Discourse and Pragmatic 2
Discourse and Pragmatic 2
net/publication/264238575
CITATIONS READS
0 8,388
1 author:
Roumyana Slabakova
University of Southampton
192 PUBLICATIONS 3,923 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Roumyana Slabakova on 27 July 2014.
1. Introduction
Recent research in second language acquisition acknowledges the prime importance of pragmatic
and discourse knowledge for using a second language effectively. When Hymes (1966) argued
against the perceived inadequacy of the terms “linguistic competence” and “performance”
(Chomsky 1965) and introduced the term “communicative competence,” he was implying that
the latter is a superior modelling of language knowledge and use. In the second language
acquisition literature and in the foreign language teaching literature, linguistic competence has
often been interpreted very narrowly as little more than knowledge and use of morpho-syntax.
However, there is a large part of linguistic competence outside of morpho-syntax that regulates
opposition, since effective communication cannot happen without the underlying linguistic-
pragmatic competence. The existing research on interlanguage pragmatics to date has focused
inordinately more on some aspects of pragmatic competence in preference to others. This chapter
1
I am grateful to the editors for inviting me to contribute a chapter on a topic out of my comfort zone. It has been a
very rewarding experience. I am also grateful to the students who participated actively in the “Linguistic Pragmatics
and its L2 Acquisition” seminar at the University of Iowa in the Spring of 2008. Three anonymous reviewers helped
me to improve the clarity of the presentation and the accuracy of some claims, thank you. All remaining errors are
mine.
1
will survey the literature on interlanguage discourse (sensitivity to linguistic context) and
pragmatics (knowledge of the world, Gricean maxims of co-operation and other universal
The Handbook of Pragmatics edited by Laurence Horn and Gregory Ward (2004) lists
implicature, presupposition, reference, deixis, definiteness, and speech acts as the domain of
pragmatics. These largely overlap with what Levinson (1983) identifies as the five main areas of
speech acts. L2 pragmatics, however, has traditionally investigated areas considered to be in the
Harlig and Hartford 2005). Indeed, Rose and Kasper (2001) characterize pragmatics “as
interpersonal rhetoric— the way speakers and writers accomplish goals as social actors who do
not just need to get things done but must attend to their interpersonal relationships with other
Thus the three areas that have largely been studied in L2 pragmatics are speech acts,
these topics are studied include conversation analysis and classroom discourse analysis,
sociocultural theory as well as cognitive approaches to SLA (Kasper 2009). As will be shown in
this chapter, speech acts have garnered the lion’s share of attention within these approaches, with
the latter two topics lagging far behind in research interest. While nominal reference and
L2 acquisition research, it is safe to say that deixis marking and presuppositions are severely
2
One can argue that discourse and pragmatics are in a set-superset logical relationship. Sensitivity to linguistic
discourse context is only part of pragmatic knowledge of the world and universal pragmatic principles as used to
decode and encode linguistic messages.
2
understudied (Bardovi-Harlig 2011). On the other hand, topic and focus marking at the
with Sorace’s Interface Hypothesis (Sorace 2003, 2011, Sorace and Serratrice 2009) proving to
be an influential proposal spurring research endeavours in the first decade of the twenty-first
century.
use the term “linguistic competence” more broadly than is presently accepted in the applied
production and comprehension of, for example, deictic expressions, implicatures and pronouns,
actions aimed at human communication will not be the focus of this chapter. Rather than repeat
the already available excellent recent reviews (Bardovi-Harling 2011, Kasper 2009), which
and pragmatic constraints on the grammar. The critical look taken into each area of pragmatics
will be based on describing language universals as well as L1-L23 meaning mismatches within
that area. I will echo and extend Bardovi-Harlig’s (2005) call to re-contextualize L2 pragmatics
complementation of, and not in opposition of, the perspective of interaction and socio-discursive
3
In using the label L2 acquisition, I refer to the acquisition not only of a second, but also of a third and fourth
language, etc., that is, all non-native acquisition.
3
dimensions of pragmatics. Finally, I will identify the areas of further research interest likely to
2. Speech acts
The L2A research in this area is mainly based on speech act theory (Austin 1962, Searle 1969).
simultaneous performance of multiple acts: a locutionary act (i.e., propositional meaning of the
sentence), an illocutionary act (i.e., the force associated with the use of the utterance in a specific
context), and a perlocutionary act (i.e., the effects on the recipient of the performed speech act).
The illocutionary act is at the heart of L2 pragmatics research because it captures the essence of
speech acts as a primary area of inquiry. For example, Blum-Kulka (1982) makes a distinction
between social, linguistic and pragmatic acceptability but identifies wrong illocutionary force as
the most salient characteristic of nonnative speech act realization. Thomas (1983) introduces the
definitions:
communicative action (e.g., deciding whether to request an extension, complain about the
neighbor’s barking dog) and does not necessarily require any links to specific forms at all
4
While both types of knowledge have been studied extensively (see Kasper and Rose
2002, Kasper 2009, Bardovi-Harlig, 2005, 2011 for reviews), it is the latter that has been better
operationalized in the literature and has received more attention in general. The development of
pragmalinguistic knowledge, the conditions, environments, and the types of instruction that
influence it profitably are still in need of more research attention (Kasper, 2001). It is also
interesting to observe that the L2A literature on speech act development is much richer than the
L1A literature on the same topic. Therefore, it has become standard for researchers in the field to
describe (but not always to test) how native and nonnative speakers perform a specific speech act
and to compare the two (e.g., Hassall 2006, Barron 2006, among many others). Although there is
a clear understanding in the literature (von Stutterheim and Klein 1987, Kasper, 2009; Bardovi-
Harlig, 2011) that learners can and do access universal pragmatic resources such as the notions
of politeness, cooperation, turn taking in conversation, etc., positive pragmatic transfer in the
conditions of L1-L2 similarity has been understudied. Perhaps understandably, researchers tend
to focus on linguistic situations where speech acts in the L1 and L2 mismatch. There is
significant evidence, surveyed in Kasper (2009) that forming new pragmatic knowledge presents
considerable challenges to learners. However, L1-L2 similar speech acts, conversational routines
and conventional expressions can give us a very interesting insight into the other side of the
issue: if learners can transfer the sociopragmatic knowledge form their native culture, how do
classroom instruction. The rationale for examining effects of instruction is based on Schmidt’s
Noticing Hypothesis (Schmidt 1983, 1993) observation that mere exposure to the target language
is not sufficient for pragmatic competence to be picked up effortlessly, even after prolonged
5
exposure. Furthermore, Bardovi-Harlig (1999) argues forcefully for the teaching of pragmatic
skills because uninstructed learners differ from native speakers not only in production but also in
perception of pragmatic norms. An implicit assumption of authors who urge the teaching of
speech acts is that grammatical competence and pragmatic competence (in the sense of
To take an example from a recent study, Koike and Pearson (2005) attempts to tease apart
the effects of explicit and implicit instruction on the complex speech act of giving suggestions.
Anglophone learners of Spanish at roughly intermediate proficiency were divided into five
groups: those that received explicit versus implicit pre-instruction crossed with those that
received explicit versus implicit feedback plus a control group that received no instruction on
this speech act. Results of a post-treatment test and a delayed post-test indicate that learners can
indeed learn and maintain pragmatically appropriate behavior when they are given instruction on
the speech act and responses before further practicing with exercises. The researchers also note
that explicit instruction seems to help learners understand the speech act while implicit
instruction helps them to produce more appropriately (Koike and Pearson 2005: 495).
Furthermore, Jeon and Kaya (2006), a recent meta-analysis based on 13 quantitative studies
suggests that explicit instruction is generally superior to implicit instruction, in the realm of
speech acts,
Since polite behavior is to some extent a matter of personal choice and upbringing, not
only of linguistic knowledge, studies comparing college-age L2 learners (which are the majority
of studies) would benefit from demonstrating that the same polite behavior is indeed the norm
for these individual learners in their native language. Furthermore, it should be a priori
established whether or not the native language and the target language differ measurably in the
6
respective speech act so that learners have something pragmatic to learn over and beyond the set
linguistic expressions of the speech act under investigation. For example, Holtgraves (2007)
performs a very interesting experiment to ascertain that speakers of a language activate a specific
speech act construct in their mental grammar upon understanding that one has been performed in
the current communication. However, the nonnative speakers in his experiment come from a
large variety of native languages so it is not clear which of them had to learn a new speech act
and which had to map the L2 speech act onto their native one.
More generally speaking, the L2 speech act acquisition research is working towards a
detailed and better-operationalized comparison of speech acts across languages of the world. To
experimental studies should include at least two native control groups (L1 and L2) as well as
learner groups. Furthermore, it should be ascertained that learners notice, recognize and
comprehend speech acts in listening, so that they can then appropriate them in their individual
3. Conversational Implicature
Conversational implicature is a linguistic phenomenon related to speech acts in the sense that
both capture the ability of the hearer to recognize the additional meaning and intention encoded
in a speaker’s utterance. While speech acts are more often culturally acceptable conventions and
rules of speaking, conversational implicature refers to the universal ability to recognize the
speaker’s underlying intention over and above the compositional semantic meaning of the
utterance. For many L2 researchers, comprehension of implied meaning is a speech act among
many others. However, literal and intended meaning interpretation is a linguistic computation
7
much wider in application: it is part of almost any communication. Consider the following
Most people would agree that, in hearing the utterance in (1), they understand that he speaker has
Notice that (2) is not encoded by the speaker’s utterance, nor is it part of what the speaker has
said. Rather, (2) is an assumption inferentially derived by the hearer on the basis of what the
speaker has said. Logically speaking, some means some and possibly all. But if the speaker of (2)
had meant all professors are smart, she would have uttered (3) or (4), being maximally
informative and not (1). Since she didn’t, then we can safely assume she means (2).
The first systematic attempt to explain how the inference in (1) is derived is due to the
conducted, which he called “maxims”. According to Grice’s five maxims, interlocutors are
normally expected to offer contributions that are truthful, informative, relevant to the goals of the
conduct constrain the range of interpretations hearers are entitled to entertain in interpreting
utterances. Furthermore, these expectations can be violated (or exploited) to create a variety of
8
effects. According to Grice’s maxims, in producing (1) and meaning (2), the speaker has used
ii. do not make your contribution more informative than is required.” (Grice 1989:26)
The speaker has chosen a relatively weak term among a range of words ordered in terms of
informational strength: some … most … all. Assuming that the speaker is trying to be cooperative
and will say as much as she truthfully can, the fact that she chose the weaker term (some) gives
the listener reason to think that she is not prepared to make the stronger statements in (3) and (4).
This leads to the inference that the stronger statement does not hold, that is, to (2). The
implicature, since the propositions which some … most … all give rise to are ordered on a scale
(Horn, 1972, Gazdar, 1979). Implicatures are studied from the perspective of Relevance Theory
(Sperber and Wilson 1986) and from a neo-Gricean perspective (e.g., Levinson, 2000).
language and all languages should exhibit a similar process of implied meaning inferencing.
Therefore, the issue of transfer from the native language plays out in an interesting way in this
area of linguistic pragmatics. The mechanisms of scalar implicature computation, whatever they
are, can readily be transfered from the native language of the learner. On the other hand,
implicature in certain situations certainly depends on the lexical knowledge of set expressions, or
chunks.
(1988, 1994). Initially based on a cross-sectional picture, Bouton followed the development of
9
several types of conversational implicature such as relevance and implied criticism. He tested
two groups of students after 17 months and after 54 months in the US. The general conclusion
from his findings was that the learners were capable of computing implicature after a period of
study in the US. The only area of uncertainty and difficulty remained “specific points of
American culture and not the type of implicature involved” (Bouton 1994: 163). Bouton’s
findings confirmed that implicature is a cognitive process distinct from cultural knowledge and
that its acquisition does benefit from instruction and longer exposure to the target language.
The effect of the learning environment, in the target language country or in the native
language country, was taken up by Röver (2005). The study tested ESL and EFL learners and
implicatures, e.g., indicating agreement that should have been patently obvious to the
interlocutor by saying “Is the Pope Catholic?” and conversational implicatures that had to be
computed online without the benefit of conventional expressions (Q: Are you coming to the
party? A: I have to work, where the answer means No). Results revealed no effect of L2
Recently, Taguchi (2008) examined the comprehension speed and accuracy of Japanese ESL and
EFL learners. She employed a pragmatic listening task with indirect refusals and indirect
opinions and she administered it twice: before and after a 5 to 7 week period of instruction.
Results indicate that both learning groups improved in speed and accuracy, suggesting that the
learning environment does not have a decisive effect on interlanguage pragmatics. In other
words, even a foreign language classroom affords sufficient input for the learners to make
decisive gains in pragmalinguistic competence. In this respect, these two studies contradicted
earlier findings suggesting that instruction in a study-abroad situation was beneficial for
10
pragmatic development (Bardovi-Harlig and Dörnyei 1998).
children can answer experimental questions in a pragmatic way, but not until the ages of 5 to 7
(Guasti et al, 2005; Papafragou and Musolino, 2003). A central question of the child acquisition
the maturation of some cognitive capacity in children, we expect adult learners to be much better
at it than children learning their mother tongue. Not only are they cognitively mature individuals
but their native language is in a position to assist them in inference calculation. If, on the other
hand, scalar implicature computation depends on processing capacity because it involves choice
of an optimal competitor within a narrowly constructed set of options (a sentence with some
versus a sentence with not all), we could expect adult learners to have more difficulty than adult
These predictions were tested in Slabakova (2010) and Lieberman (2009). Slabakova
one experiment the participants had to judge the felicity of underinformative sentences without
context as in (6) and had to say whether they agree with the statement.
A positive answer represents the logical option since some and indeed all elephants have
informative; the negative is the pragmatic answer. The test sentences were translated in Korean
and administered to Korean native speakers, as well as to English natives in English. Slabakova
found differences in the Korean speakers’ performance in their native and in their second
11
language. They gave around 40% pragmatic answers in their native language (not significantly
different from the English native group) and about 60% pragmatic answers in their second
language. The results suggest that L2 learners have no problem computing scalar implicatures;
indeed they do so more often than native speakers. In the second experiment with added context,
the learners gave pragmatic answers over 90% of the time. Slabakova (2010) argues that the
difference between native and second language speakers is due to processing resources. Since the
logical responses are arguably due to conjuring up alternative contexts in order to agree with the
logical use of some (only some elephants have trunks because some others may have been
injured, or born without trunks, Guasti et al 2005), speakers have a harder time coming up with
A sentence such as (7) involves an indirect implicature because of a scale reversal and is harder
to process than the direct implicature in (8), even for native speakers (Gillingham, 2007).
<partly, completely>, as well as every in the scope of negation. Participants had to evaluate the
felicity of sentences in short contexts. When forced to judge the acceptability of single test
sentences, native speakers as well as learners had difficulty computing the indirect implicatures
compared to the direct one. The nonnative speakers were even less accurate than the natives,
suggesting that in these cases there is indeed a processing problem and the native nonnative
12
differences are a matter of degree. When the processing load was reduced by presenting the
participants with two alternatives, one felicitous and one infelicitous, the nonnative speakers had
no trouble with the task and performed similarly to the native speakers. It is interesting to note
that neither in Slabakova (2010) nor in Lieberman (2009) was proficiency a factor in the
learners’ performance.
executive functioning (involving attention, inhibition and focusing) in children and adults.
Bialystok (2001), Bialystok and Senman (2004), Bialystok and Martin (2004) and others have
shown that bilinguals often exhibit significantly superior executive functioning and attentional
abilities that are associated with better responses on metacognitive and metalinguistic tasks. Thus
This research question is examined by Siegal, Iozzi and Surian (2009), which compares
pragmatic competence in bilingual and monolingual children. Children participating in this study
were bilingual in Italian and Slovenian, or monolingual in either language. The researchers tested
3–6-year-old children on a conversational violations test to find out whether they would obey
Gricean maxims. Results of two experiments in Siegal et al. (2009) show that there is a definite
advantage of the bilingual children over the monolingual ones on four Gricean maxims: Quantity
II, Quality, Relation and Politeness. Bilingual children were more accurate in choosing non-
redundant answers, true answers over false ones, answers that were relevant to the questions, and
polite answers over rude ones. The only maxim on which all the children performed equally well
and hovered at around 60% pragmatic responses was the Maxim of Quantity I. Here is a test
item:
13
(9) Question: “What did you get for your birthday?”
Results of 60% pragmatic answers for children before the age of six are largely in line with other
however, Siegal et al. (2009) do not establish an advantage for bilingual children comprehending
knowledge with scalar implicature knowledge in L2 speakers. Findings suggest that when
universal computation mechanisms are at play, learners have no trouble comprehending them;
when culturally specific knowledge or formulaic expressions are involved, learners are less
accurate. In addition, the bilingual advantage may only be afforded with respect to the latter but
While reference in linguistic pragmatic theory is concerned with the aboutness of the utterance
factors that lead to the introduction of a new referent in a discourse, the linguistic form that the
speaker chooses on its first mention, the linguistic forms employed for repeated reference to the
same entity and the interaction between linguistic (encoded) and contextual (inferred) cues that
determine the hearer’s identification of the intended referent. Two influential theoretical
proposals on reference resolution within generative linguistics are Chomsky’s (1981) binding
14
Theory and Reinhart and Reuland’s (1993) Reflexivity Theory. While the former uses
predominantly syntactic concepts to formulate its constraints, the latter uses semantic and
Reuland, 1991; Pollard & Sag, 1992; Pollard & Xue, 2001) have pointed out serious problems
for any purely syntactic account and proposed that interpretation of anaphora is determined not
only by syntactic constraints, but also by pragmatic constraints. The discourse principles have
that in several languages, such as Chinese and Korean, pragmatics play a central role and thus,
binding of reflexives may be primarily subject to principles of language use, while in English,
syntactic constraints, such as c-command and locality, are fundamental factors in reflexive
the best interpretation’ (Atlas & Levinson, 1981): implicature may cancel some possible
interpretations until it finds an antecedent for the reflexive that gives the most informative,
stereotypical interpretation consistent with our knowledge of the world. To illustrate, note
example (10).
‘Grandma Yangi is worried that her daughterj is not willing to look after heri/
4
“Logophoricity refers to the phenomenon in which the perspective of an internal protagonist of a sentence or
discourse, as opposed to that of the current, external speaker, is being reported by some morphological and/or
syntactic means. (Huang 2005: 310)” Contrastiveness refers to the usage of emphatic pronouns which highlight a
contrast to current expectations or involving a “he and not anyone else” type of interpretation. Discourse prominence
captures the fact that some discourse referents are more prominent than others in a given discourse situation.
15
herselfj.’
In English, herself and Grandma cannot corefer on syntactic grounds. In Chinese, the
reflexive can be referentially dependent on the local subject and on the long-distance subject.
However, the local subject interpretation can be rejected when it is inconsistent with our
knowledge of the world. The anaphor ziji in (10) is preferably interpreted as referentially
dependent on the embedded subject, in this case nüer ‘daughter’. But this is not the best
interpretation since it contradicts our knowledge of the world: stereotypical expectations are that
younger people look after older people. The main verb danxin ‘worry’ suggests that the person
who the daughter is not willing to look after is not the daughter herself, but the grandma.
Therefore, the interpretation is cancelled, and the I-principle promotes an interpretation that ziji
Only a few studies have addressed the role of pragmatic factors in the acquisition of L2
reflexives thus this is a significantly underresearched area. Thomas (1989a) examined the
large subgroups, Chinese and Spanish. Although Thomas focused on the issue of the resetting of
parameters and of L1 transfer within the generative framework, she also looked at the pragmatic
influences on the interpretation of reflexives. She concluded that unlike native speakers, L2
learners frequently permit non-local binding in bi-clausal sentences, whether or not the NP is
Demirci (2000, 2001), on the other hand, argues that pragmatic knowledge plays an
important role in the L2 learners’ interpretation of reflexives, and interferes with the learners’
16
acquisition of locality conditions in English reflexive binding. Demirci studied the acquisition of
English reflexive by Turkish learners of English at five proficiency levels. Unlike English
reflexives, which only allow an antecedent in the same clause, Turkish reflexives allow both
local and non-local binding. Furthermore, unlike other LD reflexives, such as Chinese reflexive
ziji, Turkish reflexives can be bound by both subject and non-subject antecedents. Therefore,
Turkish native speakers need to rely on inference, context, and knowledge about the world in
order to choose between several possible antecedents. Demirci (2000) contrasted pragmatically
neutral and biased (in favor of a local NP and of a non-local NP) finite and non-finite biclausal
sentences by world knowledge. She concluded that the L2 learners transferred pragmatic
principles from L1 to L2; however, they were not able to overcome the transfer and to acquire
Lee (2008) also used pragmatically biased and neutral test items to check the reflexive
interpretation choices of English and Korean native speakers as well as Korean-native ESL
learners. The surprising finding was that less than 40% of the English control group chose a local
antecedent in biclausal sentences (the expected English choice) when the contexts of the
sentence favored a non-local antecedent. Learners were also swayed by the context to choose a
long-distance antecedent. This suggests that a pragmatic factor, that is, a given context in the
task, induced the native speakers as well as the L2 learners to choose a grammatically
acquisition deserves a lot more attention than it has received in the literature so far. The research
findings to date suggest that even native speakers of languages that have syntactically-
17
constrained binding are influenced by context in interpreting anaphora. A linguistic theory
unifying syntactic and pragmatic binding constraints should spur acquisition studies that take
both factors into account. We will come back to the interpretation of pronouns in the section on
Like anaphora resolution, L2 acquisition of definite descriptions and specificity marking has
largely been treated from a semantic point of view. However, the calculation of definiteness and
specificity happens in real discourse situations, so it is vitally dependent on how the speaker and
Research on article acquisition (Huebner 1983, Thomas 1989b, among many others) has
established that L2-English learners, particularly those speaking a native language without
articles, have persistent difficulties with articles. They often overuse the with indefinites and/or
overuse a with definites. A number of proposals have been made to account for these patterns of
article misuse, including purely syntactic accounts (The Representational Deficit Hypothesis
(Tsimpli and Roussou 1991) and the Prosodic Transfer Hypothesis (Goad and White 2004). In
this section, we will focus on explanations involving the role of speaker vs. hearer discourse-
dependent knowledge.
features [specific referent] or [hearer knowledge]. The success of this explanation has been
criticized on the grounds of insufficient empirical coverage (Thomas 1989) and on imprecise
5
The Language Bioprogram Hypothesis (Bickerton 1981) proposes that the similarity of creoles is due to their
being formed from a prior pidgin by children who all share a universal human innate grammar capacity.
18
semantic definitions of the features (Ionin 2003). Starting from Ionin (2003), a fruitful line of
studies of definiteness has developed that assume a discourse-related definition of this property.
that if a nominal phrase is definite, then the speaker and hearer presuppose the existence of a
unique individual in the set denoted by the NP. Ionin’s definition of specificity encompasses
grammatical and pragmatic specificity and is based on Fodor and Sag’s (1982) definition of
of the speaker about the identity of the referent, the speaker having the referent in mind, the
speaker being able to identify the referent, etc. A crucial difference between the two features is
that definiteness encodes a shared state of knowledge between speaker and hearer while
Based on these definitions, Ionin (2003) and Ionin, Ko and Wexler (2004) proposed the
Article Choice Parameter with two settings in languages that have two articles. In one type of
language, articles are distinguished on the basis of specificity; in the other type articles are
distinguished on the basis of definiteness. This linguistic situation presents specific difficulties
for learners whose native language does not mark these features morphologically. Since the
Article Choice Parameter is a semantic universal, L2 learners fluctuate between the two settings
of the Article Choice Parameter until the input leads them to set this parameter to the appropriate
value. This is known as the Fluctuation Hypothesis and it makes very concrete predictions for the
pattern of errors in L2 acquisition: learners are supposed to make errors overgeneralizing the in
We illustrate how crucial pragmatic knowledge is for supplying and interpreting articles
with examples from Ionin et al (2004: 22-3). The target sentences are in italics and the expected
19
article is in bold.
Meeting on a street
Roberta: Hi, William! It’s nice to see you again. I didn’t know that you were in Boston.
William: I am here for a week. I am visiting (a, the, ----) friend from college—his name is
Rick: Yes, but he’s on the phone. It’s an important business matter. He is talking to (a,
the, ----) owner of his company! I don’t know who that person is—but I know that this
Ionin et al (2004) tested beginning, intermediate, and advanced learners of English with
Russian or Korean as their native languages. Both Russian and Korean lack articles. The
researchers employed a forced-choice elicitation task and a production task as in examples (11)
and (12), as well as in [+definite, +specific] and [−definite, −specific] situations. Group results
from the Russian learners largely support the Fluctuation Hypothesis in the sense that learners
overused article in precisely the predicted learning conditions. However, the individual results
presented a more complex picture where a number of individual subjects did not exhibit the
expected pattern. In addition, their production results revealed that learners overused the with
The series of studies by Ionin and colleagues has proved highly influential and has
inspired a number of following studies. For example, Zdorenko and Paradis (2008) finds that in
the case of child L2 learners of English, all informants fluctuate between definiteness and
20
specificity, no matter what their L1 is (only children from article-less L1s exhibited article
omission). Garcia-Mayo (2009) uses the same English forced-choice elicitation task used by
Ionin et al. (2004) with two groups of native speakers of Spanish, one of low-intermediate
proficiency in English and the other of advanced proficiency. Results show no evidence for
fluctuation even at the low-intermediate proficiency level. However, Spanish and English articles
share the encoding of definiteness, although Spanish articles additionally encode gender. Ionin,
Zubizarreta and Bautista-Maldonado (2008) replicated Garcia Mayo’s findings and found that L1
transfer took precedence over fluctuation in the case of Spanish learners of English. Snape
(2009) confirmed the fluctuation findings with Chinese learners of English while only half of
Tryzna’s (2009) Polish native speakers learning English showed the expected pattern. Finally,
overuse of a with definites was practically non-existent in the performance of Zdorenko and
Paradis’s children.
Ionin, Zubizarreta and Philippov (2009) modified the original Fluctuation Hypothesis
proposed in Ionin et al (2004). New linguistic research (Fuli 2007, Tryzna 2009) has showed that
instead of distinguishing between articles based on specificity and not definiteness, Samoan
distinguishes specificity, but within indefinites only. Since the universal specificity distinction is
only demonstrated within a part of the article space, children and adult L2 learners are expected
to be overusing the with specific indefinites, but not overuse a with non-specific definites. Ionin
et al. (2009) argue that only specificity-related errors with indefinites, not specificity-related
errors with definites, reflect L2-learners’ access to the semantic universal of specificity. Their
revised proposal was anticipated in some of the results from Ionin et al (2004) and receives
21
Trenkic (2008) takes issue with Ionin et al.’s operationalization of specificity as in items
designed as [+specific] in their experiment such as those in (11) above, where there is an explicit
statement of the speaker’s familiarity with the referent. Trenkic argues that the semantic
universal of specificity is not really at play in the learners’ grammars, what they are sensitive to
is “explicitly stated knowledge”. Based on her critique of Ionin’s test items, Trenkic provides an
alternative explanation: L2-English learners are mis-analyzing the and a as adjectives, and
assigning the meanings of “identifiable” and “unidentifiable” to them. Ionin et al (2009) argue
against Trenkic’s explanation of article mis-analysis and provide their own explanation in terms
In this section, we reviewed L2 learner’s choice of definite and indefinite articles based
on the discourse information provided by the utterance context. The current findings suggest that
some adult learners fluctuate between marking definiteness and specificity, other groups of
learners at similar proficiency levels do not fluctuate much, and child learners only overuse the
with specific indefinites but not a with non-specific definites. We also reviewed two versions of
the Fluctuation Hypothesis, an influential current explanation for the error patterns. There is still
more to explain in the findings to date. The burden of proof is on the researchers providing
6. Deixis
A search of the terms “deixis” and “second language acquisition” in the LLBA database yields a
miserly number of published articles, 5 or 6 altogether. At the same time, deixis underlies all
pragmatics and is such a fundamental property of human language that without it no human
communication would exist. Thus this section will list linguistic properties that are still awaiting
22
its second language acquisition researchers and whose acquisition patterns will give us important
Deixis refers to the phenomenon wherein understanding the meaning of certain words
and phrases in an utterance requires contextual information. Words that have a fixed semantic
meaning but have a denotational meaning that constantly changes depending on time and/or
place, are deictic. Classical examples involve the meaning of personal pronouns and adverbs
such as tomorrow and here. Deixis is a pervasive and complex linguistic phenomenon that
covers diverse aspects related to time, space and social aspects of the communicative context.
Levinson (2004: 103) cogently points out that there is a dynamic coexistence between the
indexical sign and its object of reference. The deictic linguistic expressions are not sufficient to
achieve reference without contextual support, but that support is provided “by the mutual
attention of the interlocutors and their ability to reconstruct the speaker’s referential intentions
given clues in the environment.” A programmatic chapter in Klein (1986) is chapter 7 entitled
“The embedding problem.” “Any utterance, whether belonging to a learner variety or to the
target language, is embedded in the speaker’s and hearer’s informational set-up, composed of
current perception, recollection of preceding events and utterances, and knowledge of the world
(Klein 1986: 112).” Klein discusses the necessity to always assess second language knowledge
and performance embedded in context. He gives the example of the utterance in (13) produced
by a migrant worker in a bakery, which can be considered ungrammatical if its context is not
(13) Me bread.
23
While the indexical properties of the utterance are impeccable, considering that it is
produced in a place that sells bread, the sentence may not even be ungrammatical if uttered after
(14) Here’s your apple pie, Madam. Now, what would you like, Sir?
In order to understand an utterance, a learner must possess shared knowledge of the origo
of the speaker, the lexical meaning of the deictic word, and where to draw the line about the
origo (now may mean ‘today’ or ‘this year’ or ‘in recent years’ depending on the situation). The
origo is the “ground zero” around which the deictic field is organized (Bühler 1935): it consists
of information about the speaker, the time and place of speaking. In order to produce an
appropriate utterance, the learner must take into account the origo as well as the contextual
knowledge of the hearer. While certain aspects of Klein’s embedding problem have found its
Among the different types of deixis, one that has attracted traditional attention is person
deixis, having to do with the personal pronouns I, we, etc. Note that when Sally produces we in
(15) and in (16), the denotation of we is different and it depends on an active listener to
understand.
Another type is space deixis, where demonstratives and adverbs like here and there are
discussed. Unless otherwise specified, place deictic terms are generally understood to be relative
to the location of the speaker, as in (17), where the speaker and the shop are positioned on
24
Languages usually show at least a two-way referential distinction in their deictic system:
proximal, i.e. near or closer to the speaker, and distal, i.e. far from the speaker and/or closer to
the addressee. English exemplifies this with such pairs as this and that, here and there, etc. In
other languages, the distinction is three-way: proximal, i.e. near the speaker, medial, i.e. near the
addressee, and distal, i.e. far from both. The three German demonstrative pronouns, hier, da,
dort, corresponding to here, here/there, there, may be analyzed that way. Some systems combine
both speaker- and addressee-anchored systems, as in the Yélî Dnye demonstrative determiners
(Levinson 2000).
Niimura and Hayashi (1995) and Gajdos (2011) are among the very few studies that have
examined the L2 acquisition of a deictic mismatch. Niimura and Hayashi compare English this
and that with Japanese demonstratives ko, so and a. They argue that the choice is highly
subjective and psychological, rather than physical, proximity is a determining factor in both
language systems. However, in English, focus, or the degree of attention on the referent, is the
critical determinant whereas in Japanese the overriding factor is whether or not the referent is in
the domain of the speaker's direct experience. Niimura and Hayashi (1995) studied natives’ and
person focus system (English), there was more variety in demonstrative choice than in the
situation focus system (Japanese). Therefore, learners of Japanese had answers more widely
distant from native answers compared to learners of English, but on the whole even advanced
learners diverged a lot from the native performance. The findings of Gajdos (2011), which
studied L2 acquisition of German hier, dort and da by native speakers of English, point to the
same conclusion. On a picture and text acceptability judgment task, all of Gaijdos’s participants
demonstrated native-like knowledge of hier and dort, which are equivalent to English here and
25
there. Even near-native speakers did not accept the spatial adverb da, which has no equivalent in
English, as often as the natives did. However, the large variability in the judgments of the native
speakers (48-95% on various test items) underscores the difficulty of the learning task.
relation to the speaker’s deictic origo, the hearer’s knowledge and the situational context. From
this marking, the hearer should be able to infer the time of the event and its position on the time
line. Klein (1986: 125) describes four kinds of factors involved in time marking: a common time
conception shared by speaker and hearer; a common point of reference such as the deictic origo
(e.g. the moment of speech); means for marking temporal spans or relations such as adverbials
and verb tenses; certain discourse rules based on common knowledge, for example the Principle
of Natural Order (unless marked otherwise, the sequence of events mentioned in an utterance
The marking of temporal deixis has been studied in the so-called “Basic Variety,” the
speech of naturalistic (uninstructed) learners in the European Science Foundation (ESF) corpus.
The corpus incorporates longitudinal data from adult migrant workers in five European countries
with target languages English, French, Dutch, German, and Swedish (Dietrich, Klein and Noyau,
1995; Klein and Perdue 1997; Perdue and Klein 1992, Meisel 1987, see also a review of these
studies in Bardovi-Harling 2000, ch. 2). The main finding is that the untutored learners “are
perfectly able to express temporal reference and relations despite the complete absence of verbal
morphology and even verbs in a large proportion of their utterances. (Dietrich et al 1995: 6)” An
26
“After he came back from vacation in Turkey, my husband was ill.”
non-European studies as well. For example, Sato (1990) examined the development of L2 past
tense inflection (among other properties) in two Vietnamese-speaking bothers aged 10 and 12
adopted in a US family. During the ten-month period of observation, the brothers did not mark
temporality with morphological means and relied on other means, such as adverbials and the
interlocutor’s marking of past tense. Findings of this type highlight the fact that deictic
(pragmatic) marking of temporality is indeed universal and is the foundation for the development
of morphological marking. It is also clear from this literature that the development of aspectual
and tense morphology beyond the Basic Variety happens over a long period of time and emerges
The marking of temporality in instructed learners proceeds very differently from that of
uninstructed learners. There is a vast literature on this topic, surveyed in Bardovi-Harlig (2000),
among many others. Bardovi-Harlig (2000, ch. 2) shows that learners develop functional, and
often rich, means of temporal expression before the acquisition of verbal morphology, and the
use of lexical adverbials to mark temporality continues long after the acquisition of tense
morphology. While the marking of temporality through morphological means is beyond the
purview of this chapter, it is important to note that the study of deictic temporal marking should
be expanded beyond the morphological means to include the pragmatic means of that marking.
For example, this deictic marking of the time line and temporal relations becomes crucially
important when a learner whose native language marks temporality morphologically (say
English) approaches a language that does not (say Mandarin Chinese). It is expected that such
27
learners will have access to the universal temporal deictic schema, but this access is not
Finally, social deixis marks the social role or status of the participants in the speech
event. Special expressions exist in many languages, including the honorifics of Southeast Asian
languages (Thai, Japanese, Javanese, Korean) and the so-called T/V distinction in Slavic
languages, Spanish, German and French. The latter label is based on the Latin pronouns tu ‘you-
sg’ and vos ‘you-pl’ (Brown and Gilman, 1960): when used to a single interlocutor, tu and its
equivalents are informal while vos and its equivalents are a formal means of address implying
social distance. While the linguistic structures involved are simple, the cultural context in which
they are deployed is complex and involves an understanding of how interpersonal relationships
are constructed and communicated in the languages which distinguish T/V pronouns. These
distinctions are widely studied in the L2 pragmatics literature on conventional expressions (e.g.,
Dijkstra, 2006; Liddicoat 2006; Dewaele, 2004 among others). Findings suggest that while
perception of the pragmatic distinction is not a problem (Dijkstra 2006), the target-like
production of these lags behind perception for a long time (Lyster, 2004).
In summary, the universal concept of deixis describes the embedding of every human
utterance in the surrounding context and is a much more pervasive feature of language than
normally recognized. While some aspects of deictic marking have been studied widely, e.g.,
social deixis, others have not enjoyed much attention, e.g., person and space deixis. After 25
years, the bottom-line message of Klein’s (1986) chapter 7 still rings true: there is a lot of work
that still remains to be done on context embedding in learner varieties. The most important
28
7. Information structure (the syntax-discourse interface)
The marking and comprehension of information structure, or topic and focus, has enjoyed prime
attention in the generative L2 literature in the last decade. A lot of attention has been paid to
motivated distinctions. Generative linguists assume a language architecture that is modular: the
within which specialized internal linguistic processes go on, for example feature checking and
displacement of constituents within the syntax module. Between each two modules, however,
another type of linguistic process occurs, the so-called interface processes. The latter take units
of one module and map it to units in another module (Jackendoff 2002, Chomsky 1995). Thus
interface processes are by definition more complex and involve keeping more information in
The syntax-discourse interface has a privileged position in this language architecture. For
some scholars (e.g., Jackendoff 2002, topic-focus calculation is part of the conceptual (largely
semantic) module. For others (e.g., Reinhart 2006), it is outside of the semantic module and is an
interface between language and extra-linguistic reality. Whether one or the other approach is
correct is actually an empirical question. However, under both approaches the syntax-discourse
interface is the meeting place between language and other cognitive systems.
Looking into the endstate competence of near-native learners, the Interface Hypothesis
(Sorace 2003, Sorace and Filiaci 2006) proposed that if these learners’s grammars diverge from
native speakers’, the divergence is more likely to be within the syntax-discourse interface than at
other interfaces. A more recent version of the hypothesis (Sorace and Serratrice 2009, Sorace
2011) argues that linguistic structures at this interface are prone to lasting optionality of
29
judgement (in the sense that learners treat the acceptable and the unacceptable versions of the
construction equally) and hence even near-native learners exhibit non-native grammatical
competence. For an excellent review of recent research at the linguistic interfaces and the
Interface Hypothesis, see White (2011). In agreement with White (2011), in this section I will
review some seminal research findings and suggest that the sweeping proposal that all properties
The interrelated notions of topic (or theme, what a given sentence is about, thus
discourse-old information) and focus (or rheme, what is predicated of this topic, hence
discourse-new information) have been studied ever since the Prague School of linguistics in the
30ies. In second language acquisition, researchers have been preoccupied with whether learners
encode and comprehend these notions through the use of null and overt subjects (in languages
that allow null subjects in the first place), word order (post-verbal versus preverbal subjects) and
clitic-doubling of displaced topics. Research findings have been decidedly mixed. First of all, at
lower proficiency levels, learners do not demonstrate sensitivity to discourse new and old
information (Lozano 2006, Hertel 2003, Ivanov 2009, Rothman 2009). At near-native levels,
some studies find complete convergence while others find subtle but persistent divergence. We
Findings in Belletti, Bennati and Sorace (2007) present a prime example of difficulties
and optionality at near-native levels. The study investigated knowledge of null subject grammars
by near-native learners of Italian whose native language was English. One of the tasks of the
study was a picture verification task where participants were given a test sentence and 3 pictures
identifying the pronoun antecedent as either the matrix subject, the matrix complement, or an
external referent. The null subject is appropriate when the subject of the embedded clause is the
30
same as the matrix subject (the old lady) as in (19) below. However, if the speaker wants to shift
the topic from the matrix subject to the matrix object (the girl), she will use an overt pronoun to
mark topic shift as in (20). Thus the non-optional appearance of overt or null embedded subject
the old lady greets the girl when crosses the street
the old lady greets the girl when she crosses the street
“The old lady greets the girl when ∅/she crosses the street.”
In processing sentences such as (20), Italian near-native speakers were found to interpret
the overt pronominal subject of the embedded clause as coreferential with the lexical subject of
the main clause 30% of the time, while the natives only interpreted it in this way 5% of the time,
a significant difference. At the same time, 65% of near-native answers and 85% of native
answers converged on the correct interpretation (embedded subject refers to matrix complement).
Thus the Italian near-natives in this study were less sensitive than the native speakers to topic
English-Spanish interlanguage. One of the tasks of his study was a pragmatic felicity judgment
task, in which he gave a context story and a test sentence to judge for acceptability. Unlike
Belleti et al’s near-natives, Rothman’s advanced speakers performed similarly to the native
much attention, is clitic doubling as a marker of topic (Valenzuela 2005, 2006; Ivanov 2009,
31
Parodi 2009). Topicalization in Spanish and Bulgarian may involve a dislocation of an object
that has a discourse antecedent and the clitic-doubling of that object. Note that Spanish and
Bulgarian clitic-double the dislocated object while English does not, because clitics are not part
There is a crucial requirement that when the object is specific, clitic doubling is
obligatory. However, when the object is non-specific or generic, native speakers allow less
and Ivanov, 2011, for more discussion). Near-native speakers of Spanish in Valenzuela (2005)
were 100% accurate on observing the specificity requirement in a sentence felicity judgment
task. Very advanced learners of Bulgarian in Ivanov (2009) were non-distinguishable from
native speakers in a very similar task. On the other hand, Valenzuela’s near-natives demonstrated
variability in judging generic dislocated objects, perhaps supported by the larger variability in the
input, as ascertained by the native results. To contrast with that, Ivanov’s advanced learners
again patterned with the natives on judging the inappropriateness of clitic-doubling in focus
contexts. Finally, Parodi (2009) used a grammaticality judgement task and contrasted definite
32
and indefinite objects. She found that advanced learners of Spanish patterned like the native
We shall compare two online processing studies next, which, although they do not
investigate the same property, come to a similar conclusion. Roberts, Gulberg and Indefrey
(2008) studied the online and offline performance of Turkish (a null subject language) and
German (non-null subject) learners of Dutch (another non-null subject language) with respect to
ambiguous pronoun resolution. The Turkish speakers chose a clause-external antecedent for an
ambiguous pronoun more often than the German learners. Recall that there is a discourse
preference for an overt pronoun in null subject languages to signal a topic shift (see Italian
example in (20) above. Thus Turkish learners were essentially showing L1 transfer in the offline
task of this study. However, in the online task both advanced learner groups diverged from
native speaker behavior, suggesting that processing of ambiguous pronouns where the choice of
antecedent depends on the context is hard, even if the native language of the learners gives them
an acquisitional advantage.
specifically, discourse-related word order optionality in German. English, Dutch and Russian
acceptability judgment task and an on-line self-paced reading task. Hopp’s results indicate that
both in off-line knowledge and on-line processing, even for L1 English speakers, whose L1 does
not correspond to L2 German in discourse-to-syntax mappings. At the same time, just like
Roberts et al’s conclusions, Hopp points to the fact that L2 speakers have computational
difficulties in the matching between discourse and syntactic information even when their native
33
language has very similar properties to the ones they are acquiring. The challenge for research at
the syntax-discourse interface, then, will be to reconcile the findings of the on-line studies
(Roberts et all 2008, Hopp 2009) with the discrepant findings of the off-line studies (Belletti et
al. 2007 versus Rothman 2009, Valenzuela 2005 versus Ivanov 2009). More online studies of
various properties at this interface involving more languages as L1s and L2s will shed light on
the issue of computational resources as the bottleneck of this type of discourse-related word
In conclusion, this chapter has taken the point of view of pragmatics as a field of
Grice, Carnap and Peirce as opposed to the more sociological conception of other, especially
all context-dependent aspects of meaning encoding and decoding. As in all modules of the
properties, where mismatches between L1 and L2 can occur. It was argued that not all areas of
L2 pragmatics have enjoyed equal attention and inquiry. For example, research on
these imbalances in the coming decades will elucidate the big question of how second language
speakers bring context to bear on syntactic and semantic computations and process both what is
References:
Atlas, J.D. and Levinson, S.C. 1981. It-clefts, informativeness and logical form, in Cole (ed.),
Radical pragmatics, pp.1-61. London: Academic Press.
Austin, J. L. 1962. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bachman, L. 1990. Fundamental Considerations in Language Testing. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
34
Bardovi-Harlig, K. 1999. The interlanguage of interlanguage pragmatics: A research agenda for
acquisitional pragmatics. Language Learning, 49, 677-713.
Bardovi-Harlig, K. 2000. Tense and aspect in second language acquisition: Form, meaning, and
use. Oxford: Blackwell.
Bardovi-Harlig, K. 2005. Contextualizing interlanguage pragmatics, in Tyler, A. E. Takada, M.,
Kim, Y. (eds.), Language in Use: Cognitive and Discourse Perspectives on Language
and Language Learning. Washington, DC, USA: Georgetown University Press, pp. 65-
84.
Bardovi-Harlig, K. 2009. Conventional expressions as a pragmalinguistic resource: Recognition
and production of conventional expressions in L2 pragmatics. Language Learning, 59,
755-795.
Bardovi-Harlig, K. 2011. Pragmatics in SLA. In Gass, S. M. and Mackey, A. (eds.), Handbook of
Second Language Acquisition. London: Routledge.
Bardovi-Harlig, K. and Dörnyei, Z. 1998. Do language learners recognize pragmatic violations?
Pragmatic versus grammatical awareness in instructed L2 learning. TESOL Quarterly, 32,
233–259.
Barron, T. 2006. Learning to say ‘you’ in German: The acquisition of sociolinguistic competence
in a study-abroad context, in M. A. DuFon & E. Churchill (eds.), Language Learners in
Study Abroad Contexts (pp. 59-88). Clevendon, UK: Multilingual Matters.
Belletti, A., Bennati, E., and Sorace, A. 2007. Theoretical and developmental issues in the syntax
of subjects: evidence from near-native Italian. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory,
25, 657–689.
Bialystok, E. 2001. Bilingualism in Development: Language, Literacy, and Cognition.
Cambridge University Press, New York.
Bialystok, E. and Martin, M. 2004. Attention and inhibition in bilingual children: evidence from
the dimensional change card sort task. Developmental Science 7, 325–339.
Bialystok, E. and Senman, L. 2004. Executive processes in appearance reality tasks: the role of
inhibition of attention and symbolic representation. Child Development 75, 562–579.
Bickerton, D. 1981. Roots of language. Ann Arbor, MI: Karoma.
Blum-Kulka, S. 1982. Learning to say what you mean in a second language: A study of the
speech act performance of learners of Hebrew as a second language. Applied Linguistics,
3, 29-59.
Bouton, L. 1994. Can NNS skill in interpreting implicature in American English be improved
through explicit instruction? A pilot study. In: Bouton, L. (Ed.), Pragmatics and
Language Learning Monograph Series, vol. 5. DEIL, University of Illinois at Urbana-
Champaign, pp. 88–109.
Brown, R. and Gilman, A. 1960. The pronouns of power and solidarity. American
Anthropologist 4, 24–39.
Bühler, K. 1935. The deictic field of language and deictic words, reprinted in Jarvella, R. and
Klein, W. (eds.), 1982, Speech, Place and Action: Studies of Deixis and Related Topics,
pp. 9-30. New York: John Wiley.
Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. 1991. Lectures on Government and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
Chomsky, N. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Demirci, M. 2000. The role of pragmatics in reflexive interpretation by Turkish learners of
English. Second Language Research 14, 325-353.
35
Demirci, M. 2001. Acquisition of binding of English reflexives by Turkish L2 learners: A Neo-
Gricean pragmatic account. Journal of Pragmatics 33, 753-775.
Dewaele, J.M. (2004). Vous or tu? Native and Non-Native Speakers of French on a
Sociolinguistic Tightrope, International Review of Applied Linguistics, 42, 4, 383-402.
Dietrich R., Klein W. and C. Noyau (eds.) 1995. The Acquisition of Temporality in a Second
Language, Amsterdam, John Benjamins.
Dijkstra, L. 2006. On pragmatic perception: Do American learners of Russian perceive the
sociocultural weight of the address pronouns? Unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, University
of Iowa.
Fodor, J. D. and Sag, I. A. 1982. Referential and quantificational indefinites. Linguistics and
Philosophy, 5, 355–398.
Fuli, L. T. 2007. Definiteness vs. specificity: An investigation into the terms used to describe
articles in Gagana Samoa. Unpublished Master’s thesis, the University of Auckland.
Gajdos, J. 2011. German demonstrative adverbs od spatial deixis: Evidence from native
speakers, L2 learners and corpora. Unpublished PhD dissertation, University of Iowa.
García Mayo, M. d. P. 2009. Article choice in L2 English by Spanish speakers: Evidence for full
transfer, in M. d. P. García Mayo and R. Hawkins (eds.), Second language acquisition of
articles: Empirical findings and theoretical implications, pp. 13-35. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Gazdar, G.A. (1979). Pragmatics: Implicatures, Presuppositions and Logical Form. New York,
NY: Academic Press.
Goad, H. & White, L. 2004. Ultimate attainment of L2 inflection: Effects of L1 prosodic
structure. EUROSLA Yearbook 4, S. Foster-Cohen, M. Sharwood Smith, A. Sorace & M.
Ota (eds), 119–145. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Grice, P. 1989. Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Guasti, M.T., Cheirchia, G., Crain, S., Foppolo, F., Gualmini, A., and Meroni, L. 2005. Why
children and adults sometimes (but not always) compute implicatures. Language and
Cognitive Processes 20, 667–696.
Hassall, T. 2006. Learning to take leave in social conversations: A diary study, in M. A. DuFon
& E. Churchill (eds.), Language Learners in Study Abroad Contexts (pp. 31-58).
Clevendon, UK: Multilingual Matters.
Heim, I. 1991. Artikel und Definitheit [Articles and definiteness], in A. von Stechow & D.
Wunderlich (eds.), Semantik: Ein internationales Handbuch zeitgen¨ossischer
Forschung/Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary research, pp. 487–
535. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Hertel, T.J. 2003. Lexical and discourse factors in the second language acquisition of Spanish
word order. Second Language Research 19, 273–304.
Holtgraves, T. 2007. Second language learners and speech act comprehension. Language
Learning, 57, 595–610.
Hopp, H. 2009. The syntax-discourse interface in near-native L2 acquisition: Off-line and on-
line performance. Bilingualism: Language and Cognition, 12, 463-483.
Horn, L. 1972. On the semantic properties of the logical operators in English. Doctoral
Dissertation, UCLA.
Horn, L. and Ward, G. (eds.) 2004. The Handbook of Pragmatics. Malden, MA: Blackwell
Publishing.
36
Huang, Y. 1994. The syntax and pragmatics of anaphor. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press
Huang, Y. 2000. Anaphora: a cross-linguistic study. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Huebner, T. 1983. A longitudinal analysis of the acquisition of English. Ann Arbor, MI: Karoma.
Hymes, D.H. 1966. Two types of linguistic relativity, in W. Bright (ed.) Sociolinguistics (pp.
114-158). The Hague: Mouton.
Ionin, T. 2003. Article semantics in second language acquisition. PhD dissertation, MIT
Ionin, T., Ko, H. and Wexler, K. 2004. Article semantics in L2-acquisition: the role of
specificity. Language Acquisition 12, 3-69.
Ionin, T., Zubizarreta, M. L. and Bautista Maldonado, S. 2008. Sources of linguistic knowledge
in the second language acquisition of English articles. Lingua, 118, 554-576.
Ionin, T., Zubizarreta, M. L. and Philippov, V. 2009. Acquisition of article semantics by child
and adult L2-English learners. Bilingualism: Language and Cognition, 12 (3), 337–361.
Ivanov, I. 2009. Topicality and clitic doubling in L2 Bulgarian: a test case for the interface
hypothesis, in Bowles, M., Ionin, T., Montrul, S., Tremblay, A. (eds.), Proceedings of the
10th Generative Approaches to Second Language Acquisition Conference (GASLA 2009)
(pp. 17–24). Cascadilla Proceedings Project, Somerville, MA.
Jackendoff, R. 2002. Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution. Oxford,
UK: Oxford University Press.
Kasper, G. 2001. Classroom research on interlanguage pragmatics. In K. Rose & G. Kasper
(Eds.), Pragmatics in language teaching (pp. 33-60). Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Kasper, G. 2009. L2 pragmatic development, in Ritchie, W. C. and Bhatia, T. K. (eds.), The New
Handbook of Second Language Acquisition (pp. 259-293). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Kasper, G. and Rose, K. 2002. Pragmatic development in a second language. Malden, MA:
Blackwell. [also Language Learning, 52, Supplement 1.]
Klein W. and Perdue, C. 1997. The Basic Variety, Second Language Research 13 (4), pp. 301-
347.
Klein, W. 1986. Second Language Acquisition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Koike, D. A. and Pearson, L. 2005. The effect of instruction and feedback in the development of
pragmatic competence. System 33, 481–501.
Lee, K. Y. 2008. The Role of Pragmatics in Reflexive Interpretation by Korean Learners of
English, in Melissa Bowles, Rebecca Foote, Silvia Perpiñán, and Rakesh Bhatt (eds.),
Selected Proceedings of the 2007 Second Language Research Forum (pp. 97-112).
Cascadilla Proceedings Project, Somerville, MA, USA.
Levinson, S. 2000. Yélî Dnye and the theory of basic color terms. Journal of Linguistic
Anthropology 10, 3-55.
Levinson, S. C. 1983. Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Levinson, S. C. 2000. Presumptive meanings: The theory of generalized conversational
implicature. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Levinson, S. C. 2004. Deixis, in Laurence R. Horn, Gregory L. Ward (eds.) The Handbook of
Pragmatics (pp. 97–120). Blackwell Publishing.
Liddicoat, A. 2006. Learning the culture of interpersonal relationships: Students' understandings
of personal address forms in French. Intercultural Pragmatics, 2006, 3, 1, 55-80
Lieberman, M. 2009. Necessary interpretation at the syntax/pragmatics interface: L2 acquisition
of scalar implicatures. Paper presented at the Workshop on the Mind- Context Divide:
37
Language Acquisition and Interfaces of Cognitive Linguistic Modules. University of
Iowa, April.
Lozano, C. 2006. Focus and split-intransitivity: the acquisition of word order alternations in non-
native Spanish. Second Language Research, 22, 145–187.
Lyster, R. 2004. Research on form-focused instruction in immersion classrooms: Implications for
theory and practice. Journal of French Language Studies, 14, 3, 321-341
Meisel, J. 1987. Reference to past events and actions in the development of natural second
language acquisition, in C. Pfaff (ed.), First and Second Language Acquisition. New
York: Newbury House.
Niimura T. and Hayashi, B. 1996. Contrastive Analysis of English and Japanese Demonstratives
from the perspective of L1 and L2 Acquisition. Language Sciences, Vol. 18, 811-834.
Papafragou, A. and Musolino, J. 2003. Scalar implicatures: experiments at the syntax semantics
interface. Cognition 86, 253–282.
Parodi, T. 2009. Clitic doubling and clitic left dislocation in Spanish and Greek L2 grammars, in
Snape, N., Leung, Y.-K.I., Sharwood Smith, M. (eds.), Re- presentational Deficits in
SLA: Studies in Honor of Roger Hawkins (pp. 167–185). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Perdue, C. and Klein, W. 1992. Why does the production of some learners not grammaticalize?
Studies in Second Language Acquisition, 14, 259-272.
Pollard, C. and Sag, I.A. 1992. Anaphors in English and the scope of binding theory. Linguistic
Inquiry 23, 261-303.
Pollard, C. and Xue, P. 2001. Syntactic and nonsyntactic constraint on long-distance reflexives,
in Cole, P., Hermon, G. & Huang C.-T. J. (eds), Syntax and semantics v. 33, 317-342.
San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
Reinhart, T. 2006. Interface Strategies: Optimal and Costly Computations. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Reinhart, T. and Reuland, E. 1993. Reflexivity. Linguistic Inquiry 24, 657-720.
Reinhart, T. and Reuland, E. 1991. Anaphors and logophors: An argument structure perspective,
in J. Koster and E. Reuland (eds.), Long-distance anaphors. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Roberts, L., Gullberg, M., and Indefrey, P. 2008. Online pronoun resolution in L2 discourse: L1
influence and general learner effects. Studies in Second Language Acquisition, 30, 333–
357.
Rose, K. 2005. On the effects of instruction in second language pragmatics. System, 33, 385-399.
Rose, K.R. and Kasper, G. (eds.) 2001. Pragmatics in Language Teaching. Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge,
Rothman, J. 2009. Pragmatic deficits with syntactic consequences? L2 pronominal subjects and
the syntax-pragmatics interface. Journal of Pragmatics, 41, 951–973.
Röver, C. 2005. Testing EFL Pragmatics. Tübingen: Gunter Narr Verlag.
Sato, C. 1990. The Syntax of Conversation in Interlanguage Development. Tübingen: Günter
Narr.
Searle, J. R. 1969. Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Siegal, M., Iozzi, L. and Surian, L. 2009. Bilingualism and conversational understanding in
young children. Cognition 110, 115–122.
Slabakova, R. 2010. Scalar implicatures in second language acquisition. Lingua 120, 2444-2462.
38
Slabakova, R. and Ivanov, I. 2011. A more careful look at the syntax-discourse interface. Lingua
121, 637-651.
Snape, N. 2009. Exploring Mandarin Chinese speakers’ article use, in N. Snape, Y.-k. I, Leung
and M. Sharwood Smith (eds.), Representational Deficits in SLA: Studies in Honour of
Roger Hawkins (pp. 25-71). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
Sorace, A. 2003. Near-nativeness, in Doughty, C., Long, M. (eds.), Handbook of Second
Language Acquisition (pp. 130–151). Oxford, UK: Blackwell.
Sorace, A. 2011. Pinning down the concept of “interface” in bilingualism. Linguistic Approaches
to Bilingualism 1(1), 1–33.
Sorace, A. and Filiaci, F. 2006. Anaphora resolution in near-native speakers of Italian. Second
Language Research, 22, 339–368.
Sorace, A. and Serratrice, L. 2009. Internal and external interfaces in bilingual language
development: beyond structural overlap. International Journal of Bilingualism, 13, 195–
210.
Sperber, D. and Wilson, D. 1986/1995. Relevance: Communication and Cognition. 2nd edition.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Taguchi, N. 2008. The role of learning environment in the development of pragmatic
comprehension: A Comparison of Gains Between EFL and ESL Learners. Studies in
Second Language Acquisition, 30, 423–452.
Thomas, J. 1983. Cross-cultural pragmatics. Applied Linguistics, 4, 91-112.
Thomas, M. 1989a. The interpretation of English reflexive pronouns by non-native speakers.
Studies in Second Language Acquisition 11, 281-301.
Thomas, M. 1989b. The acquisition of English articles by first- and second language learners.
Applied Psycholinguistics 10, 335-355.
Trenkic, D. 2008. The representation of English articles in second language grammars:
determiners or adjectives? Bilingualism: Language and Cognition 11, 1-18.
Tryzna,M. 2009. Questioning the validity of the Article Choice Parameter and the Fluctuation
Hypothesis: Evidence from L2 English article use by L1 Polish and L1 Mandarin Chinese
speakers, in M. d. P. García Mayo and R. Hawkins (eds.), Second language acquisition of
articles: Empirical findings and theoretical implications (pp. 67-86). Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Valenzuela, E. 2005. L2 Ultimate attainment and the syntax- discourse interface: the acquisition
of topic constructions in Non-Native Spanish and English. Ph.D. Dissertation. McGill
University.
Valenzuela, E. 2006. L2 endstate grammars and incomplete acquisition of the Spanish CLLD
constructions, in Slabakova,R.,Montrul,S.,Prévost, P. (eds.), Inquiries in Linguistic
Development: in Honor of Lydia White (pp.283–304). Amsterdam: John Benjamins.
von Stutterheim,C., and Klein,W. 1987. A concept-oriented approach to second language studies.
In C. W. Pfaff (Ed.), First and second language acquisition processes (pp. 191–205).
Cambridge, MA: Newbury House.
White, L. (2011). Second language acquisition at the interfaces. Lingua 121, 577-590.
Zdorenko, T. and Paradis, J. 2008. The acquisition of articles in child second language English:
Fluctuation, transfer or both? Second Language Research, 24, 227–250.
Zribi-Hertz, A. 1989. Anaphora binding and narrative point of view: English reflexive pronouns
in sentence and discourse. Language 65, 695-727.
39
40