Classical Liberal Perspective
Classical Liberal Perspective
John Locke(1632-1704)
John Locke, an English philosopher and physician, followed the
Hobbesian method by building his theories on assumptions about
The Classical Liberal Perspective 43
disorder in Great Britain had been largely resolved, and the task at hand
was to raise the material standard of living.
In his first major work, The Theory of Moral Sentiments (1759), Smith
argued that humans are able, through social interaction, to overcome their
narrow self-interest and view situations from the perspective of an "impar-
tial spectator." The human capacity for sympathy would restrain aggres-
sive, selfish behavior and create a stable society. Yet Smith was deeply
concerned that the emerging market economy unleashed powerful and
potentially dangerous motives such as greed, envy, and selfishness. The
aggressive pursuit of self-interest threatened to erode the social bonds of
sympathy and concern for others. Given these pressures, Smith wondered
whether human virtue could withstand the temptations of wealth.
Motivated by these concerns, Smith turned his attention from moral phi-
losophy to political economy. After being introduced to the idea of laissez-
faire by a group of French political economists known as the Physiocrats,
he concluded that a market society could not only withstand the effects of
acquisitive selfishness, but could actually steer this "vice" into productive
and socially beneficial channels. Without meaning to do so, self-interested
individuals actually promote the good of society by engaging their talents
and resources in the most profitable use. By the time he published The
Wealth of Nations in 1776, Adam Smith had substituted the market for
individual conscience as the mechanism for reconciling self-interest with an
orderly and prosperous society.
Although Smith is often portrayed as the champion of capitalism, he was
not completely optimistic about the market. He found self-interest com-
patible with the public good only when competition prevailed, and he
warned that businessmen would constantly seek to suppress competition
and deceive the public to increase profits. Smith also expressed concern
about the well-being of workers in a market economy. While he recognized
the tremendous efficiency gained by dividing production into separate, rou-
tine tasks, he worried that the monotony and mindlessness of factory jobs
would render workers "as stupid as it is possible for a human being to
become." Finally, Smith set the tone for subsequent classical political econ-
omists with his fear that the dynamism and growth of a market society
would eventually come to an end as profitable investment opportunities
were exhausted.
Whatever qualms he may have expressed about capitalism, Adam
Smith's legacy has been his defense of free markets and nonintervention by
government. During the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, mercantilist
policies had involved government in taxing commerce, opening new mar-
kets in foreign lands, protecting companies from competition, and assuring
product quality. Smith believed this meddling interfered with the potential
benefits of the market and proposed that government be limited to three
The Classical Liberal Perspective 45
T h o m a s Malthus ( 1 7 6 6 - 1 8 3 4 )
Malthus, a professor of history and political economy at the East India
College in England, was most responsible for steering Classical Liberalism
away from its earlier predisposition toward the Enlightenment values of
optimism, egalitarianism, and faith in reason. In contrast to Enlightenment
thinkers, Malthus believed that human misery was caused by nature rather
than badly organized institutions. In his book An Essay on the Principle of
Population (1798), Malthus claimed that population grows at a faster rate
than do food supplies because of the limited availability of fertile land.
Population growth could be restrained either by "positive checks" such as
famines, plagues, and wars, or by "preventive checks" such as delayed
marriages and "moral restraint."
Malthus had little hope that humans would be capable of exercising the
restraint required to control population growth, so positive checks would
be the effective controls on overpopulation. Moreover, Malthus believed
that government should not attempt to interfere with the operation of these
positive checks. He proposed that raw sewage be permitted to flow in the
streets, that insect-infested swamps remain undrained, and that cures for
disease be suppressed, thereby allowing nature to carry out the grisly task
of limiting population growth.
In addition to rejecting efforts to help the poor, Malthus argued that the
privileges and wealth of the upper classes benefitted all of society. He rea-
soned that workers as a group received insufficient wages to permit them
to purchase the vast array of goods being produced by the new factories,
so the economy would be plagued by periodic "gluts" of unsold goods
unless some members of society could afford to spend large amounts on
consumption without adding to production. Idle consumption by the rich
was therefore essential to maintain high levels of employment.
Malthus represents a turning point in Classical Liberalism. The
Enlightenment attack on aristocratic privilege evolved into a defense of
capitalist inequality. Later in the nineteenth century, Malthus's ideas would
resurface as "social Darwinism." Relying on the evolutionary theory of
Charles Darwin, Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) in England and William
Graham Sumner (1840-1910) in America claimed that the human species
evolves according to the principle of "survival of the fittest." Any attempts
by government to aid the poor would cause deterioration of the human
gene pool by allowing unfit members of the human species to survive and
reproduce. This biological argument for hierarchy and inequality became a
powerful ideological force in Europe and the United States.
46 Political Economy
Priedrich A. Hayek ( 1 8 9 9 - 1 9 9 2 )
Although born in Austria, Hayek spent most of his adult life in England
and America, where he devoted himself to defending laissez-faire capital-
ism against the challenges posed by Conservatives, Modern Liberals, and
Radicals. In The Road to Serfdom (1944), Hayek rejected the notion of a
middle ground between capitalism and socialism; the concept of a "mixed
economy" is untenable. Government intervention disrupts the smooth
functioning of a free-market economy, thereby generating the need for
additional corrective intervention. This vicious circle by which govern-
ment-induced problems lead to a larger role for government will eventually
push society toward socialism. The only way to halt this process is to resist
the initial temptation to improve society through government action.
The movement of Classical Liberalism away from the Enlightenment's
optimism and confidence in human reason can be clearly discerned in Hayek's
writings. He defended the market not because he believed in the power of
individual reason, but rather because of his skepticism about the capacity of
the human mind to obtain knowledge. Since each person can have detailed
knowledge of only a small portion of society, humans lack sufficient knowl-
edge to plan or direct the entire economy. Hayek explicitly denounced what
he called "constructivist rationalism," which seeks to remake society in accor-
dance with more humane and enlightened values.
Hayek praised the market for upholding individual freedom and empha-
sized its ability to process and transmit vast amounts of information about
individual preferences, availability of resources, and technology. Prices
reflect the conditions underlying supply and demand, so individuals are
able to compensate for their personal lack of knowledge by simply com-
paring prices. Moreover, through their own particular experience, individ-
uals gain specialized knowledge of niches in the market and may take
advantage of any profitable opportunities they discover.
Hayek's distrust of human reason led him to oppose virtually all gov-
ernment activity on the grounds that politicians and bureaucrats cannot
know what is best for society. The task of politics should be merely to
establish a constitution and set of laws restraining individuals from harm-
ing others. Hayek warned that when government is permitted to expand its
activities Seyond the protection of property rights, it will inevitably become
the tool of special interests. Various groups will claim that their interests
should be met to promote the public good or to achieve social justice, but
these appeals are simply disguised attempts to secure government benefits.
The public good is simply the aggregation of the private interests of indi-
viduals, and justice is a "mirage" based on the false supposition that some
interests are more deserving of fulfillment than others.
Hayek rejected the notion that economics can provide a scientific basis
for predicting or attempting to control the future of the economy. Not only
The Classical Liberal Perspective 47
Robert Nozick ( 1 9 3 8 - )
A recent restatement of Classical Liberalism has been undertaken by
Harvard philosopher Robert Nozick in his book Anarchy, State, and
Utopia (1974). Nozick argues that the free market will create justice in the
distribution of rewards if the following three conditions are met: (1) prop-
erty must be acquired without theft, fraud, or coercion; (2) transfers of
property from one person to another must occur through free exchanges,
inheritance, gifts, or charity; and (3) any property holdings failing to meet
the first two requirements must be "rectified" through redistribution.
Nozick rejects the notion that justice requires any specific distribution
of rewards. On the contrary, if a particular "pattern" of distribution
were enforced, then government would have to confiscate and redistrib-
ute income earned in the market, thus violating individual liberty.
Nozick also dismisses any conception of justice linking reward with indi-
vidual merit. There are many possible criteria of merit including effort,
need, productivity, contribution, social status, or virtue, but society has
no way of objectively choosing from among these criteria. Therefore,
Nozick argues, any effort to assess individual merit and reward it would
be arbitrary.
Nozick instead proposes the following definition of justice: "from each
as they choose, to each as they are chosen." Each person's reward should
be determined by his or her choices of what to offer in the market and by
other people's choices to buy the person's goods or services. Personal
income may be justifiably low if an individual chooses not to offer much
or if what is offered is not desired by others.
For Nozick, inequality is the result of individual choice. So long as peo-
ple are free to choose, markets will tend to generate inequality, but this
inequality will be fair. In fact, attempts by government to interfere with
market distributions are the major cause of injustice. Nozick equates
taxation with slavery, claiming that it forces citizens to work for the
48 Political Economy
Neo-Austrian E c o n o m i c s
The conquest of Austria by the German army during World War II forced
many intellectuals in that country to emigrate. Ludwig von Mises
(1881-1973) and Friedrich A. Hayek were the principle carriers of Austrian
economics to England and the United States. Although never fully embraced
by mainstream economists, Mises and Hayek managed to gain the respect
of influential economists such as Lionel Robbins (1898-1984), Fritz
Machlup (1881-1973), Oskar Morgenstern (1902-1977), and Gottfried
Haberler. More recently, a neo-Austrian school of thought has developed in
the United States under the leadership of Israel Kirzner, Murray Rothbard
(1926-1995), and Roger Garrison. Neo-Austrian writings are featured in
the Austrian Economics Newsletter, the Journal of Libertarian Studies,
Social Philosophy & Policy, and Critical Review.
Although neo-Austrians are committed to free markets and personal lib-
erty, they reject the neoclassical assumption that individuals possess full
information. If full information prevailed, then planners could conceivably
replicate the market, and the defense of private property would be weakened.
50 Political Economy
New Classical E c o n o m i c s
When Keynesian policies faltered in the early 1970s, Classical Liberals
were quick to fill the theoretical void. New classical economics describes
the modern revival of laissez-faire ideas from the nineteenth century. Some
of its leading proponents are Thomas Sargent, Neal Wallace, Robert Lucas,
and Robert Barro. Writings by new classical economists can be found in the
Journal of Political Economy and the American Economic Review.
New classical economists focus on the role of expectations in affecting
individual behavior. Sargent and Wallace developed the theory of "rational
expectations" to demonstrate the fallacy of Keynesian efforts to lower the
rate of unemployment. If citizens have rational expectations, their behav-
ior will take into account any anticipated effects of government policy.
When government attempts to stimulate the economy, citizens anticipat-
ing greater inflation will raise their wage demands, thereby offsetting any
tendency for employers to hire more workers. In short, any deliberate
effort by government to increase economic activity will be frustrated by
the reactions of citizens seeking to defend their income against antici-
pated inflation. The new classical economists conclude that government
cannot lower the level of unemployment and therefore ought to abandon
such attempts.
Closely related to new classical economics are two other theoretical
approaches: monetarism and supply-side economics. The former, champi-
oned by Milton Friedman, seeks to revive the classical idea that the amount
of money in the economy affects prices but not the level of employment or
output. Monetarists conclude that active monetary policy by the Federal
Reserve System can have no positive impact on unemployment and there-
fore should be abandoned in favor of steady growth of the money supply
at a rate sufficient to accommodate increases in real output.
52 Political Economy
ADDITIONAL READING
Barry, Norman P. Hayek's Social and Economic Philosophy. London: Macmillan,
1979.
Boaz, David, ed. The Libertarian Reader. New York: The Free Press, 1997.
Boaz, David, and Edward H. Crane, eds. Market Liberalism: A Paradigm for the
21st Century. Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 1993.
Brittan, Samuel. A Restatement of Economic Liberalism, 2nd ed. London:
Macmillan, 1988.
Buchanan, James M. Post-socialist Political Economy. Lyme, NH: Edward Elgar,
1997.
Burke, T. Patrick. Ethical Principles for a Free Market. New York: Paragon House,
1993.
Conway, David. Classical Liberalism: The Unvanquished Ideal. New York: St.
Martin's, 1995.
Friedman, Milton. Capitalism and Freedom. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1962.
Friedman, Milton, and Rose Friedman. Free to Choose: A Personal Statement. New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1980.
Hendrickson, Mark W., ed. The Morality of Capitalism. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY:
The Foundation for Economic Education, 1996.
Machan, Tibor. Capitalism and Individualism. New York: St. Martin's, 1990.
McKenzie, Richard, and Gordon Tullock. Modem Political Economy. New York:
McGraw-Hill, 1978.
Rand, Ayn. Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal. New York: Signet, 1967.
Roberts, Paul Craig. The Supply-Side Revolution. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1984.
Rockwell, Llewellyn H., Jr., ed. The Free Market Reader. Burlingame, CA: The
Ludwig von Mises Institute, 1988.
Rothbard, Murray. For a New Liberty. New York: Collier-Macmillan, 1978.
Rowley, Charles K. Liberty and the State. Brookfield, VT: Edward Elgar, 1993.
Schotter, Andrew. Free Market Economics. New York: St. Martin's, 1985.
Shand, Alexander H. Free Market Morality: The Political Economy of the Austrian
School New York: Routledge, 1989.
Stigler, George J., ed. Chicago Studies in Political Economy. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1988.
Vaughn, Karen I. Austrian Economics in America. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1994.