Mikir
Mikir
In their most common sense, the terms thought and thinking refer to conscious cognitive processes
that can happen independently of sensory stimulation. Their most paradigmatic forms are judging,
reasoning, concept formation, problem solving, and deliberation. But other mental processes, like
considering an idea, memory, or imagination, are also often included. These processes can happen
internally independent of the sensory organs, unlike perception. But when understood in the widest
sense, any mental event may be understood as a form of thinking, including perception and unconscious
mental processes. In a slightly different sense, the term thought refers not to the mental processes
themselves but to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes.
Various theories of thinking have been proposed, some of which aim to capture the characteristic
features of thought. Platonists hold that thinking consists in discerning and inspecting Platonic forms
and their interrelations. It involves the ability to discriminate between the pure Platonic forms
themselves and the mere imitations found in the sensory world. According to Aristotelianism, to think
about something is to instantiate in one's mind the universal essence of the object of thought. These
universals are abstracted from sense experience and are not understood as existing in a changeless
intelligible world, in contrast to Platonism. Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism: it
identifies thinking with mentally evoking concepts instead of instantiating essences. Inner speech
theories claim that thinking is a form of inner speech in which words are silently expressed in the
thinker's mind. According to some accounts, this happens in a regular language, like English or French.
The language of thought hypothesis, on the other hand, holds that this happens in the medium of a
unique mental language called Mentalese. Central to this idea is that linguistic representational systems
are built up from atomic and compound representations and that this structure is also found in thought.
Associationists understand thinking as the succession of ideas or images. They are particularly
interested in the laws of association that govern how the train of thought unfolds. Behaviorists, by
contrast, identify thinking with behavioral dispositions to engage in public intelligent behavior as a
reaction to particular external stimuli. Computationalism is the most recent of these theories. It sees
thinking in analogy to how computers work in terms of the storage, transmission, and processing of
information.
Various types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature. A judgment is a mental operation in
which a proposition is evoked and then either affirmed or denied. Reasoning, on the other hand, is the
process of drawing conclusions from premises or evidence. Both judging and reasoning depend on the
possession of the relevant concepts, which are acquired in the process of concept formation. In the case
of problem solving, thinking aims at reaching a predefined goal by overcoming certain obstacles.
Deliberation is an important form of practical thought that consists in formulating possible courses of
action and assessing the reasons for and against them. This may lead to a decision by choosing the most
favorable option. Both episodic memory and imagination present objects and situations internally, in
an attempt to accurately reproduce what was previously experienced or as a free rearrangement,
respectively. Unconscious thought is thought that happens without being directly experienced. It is
sometimes posited to explain how difficult problems are solved in cases where no conscious thought was
employed.
Definition
The terms "thought" and "thinking" refer to a wide variety of psychological activities.[1][2][3] In their
most common sense, they are understood as conscious processes that can happen independently of
sensory stimulation.[4][5] This includes various different mental processes, like considering an idea or
proposition or judging it to be true. In this sense, memory and imagination are forms of thought but
perception is not.[6] In a more restricted sense, only the most paradigmatic cases are considered
thought. These involve conscious processes that are conceptual or linguistic and sufficiently abstract,
like judging, inferring, problem solving, and deliberating.[1][7][8] Sometimes the terms "thought" and
"thinking" are understood in a very wide sense as referring to any form of mental process, conscious or
unconscious.[9][10] In this sense, they may be used synonymously with the term "mind". This usage is
encountered, for example, in the Cartesian tradition, where minds are understood as thinking things,
and in the cognitive sciences.[6][11][12][13] But this sense may include the restriction that such processes
have to lead to intelligent behavior to be considered thought.[14] A contrast sometimes found in the
academic literature is that between thinking and feeling. In this context, thinking is associated with a
sober, dispassionate, and rational approach to its topic while feeling involves a direct emotional
engagement.[15][16][17]
The terms "thought" and "thinking" can also be used to refer not to the mental processes themselves but
to mental states or systems of ideas brought about by these processes.[18] In this sense, they are often
synonymous with the term "belief" and its cognates and may refer to the mental states which either
belong to an individual or are common among a certain group of people.[19][20] Discussions of thought
in the academic literature often leave it implicit which sense of the term they have in mind.
The word thought comes from Old English þoht, or geþoht, from the stem of þencan "to conceive of in
the mind, consider".[21]
Theories of thinking
Various theories of thinking have been proposed.[22] They aim to capture the characteristic features of
thinking. The theories listed here are not exclusive: it may be possible to combine some without leading
to a contradiction.
Platonism
According to Platonism, thinking is a spiritual activity in which Platonic forms and their interrelations
are discerned and inspected.[22][23] This activity is understood as a form of silent inner speech in which
the soul talks to itself.[24] Platonic forms are seen as universals that exist in a changeless realm different
from the sensible world. Examples include the forms of goodness, beauty, unity, and sameness.[25][26]
[27] On this view, the difficulty of thinking consists in being unable to grasp the Platonic forms and to
distinguish them as the original from the mere imitations found in the sensory world. This means, for
example, distinguishing beauty itself from derivative images of beauty.[23] One problem for this view is
to explain how humans can learn and think about Platonic forms belonging to a different realm.[22]
Plato himself tries to solve this problem through his theory of recollection, according to which the soul
already was in contact with the Platonic forms before and is therefore able to remember what they are
like.[23] But this explanation depends on various assumptions usually not accepted in contemporary
thought.[23]
Conceptualism is closely related to Aristotelianism. It states that thinking consists in mentally evoking
concepts. Some of these concepts may be innate, but most have to be learned through abstraction from
sense experience before they can be used in thought.[22]
It has been argued against these views that they have problems in accounting for the logical form of
thought. For example, to think that it will either rain or snow, it is not sufficient to instantiate the
essences of rain and snow or to evoke the corresponding concepts. The reason for this is that the
disjunctive relation between the rain and the snow is not captured this way.[22] Another problem shared
by these positions is the difficulty of giving a satisfying account of how essences or concepts are learned
by the mind through abstraction.[22]
Inner speech theory has a strong initial plausibility since introspection suggests that indeed many
thoughts are accompanied by inner speech. But its opponents usually contend that this is not true for all
types of thinking.[22][5][33] It has been argued, for example, that forms of daydreaming constitute non-
linguistic thought.[34] This issue is relevant to the question of whether animals have the capacity to
think. If thinking is necessarily tied to language then this would suggest that there is an important gap
between humans and animals since only humans have a sufficiently complex language. But the existence
of non-linguistic thoughts suggests that this gap may not be that big and that some animals do indeed
think.[33][35][36]
The language of thought hypothesis states that the same is true for thinking in general. This would mean
that thought is composed of certain atomic representational constituents that can be combined as
described above.[37][32][40] Apart from this abstract characterization, no further concrete claims are
made about how human thought is implemented by the brain or which other similarities to natural
language it has.[37] The language of thought hypothesis was first introduced by Jerry Fodor.[32][37] He
argues in favor of this claim by holding that it constitutes the best explanation of the characteristic
features of thinking. One of these features is productivity: a system of representations is productive if it
can generate an infinite number of unique representations based on a low number of atomic
representations.[37][32][40] This applies to thought since human beings are capable of entertaining an
infinite number of distinct thoughts even though their mental capacities are quite limited. Other
characteristic features of thinking include systematicity and inferential coherence.[32][37][40] Fodor
argues that the language of thought hypothesis is true as it explains how thought can have these features
and because there is no good alternative explanation.[37] Some arguments against the language of
thought hypothesis are based on neural networks, which are able to produce intelligent behavior without
depending on representational systems. Other objections focus on the idea that some mental
representations happen non-linguistically, for example, in the form of maps or images.[37][32]
Computationalists have been especially interested in the language of thought hypothesis since it
provides ways to close the gap between thought in the human brain and computational processes
implemented by computers.[37][32][41] The reason for this is that processes over representations that
respect syntax and semantics, like inferences according to the modus ponens, can be implemented by
physical systems using causal relations. The same linguistic systems may be implemented through
different material systems, like brains or computers. In this way, computers can think.[37][32]
Associationism
An important view in the empiricist tradition has been associationism, the view that thinking consists in
the succession of ideas or images.[1][42][43] This succession is seen as being governed by laws of
association, which determine how the train of thought unfolds.[1][44] These laws are different from
logical relations between the contents of thoughts, which are found in the case of drawing inferences by
moving from the thought of the premises to the thought of the conclusion.[44] Various laws of
association have been suggested. According to the laws of similarity and contrast, ideas tend to evoke
other ideas that are either very similar to them or their opposite. The law of contiguity, on the other
hand, states that if two ideas were frequently experienced together, then the experience of one tends to
cause the experience of the other.[1][42] In this sense, the history of an organism's experience determines
which thoughts the organism has and how these thoughts unfold.[44] But such an association does not
guarantee that the connection is meaningful or rational. For example, because of the association
between the terms "cold" and "Idaho", the thought "this coffee shop is cold" might lead to the thought
"Russia should annex Idaho".[44]
One form of associationism is imagism. It states that thinking involves entertaining a sequence of
images where earlier images conjure up later images based on the laws of association.[22] One problem
with this view is that we can think about things that we cannot imagine. This is especially relevant when
the thought involves very complex objects or infinities, which is common, for example, in mathematical
thought.[22] One criticism directed at associationism in general is that its claim is too far-reaching.
There is wide agreement that associative processes as studied by associationists play some role in how
thought unfolds. But the claim that this mechanism is sufficient to understand all thought or all mental
processes is usually not accepted.[43][44]
Behaviorism
According to behaviorism, thinking consists in behavioral dispositions to engage in certain publicly
observable behavior as a reaction to particular external stimuli.[45][46][47] On this view, having a
particular thought is the same as having a disposition to behave in a certain way. This view is often
motivated by empirical considerations: it is very difficult to study thinking as a private mental process
but it is much easier to study how organisms react to a certain situation with a given behavior.[47] In this
sense, the capacity to solve problems not through existing habits but through creative new approaches is
particularly relevant.[48] The term "behaviorism" is also sometimes used in a slightly different sense
when applied to thinking to refer to a specific form of inner speech theory.[49] This view focuses on the
idea that the relevant inner speech is a derivative form of regular outward speech.[1] This sense overlaps
with how behaviorism is understood more commonly in philosophy of mind since these inner speech
acts are not observed by the researcher but merely inferred from the subject's intelligent behavior.[49]
This remains true to the general behaviorist principle that behavioral evidence is required for any
psychological hypothesis.[47]
One problem for behaviorism is that the same entity often behaves differently despite being in the same
situation as before.[50][51] This problem consists in the fact that individual thoughts or mental states
usually do not correspond to one particular behavior. So thinking that the pie is tasty does not
automatically lead to eating the pie, since various other mental states may still inhibit this behavior, for
example, the belief that it would be impolite to do so or that the pie is poisoned.[52][53]
Computationalism
Computationalist theories of thinking, often found in the cognitive sciences, understand thinking as a
form of information processing.[41][54][45] These views developed with the rise of computers in the
second part of the 20th century, when various theorists saw thinking in analogy to computer operations.
[54] On such views, the information may be encoded differently in the brain, but in principle, the same
operations take place there as well, corresponding to the storage, transmission, and processing of
information.[1][13] But while this analogy has some intuitive attraction, theorists have struggled to give a
more explicit explanation of what computation is. A further problem consists in explaining the sense in
which thinking is a form of computing.[45] The traditionally dominant view defines computation in
terms of Turing machines, though contemporary accounts often focus on neural networks for their
analogies.[41] A Turing machine is capable of executing any algorithm based on a few very basic
principles, such as reading a symbol from a cell, writing a symbol to a cell, and executing instructions
based on the symbols read.[41] This way it is possible to perform deductive reasoning following the
inference rules of formal logic as well as simulating many other functions of the mind, such as language
processing, decision making, and motor control.[54][45] But computationalism does not only claim that
thinking is in some sense similar to computation. Instead, it is claimed that thinking just is a form of
computation or that the mind is a Turing machine.[45]
Computationalist theories of thought are sometimes divided into functionalist and representationalist
approaches.[45] Functionalist approaches define mental states through their causal roles but allow both
external and internal events in their causal network.[55][56][57] Thought may be seen as a form of
program that can be executed in the same way by many different systems, including humans, animals,
and even robots. According to one such view, whether something is a thought only depends on its role
"in producing further internal states and verbal outputs".[58][55] Representationalism, on the other
hand, focuses on the representational features of mental states and defines thoughts as sequences of
intentional mental states.[59][45] In this sense, computationalism is often combined with the language of
thought hypothesis by interpreting these sequences as symbols whose order is governed by syntactic
rules.[45][32]
Various arguments have been raised against computationalism. In one sense, it seems trivial since
almost any physical system can be described as executing computations and therefore as thinking. For
example, it has been argued that the molecular movements in a regular wall can be understood as
computing an algorithm since they are "isomorphic to the formal structure of the program" in question
under the right interpretation.[45] This would lead to the implausible conclusion that the wall is
thinking. Another objection focuses on the idea that computationalism captures only some aspects of
thought but is unable to account for other crucial aspects of human cognition.[45][54]
Types of thinking
A great variety of types of thinking are discussed in the academic literature. A common approach divides
them into those forms that aim at the creation of theoretical knowledge and those that aim at producing
actions or correct decisions,[22] but there is no universally accepted taxonomy summarizing all these
types.
Other theories of judgment focus more on the relation between the judged proposition and reality.
According to Franz Brentano, a judgment is either a belief or a disbelief in the existence of some entity.
[63][65] In this sense, there are only two fundamental forms of judgment: "A exists" and "A does not
exist". When applied to the sentence "all men are mortal", the entity in question is "immortal men", of
whom it is said that they do not exist.[63][65] Important for Brentano is the distinction between the mere
representation of the content of the judgment and the affirmation or the denial of the content.[63][65]
The mere representation of a proposition is often referred to as "entertaining a proposition". This is the
case, for example, when one considers a proposition but has not yet made up one's mind about whether
it is true or false.[63][65] The term "thinking" can refer both to judging and to mere entertaining. This
difference is often explicit in the way the thought is expressed: "thinking that" usually involves a
judgment whereas "thinking about" refers to the neutral representation of a proposition without an
accompanying belief. In this case, the proposition is merely entertained but not yet judged.[19] Some
forms of thinking may involve the representation of objects without any propositions, as when someone
is thinking about their grandmother.[6]
Reasoning is one of the most paradigmatic forms of thinking. It is the process of drawing conclusions
from premises or evidence. Types of reasoning can be divided into deductive and non-deductive
reasoning. Deductive reasoning is governed by certain rules of inference, which guarantee the truth of
the conclusion if the premises are true.[1][66] For example, given the premises "all men are mortal" and
"Socrates is a man", it follows deductively that "Socrates is mortal". Non-deductive reasoning, also
referred to as defeasible reasoning or non-monotonic reasoning, is still rationally compelling but the
truth of the conclusion is not ensured by the truth of the premises.[67] Induction is one form of non-
deductive reasoning, for example, when one concludes that "the sun will rise tomorrow" based on one's
experiences of all the previous days. Other forms of non-deductive reasoning include the inference to the
best explanation and analogical reasoning.[68]
Fallacies are faulty forms of thinking that go against the norms of correct reasoning. Formal fallacies
concern faulty inferences found in deductive reasoning.[69][70] Denying the antecedent is one type of
formal fallacy, for example, "If Othello is a bachelor, then he is male. Othello is not a bachelor.
Therefore, Othello is not male".[1][71] Informal fallacies, on the other hand, apply to all types of
reasoning. The source of their flaw is to be found in the content or the context of the argument.[72][69]
[73] This is often caused by ambiguous or vague expressions in natural language, as in "Feathers are
light. What is light cannot be dark. Therefore, feathers cannot be dark".[74] An important aspect of
fallacies is that they seem to be rationally compelling on the first look and thereby seduce people into
accepting and committing them.[69] Whether an act of reasoning constitutes a fallacy does not depend
on whether the premises are true or false but on their relation to the conclusion and, in some cases, on
the context.[1]
Concept formation
Concepts are general notions that constitute the fundamental building blocks of thought.[75][76] They are
rules that govern how objects are sorted into different classes.[77][78] A person can only think about a
proposition if they possess the concepts involved in this proposition.[79] For example, the proposition
"wombats are animals" involves the concepts "wombat" and "animal". Someone who does not possess
the concept "wombat" may still be able to read the sentence but cannot entertain the corresponding
proposition. Concept formation is a form of thinking in which new concepts are acquired.[78] It involves
becoming familiar with the characteristic features shared by all instances of the corresponding type of
entity and developing the ability to identify positive and negative cases. This process usually
corresponds to learning the meaning of the word associated with the type in question.[77][78] There are
various theories concerning how concepts and concept possession are to be understood.[75] The use of
metaphor may aid in the processes of concept formation.[80]
According to one popular view, concepts are to be understood in terms of abilities. On this view, two
central aspects characterize concept possession: the ability to discriminate between positive and
negative cases and the ability to draw inferences from this concept to related concepts. Concept
formation corresponds to acquiring these abilities.[79][81][75] It has been suggested that animals are also
able to learn concepts to some extent, due to their ability to discriminate between different types of
situations and to adjust their behavior accordingly.[77][82]
Problem solving
In the case of problem solving, thinking aims at reaching a predefined goal by overcoming certain
obstacles.[7][1][78] This process often involves two different forms of thinking. On the one hand,
divergent thinking aims at coming up with as many alternative solutions as possible. On the other hand,
convergent thinking tries to narrow down the range of alternatives to the most promising candidates.[1]
[83][84] Some researchers identify various steps in the process of problem solving. These steps include
recognizing the problem, trying to understand its nature, identifying general criteria the solution should
meet, deciding how these criteria should be prioritized, monitoring the progress, and evaluating the
results.[1]
An important distinction concerns the type of problem that is faced. For well-structured problems, it is
easy to determine which steps need to be taken to solve them, but executing these steps may still be
difficult.[1][85] For ill-structured problems, on the other hand, it is not clear what steps need to be taken,
i.e. there is no clear formula that would lead to success if followed correctly. In this case, the solution
may sometimes come in a flash of insight in which the problem is suddenly seen in a new light.[1][85]
Another way to categorize different forms of problem solving is by distinguishing between algorithms
and heuristics.[78] An algorithm is a formal procedure in which each step is clearly defined. It guarantees
success if applied correctly.[1][78] The long multiplication usually taught in school is an example of an
algorithm for solving the problem of multiplying big numbers. Heuristics, on the other hand, are
informal procedures. They are rough rules-of-thumb that tend to bring the thinker closer to the solution
but success is not guaranteed in every case even if followed correctly.[1][78] Examples of heuristics are
working forward and working backward. These approaches involve planning one step at a time, either
starting at the beginning and moving forward or starting at the end and moving backward. So when
planning a trip, one could plan the different stages of the trip from origin to destiny in the chronological
order of how the trip will be realized, or in the reverse order.[1]
Obstacles to problem solving can arise from the thinker's failure to take certain possibilities into account
by fixating on one specific course of action.[1] There are important differences between how novices and
experts solve problems. For example, experts tend to allocate more time for conceptualizing the problem
and work with more complex representations whereas novices tend to devote more time to executing
putative solutions.[1]
Various theorists emphasize the practical nature of thought, i.e. that thinking is usually guided by some
kind of task it aims to solve. In this sense, thinking has been compared to trial-and-error seen in animal
behavior when faced with a new problem. On this view, the important difference is that this process
happens inwardly as a form of simulation.[1] This process is often much more efficient since once the
solution is found in thought, only the behavior corresponding to the found solution has to be outwardly
carried out and not all the others.[1]
Unconscious thought
Conscious thought is the paradigmatic form of thinking and is often the focus of the corresponding
research. But it has been argued that some forms of thought also happen on the unconscious level.[9][10]
[4][5] Unconscious thought is thought that happens in the background without being experienced. It is
therefore not observed directly. Instead, its existence is usually inferred by other means.[10] For
example, when someone is faced with an important decision or a difficult problem, they may not be able
to solve it straight away. But then, at a later time, the solution may suddenly flash before them even
though no conscious steps of thinking were taken towards this solution in the meantime.[10][9] In such
cases, the cognitive labor needed to arrive at a solution is often explained in terms of unconscious
thoughts. The central idea is that a cognitive transition happened and we need to posit unconscious
thoughts to be able to explain how it happened.[10][9]
It has been argued that conscious and unconscious thoughts differ not just concerning their relation to
experience but also concerning their capacities. According to unconscious thought theorists, for
example, conscious thought excels at simple problems with few variables but is outperformed by
unconscious thought when complex problems with many variables are involved.[10][9] This is sometimes
explained through the claim that the number of items one can consciously think about at the same time
is rather limited whereas unconscious thought lacks such limitations.[10] But other researchers have
rejected the claim that unconscious thought is often superior to conscious thought.[96][97] Other
suggestions for the difference between the two forms of thinking include that conscious thought tends to
follow formal logical laws while unconscious thought relies more on associative processing and that only
conscious thinking is conceptually articulated and happens through the medium of language.[10][98]
In various disciplines
Phenomenology
Phenomenology is the science of the structure and contents of experience.[99][100] The term "cognitive
phenomenology" refers to the experiential character of thinking or what it feels like to think.[4][101][102]
[6][103] Some theorists claim that there is no distinctive cognitive phenomenology. On such a view, the
experience of thinking is just one form of sensory experience.[103][104][105] According to one version,
thinking just involves hearing a voice internally.[104] According to another, there is no experience of
thinking apart from the indirect effects thinking has on sensory experience.[4][101] A weaker version of
such an approach allows that thinking may have a distinct phenomenology but contends that thinking
still depends on sensory experience because it cannot occur on its own. On this view, sensory contents
constitute the foundation from which thinking may arise.[4][104][105]
Phenomenologists are also concerned with the characteristic features of the experience of thinking.
Making a judgment is one of the prototypical forms of cognitive phenomenology.[102][108] It involves
epistemic agency, in which a proposition is entertained, evidence for and against it is considered, and,
based on this reasoning, the proposition is either affirmed or rejected.[102] It is sometimes argued that
the experience of truth is central to thinking, i.e. that thinking aims at representing how the world is.[6]
[101] It shares this feature with perception but differs from it in the way how it represents the world:
One of the characteristic features often ascribed to thinking and judging is that they are predicative
experiences, in contrast to the pre-predicative experience found in immediate perception.[109][110] On
such a view, various aspects of perceptual experience resemble judgments without being judgments in
the strict sense.[4][111][112] For example, the perceptual experience of the front of a house brings with it
various expectations about aspects of the house not directly seen, like the size and shape of its other
sides. This process is sometimes referred to as apperception.[4][111] These expectations resemble
judgments and can be wrong. This would be the case when it turns out upon walking around the "house"
that it is no house at all but only a front facade of a house with nothing behind it. In this case, the
perceptual expectations are frustrated and the perceiver is surprised.[4] There is disagreement as to
whether these pre-predicative aspects of regular perception should be understood as a form of cognitive
phenomenology involving thinking.[4] This issue is also important for understanding the relation
between thought and language. The reason for this is that the pre-predicative expectations do not
depend on language, which is sometimes taken as an example for non-linguistic thought.[4] Various
theorists have argued that pre-predicative experience is more basic or fundamental since predicative
experience is in some sense built on top of it and therefore depends on it.[112][109][110]
Another way how phenomenologists have tried to distinguish the experience of thinking from other
types of experiences is in relation to empty intentions in contrast to intuitive intentions.[113][114] In this
context, "intention" means that some kind of object is experienced. In intuitive intentions, the object is
presented through sensory contents. Empty intentions, on the other hand, present their object in a more
abstract manner without the help of sensory contents.[113][4][114] So when perceiving a sunset, it is
presented through sensory contents. The same sunset can also be presented non-intuitively when
merely thinking about it without the help of sensory contents.[114] In these cases, the same properties
are ascribed to objects. The difference between these modes of presentation concerns not what
properties are ascribed to the presented object but how the object is presented.[113] Because of this
commonality, it is possible for representations belonging to different modes to overlap or to diverge.[6]
For example, when searching one's glasses one may think to oneself that one left them on the kitchen
table. This empty intention of the glasses lying on the kitchen table are then intuitively fulfilled when
one sees them lying there upon arriving in the kitchen. This way, a perception can confirm or refute a
thought depending on whether the empty intuitions are later fulfilled or not.[6][114]
Metaphysics
The mind–body problem concerns the explanation of the relationship that exists between minds, or
mental processes, and bodily states or processes.[115] The main aim of philosophers working in this area
is to determine the nature of the mind and mental states/processes, and how—or even if—minds are
affected by and can affect the body.
Human perceptual experiences depend on stimuli which arrive at one's various sensory organs from the
external world and these stimuli cause changes in one's mental state, ultimately causing one to feel a
sensation, which may be pleasant or unpleasant. Someone's desire for a slice of pizza, for example, will
tend to cause that person to move his or her body in a specific manner and in a specific direction to
obtain what he or she wants. The question, then, is how it can be possible for conscious experiences to
arise out of a lump of gray matter endowed with nothing but electrochemical properties. A related
problem is to explain how someone's propositional attitudes (e.g. beliefs and desires) can cause that
individual's neurons to fire and his muscles to contract in exactly the correct manner. These comprise
some of the puzzles that have confronted epistemologists and philosophers of mind from at least the
time of René Descartes.[116]
The above reflects a classical, functional description of how we work as cognitive, thinking systems.
However the apparently irresolvable mind–body problem is said to be overcome, and bypassed, by the
embodied cognition approach, with its roots in the work of Heidegger, Piaget, Vygotsky, Merleau-Ponty
and the pragmatist John Dewey.[117][118]
This approach states that the classical approach of separating the mind and analysing its processes is
misguided: instead, we should see that the mind, actions of an embodied agent, and the environment it
perceives and envisions, are all parts of a whole which determine each other. Therefore, functional
analysis of the mind alone will always leave us with the mind–body problem which cannot be solved.[119]
Psychology
Psychologists have concentrated on thinking as an intellectual exertion aimed at finding an answer to a
question or the solution of a practical problem. Cognitive psychology is a branch of psychology that
investigates internal mental processes such as problem solving, memory, and language; all of which are
used in thinking. The school of thought arising from this approach is known as cognitivism, which is
interested in how people mentally represent information processing. It had its foundations in the Gestalt
psychology of Max Wertheimer, Wolfgang Köhler, and Kurt Koffka,[120] and in the work of Jean Piaget,
who provided a theory of stages/phases that describes children's cognitive development.
Cognitive psychologists use psychophysical and experimental approaches to understand, diagnose, and
solve problems, concerning themselves with the mental processes
which mediate between stimulus and response. They study various
aspects of thinking, including the psychology of reasoning, and how
people make decisions and choices, solve problems, as well as
engage in creative discovery and imaginative thought. Cognitive
theory contends that solutions to problems either take the form of
algorithms: rules that are not necessarily understood but promise a
solution, or of heuristics: rules that are understood but that do not
Man thinking on a train journey
always guarantee solutions. Cognitive science differs from cognitive
psychology in that algorithms that are intended to simulate human
behavior are implemented or implementable on a computer. In other instances, solutions may be found
through insight, a sudden awareness of relationships.
In developmental psychology, Jean Piaget was a pioneer in the study of the development of thought
from birth to maturity. In his theory of cognitive development, thought is based on actions on the
environment. That is, Piaget suggests that the environment is understood through assimilations of
objects in the available schemes of action and these accommodate to the objects to the extent that the
available schemes fall short of the demands. As a result of this interplay between assimilation and
accommodation, thought develops through a sequence of stages that differ qualitatively from each other
in mode of representation and complexity of inference and understanding. That is, thought evolves from
being based on perceptions and actions at the sensorimotor stage in the first two years of life to internal
representations in early childhood. Subsequently, representations are gradually organized into logical
structures which first operate on the concrete properties of the reality, in the stage of concrete
operations, and then operate on abstract principles that organize concrete properties, in the stage of
formal operations.[121] In recent years, the Piagetian conception of thought was integrated with
information processing conceptions. Thus, thought is considered as the result of mechanisms that are
responsible for the representation and processing of information. In this conception, speed of
processing, cognitive control, and working memory are the main functions underlying thought. In the
neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive development, the development of thought is considered to come
from increasing speed of processing, enhanced cognitive control, and increasing working memory.[122]
Positive psychology emphasizes the positive aspects of human psychology as equally important as the
focus on mood disorders and other negative symptoms. In Character Strengths and Virtues, Peterson
and Seligman list a series of positive characteristics. One person is not expected to have every strength,
nor are they meant to fully capsulate that characteristic entirely. The list encourages positive thought
that builds on a person's strengths, rather than how to "fix" their "symptoms".[123]
Psychoanalysis
The "id", "ego" and "super-ego" are the three parts of the "psychic apparatus" defined in Sigmund
Freud's structural model of the psyche; they are the three theoretical constructs in terms of whose
activity and interaction mental life is described. According to this model, the uncoordinated instinctual
trends are encompassed by the "id", the organized realistic part of the psyche is the "ego", and the
critical, moralizing function is the "super-ego".[124]
For psychoanalysis, the unconscious does not include all that is not conscious, rather only what is
actively repressed from conscious thought or what the person is averse to knowing consciously. In a
sense this view places the self in relationship to their unconscious as an adversary, warring with itself to
keep what is unconscious hidden. If a person feels pain, all he can think of is alleviating the pain. Any of
his desires, to get rid of pain or enjoy something, command the mind what to do. For Freud, the
unconscious was a repository for socially unacceptable ideas, wishes or desires, traumatic memories,
and painful emotions put out of mind by the mechanism of psychological repression. However, the
contents did not necessarily have to be solely negative. In the psychoanalytic view, the unconscious is a
force that can only be recognized by its effects—it expresses itself in the symptom.[125]
In the "Definitions" chapter of Jung's seminal work Psychological Types, under the definition of
"collective" Jung references representations collectives, a term coined by Lucien Lévy-Bruhl in his 1910
book How Natives Think. Jung says this is what he describes as the collective unconscious. Freud, on
the other hand, did not accept the idea of a collective unconscious.
Laws of thought
Traditionally, the term "laws of thought" refers to three fundamental laws of logic: the law of
contradiction, the law of excluded middle, and the principle of identity.[127][128] These laws by
themselves are not sufficient as axioms of logic but they can be seen as important precursors to the
modern axiomatization of logic. The law of contradiction states that for any proposition, it is impossible
that both it and its negation are true: . According to the law of excluded middle, for any
proposition, either it or its opposite is true: . The principle of identity asserts that any object is
identical to itself: . [127][128] There are different conceptions of how the laws of thought are to
be understood. The interpretations most relevant to thinking are to understand them as prescriptive
laws of how one should think or as formal laws of propositions that are true only because of their form
and independent of their content or context.[128] Metaphysical interpretations, on the other hand, see
them as expressing the nature of "being as such".[128]
While there is a very wide acceptance of these three laws among logicians, they are not universally
accepted.[127][128] Aristotle, for example, held that there are some cases in which the law of excluded
middle is false. This concerns primarily uncertain future events. On his view, it is currently "not ... either
true or false that there will be a naval battle tomorrow".[127][128] Modern intuitionist logic also rejects
the law of excluded middle. This rejection is based on the idea that mathematical truth depends on
verification through a proof. The law fails for cases where no such proof is possible, which exist in every
sufficiently strong formal system, according to Gödel's incompleteness theorems.[129][130][127][128]
Dialetheists, on the other hand, reject the law of contradiction by holding that some propositions are
both true and false. One motivation of this position is to avoid certain paradoxes in classical logic and
set theory, like the liar's paradox and Russell's paradox. One of its problems is to find a formulation that
circumvents the principle of explosion, i.e. that anything follows from a contradiction.[131][132][133]
Some formulations of the laws of thought include a fourth law: the principle of sufficient reason.[128] It
states that everything has a sufficient reason, ground, or cause. It is closely connected to the idea that
everything is intelligible or can be explained in reference to its sufficient reason.[134][135] According to
this idea, there should always be a full explanation, at least in principle, to questions like why the sky is
blue or why World War II happened. One problem for including this principle among the laws of
thought is that it is a metaphysical principle, unlike the other three laws, which pertain primarily to
logic.[135][128][134]
Counterfactual thinking
Counterfactual thinking involves mental representations of non-actual situations and events, i.e. of what
is "contrary to the facts".[136][137] It is usually conditional: it aims at assessing what would be the case if
a certain condition had obtained.[138][139] In this sense, it tries to answer "What if"-questions. For
example, thinking after an accident that one would be dead if one had not used the seatbelt is a form of
counterfactual thinking: it assumes, contrary to the facts, that one had not used the seatbelt and tries to
assess the result of this state of affairs.[137] In this sense, counterfactual thinking is normally
counterfactual only to a small degree since just a few facts are changed, like concerning the seatbelt,
while most other facts are kept in place, like that one was driving, one's gender, the laws of physics, etc.
[136] When understood in the widest sense, there are forms of counterfactual thinking that do not
involve anything contrary to the facts at all.[139] This is the case, for example, when one tries to
anticipate what might happen in the future if an uncertain event occurs and this event actually occurs
later and brings with it the anticipated consequences.[138] In this wider sense, the term "subjunctive
conditional" is sometimes used instead of "counterfactual conditional".[139] But the paradigmatic cases
of counterfactual thinking involve alternatives to past events.[136]
Counterfactual thinking plays an important role since we evaluate the world around us not only by what
actually happened but also by what could have happened.[137] Humans have a greater tendency to
engage in counterfactual thinking after something bad happened because of some kind of action the
agent performed.[138][136] In this sense, many regrets are associated with counterfactual thinking in
which the agent contemplates how a better outcome could have been obtained if only they had acted
differently.[137] These cases are known as upward counterfactuals, in contrast to downward
counterfactuals, in which the counterfactual scenario is worse than actuality.[138][136] Upward
counterfactual thinking is usually experienced as unpleasant, since it presents the actual circumstances
in a bad light. This contrasts with the positive emotions associated with downward counterfactual
thinking.[137] But both forms are important since it is possible to learn from them and to adjust one's
behavior accordingly to get better results in the future.[137][136]
Thought experiments
Thought experiments involve thinking about imaginary situations, often with the aim of investigating
the possible consequences of a change to the actual sequence of events.[140][141][142] It is a controversial
issue to what extent thought experiments should be understood as actual experiments.[143][144][145] They
are experiments in the sense that a certain situation is set up and one tries to learn from this situation by
understanding what follows from it.[146][143] They differ from regular experiments in that imagination is
used to set up the situation and counterfactual reasoning is employed to evaluate what follows from it,
instead of setting it up physically and observing the consequences through perception.[147][141][143][142]
Counterfactual thinking, therefore, plays a central role in thought experiments.[148]
The Chinese room argument is a famous thought experiment proposed by John Searle.[149][150] It
involves a person sitting inside a closed-off room, tasked with responding to messages written in
Chinese. This person does not know Chinese but has a giant rule book that specifies exactly how to reply
to any possible message, similar to how a computer would react to messages. The core idea of this
thought experiment is that neither the person nor the computer understands Chinese. This way, Searle
aims to show that computers lack a mind capable of deeper forms of understanding despite acting
intelligently.[149][150]
Thought experiments are employed for various purposes, for example, for entertainment, education, or
as arguments for or against theories. Most discussions focus on their use as arguments. This use is found
in fields like philosophy, the natural sciences, and history.[141][145][144][143] It is controversial since there
is a lot of disagreement concerning the epistemic status of thought experiments, i.e. how reliable they
are as evidence supporting or refuting a theory.[141][145][144][143] Central to the rejection of this usage is
the fact that they pretend to be a source of knowledge without the need to leave one's armchair in search
of any new empirical data. Defenders of thought experiments usually contend that the intuitions
underlying and guiding the thought experiments are, at least in some cases, reliable.[141][143] But
thought experiments can also fail if they are not properly supported by intuitions or if they go beyond
what the intuitions support.[141][142] In the latter sense, sometimes counter thought experiments are
proposed that modify the original scenario in slight ways in order to show that initial intuitions cannot
survive this change.[141] Various taxonomies of thought experiments have been suggested. They can be
distinguished, for example, by whether they are successful or not, by the discipline that uses them, by
their role in a theory, or by whether they accept or modify the actual laws of physics.[142][141]
Critical thinking
Critical thinking is a form of thinking that is reasonable, reflective, and focused on determining what to
believe or how to act.[151][152][153] It holds itself to various standards, like clarity and rationality. In this
sense, it involves not just cognitive processes trying to solve the issue at hand but at the same time meta-
cognitive processes ensuring that it lives up to its own standards.[152] This includes assessing both that
the reasoning itself is sound and that the evidence it rests on is reliable.[152] This means that logic plays
an important role in critical thinking. It concerns not just formal logic, but also informal logic,
specifically to avoid various informal fallacies due to vague or ambiguous expressions in natural
language.[152][74][73] No generally accepted standard definition of "critical thinking" exists but there is
significant overlap between the proposed definitions in their characterization of critical thinking as
careful and goal-directed.[153] According to some versions, only the thinker's own observations and
experiments are accepted as evidence in critical thinking. Some restrict it to the formation of judgments
but exclude action as its goal.[153]
A concrete everyday example of critical thinking, due to John Dewey, involves observing foam bubbles
moving in a direction that is contrary to one's initial expectations. The critical thinker tries to come up
with various possible explanations of this behavior and then slightly modifies the original situation in
order to determine which one is the right explanation.[153][154] But not all forms of cognitively valuable
processes involve critical thinking. Arriving at the correct solution to a problem by blindly following the
steps of an algorithm does not qualify as critical thinking. The same is true if the solution is presented to
the thinker in a sudden flash of insight and accepted straight away.[153]
Critical thinking plays an important role in education: fostering the student's ability to think critically is
often seen as an important educational goal.[153][152][155] In this sense, it is important to convey not just
a set of true beliefs to the student but also the ability to draw one's own conclusions and to question pre-
existing beliefs.[155] The abilities and dispositions learned this way may profit not just the individual but
also society at large.[152] Critics of the emphasis on critical thinking in education have argued that there
is no universal form of correct thinking. Instead, they contend that different subject matters rely on
different standards and education should focus on imparting these subject-specific skills instead of
trying to teach universal methods of thinking.[153][156] Other objections are based on the idea that
critical thinking and the attitude underlying it involve various unjustified biases, like egocentrism,
distanced objectivity, indifference, and an overemphasis of the theoretical in contrast to the practical.
[153]
Positive thinking
Positive thinking is an important topic in positive psychology.[157] It involves focusing one's attention on
the positive aspects of one's situation and thereby withdrawing one's attention from its negative sides.
[157] This is usually seen as a global outlook that applies especially to thinking but includes other mental
processes, like feeling, as well.[157] In this sense, it is closely related to optimism. It includes expecting
positive things to happen in the future.[158][157] This positive outlook makes it more likely for people to
seek to attain new goals.[157] It also increases the probability of continuing to strive towards pre-existing
goals that seem difficult to reach instead of just giving up.[158][157]
The effects of positive thinking are not yet thoroughly researched, but some studies suggest that there is
a correlation between positive thinking and well-being.[157] For example, students and pregnant women
with a positive outlook tend to be better at dealing with stressful situations.[158][157] This is sometimes
explained by pointing out that stress is not inherent in stressful situations but depends on the agent's
interpretation of the situation. Reduced stress may therefore be found in positive thinkers because they
tend to see such situations in a more positive light.[157] But the effects also include the practical domain
in that positive thinkers tend to employ healthier coping strategies when faced with difficult situations.
[157] This effects, for example, the time needed to fully recover from surgeries and the tendency to
But it has been argued that whether positive thinking actually leads to positive outcomes depends on
various other factors. Without these factors, it may lead to negative results. For example, the tendency of
optimists to keep striving in difficult situations can backfire if the course of events is outside the agent's
control.[158] Another danger associated with positive thinking is that it may remain only on the level of
unrealistic fantasies and thereby fail to make a positive practical contribution to the agent's life.[159]
Pessimism, on the other hand, may have positive effects since it can mitigate disappointments by
anticipating failures.[158][160]
Positive thinking is a recurrent topic in the self-help literature.[161] Here, often the claim is made that
one can significantly improve one's life by trying to think positively, even if this means fostering beliefs
that are contrary to evidence.[162] Such claims and the effectiveness of the suggested methods are
controversial and have been criticized due to their lack of scientific evidence.[162][163] In the New
Thought movement, positive thinking figures in the law of attraction, the pseudoscientific claim that
positive thoughts can directly influence the external world by attracting positive outcomes.[164]
See also
▪ Animal cognition
Philosophy portal
▪ Freethought
▪ Outline of human intelligence – topic tree presenting the traits, capacities, Psychology portal
models, and research fields of human intelligence, and more
▪ Outline of thought – topic tree that identifies many types of thoughts, types of thinking, aspects of
thought, related fields, and more
▪ Rethinking
References
1. "Thought" (https://www.britannica.com/topic/thought). Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved
14 October 2021.
2. Random House Webster's Unabridged Dictionary, 2nd ed., 2001, Published by Random House, Inc.,
ISBN 978-0-375-42599-8, p. 1975
3. Webster's II New College Dictionary, Webster Staff, Webster, Houghton Mifflin Company, 2nd ed.,
illustrated, revised Published by Houghton Mifflin Harcourt, 1999, ISBN 978-0-395-96214-5, p. 1147
4. Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (2015). "Introduction". Phenomenology of Thinking:
Philosophical Investigations into the Character of Cognitive Experiences (https://philpapers.org/rec/B
REI-15). pp. 1–24.
5. Nida-rümelin, Martine (2010). "Thinking Without Language. A Phenomenological Argument for Its
Possibility and Existence" (https://philpapers.org/rec/NIDTWL). Grazer Philosophische Studien. 81
(1): 55–75. doi:10.1163/9789042030190_005 (https://doi.org/10.1163%2F9789042030190_005).
6. Crowell, Steven (2015). "What Is It to Think?". In Breyer, Thiemo; Gutland, Christopher (eds.).
Phenomenology of Thinking (https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9781315697734-1
4/think-steven-crowell). Routledge. pp. 189–212. doi:10.4324/9781315697734 (https://doi.org/10.43
24%2F9781315697734). ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4.
7. Mole, Christopher (2021). "Attention: 2.3 Coherence Theories" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/atte
ntion/#CohThe). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
8. Katsafanas, Paul (2015). "Nietzsche on the Nature of the Unconscious" (https://philpapers.org/rec/K
ATNOT). Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 58 (3): 327–352.
doi:10.1080/0020174X.2013.855658 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F0020174X.2013.855658).
S2CID 38776513 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:38776513).
9. Garrison, Katie E.; Handley, Ian M. (2017). "Not Merely Experiential: Unconscious Thought Can Be
Rational" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519). Frontiers in Psychology. 8:
1096. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2017.01096 (https://doi.org/10.3389%2Ffpsyg.2017.01096).
ISSN 1664-1078 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1664-1078). PMC 5498519 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.ni
h.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5498519). PMID 28729844 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/28729844).
10. Dijksterhuis, Ap; Nordgren, Loran F. (1 June 2006). "A Theory of Unconscious Thought" (https://jour
nals.sagepub.com/doi/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x). Perspectives on Psychological Science.
1 (2): 95–109. doi:10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00007.x (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1745-6916.2006.0
0007.x). hdl:2066/55863 (https://hdl.handle.net/2066%2F55863). ISSN 1745-6916 (https://www.worl
dcat.org/issn/1745-6916). PMID 26151465 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/26151465).
S2CID 7875280 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:7875280).
11. Skirry, Justin. "Descartes, Rene: Mind-Body Distinction" (https://iep.utm.edu/descmind/). Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021.
12. Smith, Kurt (2021). "Descartes' Theory of Ideas: 1. Ideas Understood as Modes of Thinking" (https://
plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes-ideas/#thoughts). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
13. Baum, Eric B. (2004). "1. Introduction". What Is Thought? (https://philpapers.org/rec/BAUWIT).
Cambridge MA: Bradford Book/MIT Press.
14. Block, Ned (1981). "Psychologism and Behaviorism" (https://philpapers.org/rec/BLOPAB).
Philosophical Review. 90 (1): 5–43. doi:10.2307/2184371 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F2184371).
JSTOR 2184371 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2184371).
15. Romer, Paul M. (May 2000). "Thinking and Feeling" (https://www.aeaweb.org/articles?id=10.1257/ae
r.90.2.439). American Economic Review. 90 (2): 439–443. doi:10.1257/aer.90.2.439 (https://doi.or
g/10.1257%2Faer.90.2.439). ISSN 0002-8282 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0002-8282).
16. Planalp, Sally; Fitness, Julie (1 December 1999). "Thinking/Feeling about Social and Personal
Relationships" (https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0265407599166004). Journal of
Social and Personal Relationships. 16 (6): 731–750. doi:10.1177/0265407599166004 (https://doi.or
g/10.1177%2F0265407599166004). ISSN 0265-4075 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0265-4075).
S2CID 145750153 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:145750153).
17. Phelan, Mark; Arico, Adam; Nichols, Shaun (2013). "Thinking Things and Feeling Things: On an
Alleged Discontinuity in Folk Metaphysics of Mind" (https://philpapers.org/rec/PHETTA).
Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences. 12 (4): 703–725. doi:10.1007/s11097-012-9278-7 (http
s://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs11097-012-9278-7). S2CID 15856600 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/Corp
usID:15856600).
18. "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: thought" (https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?
q=thought). www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October
2021.
19. Mandelbaum, Eric (2014). "Thinking is Believing" (https://philpapers.org/rec/MANTIB-2). Inquiry: An
Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy. 57 (1): 55–96. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2014.858417 (https://d
oi.org/10.1080%2F0020174X.2014.858417). S2CID 52968342 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/Corp
usID:52968342).
20. "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: think" (https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/search.html?q=t
hink). www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing. Retrieved 23 October 2021.
21. Harper, Douglas. "Etymology of Thought" (http://www.etymonline.com/index.php?search=Thought).
Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved 2009-05-22.
22. Borchert, Donald (2006). "Thinking". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition (https://phil
papers.org/rec/BORMEO). Macmillan.
23. Woolf, Raphael (1 January 2013). "Plato and the Norms of Thought" (https://academic.oup.com/min
d/article/122/485/171/961176). Mind. 122 (485): 171–216. doi:10.1093/mind/fzt012 (https://doi.org/1
0.1093%2Fmind%2Ffzt012). ISSN 0026-4423 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0026-4423).
24. Langland-Hassan, Peter; Vicente, Agustin (2018). "Introduction". Inner Speech: New Voices (https://
philpapers.org/rec/LANISN). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
25. Kraut, Richard (2017). "Plato" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plato/). The Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 April 2021.
26. Brickhouse, Thomas; Smith, Nicholas D. "Plato: 6b. The Theory of Forms" (https://iep.utm.edu/plato/
#SH6b). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 24 April 2021.
27. Nehamas, Alexander (1975). "Plato on the Imperfection of the Sensible World" (https://www.jstor.or
g/stable/20009565). American Philosophical Quarterly. 12 (2): 105–117. ISSN 0003-0481 (https://ww
w.worldcat.org/issn/0003-0481). JSTOR 20009565 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/20009565).
28. Sellars, Wilfrid (1949). "Aristotelian Philosophies of Mind". Philosophy for The Future, The Quest of
Modern Materialism (http://www.ditext.com/sellars/apm.html).
29. Klima, Gyula (2017). "The Medieval Problem of Universals: 1. Introduction" (https://plato.stanford.ed
u/entries/universals-medieval/#Intr). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics
Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
30. Harman, Gilbert (1973). "4. Thought and meaning". Thought (https://philpapers.org/rec/HART).
Princeton University Press.
31. Roessler, Johannes (2016). "Thinking, Inner Speech, and Self-Awareness" (https://philpapers.org/re
c/ROETIS-2). Review of Philosophy and Psychology. 7 (3): 541–557. doi:10.1007/
s13164-015-0267-y (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs13164-015-0267-y). S2CID 15028459 (https://api.s
emanticscholar.org/CorpusID:15028459).
32. Rescorla, Michael (2019). "The Language of Thought Hypothesis" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/
language-thought/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. Retrieved 18 October 2021.
33. Bermudez, Jose Luis (2003). Thinking Without Words (https://philpapers.org/rec/LUITWW). Oxford
University Press USA.
34. Lohmar, Dieter (2012). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). "Language and non-linguistic thinking" (https://www.oxford
handbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199594900.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780199594900-e-19).
The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Phenomenology. doi:10.1093/
oxfordhb/9780199594900.001.0001 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Foxfordhb%2F9780199594900.001.0
001). ISBN 978-0-19-959490-0.
35. Andrews, Kristin; Monsó, Susana (2021). "Animal Cognition: 3.4 Thought" (https://plato.stanford.ed
u/entries/cognition-animal/#Thou). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research
Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 25 October 2021.
36. Premack, David (28 August 2007). "Human and animal cognition: Continuity and discontinuity" (http
s://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1955772). Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences. 104 (35): 13861–13867. Bibcode:2007PNAS..10413861P (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/a
bs/2007PNAS..10413861P). doi:10.1073/pnas.0706147104 (https://doi.org/10.1073%2Fpnas.07061
47104). ISSN 0027-8424 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0027-8424). PMC 1955772 (https://www.nc
bi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1955772). PMID 17717081 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/17717
081).
37. Katz, Matthew. "Language of Thought Hypothesis" (https://iep.utm.edu/lot-hypo/). Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 27 October 2021.
38. Aydede, Murat. "Oxford Bibliographies: Language of Thought" (https://www.oxfordbibliographies.co
m/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-9780195396577-0151.xml). Retrieved 27 October 2021.
39. Fodor, Jerry A. (2008). Lot 2: The Language of Thought Revisited (https://philpapers.org/rec/FODLT)
. Oxford University Press.
40. Borchert, Donald (2006). "Language of thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition
(https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/languag
e-thought). Macmillan.
41. Milkowski, Marcin. "Computational Theory of Mind" (https://iep.utm.edu/compmind/). Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
42. Doorey, Marie. "Conditioning". The Gale Encyclopedia of Science (https://www.encyclopedia.com/m
edicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/conditioning).
43. Van der Veldt, J. H. "Associationism". New Catholic Encyclopedia (https://www.encyclopedia.com/m
edicine/psychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/associationism).
44. Mandelbaum, Eric (2020). "Associationist Theories of Thought" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/as
sociationist-thought/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab,
Stanford University. Retrieved 23 October 2021.
45. Rescorla, Michael (2020). "The Computational Theory of Mind" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/co
mputational-mind/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. Retrieved 22 October 2021.
46. Lazzeri, Filipe (2019-08-16). "O que é Behaviorismo sobre a mente?" (https://periodicos.ufsc.br/inde
x.php/principia/article/view/1808-1711.2019v23n2p249). Principia (in Portuguese). 23 (2): 249–277.
doi:10.5007/1808-1711.2019v23n2p249 (https://doi.org/10.5007%2F1808-1711.2019v23n2p249).
ISSN 1808-1711 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1808-1711). S2CID 212888121 (https://api.semantic
scholar.org/CorpusID:212888121).
47. Graham, George (2019). "Behaviorism" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/behaviorism/). The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved
31 May 2021.
48. Audet, Jean-Nicolas; Lefebvre, Louis (18 February 2017). "What's flexible in behavioral flexibility?"
(https://academic.oup.com/beheco/article/28/4/943/3003315). Behavioral Ecology. 28 (4): 943–947.
doi:10.1093/beheco/arx007 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Fbeheco%2Farx007). ISSN 1045-2249 (http
s://www.worldcat.org/issn/1045-2249).
49. Reese, Hayne W. (2000). "Thinking as the Behaviorist Views It" (https://psycnet.apa.org/fulltext/201
4-55592-003.html). Behavioral Development Bulletin. 9 (1): 10–12. doi:10.1037/h0100531 (https://do
i.org/10.1037%2Fh0100531).
50. Mele, Alfred R. (2003). "Introduction". Motivation and Agency (https://philpapers.org/rec/MELMAA-2)
. Oxford University Press.
51. Mele, Alfred R. (1995). "Motivation: Essentially Motivation-Constituting Attitudes" (https://philpaper
s.org/rec/MELMEM). Philosophical Review. 104 (3): 387–423. doi:10.2307/2185634 (https://doi.or
g/10.2307%2F2185634). JSTOR 2185634 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2185634).
52. Schwitzgebel, Eric (2019). "Belief" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/). The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived (https://we
b.archive.org/web/20191115080001/https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/belief/) from the original on 15
November 2019. Retrieved 22 June 2020.
53. Borchert, Donald (2006). "Belief". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition (https://philpap
ers.org/rec/BORMEO). Macmillan. Archived (https://web.archive.org/web/20210112065913/https://p
hilpapers.org/rec/BORMEO) from the original on 12 January 2021. Retrieved 2 April 2021.
54. "Philosophy of mind – The computational-representational theory of thought (CRTT)" (https://www.br
itannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/The-computational-representational-theory-of-thought-CRTT).
Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 21 October 2021.
55. Polger, Thomas W. "Functionalism" (https://iep.utm.edu/functism/). Internet Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Retrieved 31 May 2021.
56. Gulick, Robert Van (2009). Beckermann, Ansgar; McLaughlin, Brian P; Walter, Sven (eds.).
"Functionalism" (https://www.oxfordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199262618.001.00
01/oxfordhb-9780199262618-e-8). The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind. doi:10.1093/
oxfordhb/9780199262618.001.0001 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Foxfordhb%2F9780199262618.001.0
001). ISBN 978-0-19-926261-8.
57. Honderich, Ted (2005). "Mind". The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (https://philpapers.org/rec/HO
NTOC-2). Oxford University Press.
58. Levin, Janet (2021). "Functionalism: 2.2 Thinking Machines and the "Turing Test" " (https://plato.stan
ford.edu/entries/functionalism/#ThiMacTurTes). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021.
59. Pitt, David (2020). "Mental Representation: 1. The Representational Theory of Mind" (https://plato.st
anford.edu/entries/mental-representation/#Representational). The Stanford Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 October 2021.
60. Schmidt, R. W. "Judgment". New Catholic Encyclopedia (https://www.encyclopedia.com/social-scien
ces-and-law/law/law/judgment).
61. Sgarbi, Marco (2006). "Theories of Judgment. Historical and Theoretical Perspectives" (https://philpa
pers.org/rec/SGATOJ). Quaestio. 6 (1): 589–592. doi:10.1484/J.QUAESTIO.2.302491 (https://doi.or
g/10.1484%2FJ.QUAESTIO.2.302491).
62. Robins, E. P. (1898). "Modern Theories of Judgment" (https://philpapers.org/rec/ROBMTO).
Philosophical Review. 7 (6): 583–603. doi:10.2307/2176171 (https://doi.org/10.2307%2F2176171).
JSTOR 2176171 (https://www.jstor.org/stable/2176171).
63. Rojszczak, Artur; Smith, Barry (2003). "Theories of Judgment" (https://philpapers.org/rec/ROJTOJ).
The Cambridge History of Philosophy 1870-1945. Cambridge University Press: 157–173.
doi:10.1017/CHOL9780521591041.013 (https://doi.org/10.1017%2FCHOL9780521591041.013).
ISBN 978-0521591041.
64. Hanna, Robert (2018). "Kant's Theory of Judgment" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-judgmen
t/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Retrieved 24 October 2021.
65. Brandl, Johannes L.; Textor, Mark (2020). "Brentano's Theory of Judgement" (https://plato.stanford.e
du/entries/brentano-judgement/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research
Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 October 2021.
66. Vinacke, W. Edgar. "Thought". International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (https://www.encycl
opedia.com/social-sciences-and-law/sociology-and-social-reform/sociology-general-terms-and-conc
epts/thinking).
67. Pollock, John L. (1987). "Defeasible Reasoning" (https://doi.org/10.1207%2Fs15516709cog1104_4).
Cognitive Science. 11 (4): 481–518. doi:10.1207/s15516709cog1104_4 (https://doi.org/10.1207%2F
s15516709cog1104_4).
68. Koons, Robert (2021). "Defeasible Reasoning" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-defeasib
le/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Retrieved 16 October 2021.
69. Hansen, Hans (2020). "Fallacies" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fallacies/). The Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 18 March
2021.
70. Vleet, Van Jacob E. (2010). "Introduction". Informal Logical Fallacies: A Brief Guide (https://philpaper
s.org/rec/VLEILF). Upa.
71. Stone, Mark A. (2012). "Denying the Antecedent: Its Effective Use in Argumentation" (https://philpap
ers.org/rec/STODTA). Informal Logic. 32 (3): 327–356. doi:10.22329/il.v32i3.3681 (https://doi.org/1
0.22329%2Fil.v32i3.3681).
72. Dowden, Bradley. "Fallacies" (https://iep.utm.edu/fallacy/). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Retrieved 19 March 2021.
73. Walton, Douglas N. (1987). "1. A new model of argument". Informal Fallacies: Towards a Theory of
Argument Criticisms (https://philpapers.org/rec/WALIFT). John Benjamins.
74. Engel, S. Morris (1982). "2. The medium of language". With Good Reason an Introduction to
Informal Fallacies (https://philpapers.org/rec/ENGWGR). St. Martin's Press.
75. Margolis, Eric; Laurence, Stephen (2021). "Concepts" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/concepts/).
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Retrieved 28 September 2021.
76. "Philosophy of mind – Thoughts and attitudes" (https://www.britannica.com/topic/philosophy-of-mind/
Thoughts-and-attitudes). Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 16 October 2021.
77. "Concept formation" (https://www.britannica.com/topic/concept-formation). Encyclopedia Britannica.
Retrieved 16 October 2021.
78. Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Thinking: An Overview". Encyclopedia of Psychology (https://www.ap
a.org/pubs/books/4600100). American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5.
79. Fodor, Jerry (2004). "Having Concepts: A Brief Refutation of the Twentieth Century" (https://philpape
rs.org/rec/FODHCA). Mind and Language. 19 (1): 29–47. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00245.x (htt
ps://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1468-0017.2004.00245.x).
80. Ortony, Andrew (26 November 1993) [1979]. "Metaphor, language, and thought". In Ortony, Andrew
(ed.). Metaphor and Thought (https://books.google.com/books?id=QiJRvuXA_VcC) (2 ed.).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 2. ISBN 9780521405614. Retrieved 21 February 2024.
"The constructivist approach seems to entail an important role for metaphor in both language and
thought [...]."
81. Weiskopf, Daniel A.; Bechtel, William (2004). "Remarks on Fodor on Having Concepts" (https://philp
apers.org/rec/WEIROF). Mind and Language. 19 (1): 48–56. doi:10.1111/j.1468-0017.2004.00246.x
(https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1468-0017.2004.00246.x).
82. "Learning theory" (https://www.britannica.com/science/learning-theory). Encyclopedia Britannica.
Retrieved 16 October 2021.
83. Kim, Kyung Hee; Pierce, Robert A. (2013). "Convergent Versus Divergent Thinking". Encyclopedia
of Creativity, Invention, Innovation and Entrepreneurship (https://link.springer.com/referenceworkentr
y/10.1007%2F978-1-4614-3858-8_22). Springer. pp. 245–250. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-3858-8_22
(https://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-1-4614-3858-8_22). ISBN 978-1-4614-3857-1. Retrieved
24 October 2021. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
84. Razumnikova, Olga M. (2013). "Divergent Versus Convergent Thinking" (https://link.springer.com/ref
erenceworkentry/10.1007%2F978-1-4614-3858-8_362). Encyclopedia of Creativity, Invention,
Innovation and Entrepreneurship. Springer. pp. 546–552. doi:10.1007/978-1-4614-3858-8_362 (http
s://doi.org/10.1007%2F978-1-4614-3858-8_362). ISBN 978-1-4614-3857-1. Retrieved 24 October
2021. {{cite book}}: |website= ignored (help)
85. Reed, Stephen K. (1 December 2016). "The Structure of Ill-Structured (and Well-Structured)
Problems Revisited" (https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1). Educational
Psychology Review. 28 (4): 691–716. doi:10.1007/s10648-015-9343-1 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs
10648-015-9343-1). ISSN 1573-336X (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1573-336X). S2CID 146496245
(https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:146496245).
86. Arpaly, N.; Schroeder, T. (2012). "Deliberation and Acting for Reasons" (https://philpapers.org/rec/A
RPDAA). Philosophical Review. 121 (2): 209–239. doi:10.1215/00318108-1539089 (https://doi.org/1
0.1215%2F00318108-1539089).
87. Steele, Katie; Stefánsson, H. Orri (2020). "Decision Theory" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decisi
on-theory/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. Retrieved 24 October 2021.
88. Buchak, Lara (2016). "Decision Theory". The Oxford Handbook of Probability and Philosophy (http
s://philpapers.org/rec/BUCDT). Oxford University Press.
89. Perrin, Denis; Michaelian, Kourken; Sant’Anna, André (2020). "The Phenomenology of
Remembering Is an Epistemic Feeling" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7350950).
Frontiers in Psychology. 11: 1531. doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2020.01531 (https://doi.org/10.3389%2Ffpsy
g.2020.01531). ISSN 1664-1078 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1664-1078). PMC 7350950 (https://
www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC7350950). PMID 32719642 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.go
v/32719642).
90. Gardiner, J. M. (29 September 2001). "Episodic memory and autonoetic consciousness: a first-
person approach" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC1088519). Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences. 356 (1413): 1351–1361.
doi:10.1098/rstb.2001.0955 (https://doi.org/10.1098%2Frstb.2001.0955). ISSN 0962-8436 (https://w
ww.worldcat.org/issn/0962-8436). PMC 1088519 (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC10
88519). PMID 11571027 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/11571027).
91. Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 3. Episodicity" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entrie
s/memory/#Epis). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. Retrieved 2 October 2021.
92. Tulving, Endel. "Learning and Memory: Episodic Memory" (https://www.encyclopedia.com/psycholog
y/encyclopedias-almanacs-transcripts-and-maps/episodic-memory).
93. Michaelian, Kourken; Sutton, John (2017). "Memory: 4. Mnemicity" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entrie
s/memory/#Mnem). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University. Retrieved 2 October 2021.
94. Manser, A. R. "Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Imagination" (https://www.encyclopedia.com/medicine/p
sychology/psychology-and-psychiatry/imagination). Retrieved 3 October 2021.
95. Russell, Bertrand (1915). "Sensation and Imagination" (https://philpapers.org/rec/RUSSAI). The
Monist. 25 (1): 28–44. doi:10.5840/monist191525136 (https://doi.org/10.5840%2Fmonist191525136)
.
96. Abbott, Alison (1 January 2015). "Unconscious thought not so smart after all". Nature. 517 (7536):
537–538. Bibcode:2015Natur.517..537A (https://ui.adsabs.harvard.edu/abs/2015Natur.517..537A).
doi:10.1038/517537a (https://doi.org/10.1038%2F517537a). ISSN 1476-4687 (https://www.worldca
t.org/issn/1476-4687). PMID 25631423 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/25631423).
97. Mealor, Andy David; Dienes, Zoltan (2012). "Conscious and Unconscious Thought in Artificial
Grammar Learning" (https://philpapers.org/rec/MEACAU). Consciousness and Cognition. 21 (2):
865–874. doi:10.1016/j.concog.2012.03.001 (https://doi.org/10.1016%2Fj.concog.2012.03.001).
PMID 22472202 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/22472202). S2CID 40114660 (https://api.semantic
scholar.org/CorpusID:40114660).
98. Fowles, Christopher (2 January 2019). "Nietzsche on conscious and unconscious thought" (https://w
ww.tandfonline.com/doi/abs/10.1080/0020174X.2019.1527537?journalCode=sinq20). Inquiry. 62 (1):
1–22. doi:10.1080/0020174X.2019.1527537 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F0020174X.2019.1527537).
ISSN 0020-174X (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0020-174X). S2CID 171812391 (https://api.semanti
cscholar.org/CorpusID:171812391).
99. Smith, David Woodruff (2018). "Phenomenology: 1. What is Phenomenology?" (https://plato.stanfor
d.edu/entries/phenomenology/#WhatPhen). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics
Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 20 September 2021.
100. Smith, Joel. "Phenomenology" (https://iep.utm.edu/phenom/). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Retrieved 10 October 2021.
101. Hansen, Mette Kristine. "Cognitive Phenomenology" (https://iep.utm.edu/cog-phen/). Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 17 October 2021.
102. Kriegel, Uriah (2015). "The Character of Cognitive Phenomenology". Phenomenology of Thinking (ht
tps://philpapers.org/rec/KRITCO-10). London and New York: Routledge. pp. 25–43.
103. Carruthers, Peter; Veillet, Bénédicte (2011). "The Case Against Cognitive Phenomenology".
Cognitive Phenomenology (https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9
780199579938.001.0001/acprof-9780199579938-chapter-2). Oxford University Press.
ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
104. Prinz, Jesse J. (2011). "The Sensory Basis of Cognitive Phenomenology 1". Cognitive
Phenomenology (https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/978019957
9938.001.0001/acprof-9780199579938-chapter-8). Oxford University Press.
ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
105. Levine, Joseph (2011). "On the Phenomenology of Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology (https://oxfo
rd.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199579938.001.0001/acprof-97801
99579938-chapter-5). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
106. Siewert, Charles (2011). "Phenomenal Thought". Cognitive Phenomenology (https://oxford.university
pressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199579938.001.0001/acprof-9780199579938-c
hapter-11). Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
107. Pitt, David (2004). "The Phenomenology of Cognition: Or What Is It Like to Think That P?" (https://ph
ilpapers.org/rec/PITWII). Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. 69 (1): 1–36. doi:10.1111/
j.1933-1592.2004.tb00382.x (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fj.1933-1592.2004.tb00382.x).
108. Smith, David Woodruff (2011). "The Phenomenology of Consciously Thinking". Cognitive
Phenomenology (https://oxford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/acprof:oso/978019957
9938.001.0001/acprof-9780199579938-chapter-15). Oxford University Press.
ISBN 978-0-19-957993-8.
109. Dastur, Françoise; Vallier, Robert (2017). "The Problem of Pre-Predicative Experience: Husserl".
Questions of Phenomenology (https://www.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.5422/fordham/9
780823233731.001.0001/upso-9780823233731-chapter-003). Fordham University Press.
doi:10.5422/fordham/9780823233731.001.0001 (https://doi.org/10.5422%2Ffordham%2F97808232
33731.001.0001). ISBN 978-0-8232-3373-1. S2CID 148619048 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/Cor
pusID:148619048).
110. Staiti, Andrea (2018). Zahavi, Dan (ed.). Pre-Predicative Experience and Life-World (https://www.oxf
ordhandbooks.com/view/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.001.0001/oxfordhb-9780198755340-e-1
2). doi:10.1093/oxfordhb/9780198755340.013.12 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2Foxfordhb%2F9780198
755340.013.12). ISBN 978-0-19-875534-0.
111. Diaz, Emiliano (2020). "Transcendental Anticipation: A Reconsideration of Husserl's Type and Kant's
Schemata" (https://philpapers.org/rec/DIATAA-4). Husserl Studies. 36 (1): 1–23. doi:10.1007/
s10743-019-09249-3 (https://doi.org/10.1007%2Fs10743-019-09249-3). S2CID 203547989 (https://
api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:203547989).
112. Doyon, Maxime (2015). "The "As-Structure" of Intentional Experience in Husserl and Heidegger".
Phenomenology of Thinking (https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9781315697734-1
0/structure-intentional-experience-husserl-heidegger-maxime-doyon?context=ubx). Routledge.
pp. 122–139. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-10 (https://doi.org/10.4324%2F9781315697734-10).
ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4.
113. Hopp, Walter (2015). "Empty Intentions and Phenomenological Character: A Defense of
Inclusivism". Phenomenology of Thinking (https://www.taylorfrancis.com/chapters/edit/10.4324/9781
315697734-6/empty-intentions-phenomenological-character-defense-inclusivism-walter-hopp).
Routledge. pp. 50–67. doi:10.4324/9781315697734-6 (https://doi.org/10.4324%2F978131569773
4-6). ISBN 978-1-315-69773-4.
114. Spear, Andrew D. "Husserl, Edmund: Intentionality and Intentional Content: 2ai Act-Character" (http
s://iep.utm.edu/huss-int/#SSH2ai). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 October 2021.
115. Kim, J. (1995). Honderich, Ted (ed.). Problems in the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford Companion to
Philosophy (https://archive.org/details/oxfordcompaniont00hond). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
ISBN 978-0-19-866132-0.
116. Companion to Metaphysics, By Jaegwon Kim, Gary S. Rosenkrantz, Ernest Sosa, Contributor
Jaegwon Kim, 2nd ed., Wiley-Blackwell, 2009, ISBN 978-1-4051-5298-3
117. Varela, Francisco J., Thompson, Evan T., and Rosch, Eleanor. (1992). The Embodied Mind:
Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-72021-3
118. Cowart, Monica (2004). "Embodied Cognition" (http://www.iep.utm.edu/embodcog/). The Internet
Encyclopedia of Philosophy. ISSN 2161-0002 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/2161-0002). Retrieved
27 February 2012.
119. Di Paolo, Ezequiel (2009). "Shallow and Deep Embodiment" (https://cast.switch.ch/vod/clips/74nrkb
wys) (Video, duration: 1:11:38). University of Sussex. Retrieved 27 February 2012.
120. Gestalt Theory, By Max Wertheimer. Hayes Barton Press, 1944, ISBN 978-1-59377-695-4
121. Piaget, J. (1951). Psychology of Intelligence. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul
122. Demetriou, A. (1998). Cognitive development. In A. Demetriou, W. Doise, K. F. M. van Lieshout
(Eds.), Life-span developmental psychology. pp. 179–269. London: Wiley.
123. Schacter, Daniel L. (2011). Psychology Second Edition, "Positive Psychology". New York. 584 pp.
124. Snowden, Ruth (2006). Teach Yourself Freud (illustrated ed.). McGraw-Hill. p. 107.
ISBN 978-0-07-147274-6.
125. The Cambridge companion to Freud, By Jerome Neu. Cambridge University Press, 1991, p. 29,
ISBN 978-0-521-37779-9
126. Jensen, Peter S., Mrazek, David, Knapp, Penelope K., Steinberg, Laurence, Pfeffer, Cynthia,
Schowalter, John, & Shapiro, Theodore. (Dec 1997) "Evolution and revolution in child psychiatry:
ADHD as a disorder of adaptation. (attention-deficit hyperactivity syndrome)". Journal of the
American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry. 36. p. 1672. (10). July 14, 2007.
127. "Laws of thought" (https://www.britannica.com/topic/laws-of-thought). Encyclopedia Britannica.
Retrieved 28 October 2021.
128. Borchert, Donald (2006). "Laws of Thought". Macmillan Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 2nd Edition (htt
ps://philpapers.org/rec/BORMEO). Macmillan.
129. Moschovakis, Joan (2021). "Intuitionistic Logic: 1. Rejection of Tertium Non Datur" (https://plato.stanf
ord.edu/entries/logic-intuitionistic/#RejTerNonDat). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
130. McKubre-Jordens, Maarten. "Constructive Mathematics: 1b Constructivism as Philosophy" (https://ie
p.utm.edu/con-math/#SH1b). Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
131. Priest, Graham; Berto, Francesco; Weber, Zach (2018). "Dialetheism" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entr
ies/dialetheism/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford
University.
132. Horn, Laurence R. (2018). "Contradiction" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/contradiction/). The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
133. Weber, Zach. "Dialetheism" (https://www.oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396
577/obo-9780195396577-0310.xml). Oxford Bibliographies. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
134. "principle of sufficient reason" (https://www.britannica.com/topic/principle-of-sufficient-reason).
Encyclopædia Britannica. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
135. Melamed, Yitzhak Y.; Lin, Martin (2021). "Principle of Sufficient Reason" (https://plato.stanford.edu/e
ntries/sufficient-reason/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab,
Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
136. Roese, Neal J. (1997). "Counterfactual thinking" (https://psycnet.apa.org/record/1997-02112-007).
Psychological Bulletin. 121 (1): 133–148. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.121.1.133 (https://doi.org/10.103
7%2F0033-2909.121.1.133). PMID 9000895 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/9000895).
137. Kazdin, Alan E., ed. (2000). "Counterfactual thought". Encyclopedia of Psychology (https://www.ap
a.org/pubs/books/4600100). American Psychological Association. ISBN 978-1-55798-187-5.
138. Van Hoeck, Nicole; Watson, Patrick D.; Barbey, Aron K. (2015). "Cognitive neuroscience of human
counterfactual reasoning" (https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4511878). Frontiers in
Human Neuroscience. 9: 420. doi:10.3389/fnhum.2015.00420 (https://doi.org/10.3389%2Ffnhum.20
15.00420). ISSN 1662-5161 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1662-5161). PMC 4511878 (https://ww
w.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4511878). PMID 26257633 (https://pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/26
257633).
139. Starr, William (2021). "Counterfactuals: 1.1 What are Counterfactuals?" (https://plato.stanford.edu/e
ntries/counterfactuals/#WhatCoun). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics
Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 28 October 2021.
140. "The American Heritage Dictionary entry: thought experiment" (https://www.ahdictionary.com/word/s
earch.html?q=thought+experiment). www.ahdictionary.com. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt Publishing.
Retrieved 30 October 2021.
141. Brown, James Robert; Fehige, Yiftach (2019). "Thought Experiments" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entr
ies/thought-experiment/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab,
Stanford University. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
142. Goffi, Jean-Yves; Roux, Sophie (2011). "On the Very Idea of a Thought Experiment" (https://philpape
rs.org/rec/GOFOTV). Thought Experiments in Methodological and Historical Contexts. Brill: 165–
191. doi:10.1163/ej.9789004201767.i-233.35 (https://doi.org/10.1163%2Fej.9789004201767.i-233.3
5). ISBN 978-9004201774. S2CID 260640180 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:26064018
0).
143. Sorensen, Roy A. (1999). "Are Thought Experiments Experiments?". Thought Experiments (https://o
xford.universitypressscholarship.com/view/10.1093/019512913X.001.0001/acprof-9780195129137-c
hapter-10). Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/019512913X.001.0001 (https://doi.org/10.1093%2
F019512913X.001.0001). ISBN 978-0-19-512913-7.
144. Bishop, Michael A. (1999). "Why Thought Experiments Are Not Arguments" (https://philpapers.org/re
c/BISWTE). Philosophy of Science. 66 (4): 534–541. doi:10.1086/392753 (https://doi.org/10.1086%2
F392753). S2CID 170519663 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:170519663).
145. Norton, John D. (1996). "Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought?" (https://philpapers.org/
rec/NORATE). Canadian Journal of Philosophy. 26 (3): 333–366.
doi:10.1080/00455091.1996.10717457 (https://doi.org/10.1080%2F00455091.1996.10717457).
S2CID 143017404 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:143017404).
146. Sorensen, Roy (1 January 1995). "Roy Sorensen's Thought Experiments" (https://informallogic.ca/in
dex.php/informal_logic/article/view/2425/). Informal Logic. 17 (3). doi:10.22329/il.v17i3.2425 (https://
doi.org/10.22329%2Fil.v17i3.2425). ISSN 2293-734X (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/2293-734X).
147. Reiss, Julian (1 December 2009). "Counterfactuals, Thought Experiments, and Singular Causal
Analysis in History" (https://www.journals.uchicago.edu/doi/abs/10.1086/605826?journalCode=phos)
. Philosophy of Science. 76 (5): 712–723. doi:10.1086/605826 (https://doi.org/10.1086%2F605826).
ISSN 0031-8248 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0031-8248). S2CID 43496954 (https://api.semantics
cholar.org/CorpusID:43496954).
148. Aligica, Paul Dragos; Evans, Anthony J. (1 September 2009). "Thought experiments, counterfactuals
and comparative analysis" (https://link.springer.com/article/10.1007/s11138-009-0082-8). The
Review of Austrian Economics. 22 (3): 225–239. doi:10.1007/s11138-009-0082-8 (https://doi.org/1
0.1007%2Fs11138-009-0082-8). ISSN 1573-7128 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1573-7128).
S2CID 144831020 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:144831020).
149. Cole, David (2020). "The Chinese Room Argument" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/chinese-roo
m/). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
Retrieved 29 October 2021.
150. Hauser, Larry. "Chinese Room Argument" (https://iep.utm.edu/chineser/). Internet Encyclopedia of
Philosophy. Retrieved 29 October 2021.
151. Ennis, Robert H. (2015). "Critical Thinking: A Streamlined Conception" (https://link.springer.com/cha
pter/10.1057/9781137378057_2). The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education.
Palgrave Macmillan US. pp. 31–47. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_2 (https://doi.org/10.1057%2F978
1137378057_2). ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7.
152. Davies, Martin; Barnett, Ronald (2015). "Introduction" (https://link.springer.com/chapter/10.1057/978
1137378057_1). The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Thinking in Higher Education. Palgrave
Macmillan US. pp. 1–25. doi:10.1057/9781137378057_1 (https://doi.org/10.1057%2F978113737805
7_1). ISBN 978-1-137-37805-7.
153. Hitchcock, David (2020). "Critical Thinking" (https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/critical-thinking/). The
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved
1 November 2021.
154. Dewey, John (1910). "6: The Analysis of a Complete Act of Thought". How We Think (https://brock
u.ca/MeadProject/Dewey/Dewey_1910a/Dewey_1910_f.html).
155. Siegel, Harvey (2006). "Philosophy if Education, Epistemological Issues In". Macmillan Encyclopedia
of Philosophy, 2nd Edition (https://www.encyclopedia.com/humanities/encyclopedias-almanacs-trans
cripts-and-maps/philosophy-education-epistemological-issues). Macmillan.
156. Monteiro, Sandra; Sherbino, Jonathan; Sibbald, Matthew; Norman, Geoff (2020). "Critical thinking,
biases and dual processing: The enduring myth of generalisable skills" (https://doi.org/10.1111%2Fm
edu.13872). Medical Education. 54 (1): 66–73. doi:10.1111/medu.13872 (https://doi.org/10.1111%2F
medu.13872). ISSN 1365-2923 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/1365-2923). PMID 31468581 (https://
pubmed.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/31468581). S2CID 201674464 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:2
01674464).
157. Khalid, Ruhi (June 2010). "Positive Thinking in Coping with Stress and Health outcomes: Literature
Review" (https://www.academia.edu/30299598). Journal of Research and Reflections in Education.
4 (1): 42–61.
158. Scheier, Michael F.; Carver, Charles S. (1 February 1993). "On the Power of Positive Thinking: The
Benefits of Being Optimistic" (https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1111/1467-8721.ep1077057
2?journalCode=cdpa). Current Directions in Psychological Science. 2 (1): 26–30.
doi:10.1111/1467-8721.ep10770572 (https://doi.org/10.1111%2F1467-8721.ep10770572).
ISSN 0963-7214 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0963-7214). S2CID 145393172 (https://api.semantic
scholar.org/CorpusID:145393172).
159. Oettingen, Gabriele; Cachia, Julie Y. A. (2017). "30. Problems with Positive Thinking and How to
Overcome Them". Handbook of Self-Regulation: Third Edition: Research, Theory, and Applications
(https://www.guilford.com/books/Handbook-of-Self-Regulation/Vohs-Baumeister/9781462533824/co
ntents).
160. Thomas, Sandra P. (2020). "Defensive Pessimism". Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual
Differences (https://link.springer.com/referenceworkentry/10.1007%2F978-3-319-24612-3_1061).
Springer International Publishing. pp. 1036–1038. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_1061 (https://do
i.org/10.1007%2F978-3-319-24612-3_1061). ISBN 978-3-319-24612-3. S2CID 243736790 (https://a
pi.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:243736790).
161. Peale, Norman Vincent. The Power of Positive Thinking (https://books.google.com/books?id=A0u0D
AAAQBAJ). Om Books International. ISBN 978-93-85609-89-3.
162. Seligman, Martin E. P. (2002). "6. Optimism about the Future". Authentic Happiness: Using the New
Positive Psychology to Realize Your Potential for Lasting Fulfillment (https://books.google.com/book
s?id=_JaY2K2dhC0C). Simon and Schuster. ISBN 978-0-7432-4788-7.
163. Woodstock, Louise (1 April 2007). "Think About It: The Misbegotten Promise of Positive Thinking
Discourse" (https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/abs/10.1177/0196859906298177). Journal of
Communication Inquiry. 31 (2): 166–189. doi:10.1177/0196859906298177 (https://doi.org/10.117
7%2F0196859906298177). ISSN 0196-8599 (https://www.worldcat.org/issn/0196-8599).
S2CID 145436993 (https://api.semanticscholar.org/CorpusID:145436993).
164. Chabris, Christopher F.; Simons, Daniel J. (24 September 2010). "Fight 'The Power' " (https://www.n
ytimes.com/2010/09/26/books/review/Chabris-t.html). The New York Times.
Further reading
▪ Bayne, Tim (21 September 2013), "Thoughts", New Scientist. 7-page feature article on the topic.
▪ Fields, R. Douglas, "The Brain Learns in Unexpected Ways: Neuroscientists have discovered a set
of unfamiliar cellular mechanisms for making fresh memories", Scientific American, vol. 322, no. 3
(March 2020), pp. 74–79. "Myelin, long considered inert insulation on axons, is now seen as making
a contribution to learning by controlling the speed at which signals travel along neural wiring."
(p. 79.)
▪ Rajvanshi, Anil K. (2010), Nature of Human Thought (https://books.google.com/books?id=__YlBAAA
QBAJ&q=nature+of+human+thought&pg=PA40), ISBN 978-81-905781-2-7.
▪ Simon, Herbert, Models of Thought, Vol I, 1979, ISBN 0-300-02347-2; Vol II, 1989,
ISBN 0-300-04230-2, Yale University Press.
External links
▪ The dictionary definition of think at Wiktionary
▪ Media related to Thinking at Wikimedia Commons