Function of Language: Group 8
Function of Language: Group 8
language
group 8
members
01 Ade ira miranda
04 Yukana
Austin’s Speech Act
Theory
Austin’s work is in many respects a reaction to some traditional and
influential attitudes to language. We can risk simplifying these as a starting
point. The attitudes can be said to involve three related assumptions, as
follows:
a. that the basic sentence type in language is declarative (i.e. a statement
or assertion);
b. that the principal use of language is to describe states of affairs (by using
statements);
c. that the meaning of utterances can be described in terms of their truth or
falsity
He makes two important observations. The first is that not all sentences are statements and that much
of conversation is made up of questions, exclamations, commands, and expressions of wishes like the
examples in below:
a. Excuse me!
b. Are you serving?
c. Hello.
d. Six pints of stout and a packet of peanuts, please!
e. Give me the dry roasted ones.
f. How much? Are you serious?
g. O tempora! O mores!
Austin’s second observation was that even in sentences with the grammatical form
of declaratives, not all are used to make statements. Austin identified a subset of
declaratives that are not used to make true or false statements, such as the
examples in below:
a.I promise to take a taxi home.
b. I bet you five pounds that he gets breathalyzed.
c. I declare this meeting open.
d. I warn you that legal action will ensue. e. I name this ship The Flying Dutchman
01 Evaluating performative utterances
Utterances with these characteristics we can call explicit performatives. The importance of speech
act theory lies in the way that Austin and others managed to extend their analysis from these
explicit performatives to other utterances. The first step was to point out that in some cases the
same speech act seems to be performed but with a relaxation of some of the special characteristics
mentioned in above. We regularly meet utterances like those in below, where this is so:
a. You are (hereby) charged with treason.
b. Passengers are requested to avoid jumping out of the aircraft.
c. Five pounds says he doesn’t make the semifinal.
d. Come up and see me sometime.
We can easily provide the sentences in above with corresponding explicit performatives, as below:
a. I (hereby) charge you with treason.
b. We request that passengers avoid jumping out of the aircraft.
c. I bet you five pounds that he doesn’t make the semifinal.
d. I invite you to come up and see me sometime.
03 Statements as performatives
Austin proposed that a speech act consists of three elements: the speaker says
something, signals an associated speech act, and causes an effect on the listeners. The
first element, the locutionary act, refers to the speaker's language rules and grammar.
The second element, the speaker's intended action, is the illocutionary act, which focuses
on the uses of language in society. The third element, the perlocutionary act, is the effect
of the illocutionary act on the listeners.
categorizing speech acts
After Austin's initial exploration of speech act theory, there have been a
number of works that have attempted to systematise the approach. While
acknowledging that there are a large number of distinctive speech acts in
language, it is proposed that all speech acts can be categorised into five
main types:
1. Representatives
2. Directives
3. Commissives
4. Expressives
5. Declaration
Searle distinguishes between preparatory, propositional, sincerity, and
essential conditions for an action. See the example below where we exemplify
the conditions for the act of promising:
The conditions for requests, we can predict that instead of using the
sentence Please come home!, the following indirect strategies are
possible:
a. Question the preparatory condition: Can you please come home?
b. State the sincerity condition: I want you to please come home.
c. Question the propositional content condition: Will you please come home?
Indirect acts and politeness