (2008). Offering choices to people with
intellectual disabilities: An interactional study. Journal of Intellectual Disability
Research, 52(12), 1165–1175.
Antonovsky, A. (1993). The structure and properties of the sense of coherence scale.
Social Science & Medicine, 36(6), 725–733.
Ash, M. G. (1995). Gestalt psychology in German culture, 1890–1967: Holism and the quest
for objectivity. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.
Aulakh, R. (2016). Mandatory publication in India: Setting quotas for research output
could encourage scientific fraud. British Medical Journal, 354, i5002.
Bannister, D., & Fransella, F. (2019). Inquiring man: The psychology of personal constructs.
Abingdon, UK: Routledge.
Barker, D. J. P. (1992). The fetal origins of disease. Journal of Hypertension, 10(Suppl. 7),
S39–S44.
Bartle, J. (2002). Market analogies, the marketing of labour and the origins of new
labour. In N. O. O’Shaughnessy, N. J. O’Shaughnessy, S. C. Henneberg, S. Henne-
berg, & C. Henry (eds.), The idea of political marketing. Westport, CT: Greenwood
Publishing Group.
Baumeister, A. A., Hawkins, M. F., & Uzelac, S. M. (2003). The myth of reserpine-induced
depression: Role in the historical development of the monoamine hypothesis.
Journal of the History of the Neurosciences, 12(2), 207–220.
220 ◆ References
Breuer, J., & Freud, S. (1895/1955). Fraulein Anna O. In J. Strachey (ed. and trans.), The
standard edition of the complete psychological works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 2: Stud-
ies on hysteria (pp. 21–47). London, England: Hogarth Press.
Bringmann, W. G. (1975). Wundt in Heidelberg: 1845–1874. Canadian Psychological
Review/Psychologie canadienne, 16(2), 124–129.
Bringmann, W. G., & Tweney, R. D. (eds.) (1980). Wundt studies: A centennial collection.
Toronto, Canada: Hogrefe.
Broadbent, D. E. (1958). Perception and communication. Oxford, England: Pergamon
Press.
Brocki, J. M., & Wearden, A. J. (2006). A critical evaluation of the use of interpretative
phenomenological analysis (IPA) in health psychology. Psychology and Health,
21(1), 87–108.
Bruce, D. (1998). The Lashley–Hull debate revisited. History of Psychology, 1(1), 69–84.
Buckley, K. W. (1982). The selling of a psychologist: John Broadus Watson and the
application of behavioral techniques to advertising. Journal of the History of the
Behavioral Sciences, 18(3), 207–221.
Buckley, K. W. (1989). Mechanical man: John B Watson and the beginnings of behaviour-
ism. New York, NY: The Guilford Press.
Burnham, J. C. (1972). Thorndike’s puzzle boxes. Journal of the History of the Behavioral
Sciences, 8(2), 159–167.
Burt, C. (1966). The genetic determination of differences in intelligence: A study of
monozygotic twins reared together and apart. British Journal of Psychology, 57(1–
2), 137–153.
Bushman, B. J. (2002). Does venting anger feed or extinguish the flame? Catharsis,
rumination, distraction, anger, and aggressive responding. Personality and Social
Psychology Bulletin, 28(6), 724–731.
Bushman, B. J., Baumeister, R. F., & Stack, A. D. (1999). Catharsis, aggression, and persua-
sive influence: Self-fulfilling or self-defeating prophecies? Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology, 76(3), 367.
Buss, D. (2015). Evolutionary psychology: The new science of the mind. Hove, England:
Psychology Press.
Caldwell, N., & Coshall, J. (2002). Measuring brand associations for museums and galler-
ies using repertory grid analysis. Management Decision, 40(4), 383–392.
Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1982). Control theory: A useful conceptual framework for
personality: Social, clinical, and health psychology. Psychological Bulletin, 92(1),
111–135.
Carver, C. S., & Scheier, M. F. (1990). Origins and functions of positive and negative
affect: A control-process view. Psychological Review, 97(1), 19–35.
Catania, A. C. (1992). B. F. Skinner, organism. American Psychologist, 47(11), 1521–
1530.
Caton, R. (1875). The electric currents of the brain. British Medical Journal, 2, 278.
Chomsky, N. (1959). A review of B. F. Skinner’s verbal behavior. Language, 35, 26–58.
Clarke, V., & Braun, V. (2013). Teaching thematic analysis: Overcoming challenges and
developing strategies for effective learning. The Psychologist, 26(2), 120–123.
222 ◆ References
Cohen, D. (1979). J. B. Watson: The founder of behaviourism. Boston, MA: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Cohen, S., Janicki-Deverts, D., & Miller, G. E. (2007). Psychological stress and disease.
Jama, 298(14), 1685–1687.
Coon, D. J. (2000). Salvaging the self in a world without soul: William James’s the prin-
ciples of psychology. History of Psychology, 3(2), 83–103.
Craik, K. J. (1943). The nature of explanation. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University
Press.
Craik, K. J. (1948). Theory of the human operator in control systems: II. Man as an ele-
ment in a control system. British Journal of Psychology, 38(3), 142–148.
Croce, P. J. (1999). Physiology as the antechamber to metaphysics: The young William
James’s hope for a philosophical psychology. History of Psychology, 2(4), 302.
Cronbach, L. J. (1957). The two disciplines of scientific psychology. American Psycholo-
gist, 12(11), 671–684.
Cronbach, L. J., & Meehl, P. E. (1955). Construct validity in psychological tests. Psycho-
logical Bulletin, 52(4), 281–302.
Csikszentmihalyi, M., & Seligman, M. E. (2000). Positive psychology: An introduc-
tion. American Psychologist, 55(1), 5–14.
Danziger, K. (2001). The unknown Wundt: Drive, apperception and volition. In R. W.
Rieber & D. K. Robinson (eds.), Wilhelm Wundt in history: The making of a scientific
psychology (pp. 95–120). New York, NY: Kluwer Academic and Plenum Publishers.
Deci, E. L., & Ryan, R. M. (1985). Intrinsic motivation and self-determination in human
behavior. New York, NY: Plenum.
Decker, H. S. (1991). Freud, Dora and Vienna 1900. New York, NY: Free Press.
De Marneffe, D. (1991). Looking and listening: The construction of clinical knowledge
in Charcot and Freud. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society, 17(1), 71–111.
de Paula Ramos, S. (2003). Revisiting Anna O.: A case of chemical dependence. History
of Psychology, 6(3), 239–250.
Dichter, W. (1964). Handbook of human motivations: The psychology of the world of
objects. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill.
Diener, E. D., Emmons, R. A., Larsen, R. J., & Griffin, S. (1985). The satisfaction with life
scale. Journal of Personality Assessment, 49(1), 71–75.
Digdon, N., Powell, R. A., & Harris, B. (2014). Little Albert’s alleged neurological impair-
ment: Watson, Rayner, and historical revision. History of Psychology, 17(4), 312.
Dilthey, W. (1894/1977). Descriptive psychology and historical understanding. In R. M.
Zaner & K. L. Heiges (trans.), The Hague, the Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff. (Original
work published 1894).
Dix, D. L. (1843–1852/1971). On behalf of the insane poor: Selected reports. New York, NY:
Arno Press.
Edley, N. (2001). Unravelling social constructionism. Theory & Psychology, 11(3), 433–
441.
Ellenberger, H. F. (1972). The story of “Anna O”: A critical review with new data. Journal
of the History of the Behavioral Sciences, 8(3), 267–279.
References ◆ 223
Ellis, R., & Humphreys, G. W. (1999). Connectionist psychology: A text with readings. Hove,
England: Psychology Press.
Ellis, W. D. (ed.) (1999). A source book of gestalt psychology. London, England: Routledge
and Kegan Paul.
Engel, G. L. (1978). The biopsychosocial model and the education of health profession-
als. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, 310(1), 169–181.
Epstein, S., & O’brien, E. J. (1985). The person: Situation debate in historical and current
perspective. Psychological Bulletin, 98(3), 513.
Esterson, A. (2002a). The myth of Freud’s ostracism by the medical community in
1896–1905: Jeffrey Masson’s assault on truth. History of Psychology, 5(2), 115–134.
Esterson, A. (2002b). Misconceptions about Freud’s seduction theory: Comment on
Gleaves and Hernandez (1999). History of Psychology, 5(1), 85–91.
Evans, R. B., & Koelsch, W. A. (1985). Psychoanalysis arrives in America: The 1909 psy-
chology conference at Clark University. American Psychologist, 40(8), 942–948.
Fang, F. C., Steen, R. G., & Casadevall, A. (2012). Misconduct accounts for the majority of
retracted scientific publications. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
109(42), 17028–17033.
Farr, R. M. (1983). Wilhelm Wundt (1832–1920) and the origins of psychology as an
experimental and social science. British Journal of Social Psychology, 22(4), 289–
301.
Fechner, G. T. (1860/1966). Elements of psychophysics. New York, NY: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston.
Fechner, G. T. (1865). Über die Frage des goldenen Schnittes (On the question of the
golden section). Archiv für die zeichnenden Künste, 11, 100–112.
Fechner, G. T. (1871). Zur experimentalen ästhetik (On experimental aesthetics). Leipzig,
Germany: Hirzel.
Fechner, G. T. (1904/2005). The little book of life after death. Boston, MA: Weisser Books.
Fernandez-Duque, D., Evans, J., Christian, C., & Hodges, S. D. (2015). Superfluous neu-
roscience information makes explanations of psychological phenomena more
appealing. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 27(5), 926–944.
Fleeson, W. (2004). Moving personality beyond the person-situation debate: The chal-
lenge and the opportunity of within-person variability. Current Directions in Psy-
chological Science, 13(2), 83–87.
Fodor, J. A. (1968). Psychological explanation: An introduction to the philosophy of psy-
chology. New York, NY: Random House.
Fodor, J. A. (1983). The modularity of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Fodor, J. A. (1985). Precis of the modularity of mind. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 8(1),
1–5.
Forrester, J. (1986). The true story of Anna O. Social Research, 53(2), 327.
Fowler, R. D. (1990). In memoriam: Burrhus Frederic Skinner, 1904–1990. American Psy-
chologist, 45(11), 1203.
Fox, B. (2017). It’s nature and nurture: Integrating biology and genetics into the social
learning theory of criminal behavior. Journal of Criminal Justice, 49, 22–31.
224 ◆ References
Frank, J. D., & Frank, J. B. (1991). Persuasion and healing: A comparative study of psycho-
therapy (3rd ed.). Baltimore, MD: John Hopkins University Press.
Frankl, V. E. (1959). Man’s search for meaning. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Frankl, V. E. (1967). Psychotherapy and existentialism. New York, NY: Washington Square
Press.
Frankl, V. E. (1969). The will to meaning. New York, NY: The New American Library, Inc.
Freud, S. (1895a). Project for a scientific psychology. In The standard edition of the com-
plete works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 1). London, England: Hogarth Press.
Freud, S. (1895b). Studies in hysteria (with Joseph Breuer). In The standard edition of the
complete works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 2). London, England: Hogarth Press.
Freud, S. (1905/1955). Fragments of an analysis of a case of hysteria. In The standard
edition of the complete works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 7). London, England: Hogarth
Press.
Freud, S. (1909/1955). Analysis of a phobia in a five-year-old boy. In The standard edi-
tion of the complete works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 10). London, England: Hogarth
Press.
Freud, S. (1918/1955). From the history of an infantile neurosis. The standard edition of
the complete works of Sigmund Freud (Vol. 17). London, England: Hogarth Press.
Froh, J. J. (2004). The history of positive psychology: Truth be told. NYS Psychologist,
16(3), 18–20.
Galton, F. (1869). Hereditary genius: An inquiry into its laws and consequences. London,
England: Palgrave Macmillan.
Galton, F. (1874). English men of science: Their nature and nurture. London, England:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Galton, F. (1875). The history of twins as a criterion of the relative powers of nature and
nurture. Fraser’s Magazine, 92, 566–576.
Galton, F. (1883). Inquiries into human faculty and its development. London, England:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Gergen, K. J. (1985). The social constructionist movement in modern psychology.
American Psychologist, 40(3), 266–275.
Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston, MA: Houghton
Mifflin.
Glaser, B. G., & Strauss, A. L. (1967). Grounded theory: The discovery of grounded theory.
Rutgers, NJ: Transaction Publishers.
Glass, N. (1999). Sure start: The development of an early intervention programme for
young children in the United Kingdom. Children & Society, 13(4), 257–264.
Gorham, J. (1988). The relationship between verbal teacher immediacy behaviors and
student learning. Communication Education, 37(1), 40–53.
Graebner, W. (2006). “Back-fire to lust”: G. Stanley Hall, sex-segregated schooling, and
the engine of sublimation. History of Psychology, 9(3), 236–246.
Greely, H. T., & Farahany, N. A. (2019). Neuroscience and the criminal justice system.
Annual Review of Criminology, 2, 451–471.
Greenwald, A. G. (1992). New Look 3: Unconscious cognition reclaimed. American Psy-
chologist, 47(6), 766–779.
References ◆ 225
Hull, C. L. (1930). Simple trial and error learning: A study in psychological theory. Psy-
chological Review, 37(3), 241–256.
Hull, C. L. (1933). Hypnosis and suggestibility. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc.
Hull, C. L. (1945). Principles of behaviour. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc.
Hull, C. L. (1951). Essentials of behaviour. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc.
Hull, C. L. (1952). A behaviour system. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Husserl, E. (1910/1965). Philosophy as rigorous science. In Q. Lauer (ed.), Phenomenol-
ogy and the crisis of philosophy. New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Hussinger, K., & Pellens, M. (2019). Guilt by association: How scientific misconduct
harms prior collaborators. Research Policy, 48(2), 516–530.
Huxley, A. (1932). Brave new world. London, England: Chatto & Windus.
Hyland, M. (1981). Introduction to theoretical psychology. London, England: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Hyland, M. E. (1985). Do person variables exist in different ways? American Psychologist,
40(9), 1003–1010.
Hyland, M. E. (1987). Control theory interpretation of psychological mechanisms of
depression: Comparison and integration of several theories. Psychological Bul-
letin, 102(1), 109–121.
Hyland, M. E. (2001). A two-phase network theory of atopy and asthma causation: A
possible solution to the impact of genes, hygiene and air quality. Clinical & Experi-
mental Allergy, 31(10), 1485–1492.
Hyland, M. E. (2002). The intelligent body and its discontents. Journal of Health Psychol-
ogy, 7(1), 21–32.
Hyland, M. E. (2011). The origins of health and disease. Cambridge, England: Cambridge
University Press.
Hyland, M. E. (2017). A new paradigm to explain functional disorders and the adap-
tive network theory of chronic fatigue syndrome and fibromyalgia syndrome. In
G. B. Sullivan, J. Cresswell, B. Ellis, M. Morgan & E. Schraube (eds.), Resistance and
renewal in theoretical psychology (pp. 21–31). Concord, Canada: Captus University
Publications.
Hyland, M. E., Hinton, C., Hill, C., Whalley, B., Jones, R. C., & Davies, A. F. (2016). Explaining
unexplained pain to fibromyalgia patients: Finding a narrative that is acceptable
to patients and provides a rationale for evidence based interventions. British
Journal of Pain, 10(3), 156–161.
Hyland, M. E., Lanario, J. W., Pooler, J., Masoli, M., & Jones, R. C. (2018). How patient par-
ticipation was used to develop a questionnaire that is fit for purpose for assessing
quality of life in severe asthma. Health and Quality of Life Outcomes, 16(1), 24.
Hyland, M. E., Lanario, J. W., Wei, Y., Jones, R. C., & Masoli, M. (2019). Evidence for similarity
in symptoms and mechanism: The extra-pulmonary symptoms of severe asthma
and polysymptomatic presentation of fibromyalgia. Immunity, Inflammation and
Disease (in press).
Hyland, M. E., Whalley, B., Jones, R. C., & Masoli, M. (2015). A qualitative study of the impact
of severe asthma and its treatment showing that treatment burden is neglected in
existing asthma assessment scales. Quality of Life Research, 24(3), 631–639.
References ◆ 227
Hyland, M. E., Lanario, J. W., Pooler, J., Masoli, M., & Jones, R. C. (2018). How patient
participation was used to develop a questionnaire that is fit for purpose
for assessing quality of life in severe asthma. Health and Quality of Life Out-
comes, 16(1), 24.
Ivonin, L., Chang, H. M., Diaz, M., Catala, A., Chen, W., & Rauterberg, M. (2015). Traces
of unconscious mental processes in introspective reports and physiological
responses. PloS One, 10(4), e0124519.
James, W. (1890). The principles of psychology. New York, NY: Holt.
James, W. (1895). Is life worth living? International Journal of Ethics, 6(1), 1–24.
James, W. (1899/1922). Talks to teachers on psychology. London, England: Longmans,
Green and Co.
Jones, M. B. (2003). Two early studies on learning theory and genetics. Behavior Genet-
ics, 33(6), 669–676.
Jones, M. J., Moore, S. R., & Kobor, M. S. (2018). Principles and challenges of apply-
ing epigenetic epidemiology to psychology. Annual Review of Psychology, 69,
459–485.
Jonides, J., Lewis, R. L., Nee, D. E., Lustig, C. A., Berman, M. G., & Moore, K. S. (2008). The
mind and brain of short-term memory. Annual Review of Psychology, 59, 193–224.
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. London, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.
Kamin, L. J. (1974). The science and politics of IQ. Potomac, MD: Lawrence Erlbaum Asso-
ciates.
Kamin, L. J. (1981). The Cyril Burt affair. In H. J. Eysenk & L. Kamin (eds.), Intelligence: The
battle for the mind. London, England: Pan.
Kantor, J. R. (1970). An analysis of the experimental analysis of behavior (TEAB). Journal
of the Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 13(1), 101.
Kelly, G. A. (1955). The psychology of personal constructs (Vols. 1–2). New York, NY: Nor-
ton & Co.
Kelly, G. A. (1963). A theory of personality: The psychology of personal constructs. New
York, NY: Norton & Co.
Kemeny, J. G., & Oppenheim, P. (1956). On reduction. Philosophical Studies, 7, 6–19.
Kirsch, I. (1985). Response expectancy as a determinant of experience and behavior.
American Psychologist, 40(11), 1189–1202.
Kirsch, I. (2010). The emperor’s new drugs: Exploding the antidepressant myth. New York,
NY: Basic Books.
Kirsch, I. (2014). The emperor’s new drugs: Medication and placebo in the treatment
of depression. In F. Benedetti, P. Enck, E. Frisaldi & M. Schedlowski (eds.), Placebo
(pp. 291–303). Berlin, Germany: Springer.
Kirsch, I., & Hyland, M. E. (1987). How thoughts affect the body: A metatheoretical
framework. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 8, 417–434.
Kirsch, I., Moore, T. J., Scoboria, A., & Nicholls, S. S. (2002). The emperor’s new drugs: An
analysis of antidepressant medication data submitted to the US Food and Drug
Administration. Prevention & Treatment, 5(1), 23a.
Koffka, K. (1922). Perception: An introduction to the Gestalt-Theorie. Psychological Bul-
letin, 19(10), 531.
228 ◆ References
Koffka, K. (1924). The growth of the mind: An introduction to child psychology (R. M.
Ogden, trans.). New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.
Koffka, K. (1935). Principles of Gestalt psychology. New York, NY: Harcourt, Brace & World,
Inc.
Köhler, W. (1925). The mentality of apes. London, England: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
(Original work published 1917).
Köhler, W. (1947). Gestalt psychology: An introduction to new concepts in modern psychol-
ogy. New York, NY: Liveright. (Original work published 1929).
Köhler, W. (1959). Gestalt psychology today. American Psychologist, 14(12), 727.
Köhler, W. (1966). The place of value in a world of facts. New York, NY: Liveright. (Original
work published 1938).
Kuhn, T. S. (1962). The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: The University of
Chicago Press.
Lakatos, I. (1978). Philosophical papers (2 vols.). New York, NY: Cambridge University
Press.
Lakatos, I., & Musgrave, A. (eds.) (1970). Criticism and the growth of knowledge. New York,
NY: Cambridge University Press.
Lamiell, J. T. (1998). Nomothetic’ and idiographic’ contrasting Windelband’s under-
standing with contemporary usage. Theory & Psychology, 8(1), 23–38.
Landy, F. J. (1992). Hugo Münsterberg: Victim or visionary? Journal of Applied Psychol-
ogy, 77(6), 787–802.
Le Nguyen, K. D., Lin, J., Algoe, S. B., Brantley, M. M., Kim, S. L., Brantley, J., . . . Fredrick-
son, B. L. (2019). Loving-kindness meditation slows biological aging in novices:
Evidence from a 12-week randomized controlled trial. Psychoneuroendocrinology,
108, 20–27.
Lewin, K. (1938). The conceptual representation and measurement of psychological
forces. In Contributions to psychological theory (Vol. 1, No. 4). Durham, NC: Duke
University Press.
Lewin, K. (1939). Field theory and experiment in social psychology: Concepts and
methods. American Journal of Sociology, 44(6), 868–896.
Lewin, K. (1943a). Psychology and the process of group living. The Journal of Social
Psychology, 17(1), 113–131.
Lewin, K. (1943b). Defining the “field at a given time”. Psychological Review, 50(3),
292–310.
López-Muñoz, F., Alamo, C., Cuenca, E., Shen, W. W., Clervoy, P., & Rubio, G. (2005). His-
tory of the discovery and clinical introduction of chlorpromazine. Annals of Clini-
cal Psychiatry, 17(3), 113–135.
Lothane, Z. (1998). Freud’s 1895 project: From mind to brain and back again. Annals of
the New York Academy of Sciences, 843(1), 43–65.
Luce, R. D. (1977). The choice axiom after twenty years. Journal of Mathematical Psychol-
ogy, 15(3), 215–233.
Lyman, R. L., & O’Brien, M. J. (2004). Nomothetic science and idiographic history in
twentieth-century Americanist anthropology. Journal of the History of the Behav-
ioral Sciences, 40(1), 77–96.
References ◆ 229
Miller, G. A., Galanter, E., & Pribram, K. H. (1960). Plans and the structure of behavior. New
York, NY: Henry Holt and Company.
Mills, J. A. (1978). Hull’s theory of learning: II. A criticism of the theory and its relation-
ship to the history of psychological thought. Canadian Psychological Review/
Psychologie canadienne, 19(2), 116–127.
Misiak, H., & Sexton, V. S. (1966). History of psychology: An overview. New York, NY: Grune
& Stratton.
Monroe, S. M., & Harkness, K. L. (2005). Life stress, the “kindling” hypothesis, and the
recurrence of depression: Considerations from a life stress perspective. Psycho-
logical Review, 112(2), 417–445.
Morris, E. K. (1984). Interbehavioral psychology and radical behaviorism: Some similari-
ties and differences. The Behavior Analyst, 7(2), 197–204.
Münsterberg, H. (1908). On the witness stand. New York, NY: Clark Boardman.
Myers, G. E. (2001). William James: His life and thought. New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Myers, I. B. (1962). Myers-Briggs type indicator manual. Palo Alto, CA: Consulting Psy-
chologists Press.
Nagel, E. (1961). The structure of science: Problems in the logic of explanation. New York,
NY: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc.
Nagel, T. (1998). Reductionism and antireductionism. In The limits of reductionism in
biology (Novartis Foundation Symposium 213) (pp. 3–14). Chichester, England:
Wiley.
O’Brien, M. (2004). When Adam Delved and Eve Span: A history of the peasants’ revolt of
1381. Cheltenham, England: New Clarion Press.
O’Donnell, J. M. (1987). The origins of behaviourism: American psychology, 1870–1920.
New York, NY: New York University Press.
Osgood, C. E., Suci, G., & Tannenbaum, P. (1967). The measurement of meaning. Cham-
paign, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Parker, I. (1999). Critical psychology: Critical links. Annual Review of Critical Psychology,
1(1), 3–18.
Parsons, F. T. (1873). The art of questioning. The Maine Journal of Education, 7(8), 301–303.
Pearce, J. M. (2009). The ophthalmoscope: Helmholtz’s augenspiegel. European Neurol-
ogy, 61(4), 244–249.
Pearson, K. (1914). The life, letters and labours of Francis Galton (Vol. 1). London, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Pearson, K. (1924). The life, letters and labours of Francis Galton (vol 2): Researches of
middle life. London, England: Cambridge University Press.
Pelosi, A. J. (2019). Personality and fatal diseases: Revisiting a scientific scandal. Journal
of Health Psychology, 24(4), 421–439.
Pilgrim, D. (2015). The biopsychosocial model in health research: Its strengths and limi-
tations for critical realists. Journal of Critical Realism, 14(2), 164–180.
Plato (380BCE/1935). The republic of Plato (A. D. Lindsay, trans.). London, England: J.M.
Dent.
Popper, K. (1935/1992). The logic of scientific discovery. Abingdon, England: Routledge.
References ◆ 231
Sandford, S. (2006). Sexually ambiguous: Eros and sexuality in Plato and Freud. Angelaki:
Journal of the Theoretical Humanities, 11(3), 43–59.
Sauce, B., & Matzel, L. D. (2018). The paradox of intelligence: Heritability and malleability
coexist in hidden gene-environment interplay. Psychological Bulletin, 144(1), 26.
Schlotz, W., & Phillips, D. I. (2009). Fetal origins of mental health: Evidence and mecha-
nisms. Brain, Behavior, and Immunity, 23(7), 905–916.
Schneider, S. M., & Morris, E. K. (1987). A history of the term radical behaviorism: From
Watson to Skinner. The Behavior Analyst, 10(1), 27–39.
Schwitzgebel, E. (2004). Introspective training apprehensively defended: Reflections
on Titchener’s lab manual. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 11(7–8), 58–76.
Scott, W. D. (1911). Influencing men in business: The psychology of argument and sugges-
tion. New Yok, NY: Ronald Press Co.
Segerstrom, S. C., & Miller, G. E. (2004). Psychological stress and the human immune
system: A meta-analytic study of 30 years of inquiry. Psychological Bulletin, 130(4),
601.
Seligman, M. E. (1968). Chronic fear produced by unpredictable electric shock. Journal
of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 66(2), 402–411.
Seligman, M. E., & Maier, S. F. (1967). Failure to escape traumatic shock. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology, 74(1), 1–9.
Sharps, M. J., & Wertheimer, M. (2000). Gestalt perspectives on cognitive science and on
experimental psychology. Review of General Psychology, 4(4), 315–336.
Shubla, H. C., Solomon, G. F., & Dosli, R. P. (1979). Psychoimmunology. Journal of Holistic
Health, 4, 125–131.
Silk, J. B., & House, B. R. (2016). The evolution of altruistic social preferences in human
groups. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences,
371(1687), 20150097.
Skinner, B. F. (1935). Two types of conditioned reflex and a pseudo type. The Journal of
General Psychology, 12(1), 66–77.
Skinner, B. F. (1938). The behavior of organisms. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts,
Inc.
Skinner, B. F. (1948). Walden Two. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behaviour. Oxford, England: Macmillan.
Skinner, B. F. (1957). Verbal behavior. New York, NY: Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc.
Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and dignity. New York, NY: Knopf.
Skinner, B. F. (1974). About behaviourism. New York, NY: Vintage Books.
Skinner, B. F. (1976). Particulars of my life. New York, NY: Knopf.
Skinner, B. F. (1984a). Behaviourism at fifty. Behavioural and Brian Sciences, 7(4), 615–667.
Skinner, B. F. (1984b). Reply to Catania. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 7(4), 718–719.
Slife, B. D., & Christensen, T. R. (2013). Hermeneutic realism: Toward a truly meaningful
psychology. Review of General Psychology, 17(2), 230–236.
Smith, J. A. (1996). Beyond the divide between cognition and discourse: Using inter-
pretative phenomenological analysis in health psychology. Psychology and
Health, 11(2), 261–271.
Smith, J. M. (1964). Group selection and kin selection. Nature, 201(4924), 1145.
References ◆ 233
Sodergren, S. C., Hyland, M. E., Crawford, A., & Partridge, M. R. (2004). Positivity in ill-
ness: Self-delusion or existential growth? British Journal of Health Psychology, 9(2),
163–174.
Sodergren, S. C., & Lewith, G. T. (2006). Chronic fatigue syndrome: The role of positivity
to illness in chronic fatigue syndrome patients. Journal of Health Psychology, 11(5),
731–741.
Spearman, C. (1927). The abilities of man. London, England: Palgrave Macmillan.
Steen, R. G. (2011). Retractions in the scientific literature: Do authors deliberately com-
mit research fraud? Journal of Medical Ethics, 37(2), 113–117.
Steger, M. F., Frazier, P., Oishi, S., & Kaler, M. (2006). The meaning in life questionnaire:
Assessing the presence of and search for meaning in life. Journal of Counseling
Psychology, 53(1), 80–93.
Steiner, R. (1883/1988). Goethean science (Goethes Naturwissenschaftliche Schriften,
Einleitungen). Liverpool, England: Mercury Press.
Stevenson, R. L. (1886). Strange case of Dr Jekyll and Mr Hyde. London, England: Long-
mans, Green and Co.
Stern, B. B. (2004). The importance of being Ernest: Commemorating Dichter’s con-
tribution to advertising research. Journal of Advertising Research, 44(2), 165–169.
Stolt, C. M. (2001). Why did Freud never receive the Nobel Prize? International Forum of
Psychoanalysis, 10(3–4), 221–226.
Tansley, A. G. (1920). The new psychology. London, England: George Allen & Unwin.
Taylor, E. (1995). An epistemological critique of experimentalism in psychology: Or,
why G. Stanley Hall waited until William James was out of town to found the
American Psychological Association. In H. E. Adler & R. W. Rieber (eds.), Aspects of
the history of psychology in America, 1892–1992 (Vol. 727, pp. 37–61). New York, NY:
Annals of the New York Academy of Science.
Taylor, E. (1996). William James on consciousness beyond the margin. Princeton, MA:
Princeton University Press.
Thorndike, E. (1899). A reply to “the nature of animal intelligence and the methods of
investigating it”. Psychological Review, 6(4), 412–420.
Thorndike, E. L. (1905). The elements of psychology. New York, NY: Mason Printing Cor-
poration.
Thorndike, E. L. (1911). Animal intelligence. New York, NY: Palgrave Macmillan.
Thorndike, E. L. (1918). The nature, purposes, and general methods of measurements of
educational products. In G. M. Wipple (ed.), Seventeenth yearbook of the national
society for the study of education (Vol. 2, pp. 16–24). Bloomington, IL: Public School
Publishing.
Thorndike, E. L. (1921). Measurement in education. Teachers College Record, 22, 371–379.
Thorndike, E. L. (1932). The fundamentals of learning. New York, NY: Teachers College.
Titchener, E. B. (1912). The schema of introspection. American Journal of Psychology,
23(4), 485–508.
Todorov, E., & Jordan, M. I. (2002). Optimal feedback control as a theory of motor coor-
dination. Nature Neuroscience, 5(11), 1226–1235.
Tolman, E. C. (1922). A new formula for behaviorism. Psychological Review, 29(1), 44–53.
234 ◆ References
Tolman, E. C. (1932). Purposive behavior in animals and men. New York, NY: Appleton-
Century-Crofts, Inc.
Tolman, E. C. (1945). A stimulus-expectancy need-cathexis psychology. Science, 101,
160–166.
Tolman, E. C. (1948). Cognitive maps in rats and men. Psychological Review, 55(4),
189–208.
Tolman, E. C. (1959). Principles of purposive behaviour. In S. Koch (ed.), Psychologicaly:
A study of a science (Vol. 2, pp. 92–157). New York, NY: McGraw Book Company.
Tuke, S. (1813/1964). Description of the retreat: An institution near York for insane persons
of the Society of Friends. London, England: Dawson.
U.S. Department of Health and Human Services Food and Drug Administration (2009).
Guidance for Industry Patient-Reported Outcome Measures: Use in Medical Prod-
uct Development to Support Labeling Claims. www.fda.gov/downloads/drugs/
guidancecomplianceregulatoryinformation/guidances/ucm193282.pdf
Van Rappard, H. (2004). Wundt as an activity/process theorist. In A. C. Brock, J. Louw
& W. van Hoorn (eds.), Rediscovering the history of psychology: Essays inspired
by the work of Kurt Danziger. New York, NY: Kluwer Academic and Plenum
Publishers.
Van Rappard, H., Sanders, C., & De Swart, J. H. (1980). Wilhelm Wundt and the cognitive
shift. Acta Psychologica, 46(3), 235–255.
Veenendaal, M. V., Painter, R. C., de Rooij, S. R., Bossuyt, P. M., van der Post, J. A., Gluck-
man, P. D., . . . Roseboom, T. J. (2013). Transgenerational effects of prenatal expo-
sure to the 1944–45 Dutch famine. BJOG: An International Journal of Obstetrics &
Gynaecology, 120(5), 548–554.
Vincent, N. A. (2010). On the relevance of neuroscience to criminal responsibility. Crimi-
nal Law and Philosophy, 4(1), 77–98.
Virués-Ortega, J. (2006). The case against BF Skinner 45 years later: An encounter with
N. Chomsky. The Behavior Analyst, 29(2), 243–251.
Wade, N. J. (1994). Guest editorial: Hermann von Helmholtz (1821–1894). Perception,
23, 961–989.
Wade, N. J., & Finger, S. (2001). The eye as an optical instrument: From camera obscura
to Helmholtz’s perspective. Perception, 30(10), 1157–1177.
Walach, H. (2020). Naturalising religion-spiritualising science: The role of consciousness
research. Journal of Consciousness Studies (in press).
Walach, H., Horan, M., Hinterberger, T., & von Lucadou, W. (2019). Evidence for anom-
alistic correlations between human behavior and a random event generator:
Result of an independent replication of a Micro-PK experiment. Psychology of
Consciousness: Theory, Research and Practice (in press). https://psycnet.apa.org/
search/results?id=6a953a86-f303-fb36-ff07-34e71663ce86
Walsh, V., & Cowey, A. (2000). Transcranial magnetic stimulation and cognitive neuro-
science. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 1(1), 73–80.
Wampold, B. E. (2013). The great psychotherapy debate: Models, methods, and findings.
New York, NY: Routledge.
Watson, J. B. (1903). Animal education. Chicago, IL: The University of Chicago Press.
References ◆ 235
Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20(2),
158–177.
Watson, J. B. (1914). Behavior: An introduction to comparative psychology. New York, NY:
Henry Holt and Company.
Watson, J. B. (1916). The place of the conditioned-reflex in psychology. Psychological
Review, 23(2), 89–116.
Watson, J. B. (1919a). Psychology from the standpoint of a behaviorist. Pennsylvania, PA:
Lippincott.
Watson, J. B. (1919b). A schematic outline of the emotions. Psychological Review, 26(3),
165–196.
Watson, J. B. (1924/1970). Behaviorism. New York, NY: Norton & Co.
Watson, J. B. (1928/1972). Psychological care of the infant and child. New York, NY: Arno
Press.
Watson, J. B., & Rayner, R. (1920). Conditioned emotional reactions. Journal of Experi-
mental Psychology, 3(1), 1–14.
Watt, H. J. (1913). The main principles of sensory integration. British Journal of Psychol-
ogy, 6(2), 239.
Weber, E. H. (1834/1978). The sense of touch. New York, NY: Academic Press.
Wertheimer, M. (1912). Experimental studies of the perception of movement. Zeitschrift
für Psychologie, 61, 161–265. Also available in W. S. Sahakian (ed.), History of psy-
chology: A source book in systematic psychology (pp. 418–422), Itasca, IL: Peacock.
Weyant, R. G. (1968). Who’s afraid of John B. Watson? Comments on behavior: An
introduction to comparative psychology. [Review of the book Behavior: An intro-
duction to comparative psychology. J. B. Watson & R. J. Herrnstein]. Canadian
Psychologist/Psychologie canadienne, 9(3), 360–368.
Wiener, D. N. (1996). B.F. Skinner: Benign anarchist. Boston, MA: Allyn & Bacon.
Wilkinson, S. (1996). Feminist psychology: International perspectives. Buckingham,
England: Open University Press.
Williams, R. D. (1912). An investigation of the personal equation and reaction time.
Publication of the Pomona College Astronomical Society, 1(5), 1–59.
Willig, C. (2001). Introducing qualitative research in psychology. Buckingham, England:
Open University Press.
Wilson, D. S. (1975). A theory of group selection. Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, 72(1), 143–146.
Winston, A. S. (1998). “The defects of his race”: EG Boring and antisemitism in American
psychology, 1923–1953. History of Psychology, 1(1), 27–51.
Winston, A. S. (2004). Controlling the metalanguage. In A. C. Brock, J. Louw & W.
van Hoorn (eds.), Rediscovering the history of psychology: Essays inspired by the
work of Kurt Danziger (pp. 53–73). New York, NY: Kluwer Academic and Plenum
Publishers.
Winter, D. G., John, O. P., Stewart, A. J., Klohnen, E. C., & Duncan, L. E. (1998). Traits and
motives: Toward an integration of two traditions in personality research. Psycho-
logical Review, 105(2), 230–250.
Witmer, L. (1896). Practical work in psychology. Pediatrics, 2, 462–471.
236 ◆ References