(Routledge Explorations in Energy Studies) Johannes Kester - The Politics of Energy Security - Critical Security Studies, New Materialism and Governmentality-Routledge (2018)
(Routledge Explorations in Energy Studies) Johannes Kester - The Politics of Energy Security - Critical Security Studies, New Materialism and Governmentality-Routledge (2018)
Energy security is known for its ‘slippery’ nature and subsequent broad range of
definitions. Instead of another attempt to grasp its essence, this book offers a
critical reflection that problematizes the use of energy security itself.
After a short historical and methodological analysis of the proliferation of
energy security, The Politics of Energy Security unpacks three social practices that
drive energy security. These include an analysis of the logics of security, a study
of the relation between the materiality of sociotechnical (energy) systems and
the knowledge people have over such systems, and a reflection on the power
and politics behind (energy) security. Each of these is discussed and ultimately
illustrated in the last chapter to show how energy security works, how it is
shaped, and what role it plays within political processes.
Based on a novel performative reading of energy security with its focus on
ontological politics and an in-depth look at the often implicitly accepted social
practices that determine how people shape and are shaped by energy security,
this book will be of great interest to students and scholars of energy security and
policy, political theory, international relations, critical security studies and
environmental studies more broadly.
Johannes Kester
First published 2018
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
711 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10017
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2018 Johannes Kester
The right of Johannes Kester to be identified as author of this work has
been asserted by him in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the
Copyright, Designs and Patents Act 1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced
or utilized in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means,
now known or hereafter invented, including photocopying and recording,
or in any information storage or retrieval system, without permission in
writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or
registered trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation
without intent to infringe.
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record has been requested for this book
1 Introduction 1
1.1 Introduction 1
1.2 Argument, contribution and approach 2
1.3 Overview of chapters 6
Index 236
Illustrations
Figures
3.1 Perceived threats to and from natural resources 42
3.2 Energy trilemma 47
4.1 Types, techniques and logics of security 59
7.1 Frequency and magnitude of Groningen earthquakes 203
8.1 The ontology of a performative reading of energy security 226
Table
2.1 Definitions of energy security 14
Acknowledgements
This book is based on my PhD thesis Securing abundance: the politics of energy
security, which I defended in 2016 at the University of Groningen. It would not
have come into fruition without the helpful advice, patience and occasional
friendly push from a range of people. First, I would like to thank my wife,
Vimke, for joining me on a journey that was not of her choosing but which she
supported as if it was her own. Special thanks as well to both my PhD super-
visors. To Jaap de Wilde for his insightful comments and critique, his guidance
through university politics, and his initial trust in an MA student who wanted
to write ‘something’ about energy and constructivism. Thanks to Benjamin Her-
borth for his encouragement and his enthusiasm to share an almost-encyclopedic
breadth of theoretical knowledge with me. The book also builds in large part on
the international relations bubble at the Oude Boteringestraat. I feel lucky to
have been part of this group and would like to thank Stef Wittendorp, Lennart
Landman and Kars de Bruijne for their willingness to suffer as a critical sound-
ing board, one that has seen quite some use over the years. Add to them the
others with whom I started my PhD journey and shared many of the joy and
pains of writing a thesis, Petra Boudewijn, Margriet Fokken and Simon Halink,
and you have an environment in which it is a pleasure to go to work each day,
every day. Lastly, I would like to thank Benjamin Sovacool for his support and
generosity to use some of the precious time of our project on the sociotechnical
transition behind electric mobility to rewrite the thesis into the book before
you. Of course, I have encountered many others throughout my research, close
by and far off, who in one way or another have enriched my thinking. The list is
long and, if you feel you are on it, you probably are and I thank you. I can only
hope that this book properly reflects all the lessons and insights that you all
shared so freely.
1 Introduction
1.1 Introduction
I have never considered myself wealthy. Luckily, I have also never known
hunger or thirst and the longest period I have been without electricity involun-
tarily has been half a day at most. In other words, I have had the fortune to grow
up and live in a society with the norms, institutions and markets that cater for
an abundance of natural resources. In fact, as this book shows, I live in a society
that has completely structured its political markets to ensure this. That said,
these same political markets produce several adverse effects for those at its
fringes. Climate change, energy poverty, scarcity, food banks and a degrading
biodiversity are but some of the terms that indicate the negative sides of our
current political economy. A political economy that has benefited many, but
not without excluding some and harming others.1 Simultaneously, this political
economy is constantly defended and secured against the threats and dangers
that its beneficiaries believe to exist. This calls for a need to understand the
security processes at work in the production, distribution and consumption of
energy, food and other natural resources. While the security processes behind
each of these resources (and their nexus) is important, ‘nothing exists that is
not energy, or not affected by energy’.2 This book will therefore focus on the
concept, practice and politics of energy security.
There are many ways to study energy security. Some scholars approach it
conceptually, historically or quantitatively, a lot take a policy-oriented route,
and a select few offer a broader social critique.3 What many of these analyses
have in common is that they search for an answer to what energy security is or
ought to be – often simultaneously. What is studied are questions like how energy
security should be defined, what exactly needs to be secured, what the threats
are, who is in need of energy security, what needs to be done to counter the
threats, and so on.4 This book is not concerned with such questions. Instead it
argues that the studies asking these questions only partly help us understand
what energy security is, because it does not allow for an understanding of what
energy security does politically. The book thus shifts the question to: what does
energy security do? A question which it pursues by studying how energy security
is approached in current scholarship and then further unpacks with another
2 Introduction
shift in focus from the current energy security literature to the security politics
around energy security and by answering a different set of questions: what is
security and what does security do? How does energy security relate to the mate-
riality of energy, its infrastructure and resources? How does energy security work
politically as a form of governance? And how can we operationalize such a per-
formative approach to energy security?
Following these questions, the book promotes a shift away from a pre- and
descriptive understanding of the concept of energy security towards an under-
standing of energy security as performative: to see the designation and use of the
concept of energy security as an act in itself.5 By seeing energy security as an act,
the repeated practice of its use ‘constitutes’, ‘maintains’ or ‘changes’ the meaning
of the concept itself and the enactment of its material effects, and thereby the
potential involvement and identity of the actors behind it and the possible routes
of action that are open to them.6 Such a performative approach forces scholars to
move away from the ‘quest for certainty’ inherent in studies that want to under-
stand what energy security is, and replace this with the acceptance that the
concept of energy security is embedded, structured, productive, malleable and
used differently by different people in different places at different times.7
The performative reading of energy security (PRES) that is proposed in this
book builds primarily on critical international relations (IR) theory and critical
security studies (CSS), but also draws on insights from new materialism, devel-
opment studies, political geography, sociology and philosophy. By unpacking
the concept of energy security with the help of these different literatures, a
reflexive stance is imposed on both the author and reader towards the triangle
of political economy, security and natural resource policies and their trade-offs
(closely related to the energy trilemma within energy studies depicting the
trade-offs between economic concerns, security concerns and environmental
concerns).8 Importantly, these trade-offs point to the fact that energy security is
only one aspect within the wider debate on energy, which also includes discus-
sions that start from an energy transition or energy justice perspective.9
To be clear, the goal here is not to offer a specific performative reading that
explains energy security, but to problematize current understandings of energy
security through a rigorous theoretical reflection on the concept and the prac-
tices that shape it. These include the different security logics (Chapter 4), the
interaction between energy security concerns and the materiality of the actual
energy infrastructures (Chapter 5) and a deeper understanding of the politics
and power relations behind the organization of energy (Chapter 6). These three,
in all their intricacy and heterogeneity, explain part of how people approach
and secure the production, transportation and consumption of current and
future energy use.
Notes
1 Le Billon 2005, 5.
2 Ciută 2010, 124.
3 Conceptually, qualitatively or historically: Winzer 2012; Chester 2010; Cherp and
Jewell 2014; Yergin 1991. Quantitatively: Kruyt et al. 2009; Jansen and Seebregts
2010; Brown et al. 2014; Narula and Reddy 2015. More policy-oriented: Luft and
8 Introduction
Korin 2009; CIEP 2004; Kalicki and Goldwyn 2005; Bahgat 2006; Vivoda 2009. And
from a social critique: Sheller 2014; Illich 1974; Shove and Walker 2014; Byrne and
Toly 2006.
4 Cherp and Jewell 2014.
5 Butler 2010; Barad 2003; Bialasiewicz et al. 2007.
6 Aalberts 2006, 3.
7 Herborth 2012.
8 On the energy trilemma, see Figure 3.2 and its discussion in Chapter 3.
9 Goldthau and Sovacool 2012; Sovacool 2013.
10 Chester 2010; Löschel, Moslener and Rübbelke 2010; Sovacool and Brown 2010;
Dyer and Trombetta 2013; Ciută 2010; Cherp and Jewell 2011.
11 Ciută 2010; Bridge 2015. See also the broader work on ‘energopower’ by Boyer 2011;
Boyer 2014; Mitchell 2013. Other critical discursive articles include: Smith Stegen
2011; Byrne and Toly 2006; Campbell 2005; Cooper 2013; Fischhendler and Nathan
2014; Herbstreuth 2014; Kurze 2008; Lovell 2008; Nyman 2014; Teschner and
Paavola 2013.
12 Jarosz 2011; Smith, Pointing and Maxwell 1992.
13 Sovacool 2014, 11. Also, Urry 2014.
14 Kester 2018.
15 Amoore and De Goede 2008; De Goede 2012.
16 Aradau 2010; Schouten 2014; Walters 2014; Aradau, Coward et al. 2015.
17 Gilpin and Gilpin 2001. Gilpin’s classic handbook only mentions energy four times:
either as a side note or in relation to the 1973 origin of IPE. An exception is
Keohane 2009.
18 Strange 1994, 195. See also: Stoddard 2013, 2.
19 Hughes and Lipscy 2013.
20 Hancock and Vivoda 2014.
21 Aradau and Huysmans 2014; Aradau, Huysmans et al. 2015.
22 See also: Cooper 2013.
23 Barad 2003.
Bibliography
Aalberts, Tanja E. 2006. Politics of Sovereignty. PhD thesis, Amsterdam: Vrije Univer-
siteit.
Amoore, Louise, and Marieke de Goede. 2008. Transactions after 9/11: The banal face of
the preemptive strike. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 33 (2):
173–185.
Aradau, Claudia. 2010. Security that matters: Critical infrastructure and objects of pro-
tection. Security Dialogue 41 (5): 491–514.
Aradau, Claudia, Martin Coward, Eva Herschinger, Owen D. Thomas and Nadine
Voelkner. 2015. Discourse/materiality. In Critical security methods: New frameworks for
analysis, edited by Claudia Aradau, Jef Huysmans, Andrew Neal and Nadine Voelkner,
57–84. London and New York: Routledge.
Aradau, Claudia, and Jef Huysmans. 2014. Critical methods in international relations:
The politics of techniques, devices and acts. European Journal of International Relations
20 (3): 596–619.
Aradau, Claudia, Jef Huysmans, Andrew Neal and Nadine Voelkner, eds. 2015. Critical
security methods: New frameworks for analysis. London and New York: Routledge.
Bahgat, G. 2006. Europe’s energy security: Challenges and opportunities. International
Affairs 82 (5): 961–975.
Introduction 9
Barad, Karen. 2003. Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how
matter comes to matter. Signs 28 (3): 801–831.
Bialasiewicz, Luiza, David Campbell, Stuart Elden, Stephen Graham, Alex Jeffrey and
Alison J. Williams. 2007. Performing security: The imaginative geographies of current
US strategy. Political Geography 26 (4): 405–422.
Boyer, Dominic. 2011. Energopolitics and the anthropology of energy. Anthropology News
52 (5): 5–7.
Boyer, Dominic. 2014. Energopower: An introduction. Anthropological Quarterly 87 (2):
309–333.
Bridge, Gavin. 2015. Energy (in)security: World-making in an age of scarcity. The Geo-
graphical Journal 181 (4): 328–339.
Brown, Marilyn A., Yu Wang, Benjamin K. Sovacool and Anthony Louis D’Agostino.
2014. Forty years of energy security trends: A comparative assessment of 22 indus-
trialized countries. Energy Research & Social Science 4: 64–77.
Butler, Judith. 2010. Performative agency. Journal of Cultural Economy 3 (2): 147–161.
Byrne, John, and Noah Toly. 2006. Energy as a social project: Recovering a discourse. In
Transforming power: Energy, environment and society in conflict, edited by John Byrne,
Noah Toly and Leigh Glover, 1–32. New Brunswick, NJ, and London: Transaction.
Campbell, David. 2005. The biopolitics of security: Oil, empire, and the sports utility
vehicle. American Quarterly 57 (3): 943–972.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2011. The three perspectives on energy security: Intel-
lectual history, disciplinary roots and the potential for integration. Current Opinion in
Environmental Sustainability 3 (4): 202–212.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2014. The concept of energy security: Beyond the four
As. Energy Policy 75: 415–421.
Chester, Lynne. 2010. Conceptualising energy security and making explicit its polysemic
nature. Energy Policy 38 (2): 887–895.
CIEP. 2004. Study on energy supply security and geopolitics – Final report. CIEP Study for
DGTREN. The Hague: Clingendael International Energy Programme.
Ciută, Felix. 2010. Conceptual notes on energy security: Total or banal security? Security
Dialogue 41 (2): 123–144.
Cooper, Christopher. 2013. Physics envy: Why energy policy is more art than science.
The Journal of World Energy Law & Business 6 (1): 67–82.
De Goede, Marieke. 2012. Speculative security: The politics of pursuing terrorist monies.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Dyer, Hugh, and Maria Julia Trombetta. 2013. International handbook of energy security.
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Fischhendler, Itay, and Daniel Nathan. 2014. In the name of energy security: The
struggle over the exportation of Israeli natural gas. Energy Policy 70: 152–162.
Gilpin, Robert, and Jean M. Gilpin. 2001. Global political economy: Understanding the
international economic order. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Goldthau, Andreas, and Benjamin K. Sovacool. 2012. The uniqueness of the energy
security, justice, and governance problem. Energy Policy 41: 232–240.
Hancock, Kathleen J., and Vlado Vivoda. 2014. International political economy: A field
born of the OPEC crisis returns to its energy roots. Energy Research & Social Science 1:
206–216.
Herborth, Benjamin. 2012. Theorising theorising: Critical realism and the quest for
certainty. Review of International Studies 38 (01): 235–251.
10 Introduction
Herbstreuth, Sebastian. 2014. Constructing dependency: The United States and the
problem of foreign oil. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 24–42.
Hughes, Llewelyn, and Phillip Y. Lipscy. 2013. The politics of energy. Annual Review of
Political Science 16 (1): 449–469.
Illich, Ivan. 1974. Energy and Equity. New York: Harper & Row.
Jansen, Jaap C., and Ad J. Seebregts. 2010. Long-term energy services security: What is it
and how can it be measured and valued? Energy Policy 38 (4): 1654–1664.
Jarosz, Lucy. 2011. Defining world hunger: Scale and neoliberal ideology in international
food security policy discourse. Food, Culture and Society: An International Journal of
Multidisciplinary Research 14 (1): 117–139.
Kalicki, Jan H., and David L. Goldwyn. 2005. Energy and security: Toward a new foreign
policy strategy. Washington, DC: Woodrow Wilson Center Press.
Keohane, Robert O. 2009. The old IPE and the new. Review of International Political
Economy 16 (1): 34–46.
Kester, Johannes. 2018. Governing electric vehicles: Mobilizing electricity to secure
automobility. Mobilities 13 (2): 200–215.
Kruyt, B., D. P. Van Vuuren, H. J. M. De Vries and H. Groenenberg. 2009. Indicators for
energy security. Energy Policy 37 (6): 2166–2181.
Kurze, Kristina. 2008. The changing discourse of energy security. Creating new momen-
tum for energy policy integration in the European Union. Conference paper presented
at ‘Energy in Europe and North America: From National to Human Security’. In
Energy in Europe and North America: From National to Human Security. Trento.
Le Billon, Philippe. 2005. The geopolitical economy of ‘Resource Wars’. In The geopoli-
tics of resource wars: Resource dependence, governance and violence, 1–28. London and
New York: Frank Cass.
Löschel, Andreas, Ulf Moslener and Dirk T. G. Rübbelke. 2010. Indicators of energy
security in industrialised countries. Energy Policy 38 (4): 1665–1671.
Lovell, Heather. 2008. Discourse and innovation journeys: The case of low energy
housing in the UK. Technology Analysis & Strategic Management 20 (5): 613–632.
Luft, Gal, and Anne Korin. 2009. Energy security challenges for the 21st century: A refer-
ence handbook. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger Security International.
Mitchell, Timothy. 2013. Carbon democracy: Political power in the age of oil. London: Verso.
Narula, Kapil, and B. Sudhakara Reddy. 2015. Three blind men and an elephant: The
case of energy indices to measure energy security and energy sustainability. Energy 80:
148–158.
Nyman, Jonna. 2014. ‘Red storm ahead’: Securitisation of energy in US–China Rela-
tions. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 43–65.
Schouten, Peer. 2014. Security as controversy: Reassembling security at Amsterdam
Airport. Security Dialogue 45 (1): 23–42.
Sheller, Mimi. 2014. Global energy cultures of speed and lightness: Materials, mobilities
and transnational power. Theory, Culture & Society 31 (5): 127–154.
Shove, Elizabeth, and Gordon Walker. 2014. What is energy for? Social practice and
energy demand. Theory, Culture & Society 31 (5): 41–58.
Smith, Marisol, Judy Pointing, and Simon Maxwell. 1992. Household food security:
Concepts and definitions – an annotated bibliography. In Household food security: Con-
cepts, indicators, and measurements. A technical review, edited by Simon Maxwell and
Timothy R. Frankenberger. Rome: Unicef/IFAD.
Smith Stegen, Karen. 2011. Deconstructing the ‘energy weapon’: Russia’s threat to
Europe as case study. Energy Policy 39 (10): 6505–6513.
Introduction 11
Sovacool, Benjamin K. 2013. Energy & ethics: Justice and the global energy challenge. Bas-
ingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Sovacool, Benjamin K. 2014. What are we doing here? Analyzing fifteen years of energy
scholarship and proposing a social science research agenda. Energy Research & Social
Science 1: 1–29.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., and Marilyn A. Brown. 2010. Competing dimensions of energy
security: An international perspective. Annual Review of Environment and Resources 35
(1): 77–108.
Stoddard, Edward. 2013. Reconsidering the ontological foundations of international
energy affairs: Realist geopolitics, market liberalism and a politico-economic altern-
ative. European Security 22 (4): 437–463.
Strange, Susan. 1994. States and Markets. 2nd edn. London: Continuum.
Teschner, Naama, and Jouni Paavola. 2013. Discourses of abundance: Transitions in
Israel’s energy regime. Journal of Environmental Policy & Planning 15 (3): 447–466.
Urry, John. 2014. The problem of energy. Theory, Culture & Society 31 (5): 3–20.
Vivoda, Vlado. 2009. Diversification of oil import sources and energy security: A key
strategy or an elusive objective? Energy Policy 37 (11): 4615–4623.
Walters, William. 2014. Drone strikes, dingpolitik and beyond: Furthering the debate on
materiality and security. Security Dialogue 45 (2): 101–118.
Winzer, Christian. 2012. Conceptualizing energy security. Energy Policy 46: 36–48.
Yergin, Daniel. 1991. The prize: The epic quest for oil, money & power. New York: Simon
and Shuster.
2 The historic proliferation of
energy security
2.1 Introduction
The crux behind debates on energy security is that the insecurity of
someone living in a European country differs from those living elsewhere in
the world, as well as from those within the same country. Different geograph-
ical, temporal and environmental circumstances dictate different energy
needs, while different market and regulatory structures dictate the options
people have to fulfil these needs. Yet, despite these differences, almost every-
body is connected through global energy systems and markets of coal, oil,
natural gas, uranium, wood pellets, corn, renewable technology, battery
storage and so on. Not a single country can run from the climate effects of
these markets nor can it be entirely independent from them. Simultaneously,
energy is closely connected to the production, trade and consumption of other
resources, while those same resources enable the production of energy, be they
water (cooling/hydro), food (biofuels) or rare earth minerals (renewable tech-
nologies).1 Furthermore, the current transformation from a traditional fossil
fuel system into a renewable electrified energy system is changing the earth’s
topography, physical infrastructures, market structures, social habits and power
structures.
This complexity returns in debates on the concept of energy security. In
fact, Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton rightly remark that there are two things
confusing about energy security: the concept of energy and the concept of
security.2 For Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton, both of these concepts hide
many of the underlying sociopolitical and economic choices behind energy
consumption and production, as they only implicitly touch upon the actual
choice for a particular energy source or the decision who is in need of security.
These latter choices are often foregone conclusions in most policy-oriented
energy security debates whose prime focus it is to secure the resulting situation
in the first place. In relation to the energy side of energy security,3 a quick
reflection on the meaning of the word already shows that a physicist’s defini-
tion of energy differs from an economic or a political conceptualization.4 Phys-
icists understand energy as the work (joules) needed to lift something over a
fixed distance and they observe that energy cannot be created or destroyed in
Historic proliferation of energy security 13
closed systems, only transformed into other less useful types of energy.5 This
clearly contrasts with an economic understanding of energy as a commodity to
be produced, sold and wasted, let alone with a political understanding of
energy as a strategic resource that needs to be acquired and controlled. In this
respect, Jansen and Van der Welle remark how it is not energy itself that is in
need of securing, but useful energy: the energy that fits current sociotechnical
energy systems.6
Then again, ever more energy sources are useful or made to be useful. Hence,
the concept of energy security has evolved along the cyclical whims of the
expanding energy markets, in particularly the global oil market. Over the years,
the concept ‘has quietly slipped into the energy lexicon and assumed a relatively
prominent position’ as evident by a range of definitions (see Table 2.1).7 The
International Energy Agency (IEA) provides one of the most accepted and basic
definitions of energy security and defines energy security as ‘adequate, affordable
and reliable supplies of energy’.8 Implicit in this definition is the sense that an
agent is energy-insecure when the supplies of energy are not adequate, affordable
or reliable. However, who defines what is adequate, affordable or reliable? What
kind of energy is needed? Who needs to make sure that energy is secure? It
seems that the simplicity of the concept quickly breaks down under questioning.
An alternative definition is provided by Ciută, who describes energy insecurity
as ‘the product of the contradiction between a general trend of increasing energy
consumption and a contradictory trend of decreasing energy reserves’.9 Easily
grasped in its simplicity and a core logic behind many of the geopolitics-oriented
considerations on energy security, such neo-Malthusian thinking is not self-
evident and neither is this definition (see Chapter 4).10 In other words, these
definitions break down under scrutiny. So, instead of discussing these and the
other definitions in Table 2.1 (to which we will return later on in this chapter),
the rest of this chapter provides a history of the evolution of energy security and
highlight its expansion by identifying five themes that have become inherent to
energy security.
Looking back, most of the literature that studies energy security retraces its
origin to the 1970s oil crises, not only for its political and economic import-
ance but also because the actual concept of energy security originates from
around that period. Of course, this does not mean that the concerns captured
by the concept of energy security did not exist before the 1970s. For instance,
security of supply concerns have a long history, arguably from the moment that
people became dependent on others for their tools (in the Bronze Age).11
However, the political meaning of the concept of energy, as denoting a combi-
nation of coal, oil, gas and electricity industries and supply chains, only
emerged in the early second half of the twentieth century.12 Before this polit-
ical understanding of energy, the discussions focused simply on the resource in
question. There was a coal problem or an electricity problem, never an energy
problem. The difference becomes clear when one compares Jevons’s 1865 argu-
ment on the importance of coal with Schumacher’s 1964 argument on the
importance of energy:
14 Historic proliferation of energy security
Coal in truth stands not beside but entirely above all other commodities. It
is the material energy of the country – the universal aid – the factor in
everything we do. With coal almost any feat is possible or easy; without it
we are thrown back into the laborious poverty of early times.13
In comparing these two quotes, three things become apparent. First, the current
understanding of energy (and thus energy security) is a relatively modern under-
standing that has evolved in tandem with developments in markets, society and
technology. Second, while the meanings and content might change and con-
cerns can be added to the concept of energy security, some of the primary con-
cerns, like security of supply, seem to remain stable over time. Lastly, the
importance and all-pervasiveness of energy in modern societies make any
security argument that calls for the protection of energy a self-evident argument,
for how can one not secure ‘the factor in everything we do’ or ‘the precondition
of all commodities’?
Source* Definition
Yergin 1988, 112 ‘The objective of energy security is to assure adequate, reliable
supplies of energy at reasonable prices and in ways that do not
jeopardize major national values and objectives.’
Bohi and Toman 1996, ‘Energy insecurity can be defined as the loss of economic
1–2 welfare that may occur as a result of a change in the price or
availability of energy.’
European Commission ‘[E]nergy supply security must be geared to ensuring, for the
2000, 2 well-being of its citizens and the proper functioning of the
economy, the uninterrupted physical availability of energy
products on the market, at a price which is affordable for all
consumers (private and industrial), while respecting
environmental concerns and looking towards sustainable
development.… Security of supply does not seek to maximise
energy self-sufficiency or to minimise dependence, but aims to
reduce the risks linked to such dependence.’
Bielecki 2002, 237 ‘Energy security is commonly defined as reliable and adequate
supply of energy at reasonable prices.’
Barton et al. 2004, 5 ‘as a condition in which a nation and all, or most of its citizens
and business have access to sufficient energy resources at
reasonable prices for the foreseeable future free from serious
risk of major disruption of service.’
Historic proliferation of energy security 15
Table 2.1 Continued
Source* Definition
continued
16 Historic proliferation of energy security
Table 2.1 Continued
Source* Definition
Jansen and Seebregts ‘Let us coin the certainty level of enduring, uninterrupted
2010, 1655 access of the population in a defined region to affordably and
competitively priced, environmentally acceptable energy end-
use services by the term energy services security.’
Sovacool and Divide APERC’s four As into five dimensions: Availability,
Mukherjee 2011 Affordability, Technology Development, Sustainability, and
Regulation.
Jansen and Van der ‘We propose to use the term energy services security (ESS)
Welle 2011, 241 instead of energy security as the notion that covers the central
topic of this chapter. Hereafter, ESS refers to the extent to which
the population in a defined area (country or region) can have access
to affordably and competitively priced, environmentally acceptable
energy services of adequate quality.’
von Hippel et al. 2011, A nation state is energy secure to the degree that fuel and energy
78 services are available to ensure: (1) survival of the nation, (2)
protection of national welfare and (3) minimization of risks
associated with supply and use of fuel and energy services.
Goldthau and Sovacool ‘Energy security, defined as the way of equitably providing
2012, 235 available, affordable, reliable, efficient, environmentally
benign, proactively governed, and socially acceptable energy
services to end-users, is gaining ever more prominence on
contemporary policy agendas. Energy security has supply-side
and demand-side components.’
Winzer 2012, 36 ‘we suggest narrowing down the concept of energy security to
the concept of energy supply continuity. This reduces the
overlap between the policy goals of energy security,
sustainability and economic efficiency.’
Yergin 2012, 269 ‘The usual definition of energy security is pretty
straightforward: the availability of sufficient supplies at
affordable prices. Yet there are several dimensions. The first is
physical security.… Second, access to energy is critical.…
Third, energy security is also a system.… And finally and
crucially, if longer-term in nature – is investment.’
Metcalf 2013, 2 ‘Energy security is the ability of households, business, and
government to accommodate disruptions in supply in energy
markets.’
Cherp and Jewell 2014, ‘We define energy security as low vulnerability of vital energy
415 systems.’
Source: author
Note
* For similar overviews and tables see: Sovacool 2011; Cherp and Jewell 2011; Sovacool and
Mukherjee 2011; Winzer 2012; Hughes 2012, 228–229; Boersma 2013. I’m grateful to Jaap de
Wilde for pointing out that many of these definitions do not discuss consumers explicitly but
implicitly take them as passive consumers, as a people who need to be pleased and are in need of
governance. From a critical position, this reinforces the position of the policymakers and scholars
discussing and organizing energy security in a top-down manner.
Historic proliferation of energy security 17
In reality, the public and scholarly attention to energy and energy security
concerns fluctuates. The oil crises of the 1970s spurred an increase in attention,
but declined in the late 1980s when the market dynamics changed back from
the 1970s’ producer’s market (where producers are able to dictate the market
price) to a buyers’ market (where demand sets the price). This buyers’ market
lasted until the rise in prices from 2003 onwards and culminating in the price
hike of 2008 following unrest in producing countries, increasing demand from
Asia and other developing countries, tightening refinery markets and decreasing
production in non-OPEC countries. Together these market developments
brought back energy security concerns and fears for a competition over the
remaining fossil resources (and renewable technologies).15 While the general
opinion was that this particular producer market was structural, the same price
hike of over $140 per barrel in July 2008 coincided with the beginning of the
financial crisis that plummeted economic growth and the global demand for
energy. This drop in demand, in turn, coincided with an increase in investments
in renewables and shale gas technology after the increase in oil and gas prices
between 2003 and 2008, in a situation comparable to the responses to the oil
crises in the 1970s, which spurred deep-sea non-OPEC oil and gas field explora-
tion. Together these factors have reduced fossil fuel prices and thereby many of
the energy insecurity concerns in Western energy policies. Even such a brief
overview already shows that, when analysing energy security, one constantly has
to be aware that energy has both physical (geographic, technologic, infrastruc-
tural, environmental), economic and sociopolitical aspects.
The concerns captured with the concept of energy security are wide-ranging
and proliferating. In a recent prominent analysis, Chester captures this prolifer-
ation by arguing that energy security is a ‘polysemic’ concept, by which she
refers to an understanding of energy security that differs depending its context.16
In arguing for a contextual approach to energy security, whole-heartedly sup-
ported here in this book, it is no longer possible to see the concept as a neutral
policy goal. Energy security instead is a ‘plastic phrase used by a range of
different interest groups to signify many often contradictory goals’.17 Below this
polysemic complexity will be introduced through a brief sketch of the historical
shifts in the meaning of energy security. While impressionistic and impossible
to date precisely, it is possible to identify five general shifts in this brief overview
of the evolution of the energy security literature.18 Section 2.2 discusses the shift
from a physical to a political security of supply; Section 2.3 embraces the eco-
nomics of energy security; Section 2.4 adds the concerns and complexity of
climate change and sustainability; and Sections 2.5 and 2.6 move away from a
state-centric focus, respectively downwards towards the individual and upward
to the protection of energy systems. The range and complexity of the energy
supply chain and all its perceived threats will be analysed more closely in
Chapter 3. Furthermore, note that most of the energy security definitions in this
chapter share a Western outlook and are thus partial to an energy consumer and
market focus, as they consider security of supply over the security of demand of
producers.19
18 Historic proliferation of energy security
2.2 From physical to political security of supply
The availability of and access to natural resources, like water and food, have in
some form always been a concern for individuals and governments. In the late
nineteenth century, Jevons and Lord Kelvin raised such concerns in relation to
the increasing reliance on coal for shipping, production, heat and electricity.20
However, while Jevons and Lord Kelvin discussed the future of British coal sup-
plies, oil was gradually gaining in significance with the development of the com-
bustion engine. Consequently, concerns over the availability of domestic coal
decreased while security of supply concerns over (foreign) oil increased. Church-
ill’s decision to shift the complete British navy to oil before World War I led to
one of the first debates that fits a modern understanding of energy supply
security.21 Weighing the increased speed and capacity of the Royal Navy in
favour of a dependency on foreign oil from Persia, the British navy tried to
minimize that dependency as much as possible. On the one hand, the Admiralty
decided to control as much as possible of the supply line itself, among other
things by taking ownership of a company nowadays known as British Petroleum
(Anglo-Persian), by using that same naval power to secure its own supply lines,
and by simultaneously building a domestic reserve. On the other hand, in line
with Churchill’s claim that ‘[s]afety and certainty in oil, lie in variety and
variety alone’, it promoted a global competition of oil suppliers by entering into
supply contracts with other companies and their access to oil resources else-
where in the world.22
While the modern energy security literature picked up on the diversification
argument, the main argument in Churchill’s speech is actually not one of
dependency but one of price volatility and market manipulation by a small
group of companies.23 He feared that the navy would become dependent on
volatile oil markets and, more precisely, would be overcharged for its oil needs.
In Churchill’s own words: ‘The problem is not one of quantity; it is one of price’
and if we are not careful ‘[i]t would mean, however, that we should be made to
pay an excessive price for it’.24 Still, while Churchill clearly points towards the
economics of oil markets, he does so in regards to the military and from within a
frame of national security concerns. Hence, the argument is still based on
national security of supply concerns – as is the energy security literature at this
point.
In fact, this military security of supply argument remained dominant up until
the oil crisis of 1973, even though oil became increasingly important in other
sectors of society, including mobility, industry and electricity generation.25
Heavily influenced by two World Wars and the early years of the Cold War,
energy security was mainly interpreted in terms of its military value: as a neces-
sity to win wars and thus as something in need of protection.26 During World
War II, many resources, including oil, were heavily regulated. These restrictions
only relaxed after the war with the realization that the oil flowed quite abun-
dantly and prices remained low. The Cold War, in turn, highlighted the (stra-
tegic) military vulnerability of energy infrastructure (oil refineries, pipelines,
Historic proliferation of energy security 19
electricity plants etc.) and gave birth to the field that nowadays is called critical
infrastructure protection.27
This changed with the 1973 oil shock when the Organization of the Petro-
leum Exporting Countries (OPEC) reduced its production level and extended
an export restriction towards Israel, the United States and the Netherlands.
This first use of the ‘oil weapon’ against industrial consumer countries reinforced
two insights: a strong feeling of foreign dependency and a realization of the
importance of energy for economic and social life.28 The first insight was an
acute and broadly shared feeling of dependency across publics in industrialized
countries and a longing for the 1960s’ uninterrupted flows of low-priced oil.29
The crises also brought forth the public realization that oil consumption had
long trumped coal by tripling in total volume since the end of World War II.30
Moreover, it led to the recognition that decolonization meant that many of
these oil sources no longer fell under colonial rule or under Western markets as
they were increasingly being nationalized.31 Contrary to the public, this was less
of a surprise to energy experts, who had been noting the incidents leading up to
1973. These include the European security of supply concerns raised in relation
to the Suez Crisis in 1956, the nationalization of Western-owned extraction and
transport facilities in former colonies, and the American debate in the 1950s in
which domestic oil producers called for and received import quotas against
cheap foreign Middle Eastern oil (lasting from 1959 until 1973).32
Still, the 1973 oil crisis and its 1979 sibling following the Iranian Revolution
shook the world. In response, the industrial countries initiated a number of
practical measures to support their continuing oil consumption. This includes
the installation of the IEA in 1974 (planned by Kissinger in 1969) and the
support from Western governments for the development of new non-OPEC-
controlled oil and gas fields, new technological development as well as the shift
to alternative energy sources (nuclear).33 It also initiated a spur in energy
security research.34 For Yergin, who later became known for his book The Prize
on the evolution of the oil industry, the 1970s’ oil shocks and the following
energy policies of consumer countries showed that ‘[t]he focus of energy security
concerns is on the shocks – interruptions, disruptions and manipulations of
supply – that can lead to sudden, sharp increases in prices and can impose heavy
economic and political costs’.35 Up to this day, politically engineered supply dis-
ruptions remain at the core of energy security concerns.
Of the world’s six billion people, one-third enjoy the kind of energy on
demand that Americans take for granted … and another third have such
energy services intermittently. The final third – two billion people – simply
lack access to modern energy systems.73
From this perspective, energy security or general security practices are not some-
thing to be achieved but an ‘administrative logic’ (Chapter 6) that is part of the
self-reinforcing nature of the current neo-liberal energy regime.97 In other words,
this energy regime literature argues that any understanding of energy security
would not be complete without a critical reflection on what energy security does
in terms of possible consequences and effects, besides questioning the essence of
what energy security is.
Energy supply security must be geared to ensuring, for the well-being of its
citizens and the proper functioning of the economy, the uninterrupted
physical availability of energy products on the market, at a price which is
affordable for all consumers (private and industrial), while respecting
environmental concerns and looking towards sustainable development.…
Security of supply does not seek to maximise energy self-sufficiency or
to minimise dependence, but aims to reduce the risks linked to such
dependence.100
Notes
1 Andrews-Speed et al. 2012; Beisheim 2013; Beddington 2009.
2 Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton 2012, 6. For a similar argument, see: Bridge 2015.
3 Chapter 4 will discuss the intricacies of the security side of energy security.
4 Stern and Aronson 1984, 14–21. In their work, Stern and Aronson identify four
perspectives besides a physicist understanding of energy. These include energy as a
commodity (economics), as an ecological resource, as a social necessity and as a
strategic material. See also Illich 2009, 13.
5 In turn, power denotes the work done per unit of time (joules per second = watt).
In terms of the discussion on materiality in Chapter 5, energy is an interesting phe-
nomenon as it escapes clear categorization and is neither matter nor force nor social
construction, but all of them together.
6 Jansen and Van der Welle 2011, 240. For politicians and those working from a
security perspective, the referent object of energy itself (that which needs securing)
is never the issue; it can be anything. See also Chapter 4.
Historic proliferation of energy security 31
7 Chester 2010, 887.
8 IEA 2010a, 559. More generally, the IEA defines energy security as ‘the uninter-
rupted availability of energy sources at an affordable price’ – see IEA 2015.
9 Ciută 2010, 126.
10 Hirsch 1976; Xenos 1989; Achterhuis 1988; Mehta 2010.
11 Buijs, Sievers and Tercero Espinoza 2012, 201.
12 Patterson 2008, 2; Illich 2009.
13 Jevons 1866, chap. I-Introduction and Outline. See also Yergin 1991, 543.
14 Schumacher and Kirk 1977, 1–2. See also Yergin 1991, 559.
15 Hoogeveen and Perlot 2005; Yergin 2006; Mallaby 2006; Klare 2008.
16 Chester 2010.
17 Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton 2012, 5. For similar arguments see: Winzer 2012,
36; Labban 2011, 327.
18 Interestingly, the positions themselves were already identified by Stern and Aronson
1984. Yet, when analysing the energy security literature many of these positions
have only been incorporated at later stages. Also, the five themes are here inter-
preted inclusionary, as only together they make up the definition of energy security
(in line with the multiplicity behind a politics of ontology – see Chapter 5).
19 Chester 2010, 891.
20 Jevons 1866; Yergin 2012, 3.
21 Yergin 1991, 153–164.
22 Ibid., 160; Parliamentary Debates, Commons 1913, 1477.
23 Parliamentary Debates, Commons 1913, 1473.
24 Ibid., 1473, 1474.
25 Mitchell 2000.
26 Ibid.; Cherp and Jewell 2011.
27 Collier and Lakoff 2008b.
28 Cherp and Jewell 2011. Stern 2006, 1650, argues that the ‘oil weapon’ was first
termed by the League of Nations debating possible sanctions against Italy in 1935,
and first applied by the United States when it sanctioned Japan over its occupation
of China in 1941 (80 per cent of Japanese imports).
29 Mitchell 2000.
30 Yergin 1991.
31 Cherp and Jewell 2011.
32 Stern 2006; Yergin 1991, 535–540.
33 On Kissinger see: Labban 2011.
34 See for example: Akins 1973; Bradley 1973; Levy 1973; Pollack 1973; Gordon 1974;
Kemp 1978; Stobaugh and Yergin 1978; Deese 1979; Lieber 1980.
35 Yergin 1988, 112, 1991.
36 Nye 1981, 12–13. For an earlier take on dependency see: Lubell 1961. For a more
recent discussion see: Verrastro and Ladislaw 2007; Greene 2010.
37 Bohi and Toman 1996, 3.
38 Ibid., 1–2.
39 IEA 2007, 12.
40 Bohi and Toman 1996, 3; Cherp and Jewell 2011.
41 See Mitchell 2013 for an alternative interpretation of these strikes.
42 IEA 2007, 12 and 32.
43 Bohi and Toman 1996, 4.
44 Labban 2011, 331.
45 WEC 2008.
46 Bohi and Toman 1996. They also conclude that except for the trade balance, which
depend on the country in question, none of the indirect price effects have been
proven.
47 Metcalf 2013. See also Mulder, ten Cate and Zwart 2007 on strategic reserves.
32 Historic proliferation of energy security
48 IEA 2007, 33–34.
49 Labban 2011.
50 European Commission 2015, 6; Beckman 2015.
51 Labban 2011, 335.
52 Mitchell 2000.
53 Mitchell 2002, 6; Bielecki 2002, 236.
54 Yergin 1988, 114. To be fair, in the same article his main conclusion was based on
the importance of energy efficiency, which he claimed had ‘turned out to be the
most important incremental energy “source” of all’ during the 1970s and 1980s; see
ibid., 114–115.
55 Chester 2010, 889; Bielecki 2002, 247–248.
56 Brundtland 1987; Meadows et al. 1972; Ehrlich 1970; Carson 1981; Dalby 2006,
2014. For an historical overview, see: Mulligan 2010.
57 See: Homer-Dixon 1991, 1994.
58 Mulligan 2010; La Branche 2013, 403–404.
59 Wright 2005, 2273; Luft, Korin and Gupta 2011.
60 Pagnamenta 2009.
61 Brown and Dworking 2011.
62 Carbon Tracker Initiative 2011.
63 Kester 2016.
64 Kester 2018.
65 Brown and Huntington 2008; Luft, Korin and Gupta 2011, 48–51.
66 Mitchell 2000.
67 Mallaby 2006.
68 Luft, Korin and Gupta 2011.
69 Ibid., 46.
70 Ibid., 47.
71 La Branche 2013, 412.
72 UNDP 1994.
73 Wirth, Boyden Gray and Podesta 2003, 138.
74 Bhattacharyya 2013, 424.
75 Bhattacharyya 2013; IEA 2010b; Kaygusuz 2011; Prasad 2011; Sokona, Mulugetta
and Gujba 2012; Okereke and Yusuf 2013.
76 Moore 2012; Hills 2012; Middlemiss and Gillard 2015.
77 Pachauri 2011b; Goldthau and Sovacool 2012; Sovacool 2013; Sovacool, Sidortsov
and Jones 2014; Heffron and McCauley 2014. For an early discussion, see:
Illich 1974.
78 Sovacool 2013, 12.
79 Heffron and McCauley 2014.
80 Sovacool, Sidortsov and Jones 2014, 197.
81 Pachauri 2011a, 191.
82 Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton 2012, 8, quoting Lovins 1990, 21.
83 Patterson 2008, 2010; Jansen 2009; Jansen and Seebregts 2010.
84 Patterson 2008. Ambient energy refers to the energy already available: sunlight,
body heat, the shadow of trees and so forth.
85 See also: Winzer 2012, 37.
86 For an analysis on the origins of CIP see Collier and Lakoff 2008b, 2008a, 2015;
Lakoff and Collier 2010. For one of the earliest systematic reflections, see Lovins
and Lovins 1982. Collier and Lakoff have described its genealogy by analysing
the correlation between the ‘invention’ of scenario studies and the protection of
large-scale infrastructure systems following World War II. What they show is
how the growing material development of vast and connected infrastructures – of
energy, communication and mobility – together with a deeper scientific under-
standing of biological and chemical flow processes has led to a governing of complex
Historic proliferation of energy security 33
interconnected infrastructure systems. A governing of systems, which in turn has
been heavily influenced by scenario techniques, which led to an understanding of
inherent vulnerability that nowadays supports all approaches to infrastructure
systems. For an interesting reflection, see Coward 2009.
87 Cherp and Jewell 2014.
88 Farrell, Zerriffi and Dowlatabadi 2004.
89 Labban 2011.
90 Ibid., 338.
91 Mayer and Acuto 2015, 678; Voelkner 2011, 2012. In this respect, Graham and
Thrift discuss the mundane activities of maintenance and repair of the electricity
grid, and in particular how, while often overlooked in political debates, the organ-
ization of these activities is a highly political affair that influences the future direc-
tion of the grid, and consequently our electricity consumption. See Graham and
Thrift 2007; see also Bennett 2005.
92 Farrell, Zerriffi and Dowlatabadi 2004, 440.
93 Byrne and Toly 2006; Hornborg 2013; Illich 1974, 2009; Nye 2014; Huber 2009,
2011a, 2011b; Labban 2010.
94 Byrne and Toly 2006.
95 Ibid., 15–16.
96 Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton 2012, 19–20.
97 Bridge 2015, 3.
98 Ciută 2010, 124.
99 IEA 2015; Cherp and Jewell 2014, 417.
100 European Commission 2000, 2.
101 Barton et al. 2004, 5.
102 Winzer 2012; Chester 2010.
103 Cherp and Jewell 2014.
104 Ibid., 416.
105 Ciută 2010, esp. 138.
106 Ciută 2010.
107 Von Hippel et al. 2011; Valentine 2011.
108 Hildyard, Lohmann and Sexton 2012.
109 Bridge 2015, 1.
Bibliography
Achterhuis, Hans. 1988. Het Rijk van de Schaarste: van Thomas Hobbes tot Michel Foucault.
Baarn: Ambo.
Akins, James E. 1973. The oil crisis: This time the wolf is here. Foreign Affairs 51 (3):
462–490.
Andrews-Speed, P., R. Bleischwitz, Tim Boersma, Corey Johnson, Geoffrey Kemp and
Stacy D. VanDeveer. 2012. The global resource nexus: The struggles for land, energy,
food, water, and minerals. Washington, DC: Transatlantic Academy.
APERC. 2007. A quest for energy security in the 21st century: Resources and constraints.
Tokyo: Asia Pacific Energy Research Centre.
Barton, Barry, Catherine Redgwell, Anita Ronne and Donald N. Zillman. 2004. Intro-
duction. In Energy security: Managing risk in a dynamic legal and regulatory environment,
edited by Barry Barton, Catherine Redgwell, Anita Ronne and Donald N. Zillman,
3–16. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.
Beckman, Karel. 2015. The plan behind the EU Energy Union. EnergyPost.eu. Available
from www.energypost.eu/energy-union-now-never-european-energy-policy. Accessed
9 June 2015.
34 Historic proliferation of energy security
Beddington, John. 2009. Food, energy, water and the climate: A perfect storm of global
events. London: Government Office for Science.
Beisheim, Marianne. 2013. The water, energy & food security nexus: How to govern complex
risks to sustainable supply? SWP Comments. Berlin: Stifting Wissenschaft und Politik.
Bennett, Jane. 2005. The agency of assemblages and the North American blackout.
Public Culture 17 (3): 445–65.
Bhattacharyya, Subhes C. 2013. Energy poverty: Access, health and welfare. In Inter-
national handbook of energy security, edited by Hugh Dyer and Maria Julia Trombetta,
423–442. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Bielecki, Janusz. 2002. Energy security: Is the wolf at the door? The Quarterly Review of
Economics and Finance 42 (2): 235–250.
Boersma, Tim. 2013. Dealing with energy security in Europe: A comparison of gas market pol-
icies in the European Union and the United States. PhD thesis, Groningen: University of
Groningen.
Bohi, Douglas R., and Michael A. Toman. 1996. The economics of energy security.
Norwell, MA: Kluwer.
Bradley, Paul G. 1973. Increasing scarcity: The case of energy resources. The American
Economic Review 63 (2): 119–125.
Bridge, Gavin. 2015. Energy (in)security: World-making in an age of scarcity. The Geo-
graphical Journal 181 (4): 328–339.
Brown, Marilyn A., and Michael Dworking. 2011. The environmental dimension of
energy security. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K.
Sovacool, 176–190. London and New York: Routledge.
Brown, Stephen P. A., and Hillard G. Huntington. 2008. Energy security and climate
change protection: Complementarity or trade-off? Energy Policy 36 (9): 3510–3513.
Brundtland, Gro Harlem. 1987. Our common future: Report of the World Commission on
Environment and Development. United Nations.
Buijs, Bram, Henrike Sievers and Luis A. Tercero Espinoza. 2012. Limits to the critical
raw materials approach. Waste and Resource Management 165 (WR4): 201–208.
Byrne, John, and Noah Toly. 2006. Energy as a social project: Recovering a discourse.
In Transforming power: Energy, environment and society in conflict, edited by John
Byrne, Noah Toly and Leigh Glover, 1–32. New Brunswick, NJ, and London: Trans-
action.
Carbon Tracker Initiative. 2011. Unburnable carbon: Are the world’s financial markets
carrying a carbon bubble? Available from www.carbontracker.org/wp-content/uploads/
2014/09/Unburnable-Carbon-Full-rev2-1.pdf.
Carson, Rachel. 1981. Silent spring. Greenwich, CT: Fawcett.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2011. The three perspectives on energy security: Intel-
lectual history, disciplinary roots and the potential for integration. Current Opinion in
Environmental Sustainability 3 (4): 202–212.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2014. The concept of energy security: Beyond the four
As. Energy Policy 75: 415–421.
Chester, Lynne. 2010. Conceptualising energy security and making explicit its polysemic
nature. Energy Policy 38 (2): 887–895.
Ciută, Felix. 2010. Conceptual notes on energy security: Total or banal security? Security
Dialogue 41 (2): 123–144.
Collier, Stephen J., and Andrew Lakoff. 2008a. Distributed preparedness: The spatial
logic of domestic security in the United States. Environment and Planning D: Society
and Space 26 (1): 7–28.
Historic proliferation of energy security 35
Collier, Stephen J., and Andrew Lakoff. 2008b. The vulnerability of vital systems: How
‘critical infrastructure’ became a security problem. In The politics of securing the home-
land: Critical infrastructure, risk and securitisation, edited by Myriam Dunn Cavelty,
40–62. London and New York: Routledge.
Collier, Stephen J., and Andrew Lakoff. 2015. Vital systems security: Reflexive biopoli-
tics and the government of emergency. Theory, Culture & Society 32 (2): 19–51.
Coward, Martin. 2009. Network-centric violence, Critical infrastructure and the urbani-
zation of security. Security Dialogue 40 (4–5): 399–418.
Dalby, Simon. 2006. Ecology, security, and change in the Anthropocene. Brown Journal
of World Affairs 13: 155.
Dalby, Simon. 2014. Rethinking geopolitics: Climate security in the Anthropocene.
Global Policy 5 (1): 1–9.
Deese, D. A. 1979. Energy: Economics, politics, and security. International Security 4 (3):
140–153.
Ehrlich, Paul R. 1970. The population bomb. 13th print edition. New York: Sierra Club/
Ballantine.
European Commission. 2000. Green Paper: Towards a European strategy for the security of
energy supply. COM(2000) 769 final. Brussels: European Commission.
European Commission. 2015. Energy union package: A framework Strategy for a resilient
energy union with a forward-looking climate change policy. COM(2015) 80 final. Brussels:
European Commission.
Farrell, Alexander E., Hisham Zerriffi and Hadi Dowlatabadi. 2004. Energy infrastructure
and security. Annual Review of Environment and Resources 29 (1): 421–469.
Goldthau, Andreas, and Benjamin K. Sovacool. 2012. The uniqueness of the energy
security, justice, and governance problem. Energy Policy 41: 232–240.
Gordon, Richard L. 1974. Mythology and reality in energy policy. Energy Policy 2 (3):
189–203.
Graham, Stephen, and Nigel Thrift. 2007. Out of order: Understanding repair and main-
tenance. Theory, Culture & Society 24 (3): 1–25.
Greene, D. L. 2010. Measuring energy security: Can the United States achieve oil inde-
pendence? Energy Policy 38 (4): 1614–1621.
Heffron, Raphael J., and Darren McCauley. 2014. Achieving sustainable supply chains
through energy justice. Applied Energy 123: 435–437.
Hildyard, Nicholas, Larry Lohmann, and Sarah Sexton. 2012. Energy security: For whom?
For what? London: Corner House.
Hills, John. 2012. Getting the measure of fuel poverty: Final report of the fuel poverty review.
CASE report. Fuel Poverty Review. London: Centre for Analysis of Social Exclu-
sion, LSE.
Von Hippel, David F., Tatsujiro Suzuki, James H. Williams, Timothy Savage and Peter
Hayes. 2011. Evaluating the energy security impacts of energy policies. In The
Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool, 74–95. London
and New York: Routledge.
Hirsch, Fred. 1976. Social limits to growth. Cambridge, MA: Twentieth Century Fund.
Homer-Dixon, Thomas F. 1991. On the threshold: Environmental changes as causes of
acute conflict. International Security 16 (2): 76–116.
Homer-Dixon, Thomas F. 1994. Environmental scarcities and violent conflict: Evidence
from cases. International Security 19 (1): 5–40.
Hoogeveen, Femke, and Wilbur Perlot. 2005. Tomorrow’s mores: The international system,
geopolitical changes and energy. The Hague: Clingendael International Energy Programme.
36 Historic proliferation of energy security
Hornborg, Alf. 2013. The fossil interlude: Euro-American power and the return of the
physiocrats. In Cultures of energy: Power, practices, technologies, edited by Sarah Strauss,
Stephanie Rupp and Thomas Love, 41–59. Walnut Creek, CA: Left Coast Press.
Huber, Matthew T. 2009. Energizing historical materialism: Fossil fuels, space and the
capitalist mode of production. Geoforum 40 (1): 105–115.
Huber, Matthew T. 2011a. Enforcing scarcity: Oil, violence, and the making of the
market. Annals of the Association of American Geographers 101 (4): 816–826.
Huber, Matthew T. 2011b. Oil, life, and the fetishism of geopolitics. Capitalism Nature
Socialism 22 (3): 32–48.
Hughes, L. 2009. The four ‘R’s of energy security. Energy Policy 37 (6): 2459–2461.
Hughes, Larry. 2012. A generic framework for the description and analysis of energy
security in an energy system. Energy Policy 42: 221–231.
IEA. 2007. Energy security and climate policy: assessing interactions. Paris: OECD/Inter-
national Energy Agency.
IEA. 2010a. World Energy Outlook 2010. World Energy Outlook. OECD/International
Energy Agency.
IEA. 2010b. Energy poverty: How to make modern energy access universal? Paris: OECD/
International Energy Agency.
IEA. 2015. What is energy security? Available from www.iea.org/topics/energysecurity/
subtopics/whatisenergysecurity. Accessed 3 June 2015.
Illich, Ivan. 1974. Energy and equity. New York: Harper & Row.
Illich, Ivan. 2009. The social construction of energy. In New geographies 2: Landscapes of
energy, edited by Rania Ghosn, 11–22. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jansen, Jaap C. 2009. Energy services security: Concepts and metrics. Expert paper submit-
ted as input to the ongoing IAEA project: ‘Selecting and Defining Integrated Indi-
cators for Nuclear Energy’. Petten: ECN.
Jansen, Jaap C., and Ad J. Seebregts. 2010. Long-term energy services security: What is it
and how can it be measured and valued? Energy Policy 38 (4): 1654–1664.
Jansen, Jaap C., and Adriaan J. Van der Welle. 2011. The energy services dimension of
energy security. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K.
Sovacool, 239–249. London and New York: Routledge.
Jevons, William Stanley. 1866. The coal question: An inquiry concerning the progress of the
nation, and the probable exhaustion of our coal mines. 2nd edn. London: Macmillan.
Kaygusuz, K. 2011. Energy services and energy poverty for sustainable rural development.
Renewable and Sustainable Energy Reviews 15 (2): 936–947.
Kemp, Geoffrey. 1978. Scarcity and strategy. Foreign Affairs 56 (2): 396.
Kester, Johannes. 2016. Conducting a smarter grid: Reflecting on the power and security
behind smart grids with Foucault. In Smart grids from a global perspective, 197–213.
Cham: Springer.
Kester, Johannes. 2018. Governing electric vehicles: Mobilizing electricity to secure
automobility. Mobilities 13 (2): 200–215.
Klare, Michael T. 2008. Rising powers, shrinking planet: The new geopolitics of energy. New
York: Henry Holt.
Kleber, Drezel. 2009. The US Department of Defense: Valuing energy security. Journal of
Energy Security.
La Branche, Stephane. 2013. Paradoxes and harmony in the energy-climate governance
nexus. In International handbook of energy security, edited by Hugh Dyer and Maria Julia
Trombetta, 402–422. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Historic proliferation of energy security 37
Labban, Mazen. 2010. Oil in parallax: Scarcity, markets, and the financialization of accu-
mulation. Geoforum 41 (4): 541–552.
Labban, Mazen. 2011. The geopolitics of energy security and the war on terror: The case
for market expansion and the militarization of global space. In Global political ecology,
edited by Richard Peet, Paul Robbins and Michael J. Watts, 325–344. London:
Routledge.
Lakoff, Andrew, and Stephen J. Collier. 2010. Infrastructure and event: The political
technology of preparedness. In Political matter: Technoscience, democracy, and public life,
edited by Bruce Braun and Sarah J. Whatmore, 243–266. Minneapolis, MN: Univer-
sity of Minnesota Press.
Levy, W. J. 1973. World oil cooperation or international chaos. Foreign Affairs 52: 690.
Lieber, Robert J. 1980. Energy, economics and security in alliance perspective. Inter-
national Security 4 (4): 139–163.
Lovins, Amory B. 1990. The negawatt revolution. Across the Board 27 (9): 18–23.
Lovins, Amory B., and L. Hunter Lovins. 1982. Brittle power. Androver, MA: Brick
House.
Lubell, Harold. 1961. Security of supply and energy policy in Western Europe. World
Politics 13 (3): 400–422.
Luft, Gal, Anne Korin, and Eshita Gupta. 2011. Energy security and climate change: A
tenuous link. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sova-
cool, 43–55. London and New York: Routledge.
Mallaby, Sebastian. 2006. What ‘energy security’ really means. Washington Post, 3
July, A21.
Mayer, Maximilian, and Michele Acuto. 2015. The global governance of large technical
systems. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (2): 660–683.
Meadows, Donella H., Dennis Meadows, Jorgen Randers and William W. Behrens. 1972.
The Limits to growth: A report for the Club of Rome’s project on the predicament of
mankind. New York: Universe.
Mehta, Lyla, ed. 2010. The limits to scarcity: Contesting the politics of allocation. Washing-
ton, DC: Earthscan.
Metcalf, Gilbert E. 2013. The economics of energy security. Working Paper. Cambridge,
MA: National Bureau of Economic Research.
Middlemiss, Lucie, and Ross Gillard. 2015. Fuel poverty from the bottom-up: Character-
ising household energy vulnerability through the lived experience of the fuel poor.
Energy Research & Social Science 6: 146–154.
Mitchell, John V. 2000. Energy supply security: Changes in concepts. Royal Institute of
International Affairs, Energy and Environment Programme. London: RIIA.
Mitchell, John V. 2002. Renewing energy security. Report. London: Chatham House:
Royal Institute of International Affairs.
Mitchell, Timothy. 2013. Carbon democracy: Political power in the age of oil. London:
Verso.
Moore, R. 2012. Definitions of fuel poverty: Implications for policy. Energy Policy 49:
19–26.
Mulder, Machiel, Arie ten Cate and Gijsbert Zwart. 2007. The economics of promoting
security of energy supply. EIB Papers 12 (2): 38–61.
Mulligan, Shane. 2010. Energy, environment, and security: Critical links in a post-peak
world. Global Environmental Politics 10 (4): 79–100.
Nye, David E. 2014. The United States and alternative energies since 1980: Technolo-
gical fix or regime change? Theory, Culture & Society 31 (5): 103–125.
38 Historic proliferation of energy security
Nye, Joseph S. 1981. Energy and Security. In Report of Harvard’s energy and security
research project, edited by D. A. Deese and Joseph S. Nye. Cambridge, MA: Ballinger.
Okereke, Chukwumerije, and Tariya Yusuf. 2013. Low carbon development and energy
security in Africa. In International handbook of energy security, edited by Hugh Dyer and
Maria Julia Trombetta, 462–482. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Pachauri, Shonali. 2011a. The energy poverty dimension of energy security. In The
Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool, 191–204.
London and New York: Routledge.
Pachauri, Shonali. 2011b. Reaching an international consensus on defining modern
energy access. Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability 3 (4). Energy Systems:
235–240.
Pagnamenta, R. 2009. France imports UK electricity as plants shut down. The Times, 3
July. Available from http://business.timesonline.co.uk/tol/business/industry_sectors/
utilities/article6626811.ece. Accessed 26 July 2010.
Parliamentary Debates, Commons. 1913. Navy estimates 1913–1914: Shipbuilding,
repairs, maintenance, Etc. Hansard: 1474–1477.
Patterson, W. 2008. Managing energy wrong. Energy, Environment and Resource Govern-
ance Working Paper. Managing Energy: for Climate and Security. London: Chatham
House.
Patterson, Walt. 2010. Managing energy: Rethinking the fundamentals. Energy, Environ-
ment and Resource Governance Working Paper. London: Chatham House.
Pollack, G. A. 1973. Economic consequences of the energy crisis. Foreign Affairs 52: 452.
Prasad, Gisela. 2011. Improving access to energy in sub-Saharan Africa. Current Opinion
in Environmental Sustainability 3 (4): 248–253.
Schumacher, E. F., and G. Kirk. 1977. Schumacher on Energy. In Speeches and Writings
of E. F. Schumacher, edited by G. Kirk. London: Cape.
Sokona, Youba, Yacob Mulugetta and Haruna Gujba. 2012. Widening energy access in
Africa: Towards energy transition. Energy Policy 47: 3–10.
Sovacool, Benjamin K. 2011. Introduction: Defining, measuring, and exploring energy
security. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool,
1–42. London and New York: Routledge.
Sovacool, Benjamin K. 2013. Energy & ethics: Justice and the global energy challenge. Bas-
ingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., and Marilyn A. Brown. 2010. Competing dimensions of energy
security: An international perspective. Annual Review of Environment and Resources 35
(1): 77–108.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., and I. Mukherjee. 2011. Conceptualizing and measuring energy
security: A synthesized approach. Energy 36 (8): 5343–5355.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., Roman V. Sidortsov and Benjamin R. Jones. 2014. Energy
security, equality and justice. Abingdon: Routledge.
Stern, Paul C., and Elliot Aronson, eds. 1984. Energy use: The human dimension. New
York: W. H. Freeman.
Stern, Roger. 2006. Oil market power and United States national security. Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences 103 (5): 1650–1655.
Stobaugh, Robert, and Daniel Yergin. 1978. After the second shock: Pragmatic energy
strategies. Foreign Affairs 57: 836.
UNDP. 1994. Human development report 1994. New York and Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Historic proliferation of energy security 39
Valentine, Scott Victor. 2011. The fuzzy nature of energy security. In The Routledge hand-
book of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool, 56–73. London and New York:
Routledge.
Verrastro, F., and S. Ladislaw. 2007. Providing energy security in an interdependent
world. Washington Quarterly 30 (4): 95–104.
Voelkner, Nadine. 2011. Managing pathogenic circulation human security and the
migrant health assemblage in Thailand. Security Dialogue 42 (3): 239–259.
Voelkner, Nadine. 2012. Human security assemblages in global politics: The materiality and
instability of biopolitical governmentality in Thailand and Vietnam. PhD thesis, Brighton:
University of Sussex.
WEC. 2008. Europe’s vulnerability to energy crises. London: World Energy Council.
Winzer, Christian. 2012. Conceptualizing energy security. Energy Policy 46: 36–48.
Wirth, Timothy E., C. Boyden Gray, and John D. Podesta. 2003. The future of energy
policy. Foreign Affairs 82 (4): 132–155.
Wright, Philip. 2005. Liberalisation and the security of gas supply in the UK. Energy
Policy 33 (17): 2272–2290.
Xenos, Nicholas. 1989. Scarcity & modernity. London and New York: Routledge.
Yergin, Daniel. 1988. Energy security in the 1990s. Foreign Affairs 67 (1): 110–132.
Yergin, Daniel. 1991. The prize: The epic quest for oil, money & power. New York: Simon
and Shuster.
Yergin, Daniel. 2006. Ensuring energy security. Foreign Affairs 85 (2): 69–82.
Yergin, Daniel. 2012. The quest: Energy, security, and the remaking of the modern world.
New York, NY: Penguin.
3 Analysing energy security
3.1 Introduction
The multiplicity of energy security, its ‘slipperiness’ or ‘multidimensional’ char-
acter, is well acknowledged within studies on the concept of energy security.1
With energy as one of the core pillars of modern societies, energy (in)security
arguably is everywhere, crossing a wide range of energy sources, actors and posi-
tions within the energy supply chains.2 However, work by both Jarosz and
Maxwell on food security shows that this proliferation is not unique to energy
security, which confirms the argument in Chapter 2 that the security logic itself
could be driving the proliferation instead of an expansion of the referent objects
of energy. This is not how the energy security literature sees it.3 Cherp and
Jewell, for example, argue that the proliferation of energy security results from
the inherent complexity of the supply of energy, the uncertainties within such a
complex energy system, and the conflicting positions that actors have within
this system.4 Another recent overview attributes this proliferation to the differ-
ence in ‘academic disciplines … historical contexts … levels of development …
timeframes … market dimensions … value chain … levels of analysis … and
the primary or transformed fuel in question’,5 in other words all aspects and
positions of the energy supply chain as well as its broader economic and histor-
ical context, including the different disciplinary reflections on the issue of
energy. This chapter turns to this last aspect and discusses how the energy
security literature tries to grasp the proliferation and complexity of energy in
order to secure it.
There are multiple ways to come to grips with the multiplicity of energy
security. Three are worth highlighting and are analysed in this chapter. First,
Section 3.2 discusses how both qualitative and quantitative approaches analyse
this multiplicity by categorizing and systematizing the wide range of energy
security threats. In turn, Section 3.3 looks at the theories that are used to
handle the complexity. For energy security, there are three main theoretical
lenses: a geopolitical, a neo-liberal and a historic-materialist analysis.6 Third,
Section 3.4 studies the work of several scholars who look more closely how
energy security works and try to identify the driving logics behind energy
security. Lastly, Section 3.5 builds up to a performative interpretation of energy
Analysing energy security 41
security and the chapters. Importantly, this chapter does not discuss the emerg-
ing use of securitization theory in energy security, but only because this liter-
ature is extensively discussed in Section 4.4.7 For now, this chapter
problematizes the mainstream energy security literature, because, without a
reflective understanding of how the search for definitions actually shapes human
relationships and human relations with nature, the literature misses a core
understanding that could move the field out of its current impasse of the con-
stant struggle to tackle the proliferation of energy security and come to a fuller
understanding of the practice that is energy security.
YƵĂůŝƚLJŽĨZĞƐŽƵƌĐĞƐ
;ĐŽŶƚĞŶƚ͕ƉƵƌŝƚLJ͕ŶƵƚƌŝĐŝĞŶĐLJ͕
ŝŶƚĞƌŵŝƩĞŶĐLJͿ
ǀĂŝůĂďŝůŝƚLJ
;ŐĞŽůŽŐLJͬĞŶŐŝŶĞĞƌŝŶŐͿ
'ůŽďĂů^ƵƉƉůLJŚĂŝŶƐ
;^ŝŶŬƐ͕>ŽƐƐĞƐͬ^ƉŝůůƐͿ
dĞĐŚŶŽůŽŐŝĐĂůĞǀĞůŽƉŵĞŶƚ
ĞƉĞŶĚĞŶĐLJŽŶWƌŽĚƵĐĞƌƐ͕
ŽŶƐƵŵĞƌƐΘDƵůƟŶĂƟŽŶĂůƐ
;sƵůŶĞƌĂďŝůŝƚLJƚŽWŽůŝƟĐĂůΘDĂƌŬĞƚ
WƌĞƐƐƵƌĞͿ
/ŶĐƌĞĂƐĞŝŶ;'ůŽďĂůͿĞŵĂŶĚ͖
ŽŵƉĞƟƟŽŶĨŽƌZĞƐŽƵƌĐĞƐ
ĐĐĞƐƐΘ^ƵƉƉůLJ /ŶĨƌĂƐƚƌƵĐƚƵƌĞ
;dĞƌƌŽƌŝƐŵ͕ůŽĐŬĂĚĞƐŽĨ^ƵƉƉůLJ
;ƉŽůŝƟĐƐͬƐŽĐŝĞƚLJͿ ZŽƵƚĞƐͿ
dŚƌĞĂƚƐƚŽͬĨƌŽŵƌĞƐŽƵƌĐĞƵƐĞ
ŽŵĞƐƟĐ^ĞĐƵƌŝƚLJͲDĂƌŐŝŶ
;ĞŵĞƌŐĞŶĐLJƐƚŽĐŬƐĂŶĚƐƚŽƌĂŐĞ͕ďĂĐŬͲ
ƵƉĐĂƉĂĐŝƚLJ͕ƌĞƐŝůŝĞŶĐĞ;ŽǀĞƌͲ
ĐĂƉĂĐŝƚLJͿͿ
ŽŵĞƐƟĐĐƟǀŝƐŵ
;WƌŽƚĞƐƚͬůŽĐŬĂĚĞƐ͕WƵďůŝĐ
KƉŝŶŝŽŶͬ>ŽƐƐŽĨĞŵĂŶĚͿ
dŚƌĞĂƚƐƚŽƚŚĞŵĂƌŬĞƚ
;WƌŝĐĞsŽůĂƟůŝƚLJ͕ĂůĂŶĐĞŽĨWĂLJŵĞŶƚƐ͕
ŽŵƉĞƟƟǀĞŶĞƐƐŽĨ/ŶĚƵƐƚƌLJͿ
DĂƌŬĞƚƐ
dŚĞĂƚƐĨƌŽŵƚŚĞŵĂƌŬĞƚ
;>ĂĐŬŽĨ/ŶǀĞƐƚŵĞŶƚĂŶĚZΘ͕>ĂĐŬŽĨ
^ŽĐŝĂůƌĞůĂƟǀŝƚLJ DĂŝŶƚĞŶĂŶĐĞͿ
;WƌŝĐĞ>ĞǀĞůͬWŽǀĞƌƚLJ͕DŝŐƌĂƟŽŶͿ
ǀĂŝůĂďůŝƚLJΘīŽƌĚĂďŝůŝƚLJŽĨKƚŚĞƌ
īŽƌĚĂďŝůŝƚLJ /ŶƉƵƚZĞƐŽƵƌĐĞƐ
;ĞĐŽŶŽŵŝĐƐͿ
ƌŽƉŝŶĞŵĂŶĚ
WƌŽĚƵĐƟŽŶ ;ĐŽŶŽŵŝĐƌŝƐĞƐ͕ĸĐŝĞŶĐLJ͕
^ƵďƐƟƚƵƟŽŶͿ
'ŽǀĞƌŶŵĞŶƚ
;KǀĞƌ͕hŶĚĞƌŽƌ&ĂƵůƚLJZĞŐƵůĂƟŽŶͿ WŽůŝƟĐĂů/ŶƐƚĂďŝůŝƚLJ
ůŝŵĂƚĞŚĂŶŐĞ
;džƚƌĞŵĞtĞĂƚŚĞƌ͕ŝŽͲŝǀĞƌƐŝƚLJͿ
^ƵƐƚĂŝŶĂďŝůŝƚLJ
;ĞĐŽůŽŐLJͿ WŽůůƵƟŽŶΘŵŵŝƐƐŝŽŶ
ŝƐĞĂƐĞƐΘƉŝĚĞŵŝĐƐ
The basis for these classifications is rarely systematically justified: they often
seem almost as arbitrary as the lists of energy security concerns which they
seek to structure. Moreover, classification is not integration. Placing several
concerns in one group does not necessarily help us to understand them
better or to develop integrated solutions.16
Figure 3.1 is a prime example of this. It is per definition incomplete and its sys-
temization is based on implicit assumptions on the meaning of the four cat-
egories in terms of geography and technological prowess, politics and society,
economics and ecology. More important, the close connections between the
subcategories make the initial differentiation rather arbitrary. Subcategories like
government regulation and technology are interwoven in all four categories and
could be read as threat and solution at the same time.
Second, the chosen definition of energy security often prestructures the con-
clusions that can be drawn, as such definitions fixate assumptions on energy,
energy security and temporality.17 To be fair, that is exactly the purpose of sim-
plification. On the other hand, this often leads to an acceptance of a pre-agreed-
upon status quo. For instance, the food security literature shows how hunger is
often put forward, implicitly, as a supply problem that can only be solved by
adding more supply without regard for social entitlements that hinder the distri-
bution of available supplies.18 It also returns in qualitative energy research
where, for example, Von Hippel et al. and Valentine show how studies that take
a longer time frame often value stability over costs whereas short-time frame
studies favour costs above all else.19 Likewise, Zeniewski, Martinez-Anido and
Pearson argue that quantitative approaches regularly favour free market solu-
tions, while qualitative approaches, which are often more socially oriented,
prefer regulated energy markets.20 As they conclude:
On a practical level, the definition of energy security and its scope con-
ditions will crucially affect how both policymakers and academics identify,
order and manage risks and vulnerabilities affecting the energy system, in
whatever form it is analysed.21
44 Analysing energy security
To a certain extent, scholars like Valentine or Zeniewski, Martinez-Anido and
Pearson draw attention to the claim of this book that the concepts and theories
of energy security help shape the world around us.
This becomes important when one realizes that the definitions and indicators
of energy security are, if not defined, then strongly influenced by the IEA, an
organization by and for developed countries and their search for secure energy
supplies. In other words, modern understandings of energy security build upon
definitions written by a small number of capital-intensive consumer countries
and their identification of indicators based on their particular experiences.22 In
time, Cherp and Jewell argue, these indicators are exported to other parties who
are unable to develop such indicators on their own.23 To be clear, this does not
necessary have to be a bad thing, but it does point to a level of politics often
ignored.
Similarly, it is well known that energy security contains both absolute and
relative aspects. Chester, in this respect argues that availability and accessibility
are absolute aspects of energy security as they are measurable, while affordability
and acceptability are relative aspects that depend on weighing and agreement.24
However, the idea that there are absolute numerical aspects of energy security
clearly overlooks the actual politics of energy reserves. A good example is the
increase of the officially proven oil and gas reserves between 1982 and 1988 by a
number of OPEC members during the run-up to new OPEC production quotas.
These increases are circumspect as those countries were not witness to any
obvious exploration or technological advancements in that time, while their
respective quotas were going to be based on their total reserves.25 As the 2010
World Energy Outlook stated:
ŶĞƌŐLJ
^ĞĐƵƌŝƚLJ
ŶĞƌŐLJ ŶǀŝƌŽŶŵĞŶƚĂů
ĐŽŶŽŵŝĐƐ ^ƵƐƚĂŝŶĂďŝůŝƚLJ
Notes
1 Ciută 2010; Sovacool and Brown 2010, 102; Chester 2010; Dyer and Trombetta
2013; Sovacool and Mukherjee 2011; Sovacool 2011a.
2 Ciută 2010, 133.
3 With the exception of Ciută 2010; Bridge 2015.
4 Cherp and Jewell 2011a.
5 Zeniewski, Martinez-Anido and Pearson 2013, 40.
6 There are many more social theories used to analyse energy (transitions). A place to
start is Smits 2015, 21, or Rosa, Machlis and Keating 1988.
7 Christou and Adamides 2013; Fischhendler, Boymel and Boykoff 2014; Leung et al.
2014; Trombetta 2012; Nyman 2014; Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008; Stoddard
2012.
Analysing energy security 51
8 Including this book, although here categories are used more loosely (see the shift
from definitions to reflection in Chapter 4).
9 APERC 2007.
10 Hughes 2009 (four categories); Sovacool and Mukherjee 2011; APERC 2007; Ang,
Choong and Ng 2015; Sovacool and Brown 2010; Vivoda 2010 (11 categories with
44 indicators); Sovacool 2011b (20 dimensions and 320 indicators).
11 Sovacool 2011b; Jansen 2009; Le Coq and Paltseva 2009; IEA 2011.
12 Cherp and Jewell 2014, 418.
13 Johansson 2013.
14 Winzer 2012.
15 Ibid., 37–39.
16 Cherp and Jewell 2011b, 209.
17 Valentine 2011.
18 Sen 1983.
19 Von Hippel et al. 2011; Valentine 2011.
20 Zeniewski, Martinez-Anido and Pearson 2013, 41.
21 Ibid.
22 Cherp and Jewell 2011a.
23 Ibid.
24 Chester 2010.
25 Salameh 2004.
26 IEA 2010, 115; Cobb 2012.
27 Reynolds 2005, 55.
28 Smits 2015; Rosa, Machlis and Keating 1988; Aalto et al. 2014.
29 Stoddard 2013; Raphael and Stokes 2016.
30 Aalto et al. 2014.
31 Correljé and Van der Linde 2006; Bosse and Schmidt-Felzmann 2011; Barnes and
Jaffe 2006; Criekemans 2011; Klare 2008; Kropatcheva 2011.
32 Stoddard 2013, 7, quoting Ciută 2010, 130. See also Casier 2011.
33 Waltz 1988.
34 Klare 2001, 2008, 2012; Van der Linde, Perlot and Hoogeveen 2006.
35 Labban 2011, 326.
36 Campbell 2005, 954.
37 Criekemans 2011; Scholten and Bosman 2016.
38 Correljé and Van der Linde 2006.
39 Stoddard 2013; Goldthau and Witte 2009.
40 Van der Linde 2007, 70.
41 Stoddard 2013, 10.
42 On energy regimes see Section 2.6. On discourse analyses see Alcock 2009; Jarosz
2014; Lovell 2008; Scrase and Ockwell 2010. On securitization theory see for
example Nyman 2014; Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008; Shepherd 2012.
43 Nyman 2014, 47.
44 WEC 2015.
45 Graham and Thrift 2007.
46 Mulligan 2010; Patterson 2008.
47 Cherp and Jewell 2011b; Ciută 2010.
48 Not many scholars describe what dependency means for them. Somebody who does is
Le Billon, following Ribot and Peluso, who discusses dependency by separating access
from control. Whereas access is ‘ “the ability to derive benefits” using all possible
means’, control should be seen as ‘gaining, controlling or maintaining access’. Hence,
‘control can be defined as the ability to enforce the rights to benefit from resources,
using all possible means’. See Le Billon 2007, 175–176, who quotes Ribot and Peluso
2003, 173.
49 See Friedrichs 2010.
52 Analysing energy security
50 In case of energy, especially oil and gas, this interdependence can even be asymmetri-
cal as the short-term disruptive power of gas suppliers is only balanced on the medium
to long term by the income dependency of producers. See Stoddard 2012, 347.
51 Ciută 2010, 139.
52 Ibid., 128.
53 Ibid., 139.
54 Sovacool 2014.
Bibliography
Aalto, Pami, David Dusseault, Michael D. Kennedy and Markku Kivinen. 2014. Russia’s
energy relations in Europe and the Far East: Towards a social structurationist approach
to energy policy formation. Journal of International Relations and Development 17
(1): 1–29.
Alcock, Rupert. 2009. Speaking food: A discourse analytic study of food security. University
of Bristol Working Paper. School of Sociology, Politics and International Studies
(SPAIS). Available from www.bris.ac.uk/spais/research/workingpapers/wpspaisfiles/
alcock0709.pdf. Accessed 23 January 2013.
Ang, B. W., W. L. Choong and T. S. Ng. 2015. Energy security: Definitions, dimensions
and indexes. Renewable and Sustainable Energy Reviews 42: 1077–1093.
APERC. 2007. A quest for energy security in the 21st century: Resources and constraints.
Tokyo: Asia Pacific Energy Research Centre.
Barnes, J., and A. M. Jaffe. 2006. The Persian Gulf and the geopolitics of oil. Survival 48
(1): 143–162.
Bosse, Giselle, and Anke Schmidt-Felzmann. 2011. The geopolitics of energy supply in
the ‘Wider Europe’. Geopolitics 16 (3): 479–485.
Bridge, Gavin. 2015. Energy (in)security: World-making in an age of scarcity. The Geo-
graphical Journal 181 (4): 328–339.
Campbell, David. 2005. The biopolitics of security: Oil, empire, and the sports utility
vehicle. American Quarterly 57 (3): 943–972.
Casier, Tom. 2011. Russia’s energy leverage over the EU: Myth or reality? Perspectives on
European Politics and Society 12 (4): 493–508.
Cherp, Aleh. 2012. Defining energy security takes more than asking around. Energy
Policy 48: 841–842.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2011a. Energy Challenges: From local universalism to
global contextualism. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin
K. Sovacool, 330–355. London and New York: Routledge.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2011b. The three perspectives on energy security: Intel-
lectual history, disciplinary roots and the potential for integration. Current Opinion in
Environmental Sustainability 3 (4): 202–212.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2014. The concept of energy security: Beyond the four
As. Energy Policy 75: 415–421.
Chester, Lynne. 2010. Conceptualising energy security and making explicit its polysemic
nature. Energy Policy 38 (2): 887–895.
Christou, Odysseas, and Constantinos Adamides. 2013. Energy securitization and dese-
curitization in the New Middle East. Security Dialogue 44 (5–6): 507–522.
Ciută, Felix. 2010. Conceptual notes on energy security: Total or banal security? Security
Dialogue 41 (2): 123–144.
Analysing energy security 53
Cobb, Kurt. 2012. Has OPEC misled us about the size of its oil reserves? Does it matter?
Resource Insights. Available from http://resourceinsights.blogspot.nl/2012/09/has-opec-
misled-us-about-size-of-its.html. Accessed 22 June 2015.
Correljé, Aad, and Coby van der Linde. 2006. Energy supply security and geopolitics: A
European perspective. Energy Policy 34 (5): 532–543.
Criekemans, David. 2011. The geopolitics of renewable energy: different or similar to the
geopolitics of conventional energy? In Panel ‘Geopolitics, Power Transitions, and
Energy’. Montréal, Québec, Canada. Available from www.exploringgeopolitics.org/pdf/
Criekemans_David_Geopolitics_Renewable_Energy.pdf. Accessed 9 December 2013.
Dyer, Hugh, and Maria Julia Trombetta. 2013. International handbook of energy security.
Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Fischhendler, Itay, Dror Boymel and Maxwell T. Boykoff. 2014. How competing securi-
tized discourses over land appropriation are constructed: The promotion of solar
energy in the Israeli desert. Environmental Communication 10 (2): 147–168.
Friedrichs, Jörg. 2010. Global energy crunch: How different parts of the world would
react to a peak oil scenario. Energy Policy 38 (8): 4562–4569.
Goldthau, Andreas, and Jan Martin Witte. 2009. Back to the future or forward to the
past? Strengthening markets and rules for effective global energy governance. Inter-
national Affairs 85 (2): 373–390.
Graham, Stephen, and Nigel Thrift. 2007. Out of order: Understanding repair and main-
tenance. Theory, Culture & Society 24 (3): 1–25.
Von Hippel, David F., T. Suzuki, J. H. Williams, T. Savage and P. Hayes. 2011. Energy
security and sustainability in Northeast Asia. Energy Policy 39 (11): 6719–6730.
Hughes, L. 2009. The four ‘R’s of energy security. Energy Policy 37 (6): 2459–2461.
IEA. 2010. World Energy Outlook 2010. World Energy Outlook. OECD/International
Energy Agency.
IEA. 2011. Measuring short-term energy security. Paris: OECD/International Energy
Agency.
Jansen, Jaap C. 2009. Energy services security: Concepts and metrics. Expert paper submit-
ted as input to the ongoing IAEA project: ‘Selecting and Defining Integrated Indi-
cators for Nuclear Energy’. Petten: ECN.
Jarosz, Lucy. 2014. Comparing food security and food sovereignty discourses. Dialogues in
Human Geography 4 (2): 168–181.
Johansson, Bengt. 2013. A broadened typology on energy and security. Energy 53:
199–205.
Klare, Michael T. 2001. Resource wars: The new landscape of global conflict. New York:
Henry Holt.
Klare, Michael T. 2008. Rising powers, shrinking planet: The new geopolitics of energy. New
York: Henry Holt.
Klare, Michael T. 2012. The race for what’s left: The global scramble for the world’s last
resources. New York: Henry Holt.
Kropatcheva, E. 2011. Playing both ends against the middle: Russia’s geopolitical energy
games with the EU and Ukraine. Geopolitics 16 (3): 553–573.
Labban, Mazen. 2011. The geopolitics of energy security and the war on terror: The case
for market expansion and the militarization of global space. In Global political ecology,
edited by Richard Peet, Paul Robbins and Michael J. Watts, 325–344. London:
Routledge.
Le Billon, Philippe. 2007. Geographies of war: Perspectives on ‘resource wars’. Geography
Compass 1 (2): 163–182.
54 Analysing energy security
Le Coq, C., and E. Paltseva. 2009. Measuring the security of external energy supply in
the European Union. Energy Policy 37 (11): 4474–4481.
Leung, Guy C. K., Aleh Cherp, Jessica Jewell and Yi-Ming Wei. 2014. Securitization of
energy supply chains in China. Applied Energy 123: 316–326.
Lovell, Heather. 2008. Discourse and innovation journeys: The case of low energy
housing in the UK. Technology Analysis & Strategic Management 20 (5): 613–632.
Mulligan, Shane. 2010. Energy, environment, and security: Critical links in a post-peak
world. Global Environmental Politics 10 (4): 79–100.
Natorski, Michal, and Anna Herranz Surrallés. 2008. Securitizing moves to nowhere?
The framing of the European Union’s energy policy. Journal of Contemporary European
Research 4 (2): pp. 70–89.
Nyman, Jonna. 2014. ‘Red storm ahead’: Securitisation of energy in US–China Rela-
tions. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 43–65.
Patterson, W. 2008. Managing energy wrong. Energy, Environment and Resource Govern-
ance Working Paper. Managing Energy: for Climate and Security. London: Chatham
House.
Raphael, Sam, and Doug Stokes. 2016. Energy security. In Contemporary security studies,
edited by Alan Collins, 343–355. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Reynolds, Douglas B. 2005. The economics of oil definitions: The case of Canada’s oil
sands. OPEC review 29 (1): 51–73.
Ribot, Jesse C., and Nancy Lee Peluso. 2003. A theory of access. Rural Sociology 68 (2):
153–181.
Rosa, Eugene A., Gary E. Machlis and Kenneth M. Keating. 1988. Energy and society.
Annual Review of Sociology 14: 149–172.
Salameh, Mamdouh G. 2004. How realistic are OPEC’s proven oil reserves? Petroleum
Review, August: 26–29.
Scholten, Daniel, and Rick Bosman. 2016. The geopolitics of renewables: Exploring the
political implications of renewable energy systems. Technological Forecasting and Social
Change 103: 273–283.
Scrase, J. Ivan, and David G. Ockwell. 2010. The role of discourse and linguistic framing
effects in sustaining high carbon energy policy – An accessible introduction. Energy
Policy 38 (5): 2225–2233.
Sen, Amartya. 1983. Poverty and famines. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shepherd, Benjamin. 2012. Thinking critically about food security. Security Dialogue 43
(3): 195–212.
Smits, Mattijs. 2015. Southeast Asian energy transitions: Between modernity and sustain-
ability. London and New York: Routledge.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., ed. 2011a. The Routledge handbook of energy security. London and
New York: Routledge.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., ed. 2011b. Evaluating energy security in the Asia pacific:
Towards a more comprehensive approach. Energy Policy 39 (11). Asian Energy
Security: 7472–7479.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., ed. 2014. What are we doing here? Analyzing fifteen years of
energy scholarship and proposing a social science research agenda. Energy Research &
Social Science 1: 1–29.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., and Marilyn A. Brown. 2010. Competing dimensions of energy
security: An international perspective. Annual Review of Environment and Resources 35
(1): 77–108.
Analysing energy security 55
Sovacool, Benjamin K., and I. Mukherjee. 2011. Conceptualizing and measuring energy
security: A synthesized approach. Energy 36 (8): 5343–5355.
Stoddard, Edward. 2012. A common vision of energy risk? Energy securitisation and
company perceptions of risk in the EU. Journal of Contemporary European Research 8
(3): 340–366.
Stoddard, Edward. 2013. Reconsidering the ontological foundations of international
energy affairs: Realist geopolitics, market liberalism and a politico-economic altern-
ative. European Security 22 (4): 437–463.
Trombetta, Maria Julia. 2012. European energy security discourses and the development of a
common energy policy. Working Paper. Energy Delta Gas Research. Available from
www.edgar-program.com/uploads/fckconnector/7acf1f46-7358-4057-86e5-ffee558
13be3. Accessed 6 January 2015.
Valentine, Scott Victor. 2011. The fuzzy nature of energy security. In The Routledge hand-
book of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool, 56–73. London and New York:
Routledge.
Van der Linde, Coby. 2007. The art of managing energy security risks. EIB Papers 12 (1):
50–78.
Van der Linde, Coby, Wilbur Perlot and Femke Hoogeveen. 2006. Tomorrow’s mores:
The future geopolitical system and the structure of the international oil market. The Hague:
Clingendael International Energy Programme. Available from www.clingendael
energy.com/inc/upload/files/tomorrows_mores_oil.pdf. Accessed 15 January 2014.
Vivoda, Vlado. 2010. Evaluating energy security in the Asia-Pacific region: A novel
methodological approach. Energy Policy 38 (9): 5258–5263.
Waltz, Kenneth N. 1988. The origins of war in neorealist theory. The Journal of Inter
disciplinary History 18 (4): 615–628.
WEC. 2015. Priority actions on climate change and how to balance the trilemma. World
Energy Trilemma. London: World Energy Council & Oliver Wyman.
Winzer, Christian. 2012. Conceptualizing energy security. Energy Policy 46: 36–48.
Zeniewski, Peter, Carlo Brancucci Martinez-Anido and Ivan L. G. Pearson. 2013.
Framing new threats: The internal security of gas and electricity networks in the Euro-
pean Union. In International handbook of energy security, edited by Hugh Dyer and
Maria Julia Trombetta, 40–69. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
4 Securing undesired (energy)
futures
4.1 Introduction
The previous chapters show that energy security is characterized by a constant
proliferation, which complicates a study of what it is and how this expansion
impacts the inherent prioritization of security. This chapter unpacks this logic
of security and finds four characteristics, each of them applicable to energy
security.1 First, (energy) security is not one logic. It consists of multiple forms of
insecurity and logics of security, which rely on five different techniques to get to
know the future. Many of these logics are inclusionary: there is always another
unknown potentially threatening future, just as a failed countermeasure only
inspires to do better. Second, (energy) security is highly normative. It is the
choice of what to protect and what not to protect, the choice between what to
see as a threat and what not to see as a threat. Simultaneously, the urgency of
security dispels any thought about the ethical choices inherent to security. Third,
(energy) security is something that is made; it does not exist out there but it is
called upon or written by politicians, concerned citizens, security experts, insur-
ers etc. Lastly, this chapter will discuss that (energy) security is not only a goal,
something that initiates action against a threat, but rather an exercise of power,
a way to govern the present based on an imagination of the future.
One of the most elegant descriptions of security is provided by Booth who
states that security ‘is a powerful political concept; it … energizes opinion and
moves material power’.2 Obviously, this description, in line with the focus of
this book, describes what security does instead of providing a definition of what
it is. In terms of what security is: often security is simply defined as the absence
of threats, in line with Buzan, who sees security as ‘being protected from danger,
feeling safe, and being free from doubt’.3 Alternatively, Brauch defines security
as something that ‘is achieved if there is an absence of objective threats and
subjective fears to basic values’.4 These definitions already show that security
has neither a fixed value nor strong boundaries defining its use, and leads to the
conclusion that security is an empty logic that carries a multitude of meanings
for different people in different times.5 Security is both a state of being (the end
goal of ‘feeling secure’) and the means towards that end (either repairing threats
or avoiding them). Security can be negative (negating threats and dangers) or
Securing undesired (energy) futures 57
positive (something to strive for). Definitions range from the individual to the
international, from material (food) to symbolic (democracy) forms of security,
from internal (rebellion) to external security considerations (invasion), from
the security of public goods (air quality) to private services (insurance), and
from objective and subjective to intersubjective notions of security (see this
chapter).6
With security (and energy security) construed as an empty logic, any content
driven definition or explanation of what security is comes with strong normative
consequences. Chapter 2 on the evolution of the concept of energy security
already shows how such definitions not only describe what the insecurities are,
but also steer what they ought to be. Any decision on insecurity contains an
image of who/what is to be secured, and hence who/what is not part of that
security. Following the definition of Booth above, this book moves away from
such substantive definitions and instead approaches security as the mode through
which people identify undesirable futures and act upon them in the present. Such a
broad definition might invite the response that it is not a definition, that it is
too broad and unworkable because it can include anything that is deemed
important,7 in other words that it makes security into something banal, a cri-
tique forwarded earlier in relation to energy security. However, the approach to
security proposed above enables a process-driven analysis of what security is said
to be, how it comes to be and how it affects current decision-making practices
as well as the consequences of such decision-making. In other words, this broad
definition enables us to transcend the inherent duality within current under-
standings of security of friend/enemy or secure/insecure to the politics and
origins of security by focusing on how people come to know the future and
decide upon its undesirability.
This chapter consists of four sections. Section 4.2 deals with the question of
what security is. It provides a detailed and up-to-date examination of security as
it lets go of any fixed definition, instead focusing on general processes and how
it works: the specific rationalities through which we approach uncertain futures,
the techniques used to identify undesired futures, and the security logics that
secure these undesirable futures. Together these make up what here is under-
stood as security. Section 4.3 proceeds to discuss the normative dimension of
security and goes so far as to argue that security essentially is a form of ethics.
This chapter examines the close connection between security decisions and
knowledge, the role of fear in relation to security, and the active political
(mis)use of security to govern vulnerable populations. The last two sections shift
to theories of security and deal with the processes through which undesired
futures are turned into a security issue. Section 4.4 looks closely at securitization
theory, one of the core theories on security that provides a framework to study
how people call upon security (interpreted as exceptional circumstances) in
political arenas. Section 4.5 studies the theoretical literature on the security
technique of risk calculations (with its focus on routine security practices) and
how this helps govern our daily lives. Section 4.6 offers a brief reflection.
58 Securing undesired (energy) futures
4.2 Tackling the unknown
The importance of the process itself follows from the main function of scenarios,
which is to order all possible imaginable futures into coherent stories. It is this
ordering process and its socializing effect that helps participants to understand
the scenarios they are working with.44 After Shell’s success, the use of scenarios
quickly spread across society.45 The main issue with scenarios is that, irrespec-
tive of (or due to) their broad application, they are often developed by experts
64 Securing undesired (energy) futures
instead of executive decision makers. This leads to situations where, in hind-
sight, the future is almost always imagined by someone somewhere, but that this
does not guarantee that they are acted upon or favoured by the decision
makers.46 Salter, for example, notes how the terrorist attacks of 9/11 were not a
failure of imagination or scenario planning but that the failure corresponds to
the fact that the imageries in this case failed to convince the policymakers in
charge.47 This practice of using imagination and scenarios by policy and the
media to identify as many possible futures as possible has also been called
premediation.48
The third technique is extrapolation. This is a quantitative way of forecasting
the future by estimating the future value of a variable through an extension of
the historic trend into the future. In the case of natural resources, extrapolation
can be traced to Malthus’s argument about the arithmetic versus geometric
change of respectively food production and population growth.49 More sophist-
icated approaches gained traction, in particular during the first half of the twen-
tieth century in relation to industrial development and, in particular, in relation
to the military during World War II.50 However, extrapolation techniques really
took off with the development of information technology that allowed for the
handling of more complex trend analyses over larger data sets. One of the main
examples remains the original Limits to Growth report, which reinforced
(neo‑)Malthusian concerns on the environmental consequences of economic
growth. Similarly, the price expectations in relation to natural resource com-
modities are partly based on trend analyses. An example would be the oil price
expectations in 2008. At that time, a report by Goldman and Sachs stated that
the oil price, at that moment hovering around 120 dollars a barrel, would con-
tinue to rise to 150 or 200 dollars per barrel (the price peaked at 147 dollars).51
These days, extrapolation is often combined with scenarios wherein particular
variables are altered to offer bandwidths of most likely trends.
The fourth technique is risk calculation. Where extrapolation deals with the
identification of the future, ‘[c]alculation … renders complex future geographies
actionable through the numericalization of a reality to come – numbers that
may thereafter circulate, be reflected on and take on an affective charge’.52 In
other words, calculation focuses on the likely impacts and the chance of an
event occurring. The technique of risk calculation thus centres on the statistical
probability of well-known events with known variables.53 Accordingly, and
unlike the previous security techniques, risk calculation does not identify the
future but instead categorizes multiple futures. This leads some scholars to argue
that risk should be seen ‘as a governance framework [which] seeks to focus
scarce resources on risks that are ranked according to frequency and impact’.54
The reason that risk calculation is interpreted as a security technique is because
risk assessments are used to identify a set of futures that are not per definition
undesirable or desirable. Risks display both possible costs and potential benefits
and it is up to the individual to decide whether to take the risk or not. This sub-
sequently points towards the politics behind risk calculation, as quantitative
models do not explain the ‘disaster threshold’ or that point in time when people
Securing undesired (energy) futures 65
decide that the risks are no longer acceptable.55 Recent work by Amoore, among
others, shows the importance of this, as risk calculation seems to be shifting
from the statistical probability of imagined futures and their underlying variables
to calculations that try to prevent events through a method that uses risk calcu-
lation to search for statistical correlations of non-related variables in extremely
large databases (see Section 4.5.5) in order to identify terrorists before the actual
act by the (not related and non-criminal) acts that they have in common.56
A last security technique is simulation (performance or acting). This tech-
nique too does not primarily discover new futures but instead enables people to
experience a particular future. For Anderson, performance involves that ‘futures
are … made present through practices that stage an interval between the here
and now and a specific future through some form of acting, role-play, gaming or
pretending’.57 By simulating a future, participants emotionally and affectively
experience that future as they play it out in the present, leading to a better
understanding of that particular possible future and one’s potential response.
The best-known examples are fire drills (e.g. on oil and gas platforms), the Cold
War-style war games, large-scale disaster management exercises and the stress
testing of oil and gas systems by the IEA.58 On a more individual level, the per-
formance technique is of course the corner stone behind many training pro-
grammes. Pilots, soldiers, physicians and managers are all trained with simulators
and real-life exercises. In these exercises, people act in the present based on
imagined and experienced futures. They get to know particular futures, and the
skills to handle them, by experiencing these futures.
The only way to have the kind of epistemological immediacy necessary for
deterrence is for its process to have its own cause and to hold it fast within
itself. The quickest and most direct way for a process to acquire its own
cause is for it to produce one. The easiest way to do this is to take the immi-
nence of the very threat prevention has failed to neutralize and make it the
foundation of a new process.62
In this new process, the perceived urgency of the undesired future loses all
doubt; it becomes the justification for the urgency itself and makes the unde-
sired future a reality in the present. In other words, the undesired future is
known because it is acted upon as if it were real. It is performed.
Then there are also undesirable futures that are ‘not yet fully formed’.63 These
undesirable futures are both epistemological and ontological uncertain: they
cannot be known because the ontic nature of the future is not fully known.64 In
other words, there is some idea about what the undesirable future is, but not
where or how it will come about. A logic of pre-emption was originally coined in
relation to pre-emptive wars: wars that break the peace in the face of an attack
of the threatening other (contra preventive wars, in which one attacks without
immediate threat of attack). Pre-emption thus tries to halt a threat from coming
into existence and hence does not deal with possibilities (risks) but with poten-
tialities (scenarios), a constant flux of self-referential new potentialities.65
Similar to deterrence, the logic of pre-emption deals with these imagined
undesirable futures by believing them to happen at any moment and with drastic
impacts.66 Massumi sees pre-emption therefore as a logic that works affectively
instead of causally, as it needs to create its own ‘otherness’ based on a constant
regeneration of the fear of new potential threats.67 The best way to counter such
fears is by acting upon them as if they are real. In doing so, pre-emption realizes
the potential undesired future in the present. When you fear your neighbour
and treat him as a threat, everything the neighbour does potentially is threaten-
ing and thereby reinforces your fear and further justifies the actions you take to
‘keep him in check’. Consequently, such an affective realization of an undesir-
able future cannot be proven wrong.68 When acting upon pre-emptive fear,
there is no objective ground to reflect on your actions and subsequently no
Securing undesired (energy) futures 67
ground for proportionality to your actions. Whether the undesired future ensues
or not, countering the fear was the right thing to do.
Comparable to a logic of pre-emption, a logic of precaution also works on and
through potentially undesirable futures. Contrary to pre-emption, however, pre-
caution does not ‘unleash … transformative events in order to avoid a rupture
in a valued life’ but instead cautions against any actions that could potentially
lead to undesired futures.69 This logic is best known through the precautionary
principle, a principle that states that ‘when human activities may lead to
morally unacceptable harm that is scientifically plausible but uncertain, actions
shall be taken to avoid or diminish that harm’.70 Often precaution leads to
demands for more scientific knowledge, although it is just as often a justification
to prevent undesirable actions completely.71 In other words, the precautionary
logic contains strong debates on the proportionality of activities, weighing the
potentiality of a decision to commence those activities against their potential
impacts (in contrast to deterrence and pre-emption). Precaution is thus a logic
that focuses primarily on the potential impacts of one’s own actions and one’s
own decisions instead of something exogenous. In this it closely resembles
Luhmann’s analyses of a risk rationality, although it misses the ability to calcu-
late the impact of an action or decision as the potential future itself is still
uncertain.72
Besides avoiding undesired futures, some logics work to reduce the impacts of
those undesired futures that are deemed unavoidable. A logic of preparedness, for
example, focuses on a reduction of impacts. It has preventive qualities in that it
deals with what you as an individual or social group can do to keep your current
way of life.73 When analysing natural resource use and critical infrastructure,
preparedness includes well-known measures like the construction of reserves,
redundancy, interconnections and back-up capacity, but also includes instru-
ments like insurance and contract law. In the case of insurance, risk calculation
is used to reduce the impact of certain undesired futures by spreading the costs
for rebuilding over a group of people. In the case of contract law, the uncer-
tainty of decision-making is reduced by agreeing to keep each other accountable
and to discuss responsibilities and cost distribution in case of impacts. Prepared-
ness (or mitigation) contrasts in this case with a logic of resilience. Resilience (or
adaptation) is discussed a bit more in Section 4.5 and Chapter 6, but for now
can be described as a prudential way to tackle the future by taking a more proac-
tive approach, in line with pre-emption, in actively adapting towards undesir-
able futures.74 These two differ because a logic of resilience does not actualize a
particular undesired future like pre-emption. Instead, it makes agents see them-
selves as vulnerable and forces them to be aware and constantly open to undesir-
able futures. In other words, a resilience logic does not try to prepare for the
impacts of possible undesirable futures (as in a logic of preparedness) but forces
the agent to adapt by changing himself instead of his surroundings.
In sum, the above forms of insecurity, techniques and logics of security
quickly dispel any remaining illusion or hope for a clear definition of what
(energy) security is. Security is all of those and more. First, security relates to
68 Securing undesired (energy) futures
different types of insecurity following rationalities of threats, dangers, cata-
strophes, uncertainties, risks and safety. Second, security is the range of tech-
niques used to gain knowledge over the future, whether through uncertainty,
extrapolation, imagination, risk calculation or simulation. Lastly, security is the
combination of logics that aim to counter undesired futures, whether known
through the logics of prevention and deterrence, unknown through pre-emption
and precaution or unavoidable via preparedness and resilience. This multiplicity
of logics and techniques reinforces the richness that lies behind the emptiness
of security and energy security while focusing our attention away from energy to
the range of rationalities, techniques and logics that we use to get to know and
prioritize undesired (energy) futures.
The moment something is identified as undesirable, the referent object and our
relation to the referent object are changed, irrespective whether action has been
taken or not. For Dillon the question therefore is not what security is, or who or
what is threatening or in need of protection, but instead:
What does a representation of danger make of ‘us’ and of those who are not
‘us’? Not by asking who or what is threatened, or what is doing the threat-
ening? But by asking how does the specification of threat and its discourse
of danger determine ‘who’, the ‘we’, and the ‘what’ that is said one the one
hand to be endangered, and on the other to be doing the endangering? …
And, finally, not by asking how to secure security? But, by enquiring about
what is lost and forgotten, and who or what pays the inevitable price, for
the way that ‘we’ are thus habited in fear?87
This gets to the core of the critical position on security. Rejecting the assump-
tions that it is possible to separate theory from reality, facts from values and self
from others, a critical security perspective questions and problematizes the
70 Securing undesired (energy) futures
taken-for-granted nature of security as something easily identified, with clear
consequences and equally clear countermeasures. Instead, it focuses on the pol-
itics of security: the hard work that is needed to make something into a security
issue, for example by highlighting the American diplomatic efforts to find
support for the 2003 Iraq War. In addition, a critical perspective also focuses on
the consequences of the security distinctions that are forwarded in these polit-
ical debates, and studies the effects that result from the countermeasures which
both reinforce previous situations and materialize their own cause for concern.
From such a critical security position, it is possible to derive an understanding
of security as a highly normative process, if not a form of ethics in itself. Burgess
makes this argument when he states that:
The close connection between security and ethics can be witnessed in the mul-
tiple ethical positions on energy security. Chapter 2 concludes that current defi-
nitions of energy security contain an equality principle when they support the
right of all humankind to energy. On the one hand, such a position can be
pushed further by arguing along Kantian lines that it should be forbidden to act-
ively cause harm. This would imply that we take action against those who act-
ively withhold energy from those without, but it could also include all those
benefiting from a system that methodically excludes sections of the global popu-
lation. On the other hand, a utilitarian would claim that the benefit of most
precedes the harm done to some and that an unequal system does not automati-
cally imply an unethical system. Of course, contrary to both, it is also possible to
argue in favour of a primary biological imperative to feed and protect oneself
and one’s children first (the few over the many). Such a self-centred position
clearly conflicts with the others’ ethical positions, and is generally frowned
upon, but lies at the heart of security.
Within CSS, the ethical dimension of security and the normativity of
security choices are interpreted both positively, neutrally and negatively. First, a
more positive form of security can be found in Booth’s theory of emancipatory
security.89 Booth argues that true security can only come about if people are free
of ‘the life-determining conditions of insecurity’, which for him cannot come to
pass without their equality and emancipation.90 In his work, Booth explicitly
studies security in terms of what should be. Not in terms of a utilitarian end goal,
as the future cannot be known precisely, but as an egalitarian process that con-
stantly strives for a more equal and inclusionary humanitarian world. For Booth,
a critique of current security practices alone is not enough; those practices need
to be improved. To do this he accepts the exclusionary nature of security, but
only because he explicitly starts from those who are least secure in life. As
Booth makes clear:
Securing undesired (energy) futures 71
Like health and status, security is a condition that is not difficult to define;
in each case, the starting-point should begin in the experiences, imagin-
ings, analyses, and fears of those living with insecurity, ill-health, or low
status.91
If security is the drawing of boundaries, then Booth’s position is to shift its moral
entry point to those who are less secure and put the burden and responsibility
on to those who are more secure.
Second, Booth’s explicit positive interpretation of security contrasts with the
interpretation of scholars like Dillon and Massumi for whom security is neither
positive nor negative. For them, and other scholars following the insights from
Foucault, security is the process through which society is organized and gov-
erned (see Chapter 6).92 They study how security is used to govern society but
refrain from normative judgements on whether the governing is good or bad.
They do not focus on the objects in need of security but on the process of
security by studying for example how freedom and equality are used instrumen-
tally as a form of governance.
Lastly, Booth’s positive reading of security also contrasts with those who see
security negatively. This is, for example, the position of scholars working from
securitization theory.93 This theory analyses how agents use security arguments
to justify extraordinary measures that ignore normal decision-making proced-
ures. It poses security as a temporary state of affairs, as a moment to deal with an
undesirable future and then to be returned to normal.94 Security is something
you need, but is not preferable. Another example, one even stronger driven by a
negative understanding of security, can be found in the work of the Foucauldian-
and Marxist-inspired scholar Neocleous, who equates security with oppression.95
For Neocleous, security is and has been actively (mis)used to structure society in
such a way that it is beneficial for the elites and capital rich. Among other
things, he discusses the close connection between capital/business and security
in the security industry, where security is transformed into a commodity to be
sold and bought at will (creation of demand/insecurity) while, simultaneously,
capital, business and finance are deemed in need of protection themselves as
well from attempts to alter/transform them. With this last point Neocleous
pushes the business–security linkage a step further than, for example Leander,
who studies the ‘commodification of violence’ by focusing solely on the role of
private security companies and how their supply of security creates the actual
demand for it.96
While these positions within CSS differ in respect to the role that security
plays in the governing of the state and the political economy, they do highlight
the importance of a reflection on the hidden normativity of one’s view on
security in general and the security choices one makes in particular. Unfortu-
nately, any such normative reflections on security are dispelled by the inherent
logic(s) of security that overrule any ethical reflection with the urgency of the
threat.
72 Securing undesired (energy) futures
4.3.2 Fear and undesirable futures
The above-mentioned logics and techniques describe how futures are character-
ized as undesired and as something in need of prevention, adaptation or mitiga-
tion. However, they do not explain why a future is deemed undesirable. The
intricate relationship between ethics and security has already offered a glimpse
of the origin of insecurity by showing that security is something that can be act-
ively used and called upon. This section enquires further into these processes by
analysing how fear works and is mobilized collectively to make some futures
feared and others desired (to be clear, fear is only one motivational force; others
include anger, grief, profit and power).97 In general, people desire and fear to
lose three things. First, a conservation or improvement of the status quo (goods,
relations, needs). Second, a solution to the threat or object that they fear.
Third, knowledge itself, in particular the ontological certainty derived from a
knowledge of the future.98 These three together indicate that fear and desire are
not one-on-one related. Hence, it should come as no surprise that the processes
behind fear and a desire for security are as context-bound and relative as security
itself. Some people desire an emotion of fear (adrenaline junkies), while others
fear their desires (addicts). Similarly, emotions like fear and desire on their own
do not explain why some futures are feared or desired, nor which referent objects
are so desired that they need security. Fear is an emotion, but also a mechanism
of security. Below, we will discuss, respectively, the cause and identification of
fear, the active (mis)use of fear, how fear is changing as it is shifting from fear
alone to a fear of fear itself, and how this latter shift affects society.
First, the cause and identification of fear. In brief, the literature suggests that
fear results from desire and simultaneously enables desire to act upon that par-
ticular fear. ‘In fear we are met by something outside ourselves, and what we
meet is a negation of what we want’.99 We fear a rejection of our desires, but at
the same time fear also spurs a desire for action. As Svendsen continues, fear is
an emotion ‘through which we consider the world’, a ‘contagious’ emotion that
‘seek[s] to conserve’ and simultaneously spurs ‘creativity’ to counter itself.100 Fear
is not just an emotion but, as Frost argues, a ‘passion’ that is always applied
towards an object.101 This includes obvious objects, like forms and quantities of
energy, but also a fear for the unknown – where the unknown becomes the
object to be feared. The presence of an object is important because, contrary to
fear, anxiety and panic miss such an object.102 Anxiety for example is a pure
emotion that disperses itself to other people through mimesis.103 Where fear
offers ‘the illusion of individual autonomous agency’, anxiety has no (un)desir-
able external object and thus cannot be countered.104 Fear thus differs from
anxiety and notions like resilience with its sense of vulnerability, as the desire
to counter a fear provides it with an object that leads to the ability to act upon
it. In other words, fear empowers the individual, while anxiety and the inescap-
able vulnerability of resilience undermine such empowerment.
Second, this brings us to the active (mis)use of fear. Building on this dis-
tinction between fear and (objectless) anxiety or panic, Robin distinguishes
Securing undesired (energy) futures 73
private fears from two forms of public fears. Under private fears Robin categor-
izes phobias for spiders and so on. Under public fears Robin includes those fears
which are shared across groups of people and which originate either exoge-
nously or endogenously. Exogeneous fears are defined by political elites and,
through a politics of fear and self–other distinctions, come to determine the
political agenda. On the other hand, endogenous fears are based on the inher-
ent inequalities within society.105 In this case, fear, through security practices,
not only helps identify the self in relation to a threatening other but also
fixates the socio-economic and political hierarchies within society. For Robin,
endogenous fear is not just about survival or physical harm, but about some-
thing that he describes ‘[as] an apprehension of harm, and because harm is the
deprivation of some good to the individual, wielders of power can arouse fear
merely by threatening the individual’s enjoyment of that good’.106 This form of
fear deals not with fear in the sense of explicit threats to life and limb but with
the fear of losing employment, liberty or education, in other words the ‘quite
fears’ or the ‘low-grade fears’ to livelihoods.107 Interestingly, Robin sees these
public low-key political fears often actively translated as depoliticized private
fears and terrors. For Robin, it is the active conflation of private and public
fears that leads to ‘a separation of fears from morality and politics’ as public
fears are no longer seen to originate from politics and thereby reinforce the
underlying social order.108
Third, while Robin analyses the institutionalized depoliticization of fear,
others conflate Robin’s public fear with the understanding of anxiety proposed
by Svendsen and Frost. Scholars like Massumi, Dillon or Furedi, for example,
argue that fears are feared not because of the object to which fear is attached,
nor because of the active manipulation of fear, but because of the fear for fear
itself.109 Fearing fear itself or the ‘objectification’ of fear can be linked, according
to Furedi, to the idea of constant vulnerability and risk, which gained momen-
tum in the late 1980s.110 The idea behind vulnerability is one of victimhood, for
‘to be a victim is to be relieved of responsibility for the situation in which one
finds oneself ’.111 Such a sense of vulnerability leads to a constant attentiveness
to ones surroundings, an attentiveness that starts to blur underlying causes and
objects, away from a person’s direct experiences with the object and towards the
fear itself. This fear for fear itself and how it motivates or ‘activates’ people, is
something Massumi elsewhere describes in relation to the colour-coded terror
warning systems.112 These yellow, orange and red coded schemes indicate threat
levels and are aimed to change people’s routines without sharing the informa-
tion or evidence behind the indicated threat level. According to Massumi, such
a coding scheme works on the future present ‘pre-effect of fear’, by which he
refers to the unconscious effects of fear:
As William James famously argued, fear strikes the body and compels it to
action before it registers consciously. When it registers, it is as a realization
growing from the bodily action already under way: we don’t run because we
feel afraid, we feel afraid because we run.113
74 Securing undesired (energy) futures
The body acts even before we are consciously aware of it. Only when we realize
that our body responds, whether via fight, flight or freeze reactions, do we feel
afraid. This private feeling then continues to drive us. Massumi describes how
people start to reflect on their bodily reaction, trying to find the object or source
of what has become their fear.114 In rationalizing the moment and source of fear,
the fear becomes an affective emotion. Moreover, when we recount that fear
and its rationalized origin to others in a later step, the fear becomes an object
itself, an object that is anticipated by the people who have heard of it and forces
their bodies to react without the initial unconscious bodily response.115 As an
emotion, fear ‘becomes its own virtual cause’.116 When the colour shifts from
yellow to red, the collective calls upon the embodied private fear, without ever
experiencing the original object ‘that we have become fearful in response to’.117
Fearing the fear itself thus has two effects: it decouples the social from the
material (the body) while simultaneously linking the individual to the
collective.118
Fourth, such a publicly shared sense of private fear affects society as it has
many forms and can be found everywhere, to be called upon and experienced
together and alone. Whereas Robin and Neocleous focus on elites using this
public fear for their benefit, Furedi shows how extensive the use of this public
fear is across government, business, media and NGOs. Basically he points to
everyone who is trying to generate ‘awareness’ and influence people’s individual
lives based on the urgency of a particular cause (or a reduction of the urgency of
other causes).119 ‘When we witness the autonomisation of fear,’ Furedi states,
‘then the question becomes not simply what is causing fear, but what are the
potential negative consequences of fear’.120 The main consequence for Furedi is
that the existence of such an objectified fear has led to a society characterized
by a ‘culture of fear’ that is constantly ‘at risk’,121 in other words a society that
sees individuals as passive and vulnerable.122 And, because it sees individuals as
vulnerable, it treats them as vulnerable. According to Furedi, this leads to a situ-
ation where (1) everybody else is deemed governable by those who know best
on a particular issue; (2) fear, not vision, is seen as something positive within
politics as it helps govern those who are vulnerable, passive and unknowing;
(3) those who know best are often so convinced of their cause that they are not
afraid of using half-truths and ‘good lie[s for] the greater truth’; and (4) with
new issues constantly emerging everyone can become an expert – thereby
reinforcing the culture of public fear as nobody can ‘know’ everything.123
Elsewhere, Burgess describes this inability to understand all the security con-
cerns that are affecting us in terms of the ‘fundamental asymmetry of security
politics’.124
When we follow Massumi and Furedi, the cause of fear is of little importance
anymore. The autonomous existence of political fear implies that it cannot be
proven wrong. While it only works when called upon, the above makes clear
that almost everybody does so. What is more, contrary to an individual’s private
experience of fear, where the undesired future and desired future are identified
simultaneously in response to bodily reactions, in the case of public fear there is
Securing undesired (energy) futures 75
a more intentional logic at work as the particular desired futures are identified
before their current state is publicized as undesirable and something to be feared.
This brings this chapter back to where it started, with security as a way to
govern the present based on an imagination of the future. Even a primal
emotion like fear turns out to be open to (mis)use based on political choices
over which futures are desirable or not.
Unfortunately, the discussion about fear has not helped us to understand why
some futures are feared or desired, only how they become so. Perhaps it should
be concluded that this is not necessarily a bad thing, as the contextual nature of
security makes any answer to such a question a relative answer anyway. This
chapter instead highlighted the institutionalized and intentional social use of
public fear, as one way to explain how security acts as a form of ethics. In fact,
the above showed that there are multiple ethical positions towards security, also
within the literature itself, and choosing one of them is already a normative act
that shapes a particular world. What is more, this normativity is often dispelled
from awareness through the urgency and necessity that is inherent in the exer-
cise of security itself. When one is trying to secure an object, or minimize the
actions of another, that security process and logic trumps any reflection on one’s
own position and actions. Taking all of this into account means that the chal-
lenge becomes to ‘explore the meaning attached to fear and the rules and
customs that govern the way in which fear is experienced and expressed’,125 in
other words to look even further into how security works. Fortunately, CSS has
two theoretical approaches that do this: on the one hand, securitization theory,
focusing mainly on the manner in which public fears are called upon, and, on
the other, the Foucauldian governmentality approach to risk that studies how
vulnerability is translated into routine and everyday risks and thereby governs
society.
Besides this ethical implication, we are also left with a methodological herme-
neutic critique: that between a strict observer who observes what actors them-
selves see as a security practice and a more judgemental observer who decides
when something truly is a successful security speech act – in this case, when
extraordinary measures are adopted.155 This is a split which, according to Ciută,
originates from a double definition of the term security in the original theory,
where security is defined simultaneously intersubjectively in-between the agents
themselves and by the security analyst in terms of survival, extraordinarity and
existentialism.156 This complicates the theory and combined with its notion of
success makes it turn from a theory and method into a model, a static one that
could blind scholars to the other logics of security at work in their case
studies.157
The EU’s energy dependence is of course not new. But it did gain an added
dimension in the light of recent geopolitical events, i.e. the crisis in
Ukraine. Temporary disruptions of gas supplies in the winters of 2006 and
2009 already provided a wake-up call for the EU, underlining the need of
infrastructure development, increased cooperation and of a common Euro-
pean energy policy.168
With the events in Ukraine, Europe is facing a threat to its peace, stability
and security the likes of which we have not seen since the fall of the Iron
Curtain. The ‘Great Game’ of geopolitics has made an unwelcome return
and this is being particularly felt in the area of energy.… In fact the
Ukraine crisis once again shows that for Europe energy independence is
crucial.169
In both cases, the Ukraine crises are clearly used by speech actors. But they are
not used to securitize a new issue. They are not even put forward as new threats.
Instead they are voiced as self-evident, as threats for which the audience accept-
ance is taken for granted. In these high-level notifications, the crises are used to
reinforce the existing securitized issue of energy dependency and to legitimize
existing and new political and institutional arrangements dealing with that. As
Barroso argued:
There were many times in which we … were pleading for a truly European
energy policy. The reality is that because there were probably other prior-
ities at the time … minds were not sufficiently focused on the urgency of a
real energy policy for the EU. But because of these recent developments, I
believe now minds are focused and we could now make more progress than
in the years before.170
In line with the strict perspective on speech acts in securitization theory, this
form of bureaucratic agenda setting can be regarded as a securitizing move (as it
82 Securing undesired (energy) futures
lacks the extraordinarity of securitization). This is similar to earlier conclusions
by other scholars on the applicability of the theory to the 2006 and 2009
Ukraine–Russia gas crises,171 simply because they cannot confirm whether the
measures enacted in response are truly exceptional. More integration, back-up
capacity, strategic reserves, or a diversification of suppliers and resources are not
exceptional because these measures have been in place even before Churchill’s
famous statement in 1913 that ‘safety and certainty in oil lie in variety and
variety alone’.172 The events and their interpretations therefore do not break
with the already-accepted routine security measures. They are integrated into
an existing perception of insecurity and subsequently used to reinforce the
underlying social and material dynamics of a fossil fuel system and the com-
munity that lies at its core – in this case a European community as favoured by
the European Commission.173
At the same time, such wake-up calls do enable additional institutional and
financial measures that might not have been possible otherwise. In the words of
Barroso, minds are focused once more, and the urgency of insecurity pushes
other items from the agenda, opens up additional budget and enables a stretch-
ing of the original mandate. In response to the 2006 and 2009 interruptions, the
EU pushed for preventive action plans, further integration of the EU internal
gas and energy markets and introduced the Third Energy Package, which
includes a clause that inhibits international parties (read Gazprom) from buying
into European upstream markets without reciprocity on its own markets. The
first two measures in particular, through which the European Commission
encroached on the energy security mandate of the member states, had little
institutional backing before these interruptions.174 These initiatives were fol-
lowed by an extensive EU programme on infrastructure priorities and added the
concept of energy solidarity to the Lisbon Treaty (nowadays extended to an
overall European Energy Union). Similarly, in response to the early 2014
Russia–Ukraine conflict the European Council tasked the Commission to come
up with a revised European Energy Security Strategy before June 2014. For
Trombetta, this request and the time pressure behind it enabled the Commis-
sion to put forward its own community building project, as it combined the spe-
cific supply risks with broader environmental and socio-economic concerns and
thereby strengthened the Commission’s claim for a stronger mandate on Euro-
pean energy policy.175 Then again, Natorski and Surrallés disagree and have
argued that this initial communitarian call on security in effect undermines the
Commissions position, because a successful framing of the events in a particular
neorealist geopolitical security frame reinforces the intergovernmental mandate
of the member states themselves.176
The tension between, on the one hand, a neorealist geopolitical security per-
spective on energy supplies and, on the other hand, the depoliticized measures
proposed to deal with energy security threats fits well with the theory’s norm-
ative position that securitized issues should be approached from a desecuritiza-
tion logic. The problem being that securitization is only helpful in analysing
(and thereby reifying) these and other geopolitical aspects of security and not
Securing undesired (energy) futures 83
the wide range of uncertainties found elsewhere in energy politics. Theoretic-
ally, only these explicit threats allow for successful securitization based on extra-
ordinary measures, whereas for oil and gas it is so far only possible to conclude
that ‘threats are successfully constructed, that construction has been accepted
by a relevant audience and often policy changes have followed’.177 Hardly ever
are these policy changes extraordinary. Is it extraordinary that the gas pipeline
from Ukraine to Slovakia is refitted for two-way transport, enabling the supply
of gas to Ukraine from Europe if needed? One can argue that without the per-
ception of supply risks this investment would not have been made as the market
would not have made it. On the other hand, it is a technical solution to resolve
the Ukraine plight temporarily by increasing the flexibility of the grid; it does
not tackle the root cause – dependency on and political intervention from
Russia – at all.
A last aspect of the use of securitization theory to explain EU–Russian
natural gas relations has to do with the ‘other’ and the referent object. The
‘other’ in the case above, for many is self-evident. But is it? At first glance, the
idea of supply disruption due to Russia’s political control of its gas exports
merits seeing Russian political elites as the other. However, such a perspective
excludes the role played by the Ukrainian government, which decided to tap
its share from European deliveries. It also excludes the role played by European
member states, for example Germany, and their bilateral agreements with
Russia. In other words, the ‘other’ is made to be Russia. In addition, while the
above is written from the idea of a securitizing move on supply disruptions,
from the implicit undesired future of scarcity, Trombetta argues that, while
important, this was not the main referent object in the securitizing move for
the European Commission. For the Commission, ‘[t]he threat was posed not
directly by Russia or by the scarcity issue but by what Russia represented and by
the reaction to the possibility of a return of geopolitics’.178 The threat for the
Commission, besides the supply disruptions, relates to Russia’s geopolitical
realist approach to international relations, which contrasts with the European
Union’s neo-liberal faith in trade and international institutions. From
this argument, it is a threat to both what we need and who we are. If one pushes
this point, then the claim would be that without the geopolitical realist pol-
icies of Russia the Commission has no ‘other’ to justify a ‘self ’ (on this issue at
least).179
This brief reflection on EU–Russia natural gas relations through the lens of
securitization theory highlights its workings as well as its strengths and weak-
nesses. On the one hand, the EU–Russia gas illustration shows why securitiza-
tion theory is considered elitist, realist and statist.180 It is most easily applicable
to cases like traditional energy security of supply concerns, where the debate is
structured and organized on a national level by governments and with a clearly
identifiable ‘other’. Similarly, the above clearly shows the difficulties in catego-
rizing the counter measures in terms of exceptionality, especially as the proposed
countermeasures are market-oriented and hence non-political, thereby desecuri-
tizing the issue the moment it is securitized. On the other hand, the theory
84 Securing undesired (energy) futures
helps pinpoint at least part of the politics of security, including the active pro-
duction of security issues and the analysis and definition of the threat in line
with the history and language it builds on by naming the other, while fixating
the referent object and reinforcing the self.
Such a linguistic contextualized understanding helps explain why the same illo-
cutionary speech act can have different perlocutionary consequences for
different audiences.194 It explains for example why the US security claims for
the most recent Iraq War were interpreted differently in the US and in parts of
Europe. The exception in these cases is always local and relative, a form of pol-
itics that plays out at the same time, in different places for different people.
Both Huysmans’s rupture and Stritzel’s translation will be taken up in the next
chapters when discussing the materiality of energy and the ontological politics
around it.
To sum up, securitization theory offers an analysis of how security works as a
social mechanism through the speech act of moving something out of the
regular political debate into the exceptionality of security. The theory is ques-
tioned from two directions: first, in terms of the meaning of exceptionality (vs
politics) and the absence of any contextualization and, second, in relation to
the theory’s double methodological positions and the normativity of these posi-
tions and assumptions. By taking on the same questions that securitization
theory has introduced and has been openly struggling with, Huysmans, Vuori,
Stritzel and Balzacq offer interesting additions and alternatives to the speech act
theory that opens the focus of the theory to broader social contexts and to com-
parable logics that do not depend on the word security as such. This broader
approach fits the field of energy security better, as energy security sees a lot of
securitizing moves but hardly any strict securitization in terms of exceptionality.
It is hard to find exceptionality, because there are very few crises in energy (and
other fields) that, one way or another, have not seen any preparation. These
preparations, which are based on imaginations and an abstraction of scarcity
and shortages, lead to a politics of energy security. Security in energy, or energy
security, is not just the moment of crisis itself but the routine prevention of the
next crisis. This makes it a form of politics where security arguments are used to
dramatize an issue to justify investments for one course of action over another.
Nevertheless, if we ignore the focus on successfulness, securitization theory
remains one of the more interesting perspectives on security owing to its focus
on the securitizing moves and the speech acts behind those moves. Speech acts
are an interesting method to highlight how, within the political domain, actors
are dramatizing issues through a call on security logics by which they claim
scarce resources and the time to tackle their preferred issue. It bears reminding
Securing undesired (energy) futures 87
that, although the theory helps to explain how security comes to be, it does
not provide reasons why it does. It only shows the politics of security, the con-
struction of a (self-evident) need to counter an undesirable future. Simultan-
eously, by using insights from securitization theory it becomes possible to analyse
both routine practices and moments of rupture. And, instead of putting one
before the other, Bourbeau is correct when he argues that ‘the social world we
live in is a world of feedback’, where speech acts and routine security practices
are acting together ‘in a complex and wider range of ways’.195 The next section
therefore will take up a theory that looks at a more routine security practice
named risk.
The arrest and detention of travellers at the border, the freezing of financial
transactions, the pre-emptive disruption of plots and indictment of suspects,
the stopping and searching of young Muslim men in the city subway, the
entry of a name onto a selectee list [or the kill orders for a drone attack] –
all advance an invisible political violence, taking unaccountable and often
unchallengeable decisions.257
4.6 Reflection
The goal of this chapter was threefold. First, to give a potential explanation for
the proliferation of energy security concerns. Second, to unpack the notion of
security in order to problematize its use in the field of energy security. And,
third, closely related, to introduce and provide an overview of the recent
insights from critical security studies as a basis to push energy security analyses
beyond its realist, liberalist and securitization applications. The subsequent sec-
tions offered insights into the multiple logics of security, the ethics of security,
the manner in which security is called upon, and the exercise of power inherent
to the calculation of risk. Together these sections present security as a form of
governing the present based on an imagination of undesired futures.
In pushing the recent literature on security, this chapter started by approach-
ing security in its broadest sense as dealing with and deciding upon undesired
futures. A logical consequence of such a broad definition is the possibility to
observe a more extensive range of different insecurities or undesirable futures,
the techniques used to imagine and decide on that undesirability and the logics
of security that drive the application of these techniques and search for counter-
measures. Together, these techniques and logics help make sense of the future
and make people act performatively in the here and now. The security logics are
both inclusionary and exclusionary. They are inclusionary as there is always
another unknown potentially threatening future, just as failed countermeasures
only inspire to do better. While these logics are inclusionary and help make
sense of events, they do not define the issues at stake. Instead, interpretations
shift and depend on the agent’s position and relation to the referent object.
Hence, security is exclusionary as the identification of an undesired future
always builds on a politics that excludes those not part of the security arrange-
ment. Such normative judgements create ruptures, which are reinforced by the
countermeasures that are enacted. Security was reasoned to be a form of ethics
itself, shaping and reinforcing the interpretation of an event, the image of the
other, the referent object and oneself. The security of undesirable futures is thus
not only epistemological but strongly ontological as well. It is the choice of
what to protect and what not to protect, or, more importantly, the choice
between what to see as a threat and what not to see as a threat.
Security is something that is made; it does not exist out there but is called
upon or written by politicians, concerned citizens, security experts, insurers etc.
To understand the identification of undesired futures, this chapter focused on
the emotion of fear (and desire) as well as the explicit use of fear in political
contexts. Through a separation of private and public fears, it becomes possible
to see the emotive and political use of fear, more specifically how public fears
Securing undesired (energy) futures 97
build upon a depoliticized idea of private fear by linking the individual to the
collective, while decoupling the private experience of fear from the social call
upon fear. Together with an increasing epistemic and ontic uncertainty that
triggers an autopoietic fear for fear itself, this leads to a situation where the
existence of political fears cannot be proven wrong. Besides, while it only works
when called upon, the above makes clear that almost everybody calls on security
and thus engages or is subject to to security practices. Clearly, not all calls are
successful, but in today’s culture of fear that seems to be of less importance as
the calls always already succeed in reinforcing the desire for more security.
Moreover, contrary to an individual private experience of fear, where the
undesirable future and its opposite (the desired future) are identified in response
to a bodily reaction, in the case of public fear there is a more intentional logic
at work where particular desired futures are identified before their current state is
publicized as undesirable and something to be feared.
The call upon security was analysed more closely through a study of the
insights provided by securitization theory and its singular focus on the excep-
tionality of security over normal politics. With the concepts of speech acts,
securitizing moves and securitization, this theory helps to understand and study
how people call on security. While the theory highlights the process of how
something becomes a security issue, it does not provide the reasons why par-
ticular issues are called on and hence should not be used as such. More gener-
ally, there are questions on the conflation of the theory and methodology of
securitization, its normativity and its focus on exceptionality and lack of
context. Still, the theory, as well as its different critiques, highlight the politics
behind security instead of the outcome of such processes. Behind the self-
evident threats lies the active politics of multiple audiences, multiple speech
actors and multiple issues that are securitized. In addition, besides showing the
activity that goes into making something a security issue, the theory also opens
up the relationality behind the self–other distinction.
While securitization has proven useful to analyse energy security, it struggles
with the routine nature of energy security. Energy definitely has extraordinary
moments, but most of the time it is characterized by practices that try to secure
the daily functioning of its sources and systems. The reflection on risk with its
focus on routine security practices and its underlying risk calculations offered an
alternative theory. Risk was described as a performative practice that identifies
and problematizes uncertainty as contingency following mobile norms of
security that can only be managed, not overcome. Through its statistical
methods, risk makes the unknown real as it imagines, calculates and visualizes
the future. These commodified ‘facts’ are repeated in speeches and used as argu-
ments in decision-making processes. Financial insurance schemes aimed at risk
minimization thus actively shape how individuals organize their daily lives:
what they buy, say and do. The use of risk calculation was problematized by
highlighting the growing political role of risk underwriters and ICT experts and
the shifting accountability following recent changes in risk calculation from
probable to possible risks.
98 Securing undesired (energy) futures
Both theories discuss a particular logic of security, respectively a threat
rationality and a logic and technique of risk, but both agree that security is an
exercise of power that is called upon by people who decide on its boundaries.
Yet, where the risk logic accepts an increasing level of contingency, a threat
logic actively resists such contingency. At the same time, the risk literature can
only ascribe probability to an already-identified undesired future but cannot
explain how something becomes a threat nor how particular thresholds of risk
are set. In turn, the speech act-inspired security literature is unable to move
away from the exceptional threat to the routine of everyday security and safety
practices that are also inherent to these threats. Clearly, we need to understand
the normative and instrumental characteristics of security and risk, as both
security and risk ‘do … things rather than merely name things’.264 Equally
importantly, they both approach events from a how question, with neither offer-
ing reasons or generalized conclusions that can be used predictively.
What this chapter means for energy security is manifold. At the beginning,
this chapter stated that it is very well possible to read this chapter by just
adding the word energy whenever it spoke of security. While that might push
it, this chapter makes a clear case for moving away from a ‘simple’ goal-oriented
definition of energy security to an understanding of energy security that is
called upon every time it is used. This chapter thus supports the initial reflec-
tions in the chapters on energy security to move beyond the search for a better
understanding of the content of energy security, to the actual political work
that is done to get particular forms of energy security accepted as a security
concern. Energy security is made to be, by elites, (insurance) companies,
academia (including observing energy security scholars) and the public. It is
not some natural state of affairs. Many of the issues raised in the first two chap-
ters, on the proliferation of the concept, the geopolitical and state-centric
focus, and the uncritical theorization, can be placed in context now. At the
same time, this chapter also shows that energy security does exist. In line with
Ciută (energy) security is not a banal process; it is very much the opposite.
While everything is constantly performed, there are concerns, like Russian gas,
that can be called on much easier and with a much larger backing and audi-
ence than others, because they fit historical insecurities or because they are
materialized in such a way that they could affect many. The difference between
traditional theories of energy security and the theories on security that were
discussed in this chapter is that the latter acknowledge that they themselves
play a role in the process of securing energy while analysing these processes and
the conditions behind them. In this way, they introduce an understanding of
energy security that is socially performed and never the same, yet made to be
so, while functioning as an exercise of power with strong normative
consequences.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 99
Notes
1 This chapter discusses security, not energy security. However, as a logic it is possible
to read this chapter almost from the beginning to end and just add the word energy
before the word security to make it into a discussion on energy security.
2 Booth 2005, 23, as quoted by C.A.S.E. Collective 2006, 456.
3 Buzan 1983, 19.
4 Brauch 2011, 99.
5 Booth 2007, 95–101.
6 Zedner 2003; Booth 2007, 105–106.
7 Such a debate about what is acceptable or real, points to a ontopolitics of (in)
security.
8 Zedner 2003, 157, quoting Macbeth, Act III.
9 Der Derian 1995, 28–29.
10 Ibid.
11 Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008.
12 Dillon 1996, 33 (emphasis in original); also Neocleous 2008, 28.
13 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 32.
14 Anderson 2010b, 779. Also Anderson 2010a; Massumi 2007.
15 Burgess 2011, 26.
16 Anderson 2010b, 781.
17 Anderson and Adey 2011.
18 Booth 2007, 104; Svendsen 2008.
19 Anderson 2010a, 778 (emphasis in original), quoting Massumi 2007, n.p.
20 Luhmann 1993.
21 See Anderson 2010a.
22 Alternatively, Daase and Kessler 2007 argue for a categorization of uncertainty built
upon four categories of knowledge. In their article these authors differentiate
between known knowns (meaning actual threats that provide a clear basis for
action), known unknowns (risks where the ontic structure is blurred but methods
exist to diminish these unknowns), unknown unknowns (dangers in the form of
uncertainty) and unknown knowns (ignored or forgotten actual threats). Daase and
Kessler thus approach the concepts of risk, uncertainty, danger and threat from a
systemic perspective by showing the ontic and epistemic differences between these
categories.
23 Anderson 2010a, 789.
24 On surprise and the politics of events, see Section 4.5.
25 Knight 1921; Best 2008; Kessler 2012.
26 Keynes 1921. Compare with Barad in Section 5.5.
27 Kessler and Daase 2008.
28 Best 2008, 356. Best argues that linguistic ambiguity has three functions: it could
actually help govern forms of epistemic uncertainty, it could also be used as an
instrument to govern through, and, lastly, it poses a limit to the actual governance
that can take place.
29 Latour 2005, 244; Bennett 2010; Adorno 1973. For a discussion on Latour’s plasma,
see Harman 2009, 132–134.
30 Rasmussen 2004, 393. See also: Luhmann 1993, 21–22; Beck 2002, 41; Corry 2012.
31 Buzan 1983, 83–84.
32 Wæver 1995.
33 Massumi 2009, 162.
34 Burgess 2011, 61.
35 Luhmann 1993, 107.
36 Ibid., 109.
37 Ibid., 119 (emphasis in original).
100 Securing undesired (energy) futures
38 Ibid., 68.
39 Vergragt and Quist 2011.
40 Linstone and Turoff 2002; Mullen 2003.
41 Mietzner and Reger 2005.
42 Davis 2002.
43 Ibid., 1.
44 De Goede and Randalls 2009, 869.
45 For an overview of different types of scenarios: Mietzner and Reger 2005, 225–227.
46 Salter 2008a, 233.
47 Ibid., 235–236.
48 Grusin 2004; De Goede 2008a.
49 Malthus 1798.
50 Linstone 2011.
51 Subrahmaniyan 2008. Other expectations predicted prices of $300 a barrel in ten to
fifteen years: Korosec 2009, 2011.
52 Anderson 2010a, 784.
53 Amoore 2013, 73.
54 Salter 2008a, 233.
55 Luhmann 1993, 2.
56 Amoore 2013, 73.
57 Anderson 2010a, 786.
58 IEA 2014.
59 Rumsfeld 2002; Daase and Kessler 2007.
60 Daase and Kessler 2007.
61 Massumi 2007.
62 Ibid., para. 7 (emphasis in original).
63 Ibid., 13.
64 Ibid.
65 Also Amoore 2013; Amoore and De Goede 2008c; De Goede 2008b, 2008c, 2011;
De Goede and Randalls 2009; Anderson 2010a, 791.
66 Anderson 2010a, 791.
67 Massumi 2007, note 9.
68 Ibid., paras 17–20; Anderson 2010a, 791.
69 Anderson 2010a, 791; Commission of the European Communities 2000.
70 UNESCO World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Techno-
logy 2005, 14.
71 Bigo 2010, 11; Ravetz 2004.
72 See also Anderson 2010a, 791.
73 Ibid., 792; Collier and Lakoff 2015, 2008b.
74 Evans and Reid 2013.
75 Booth 1991; UNDP 1994.
76 Beck 1992, 2002.
77 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998.
78 Bigo 2002; Balzacq et al. 2010; Dillon 1996; Huysmans 2011; Dillon and Lobo-
Guerrero 2008; Amoore and De Goede 2008b; De Goede 2012; Amoore 2013.
79 Massumi 2009, 161.
80 Ibid.
81 Luhmann 1993.
82 Massumi 2009, 162.
83 Ibid.
84 Ibid., 161.
85 Campbell 1998, 3.
86 Dillon 1996, 122. Italics added.
87 Ibid., 35.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 101
88 Burgess 2011, 4. See also Browning and McDonald 2013.
89 Booth 1991, 2007.
90 Booth 2007, 256, 348–392.
91 Ibid., 98.
92 Foucault 2007.
93 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998.
94 Ibid.; Wæver 1995.
95 Neocleous 2008.
96 Leander 2003; Leander 2005. See also C.A.S.E. Collective 2006, 464.
97 See also Åhäll and Gregory 2013.
98 On ontological security, see Wendt 1999, 131.
99 Svendsen 2008, 12.
100 Ibid., 13–16, 71.
101 Frost 2010, 160.
102 Ibid., 167–170; Svendsen 2008, 35–37.
103 Frost 2010, 169.
104 Ibid., 160.
105 Robin 2004, 16–18.
106 Ibid., 19.
107 Furedi 2007.
108 Robin 2004, 6, 9.
109 Furedi 2007.
110 Ibid.
111 Svendsen 2008, 52–53.
112 Massumi 2005, 36.
113 Ibid. quotes William, James. 1950. Principles of Psychology, vol. 2. New York: Dover,
449–450, 467.
114 Ibid., 38.
115 Ibid., 40.
116 Ibid., 41.
117 Furedi 2007.
118 Massumi 2005, 45–46.
119 Furedi 2005, chap. 7.
120 Furedi 2007.
121 Ibid.
122 Furedi 2008, 2005, 2007.
123 Furedi 2005, chap. 7, in particular 137 and 139.
124 Burgess 2011, 62.
125 Furedi 2007.
126 Booth 2007, 325.
127 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998. The securitization framework also contains a
level of analysis focus, a sectorial focus and regional security theory.
128 This argument on materiality will be taken up in Chapter 5.
129 See also: Latour 2004.
130 Schmitt 1985, 5; see also Neal 2006.
131 Austin 1975. Austin differentiates within a speech act between: locutionary acts
that are the utterances; illocutionary acts or that what is done in saying (shifting
discourse to exceptionality); and perlocutionary acts or that what is done by saying
(effects on target audience). Balzacq 2005, 175, quotes Habermas: ‘To say some-
thing, to act in saying something, to bring about something through acting in saying
something’.
132 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 27.
133 Ibid., 32.
134 Roe 2008; Vuori 2008; Balzacq 2005.
102 Securing undesired (energy) futures
135 Besides the securitizing actors, referent objects and the audiences that accept the
securitization move, the theory also mentions functional agents, actors not actively
involved in the securitization process but profoundly influencing the issue
nevertheless.
136 Compare with Latour 2004 on matters of fact (non-political) and matters of
concern (political/security).
137 On speed and silence, see Roe 2012. However, see the earlier discussion on
Neocleous 2008.
138 Booth 2007, 106.
139 Ibid., 107. Compare with recent work on scarcity and abundance that defines abun-
dance as the ability to choose wrongly, see Mullainathan and Shafir 2013.
140 Wæver 2011, 467.
141 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 29; Roe 2012; de Wilde 2012.
142 Wæver 1995, 54. Compare with Ciută 2009.
143 Aradau 2008, 72.
144 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 29.
145 Ibid.
146 de Wilde 2012, 213, 2008.
147 de Wilde 2012, 213.
148 Ibid.
149 Ibid.
150 Wæver 2011, 469; Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 29.
151 Hansen 2000, 2012.
152 Hansen 2012. She actually identifies four options of desecuritization: stabilization,
replacement, rearticulation and silencing.
153 Huysmans 1998b.
154 Wæver 1999, 334.
155 Roe 2008; Salter 2008b; Stritzel 2007.
156 Ciută 2009; Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 27.
157 Huysmans 1998b, 501; Wæver 2011, 469.
158 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998.
159 Nyman 2014.
160 Leung et al. 2014.
161 Christou and Adamides 2013.
162 Judge and Maltby 2017.
163 For specific applications of securitization theory on the Russian and European
energy relationship, see: Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008; Stoddard 2012;
Khrushcheva 2011; Radoman 2007; Boersma 2013; McGowan 2011; Trombetta
2012. For more general energy security reflections on Russia and the European
Union, see: Aalto 2008; Aalto and Korkmaz Temel 2014; Casier 2011; Goldthau
2008; Högselius 2012; Stern 2006. And for good use of the theory in relation to
other countries, see: Nyman 2014; Christou and Adamides 2013; Leung et al. 2014;
Nyman and Zeng 2016; Judge and Maltby 2017; Judge, Maltby and Szulecki 2018;
Cox 2016; Aglaya Snetkov 2017; Fischhendler and Nathan 2014.
164 Stern 2006.
165 Smith Stegen 2011; McGowan 2011; Boersma 2013; European Commission 2000.
166 McGowan 2011.
167 Stoddard 2012.
168 European Commission 2014.
169 Barroso 2014.
170 Ibid.
171 Boersma 2013, 37; McGowan 2011, 488; Trombetta 2012, 22.
172 Yergin 1991.
173 Trombetta 2012.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 103
174 Ibid., 16.
175 Trombetta 2012; for the theoretical argument, see Huysmans 1998a.
176 Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008, 84.
177 Trombetta 2012, 9.
178 Ibid., 21.
179 Huysmans 1998b, 239.
180 Ciută 2009; McDonald 2008; Stritzel 2007; Balzacq 2005.
181 Ciută 2009.
182 Butler 2010, 149 (emphasis added).
183 Neal 2006, 34.
184 Patomäki 2015, 133.
185 Balzacq 2005, 178–179. Interestingly, in this article Balzacq also argues, with
numerous disclaimers, that there are non-social, ‘brute’ threats that affect humans
‘regardless of the use of language’ (181). He argues that these external effects/threats
should stand central in any constructivist analysis of security (181) as these are used
by the audience as evidence in weighing securitization claims thereby reducing the
importance of the speaker (191, 193); Bigo 2002, 2014.
186 Bigo 2014, 211; Bourbeau 2014, 196.
187 Bigo 2014.
188 See note 131 on Austin and Habermas.
189 Vuori 2008, 76; Stritzel 2012.
190 Huysmans 2011, 372, 373; Isin 2008.
191 Stritzel 2011.
192 Ibid., 346.
193 Neal 2006, 44.
194 Stritzel 2011, 350.
195 Bourbeau 2014, 197.
196 A recent exception includes Judge and Maltby 2017.
197 Foucault 2007, 2008; Luhmann 1993, 13; C.A.S.E. Collective 2006, 468.
198 Salter 2008a, 233 explicitly mentions scarce resource management: ‘Risk manage-
ment as a governance framework seeks to focus scarce resources on risks that are
ranked according to frequency and impact’.
199 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 9. Dean 2010, 206–207 argues, contra Beck, that
because risks is about making future threats calculable, there is no such thing as
incalculable risks. If something is incalculable it cannot be a risk.
200 Ewald 1991, 199.
201 Ibid.
202 Butler 2010; Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 9.
203 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 11, quoting Foucault 2007, 68 and 91.
204 See also Ewald 1993, 221.
205 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 9, quoting Valverde, M., and M. Mopas. 2004. Insec-
urity and the dream of targeted governance. In Global governmentality: Governing
international spaces, edited by W. Larner and W. Walters, 233–250. London:
Routledge; De Goede 2012.
206 As Dean argues: ‘Risk is a continuum rather than a clear break. Risk, in this sense,
never completely evaporates. It can be minimized, localized and avoided, but never
dissipated’. 2010, 195.
207 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 9.
208 Dean 2010, 206–207.
209 Lobo-Guerrero 2012, 10.
210 Ewald 1991. Also Ewald 1993, 2002, 2012.
211 Ewald 1991, 206.
212 Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 281.
213 Ewald 1991, 201–205.
104 Securing undesired (energy) futures
214 Ibid., 202.
215 Dean 2010, 214.
216 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 25–26.
217 Dillon 2007, 45.
218 Lobo-Guerrero 2012, 128–129.
219 Ibid., 18.
220 Dillon 2008, 327; Foucault 2007, 20.
221 Lobo-Guerrero 2012, 128; Nancy 2000.
222 Foucault 1991, 76.
223 Ibid.
224 Lundborg 2012, 1–7.
225 Ibid., 7.
226 Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 280–281; Dillon 2008, 320.
227 Ewald 1993, 227.
228 Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 287. Elsewhere, Dillon describes how biopolitical
security builds upon biological complex systems theories, à la Kauffman, to describe
life as being about circulation (autocatalysis), connectivity (radical relationality)
and complexity (non-linearity). See Dillon 2008, 312.
229 Dillon 2008, 314–315, 2007; Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 280 and 283.
230 Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 268; Lobo-Guerrero 2012, 18.
231 Foucault 2007, 18.
232 Butler 2004; Amoore 2013, 6. As also discussed in De Goede 2008b, 101. Compare
with Shannon 2014, 252.
233 Dean 2010, 259.
234 Amoore 2013, 6–7, 17–18.
235 Ewald 1993, 225.
236 Ibid.
237 Lobo-Guerrero 2012, 18.
238 Ibid.
239 Dean 2010, 220.
240 Ibid., 218–219.
241 See for example Lobo-Guerrero 2012.
242 Dean 2010, 221.
243 Aradau and Van Munster 2007, 92.
244 Rose 2001, 11; Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 27.
245 Collier and Lakoff 2015, 2008b, 2008a.
246 Kester 2018.
247 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 27–28.
248 Ewald 1993, 222; Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 27.
249 Beck 1992.
250 Aradau and Van Munster 2007, 106–107.
251 Amoore 2013, 9–10. In respect to information, Amoore (p. 85) also discusses how
risk analyses, for example during border control, increasingly reject people based on
information that would not have been acceptable in court, thereby effectively
judging people outside the law.
252 Prevention is acting without imminent threat (in conflict a preventive war is legally
deemed an act of aggression). Pre-emption is acting before an imminent threat
materializes and as such is seen as the more justifiable tactic. See also Massumi
2009, 168.
253 Aradau and Van Munster 2007, 103; Amoore 2013, 9.
254 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 29.
255 Aradau and Van Munster 2008, 35.
256 Aradau and Van Munster 2007, 109.
257 Amoore and De Goede 2008a, 14.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 105
258 Amoore 2013, 9; Amoore and De Goede 2008b; Aradau and Van Munster 2007,
2008; De Goede 2008b.
259 Amoore 2013, 67–68 (emphasis in original).
260 Ibid.
261 Ibid., 69–70, 103.
262 Ibid., 17.
263 Ibid., 20–21.
264 Dillon 1996, 34.
Bibliography
Aalto, Pami. 2008. The EU-Russian energy dialogue: Europe’s future energy security. Alder-
shot: Ashgate.
Aalto, Pami, and Dicle Korkmaz Temel. 2014. European energy security: Natural gas and
the integration process. Journal of Common Market Studies 52 (4): 758–774.
Adorno, Theodor W. 1973. Negative dialectics, translated by E. B. Ashton. London:
Routledge.
Aglaya Snetkov. 2017. Theories, methods and practices – a longitudinal spatial analysis
of the (de)securitization of the insurgency threat in Russia. Security Dialogue 48 (3):
259–275.
Åhäll, Linda, and Thomas A. Gregory. 2013. Security, emotions, affect. Critical Studies
on Security 1 (1): 117–120.
Amoore, Louise. 2013. The politics of possibility: Risk and security beyond probability.
Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Amoore, Louise, and Marieke de Goede. 2008a. Introduction: Governing by risk in the
war on terror. In Risk and the war on terror, edited by Louise Amoore and Marieke de
Goede, 5–20. London and New York: Routledge.
Amoore, Louise, and Marieke de Goede. 2008b. Risk and the war on terror. London and
New York: Routledge.
Amoore, Louise, and Marieke de Goede. 2008c. Transactions after 9/11: The banal face of
the preemptive strike. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 33 (2): 173–185.
Anderson, Ben. 2010a. Preemption, precaution, preparedness: Anticipatory action and
future geographies. Progress in Human Geography 34 (6): 777–798.
Anderson, Ben. 2010b. Security and the future: Anticipating the event of terror. Geofo-
rum 41 (2): 227–235.
Anderson, Ben, and Peter Adey. 2011. Affect and security: Exercising emergency in ‘UK
civil contingencies’. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 29 (6): 1092–1109.
Aradau, Claudia. 2008. Rethinking trafficking in women: Politics out of security. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Aradau, Claudia, and Rens van Munster. 2007. Governing terrorism through risk: Taking
precautions, (un)knowing the future. European Journal of International Relations 13 (1):
89–115.
Aradau, Claudia, and Rens van Munster. 2008. Taming the future: The dispositif of risk
in the war on terror. In Risk and the war on terror, edited by Louise Amoore and
Marieke de Goede, 23–40. London and New York: Routledge.
Austin, J. L. 1975. How to do things with words: J. L. Austin, edited by J. O. Urmson and
M. Sbisá. 2nd edn. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Balzacq, Thierry. 2005. The three faces of securitization: Political agency, audience and
context. European Journal of International Relations 11 (2): 171–201.
106 Securing undesired (energy) futures
Balzacq, Thierry, Tugba Basaran, Didier Bigo, Emmanuel-Pierre Guittet and Christian
Olsson. 2010. Security practices. In International Studies Encyclopedia Online, edited by
Robert A. Denemark. Oxford: Blackwell. Available from www.blackwellreference.
com/public/book.html?id=g9781444336597_9781444336597.
Barroso, Jose Manuel Durao. 2014. Speech by President Barroso at the conference ‘Paving the
way for a European energy security strategy’. Speech. Brussels: European Commission.
Beck, Ulrich. 1992. Risk society: Towards a new modernity. London: SAGE.
Beck, Ulrich. 2002. The Terrorist Threat: World Risk Society Revisited. Theory, Culture
& Society 19 (4): 39–55.
Bennett, Jane. 2010. Vibrant matter: A political ecology of things. Durham, NC, and
London: Duke University Press.
Best, Jacqueline. 2008. Ambiguity, uncertainty, and risk: Rethinking indeterminacy.
International Political Sociology 2 (4): 355–374.
Bigo, Didier. 2002. Security and immigration: Toward a critique of the governmentality
of unease. Alternatives: Global, Local, Political 27 (special issue): 63–92.
Bigo, Didier. 2010. The future perfect of (in)security (P8): Pre-crime strategy, proactiv-
ity, preemption, prevention, precaution, profiling, prediction, & privacy. Interdisci-
plines. Available from www.interdisciplines.org/paper.php?paperID=342. Accessed 2
November 2014.
Bigo, Didier. 2014. The (in)securitization practices of the three universes of EU border
control: Military/Navy – border guards/police – database analysts. Security Dialogue 45
(3): 209–225.
Boersma, Tim. 2013. Dealing with energy security in Europe: A comparison of gas market pol-
icies in the European Union and the United States. PhD thesis, Groningen: University of
Groningen.
Booth, Ken. 1991. Security and emancipation. Review of International Studies 17 (4):
313–326.
Booth, Ken. 2005. Security. In Critical security studies and world politics, edited by Ken
Booth, 21–25. London: Lynne Rienner.
Booth, Ken. 2007. Theory of world security. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Bourbeau, Philippe. 2014. Moving forward together: Logics of the securitisation process.
Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 187–206.
Brauch, Hans Günter. 2011. Concepts of security threats, challenges, vulnerabilities and
risks. In Coping with global environmental change, disasters and security, edited by
Hans Günter Brauch, Úrsula Oswald Spring, Czeslaw Mesjasz, John Grin, Patricia
Kameri-Mbote, Béchir Chourou, Pál Dunay and Jörn Birkmann, 61–106. Berlin and
Heidelberg: Springer.
Browning, Christopher S., and Matt McDonald. 2013. The future of critical security
studies: Ethics and the politics of security. European Journal of International Relations 19
(2): 235–255.
Burgess, J. Peter. 2011. The ethical subject of security: Geopolitical reason and the threat
against Europe. London and New York: Routledge.
Butler, Judith. 2004. Precarious life: The powers of mourning and violence. London and New
York: Verso.
Butler, Judith. 2010. Performative agency. Journal of Cultural Economy 3 (2): 147–161.
Buzan, Barry. 1983. People, states, and fear: The national security problem in international
relations. Brighton: Wheatsheaf.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 107
Buzan, Barry, Ole Wæver and Jaap H. de Wilde. 1998. Security: A new framework for
analysis. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner.
Campbell, David. 1998. Writing security: United States foreign policy and the politics of iden-
tity. Revised edition. Manchester: University of Manchester Press.
C.A.S.E Collective. 2006. Critical approaches to security in Europe: A networked mani-
festo. Security Dialogue 37 (4): 443–487.
Casier, Tom. 2011. The rise of energy to the top of the EU–Russia agenda: From inter
dependence to dependence? Geopolitics 16 (3): 536–552.
Christou, Odysseas, and Constantinos Adamides. 2013. Energy securitization and dese-
curitization in the New Middle East. Security Dialogue 44 (5–6): 507–522.
Ciută, Felix. 2009. Security and the problem of context: A hermeneutical critique of
securitisation theory. Review of International Studies 35 (2): 301–26.
Collier, Stephen J., and Andrew Lakoff. 2008a. Distributed preparedness: The spatial
logic of domestic security in the United States. Environment and Planning D: Society
and Space 26 (1): 7–28.
Collier, Stephen J., and Andrew Lakoff. 2008b. The vulnerability of vital systems: How
‘critical infrastructure’ became a security problem. In The politics of securing the home-
land: Critical infrastructure, risk and securitisation, edited by Myriam Dunn Cavelty,
40–62. London and New York: Routledge.
Collier, Stephen J., and Andrew Lakoff. 2015. Vital systems security: Reflexive biopoli-
tics and the government of emergency. Theory, Culture & Society 32 (2): 19–51.
Commission of the European Communities. 2000. Communication from the Commission:
on the precautionary principle. Brussels.
Corry, Olaf. 2012. Securitisation and ‘riskification’: Second-order security and the pol-
itics of climate change. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 40 (2): 235–258.
Cox, Emily. 2016. Opening the black box of energy security: A study of conceptions
of electricity security in the United Kingdom. Energy Research & Social Science 21
(Supplement C): 1–11.
Daase, Christopher, and Oliver Kessler. 2007. Knowns and unknowns in the war on
terror: Uncertainty and the political construction of danger. Security Dialogue 38 (4):
411–434.
Davis, Ged. 2002. Scenarios as a tool for the 21st century. Strathclyde University. Avail-
able from www.pik-potsdam.de/news/public-events/archiv/alter-net/former-ss/2006/
programme/31-08.2006/leemans/literature/davis_how_does_shell_do_scenarios.pdf.
Accessed 6 November 2014.
De Goede, Marieke. 2008a. Beyond risk: Premediation and the post-9/11 security imagi-
nation. Security Dialogue 39 (2–3): 155–176.
De Goede, Marieke. 2008b. Risk, preemption and exception in the war on terrorist
financing. In Risk and the war on terror, edited by Louise Amoore and Marieke de
Goede, 97–111. London and New York: Routledge.
De Goede, Marieke. 2008c. The politics of preemption and the war on terror in Europe.
European Journal of International Relations 14 (1): 161–185.
De Goede, Marieke. 2011. European security culture: Preemption and precaution in Euro-
pean security. Amsterdam: Amsterdam University Press.
De Goede, Marieke. 2012. Speculative security: The politics of pursuing terrorist monies.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
De Goede, Marieke, and Samuel Randalls. 2009. Precaution, preemption: Arts and tech-
nologies of the actionable future. Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 27 (5):
859–878.
108 Securing undesired (energy) futures
de Wilde, Jaap H. 2008. Environmental security deconstructed. In Globalization and
environmental challenges, edited by Hans Günter Brauch, Úrsula Oswald Spring, Habil
Czeslaw Mesjasz, John Grin, Pál Dunay, Navnita Chadha Behera, Béchir Chourou,
Patricia Kameri-Mbote and P. H. Liotta, 595–602. Hexagon series on human and
environmental security and peace 3. Berlin and Heidelberg: Springer.
de Wilde, Jaap H. 2012. Security and the environment: Securitisation theory and US
environmental security policy. By Rita Floyd. New York: Cambridge University Press,
2010. Perspectives on Politics 10 (1): 213–214.
Dean, Mitchell. 2010. Governmentality: Power and rule in modern society. 2nd edn.
London: SAGE.
Der Derian, James. 1995. The value of security: Hobbes, Marx, Nietzsche, and Baudril-
lard. In On security, edited by Ronnie D. Lipschutz, 24–45. New York: Columbia
University Press.
Dillon, Michael. 1996. Politics of security: Towards a political philosophy of continental
thought. London and New York: Routledge.
Dillon, Michael. 2007. Governing through contingency: The security of biopolitical gov-
ernance. Political Geography 26 (1): 41–47.
Dillon, Michael. 2008. Underwriting security. Security Dialogue 39 (2–3): 309–332.
Dillon, Michael, and Luis Lobo-Guerrero. 2008. Biopolitics of security in the 21st
century: An introduction. Review of International Studies 34 (02): 265–292.
European Commission. 2000. Green Paper: Towards a European strategy for the security of
energy supply. COM(2000) 769 final. Brussels: European Commission.
European Commission. 2014. Questions and answers on security of energy supply in the
EU. Memo.
Evans, Brad, and Julian Reid. 2013. Dangerously exposed: The life and death of the resil-
ient subject. Resilience 1 (2): 83–98.
Ewald, François. 1991. Insurance and risk. In The Foucault effect: Studies in governmental-
ity, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, 197–210. London:
Harvester Wheatsheaf.
Ewald, François. 1993. Two infinities of risk. In The politics of everyday fear, edited by
Brian Massumi, 221–8. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Ewald, François. 2002. The return of Descartes’s malicious demon: An outline of a philo-
sophy of precaution. In Embracing risk: The changing culture of insurance and responsib-
ility, edited by Tom Baker and Jonathan Simon, translated by Stephen Utz, 273–301.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Ewald, François. 2012. The future of risk – François Ewald ‘After Risk’. Available from
http://vimeo.com/48164425. Accessed 2 April 2014.
Fischhendler, Itay, and Daniel Nathan. 2014. In the name of energy security: The
struggle over the exportation of Israeli natural gas. Energy Policy 70: 152–162.
Foucault, Michel. 1991. Questions of method. In The Foucault effect: Studies in govern-
mentality, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, 73–86.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Foucault, Michel. 2007. Security, territory, population: Lectures at the Collège de France
1977–1978, edited by Michel Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Foucault, Michel. 2008. The birth of biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France 1978–79,
edited by Michel Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell. New York: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 109
Frost, Samantha. 2010. Fear and the illusion of autonomy. In New materialisms: Ontology,
agency, and politics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost, 158–177. Durham,
NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Furedi, Frank. 2005. Politics of fear: Beyond left and right. London: Continuum.
Furedi, Frank. 2007. The only thing we have to fear is the ‘culture of fear’ itself. Spiked.
Available from www.spiked-online.com/newsite/article/3053#.VHSP-YuG98E. Accessed
25 November 2014.
Furedi, Frank. 2008. Fear and security: A vulnerability-led policy response. Social Policy
& Administration 42 (6): 645–661.
Goldthau, Andreas. 2008. Rhetoric versus reality: Russian threats to European energy
supply. Energy Policy 36 (2): 686–692.
Grusin, Richard A. 2004. Premediation. Criticism 46 (1): 17–39.
Hansen, Lene. 2000. The little mermaid’s silent security dilemma and the absence of
gender in the Copenhagen School. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 29 (2):
285–306.
Hansen, Lene. 2012. Reconstructing desecuritisation: the normative-political in the
Copenhagen School and directions for how to apply it. Review of International Studies
38 (03): 525–546.
Harman, Graham. 2009. Prince of networks: Bruno Latour and metaphysics. Melbourne:
re.press.
Högselius, Per. 2012. Red gas: Russia and the origins of European energy dependence. New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Huysmans, Jef. 1998a. Security! What do you mean?: From concept to thick signifier.
European Journal of International Relations 4 (2): 226–255.
Huysmans, Jef. 1998b. Revisiting Copenhagen: Or, on the creative development of a
security studies agenda in Europe. European Journal of International Relations 4 (4):
479–505.
Huysmans, Jef. 2011. What’s in an act? On security speech acts and little security noth-
ings. Security Dialogue 42 (4–5): 371–383.
IEA. 2014. Energy supply security: Emergency response of IEA countries 2014. Paris: OECD/
International Energy Agency.
Isin, Engin F. 2008. Theorizing acts of citizenship. In Acts of citizenship, edited by Greg
Marc Nielsen, 15–43. London and New York: Zed. Available from http://enginfisin.eu/
assets/2008d.pdf. Accessed 10 December 2014.
Judge, Andrew, and Tomas Maltby. 2017. European Energy Union? Caught between
securitisation and ‘riskification’. European Journal of International Security 2 (2):
179–202.
Judge, Andrew, Tomas Maltby and Kacper Szulecki. 2018. Energy securitisation:
Avenues for future research. In Energy security in Europe, edited by Kacper Szulecki,
149–173. Cham: Palgrave Macmillan. Available from https://link.springer.com/
chapter/10.1007/978-3-319-64964-1_6. Accessed 4 January 2018.
Kessler, Oliver. 2012. Sleeping with the enemy? On Hayek, constructivist thought, and
the current economic crisis. Review of International Studies 38 (2): 275–299.
Kessler, Oliver, and Christopher Daase. 2008. From insecurity to uncertainty: Risk and
the paradox of security politics. Alternatives: Global, Local, Political 33 (2): 211–232.
Kester, Johannes. 2018. Governing electric vehicles: Mobilizing electricity to secure
automobility. Mobilities 13 (2): 200–215.
Keynes, John Maynard. 1921. A treatise on probability. London: Macmillan.
Khrushcheva, Olga. 2011. The creation of an energy security society as a way to decrease
110 Securing undesired (energy) futures
securitization levels between the European Union and Russia in energy trade. Journal
of Contemporary European Research 7 (2): 216–230.
Knight, Frank H. 1921. Risk, uncertainty, and profit. Boston, MA: Houghton Mifflin.
Available from http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/306.
Korosec, Kirsten. 2009. Pickens: $300 oil is still on its way. Available from www.cbsnews.
com/news/pickens-300-oil-is-still-on-its-way. Accessed 15 January 2015.
Korosec, Kirsten. 2011. Another $300 oil prediction – and why this one matters.
Available from www.cbsnews.com/news/another-300-oil-prediction-and-why-this-one-
matters. Accessed 15 January 2015.
Latour, Bruno. 2004. Why has critique run out of steam? From matters of fact to matters
of concern. Critical inquiry 30 (2): 225–248.
Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Leander, Anna. 2003. The commodification of violence, private military companies, and
African states. Copenhagen: Danish Institute for International Studies, DIIS.
Leander, Anna. 2005. The power to construct international security: On the significance
of private military companies. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 33 (3):
803–825.
Leung, Guy C. K., Aleh Cherp, Jessica Jewell and Yi-Ming Wei. 2014. Securitization of
energy supply chains in China. Applied Energy 123: 316–326.
Linstone, Harold A. 2011. Three eras of technology foresight. Technovation 31 (2–3):
69–76.
Linstone, Harold A., and Murray Turoff, eds. 2002. The Delphi method: Techniques and
applications. Online reprint by New Jersey Institute of Technology. Available from
https://web.njit.edu/~turoff/pubs/delphibook/index.html. Accessed 5 November 2014.
Lobo-Guerrero, Luis. 2012. Insuring war: Sovereignty, security and risk. London and New
York: Routledge.
Luhmann, Niklas. 1993. Risk: A sociological theory. Berlin and New York: Walter de
Gruyter.
Lundborg, Tom. 2012. Politics of the event: Time, movement, becoming. London and New
York: Routledge.
Malthus, Thomas. 1798. An essay on the principle of population, as it affects the future
improvement of society with remarks on the speculations of Mr. Godwin, M. Condorcet,
and other writers. Project Gutenberg Ebook 4239. London: J. Johnson.
Massumi, Brian. 2005. Fear (the spectrum said). Positions: East Asia Cultures Critique 13
(1): 31–48.
Massumi, Brian. 2007. Potential politics and the primacy of preemption. Theory & Event
10 (2): n.p.
Massumi, Brian. 2009. National enterprise emergency steps toward an ecology of powers.
Theory, Culture & Society 26 (6): 153–185.
McDonald, Matt. 2008. Securitization and the construction of security. European Journal
of International Relations 14 (4): 563–587.
McGowan, Francis. 2011. Putting energy insecurity into historical context: European
responses to the energy crises of the 1970s and 2000s. Geopolitics 16 (3): 486–511.
Mietzner, Dana, and Guido Reger. 2005. Advantages and disadvantages of scenario
approaches for strategic foresight. International Journal of Technology Intelligence and
Planning 1 (2): 220–239.
Mullainathan, Sendhil, and Eldar Shafir. 2013. Scarcity: Why having too little means so
much. New York: Times.
Securing undesired (energy) futures 111
Mullen, Penelope M. 2003. Delphi: Myths and reality. Journal of Health Organization and
Management 17 (1): 37–52.
Nancy, Jean-Luc. 2000. Being singular plural: The surprise of the event, translated by Robert
D. Richardson and Anne E. O’Byrne. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Natorski, Michal, and Anna Herranz Surrallés. 2008. Securitizing moves to nowhere?
The framing of the European Union’s energy policy. Journal of Contemporary European
Research 4 (2): pp. 70–89.
Neal, Andrew W. 2006. Foucault in Guantánamo: Towards an archaeology of the excep-
tion. Security Dialogue 37 (1): 31–46.
Neocleous, Mark. 2008. Critique of security. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Nyman, Jonna. 2014. ‘Red storm ahead’: Securitisation of energy in US–China Rela-
tions. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 43–65.
Nyman, Jonna, and Jinghan Zeng. 2016. Securitization in Chinese climate and energy
politics. Wiley Interdisciplinary Reviews: Climate Change 7 (2): 301–313.
Patomäki, Heikki. 2015. Absenting the absence of future dangers and structural transfor-
mations in securitization theory. International Relations 29 (1): 128–136.
Radoman, J. 2007. Securitization of energy as a prelude to energy security dilemma.
Western Balkans Security Observer-English Edition (4): 36.
Rasmussen, Mikkel Vedby. 2004. It sounds like a riddle: Security studies, the war on
terror and risk. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 33 (2): 381–395.
Ravetz, Jerry. 2004. The post-normal science of precaution. Futures 36 (3): 347–357.
Robin, Corey. 2004. Fear: The history of a political idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Roe, Paul. 2008. Actor, audience (s) and emergency measures: Securitization and the
UK’s decision to invade Iraq. Security Dialogue 39 (6): 615–635.
Roe, Paul. 2012. Is securitization a ‘negative’concept? Revisiting the normative debate
over normal versus extraordinary politics. Security Dialogue 43 (3): 249–266.
Rose, Nikolas. 2001. The politics of life itself. Theory, Culture & Society 18 (6): 1–30.
Rumsfeld, Donald. 2002. Defense.gov transcript: DoD news briefing – Secretary Rums-
feld and Gen. Myers. Available from www.defense.gov/transcripts/transcript.
aspx?transcriptid=2636. Accessed 15 January 2015.
Salter, Mark B. 2008a. Conclusion: Risk and imagination in the war on terror. In Risk
and the war on terror, edited by Louise Amoore and Marieke de Goede, 233–246.
London and New York: Routledge.
Salter, Mark B. 2008b. Securitization and desecuritization: A dramaturgical analysis of
the Canadian Air Transport Security Authority. Journal of International Relations and
Development 11 (4): 321–349.
Schmitt, Carl. 1985. Political theology: Four chapters on the concept of sovereignty, trans-
lated by George Schwab. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Shannon, Jerry. 2014. Food deserts: Governing obesity in the neoliberal city. Progress in
Human Geography 38 (2): 248–266.
Smith Stegen, Karen. 2011. Deconstructing the ‘energy weapon’: Russia’s threat to
Europe as case study. Energy Policy 39 (10): 6505–6513.
Stern, J. 2006. The Russian-Ukrainian gas crisis of January 2006. Oxford Institute for
Energy Studies 16: 5–12.
Stoddard, Edward. 2012. A common vision of energy risk? Energy securitisation and
company perceptions of risk in the EU. Journal of Contemporary European Research 8
(3): 340–366.
Stritzel, Holger. 2007. Towards a theory of securitization: Copenhagen and beyond.
European Journal of International Relations 13 (3): 357–383.
112 Securing undesired (energy) futures
Stritzel, Holger. 2011. Security as translation: Threats, discourse, and the politics of
localisation. Review of International Studies 1 (1): 1–27.
Stritzel, Holger. 2012. Securitization, power, intertextuality: Discourse theory and the
translations of organized crime. Security Dialogue 43 (6): 549–567.
Subrahmaniyan, Nesa. 2008. Goldman’s Murti says oil ‘likely’ to reach $150–$200
(update 5) – Bloomberg. Available from www.bloomberg.com/apps/news?pid=news
archive&sid=ayxRKcAZi630. Accessed 15 January 2015.
Svendsen, Lars Fr H. 2008. A philosophy of fear, translated by John Francis Irons. London:
Reaktion.
Trombetta, Maria Julia. 2012. European energy security discourses and the development of a
common energy policy. Working Paper. Energy Delta Gas Research. Available from
www.edgar-program.com/uploads/fckconnector/7acf1f46-7358-4057-86e5-ffee558
13be3. Accessed 6 January 2015.
UNDP. 1994. Human development report 1994. Oxford: Oxford University Press
UNESCO World Commission on the Ethics of Scientific Knowledge and Technology.
2005. The Precautionary Principle. Paris: United Nations Educational, Scientific and
Cultural Organization.
Vergragt, Philip J., and Jaco Quist. 2011. Backcasting for sustainability: Introduction to
the special issue. Technological Forecasting and Social Change 78 (5): 747–755.
Vuori, Juha A. 2008. Illocutionary logic and strands of securitization: Applying the
theory of securitization to the study of non-democratic political orders. European
Journal of International Relations 14 (1): 65–99.
Wæver, Ole. 1995. Securitization and desecuritization. In On security, edited by R. D.
Lipschutz, 46–86. New York: Columbia University Press.
Wæver, Ole. 1999. Securitizing sectors? Reply to Eriksson. Cooperation and Conflict 34
(3): 334–340.
Wæver, Ole. 2011. Politics, security, theory. Security Dialogue 42 (4–5): 465–480.
Wendt, Alexander E. 1999. Social theory of international politics. Cambridge and New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Yergin, Daniel. 1991. The prize: The epic quest for oil, money & power. New York: Simon
and Shuster.
Zedner, Lucia. 2003. The concept of security: An agenda for comparative analysis. Legal
Studies 23 (1): 153–175.
5 The materialization of energy
security
5.1 Introduction
The discussion on energy security and security so far hints at a primarily social
and linguistically oriented understanding of energy security. What seems to be
ignored are the different material aspects underlying the questions of energy
security. This includes the actual supplies of energy that dissuade security con-
cerns as well as the shortages that are still prevalent, and it includes the rigid
and durable material infrastructure that handles the production, transport and
consumption of different forms of energy. In the case of oil, for example, this
infrastructure ranges from the sulphur and nitrogen content to the overall
quality of the resources, the depth of the wells, the size of the reserves, the dis-
tance to the markets, the infrastructure in place to refine and transport it and
so on.1
This chapter focuses on the social literature that discusses the relationship
between knowledge (over energy systems) and materiality (of energy systems),
and it asks three questions: (1) how do the social and material relate in line of
dominant social interpretations that characterize security, (2) how do these new
materialist theories view our ontology (e.g. how do their theories approach
social-material relations and objects) and (3) how do they approach surprising
events or change/uncertainty (e.g. their ontological politics)?
The chapter subsequently does not argue that either the material or the
social explanations are better, but it tries to understand their relationship. Based
on a discussion of both the critical constructivist literature and an analysis of
different ‘new’ materialist theories, this chapter puts forward four arguments.
First, that the dialectical representation of matter and thought (mind/body or
nature/society) is an artificial understanding that is simultaneously overblown in
theoretical discussions on poststructural and constructivist research, yet still a
necessary distinction to better understand processes of becoming (the performa-
tive identification, ascription of meaning, reactive politics and the assemblage
that closes the events). Second, when the material and social are able to
perform each other, they are open to a virtuality and eventfulness (e.g. surpris-
ing events) on both sides. Such an eventfulness calls for a politics of ontology:
the politics dealing with the identification of what the event is (like security).
114 The materialization of energy security
Based on the epistemological argument that it is impossible to know what is ‘out
there’, this calls for a relational or phenomenological ontology devoid of sub-
stance and objects except for those that are created relationally and best
described as materialdiscursive. Third, such a relational identification is based on
distinctions. With these distinctions come exclusions and the subsequent need
to be aware of the ethics of observation. In short, fourth, while new materialist
theories argue for additional attention to matter, they ultimately also discuss
knowledge gathering practices albeit in terms of durability and materialization.
In other words, they offer an account based on the materialization of potential-
ity, but have to concede that this only matters because of human-driven politics.
Unfortunately, this means that the already-abstract discussion on energy
security will turn even more abstract as discussions on materialism and discourse
cannot be separated from commentaries on, for example, different forms of
agency or the dualisms between object/subject and nature/culture. The easiest
way to introduce these theoretical discussions is by categorizing them into three
distinct positions: between positivist scholars, postpositivist scholars and new
materialist or posthumanist scholars. Where positivist-inspired research includes
realist and liberalist theories with their assumption of a material world out there
that can be studied objectively, postpositivism consists of a range of poststructur-
alist and constructivist theories that disagree with this and favour the (struc-
tured) social knowledge people have of the world. Lastly, recent ‘new materialist’
theoretical developments outside IR introduce a posthumanist view that origi-
nates from fields as diverse as sociology with actor-network theory (ANT), fem-
inism with agential realism, philosophy with object-oriented ontology (OOO),
anthropology and history (e.g. material culture).2 This is a perspective that
focuses on the material world in its becoming, instead of an exclusive focus on
human social interaction or the explanation of a world that already is. Within
IR, a small but growing number of articles is taking up these insights.3
This chapter is constructed as follows. Section 5.2 will analyse the postposi-
tivist rejection of positivism. It will briefly describe the main epistemological
argument and discuss the differences of opinion between critical realists and
radical constructivists on the role of scientific knowledge within such an episte-
mological position. It closes with a brief discussion of two highly abstract lin-
guistic and social structural scholars to see whether these really do reject the
material world as argued by some new materialist scholars. Section 5.3 moves to
the new materialist critique on postpositivist theories and discusses why new
materialist believe a focus on the material is important, what matter is, and how
this can be approached with a performative understanding that observes a mate-
rialdiscursive world. Section 5.4 delves into the new materialist theories by
introducing the relational ontology of ANT. It then reflects on this ontology by
following the critique on ANT, in particular its difficulty to discuss the origin of
the virtuality (change) of its relations. This abstract discussion is subsequently
simplified by discussing the vibrancy of the material in terms of a politics of
ontology that focuses on the event and how observations and subsequent
actions are folded together to close these events. Section 5.5 continuous on the
The materialization of energy security 115
politics behind observation as it introduces the work of Barad on agential
realism to discuss the ethics behind knowledge practices. The reflection summa-
rizes and reflects on the theoretical debates by setting the stage for the next
chapter.
Language has been granted too much power. The linguistic turn, the semi-
otic turn, the interpretative turn, the cultural turn: it seems that at every
turn lately every ‘thing’ – even materiality – is turned into a matter of lan-
guage or some other form of cultural representation.53
Where De Landa and Barad focus on the ontological and epistemological prepo-
sition of language over materiality in these quotes, Latour questions the categor-
ical use of the ‘social’ as distinct from the natural. For Latour, what happens
when people designate something as social is that they are diverting attention
away from the process of actual association between the different elements of
such a phenomenon.54 In other words, he focuses on the act of defining some-
thing as social and sees this as a form of politics that performs a closure of an
ongoing process of association between different elements that exist and
originate in the space in-between humans (e.g. Section 4.4 on the speech act
literature).
De Landa, Barad and Latour all find fault with many postpositivists, who,
according to them, have simply shifted their representational position within
the material/social dichotomy from the material towards the social. The core of
their critique thus focuses on the idea that postpositivist scholars still uphold
a Cartesian dualistic worldview, based on the observer who a priori assumes
that language and the world are separated to begin with.55 It is only in a Carte-
sian dualism where mind and body can represent each other that the above cri-
tique makes sense. This, however, might be phrased too strongly. On the one
hand, yes, it is easy to over-essentialize language in postpositivist theories, as
The materialization of energy security 123
highlighted by the quotes of Wittgenstein and Derrida above. Then again, most
of the postpositivist work, including the work of Wittgenstein and Luhmann,
acknowledges objects and materiality. As Hekman (herself working on material-
ity) reflects on Wittgenstein: ‘His discussion of language games as activities, of
general facts of nature, form of life, and many other concepts suggests an inter-
active understanding of the relationship between the discursive and the
material’.56 Similarly, Derrida’s quote on text above, which points to the under-
standing that all knowledge is ‘always already’ situated in other knowledge, is
quite easily reinterpreted in a broader sense of ‘ongoing historicity’.57 A narrow
theoretical focus on linguistic structures therefore does not automatically imply
that scholars claim that language is all that exist.58
In short, it can be argued that the Cartesian dualism that separates matter
and discourse permeates much of contemporary IR research. However, this
section shows that a dualist worldview leads to tensions on both a meta-
philosophical, theoretical and methodological level, especially for those who
accept the epistemological insight that all knowledge is mediated through dis-
course and other linguistic structures. For such postpositivist scholars, all that
we know are the discourses and the concepts that derive their meaning through
the differentiation from other concepts. These differences have a history that is
based on previous understandings and distinctions. This makes it impossible to
see or experience something new without first being structured by the rules of
society hidden in an intersubjective understanding of the world and the lin-
guistic structures that enable (or inhibit) possible routes of thought and action.
Each of these understandings and distinctions is based on a judgement made by
an observer on an object of study. This translates facts into shared distinctions,
which are based on shared values of judgement. It is here that we see a differ-
ence between critical realists, for whom the better argument is always based on
something because we can act on things (we cannot know the world, but it
exists), and radical constructivists, who instead argue for a pragmatic argument
(we agree that the world exists). Nevertheless, both share that the material
world exists and that it cannot be understood independently of shared social
understandings.
If the term ‘ontology’ is combined with that of ‘politics’ then this suggests
that the conditions of possibility are not given. That reality does not
precede the mundane practices in which we interact with it, but is rather
shaped within these practices. So the term politics works to underline this
active mode, this process of shaping, and the fact that its character is both
open and contested.77
This fifth move draws attention to the idea that in a more-than-human world
the questions what something is and who exactly acts (and through what)
126 The materialization of energy security
become two very political questions with strong ethical connotations as they
touch upon notions of responsibility and accountability. When every explana-
tion (knowledge) of an event is seen as a potential closure that fixates particular
material and social subjectivities, structures and power relations, they are con-
stantly open to critique.
New materialism is not the only theoretical work that sees the world as an
open and dynamic system devoid of inert objects. For example, the chapter on
security already described risk and resilience with their sense of vulnerability. In
addition, much of the literature on natural resources has shifted towards system
approaches (e.g. energy systems or food systems) based on infrastructure,
logistics or (political) ecological understandings of anthropocentrism. In a time
when humankind dominates its environment, many of these theories highlight
its smallness and note that humans are only a part of the total system. Dillon
and Reid describe this posthuman position as a shift from a world that is com-
plicated to a world that is complex: where complicated worlds can be ‘reduced’
and ‘simplified’, complex worlds can only be ‘embraced’ and ‘orchestrated’.78
Moreover, in such a complex relational perspective, agency and causality are
dispersed, mediated and thus no longer as predictable as once imagined.79
In a way, both McCarthy and Butler highlight that it is not a neutral affair to
describe technology in terms of determinism or instrumentalism. Any analysis
starting from these positions becomes pre-structured and directs the focus of the
scholar involved. Importantly, these predetermined positions close off any
potential analysis of the actual interaction of matter and social.96 This is a
similar point to the general criticism of Barad on positivist and postpositivist
studies, when she argues that ‘the nature/culture dualism foreclose[s] the under-
standing of how “nature” and “culture” are formed’ in the first place.97 In other
words, for Barad the driving question is not so much whether the social or the
material matter – in fact, not even whether the social and the material matter –
but ‘how matter comes to matter’.98
This question opens the analysis to both sides of the mind/body dialectic. It
studies how matter changes and sediments social understandings, but it also
studies how language plays a role in making sense of matter. Simultaneously, it
moves away from postpositivist understandings of deconstruction and construc-
tion. For new materialists the goal is not to deconstruct issues and open them to
critique and reconstruction.99 Instead, they move the speech act literature back
to its original starting point on acts (in line with Section 4.4) and thereby
include not only explicit and exceptional speech acts but also the distinctions
and delimitations implicit in ordinary language use.100 In addition, the act is
130 The materialization of energy security
extended to include things not speech-related, like human behaviour, bodily
actions and cause and effect relationships. The concept developed by Butler to
describe this is performativity.
Importantly, in Butler’s original introduction to performativity in 1993, the
concept is not taken to include non-linguistic acts. For Butler, performativity
‘must be understood not as a singular or deliberate “act,” but, rather, as the reit-
erative and citational practice by which discourse produces the effects that it
names’.101 The act that Butler describes is one based on discourse that produces
an ontological effect as it materializes and brings into reality the social effects
that follow from the discursive delimitations behind the repetition and reitera-
tion of previous practices; it ‘decides, as it were, what will and will not be the
stuff of the object to which we then refer’.102 Performativity is the ‘process of
materialization that stabilizes over time to produce the effect of boundary, fixity, and
surface we call matter’.103 For Butler, performativity highlights what discourse
does to the non-discursive. At the same time, its constant reiteration unlocks
the potential failure that is inherent to performativity by highlighting a contex-
tualized process where things only exist in the moment. Performativity is inher-
ently incomplete, even when materialized or codified (in contrast to theoretical
explanations of society).104 Part of this incompleteness stems from the material-
ity itself, as bodies and matter resist the ascription of discourse.105 A body is
never shaped by discourse but it is normalized by it and forms itself in line with
its historical social and material evolution. This productive normalization is
something Butler takes from Foucault and leads her to define materiality as
‘designat[ing] a certain effect of power or, rather, [as] power in its formative or
constituting effects’.106
Where Butler remains focused on discourse and the materialization it initi-
ates, others, including Latour and his colleagues from ANT as well as Barad,
broaden this idea of performativity. These scholars try to move away from a
human-centred approach by opening up their ontology to the actions of matter
itself. They do so by building on the relationality that is inherent in Butler’s
(and Foucault’s) performativity. Contrary to Butler, however, these authors
push the argument by officially moving away from a preference of discourse to
the entangled relationships that shape objects. These relations include the rela-
tion between humans and between minds and bodies (discourse/non-discursive),
but also the interactions or cause–effect relationships between material ele-
ments. In allowing for interaction outside and in addition to discourse, these
new materialists claim to move beyond Butler’s understanding of performativity.
An interesting performative example that details such a relational under-
standing is Bennett’s analysis of the August 2003 north-east American electri-
city blackout.107 Her discussion of this massive blackout that affected over fifty
million people highlights not only a – quite literal – relational analysis, but also
discusses the manageability of such assemblages and the ingrained ethical ques-
tions that such an approach calls for. Bennett herself describes the blackout as
‘the end point of a cascade—of voltage collapses, self-protective withdrawals
from the grid, and human decisions and omissions’.108 While she concludes that
The materialization of energy security 131
the investigators tasked with studying the blackout had no idea what stopped
the cascade,109 she analyses in detail their conclusions on the accumulation of
(unrelated) factors that contributed to it. As Bennett summarizes the official
report:
The U.S.–Canada Task Force report was more confident about how the
cascade began, insisting that there were a variety of agential loci. These
include electricity, with its internal differentiation into ‘active’ and
‘reactive’ power …; the power plants, which are understaffed by humans
but overprotective in their mechanisms; the wires of transmission lines,
which tolerate only so much heat before they refuse to transmit the elec-
tron flow; the brush fire in Ohio underneath a transmission line; FirstEnergy
and other energy-trading corporations, who, by legal and illegal means, had
been milking the grid without maintaining its infrastructure; consumers,
whose demand for electricity is encouraged to grow without concern for
consequences; and the Federal Energy Regulatory Commission, whose
Energy Policy Act of 1992 deregulated the grid, separated the generation of
electricity from its transmission and distribution, and advanced the privati-
zation of electricity.110
This assemblage of factors led to a situation where the stress on the grid
increased in a matter of minutes and kept increasing with each of the power
plants that withdrew from the grid, as each of them added to the strain and in
turn activated the alarms of other power plants. At the end of the cascade, more
than 100 power plants had initiated their automatic safety and shutdown
procedures.
Most interesting for Bennett about this cascade is the fact that it is imposs-
ible to account it to human agency alone. This is not to say that humans played
no role at all. In fact, Bennett is quite adamant that humans most definitely
played a role in the blackout through their capitalist behaviour in the – in hind-
sight – faulty regulated and liberalized electricity markets. However, in addition
to the automatic safety systems, Bennett also highlights the agentic capacity of
the electricity flow itself, a flow which spontaneously shifted its direction after
several transmission lines broke down and thereby strained the grid in ways it
had not experienced before.111 For Bennett, such a distributed agency calls for
an equally distributed accountability, and hence for an ethics that is ‘detached
from moralism’ and a ‘politics of blame’ as both of these are human-focused.112
In fact, Bennett argues that responsibility and accountability in events like the
blackout should be approached in terms of a choice. Pending the political or
social need, it becomes a judgement to either acknowledge a distributed
accountability or hold only humans accountable.
In sum, in the rejection of a sole focus on language and discourse, new mate-
rialist scholars are trying to study the actual relationship between the social and
the material, by moving away from human-centred analyses and asking how
matter comes to matter. For this, they use a local and relational ontology that
132 The materialization of energy security
allows them to study the materialization of relationships between humans,
matter, discourse and so forth. They study the becoming or enactment of new
sets of relationships, by taking a performative approach that looks at these rela-
tionships irrespective whether their origin is social or material. In other words,
they place the material on an equal footing with the discursive, as in Bennett’s
example. Interestingly, they still separate the material and social analytically,
and they are unable to study these ontological politics without referring to
knowledge and language. In addition, as discussed below, while new materialism
has the tools to describe and observe new relationships from both sides of the
materialdiscursive assemblage, that is all it can do. It is an approach that does
not hypothesize the reasons why people and objects do things and it has trouble
explaining change as it can only describe what the relationships do and how
they do it.
The task of defining and ordering the social should be left to the actors
themselves, not taken up by the analyst. This is why, to regain some sense
of order, the best solution is to trace connections between the controversies
themselves rather than try to decide how to settle any given controversy.123
An account which accepts to be ‘just a story’ is an account that has lost its
main source of uncertainty: it does not fret any longer at being accurate,
faithful, interesting, or objective.… In a bad text only a handful of actors
will be designated as the causes of all the others.141
Latour refers here to the idea of capitalism. He does not deny that capitalism
exists but argues that one can only truly study it by tracing its local relations,
which in this case means starting with the Wall Street trading rooms and house-
hold budgets decided on at kitchen tables.142
In other words, for ANT scholars, the idea of society or social explanations
like norms, social facts or a concept as scarcity or energy security do more harm
than good because they close off an understanding of what is really going on.
Latour is quite strong on this and criticizes social scientists, who, instead of pro-
viding ‘powerful explanations’, are engaging in the politics of the situation they
describe by freezing ‘the entities already mobilized to render asymmetries longer
lasting’.143 Instead, ANT scholars argue in favour of a better examination of the
construction of social events, one that acknowledges that things can always
fail.144 Because when everything is based on inherently fragile heterogeneous
networks and their mediators, ‘the dichotomy between the real and the con-
structed is, like all dichotomies, a false one’.145 Instead, the question becomes
one of stability or how well things are constructed and performed.146
it gives to that something a power it does not generally possess: the power
to cause us to think, feel and wonder, the power to have us wondering how
practically to relate to it, how to pose relevant questions about it.176
Events actually can be perceived in two ways. First, an event is the surprise (e.g.
something in need of interpretation). Connolly describes an event in this
respect as something that:
Happens rather rapidly; it throws some regular institutions and role defini-
tions into turmoil or disarray; its antecedents often seem insufficient to
explain its emergence and amplifications; its settlement, when under way,
is uncertain; and it makes a real difference in the world, for good or ill.177
The materialization of energy security 139
As a surprise, an event often emerges as a failure or a breakdown that transforms
a matter of fact into a matter of concern.178 Barry, for example, is interested in
the manner in which the corrosion of the metals of an oil pipeline ignites a
political debate, sometimes even constituting a public that was not there
before.179 Second, Latour also talks about the event in terms of an achievement.
In this interpretation, events are seen as successful practices of observation, as
the achievement to observe and ascribe meaning to a phenomenon that has
never been observed before.180 For Latour, this is an event because it achieves to
connect two previously unlinked objects, thereby creating ‘new possibilities and
new questions for the concerned parties’.181 Defining events in terms of surprise
and achievement thus very much depends on one’s perspective. For instance,
the breakdown of a pipeline through corrosion is an achievement of the ele-
ments involved but a surprise for the people who depend on the pipeline.
Another way to indicate both the surprise and the achievement is by describ-
ing objects, including (post)humans, as folded entities. A fold (or assemblage)
refers to the manner in which an object bridges moments in space and time as
well as opening up additional actions for the user. Latour, when not discussing
the withdrawal or black boxing of objects, uses the example of a hammer to
show how such an object folds time (the history of iron, wood, production,
transport, use), space (mines, forests, factories, markets, homes) and the ‘flux of
possibilities’ that the hammer offers to its wielder (construction, weapon, orna-
ment).182 These folds are never static and always hide their own negation,
simply because something that can be folded can also be stretched, broken and
opened up. 183 The surprise of the inherent failure is countered by the achieve-
ment of the folding itself. Brassett and Vaughan-Williams draw on Butler when
they describe this as ‘the performative politics of … attempted closures, which are
nevertheless already in excess of their own logic and give rise to unexpected,
unforeseen, and disruptive effects’.184 This separates new materialism once more
from strict constructivist approaches. According to new materialism, the habit-
ual and repetitive folding of sets of relations is based on fragile practices and not
on social norms or rules, as the latter do not allow for their own negation and
have to be resisted from the outside by another norm.185 Furthermore, these
practices enact or perform the actual reality of the folding itself, they ‘co-
constitut[e] “subjects”, “objects” and “environments” ’186 This means that folds,
and the practices that create them, cannot be studied from a distance as any
observation is an act itself and affects the folded object.187
In short, this section offered an example of a new materialist, posthuman and
relational theory by introducing Latour’s ANT and how it deals with change
and stability. While discussing this theory and its assumptions, two things
became clear. First, specifically in relation to this theory, that the flat ontology
and irreducibility of actor-networks prevent the theory from explaining change
and instead leave it open to a constant regress of actants. This follows, in part
because the theory is biased towards observable relations and provides no guid-
ance for observers on where to limit their research. The work of Farías and
Bryant offered an alternative, with their focus on differences as the answer to
140 The materialization of energy security
the question of virtuality. Both argue that these differences are performatively
given shape in and by the relations themselves, as these relationships observe
their own distinctions – either as a surprise or an achievement – in something
that the last section introduced as a practice of eventful folding. Second, more
generally, that all of this (1) extends the discussion on the surprising event in
the security chapter, (2) offers a materialdiscursive ontology that adds and con-
trasts to the socially oriented performative security theories, and (3) starts to
point to a more general shared performative notion of ontological politics and
the close connection between events, observation and assemblages. This is
taken up further in the next section.
what is on the other side of the agential cut is not separate from us –
agential separability is not individuation. Ethics is therefore not about
right response to a radically exterior/ized other, but about responsibility
and accountability for the lively relationalities of becoming of which we are
a part.214
With her example of the brittle star, a sea creature not to be confused with
the more popular sea star (brittle stars have snakelike arms), Barad clarifies both
the entanglement and ethics of observational ‘cuts’.215 First, there is the obser-
vation that a brittle star does not have eyes, nor does it have a brain. As such it
does not have the capacity for language, nor can its body be separated from its
mind (it has none). That said, a brittle star still reacts to differences in light
intensity and, above all, it can flee from its predators. Instead of eyes, brittle
stars have an extensive nerve system that makes their entire body act as one big
eye. Theoretically, this means that a brittle star is constantly intra-acting with
144 The materialization of energy security
its environment: it does not separate between what it sees or what it thinks; it
just is. ‘For a brittle star, being and knowing, materiality and intelligibility, sub-
stance and form, entail one another.’216 In other words, a brittle star does not
face the Cartesian dualism intuitively ascribed to humans and (most other)
animals. A second interesting lesson from the brittle star is that it can break off
one of its arms when it is cornered by a predator. In terms of Barad’s theory, the
moment a brittle star observes a predator it is thus able to discursively redraw the
material boundary between itself and its environment. Sometimes these arms
still wriggle, an event that is often interpreted by human observers as a survival
technique. For Barad, such an interpretation would mean that the main body
and arm are still part of the same phenomenon, e.g. the original brittle star.
However, she argues that one could also see the arm as becoming an auto-
nomous living thing itself, especially in light of the observation that some brittle
stars reproduce by cloning their arms. As Barad concludes, in the end, ‘it’s all a
matter of where we place the cut’ that defines ‘what matters and what is excluded
from mattering’.217
In other words, through the act of observation differences emerge, phenomena
are enacted ‘and knowledge is produced about “subjects” and “objects” (and
“environments”)’.218 First, these cuts are never definitive. Any observation, like
ANT’s settlement of relations, is a simplification of a messy reality and is tempo-
rary as it incorporates its own demise.219 Second, these cuts are not only human-
made. Barad in particular highlights the role instruments play when humans gain
knowledge, as when she discusses the piezoelectric transducer, a scanning device
used in ultrasonography.220 These and other observational devices often measure
only one thing (e.g. sound, light etc.) and a such play an active role in deciding
what is observed or not, especially when they stutter or break down. What is
more, people need particular skills to use them.221 Tools and tool use are both
part of the agential cut that is made. So, while all theoretical insights from new
materialism highlight their attentiveness to a vibrant material world, Barad, in
ascribing this role to observational tools, is most explicit in stating how tools and
objects actively influence not only other objects but our practices of knowledge
gathering as well. Third, in line with Bryant, these cuts are ontological and not
epistemological.222 They shape the world(s) in which people and things live,
because they engage and perform, not because they imagine.
Together, these three observations about cuts create a theoretical approach
that calls for a certain humility and perhaps even a sense of vulnerability of
humans. For if everything is both affected and affecting, then, as Butler states,
‘one’s life is always in some sense in the hands of the other’.223 Together with
Butler, Latour and other new materialists, Barad argues that we are responsible
for each other. Not in the sense of a responsibility towards the other, as in a
typical security relation, but in the sense of a responsibility for us both.224 Such
an encompassing responsibility thus explicitly includes, according to Tuana, a
responsibility for those ‘practices that account for not knowing’, those actively
‘ignored or rationalized’ accounts of issues like food insecurity or energy poverty.225
As Latour writes on the morality behind technology:
The materialization of energy security 145
Between the gesture of switching on my computer and what I write on the
screen, I can either ignore the nuclear industry which enables me to work
this morning, or find myself immersed in the uncertain destiny of that same
industry which forces me to take account of the burial in deep silos of the
waste from its stations that the French do not support.226
To deal with this, Hekman offers the concept of disclosure to approach these set-
tlements (e.g. cuts, actants or assemblages). Based on a Baradian ontology and a
critical realist perspective on scientific research, Hekman proposes that the
concept of disclosure can ‘bring to light’ a variety of aspects and perspectives of
those settled phenomena/folds/assemblages that hide the differentiation and
cuts underneath them. None of these disclosed messy realities is more truthful
than the other, but, in a critical realist sense, Hekman does see them as materi-
ally braced and hence comparable on objective grounds.227 Alternatively, Bel-
lacasa introduces the ethical and more critical transformative duty for matters of
care, after Latour’s matters of fact and matters of concern.228 As she would have
it, to explain matters of fact or Barad’s agential cuts, one needs to explain them
with care by respecting all those involved in the observational cut and by giving
those who are silenced a voice – even if that means that in each instance obser-
vers actively have to choose for whom to care more (in line with Booth’s
positive security). Scholars are not only part of what they study but also play a
critical transformative role in a world of becoming.229
In closing, Hekman argues that Barad’s agential realism shows promise as it is
grounded in local experiences, collapses the material/social dichotomy, focuses
on boundaries and boundary drawing practices, and draws ethical conclusions
from practices of observation.230 This chapter can only confirm Hekman’s
summary but adds that Barad, in pushing for a materialdiscursive entanglement,
argues for an understanding of the politics of ‘materialisation and dematerialisa-
tion’.231 In other words, while it is impossible to separate the material from the
discursive and to observe without acting (humans and non-humans), Barad calls
attention to the fact that it is mainly politics, broadly understood, that deals
with the virtuality of matter. Here we touch on a slightly paradoxical claim in
her argument, because, while she acknowledges the activity of tools to an extent
not seen elsewhere, she too discusses these politics overwhelmingly in terms of
observing scientists, as in the example of the brittle star. In the end, it seems
that Barad too refers back to humans, although no longer masters of the uni-
verse, as the core subjects wilfully reflecting and shaping the materialdiscursive
in their image.
5.6 Reflection
In response to the mostly sociolinguistic understandings of (energy) security
presented in the earlier chapters, this chapter drew attention to the materiality
of energy systems and subsequently examined the role and importance of matter
in relation to knowledge. At the heart of this chapter were three questions:
146 The materialization of energy security
(1) how the social and material relate in line of dominant social interpretations
that characterize security, (2) how these new materialist theories view our onto-
logy (e.g. how their theories approach social-material relations and objects) and
(3) how they approach surprising events or change/uncertainty (e.g. their onto-
logical politics)?
The chapter started with a discussion on the Cartesian mind/body duality
within IR by opposing critical realism and radical constructivism. This debate
highlighted a strong theoretically induced epistemological argument against
representational knowledge as favoured by positivism, in other words that it is
impossible to know what we observe objectively and truthfully. For many this is
not a new argument, and in fact it lies at the core of the critical theoretical
understandings of security. Still, Section 5.2 discussed a matter of contention
between these strands of theory, in particular whether the pursuit for scientific
knowledge is valid on its own or whether it is a pragmatic social activity. While
this debate is ongoing in IR, Section 5.2 ended with the new materialists, who
questioned the absence of the non-discursive world in the radical constructivist
theories dealing with meaning and discourse. Without matter, new materialists
claim, one neglects alternative sources of change and order that drastically influ-
ence human life.232 That said, the section concluded that the new materialist
critique of an absence of anything material in critical and radical social theories
was phrased a bit too strongly, as original postpositivist theorists were acutely
aware of the interplay between knowledge and matter but made the choice to
focus on that interaction through a deeper understanding of the social.233 On
the other hand, it could be argued that the many one-sided attempts to translate
these linguistic insights into empirical research do eschew anything material
and hence validate part of the new materialist claim.
In turn, the new materialist alternative seemed to have proceeded in two
phases. The first phase was mainly focused on showing the relevance of the
material world against linguistic-oriented postpositivist theories. Section 5.3 in
this respect put forward the shared assumptions of new materialism, including
its adherence to the epistemological critique of postpositivists, its trust in a
world outside of humans, its focus on local assemblages, and the ethical con-
sequences inherent to it. This chapter also offered a partial reprise of the ways
in which the material is used and spoken about. Besides the many meanings and
different terms used to describe ‘the world out there’, the material was discussed
as something non-social, as objects outside of human influence or as objects
with relational qualities (durable, hard, colourful and so forth), with a special
reference for those technological artefacts that are made by humans. Based on
the latter category, questions were raised towards the traditional separation of
matter as something passive or active and as something instrumental or deter-
ministic. The section ended with a core approach that most new materialists
use, namely an extended understanding of Butler’s performativity or the reitera-
tive acts of materialization. Bennett’s example of the north-east American
blackout subsequently exemplified this and simultaneously introduced the core
aspects of how new materialist view the world: the relationality of the different
The materialization of energy security 147
interacting nodes of the electricity grid, the surprise of unintended and unantic-
ipated material effects, and the ethical consequences of the decision on account-
ability within such a relationality.
Section 5.4 took these up as it offered a network-inspired relational ontology
based on ANT. In analysing the ontological assumptions of ANT, what emerged
was an empirical-oriented methodology that assumes a network of relations or
actants (actor-networks), which are posthuman and irreducible, stand on equal
footing in a flat ontology, and which relate to each other through traceable
translation. However, just as social theories are questioned, these networks too
are vulnerable. In particular to an infinite regress argument, meaning that there
is no end to one’s observation while scholars simultaneously only observe fixed
traceable relations, relations that are already actualized.
The story of new materialism as described in this chapter hence moved to a
second phase and the discussion on how to incorporate the virtual in already-
actualized networks of relations, in other words how to explain the transforma-
tion of beings while also allowing for independent objects. This virtuality was
later described in terms of the condition of possibility of the materialdiscursive
assemblages, or, simply, as the vibrancy of matter. This vibrancy in turn was
described as eventful, with the event acting both as a surprise and as an achieve-
ment. Here new materialist theories move beyond security theories that only
focus on the surprise. However, new materialism shows that the insecurity or
surprise for one person could very well be the achievement or security of another
(e.g. security dilemma). With events interpreted as either surprises or achieve-
ments, the virtual and actual were subsequently placed and found in the perfor-
mative folding of practices. Earlier described as a withdrawal or black boxing of
agentic capacities, a fold was seen as the closure of a phenomenon (like a
security measure), but a closure that is always incomplete and incoherent (also
like a security measure).
Another element was the performative remark that part of the folding is
completed with the practice of observation, both outward and inward. By defin-
ing observations as achievements, observations become an activity and thus a
political act based on differentiation, and as such observation is a core element
of ontological politics.234 Section 5.5 took this up and discussed the politics that
ensues from such a materialdiscursive interpretation of life. Following the phe-
nomenological agential realist approach offered by Barad, this chapter argued
for a closer attention towards the ‘agential cut’ when observing and singling out
a phenomena, object, practice or event. In connecting ontology, epistemology
and ethics, these cuts, whether enacted by humans or non-humans, affect the
observed event itself (thereby offering the only truly non-human active theory
in new materialism). They create difference. And, as difference, these cuts call
for a political awareness and ethical reflection on the cuts and where to
place them.
Barad and new materialist scholars therefore call for an ethics of responsib-
ility and care for the relations that are observed. Once observation is seen as the
creation of difference, the practice of observation by an assembly of humans and
148 The materialization of energy security
non-humans becomes performative of its own reality as it defines what comes to
matter and what does not. As such, observation has long-lasting ethical con-
sequences for that what is not observed: that excess or negation within the
assemblage that will ultimately undermine it. Knowing this, new materialist
scholars argue for an ethical awareness towards the broader ‘us’ and to support
those who do not matter (e.g. like Booth’s positive security). Basically, what
new materialist theories add is a materialdiscursive understanding of the
vibrancy and order of life and the ontopolitics of difference that shapes it. This
enables an understanding of creativity, durability and adaptability, while it dis-
rupts and discloses most dualistic understandings that we know, like the mind/
body, social/material, past/future, or expertise/laypersons.
In the end, the link between energy and this chapter is strong but not
directly crystalized. Energy security is a discourse that defines the limits of how
people properly secure energy, but it is also a knowledge practice through which
meaning is ascribed to certain events, and it is a materialdiscursive phenom-
enon or actor-network where earlier energy security observations and know-
ledge practices have generated differences and subsequently achieved to gather
and materialize an infrastructure like the electricity grid in response to that
observation. New events subsequently are influenced by these materialized
materialdiscursive relationships/phenomena through their scope, scale, historic-
ity, durability, time-binding and mediation of the observation of events. The
implies that the claim from securitization theory that the material does not
matter might be epistemologically correct, but misses that observations are not
purely social; they are materialdiscursive as well and mediated by the tools used
to observe and imagine events. Furthermore, while security is often seen as a
technique to define events/provide closure, another insight from a relational or
phenomenological materialdiscursive ontology is that every observation of
energy security is inherently incomplete and thus itself a potential ‘threat’ in
need of disclosure.
In this sense, new materialism helps to explain the underlying dynamics of
the postpositivist argument in security debates. It offers a fuller account of per-
formativity, one that pushes even the practice theories within the security liter-
ature. They also help turn the focus towards the politics of ontology and,
especially, the role of observation and knowledge in achieving closure. More-
over, they lead to a drastic ethical rereading of practices of observation and the
role that knowledge gathering plays in shaping the world. In other words, they
deflate the distinction between ontology and epistemology, between a politics of
ontology and a politics of knowledge. In general, this chapter describes the
potentiality and virtuality of the endless set of relations of matter and the social
as life itself. However, to acknowledge a more-than-human world while keeping
up with the epistemological critique of postpositivist scholars is a challenge all
on its own. With Barad’s materialized discursivity and a substance-less material-
ity, the chapter returned to the same questions of radical social constructivists:
how to account for the actuality and virtuality that can be found in-between
the discursive and non-discursive. In the end, while new materialist scholars
The materialization of energy security 149
offer an account based on the materialization of potentiality, they also acknow-
ledge that this only matters because of politics. The next chapter will therefore
focus on how humans govern their world through a materialdiscursive
environment.
Notes
1 Bridge 2008.
2 For actor-network theory, see Latour 2005; Law 1992, 2007. For agential realism,
see Barad 2003, 2007. On object-oriented ontology, see Harman 2009; Bryant,
Srnicek and Harman 2011. And on material culture, see Miller 2005. Other more
general work includes: Coole and Frost 2010b; Braun and Whatmore 2010a; Cud-
worth and Hobden 2011; Bennett 2010. Specifically, these authors depart from the
old definition of ‘materialism’, a term used to describe a theoretical framework that
depicts the world to exist from matter, energy and material interactions, and where
all social interactions can be explained by material processes. Also note that there
is quite some resistance against the use of the term of a ‘material turn’, as it is
claimed that the material has never left and as such cannot return. Interestingly, a
similar argument can be made in favour of the ‘linguistic turn’, although that term
is well established.
3 Aradau 2010; Schouten 2014; Cudworth and Hobden 2011; Voelkner 2011; See
also the special issue in Millennium: Srnicek, Fotou and Arghand 2013; including
the article by Connolly 2013. Recent articles in IR with an explicit but more tradi-
tional focus on ‘the material’ include: Sorensen 2008; Aradau 2010; Meyer and
Strickmann 2011; McCarthy 2011, 2013.
4 Robinson 2012.
5 Kessler 2007; Bieri 1981. For example, when combining (1) and (2) one enters a
classic dualist position described as interactionism where mind and body can
interact freely; similarly, a combination of (2) and (3) is described as physicalism
and stands for an approach where the mind is seen as part of the body but not reduc-
ible to it; and, lastly, a combination of (1) and (3) results in epiphenomenalism,
where the mental is seen as a by-product of the physical without any causal effects
at all.
6 Searle 1995, 2, 7.
7 Ibid., 1.
8 Ibid., 2.
9 Ibid., 121.
10 Ibid., 55–56.
11 Patomäki and Wight 2000, 216–218. Naturalism is sometimes also described as
realism, which, in turn, should not be confused with materialism.
12 Jackson 2008, 132–133 describes this position as ‘classical objectivity’, meaning
before quantum mechanics, before post-structuralism and before the linguistic turn.
13 Cox 1981.
14 Booth 2005, 11.
15 Bhaskar 2005.
16 Wight 2007b, 2007a, 2012; Patomäki and Wight 2000; Joseph and Wight 2010.
17 Wight 2007b, 383.
18 Ibid.
19 Ibid., 386.
20 The italic terms are from Patomäki and Wight 2000, 224; compare with Jackson
2008. Other scholars working from this position include Wendt 1999; Adler 2002;
Wight 2007b.
150 The materialization of energy security
21 Adler 1997.
22 Wendt 1999.
23 Ibid., 111. ‘Real’ does not imply materiality, as explained above.
24 Ibid., 110; Sorensen 2008, 10.
25 Wendt 1999, 110–113, 130–136.
26 Ibid., 1.
27 Wendt 1999. Sorensen 2008, 10. Wendt is not alone on this; see: Hopf 1998; Tan-
nenwald 2005; Guzzini 2000; Adler 2002; Checkel 1998; Reus-Smit 1996.
28 Jackson 2008, 134–135, 139.
29 See for example the illustrative, slightly ironic, subtitle of Kessler 2012b.
30 Adey, Anderson and Lobo-Guerrero 2011.
31 Kratochwil 2000, 2007b; Kessler 2012b; Fierke 2002; Milliken 1999.
32 Derrida 2005; Foucault 1977; Adorno 1973; Habermas 1984.
33 Wittgenstein 1958.
34 See for instance Derrida 2005.
35 Luhmann 1993, 1995, 2006. Also, Arnoldi 2001; Guzzini 2001; Kessler 2009, 2012a.
36 Luhmann defines communication broadly: language, writing, art, silence, gestures etc.,
everything that has or contains meaning for the entities using it to communicate.
37 In the act of observing or constituting a distinction, a system thus creates an
observer (e.g. subject/object distinction).
38 In addition, he identifies a number of social subsystems based on the recursively
used, and therefore structured or ‘codified’ processing of meaning that leads to func-
tional differentiation between subsystems. The economic subsystem, for example,
has as a code payment/non-payment and uses money as a communication medium.
Other subsystems include politics, the judiciary, art, media, ecology, society etc. In
switching to these social systems of communication, Luhmann tries to move away
from the Cartesian dualism by excluding the human and the material as a primary
focus of analysis and by placing the agency, as such, on a different level altogether
(that of systems of communication).
39 Luhmann 1993, 34–35.
40 Giddens 1986; Wendt 1987; Sewell 1992; Carlsnaes 1992; Doty 1997.
41 Foucault 1977, 27.
42 Kratochwil 2000. See also: Der Derian and Shapiro 1989; Ashley and Walker 1990;
Der Derian 2009; Onuf 2013.
43 Kratochwil 2000, 73. See Herborth 2012 on the ‘quest for certainty’.
44 Kratochwil 2000, 2007a, 2007b.
45 Wight 2007a. See also Wight 2000 or more abstract Suganami 2013.
46 Compare with Wittgenstein’s language games. God/religion is another logic.
47 See the discussion in Jackson 2008, 136–142.
48 Wittgenstein 1922, para. 5.6; Derrida 1976, 158–159.
49 Jackson 2012.
50 Patomäki and Wight 2000, 218.
51 Wight 2007a, as well as Jackson 2008; Jackson 2010.
52 Dolphijn and Van der Tuin 2012, 98 quote De Landa’s 2006 book A New Philosophy
of Society (pp. 45–46) [original emphasis]; Compare with Lemke 2002, 61, who
argues that scholars:
should prevent … a very serious flaw that dominates much contemporary
critique: the ‘essentialization of the critique of essentialism.’ What do I mean
by this? When social and political scientists increasingly claim the importance
of categories like ‘invention,’ ‘fiction,’ and ‘construction’ for their work, they
often double the theoretical attitude they initially set out to criticize: they hold
that the ‘poststructuralist’ or ‘anti-essentialist’ stance they adopt does signal a
‘right’ or ‘true’ knowledge.
The materialization of energy security 151
53 Barad 2007, 132, 2003, 801.
54 Latour 2005.
55 Jackson 2008, 2010.
56 Hekman 2010, 32.
57 Van der Tuin 2011, 285–287, quoting Barad 2003, 821 on ‘ongoing historicity’.
58 See also Hekman 2010, 30–31 or the discussion in Lundborg and Vaughan-Williams
2015. Luhmann 1995 of course starts from three systems, only one of which is the
social system of communication. Similarly, Cheah 2008 discusses the nondialectical
materialism that is present in Derrida’s focus on ‘text’.
59 Pickering 1993; Pickering 1999.
60 Coole and Frost 2010a, 27.
61 For the term intra-action, see the explanation of Barad below in Section 5.5.
62 Dolphijn and Van der Tuin 2012, 92–93. Likewise, Latour states that ‘There exists
no relation whatsoever between “the material” and “the social world”, because it is
this very division which is a complete artefact’. Latour 2005, 75–76.
63 Aradau 2010, 497.
64 Jackson 2010.
65 Jackson 2002; Barad 2007.
66 Barad 2007.
67 Whatmore 2006.
68 Coole and Frost 2010a, 11–14.
69 Ibid.
70 Hekman 2010, 68.
71 Coole 2013.
72 Whatmore 2006; Coole 2013, 454.
73 Coole 2013, 454.
74 Whatmore 2006.
75 Walters 2014, 103; Coole and Frost 2010a, 26; Bourne 2012, 155.
76 Whatmore 2006, 604.
77 Mol 1999, 75.
78 Dillon and Reid 2001, 46–47.
79 Bryant 2014, 4.
80 See Dolphijn and Van der Tuin 2012, 92–93, as well as Barad 2003, 828.
81 Dolwick 2009.
82 Pouliot 2004, 329 discusses this in terms of essentialization:
acts of essentialization … are commonplace in social life. They lie at the
foundation of the social construction of reality.… Repeated acts of
essentialization result in the generation of ‘social facts’, the portions of the
world that are treated as if they were real by social agents.… Once reified,
social facts confront agents’ everyday life as ‘objective’ facts that cannot be
ignored.
83 Elsewhere, Harman 2009, 74 and 141–143, notes that Latour sees materialism actu-
ally as a covert form of idealism because it shifts the attention away from actors and
agency towards the physical world (instead of the social) to explain everything.
84 Ahmed 2010, 234.
85 Stengers 2010, 28.
86 Winner 1980, 124, 129.
87 Ibid., 123–126.
88 Ibid., 127.
89 McCarthy 2013; Bourne 2012.
90 Bourne 2012, 142; McCarthy 2013, 473–474.
91 Bourne 2012, 143; McCarthy 2013, 472–473.
92 McCarthy 2013, 476.
152 The materialization of energy security
93 Ibid., 478–479, 481.
94 Ibid., 488.
95 Butler 2009, xii. Also in Holmqvist 2013, 545.
96 Bourne 2012, 143.
97 Barad 2003, 828.
98 Barad 2003, 2007. See also Latour 2004, 2005.
99 Bialasiewicz et al. 2007; De Goede 2012, 32.
100 Butler 2010.
101 Butler 1993, 2.
102 Butler 2010, 1993, 11.
103 Butler 1993, 9 (emphasis in original).
104 Ibid., 2; Butler 2010, 153.
105 Loxley 2007, 135.
106 Butler 1993, 34.
107 Bennett 2005.
108 Ibid., 448.
109 Thereby acknowledging Grove’s point on the incapability of network-inspired ana-
lyses like ANT to analyse creativity, or in this case non-existing agentic traces. See
Grove 2014 and Section 5.4.2.
110 Bennett 2005, 449.
111 Ibid., 451.
112 Ibid., 464.
113 Latour 2005; Law 1992; Law and Mol 1995; Callon 1986; Mol 1999.
114 Latour 2005, 70, 198. See also Law 1992, 3 on ‘material durability’ or Pels, Hether-
ington and Vandenberghe 2002, 11, who claim that: ‘Objects need symbolic fram-
ings, storylines and human spokespersons in order to acquire social lives; social
relationships and practices in turn need to be materially grounded in order to gain
temporal and spatial endurance’.
115 Miller 2005, 2–8, esp. 3. Material culture is particularly interested in the relation
between the material and the anti-material, for example, when it comes to religion,
or, more recently, the current economic society based upon consumption.
116 Latour 2005.
117 Miller 2005, 4.
118 Ibid., 5.
119 Ibid., 17–18. This material culture perspective questions the bivalent logic of reifi-
cation (the material framing of social relations) or fetishism (the symbolic framing
of material objects) as it does both. See also Le Billon 2007, 176 on commodifica-
tion versus fetishization.
120 Latour 2005, 84–85 (emphasis in original). See also: Bourne 2012, 161.
121 Latour 2005, 72 argues, for example, that ‘there might exist many metaphysical
shades between full causality and sheer inexistence’. On pages 84–85 he identifies
four: historical materialism (a material infrastructure like Marx’s that determines
social relations); a material world that ‘mirrors’ the social distinctions (Bourdieu
and other more critical oriented theories); and the material as a stage for human
interaction (instrumentalist perspective); and, lastly, those who put a heterogene-
ously layer atop the material and social (material culture).
122 Latour 2005; Law 1992; Law and Mol 1995; Callon 1986.
123 Latour 2005, 23 (emphasis added).
124 On rhizomatic networks, see Deleuze and Guattari 1987.
125 Bourne 2012, 154. Of course, this goes both ways. While it might be perceived as
more real, in fact all actants are real. They only differ in the number/strength of
their associations, see Fine 2005, 96.
126 Harman 2009, 773; Bourne 2012, 154. For a more critical discussion, see Fine 2005.
127 Latour 2005, 46.
The materialization of energy security 153
128 Tuana 2008, 9; Dolphijn and Van der Tuin 2012, 54.
129 Latour 2005, 55. Bennett 2005, 446–447 discusses actants as both coherent entities
(e.g. a tree) and forces (e.g. gravity or mineralization), depending on how they
appear to us humans.
130 Bennett 2004, 355. In general, Bennett refers to this with her concept of ‘thing-
power’.
131 Latour 2005, 180.
132 Ibid., 39.
133 Latour 2004. Things are continuously (re)produced relata, a continuous ‘gathering’
of relations as fact or concern, while Latour describes objects as failed ‘things’, as
taken-for-granted end-products of observation.
134 Latour 2005, 39.
135 Dolwick 2009, 45 (emphasis in original).
136 Latour 2005, 79.
137 Hence ‘flattening the social’ and ‘localizing the global’ – i.e. the social does not
stand above the material, and the macro is not more important than the micro/
local, thereby removing the level of analyses problem. See ibid., 165.
138 Law 1992, 6–7.
139 Ibid., 2.
140 Latour 2005, 122–130.
141 Ibid., 127, 130.
142 Ibid., 178–179, 192. For similar arguments on security and economic markets see:
Schouten 2014, 27 and Caliskan and Callon 2010.
143 Latour 2005, 5, 8, 23, 68, 85, 260.
144 Ibid., 249.
145 Hekman 2010, 110.
146 Mol 2002, 7; Hekman 2010, 110; Latour 2005, 89–90.
147 Harman 2009.
148 Ibid., 6, also 99–107.
149 Ibid., 34–35.
150 Ibid., 72 and 75.
151 Ibid., 106.
152 Fine 2005, 96. However, compare Bennett 2012, 228.
153 Harman 2009, 130–134. See also Grove 2014.
154 Harman 2009, 105.
155 Grove 2011, 1–2, 6.
156 Harman 2009, 147. However, Latour does mention overflow. See Latour 2005, 166.
157 Harman 2009, 135.
158 Ibid., 145–146 To read his specific treatise: pp. 151–228, in particular pp. 207–211,
but also p. 187: ‘The potential can only mean a potential for future relations, and
the actual can only mean what is in and of itself actual apart from any relations’.
159 Farías 2014, 28–29; Latour, Harman and Erdelyi 2011.
160 Latour 2005, 244.
161 Farías 2014, 28–29.
162 Ibid., 31.
163 Bryant 2011, 271, 272.
164 Ibid., 272–273.
165 Bryant 2011.
166 Ibid., 279.
167 Ibid., 280–282.
168 Bennett 2010.
169 Coole and Frost 2010a, 9.
170 Connolly 2010.
171 Ibid., 179.
154 The materialization of energy security
172 Coole 2010, 94.
173 Grosz 2010, 150.
174 Braun and Whatmore 2010b, xxi (emphasis added). Later in the chapter they also
call it ‘originary’ (xvii).
175 Braidotti 2010, 213; Stengers 2010, 27; Latour 2002, 251.
176 Stengers 2011, 374; Deleuze 1994; Grove 2014, 366; Bennett 2005, 457–458.
177 Connolly 2013, 404.
178 Latour 2004.
179 Barry 2013a; Marres 2005.
180 Stengers 2010, 12.
181 Ibid., 25.
182 Latour 2002, 249–250.
183 Coole 2010, 107. Compare with Adorno 1973, who discusses this in terms of a ‘non-
identity’: the difference between concept and thing, with something in the ‘thing’
always resisting the concept. For a discussion, see Bennett 2004, 349, 361–362.
184 Brassett and Vaughan-Williams 2015, 4; Butler 2010. On closure, see
Luhmann 2006.
185 Stengers 2010, 16; Connolly 2013, 404–405.
186 Squire 2015, 153. The term enactment is introduced by Mol 2002.
187 Mol 2002, 5–6.
188 Walters 2014, 103; Squire 2015, 151.
189 Coole and Frost 2010a, 19.
190 Whatmore 2006, 607; Callon, Lascoumes and Barthe 2009; Mitchell 2013,
240–242.
191 Callon, Lascoumes and Barthe 2009.
192 Hekman 2010, 82; Mol 2002. Braun and Whatmore 2010b, xxiii.
193 Barry 2013a; Barry 2013b. For another new materialist discussion on the politics of
ontology (identifying the event, debating its solution), see Schouten 2014 for a dis-
cussion on the role of the body scanner at airports from a security perspective.
194 Barry 2013b, 7.
195 Ibid., 12–13. Star 1999 actually discusses nine characteristics of infrastructure:
(1) its embeddedness in other (infra)structures; (2) its transparency (once build it is
there in the open); (3) its temporal and spatial effects; (4) its effects on users,
through skills; (5) its effects on social practices; (6) its embodiment of standards;
(7) its fixation of (capital) investments and interests; (8) its modular qualities; and
(9) its withdrawal or black boxing effects.
196 Brassett and Vaughan-Williams 2015, 39–42.
197 Barad 2007, 2003, 1996, 1998, 2011.
198 Barad 1996, 2003, 2007.
199 However, see the very recent work of Rozema et al. 2012 and Piazza et al. 2015,
which state that it is possible to observe both without influencing them. While this
places question marks behind Barad’s indeterminacy argument, it simultaneously
reinforces her argument about the role that matter plays in observing matter (as we
could not confirm this with older equipment), and thus the boundaries that objects
enact.
200 Barad 2007, 111–113. Another example given by Bohr (as described by Barad) is
when a person holds a stick: you either feel the stick, or you feel through the stick,
but never simultaneously. Compare to Heidegger’s tool-in-use.
201 Barad 2003, 2007, 2011.
202 Barad 2007, 26, 117–118 (emphasis in original).
203 Ibid., 31.
204 Ibid., 140.
205 Ibid., 120. Both Barad and Latour seem to agree that linguistic/semiotic interpreta-
tion can only occur if based on such a trace or mark.
The materialization of energy security 155
206 Ibid., 33, 141.
207 Opening her argument to claims that she is a naturalist, which she is, but not in the
normal sense of the term. See Rouse 2004.
208 Barad 2007, 49, also 55–56 and 180–181 (emphasis in original); Barad 2003, 829.
209 Barad 2007, 152.
210 Ibid., 151, 335. On boundaries, see 154–156.
211 Ibid., 151, 336; Barad 2003, 828.
212 One of the main implications of Barad’s framework is that one can only study a
phenomenon by comparing two complementary phenomena from within a third
phenomenon. Comparable to Luhmann, it is not possible to study a system from
within that system.
213 Barad 2007, 71–72.
214 Ibid., 393.
215 Ibid., 369–384.
216 Ibid., 375.
217 Ibid., 348 and 394 (emphasis in original).
218 Squire 2015, 156.
219 Ibid., 157.
220 Barad 2007, 201–222; Aradau 2010, 499.
221 Preda 1999, 350–356. The skills people need to use these machineries result from
the intra-action between the machine and the observer and hence are a folding
of both.
222 Vint 2008, 316–317.
223 Butler 2009, 14; as quoted by Holmqvist 2013, 549; Braun and Whatmore
2010b, xxv.
224 Dolphijn and Van der Tuin 2012, 69.
225 Tuana 2008, 19 (emphasis in original).
226 Latour 2002, 255.
227 Hekman 2010, 91–93, 127.
228 Bellacasa 2011.
229 Ibid., 100. Booth 2005.
230 Hekman 2010, 73.
231 Squire 2015, 151.
232 Sources of durability, resistance, sedimentation, triggers etc.
233 See also Lemke 2015.
234 Mol 2002, 5.
Bibliography
Adey, Peter, Ben Anderson and Luis Lobo-Guerrero. 2011. An ash cloud, airspace and
environmental threat. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 36 (3):
338–343.
Adler, Emanuel. 1997. Seizing the middle ground: Constructivism in world politics.
European Journal of International Relations 3 (3): 319–363.
Adler, Emanuel. 2002. Constructivism and international relations. In Handbook of inter-
national relations, edited by Walter Carlsnaes, Thomas Risse and Beth A. Simmons,
95–119. London: SAGE.
Adorno, Theodor W. 1973. Negative dialectics, translated by E. B. Ashton. London:
Routledge.
Ahmed, Sara. 2010. Orientations matter. In New materialisms: Ontology, agency, and pol-
itics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost, 234–257. Durham, NC, and London:
Duke University Press.
156 The materialization of energy security
Aradau, Claudia. 2010. Security that matters: Critical infrastructure and objects of pro-
tection. Security Dialogue 41 (5): 491–514.
Arnoldi, Jakob. 2001. Niklas Luhmann: An introduction. Theory, Culture & Society 18
(1): 1–13.
Ashley, Richard K., and R. B. J. Walker. 1990. Introduction: Speaking the language of exile:
Dissident thought in international studies. International Studies Quarterly 34 (3): 259–268.
Barad, Karen. 1996. Meeting the universe halfway: Realism and social constructivism
without contradiction. In Feminism, science, and the philosophy of science, edited by L.
H. Nelson and J. Nelson, 161–194. London: Kluwer.
Barad, Karen. 1998. Getting real: Technoscientific practices and the materialization of
reality. Differences: A Journal of Feminist Cultural Studies 10 (2): 87–128.
Barad, Karen. 2003. Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of how
matter comes to matter. Signs 28 (3): 801–831.
Barad, Karen. 2007. Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics and the entanglement of
matter and meaning. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Barad, Karen. 2011. Erasers and erasures: Pinch’s unfortunate ‘uncertainty principle’.
Social Studies of Science 41 (3): 443–454.
Barry, Andrew. 2013a. Pipelines. In Globalization in practice, edited by N. Thrift, Nick
Tickell and Steve Woolgar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Barry, Andrew. 2013b. Material politics: Disputes along the pipeline. Chichester: Wiley
Blackwell.
Bellacasa, Maria Puig de la. 2011. Matters of care in technoscience: Assembling neg-
lected things. Social Studies of Science 41 (1): 85–106.
Bennett, Jane. 2004. The force of things: Steps toward an ecology of matter. Political
Theory 32 (3): 347–372.
Bennett, Jane. 2005. The agency of assemblages and the North American blackout.
Public Culture 17 (3): 445–65.
Bennett, Jane. 2010. Vibrant matter: A political ecology of things. Durham, NC, and
London: Duke University Press.
Bennett, Jane. 2012. Systems and things: A response to Graham Harman and Timothy
Morton. New Literary History 43 (2): 225–233.
Bhaskar, Roy. 2005. A possibility of naturalism: A philosophical critique of the contemporary
human sciences. Third edition. London: Routledge.
Bialasiewicz, Luiza, David Campbell, Stuart Elden, Stephen Graham, Alex Jeffrey, and
Alison J. Williams. 2007. Performing security: The imaginative geographies of current
US strategy. Political Geography 26 (4): 405–422.
Bieri, Peter. 1981. Generelle Einfurung. In Analytische Philosophie des Geistes, edited by
Peter Bieri, 1–28. Konigstein: Hain.
Booth, Ken. 2005. Security. In Critical security studies and world politics, edited by Ken
Booth, 21–25. London: Lynne Rienner.
Bourne, Mike. 2012. Guns don’t kill people, cyborgs do: A Latourian provocation for
transformatory arms control and disarmament. Global Change, Peace & Security 24 (1):
141–163.
Braidotti, Rosi. 2010. The politics of ‘life itself ’ and new ways of dying. In New material-
isms: Ontology, agency, and politics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost,
201–220. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Brassett, James, and Nick Vaughan-Williams. 2015. Security and the performative pol-
itics of resilience: Critical infrastructure protection and humanitarian emergency pre-
paredness. Security Dialogue 46 (1): 32–50.
The materialization of energy security 157
Braun, Bruce, and Sarah Whatmore. 2010a. Political matter: Technoscience, democracy,
and public life. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Braun, Bruce, and Sarah Whatmore. 2010b. The stuff of politics: An introduction. In
Political matter: Technoscience, democracy, and public life, ix–xl. Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
Bridge, Gavin. 2008. Global production networks and the extractive sector: Governing
resource-based development. Journal of Economic Geography 8 (3): 389–419.
Bryant, Levi R. 2011. The ontic principle: Outline of an object-oriented ontology. In
The speculative turn: Continental materialism and realism, edited by Levi R. Bryant, Nick
Srnicek and Graham Harman, 261–278. Melbourne: re.press.
Bryant, Levi R. 2014. Onto-cartography: An ontology of machines and media. Speculative
realism. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Bryant, Levi R., Nick Srnicek and Graham Harman. 2011. The speculative turn: Contin-
ental materialism and realism. Melbourne: re.press.
Butler, Judith. 1993. Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of ‘sex’. New York:
Routledge.
Butler, Judith. 2009. Frames of war: When is life grievable. London and New York: Verso.
Butler, Judith. 2010. Performative agency. Journal of Cultural Economy 3 (2): 147–161.
Caliskan, Koray, and Michel Callon. 2010. Economization, part 2: A research pro-
gramme for the study of markets. Economy and Society 39 (1): 1–32.
Callon, Michel. 1986. The sociology of an actor-network: The case of the electric
vehicle. In Mapping the dynamics of science and technology, edited by Michel Callon,
John Law and Arie Rip, 19–34. Basingstoke: Macmillan.
Callon, Michel, Pierre Lascoumes and Yannick Barthe. 2009. Acting in an uncertain
world: An essay on technical democracy, translated by Graham Burchell. London: MIT
Press.
Carlsnaes, Walter. 1992. The agency-structure problem in foreign policy analysis. Inter-
national Studies Quarterly 36 (3): 245–270.
Cheah, Pheng. 2008. Nondialectical materialism. Diacritics 38 (1–2): 143–157.
Checkel, Jeffrey T. 1998. The constructivist turn in international relations theory. World
Politics 50 (2): 324–348.
Connolly, William E. 2010. Materialities of experience. In New materialisms: Ontology,
agency, and politics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost, 178–200. Durham,
NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Connolly, William E. 2013. The ‘new materialism’ and the fragility of things. Millennium
– Journal of International Studies 41 (3): 399–412.
Coole, Diana. 2010. The inertia of matter and the generativity of flesh. In New material-
isms: Ontology, agency, and politics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost,
92–115. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Coole, Diana. 2013. Agentic capacities and capacious historical materialism: Thinking
with new materialisms in the political sciences. Millennium – Journal of International
Studies 41 (3): 451–469.
Coole, Diana, and Samantha Frost. 2010a. Introducing the new materialisms. In New
materialisms: Ontology, agency, and politics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost,
1–46. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Coole, Diana, and Samantha Frost. eds. 2010b. New materialisms: Ontology, agency, and
politics. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Cox, Robert W. 1981. Social forces, states and world orders: Beyond international rela-
tions theory. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 10 (2): 126–155.
158 The materialization of energy security
Cudworth, Erika, and Stephen Hobden. 2011. Posthuman international relations: Complex-
ity, ecologism and global politics. London: Zed.
De Goede, Marieke. 2012. Speculative security: The politics of pursuing terrorist monies.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, Gilles. 1994. Difference and repetition, translated by Paul Patton. New York:
Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles, and Félix Guattari. 1987. A thousand plateaus: Capitalism and schizophre-
nia, translated by Brian Massumi. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Der Derian, James. 2009. Critical practices in international theory: Selected essays. London
and New York: Routledge.
Der Derian, James, and Michael J. Shapiro, eds. 1989. International/intertextual relations:
Postmodern readings of world politics. New York: Lexington.
Derrida, Jacques. 1976. Of grammatology. Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University
Press.
Derrida, Jacques. 2005. Writing and difference, translated by Alan Bass. London and New
York: Routledge.
Dillon, Michael, and Julian Reid. 2001. Global liberal governance: Biopolitics, security
and war. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 30 (1): 41–66.
Dolphijn, Rick, and Iris Van der Tuin. 2012. New materialism: Interviews & cartographies.
Ann Arbor, MI: Open Humanities Press. Available from http://hdl.handle.net/2027/
spo.11515701.0001.001. Accessed 12 June 2013.
Dolwick, Jim S. 2009. ‘The social’ and beyond: Introducing actor-network theory. Journal
of Maritime Archaeology 4 (1): 21–49.
Doty, Roxanne Lynn. 1997. Aporia: A critical exploration of the agent-structure prob-
lematique in international relations theory. European Journal of International Relations 3
(3): 365–392.
Farías, Ignacio. 2014. Virtual attractors, actual assemblages: How Luhmann’s theory of
communication complements actor-network theory. European Journal of Social Theory
17 (1): 24–41.
Fierke, K. M. 2002. Links across the abyss: Language and logic in international relations.
International Studies Quarterly 46 (3): 331–354.
Fine, Ben. 2005. From actor-network theory to political economy. Capitalism Nature
Socialism 16 (4): 91–108.
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison, translated by Alan
Sheridan. New York: Vintage.
Giddens, Anthony. 1986. The constitution of society: Outline of the theory of structuration.
Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Grosz, Elizabeth A. 2010. Feminism, materialism, and freedom. In New materialisms:
Ontology, agency, and politics, edited by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost, 139–157.
Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Grove, Jairus Victor. 2011. Becoming war: Ecology, ethics, and the globalization of violence.
PhD thesis, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University.
Grove, Jairus Victor. 2014. Ecology as critical security method. Critical Studies on Security
2 (3): 366–369.
Guzzini, Stefano. 2000. A reconstruction of constructivism in international relations.
European Journal of International Relations 6 (2): 147–182.
Guzzini, Stefano. 2001. Another sociology for IR? An analysis of Niklas Luhmann’s con
ceptualisation of power. Paper prepared for the 42nd Annual convention of the Inter-
national Studies Association in Chicago.
The materialization of energy security 159
Habermas, Jürgen. 1984. The theory of communicative action: Volume 1: Reason and the
rationalization of society. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Harman, Graham. 2009. Prince of networks: Bruno Latour and metaphysics. Melbourne:
re.press.
Hekman, Susan J. 2010. The material of knowledge feminist disclosures. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Herborth, Benjamin. 2012. Theorising theorising: Critical realism and the quest for cer-
tainty. Review of International Studies 38 (01): 235–251.
Holmqvist, Caroline. 2013. Undoing war: War ontologies and the materiality of drone
warfare. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 41 (3): 535–552.
Hopf, Ted. 1998. The promise of constructivism in international relations theory. Inter-
national Security 23 (1): 171–200.
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus. 2002. Rethinking Weber: Towards a non-individualist
sociology of world politics. International Review of Sociology 12 (3): 439–468.
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus. 2008. Foregrounding ontology: Dualism, monism, and IR
theory. Review of International Studies 34 (01): 129–153.
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus. 2010. The conduct of inquiry in international relations: Philo-
sophy of science and its implications for the study of world politics. London and New York:
Routledge.
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus. 2012. Fear of relativism. 2. Vol. 2. Working Paper. The Duck
of Minerva.
Joseph, Jonathan, and Colin Wight, eds. 2010. Scientific realism and international relations.
Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Kessler, Oliver. 2007. From agents and structures to minds and bodies: Of supervenience,
quantum, and the linguistic turn. Journal of International Relations and Development 10
(3): 243–271.
Kessler, Oliver. 2009. Toward a logic of social systems? International Political Sociology 3
(1): 132–136.
Kessler, Oliver. 2012a. World society, social differentiation and time. International Polit-
ical Sociology 6 (1): 77–94.
Kessler, Oliver. 2012b. On logic, intersubjectivity, and meaning: Is reality an assumption
we just don’t need? Review of International Studies 38 (01): 253–265.
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2000. Constructing a new orthodoxy? Wendt’s ‘social theory of
international politics’ and the constructivist challenge. Millennium – Journal of Inter-
national Studies 29 (1): 73–101.
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2007a. Of communities, gangs, historicity and the problem of
Santa Claus: Replies to my critics. Journal of International Relations and Development 10
(1): 57–78.
Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2007b. Of false promises and good bets: A plea for a pragmatic
approach to theory building (the Tartu lecture). Journal of International Relations and
Development 10 (1): 1–15.
Latour, Bruno. 2002. Morality and technology: The end of the means. Translated by C.
Venn. Theory, Culture & Society 19 (5–6): 247–260.
Latour, Bruno. 2004. Why has critique run out of steam? From matters of fact to matters
of concern. Critical inquiry 30 (2): 225–248.
Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Latour, Bruno, Graham Harman, and P. Erdelyi. 2011. The prince and the wolf: Latour and
Harman at the LSE. Alresford: Zero.
160 The materialization of energy security
Law, John. 1992. Notes on the theory of the actor-network: Ordering, strategy, and het-
erogeneity. Systemic Practice and Action Research 5 (4): 379–393.
Law, John. 2007. Actor network theory and material semiotics. Available from www.
heterogeneities.net/publications/Law2007ANTandMaterialSemiotics.pdf. Accessed 7
January 2013.
Law, John, and Annemarie Mol. 1995. Notes on materiality and sociality. The Sociologi-
cal Review 43 (2): 274–294.
Le Billon, Philippe. 2007. Geographies of war: Perspectives on ‘resource wars’. Geography
Compass 1 (2): 163–182.
Lemke, Thomas. 2002. Foucault, governmentality, and critique. Rethinking Marxism 14
(3): 49–64.
Lemke, Thomas. 2015. New materialisms: Foucault and the ‘government of things’.
Theory, Culture & Society 32 (4): 3–25.
Loxley, James. 2007. Performativity. London and New York: Routledge.
Luhmann, Niklas. 1993. Risk: A sociological theory. Berlin and New York: Walter de
Gruyter.
Luhmann, Niklas. 1995. Social systems, translated by John Jr. Bednarz and Dirk Baecker.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Luhmann, Niklas. 2006. System as difference. Organization 13 (1): 37–57.
Lundborg, Tom, and Nick Vaughan-Williams. 2015. New Materialisms, discourse ana-
lysis, and international relations: A radical intertextual approach. Review of Inter-
national Studies 41 (1): 3–25.
Marres, Noortje. 2005. No issue, no public: Democratic deficits after the displacement of pol-
itics. PhD thesis, Amsterdam: University of Amsterdam.
McCarthy, Daniel R. 2011. The meaning of materiality: Reconsidering the materialism
of Gramscian IR. Review of International Studies 37 (03): 1215–1234.
McCarthy, Daniel R. 2013. Technology and ‘the international’ or: How I learned to stop
worrying and love determinism. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 41 (3):
470–490.
Meyer, Christoph O., and Eva Strickmann. 2011. Solidifying constructivism: How
material and ideational factors interact in European defence. JCMS: Journal of
Common Market Studies 49 (1): 61–81.
Miller, Daniel. 2005. Materiality: An introduction. In Materiality, edited by Daniel
Miller, 1–50. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Milliken, Jennifer. 1999. The study of discourse in international relations: A critique of
research and methods. European journal of international relations 5 (2): 225–254.
Mitchell, Timothy. 2013. Carbon democracy: Political power in the age of oil. London:
Verso.
Mol, Annemarie. 1999. Ontological politics. A word and some questions. The Sociological
Review 47 (S1): 74–89.
Mol, Annemarie. 2002. The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. Durham, NC, and
London: Duke University Press.
Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood. 2013. World of our making: Rules and rule in social theory and
international relations. Reissue. New York: Routledge.
Patomäki, Heikki, and Colin Wight. 2000. After postpositivism? The promises of critical
realism. International Studies Quarterly 44 (2): 213–237.
Pels, Dick, Kevin Hetherington and Frédéric Vandenberghe. 2002. The status of the
object: Performances, mediations, and techniques. Theory, Culture & Society 19
(5–6): 1–21.
The materialization of energy security 161
Piazza, L., T. T. A. Lummen, E. Quiñonez, Y. Murooka, B. W. Reed, B. Barwick and F.
Carbone. 2015. Simultaneous observation of the quantization and the interference
pattern of a plasmonic near-field. Nature Communications 6 (7407).
Pickering, Andrew. 1993. The mangle of practice: Agency and emergence in the soci-
ology of science. American Journal of Sociology 99 (3): 559–589.
Pickering, Andrew. 1999. Explanation and the mangle: A response to my critics. Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 30 (1): 167–171.
Pouliot, Vincent. 2004. The essence of constructivism. Journal of International Relations
and Development 7 (3): 319–336.
Preda, Alex. 1999. The turn to things: Arguments for a sociological theory of things. The
Sociological Quarterly 40 (2): 347–366.
Reus-Smit, Christian. 1996. The constructivist turn: critical theory after the Cold War.
Working Paper. Canberra: National Library of Australia.
Robinson, Howard. 2012. Dualism. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, edited by
Edward N. Zalta. Available from http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/
dualism. Accessed 13 February 2015.
Rouse, Joseph. 2004. Barad’s feminist naturalism. Hypatia 19 (1): 142–161.
Rozema, Lee A., Ardavan Darabi, Dylan H. Mahler, Alex Hayat, Yasaman Soudagar and
Aephraim M. Steinberg. 2012. Violation of Heisenberg’s measurement-disturbance
relationship by weak measurements. Physical Review Letters 109 (10): 100404.
Schouten, Peer. 2014. Security as controversy: Reassembling security at Amsterdam
Airport. Security Dialogue 45 (1): 23–42.
Searle, John R. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Sewell, William H. 1992. A theory of structure: Duality, agency, and transformation.
American Journal of Sociology 98 (1): 1–29.
Sorensen, George. 2008. The case for combining material forces and ideas in the study of
IR. European Journal of International Relations 14 (1): 5–32.
Squire, Vicki. 2015. Reshaping critical geopolitics? The materialist challenge. Review of
International Studies 41 (01): 139–159.
Srnicek, Nick, Maria Fotou, and Edmund Arghand. 2013. Introduction: Materialism and
world politics. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 41 (3): 397–397.
Star, Susan Leigh. 1999. The ethnography of infrastructure. American Behavioral Scientist
43 (3): 377–391.
Stengers, Isabelle. 2010. Including nonhumans in political theory: Opening Pandoras
box? In Political matter: Technoscience, democracy, and public life, edited by Bruce Braun
and Sarah Whatmore, 3–34. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Stengers, Isabelle. 2011. Wondering about materialism. In The speculative turn: Contin-
ental materialism and realism, edited by Levi R. Bryant, Nick Srnicek and Graham
Harman, 368–380. Melbourne: re.press.
Suganami, Hidemi. 2013. Causation-in-the-world: A contribution to meta-theory of IR.
Millennium – Journal of International Studies 41 (3): 623–643.
Tannenwald, Nina. 2005. Stigmatizing the bomb: Origins of the nuclear taboo. Inter-
national Security 29 (4): 5–49.
Tuana, Nancy. 2008. Witnessing Katrina: Re/cognizing nature for socially responsible
science. In Material feminisms, edited by Stacy Alaimo, 188–213. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Van der Tuin, Iris. 2011. The new materialist ‘always already’: On an a-human humani-
ties. NORA – Nordic Journal of Feminist and Gender Research 19 (4): 285–290.
Vint, Sherryl. 2008. Entangled posthumanism. Science Fiction Studies 35 (2): 313–319.
162 The materialization of energy security
Voelkner, Nadine. 2011. Managing pathogenic circulation human security and the
migrant health assemblage in Thailand. Security Dialogue 42 (3): 239–259.
Walters, William. 2014. Drone strikes, dingpolitik and beyond: Furthering the debate on
materiality and security. Security Dialogue 45 (2): 101–118.
Wendt, Alexander E. 1987. The agent-structure problem in international relations
theory. International Organization 41 (3): 335–370.
Wendt, Alexander E. 1999. Social theory of international politics. Cambridge and New
York: Cambridge University Press.
Whatmore, Sarah. 2006. Materialist returns: Practising cultural geography in and for a
more-than-human world. Cultural Geographies 13 (4): 600–609.
Wight, Colin. 2000. Interpretation all the way down?: A reply to Roxanne Lynn Doty.
European Journal of International Relations 6 (3): 423–430.
Wight, Colin. 2007a. Inside the epistemological cave all bets are off. Journal of Inter-
national Relations and Development 10 (1): 40–56.
Wight, Colin. 2007b. A manifesto for scientific realism in IR: Assuming the can-opener
won’t work! Millennium – Journal of International Studies 35 (2): 379–398.
Wight, Colin. 2012. Critical realism: Some responses. Review of International Studies 38
(01): 267–274.
Winner, Langdon. 1980. Do artifacts have politics? Daedalus 109 (1): 121–136.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1922. Tractatus logico-philosophicus, translated by C. K. Ogden.
London: Kegan Paul, Trechn, Trubner.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1958. Philosophical investigations, translated by G. E. M. Anscombe.
2nd edn. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
6 Governing with and through
energy security
6.1 Introduction
Whereas previous chapters described security and materialization, this chapter
tries to combine many of the insights that are gathered there by introducing the
work of an author who seems to have written on all of them, yet is underutilized
in relation to energy security.1 In the security chapter, the risk literature dis-
cussed calculative metrics applied to populations to define the norm of accept-
able behaviour. In turn, the materiality chapter discussed materialization, the
performative politics through which reiterative discursive acts become material
(and vice versa), and the role that knowledge gathering practices play within
this materialization. Both of these insights are based on the work of the French
philosopher Michel Foucault, who developed a theoretical framework to under-
stand the power politics and knowledge structures that govern our lives.2 For
Foucault, the relation between security, materiality and knowledge needs to be
seen in close connection to power. He draws attention to the power/knowledge
nexus that enables discourse to materialize and security to act as a governance
technique that makes this happen. In short, with Foucault’s understanding of
governmentality it becomes possible to analyse the role of security by studying
the techniques and social structures (the mentalities and rationalities) that are
used to exercise power over a population within a political economic knowledge
base to organize, regulate and order the circulation behind human reality.3
While this is a mouthful, this chapter will explain each element in turn.
In fact, this chapter draws four arguments from the work of Foucault. First, it
explicitly understands security as a productive form of power. Productive
security implies a performative understanding of security, meaning that ideas
about (energy) security help govern and produce a specific way of life (e.g. high-
energy consumption) through the creation of subjects, markets and the materi-
alization of its concerns. Second, it is not possible to secure something, through
risk or other security practices, when people do not know what it is that needs
securing. Security, earlier interpreted broadly as undesired futures, hence is a
prime example of ontic politics: the identification of that what needs to be
secured and the politics of knowledge and observation that guide it. Third,
security works as it performs bodies, minds, objects and the material world
164 Governing with and through energy security
around us. More specific, security works increasingly in one of two ways. Either
by governing the milieu of the humans or objects that need governing or else by
letting the people involved govern themselves based on shared understandings
of normal and acceptable behaviour. Fourth, based on Foucault’s theory, this
chapter examines how security functions in relation to society, governments,
the economy and nature, and how the boundaries between these fields are con-
stantly performed and redefined through the rearticulation of these concepts,
logics and modes of reasoning.
This chapter proceeds by introducing the concept of governmentality in Section
6.2 as part of the theoretical framework behind Foucault’s notion of security and
risk. To introduce governmentality, this chapter delves deeply into Foucault’s
understanding of the conduct of conduct, his understanding of power and his
concept of biopolitics. Following the identification of biopower as a new form of
power in the early eighteenth century, and the active use of this form of power
under the header of biopolitics, Section 6.3 will continue the discussion of gov-
ernmentality by studying the relation between government, markets and society.
A particular form of governmentality that is discussed here is neo-liberalism: how
freedom is organized through security and how neo-liberalism actively works to
separate economics from politics and society. Section 6.4 will bring the different
notions together, by focusing respectively on the relations between materiality
and governmentality, between knowledge and materiality and between security
and materiality. This chapter ends with a brief summary and reflection.
Foucault teaches that power is less a commodity that can be held than a
force which comes into circulation when human beings – who he considers
to be free beings – come into relation with one another. To be crude, power
as a force that circulates is more like electricity than it is like a lever or a
sword.14
Power, for Foucault, is thus not something tangible nor is it intentional. It is not
the light switch but everything that lies behind one’s ability and desire to pull
the switch. It has no source and no end, but it shifts and transforms. It is ‘located
and exercised at the level of life’ and as such seems to resemble life.15 Moreover,
because it resembles life, Foucault argues that power is not only restrictive but
productive as well. It produces subjects: individuals behaving within and
conform a particular system of thought (a rationality of government).16 That
said, while it is impossible to touch power, it is still possible to analyse it, some-
thing that Foucault manages by differentiating between multiple forms of power,
namely sovereignty, discipline and biopower.
The first form of power is sovereign power or the power of the prince. An
often-quoted description that captures Foucault’s understanding of sovereign
power is ‘the right to take life or let live’.17 In the endorsed ability to order a
death, the sovereign is able to govern life. As a form of power, sovereign power
is aimed at the good of the prince against both internal and external opposition
(other princes). The survival or ‘good’ of the sovereign was seen in terms of the
strength of arms, which consequently was translated in the number and well-
being of the population within his territory,18 in other words on the number and
wealth of his subjects.19 Sovereign power works through both judicial instru-
ments (laws, degrees) and instruments of control (punishment). Such a feudal
form of sovereign power is no longer applicable and Foucault noticed how,
within a modern state, power is actually dispersed over state officials, mothers,
teachers, bosses, generals etc. In other words, lots of individuals and institutes
have some form of sovereign power. This ‘plurality of forms of government’ or
‘the multiplicity and immanence of these activities distinguishes them radically
from the transcendent singularity of Machiavelli’s prince’.20
A second form of power identified by Foucault is discipline. Foucault’s insight
regarding discipline is that the training and conditioning of individuals in
schools or armies, while being applied on the individual is in reality concen-
trated on the group as a whole.21 People are disciplined towards what is con-
sidered to be useful knowledge or correct behaviour. ‘Discipline, of course,
analyzes and breaks down; it breaks down individuals, places, time, movements,
actions, and operations. It breaks them down into components such that they
can be seen, on the one hand, and modified on the other.’22 In other words,
Governing with and through energy security 167
discipline separates those that ‘behave’ from those that do not and exercises
itself on the latter. It does so by exercising its power on a micro level, meaning
the individual body, by correcting towards a norm that applies to the whole
group.23 Foucault for that reason argued in a later work that discipline is not just
about ‘normalization’ or the correction of the bad, but about ‘normation’ or the
diffusion of the norm itself.24 As a form of power, discipline is of interest for
Foucault because it shifts the focus from the prince and his subject to an indi-
vidual body as part of a particular population.25
Foucault’s third form of power is what he sometimes discusses as security but
initially identified as biopower. Biopower, according to Foucault, is a form of
power that combines aspects of both disciplinary and sovereign power, but is
more than just a combination of the two. From discipline, it takes the focus on
populations and the role of individuals. From sovereign power, it takes the focus
on life and well-being. Importantly, however, is that in relation to life and well-
being the focus of biopower shifts from ‘taking lives’ to ‘making live and letting
die’.26 In other words, it differs from both as biopower is mostly a productive
form of power. Literally productive, as it deals with biological ‘matters of life and
death’ and thus ‘with birth and propagation, with health and illness … and with
the processes that sustain or retard the optimization of the life of a population’.27
Biopower is the power to increase life and decrease death through policies that
are based on birth and mortality rates and explicitly aimed at influencing those
rates. This is what Dean calls ‘the administration of life’ or what Foucault in his
earlier work described as ‘regulation’ and later called ‘biopolitics’ (a concept
that is taken up below).28
These three forms of power differ. Discipline and biopower differ on the level
at which their power is effected, with discipline focusing on the individual body
while biopower concentrates on the level of populations.29 They differ as well in
that biopower, by focusing on biological life, works on ‘a number of material
givens’, while discipline instead first ‘determines a segment’ of the overall popu-
lation by ‘isolat[ing] a space’ for itself to work on – those that are in need of
disciplining.30 As a form of power, discipline only works within this site, but
once set ‘allows nothing to escape’.31 In contrast, biopower has no boundaries
and constantly expands to new areas and spaces, depending on what is known
about life and deemed necessary to enhance that life. Most of all, the forms of
power differ on the level of the individual. Whereas discipline makes a norm-
ative judgement on the behaviour of the individual and sovereignty subjugates
the individual to the will of the sovereign, biopower instead takes the behaviour
of individuals for granted and acts only on those effects that are considered con-
sequential for the population as a whole.32 While they differ, Foucault is explicit
in arguing that they do not exclude one another and always return in specific
combinations.33 And, through these combinations, these three forms of power
make up particular forms of governmentality.
168 Governing with and through energy security
6.2.3 Biopolitics
As a form of power, biopower quickly conflates with biopolitics: the actual
administration of life, or, as the concept implies, the politics or strategies of
biopower. While biopolitics is about the politics of life, it is neither a form of
power nor a mode of governmentality. Instead, Foucault sees it as a technology
of power, Collier describes it as a ‘problem space to be analyzed’ (as does
Foucault), while Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero argue that ‘there is no biopolitics
which is not simultaneously also a security apparatus. There is no biopolitics of
this, or a biopolitics of that. When one says biopolitics one says security, albeit
in a certain way.’34 Biopolitics is all that because it administers biological life,
not through the individual as with discipline but by influencing the conditions
or the milieu of individuals based on the knowledge it has gathered over the
population that needs to be secured. Instead of feeding the hungry, biopolitics is
about setting up the conditions for people to feed themselves by enabling and
supporting a circulation of food. Ultimately, biopolitics tries to bring out the full
potential of individuals, a ‘potential [which] is sought to be promoted, enhanced
and, in the process, protected’.35 This full potential needs to be protected against
the ‘random element inherent in a population of living beings’.36 Accidents
happen and they are highly uncertain for individuals. Yet, accidents happen all
the time, so statistically on the level of the population they are far from uncer-
tain (e.g. insurance). In other words, to administer life and protect the well-
being of a population, what is needed are security apparatuses or techniques and
mechanisms aimed at the ‘objects’ of ‘species life’ by gathering and acting upon
the assessed numbers available on a population.37
Even in this brief description of biopolitics, a number of terms stand out and
call for further inquiry; these are population and statistics, prosperity and poten-
tial, things and the milieu, and security. First, biopolitics is geared towards pop-
ulations. Foucault identifies the advent of biopolitics in the shift when wars
were no longer fought in ‘the defense of the sovereign’ but instead were aimed
‘to secur[e] the existence of a population’.38 Before the idea and ability to think
in terms of populations, government was aimed either at the level of the sover-
eign, as the head of the state, or at the level of the family, as the Greek did
when describing the oeconomia as the management of the family. Combining
both levels only became possible with the invention of statistics, through which
it became possible to gain knowledge at the level of the population.39 When
Malthus advanced his food scarcity dilemma, it was based on his insight about
the ‘bio-economic problem’ of a limited area for food production and a faster-
growing population.40
Statistics, in Foucault’s argument, developed along two tracks: on the one
hand, with the organization of the police and, on the other, with the evolution
of mercantilism.41 Police, as a form of government that is internal to the state, is
said by Foucault to be aimed at securing and increasing the domestic output of
the state. It is concerned with the protection of active life, especially those
activities that relate to the state. This implies that the number and safety of the
Governing with and through energy security 169
population, their basic needs, their health and their productivity are all subject
to this form of government. Importantly, before the police can secure all of this,
it needs to know what to secure.42 In other words, to protect life it is necessary
to know life. Foucault argues in this respect that ‘police makes statistics neces-
sary, but police also makes statistics possible’.43
The biopolitical use of statistics, second, is thus aimed at the well-being of
the state.44 In this modern form of power the goal is no longer the well-being of
the prince and his tax revenue but the conditions for the well-being and poten-
tial of the population. This well-being and ‘making life proliferate’ has been
interpreted, from the Greek household oeconomia onwards and especially since
the sixteenth-century physiocrats, as being first and foremost about ‘good eco-
nomic government’.45 A good example of this can be found in Foucault’s discus-
sion of scarcity and how the main idea behind the government of scarce food
supplies shifted from mercantilism to liberalism.46 Foucault describes how food
shortages in France were originally seen as either an unlucky event caused by
bad weather or as a consequence of ‘man’s evil nature’ (his never-ending desire
and unwillingness to share).47 The reigning mercantilists countered scarcity
through an ‘anti-scarcity system’ that tried to control all economic and trade
related aspects of it through price controls, hoarding prohibitions, export restric-
tions, import diversification and the stockpiling of reserves.48 In other words,
mercantilism tried to govern scarce food supplies by introducing ‘laws, decrees,
regulations: that is to say, the traditional weapons of sovereignty’.49 As it fixed
prices and organized distribution, it also stifled incentives to increase food pro-
duction during periods of scarcity and thereby prolonged the shortage periods.50
Foucault noted how a strand of scholars called the physiocrats hence argued for
what now would be seen as a more liberal programme: one that moved away
from ‘the obsessive fear of scarcity’ to ‘the reality of grain’ and trusted the
markets to minimize scarcity by letting prices fluctuate and goods circulate in
order to provide individuals incentives to counter a shortage.51 Basically, as
Dean remarks, ‘the discovery of the ontological reality of scarcity … mean[t]
that the administration of life must take into account the means of production
for the subsistence of that life’.52 However, as these means cannot be controlled
by the state directly, the government had to find a way to let go and let the
market handle it (while indirectly governing people by managing the undesired
elements of these markets).
Third, the discovery of the ‘reality of scarcity’ and the ‘means of production’
implies that what is governed through biopolitics are things, not people alone.
Whereas sovereignty exercises its power on a particular territory, biopolitics
exercises its power on the conditions that enable people to live freely; in other
words, on the things they relate to. Foucault takes a broad perspective on these
‘things’. He sees them as material, that is, things like resources or the weather.
He also sees them as ‘men in their relationships with things’, by which he
focuses on the ‘customs, habits, ways of acting and thinking’ through which men
and things relate.53 Finally, Foucault describes these things as uncertain events,
events like ‘accidents, misfortunes, famine, epidemics and death’ that result
170 Governing with and through energy security
from ‘men in their relationship with things’,54 in other words the uncertainty
inherent in life, which is discussed as undesired futures in Chapter 4 and as sur-
prising events in Chapter 5. Biopolitics works on these things: it ‘disposes’ of
them using different forms of power to achieve the desired goal of an affluent
population.55
Fourth, not only is biopolitics a governing of individuals through the things
they relate to, it is also a form of governing based on a certain ‘naturalness’.56
Since the physiocrats, the well-being of a population has been based on the laws
of the market. While these laws are not part of nature as such – they stem from
the interaction between people – they are seen as natural, as a given. This natu-
ralness results, according to Foucault, in a separation of the state and the
economy.57 Gordon in fact describes this ‘naturalized’ way of thinking in terms
of a ‘transformation in the relationship between knowledge and government’.58
He sees it as an internalization at the side of the government of the liberal argu-
ment that it can never know the economy completely and therefore can never
govern it completely.59
Fifth, just as the category population combines the state with the household,
it also bridges the individual and his environment, a point Foucault takes from
Darwin and his focus on the survival and evolution of the species within a par-
ticular milieu.60 The milieu for Foucault is both a medium and an element. The
milieu is a medium as it ‘is needed to account for action at a distance of one
body on another’, while it is simultaneously the ‘element in which it circu-
lates’.61 As both medium and element, the milieu offers a circular reasoning of
cause and effect between those parts of the milieu that affect and those that are
affected.62 In more general terms, the milieu, for Foucault, is ‘a certain number
of combined, overall effects’ of the above-mentioned people in their relation-
ship with things and each other. In recent commentaries, the milieu is often
translated in terms of a flat network analogy, where everything is connected in
constant circulation across time and space.63 Through such a relational analogy,
discussed in Chapter 5, the milieu bridges the social environment of people with
their material environment.
To govern such a milieu, filled with men, things, mentalities and uncertain-
ties, biopolitics aims to administer the conditions of life while remaining open
to life itself, in other words to deal with the complexity and uncertainty inher-
ent in the relations that make up life itself.64 Foucault describes biopolitics con-
sequentially as a security apparatus (also security dispotif or mechanism). Such a
security apparatus tries to manage the constant uncertainty of life by ‘plan[ning]
a milieu in terms of events or series of events or [its] possible elements’.65 Bio-
politics does not govern humans directly but focuses on their conduct by:
structuring the desires, proprieties and possibilities that shape the operation
of life working on and through subjective freedoms, governmental rationali-
ties typically develop around specific problematics, such as those of health,
wealth, security, poverty, esteem, culture, sexuality or migration.66
Governing with and through energy security 171
Alternatively, as Renzi and Elmer state it:
While firmly driven by security considerations, biopolitics thus has a clear eco-
nomic focus, a focus that does not influence people by controlling their (eco-
nomic) freedom through laws but by nudging what they desire and by what they
see as possible; in other words, by administering the freedom that individuals
experience.68 Freedom in this perspective is something that is constantly con-
structed through the particular ways that we understand a problem and what we
see as appropriate behaviour. As Amoore concludes, connecting the statements
above, ‘in contrast to a world in which biopolitics eclipses sovereign and discip-
linary power, we see a security apparatus that mobilizes specific techniques for
deploying the norm to govern uncertain and unfolding populations’.69
6.3.1 Governmentality
Whereas biopolitics (security), sovereign power and discipline are techniques of
power, Foucault sees governmentality simultaneously as a technique and as
something more than a technique. Foucault writes that he sees governmentality
in three ways: as an ensemble, as a mode of power (equating it with biopower),
and as a process. Governmentality refers to the ensemble of ‘institutions, proced-
ures, analyses and reflections, calculations, and tactics’ that exercises itself as a
form of power.70 In turn, as a form of power governmentality has overshadowed
other types of power (sovereignty, discipline), which are now only active under
governmentality. This follows the creation of the modern state based on the
development of an evolving administrative process from the Middle Ages
onward, which is the third meaning of governmentality. To be clear, the state
itself is not driving this process. On the contrary: the state is an outcome, a
tactic according to Lemke, of governmentality.71 Governmentality is ‘the tactics
of government that allow the continual definition of what should or should not
fall within the state’s domain, what is public and what private, what is and is
not within the state’s competence, and so on’.72 Within this constant judging of
its domain, Dean remarks how a failure to govern has the peculiar effect of
reinforcing the actual governmentality process.73 In line with the discussion on
how failed security leads to more security, governmentality as a mode of power
continues even when its programmes have failed.
Governmentality stems from what Foucault has identified as the pastoral
mentalité and the mentalité of raison d’état. The pastoral mentalité, the Chris-
tian understanding of a shepherd herding a flock, is explained by Foucault as
172 Governing with and through energy security
‘a subtle economy of merit and fault’ where power is not applied on individuals
but through them.74 It is a teleological economy that creates obedient subjects
or people who see themselves as sheep needing to be saved and are situated
within a certain system of knowledge based on a particular truth, in this case
the word of God that can be found in scripture. Within this rationality, the
merits and faults of the individual are analysed by the pastor, atonements are
transferred and penance is offered for the individual to reach salvation. A pasto-
ral mentalité is thus guiding, instead of forcing, individuals as part of the popu-
lation for the good of the individual, instead of the state or the sovereign.75
A more modern form of pastoral power can be found, according to Foucault,
in the above-discussed ‘police government’ as this has a similar economy of
merit and faults.76 Of course, the economy of a police government is not driven
by salvation and obedience to God but by raison d’état or the survival of the
state itself. Based on statistics and calculation, the state, by way of its
authoritative subjects (police officers and other representatives of the state),
learns of itself and acts on itself through its population. Ultimately, it tries to
produce happy individuals by protecting processes of circulation (of people,
goods, ideas) and by separating good from bad circulation, for the simple
reason that happy citizens are also economically active and useful citizens
who strengthen the state, especially in comparison to other states and their
populations.77
In building on both the pastoral economy of merits and faults and the calcu-
lation and statistics of raison d’état, governmentality introduces an even larger
focus on economic reasoning and thereby increases the separation of economics
and society.78 In each of the mentalités discussed so far, individuals are subjec-
tivized as part of a population within a particular system of knowledge contain-
ing a particular truth. Foucault even argues that ‘to become individual one must
become subject’.79 In other words, while Western citizens consider themselves
free individuals, they are only free because they have become subjects. Whether
that is to a technology of the self (self-reflection), a form of discipline, or a tech-
nology of the market (promoted circulation) is irrelevant. People are free
because they are made to think and act as if they were free. They are only free,
as Hayek argues, owing ‘to restraints of freedom’.80 In other words, as stated
before, the only freedom people have is the freedom that is provided, organized
and secured.
This hints at the wider relations between the state, economy and society.81
Governmentality builds on a Marxist-inspired separation of political and non-
political spheres, with society and the economy as clear examples. By accepting
the reality of grain, the early physiocrats worked hard to make the economy into
a non-political sphere as they separated it from sovereign forms of control based
on, first, the unknowability of the total economic process (ungovernable) and,
second, the ‘naturalness’ of the economic relations between men (e.g. Smith’s
invisible hand).82 Because the sovereign or government cannot know all the
processes related to the economic circulation of men and things, it cannot act
upon them. A liberal organized economy, according to Foucault, therefore
Governing with and through energy security 173
always assumes that ‘one always governs too much’ and in reaction tries to
organize government as cost-effectively as possible.83 In Foucauldian terms, the
market (e.g. the naturalness of economic processes that cumulate in and are vis-
ualized by prices) becomes ‘a standard of truth’ that is used to judge ‘govern-
mental practices’.84 Still, while government can only act indirectly (as described
above), this does not mean that economics is the ‘science of government’ or
that it is the ‘governmental rationality itself ’.85
One reason for this is because society plays a role as well. What nowadays is
known as society is explained by Foucault as ‘the juridical structure (économie
juridique) of a governmentality pegged to the economic structure (économie
économique)’.86 He sees (civil) society as a wider and mainly judicial, sphere of
government, which, on the one hand, offers the economic relations a space to
be played out and, on the other hand, limits the government by offering another
moment of self-reflection by asking the fundamental question ‘why must one
govern’ in the first place?87 Besides limiting the government, society also inter-
acts with the economy. This too is a double-edged relationship as markets are
part of society and thus reinforce it, but at the same time undermine the com-
munitarian relations of society with their focus on self-interest.88 Foucault
describes this interaction by referring to his earlier food scarcity example:
When the economic subject sees that he can make a profit by buying wheat
in Canada, for example, and selling it in England, he will do so. He does it
because it is to his advantage, and furthermore it will benefit everyone.
However, the bonds of civil society mean that one prefers to stay in one’s
community, even if one finds abundance and security elsewhere.89
What this quote highlights is that neither the economic nor the security ration-
alities are total. In other words, there are options that ‘free’ individuals are able
to take which do not follow the forceful logics of either the market or security.
In a sense, this is what Dean means when he argues that ‘while government
gives shape to freedom, it is not constitutive of freedom’.90 Instead, Dean sees
freedom as originating in the acting and thinking of both those who are being
governed and those who are governing.91 Freedom is thus enacted or performed
by all those involved and, as such, is open to change.
Nevertheless, the resulting uncertainty inherent to life that follows from this
openness is a form of freedom that is constantly secured. The desire to secure
against the unexpected is something that Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero have iden-
tified as the ‘fundamental paradox [behind] biopolitics’.92 To secure the living,
life needs to be fixed. However, once secured it is no longer true life, as true life
thrives on transformation and unfulfilled potential. ‘In order for a living thing
… to be secured it has to be allowed – indeed encouraged – to pass out of phase
with itself and become something other than what it was in order to continue
to live’.93 Foucault’s freedom, therefore, is not a freedom in terms of ‘exemptions
and privileges’ but it is a particular ‘freedom of circulation’ of goods, people
and ideas, and it is this freedom of circulation that he sees secured in everyday
174 Governing with and through energy security
practices.94 The consequence of such a practice is that it is not an actual threat
that needs to be contained but that the attention shifts to those parts of life that
might become dangerous, in other words the virtual of Chapter 5.95 By shifting to
the virtual, every fear and imagination can become a source for action. Every-
thing can become dangerous and undesired, but Foucault argues that this all-
embracing stance is limited by the liberal cost–benefit analyses to which security
is subject as well. Instead of prohibiting all soft drugs, there is an increasing
number of countries where it is regulated or tolerated, only to be acted upon
when thresholds are crossed and the costs incurred by its usage warrant the cost
of governmental intervention.96
To be clear, the goal of governmentality or biopolitics is neither security nor
freedom, especially not liberal (democratic) freedom. In fact, Foucault argues
that a liberal governmentality, as it builds on biopower, is and needs to be
inherently racist in the sense that it constantly creates distinctions (in line with
the focus on differentiation in Chapter 5).97 It needs to be, because how else
to identify and act on those parts of the population that weaken it? How else to
decide ‘between what must live and what must die’.98 Moving this argument to
its extreme, Dean argues that this is another aspect where sovereign power and
biopower differ: contrary to sovereign power, biopolitics does not have a con-
straint on ‘the right to kill’.99 For the sovereign prince the ultimate exercise of
power was to kill, but this would have left him one fewer person to govern.
However, biopolitics, in order to strengthen the population as a whole has no
such limitations and instead contains a Darwinian need to weed out the weak.
An additional violation identified by Dean is found within the subjects them-
selves, who, in the constant biopolitical struggle to behave in a ‘mature and
responsible’ way, in effect repress any alternative desires to behave otherwise.100
Security, in short, draws a boundary between forms of life that are valued and
forms of life that are not.
These boundaries are akin to power, which in line with Foucault is a good
thing. The reason being that a person can resist, however little, a form of power
that is exercised over him or her. If a person cannot resist, if they cannot even
think or whisper, then what is exercised according to Foucault is not power but
brute force.101 Whereas brute force is applied on objects, power is meant to guide
individuals as subjects and can therefore be resisted. This resistance against the
current conduct, whether by thinking, acting or speaking, is something Foucault
named counter-conduct.102 With this term, Foucault refers not to opposition, dis-
sidence or revolt. Each of these terms originates from within a system of biopoli-
tics and is used to exclude those involved, to differentiate us from them. Indeed,
active opposition to a particular system of thought and practices often reinforces
that system, as direct opposition is simultaneously an indirect form of
acknowledgement. A system can reject and ridicule such opposition, for
example in the case of Occupy Wall Street, but it can also incorporate the con-
cerns. Liberalism is so prevalent because it incorporates sociocultural concerns
on natural resource use, climate change or privacy concerns within its own
system of thought by translating them from externalities to commodities
Governing with and through energy security 175
(carbon markets).103 In short, counter-conduct is not a direct act against a par-
ticular mentalité but refers to the desire to behave ‘well’ from within another
rationality, one that counters some of the core assumptions of the former. In
this sense, Evans and Reid as well as Lundborg and Vaughan-Williams question
the recent interest in the concept of resilience. They see resilience as a concept
which, instead of offering a way out, is a solution that constantly reinforces the
virtual uncertainty and vulnerability that is inherent in liberal systems.104 For
Evans and Reid such resilient subjects are passive subjects: they no longer act-
ively secure or change the world around them, they only adapt to ‘a series of
dangerous events’.105 This in turn, as Foucault teaches, reinforces the initial
assumption behind society, namely that individuals and their freedom are vul-
nerable and need to be governed.
6.3.2 (Neo-)liberalism
Another aspect to mention in respect to the broader line of Foucault’s work is
the already-touched-upon link between governmentality, biopolitics and
(neo-)liberalism.106 The organization and role of markets and economic rela-
tions is of principal importance in Foucault’s understanding of forms of govern-
ance. Burchell explains how, for Foucault, liberalism is not a ‘theoretical
doctrine’ but a ‘rationalizing governmental practice’.107 It is a rationalizing gov-
ernmental practice because it is ‘a political project that endeavors to create a
social reality that it suggests already exists’ (comparable to Barroso’s securitiza-
tion in Chapter 4).108 In turn, while it is a political project, it is not only a
political project. Collier rightly remarks that it is first and foremost a system
of thought that promotes its own mentalité and practices while it criticizes
other modes of thinking. It is something that is pushed by certain thinkers in a
certain time.109 In other words, ‘liberalism is a version of biopolitics’, as well as
a limit on the biopolitics of governmentality due to its dominance and
principles.110
That liberalism limits sovereign power based on both the unknowability of
the total system and the naturalness of the economic relations has already been
discussed. However, liberalism also limits governmentality by building ‘on the
rational behaviour of those who are governed’, which it does by presupposing
free and rational individuals who uphold a liberal calculative rationality instead
of envisioning individuals with juridical rights and responsibilities.111 In shaping
these rational individuals and the responding rational theories, a liberal govern-
mentality is thus reliant on free individuals who also have the ability to resist
that same liberal governmentality.112 There is, consequently, a certain restraint
on liberal governmentality and the state. Yet, at the same time, the restraint
supports the view of rational individuals and thereby upholds the liberal govern-
mentality. In this respect, Lemke sees the shifting boundaries between state,
society and markets ‘as element and effect’ of a neo-liberal-inspired governmen-
tality.113 As he argues, ‘the so-called retreat of the state is in fact a prolongation
of government: neoliberalism is not the end but a transformation’.114
176 Governing with and through energy security
This free individual is not only considered free and rational; they are also
considered to be driven by desire. By translating desire into personal interests
and by assuming that these personal interests, when given ‘free play’ on the
market, become the collective interest, it is desire that links the individual to
the population in liberal economic thought. Foucault argues that in this trans-
formation to collective interests one can witness ‘both the naturalness of popu-
lation and the possible artificiality of the means one adopts to manage it’.115
This implies that desire is something that is and can be managed, which makes
it a technology of power.116 In other words, liberalism governs through the
calculation of a population’s collective interests, which it secures by identifying
the conflicting individual desires and personal interests that endanger the popu-
lation.117 It then works on these individual desires by manipulating the milieu,
but to do so it needs to assume that individual desires are rational (cost-
effective) and thus governable based on the conduct of conduct. (If these per-
sonal interests are deemed irrational, it is hard to act upon them through the
market itself and liberalism needs to fall back on the state and more traditional
forms of power by actively intervening in the freedom of the individuals.) As
Foucault summarizes this liberal line of thought from the perspective of security
and governmentality:
The market and all of society are built around this game between freedom and
security: between the protection from dangers to the game and the protection
against dangers that stem from within the game itself.119
The description of liberalism so far should not be interpreted as if there is a
liberalism, as if it is a closed, totalized system. It is not. Foucault’s main approach
was to open up the naturalness of such central characteristics by showing how
certain ideas have developed over time. In the case of liberal thought, Foucault
differentiates for instance between classic liberals and two types of neo-liberals,
including German ordo-liberals and American liberals. Disregarding all his
nuances, early liberals can be said to have introduced the ‘naturalness’ of the
market through the principle of exchange and to have introduced the separa-
tion of market and state. Ordo-liberals shifted the focus to the principle of com-
petition and consequently looked at the twin organization of the state and the
market, while striving for the optimum conditions for individuals to be able to
live up to their potential. American liberals, in turn, exported the economic
perspective of rational individuals to other social areas, introducing a broader
economized society as a check on government action.120 Again, and following
Dean, these forms of liberalism support the initial position of Foucault that one
should not judge these liberal rationalities but instead be mindful of their
Governing with and through energy security 177
different effects and implications.121 Dean, however, contradicts his own state-
ment by concluding that both classic and neo-liberalism are ‘naïve’ as they
reduce the role of the state and thereby open the door to a return of sovereign
power, but this time applied by the markets themselves: he gives the example of
forced work projects for the unemployed.122
Of course, this does not mean that scholars using Foucault’s ideas cannot be
critical. Nally, for example, is highly critical when he discusses the influence of
a liberal rationality on hunger from a food systems perspective.123 His main con-
clusion is that the continuous struggle against hunger is not a ‘failure of the
modern food regime’ as such but instead a ‘logical expression of [the food sys-
tem’s] central paradoxes, particularly its reliance on over-production in some
places and under-production in others’.124 These paradoxes, Nally concludes, are
a result of ‘the neoliberal truth regime [which] presents global markets, agrarian
biotechnologies and multinational corporate initiatives as the structural precon-
ditions for alleviating world hunger’.125 Nally shows how hunger in Europe
steadily decreased with an increase in colonization, not because the problem of
hunger was solved but because the problem was displaced from the poor in
Europe to the people in the colonies, where ‘the destruction of pre-existing anti-
scarcity programmes was rapid and severe as market mechanisms were frequently
permitted to operate unchecked and with devastating consequences’.126 Pro-
duced food was shipped to those who could afford it: creating abundance where
there was scarcity and scarcity where there was abundance. By using a
Foucauldian-inspired critical approach to disclose these paradoxes, it becomes
possible to argue that current solutions (often technical fixes or claims for more
free markets) are ‘empirically shaky and ideologically driven’ as they inherently
disregard other alternative explanations, like Sen’s argument that the entitle-
ments to food are more important than the actual amount of food.127
Nature thus becomes part of a capitalist system, which, like liberalism, is also
not a ‘fixed’ or ‘completed’ way of doing things.130 Instead, Nitzan and Bichler
describe it as a ‘forward-looking’ and ‘commodified’ mode of power.131 The
178 Governing with and through energy security
financialization of nature, of the milieu itself, offers a search for and commodifi-
cation of knowledge about the future. In other words, in the commodification of
the milieu, ‘enterprising’ capitalists turn towards the practices of risk calculation
to make sense of a ‘permanently uncertain environment’, not to fight it, but, as
Massumi claims, to ‘ride’ it.132
Risk calculation is discussed extensively in Section 4.5, but in terms of neo-
liberalism and governmentality there are some additional remarks to be made.
First, in terms of its historic development, it is possible to say that modern risk
has its origins in the collective insurance schemes installed with the organiza-
tion of the early shipping expeditions to the Eastern and Western hemispheres.
These schemes transformed individual risks into collective risk and ultimately
evolved with and into the West European welfare states, which took responsib-
ility for social risks such as health and unemployment on a national level. More
recently, with the ‘withdrawal of the state’, risk is once more turning into an
individual responsibility, something the individual is expected to buy into (or
not) depending on the individual’s personal risk analysis.133 Expected, first,
because it is deemed cost-ineffective for governments to organize totalizing
social insurance programmes, and, second, because, as Lemke argues, a neo-
liberal rationality ‘aspires to construct responsible subjects whose moral quality
is based on the fact that they rationally assess the costs and benefits of a certain
act as opposed to other alternative acts’.134 Making a risk analysis, making the
right risk analysis and behaving in line with the countermeasures to minimize
risks become moral qualities for people to uphold and on which they are judged
and judge themselves.135 Risk thus works through the technologies of the market
towards the state (and governmentality) and as a moral quality on the level of
the self.
Not only is the meaning of risk changing over time; its contents are shifting
as well. From the possibility of insuring oneself against well-known but uncer-
tain events (natural disasters, sickness, investments), neo-liberal risk is increas-
ingly focusing on the virtual. It is no longer enough to deal with events that most
likely will happen, but these days everything needs to be analysed and secured,
from the infinitely small impact and high-likelihood events to the infinitely
large impact but low-chance calamities.136 A neo-liberal future is therefore
described as ‘radically uncertain’ and it is in this uncertainty that security and
economy meet.137 In this respect, Dillon concludes that:
6.5 Reflection
This chapter focused on the later work of Foucault in order to combine and
deepen many of the insights on security and materiality from the previous chap-
ters to further the study of energy security as a security practice. In particular,
this chapter focused on the politics of security, combining the performativity of
modern security theories with the performativity of a materialdiscursive world.
It tried to answer how we can make sense of the politics and power behind
security, narrowly in terms of how it works, and more broadly as part of society?
Section 6.2 drew on Foucault’s ontology to introduce the core elements
of security. It surmises that governmentality builds on techniques like the
186 Governing with and through energy security
power/knowledge regimes as well as notions like biopolitics and security apparatuses
to analyse a modern form of (bio)power that is aimed at populations and every-
thing that ‘makes life live’, versus the historic sovereign power ‘to kill or let live’
or the disciplinary power exercised over individuals to make them behave as
part of the norm. Power is key for Foucault in these (and other) political
processes and is understood to be intangible, relational and affective, as electri-
city instead of the light switch. Once administered through shared strategies,
this form of biopower becomes biopolitics. Biopolitics governs life as it regulates
the circulations of people and things. It does so by influencing the desires of
individuals through the milieu in the interest of the population, which is only
possible after knowledge has been gathered over populations. A process that
defines it and subjectivizes people to this population. Without knowledge, there
is no problematization and hence no ability to act. This turns biopolitics into a
security apparatus that organizes and defends freedom. The freedom that allows
circulation to take place and which allows life and the relationships that consti-
tute life to gather and splinter.
The particular manner or strategies through which biopolitics is applied,
through technologies of the self and the market (conduct of conduct), together
with the gathering of knowledge about populations, is part of what Foucault
describes as governmentality. Section 6.3 hence described the outward politics
of security by approaching governmentality as a practice that is constantly
balancing governmental (security) practices with society and economy, each
with their own biopolitics. The economy, for example, includes its own
(neo‑)liberal biopolitics based on the freedom of consumers and producers to
act within markets. It is in the constant rearticulating of this balance, among
others by the liberal argument of the unknowability and hence uncontrollabil-
ity of the economy, that economy and security meet. In the search for profit
and the need for security, both seek to know the radical uncertain future as
best as they can. This turns risk into a core technique to rule the lives of iden-
tified populations by distributing ‘security’ and the accompanying material
benefits.190
Section 6.4 discussed in more detail how Foucault approaches the material
world, by discussing the milieu and circulation, and by continuing the discus-
sion on risk. The goal of this chapter was not to differentiate Foucault from new
materialist and modern security studies or alternative understandings of perfor-
mativity. On the contrary, by reading Foucault through a material lens that
focuses on materialization (of power), which looks at the close connection
between calculation, politics of ontology, the governing of circulation and
security apparatuses, what becomes obvious is how closely related all these
different theoretical fields are. It showed how Foucault’s idea of productive
security is strongly performative of itself and of nature and society. However,
above all, his notion of the power/knowledge nexus bring out both the political
role of calculations and knowledge gathering practices as simultaneously meas-
uring, defining and differentiating, as well as the materialization of these dis-
courses through non-discursive acts and their enactment in the milieu of the
Governing with and through energy security 187
humans and things that are recognized and subjected to these knowledge
practices.
In terms of energy security, this chapter offered an alternative to the way in
which energy security is studied in regular policy debates and academia. Simul-
taneously, it offered the theoretical grounding behind many of the conclusions
and insights from the earlier theoretical chapters. Moreover, it added to those
theoretical chapters by seeing (energy) security as a security apparatus that:
(1) is productive, (2) is based on knowledge gathering practices with their
inherent differentiation, (3) is a form of governing and materialization and
(4) facilitates in drawing boundaries on a social level between nature, eco-
nomics, the political and society. With such an understanding, energy security
becomes a set of relations between men and things, a set with strategic intent
that is constantly performed and disrupted, and part of the circulation of energy.
Such a set of relations is enacted by other sets in and through a milieu, while it
acts on the milieu of other sets. In short, each call for energy security is a perfor-
mative act for a particular understanding of energy security and the work of
Foucault helps us understand the governance and politics of energy security and
how (energy) security acts politically towards other forms of governance.
Notes
1 With some exceptions, as Foucault has been used for energy broadly, with work
from Klauser, Paasche and Söderström 2014; Hargreaves, Nye and Burgess 2013;
Mitchell 2013; Tyfield 2014; Waitt et al. 2016; Gailing 2016.
2 Foucault 2003, 2007, 2008.
3 See, for example, Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008; Dillon 2008.
4 Lemke 2002, 50. However, see Michel Senellart’s course context discussion in
Foucault 2007, 339, note 126, where Senellart argues that this contraction is a
translation error and governmentality instead is the noun of governmental just as
musicality derives from musical.
5 Lemke 2002, 50.
6 Ibid.
7 Foucault 1991, 91.
8 Foucault 2007, 193.
9 Dean 2010, 17.
10 Gordon 1991, 3. This thesis follows Dean 2010, 24, who defines rationality as: ‘any
way of reasoning, or way of thinking about, calculating and responding to a
problem, which is more or less systematic, and which might draw upon formal
bodies of knowledge or expertise’.
11 Lobo-Guerrero 2012, xvi–xvii.
12 Dean 2010, 19.
13 Gordon 1991, 7.
14 Dillon 2010, 63.
15 Lobo-Guerrero 2007, 330.
16 Foucault 1982.
17 Foucault 2003, 241.
18 Foucault 1991, 90.
19 Foucault 2003, 35.
20 Foucault 1991, 91.
21 Foucault 2007, 12.
188 Governing with and through energy security
22 Ibid., 56.
23 Foucault 2003, 38.
24 Foucault 2007, 57.
25 Foucault 1991, 102.
26 Foucault 2003, 247.
27 Dean 2010, 119.
28 Ibid.; Foucault 2003, 2008.
29 Foucault 2003, 250.
30 Foucault 2007, 19, 44.
31 Ibid., 45.
32 Ibid.
33 Ibid., 8. What Foucault 1991, 102, has called the ‘sovereignty-discipline-
government’ triangle.
34 Collier 2009, 94; Foucault 2007, 11–12; Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 266;
Watts 2004b. For a problem to be governable, it needs a problem space. Methmann
describes how the earth’s carbon cycle has become such a problem space based on
the technological ability to monitor carbon emissions and their effects. Within this
problem space, the population is defined as those people and institutions that are
related to the emission of carbon. See Methmann 2013, 78.
35 Lobo-Guerrero 2007, 331.
36 Foucault 2003, 246.
37 Collier 2009, 83; Foucault 2003, 2007; Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008.
38 Campbell 2005, 950.
39 Foucault 1991, 99.
40 Foucault 2007, 77.
41 Gordon 1991, 11.
42 Foucault 2007, 323–326.
43 Ibid., 315.
44 Gordon 1991, 19.
45 Foucault 2003, 253. See also Massumi 2009, 157; Foucault 1991, 92.
46 Foucault 2007.
47 Ibid., 31.
48 Ibid., 33.
49 Foucault 1991, 98.
50 Foucault sees mercantilism as the first serious attempt to gather knowledge/data on
an issue to help govern the problem of food shortages and economic growth in
general. See Foucault 2007, 102.
51 Ibid., 36.
52 Dean 2010, 137.
53 Foucault 2007, 96.
54 Ibid.
55 Foucault 1991, 95.
56 Foucault 2007, 354.
57 Ibid., 349, 354.
58 Gordon 1991, 14.
59 Ibid., 16.
60 Foucault 2007, 78, 2003, 245.
61 Foucault 2007, 20–21.
62 Compare to the discussion of Bryant in Section 5.4.
63 Dillon and Reid 2001, 47; Campbell 2005, 951.
64 Foucault 2007, 296.
65 Ibid., 20.
66 Dillon and Reid 2001, 48. See also the quote by Mitchell Dean in Watts 2004a, 55.
67 Renzi and Elmer 2013, 48.
Governing with and through energy security 189
68 Dillon 1996, 34.
69 Amoore 2013, 65.
70 Foucault 2007, 108.
71 Foucault 1991, 103; Lemke 2002, 58.
72 Foucault 2007, 109.
73 Dean 2010, 220.
74 Foucault 2007, 173, 184–185.
75 Ibid., 129.
76 Gordon 1991, 12.
77 Dean 2010, 224.
78 Foucault 2007, 348.
79 Ibid., 231, note†.
80 Hayek 1979, 163. As quoted by Dean 2010, 182–183. See also Dillon 1996, 10.
81 And nature; see Mitchell 2013 on the manner in which economics creates nature as
something outside of politics.
82 Foucault 2008, 280–282.
83 Ibid., 319. As Best 2007, 90 argues: ‘Paradoxically, while the economy is often the
exception to politics as usual, it is an exception that simultaneously enables and
constrains the possibility of exercising sovereignty itself ’.
84 Foucault 2008, 32. Dean 2010, 184, reflects on Hayek and notes that Hayek, contra
Foucault’s naturalness, translates his non-natural state of freedom to the market,
which he sees as neither ‘natural’ nor as an ‘organized system’. Instead, Hayek sees
markets as ‘spontaneous social order[s]’.
85 Foucault 2008, 286.
86 Ibid., 296.
87 Ibid., 296, 319. Aradau and Van Munster 2008, 34 argue that ‘Rather than a formal
guideline, law is part of the material reality of society’.
88 Foucault 2008, 301, 302.
89 Ibid., 303.
90 Dean 2010, 21.
91 Ibid., 24.
92 Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 271.
93 Ibid.
94 Foucault 2007, 48; Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 282.
95 Lundborg and Vaughan-Williams 2011, 374; Foucault 2007, 315; Dillon 2008, 314.
96 Foucault 2007, 5–6.
97 Foucault 2003, 254–255.
98 Ibid., 254, 258.
99 Dean 2010, 164.
100 Ibid., 156.
101 Foucault 1988, 83–84; Selby 2007, 332.
102 Foucault 2007, 201–202.
103 Dean 2010, 182.
104 Lundborg and Vaughan-Williams 2011, 375. Evans and Reid 2013, 84 actually argue
that ‘the underlying ontology of resilience, therefore, is actually vulnerability. To be
able to become resilient, one must first accept that one is fundamentally vulnerable.’
105 Evans and Reid 2013, 87.
106 See also Collier 2009, 100, who argues that the overwhelming focus on the concept
of governmentality overshadows any critical readings of (neo-)liberalism.
107 Burchell 1991, 143. See also Best 2007, 91.
108 Lemke 2002, 60.
109 Collier 2009, 100. Collier comments on the limited number of thinkers introduced
and analysed by Foucault to make this point, and the lack of attention of current
scholars towards the fact that this is actually a process (supported by Foucault).
190 Governing with and through energy security
110 Dean 2010, 132.
111 Foucault 2008, 312; Dean 2010, 63.
112 Best 2007, 92.
113 Lemke 2002, 59.
114 Ibid., 58; Foucault 2008, 112.
115 Foucault 2007, 72–73, 73.
116 Rose 1999, 85–89.
117 Foucault 2008, 65.
118 Ibid.
119 Compare with Figure 3.1.
120 Foucault 2008; Dean 2010, chaps 2 and 8.
121 Dean 2010, 73.
122 Ibid., 259.
123 Nally 2011.
124 Ibid., 49.
125 Ibid.
126 Ibid.
127 Ibid.; Sen 1983.
128 Massumi 2009, 177.
129 Lemke 2002, 56.
130 Lobo-Guerrero 2012, 2, who continuous from Thrift 2005, 1.
131 Renzi and Elmer 2013, 48; Nitzan and Bichler 2009, 280–282, 294; Bichler and
Nitzan 2012.
132 Massumi 2009, 176.
133 Lemke 2002, 59.
134 Ibid.
135 Lupton 2006, 14; Amoore and De Goede 2008, 12.
136 Ewald 1993, 222.
137 Aradau and Van Munster 2008, 29.
138 Dillon 2007b, 45.
139 Dillon 2007a, 22. See also Luhmann 1993.
140 Amoore 2013, 5.
141 Foucault also never discussed the connections between humans and non-humans;
see Lemke 2015, 5.
142 Foucault 2002, 114, 120–121, 54.
143 Ibid., 77, 179–180.
144 Foucault 1977, 30, 1980, 57–58.
145 Butler 1993, 10–11; Lemke 2015, 13.
146 Hardy and Thomas 2015, 681, 682; Lundborg and Vaughan-Williams 2015, 19.
147 Foucault 2007, 96.
148 Lemke 2015, 9.
149 Foucault 2007, 22.
150 Lemke 2015, 10; Latour 2005; Preda 1999, 358; Bennett 2010.
151 Shannon 2014, 257.
152 Ibid., 255.
153 Ibid., 250.
154 Ibid., 261, 258.
155 Ibid., 250, 259.
156 See also Lemke 2015.
157 Ibid., 10.
158 Foucault 1980.
159 Rouse 2005, 96–97.
160 Hekman 2010, 57.
161 Ibid., 58; Mol 2002.
Governing with and through energy security 191
162 Preda 1999, 358.
163 Foucault 1980, 52.
164 Amoore 2013, 32–39.
165 Ibid., 34.
166 Ibid., 35.
167 Ibid., 36 quotes: Edgar Jones (1995) True and Fair: A History of Price Waterhouse,
London: Hamish Hamilton, 12 [emphasis added by Amoore].
168 Ibid., 38.
169 Ibid., 47.
170 Ibid., 39.
171 Luhmann 1993.
172 Related, Elden introduces the concept of geometrics and geopower as an alternative
to biometrics and biopower, believing that biopower focuses too much on humans
and not enough on territory and geography. My reading of Foucault’s biopolitics
above is more material than Elden’s, so I do not follow along in his argument. Elden
2007, 2013; Bridge 2015.
173 Barry 2006.
174 Callon 1998; MacKenzie, Muniesa and Siu 2007; Fine 2005.
175 Mitchell 2013.
176 Ibid., 251.
177 Ibid., 241.
178 Ibid., 247.
179 Ibid., 246.
180 Foucault 2007, 37.
181 Foucault 1980, 194; Aradau and Van Munster 2007, 97.
182 Foucault 2007, 11; Nally 2011, 38.
183 Dillon 2008, 311; Dillon and Lobo-Guerrero 2008, 266.
184 Schouten 2014, 30.
185 Ibid.
186 Foucault 1980.
187 Aradau et al. 2015.
188 Kester 2018.
189 Schouten 2014, 24. See also the discussion on observation in Section 5.5.
190 Dillon and Reid 2001; Dillon 2008; Amoore 2013.
Bibliography
Amoore, Louise. 2013. The politics of possibility: Risk and security beyond probability.
Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Amoore, Louise, and Marieke de Goede. 2008. Introduction: Governing by risk in the
war on terror. In Risk and the war on terror, edited by Louise Amoore and Marieke de
Goede, 5–20. London and New York: Routledge.
Aradau, Claudia, Martin Coward, Eva Herschinger, Owen D. Thomas and Nadine Voe-
lkner. 2015. Discourse/materiality. In Critical security methods: New frameworks for ana-
lysis, edited by Claudia Aradau, Jef Huysmans, Andrew Neal and Nadine Voelkner,
57–84. London and New York: Routledge.
Aradau, Claudia, and Rens van Munster. 2007. Governing terrorism through risk: Taking
precautions, (un)knowing the future. European Journal of International Relations 13 (1):
89–115.
Aradau, Claudia, and Rens van Munster. 2008. Taming the future: The dispositif of risk
in the war on terror. In Risk and the war on terror, edited by Louise Amoore and
Marieke de Goede, 23–40. London and New York: Routledge.
192 Governing with and through energy security
Barry, Andrew. 2006. Technological zones. European Journal of Social Theory 9 (2):
239–253.
Bennett, Jane. 2010. Thing-power. In Political matter: Technoscience, democracy, and
public life, edited by Bruce Braun and Sarah J. Whatmore, 35–62. Minneapolis, MN:
University of Minnesota Press.
Best, Jacqueline. 2007. Why the economy is often the exception to politics as usual.
Theory, Culture & Society 24 (4): 87–109.
Bichler, Shimshon, and Jonathan Nitzan. 2012. The asymptotes of power. Real-world
Economics Review 60: 18–53.
Bridge, Gavin. 2015. Energy (in)security: World-making in an age of scarcity. The Geo-
graphical Journal 181 (4): 328–339.
Burchell, Graham. 1991. Peculiar interests: Civil society and governing ‘the system of
natural liberty’. In The Foucault effect: Studies in governmentality, edited by Graham
Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, 119–150. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Butler, Judith. 1993. Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of ‘sex’. London and New
York: Routledge.
Callon, Michel, ed. 1998. The laws of the markets. Sociological review monograph series.
Oxford and Malden, MA: Blackwell/Sociological Review.
Campbell, David. 2005. The biopolitics of security: Oil, empire, and the sports utility
vehicle. American Quarterly 57 (3): 943–972.
Collier, Stephen J. 2009. Topologies of power: Foucault’s analysis of political govern-
ment beyond ‘governmentality’. Theory, Culture & Society 26 (6): 78–108.
Dean, Mitchell. 2010. Governmentality: Power and rule in modern society. 2nd edn.
London: SAGE.
Dillon, Michael. 1996. Politics of security: Towards a political philosophy of continental
thought. London and New York: Routledge.
Dillon, Michael. 2007a. Governing terror: The state of emergency of biopolitical emer-
gence. International Political Sociology 1 (1): 7–28.
Dillon, Michael. 2007b. Governing through contingency: The security of biopolitical
governance. Political Geography 26 (1): 41–47.
Dillon, Michael. 2008. Underwriting security. Security Dialogue 39 (2–3): 309–332.
Dillon, Michael. 2010. Biopolitics of security. In The Routledge handbook of new security
studies, edited by J. Peter Burgess, 61–71. London and New York: Routledge.
Dillon, Michael, and Luis Lobo-Guerrero. 2008. Biopolitics of security in the 21st
century: An introduction. Review of International Studies 34 (02): 265–292.
Dillon, Michael, and Julian Reid. 2001. Global liberal governance: Biopolitics, security
and war. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 30 (1): 41–66.
Elden, Stuart. 2007. Governmentality, calculation, territory. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 25 (3): 562–580.
Elden, Stuart. 2013. Secure the volume: Vertical geopolitics and the depth of power.
Political Geography 34: 35–51.
Evans, Brad, and Julian Reid. 2013. Dangerously exposed: The life and death of the resil-
ient subject. Resilience 1 (2): 83–98.
Ewald, François. 1993. Two infinities of risk. In The politics of everyday fear, edited by
Brian Massumi, 221–228. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Fine, Ben. 2005. From actor-network theory to political economy. Capitalism Nature
Socialism 16 (4): 91–108.
Governing with and through energy security 193
Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison, translated by Alan
Sheridan. New York: Vintage.
Foucault, Michel. 1980. Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings,
1972–1977, edited by Colin Gordon. New York: Pantheon.
Foucault, Michel. 1982. The subject and power. Critical Inquiry 8 (4): 777–795.
Foucault, Michel. 1988. Politics, philosophy, culture. Interviews and other writings
1977–1984, edited by Lawrence D. Kritzman, translated by Alan Sheridan. London
and New York: Routledge.
Foucault, Michel. 1991. Governmentality. In The Foucault effect: Studies in governmental-
ity, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller, 87–104. Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press.
Foucault, Michel. 2002. The archaeology of knowledge. London and New York: Routledge.
Foucault, Michel. 2003. Society must be defended: Lecutures at the Collège de France
1975–76, edited by Mauro Bertani and Alessandro Fontana, translated by David
Macey. New York: Picador.
Foucault, Michel. 2007. Security, territory, population: Lectures at the Collège de France
1977–1978, edited by Michel Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
Foucault, Michel. 2008. The birth of biopolitics: Lectures at the Collège de France 1978–79,
edited by Michel Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell. New York: Palgrave
Macmillan.
Gailing, Ludger. 2016. Transforming energy systems by transforming power relations:
Insights from dispositive thinking and governmentality studies. Innovation: The Euro-
pean Journal of Social Science Research 29 (3): 243–261.
Gordon, Colin. 1991. Governmental rationality: An introduction. In The Foucault effect:
Studies in governmentality, edited by Graham Burchell, Colin Gordon and Peter Miller,
1–52. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Hardy, Cynthia, and Robyn Thomas. 2015. Discourse in a material world. Journal of
Management Studies 52 (5): 680–696.
Hargreaves, Tom, Michael Nye, and Jacquelin Burgess. 2013. Keeping energy visible?
Exploring how householders interact with feedback from smart energy monitors in the
longer term. Energy Policy 52: 126–134.
Hayek, Friedrich A. 1979. Law legislation and liberty. Vol. 3: The political order of a free
people. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Hekman, Susan J. 2010. The material of knowledge feminist disclosures. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Kester, Johannes. 2018. Governing electric vehicles: Mobilizing electricity to secure
automobility. Mobilities 13 (2): 200–215.
Klauser, Francisco, Till Paasche and Ola Söderström. 2014. Michel Foucault and the
smart city: Power dynamics inherent in contemporary governing through code.
Environment and Planning D: Society and Space 32 (5): 869–885.
Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to actor-network-theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Lemke, Thomas. 2002. Foucault, governmentality, and critique. Rethinking Marxism 14
(3): 49–64.
Lemke, Thomas. 2015. New materialisms: Foucault and the ‘government of things’.
Theory, Culture & Society 32 (4): 3–25.
Lobo-Guerrero, Luis. 2007. Biopolitics of specialized risk: An analysis of kidnap and
ransom insurance. Security Dialogue 38 (3): 315–334.
194 Governing with and through energy security
Lobo-Guerrero, Luis. 2012. Insuring war: Sovereignty, security and risk. London and New
York: Routledge.
Luhmann, Niklas. 1993. Risk: A sociological theory. Berlin and New York: Walter de
Gruyter.
Lundborg, Tom, and Nick Vaughan-Williams. 2011. Resilience, critical infrastructure,
and molecular security: The excess of ‘life’ in biopolitics. International Political Sociology
5 (4): 367–383.
Lundborg, Tom, and Nick Vaughan-Williams. 2015. New Materialisms, discourse ana-
lysis, and international relations: A radical intertextual approach. Review of Inter-
national Studies 41 (1): 3–25.
Lupton, Deborah. 2006. Sociology and risk. In Beyond the risk society: Critical reflections
on risk and human security, edited by Gabe Mythen and Sandra Walklate, 11–24.
Maidenhead: McGraw-Hill.
MacKenzie, Donald, Fabian Muniesa and Lucia Siu, eds. 2007. Do economists make
markets: On the performativity of economics. Princeton, NJ, and Oxford: Princeton
University Press.
Massumi, Brian. 2009. National enterprise emergency steps toward an ecology of powers.
Theory, Culture & Society 26 (6): 153–185.
Methmann, Chris. 2013. The sky is the limit: Global warming as global governmentality.
European Journal of International Relations 19 (1): 69–91.
Mitchell, Timothy. 2013. Carbon democracy: Political power in the age of oil. London:
Verso.
Mol, Annemarie. 2002. The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. Durham, NC, and
London: Duke University Press.
Nally, David. 2011. The biopolitics of food provisioning. Transactions of the Institute of
British Geographers 36 (1): 37–53.
Nitzan, Jonathan, and Shimshon Bichler. 2009. Capital as power: A study of order and
cre-order. London and New York: Routledge.
Preda, Alex. 1999. The turn to things: Arguments for a sociological theory of things. The
Sociological Quarterly 40 (2): 347–366.
Renzi, Alessandra, and Greg Elmer. 2013. The biopolitics of sacrifice: Securing infra-
structure at the G20 summit. Theory, Culture & Society 30 (5): 45–69.
Rose, Nikolas. 1999. Powers of freedom: Reframing political thought. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Rouse, Joseph. 2005. Power/knowledge. In The Cambridge companion to Foucault, edited
by Gary Gutting, 92–114. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schouten, Peer. 2014. Security as controversy: Reassembling security at Amsterdam
Airport. Security Dialogue 45 (1): 23–42.
Selby, Jan. 2007. Engaging Foucault: Discourse, liberal governance and the limits of
Foucauldian IR. International Relations 21 (3): 324–345.
Sen, Amartya. 1983. Poverty and famines. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Shannon, Jerry. 2014. Food deserts: Governing obesity in the neoliberal city. Progress in
Human Geography 38 (2): 248–266.
Thrift, Nigel. 2005. Knowing capitalism. London: Sage.
Tyfield, David. 2014. Putting the power in ‘socio-technical regimes’: E-mobility trans-
ition in China as political process. Mobilities 9 (4): 585–603.
Waitt, Gordon, Kate Roggeveen, Ross Gordon, Katherine Butler and Paul Cooper. 2016.
Tyrannies of thrift: Governmentality and older, low-income people’s energy efficiency
narratives in the Illawarra, Australia. Energy Policy 90: 37–45.
Governing with and through energy security 195
Watts, Michael. 2004a. Resource curse? Governmentality, oil and power in the Niger
Delta, Nigeria. Geopolitics 9 (1): 50–80.
Watts, Michael J. 2004b. Antinomies of community: Some thoughts on geography,
resources and empire. Transactions of the Institute of British Geographers 29 (2):
195–216.
7 Energy security politics in the
Dutch natural gas debate
7.1 Introduction
Where the pervious chapters engaged with three strands of literature to under-
stand the politics of energy security, and before we sum up and reflect in the
conclusion, this chapter illustrates how such a performative reading of energy
security could look like.1 As such it draws heavily on the previous chapters to
analyse the discussion about the natural gas debate in the Netherlands, a topic
heavily debated in the author’s region at the time he wrote this book and one
that shows strong energy security politics. As discussed in the introduction and
hopefully clearer after the theoretical chapters, it is difficult to provide a
detailed operationalization of how performativity works as that itself performs
one particular reality on top of the fact that each case is highly contextual.2
This chapter specifically draws on a combination of the security theories and
ANT, as this combination helps to highlight the intra-action between events,
observation and governmentality in this particular case. Another example,
published elsewhere, focuses more on Foucault’s conduct of conduct to highlight
the same intra-action in relation to the governance of consumers through
smart grids.3 However, even though they follow different theories, discuss
different aspects of energy (fossil fuel and electricity) and focus on different
levels of materialization (the gas infrastructure is established, while the smart
grids are under construction), in both cases the eventfulness of matter is prob-
lematized, interpreted and defined through a politics of ontology. And, in both
cases, the issues are addressed by governing ‘men in its relationship with things’
through the milieu.4 In the gas example below, this returns primarily with the
lowering of the volume of gas that is extracted but also with the reinforcement
of buildings.
Furthermore, in both illustrations energy security returns as a dominant dis-
course. Yet, it is a reading that builds on a certain level of absence of energy
security within these debates. The phenomenon of energy security is so
dominant, and yet so openly defined, that it hardly leaves traces and acts as a
black box that drives people to act on others in their relationship with things in
order to fulfil their desire for energy. Only in the gas example is energy security,
in its narrow security of supply definition, mentioned as an argument. It is also
The Dutch natural gas debate 197
here that energy security is reified through its opposition, as the opposition
focused on the costs and safety decisions of a secure energy supply and not the
supply of energy itself. In contrast, in the smart grid example energy security is
hardly ever mentioned but only because it is generally accepted as the core
driver behind the development of these technologies and their security appar-
atus. Moreover, that energy security is relatively absent does not mean that its
meaning is static (both cases show how energy security itself changes). All of
these reflections are for the conclusion, however, after the actual illustration on
the earthquakes and natural gas extraction in the Netherlands.
In short, the Netherlands has been developing natural gas fields since the dis-
covery of a large field in the region of Groningen in the 1950s. By 2015, this
had resulted in C275 billion of state revenue as well as an infrastructure that
connected almost all Dutch households to these gas fields for heating and
cooking purposes. Simultaneously, the Groningen gas field has been drained to
roughly one-third of its original low-calorific reserves (680 of its original 2,800
billion m3). Unfortunately, from the mid-1980s onwards the areas above the
fields have experienced light earthquakes, which have been increasing in mag-
nitude and frequency (Figure 7.1, below).5 For local residents, the everyday
experience with and consequences of these earthquakes are conflicting with the
long-standing national economic and security of supply concerns of the Dutch
government and European energy markets. For a long time, the concerns for
earthquakes remained limited to a small number of Groningen inhabitants.6
This changed with the 2012 Huizinge earthquake, which, as the strongest and
most heavily experienced earthquake in the Groningen area to date, led to a
large public debate and a string of reports on all aspects of the Dutch natural gas
extraction and ultimately to a cap on extraction as of 2014. Consequently, the
question is why, after years of neglect, the security concerns of an initially small
number of local residents suddenly superseded the energy security concerns of
policymakers and energy scholars working on the Dutch gas and energy supplies.
In other words, this chapter studies the security politics behind an under-
standing of energy security.
As mentioned in Chapter 2, the literature has described energy security as a
‘slippery’, ‘fuzzy’ and ‘multidimensional’ concept.7 Definitions vary widely but
simultaneously often share common points of interest building around notions
of security of supply, vital systems, environmental and economic energy
(in)security concerns.8 As such, ‘the energy security concept nicely weaves
together disparate policy issues into one basket’.9 Consequentially, the discus-
sion on how energy security is used and defined seems ultimately a context-
bound one.10 As Pasqualetti remarks in his reflection on a two-day meeting of
40 energy security experts, ‘Any discussion of energy security must recognize
that it varies from one place and one culture to another, especially at the house-
hold level’.11 Chapter 3 discussed the multiple ways through which this is
resolved. More traditional historical and geopolitical policy analyses draw con-
clusions from the debates they describe.12 Another prevalent approach is to map
and develop the range of indicators and metrics used to analyse energy security.13
198 The Dutch natural gas debate
In a similar line, Cherp and Jewell, two strong proponents of a contextual
approach, confirm the importance of ‘social reality in shaping perceptions of
truth’ and identify a range of storylines about energy security, which they subse-
quently categorize into a framework that can be used for further analysis.14
Elsewhere, however, these same authors argue that ‘energy security is an
instance of security in general’ and thus needs to inquire about the often-taken-
for-granted values and assumptions behind energy security.15 This chapter
follows this latter position and argues that energy security, whether defined by
scholars or as a shared understanding of participants, is part of a wider political
spectrum. However, instead of defining what energy security is, it approaches
the context-bound nature of energy security by studying how it works. How one
of its elements, in this case security of supply, becomes what those involved
understand it to be, how it changes over time and how it shapes debates about
energy production, transport and consumption. And, while ‘the need for empiri-
cal investigation into the ramifications of using … energy security [claims], for
what purpose and by whom’ is not a new question, it remains an imperative
one,16 especially given its small sample size, as the energy security literature
mainly studies it from a constructivist perspective on language and discourse17
or from securitization theory.18
The discussion below builds on these studies in two ways. First, the gasquake
debate offers an analysis of a central energy security concept, security of supply,
in its broader societal context.19 As such, it does not study competing under-
standings of energy security20 or the linguistic construction of a specific energy
security understanding.21 Instead it shows how the Dutch security of supply
understanding is influencing the debate and in turn is shaped by the resistance
it faces coming from the safety concerns of the local population. The repetitive
intra-action between these two security concerns builds on a broader relational
understanding that is at the heart of this chapter. It is a relationality that,
second, extends the discursive focus above by incorporating ideas of securitiza-
tion into the flat relationality offered by new materialist studies, in particular
actor-network theory.22 A flat relationality puts the shared understandings of
security of supply and safety on an equal footing to the materiality of the earth-
quakes and the models used by the knowledge institutes. In other words, it
reduces the analytical importance of the security claims by forcing the observer
to study the security claims as part of their wider constantly changing context.
The analysis itself builds on media coverage, news briefs, (court) statements
and a number of reports, among them the 2015 report by the Dutch Safety
Board (DSB) on the decision-making process behind the Dutch natural gas
extraction from 1959 until 2014.23 Although the debate is still ongoing (January
2018 saw another earthquake of magnitude 3.4 on the Richter scale and
reignited the debates about the speed of the reduction of gas extraction and
damage compensation procedures), this chapter focuses specifically on the
period following the Huizinge earthquake in 2012 up to the autumn of 2015, as
by then most of the major policy changes had taken place, including the deci-
sion to cap the extraction volume.24
The Dutch natural gas debate 199
This chapter continues in Section 7.2 with an explication of the theory and
subsequent contribution of this chapter. Section 7.3 introduces the Huizinge
earthquake and its consequences. Besides a discussion of the gasquake itself, this
section touches in particular on a report from the main regulatory body (the State
Supervision of Mines (SSM)), which studied the Huizinge earthquake and shows
how it is this report that actually shifted the value judgement behind the assess-
ments of the decision makers. Section 7.4 discusses the internationally encapsul-
ated position of the gas-industrial complex, while Section 7.5 looks more closely
at the safety and security claims of the locals. Section 7.6 moves on to discuss the
knowledge politics behind the earthquakes in order to highlight the struggle over
the uncertainty behind the scientific models and how security considerations
played a role in this process as well. The reflection brings these lines together.
ϭϰϬ ϲϬ
EhDZK&K^ZsZd,Yh<^;Z^Ϳ
ϭϮϬ
ydZdEdhZ>'^/EEEDϯ;>/EͿ
ϱϬ
ϭϬϬ
ϰϬ
ϴϬ
ϯϬ
ϲϬ
ϮϬ
ϰϬ
ϭϬ
ϮϬ
Ϭ Ϭ
ϭϵϵϲ
ϮϬϬϯ
ϮϬϭϬ
ϭϵϵϭ
ϭϵϵϮ
ϭϵϵϯ
ϭϵϵϰ
ϭϵϵϱ
ϭϵϵϳ
ϭϵϵϴ
ϭϵϵϵ
ϮϬϬϬ
ϮϬϬϭ
ϮϬϬϮ
ϮϬϬϰ
ϮϬϬϱ
ϮϬϬϲ
ϮϬϬϳ
ϮϬϬϴ
ϮϬϬϵ
ϮϬϭϭ
ϮϬϭϮ
ϮϬϭϯ
ϮϬϭϰ
ϮϬϭϱ
zZ
Likewise in 2015, after the initial decision to cap the volume, the ministry
stated that:
This position has since been confirmed – but simultaneously limited – with a
ruling from the highest administrative court in the Netherlands.69 In its ruling,
the court argued that in the assessment of the balance between the safety of the
local population and security of supply (which the court defines as the low-
calorific natural gas needed to comply with the demand for this type of gas) the
minister had not explained why he chose the demand from a harsh winter scen-
ario as the minimal supply benchmark instead of other more averaged demand
scenarios.70 As such, the court considered that the lowest minimal production
was not 30 bn Nm3 as favoured by the Ministry of Economic Affairs but that it
should follow a more average scenario of 27 bn Nm3 (with upward allowances for
harsh winters).
This debate should be placed in an energy security context where the role of
gas is already shifting for the Netherlands. Before the 1960s, the Dutch did not
experience gas insecurity, simply because the level of gas consumption was
minimal. Nowadays, the Netherlands is highly gas-dependent but not seen as
gas-insecure because most of its gas is extracted domestically. With the draining
of the Groningen gas field and other Dutch natural gas reserves this is expected
to change. In the near future, the Dutch will be gas-insecure precisely because
they have come to rely on it. Similarly, while the Netherlands is one of the least
dependent European countries on Russian gas, it does import Russian gas and
expects to increase its imports in the future to balance the reduction (and
206 The Dutch natural gas debate
capping) of its emptying domestic fields – negatively influencing its security of
supply position. To counter this position in a post-gas era, the Dutch state has
launched an ambitious strategy to become the ‘gas roundabout’ of north-western
Europe, combining its central position and the empty gas fields as natural
storage facilities.71 This gas roundabout idea aims to profit from the material
(empty gas fields, pipelines and pumping and conversion capacity), legal
(national and European long-term contract law and other regulations) and
social (knowledgeable and influential gas elites) infrastructure that supports
current gas extraction practices.
It is especially the latter social framework and the practices resulting from it
that the DSB describes as encumbering the incorporation of the everyday safety
of individual citizens in the gas extraction decisions. The board describes the
everyday decision-making of these organizations as driven by three main para-
digms: (1) maximum profits and winnings, (2) an optimal and strategic use of
the natural resources, and (3) a continuity of Dutch gas supplies for both citizens
and industry.72 All three are captured in the 1974 small fields policy that
replaced the initial unstructured pumping of gas in the early 1960s with a more
strategic and economic long-term vision, based on an optimal development of
new small gas fields by giving those fields priority on the Dutch gas market while
using the Groningen field more sparingly as a swing field to fulfil the remaining
demand.73 In addition, the board also concluded that ‘all efforts within the gas-
industrial complex are aimed towards an imperceptible extraction of natural
gas’.74 Together these four maxims for a long time structured the everyday
practices within the gas-industrial complex concerning the Groningen natural
gas field. Importantly, they excluded the safety and insecurity concerns of
the locals, except as a condition to be met for the other goals.75 This, in turn,
preconditioned the initial response from the organizations to claims of insec-
urity by locals and it explains why these responses, for a long time, have been
soothing instead of informative and why they only followed the scientific
updates of the magnitude – without repeating the mentioned uncertainties and
knowledge gaps.76
Up until the debate following the SSM report, the gasquakes were considered
an externality of the gas extraction, to be paid off through damage payments.
Security of supply arguments simply meant business as usual and an optimal
utilization of the Dutch gas fields. With the SSM report and the increasing
pressure of the Grunningers, media and other parties (like local governments,
safety regions, environmental groupings and so on), the discussion for the
gas-industrial complex shifted to more extensive compensatory measures and
mitigation practices, while opening up the question of when precisely the
Dutch will be gas-secure. Looking back, the gasquake protests and subsequent
shift from the SSM and other knowledge institutes forced the government
to look closer at its understanding of security of supply. In doing so, it renewed
its security of supply considerations that structured the energy debates in
the Netherlands, but this time no longer interpreted it in economic or stra-
tegic terms but in terms of minimal gas extraction, specifically the minimum
The Dutch natural gas debate 207
extraction that is required to fulfil the expected demand within the current soci-
otechnical gas infrastructure, including the technical capacity to fulfil this
demand with alternative supplies.
7.7 Reflection
The Groningen gasquake debate offers an example of a security debate in a
developed country that puts security of supply considerations in a broader polit-
ical context (in this case human security arguments). The analysis built on the
interaction between three lines of enquiry. First, it took seriously the material
reality of the earthquakes and their impacts, but also the gas field itself and the
infrastructure around it, which keeps the debate localized (no earthquakes
outside Groningen) and situated in a Northern European market through its
pipelines at the same time. Second, it highlighted the politics over these earth-
quakes in terms of their origin and their potential impact, as well as the know-
ledge politics related to the scientific uncertainty of the models behind the
earthquakes and their future trends. Third, it illustrated the struggle by the Grun-
ningers to attribute a sense of urgency to both the materiality of the earthquakes
and their future uncertainty. While successful, the above also shows that the
local population could not escape the assessments of the gas-industrial complex.
In fact, in order to break with the conservative force stemming from the
unreflective use of security of supply and in order to increase the audience
The Dutch natural gas debate 211
acceptance of their safety claim, the local population needed, first (and pain-
fully), the frequency and magnitude of the earthquakes as well as the visibility
of their impact. Second, they helped to speed this up by focusing on the scient-
ific uncertainties in the reports, slowly convincing neighbours and local authori-
ties and then media, semi-regulatory institutions and so on. Third, once the
SSM accepted the claim and published the report that legitimized the safety
claim, the focus shifted to the decisions of the Minister of Economic Affairs.
While this was initially a decision not to act, later the focus shifted to the deci-
sion about the level at which the natural gas extraction was capped. That said,
while deciding to wait, the minister had already demanded the report from the
GTS on the minimum security of supply levels, indicating an early acceptance
to review the Dutch security of supply position.
In reflection, this illustration highlights the importance of a contextual and
broader political understanding of security of supply. Throughout the debate,
the gas-industrial complex slowly increased its willingness to accept and com-
pensate for the consequences of the gas extraction. It was not until it had com-
promised on almost all aspects of the gas supply chain that it was willing to
consider a closer look at the meaning of security of supply and reduce the
extracted volume for safety concerns. Similarly, the case showed that, while
the Grunningers called for a further reduction, they ultimately took a forced
pragmatic legal stance towards a minimum extraction volume based on security
of supply considerations. The debate thus centred on the meaning of security
of supply as it relates to the low-calorific natural gas of the Groningen gas field,
the estimated demand and the available technical capacity to substitute the
Groningen gas. From a security perspective, however, the local population
through their resistance against the gas extraction practices helped reify the
principle of security of supply. Even though their concerns fitted a potential
wider understanding of human energy security, they never really successfully
questioned the security of supply principles behind the decision-making pro-
cesses. Consequently, security of supply has been reproduced while it structured
the debate by setting the outermost boundaries of acceptable actions and
reductions. Still, it has not been reproduced the same: the gasquakes have chal-
lenged the Dutch understanding of security of supply, with natural gas no
longer seen as a silent and bountiful resource but as a necessity to which the
country is addicted.
From this we can draw three lessons. The first is the need to study the use of
security and threat images in their wider political context. This should include
the sociotechnical energy infrastructure, material causal events, and especially
how security practices relate with other knowledge practices that are used to
make sense of these events. Second, besides the insight that people who use
security language are morally responsible for the distinctions they make, the
agenda-setting power they exert and the resources that are drawn from other
options, there is the lesson that security is simultaneously about urgency and
conservation. It is about protecting and conserving a certain situation, except
that it always fails as security changes the referent object itself. Protecting the
212 The Dutch natural gas debate
existing gas extraction volumes had clear impacts (the gasquakes), just as
arguing for the safety and living standards had an impact on the actual gas
extraction (a cap). Security is never static and the search for the definition of
what energy security is can therefore only be described as an active political
intervention itself. Energy security scholars should be aware of this and not only
study ‘new’ security threats or categorize old ones but explicitly focus on existing
energy security practices, their distinctions and the constant renegotiation and
hard work that keep them stable.
Notes
1 This chapter is a lightly altered version of an article published in the journal Energy
Research & Social Science and reproduced under a Creative Commons Attribution
4.0 International License (CC BY); see Kester 2017 (doi:10.1016/j.erss.2016.
12.019).
2 Then again, not providing such an operationalization also performs a reality,
although it offers one open to free assemblages and association on the side of the
reader.
3 For the purpose of this chapter, the choice of debate is thus second to the idea to
highlight the performative approach. Another example, with another performative
approach can be found in relation to smart grids, see Kester 2016.
4 Foucault 2007, 96.
5 NAM 2015a; KNMI 2015.
6 Van der Voort and Vanclay 2015.
7 Chester 2010; Valentine 2011.
8 Sovacool 2011; Winzer 2012.
9 Fischhendler and Nathan 2014, 152.
10 Cherp and Jewell 2011; Chester 2010.
11 Pasqualetti 2011, 278.
12 Luft and Korin 2009; Yergin 2012.
13 Ang, Choong, and Ng 2015; Kruyt et al. 2009; Sovacool 2011.
14 Cherp and Jewell 2011, 334.
15 Cherp and Jewell 2014, 415.
16 Fischhendler and Nathan 2014, 153.
17 Herbstreuth 2014; Littlefield 2013.
18 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998. Christou and Adamides 2013; Fischhendler,
Boymel and Boykoff 2014; Fischhendler and Nathan 2014; Natorski and Herranz
Surrallés 2008; Nyman 2014.
19 Christou and Adamides 2013.
20 Fischhendler and Nathan 2014.
21 Herbstreuth 2014; Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008.
22 Barad 2007; Bennett 2005; Coole and Frost 2010. On ANT, see Latour 2005;
Mol 2002.
23 DSB 2015.
24 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2015d.
25 Bebbington et al. 2008.
26 This comes with a strong moral responsibility for the observer, as it is they who
decide what to study as part of this relationality or network: Latour 2002.
27 Many thanks to an anonymous reviewer for bringing this up.
28 Mandelbaum, Kristensen and Athanassiou 2016; Wibben 2016.
29 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 23–24.
30 Ibid., 26.
The Dutch natural gas debate 213
31 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998; Christou and Adamides 2013, 509–510;
Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008, 74.
32 Foucault 2007.
33 Balzacq et al. 2010.
34 Booth 2007.
35 These insights are related to a performative reading of energy security; see also
Bridge 2015, where actors are seen to be directed in how they approach the world
by earlier practices and understandings, and subsequently, when acting (re)produce
those or other new social and material practices and effects.
36 Balzacq 2011, xiii.
37 Balzacq 2005; Roe 2008.
38 Fischhendler, Boymel and Boykoff 2014; Fischhendler and Nathan 2014.
39 de Wilde 2008.
40 WEC 2015.
41 This can be read as implying that safety concerns about energy production are not
part of energy security itself, which I would argue against in line with the focus on
the social/environmental acceptability of vital energy systems. Here, however, I
make an analytical distinction to better contrast the positions of the two parties
(which together with the choice for specific spokespersons is another analytical
choice to simplify the debate).
42 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 24.
43 Van Wijk and Fischhendler 2016, 22 quoting Adam and Van Loon, 2000.
44 Natorski and Herranz Surrallés 2008, 74.
45 Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde 1998, 33.
46 Barad 2007; Bennett 2005; Coole and Frost 2010.
47 Latour 2005; Mol 2002.
48 Foucault 2007; cf. Schouten 2014.
49 Latour 2005, 76.
50 All translations from Dutch are by the author, but I am grateful to the editors and
reviewers for offering a better translation of this term.
51 The Netherlands has a framework that distributes the legal ownership, extraction
rights and profit sharing between the Dutch state and the companies involved,
through a range of legal entities and subsidiaries, which nowadays is bundled under
the heading het Gasgebouw (see for example Van Gastel, Van Maanen and Kuijken
2014). In this tight network, Shell and ExxonMobil have the licence to operate the
Groningen natural gas field through their ownership of the Nederlandse Aardolie
Maatschappij (NAM). Both also own shares of GasTerra, the company responsible
for the sale of the natural gas. The Dutch state (read the Ministry of Economic
Affairs) is directly involved through a legal entity called EBN. The NAM and EBN
both cooperate in and own the Maatschap Groningen, which is responsible for the
actual exploitation of the natural gas fields. The Dutch state also owns shares of
GasTerra both directly (via the Ministry of Finance) and indirectly (through EBN).
All in all, the DSB (2015, 8, 75, 88) concludes that, through these constructions
and the close personal connections between the boards of GasTerra and the
Maatschap Groningen, the decision-making on Dutch natural gas is made in a
closed system that is effectively owned by Shell, ExxonMobil and the Dutch state: a
system devoid of opposition and ruled by ten persons at most.
52 Although not the strongest ever experienced in the Netherlands (which was a
natural earthquake in Roermond, 1992), and not nearly close to the magnitude of
some of the recent US shale gas-induced earthquakes. The Richter scale is loga-
rithmic and its magnitude highlights the energy released. Everything below 3 on
the Richter scale is hardly perceptible. That said, the actual experienced magni-
tude depends on multiple factors (energy released, wave speed, ground conditions,
force, duration, depth and so on), not all of which relate one-on-one to the
214 The Dutch natural gas debate
earthquakes in Groningen. In particular, the minimal depth between 1 and 3 km,
the ground conditions (clay, high groundwater levels) and the fast speed of the
ground waves mean that people experience them earlier than the Richter scale
would indicate. Other complicating factors are the uncertainty within the Richter
scale itself (±0.1) and the delay of about a year between the gas extraction and the
earthquakes.
53 Up to 54 billion Nm3; see NAM 2015b.
54 Out of 133 total in the Netherlands; see KNMI 2015.
55 SSM 2013.
56 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2008.
57 SSM 2013; see also DSB 2015, 66; Muntendam-Bos and De Waal 2013.
58 DSB 2015, 77.
59 GTS 2013.
60 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2013a, 2013b, 2013c; Commissie Meijer 2013.
61 Provincie Groningen 2013; Commissie Meijer 2013.
62 KNMI 2015; NAM 2015a; SSM 2014a, 2014b.
63 Kabinet, Provincie Groningen and NAM 2014.
64 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2014.
65 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2015b, 2015a.
66 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2015d, 2015a.
67 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2013a, 4.
68 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2015c, 4.
69 RvS 2015b; RvS 2015a.
70 GTS 2013.
71 Ministerie van Economische Zaken 2006.
72 DSB 2015, 70–71; comparable: SSM 2014a, 4.
73 Steen et al. 2013.
74 DSB 2015, 74.
75 Ibid., 71; GBB 2015a.
76 DSB 2015, 81–82, 86.
77 GBB 2013b; Havermans 2015; Van den Berg 2015; Van der Voort and Vanclay
2015, 7–9.
78 FocusGroningen 2014.
79 RTL Nieuws 2014.
80 OOG TV 2015.
81 De Telegraaf 2015.
82 See Van Hamersvelt 2013 on Van der Sluis. Or, more recently, Dwarshuis 2015;
Groeneveld 2015.
83 Groninger Bodem Beweging, see GBB 2011, 2013b.
84 Schokkend-Groningen.nl 2013.
85 BOA 1993.
86 Van Hamersvelt 2013.
87 GBB 2014.
88 Van der Voort and Vanclay 2015.
89 Commissie Meijer 2013, 21.
90 See GBB 2013a.
91 Van der Voort and Vanclay 2015, 8.
92 GBB 2015b, 4.
93 GBB 2013b, 1.
94 Plas Bossinade Advocaten Notarissen 2015.
95 GBB 2015a, 7.
96 Muntendam-Bos and De Waal 2013.
97 GTS 2013.
98 GBB 2015c.
The Dutch natural gas debate 215
99 Van den Berg 2015.
100 Commissie Meijer 2013; Havermans 2015; Meij 1994; Van den Berg 2015.
101 Van Eck et al. 2004; see also Dost and Kraaijpoel 2013 for a similar study after the
Huizinge earthquake; or the BOA 1993 report for a predecessor.
102 DSB 2015, 65–66.
103 See note 3; Ibid., 64.
104 Ibid., 63.
Bibliography
Ang, B. W., W. L. Choong and T. S. Ng. 2015. Energy security: Definitions, dimensions
and indexes. Renewable and Sustainable Energy Reviews 42: 1077–1093.
Balzacq, Thierry. 2005. The three faces of securitization: Political agency, audience and
context. European journal of international relations 11 (2): 171–201.
Balzacq, Thierry. ed. 2011. Securitization theory: How security problems emerge and dissolve.
PRIO New Security Studies. London and New York: Routledge.
Balzacq, Thierry, Tugba Basaran, Didier Bigo, Emmanuel-Pierre Guittet and Christian
Olsson. 2010. Security practices. In International Studies Encyclopedia Online, edited by
Robert A. Denemark. Oxford: Blackwell. Available from www.blackwellreference.
com/public/book.html?id=g9781444336597_9781444336597.
Barad, Karen. 2007. Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics and the entanglement of
matter and meaning. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Bebbington, Anthony, Denise Humphreys Bebbington, Jeffrey Bury, Jeannet Lingan,
Juan Pablo Muñoz and Martin Scurrah. 2008. Mining and social movements: Struggles
over livelihood and rural territorial development in the Andes. World Development 36
(12): 2888–2905.
Bennett, Jane. 2005. The agency of assemblages and the North American blackout.
Public Culture 17 (3): 445–465.
BOA. 1993. Eindrapport multidisciplinair onderzoek naar de relatie tussen gaswinning en
aardbevingen in Noord-Nederland. Begeleidingscommissie Onderzoek Aardbevingen.
Booth, Ken. 2007. Theory of world security. Cambridge and New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Bridge, Gavin. 2015. Energy (in)security: World-making in an age of scarcity. The
Geographical Journal 181 (4): 328–339.
Buzan, Barry, Ole Wæver and Jaap H. de Wilde. 1998. Security: A new framework for
analysis. Boulder, CO: Lynne Rienner.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2011. Energy Challenges: From local universalism to
global contextualism. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin
K. Sovacool, 330–355. London and New York: Routledge.
Cherp, Aleh, and Jessica Jewell. 2014. The concept of energy security: Beyond the four
As. Energy Policy 75: 415–421.
Chester, Lynne. 2010. Conceptualising energy security and making explicit its polysemic
nature. Energy Policy 38 (2): 887–895.
Christou, Odysseas, and Constantinos Adamides. 2013. Energy securitization and dese-
curitization in the New Middle East. Security Dialogue 44 (5–6): 507–522.
Commissie Meijer. 2013. Vertrouwen in een Duurzame Toekomst: Een Stevig Perspectief
voor Noord-Oost Groningen. Groningen: Commissie Duurzame Toekomst Noord-Oost
Groningen.
216 The Dutch natural gas debate
Coole, Diana, and Samantha Frost, eds. 2010. New materialisms: Ontology, agency, and
politics. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
De Telegraaf. 2015. VVD beweegt nog niet in gasdebat. Available from www.telegraaf.nl/
binnenland/23676051/__VVD_beweegt_niet_in_gasdebat__.html. Accessed 9 October
2016.
de Wilde, Jaap H. 2008. Environmental security deconstructed. In Globalization and
environmental challenges, edited by Hans Günter Brauch, Úrsula Oswald Spring, Habil
Czeslaw Mesjasz, John Grin, Pál Dunay, Navnita Chadha Behera, Béchir Chourou,
Patricia Kameri-Mbote and P. H. Liotta, 595–602. Hexagon series on human and
environmental security and peace 3. Berlin Heidelberg: Springer.
Dost, Bernard, and Dirk Kraaijpoel. 2013. The August 16, 2012 earthquake near Huizinge
(Groningen). De Bilt: Koninklijk Nederlands Meteorologisch Instituut.
DSB. 2015. Aardbevingsrisico’s in Groningen: Onderzoek naar de rol van veiligheid van
burgers in de besluitvorming over de gaswinning (1959–2014). The Hague: Onderzoek-
sraad voor Veiligheid [Dutch Safety Board].
Dwarshuis, Kor. 2015. Gronings gas een ramp in slow motion. Available from www.
dwarshuis.com/aardbevingen-groningen/menu/. Accessed 19 May 2016.
Fischhendler, Itay, Dror Boymel and Maxwell T. Boykoff. 2014. How competing securi-
tized discourses over land appropriation are constructed: The promotion of solar
energy in the Israeli desert. Environmental Communication 10 (2): 147–168.
Fischhendler, Itay, and Daniel Nathan. 2014. In the name of energy security: The
struggle over the exportation of Israeli natural gas. Energy Policy 70: 152–162.
FocusGroningen. 2014. Groningen massaal in actie tegen gaswinning. Available from www.
focusgroningen.nl/groningen-massaal-in-actie-tegen-gaswinning. Accessed 9 October
2016.
Foucault, Michel. 2007. Security, territory, population: Lectures at the Collège de France
1977–1978, edited by Michel Senellart, translated by Graham Burchell. New York:
Palgrave Macmillan.
GBB. 2011. Ontstaansgeschiedenis Groninger Bodem Beweging. Available from www.
groninger-bodem-beweging.nl/index.php/geschiedenis. Accessed 14 April 2015.
GBB. 2013a. Inbreng van de vereniging Groninger bodem beweging t.a.v. commissie
onderzoek bodemdaling. Groninger Bodem Beweging.
GBB. 2013b. Hoofddoelen van de GBB. Groninger Bodem Beweging.
GBB. 2014. Besluit gaswinning wederom vertraagd. Available from www.groninger-bodem-
beweging.nl/55-besluit-gaswinning-wederom-vertraagd. Accessed 18 May 2016.
GBB. 2015a. Nieuwsbrief nr. 19. Groninger Bodem Beweging.
GBB. 2015b. Nieuwsbrief nr. 20. Groninger Bodem Beweging.
GBB. 2015c. Nieuwsbrief nr. 30. Groninger Bodem Beweging.
Groeneveld, Hilda. 2015. Onder Groningen. Available from www.ondergroningen.nl.
Accessed 19 May 2016.
GTS. 2013. Mogelijkheden kwaliteitsconversie en gevolgen voor de leveringszekerheid.
Groningengas op de Noordwest-Europese Gasmarkt. Groningen: Gasunie Transport
Services B. V.
Havermans, Onno. 2015. Groningse gasboringen: Ramp in slow motion. TROUW,
2015–02–18 edition.
Herbstreuth, Sebastian. 2014. Constructing dependency: The United States and the
problem of foreign oil. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 24–42.
Kabinet, Provincie Groningen, and NAM. 2014. Vertrouwen in herstel, herstel van
vertrouwen.
The Dutch natural gas debate 217
Kester, Johannes. 2016. Conducting a smarter grid: Reflecting on the power and security
behind smart grids with Foucault. In Smart grids from a global perspective, 197–213.
Cham: Springer.
Kester, Johannes. 2017. Energy security and human security in a Dutch gasquake context:
A case of localized performative politics. Energy Research & Social Science 24 (Supple-
ment C): 12–20.
KNMI. 2015. Geïnduceerde aardbevingen in Nederland. De Bilt: Koninklijk Nederlands
Meteorologisch Instituut. Available from www.knmi.nl/seismologie/geinduceerde-
bevingen-nl.pdf. Accessed 4 November 2015.
Kruyt, B., D. P. Van Vuuren, H. J. M. De Vries and H. Groenenberg. 2009. Indicators for
energy security. Energy Policy 37 (6): 2166–2181.
Latour, Bruno. 2002. Morality and technology: The end of the means. Translated by C.
Venn. Theory, Culture & Society 19 (5–6): 247–260.
Latour, Bruno. 2005. Reassembling the social: An introduction to Actor-Network-Theory.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Littlefield, Scott R. 2013. Security, independence, and sustainability: Imprecise language
and the manipulation of energy policy in the United States. Energy Policy 52: 779–788.
Luft, Gal, and Anne Korin. 2009. Energy security challenges for the 21st century: A refer-
ence handbook. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger.
Mandelbaum, Moran, Anna Maria Friis Kristensen and Cerelia Athanassiou. 2016. De/
Re-constructing the political: How do critical approaches to ‘security’ frame our under-
standing of the political? Critical Studies on Security 4 (2): 133–136.
Meij, Wim. 1994. KNMI helpt oliemaatschappijen. Algemeen Dagblad, 1994–09–24
edition.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2006. Visie op de gasmarkt. ET/EM/ 6009634.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2008. State Supervision of Mines: Organisation.
Available from www.sodm.nl/english/organisation. Accessed 19 April 2015.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2013a. Gaswinning Groningen veld. DGETM-
EM/13010946.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2013b. Toezending stukken naar aanleiding van gedane
toezeggingen in Algemeen Overleg gaswinning Groningen. DGETM-EM/13021701.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2013c. Nadere informatie over Groningen gaswinning
en aardbevingen. DGETM-EM/13052090.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2014. Gaswinning in Groningen. DGETM/14008697.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2015a. Instemming gewijzigd winningsplan Groningen-
veld. ETM/EM /13208000.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2015b. Gaswinning Groningen. DGETM-EM/
15015030.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2015c. Kabinetsreactie op OVV-rapport Aardbevings
risico’s in Groningen. DGETM-EM/15042994.
Ministerie van Economische Zaken. 2015d. Besluit Gaswinning Groningen in 2015.
DGETM/15086391.
Mol, Annemarie. 2002. The body multiple: Ontology in medical practice. Durham, NC, and
London: Duke University Press.
Muntendam-Bos, A. G., and J. A. De Waal. 2013. Reassessment of the probability of higher
magnitude earthquakes in the Groningen gas field. The Hague: State Supervision of
Mines.
NAM. 2015a. Aantal aardbevingen in het Groningen-gasveld. Available from http://
feitenencijfers.namplatform.nl. Accessed 4 November 2015.
218 The Dutch natural gas debate
NAM. 2015b. Gaswinning. Available from http://feitenencijfers.namplatform.nl/gaswin-
ning. Accessed 4 November 2015.
Natorski, Michal, and Anna Herranz Surrallés. 2008. Securitizing moves to nowhere?
The framing of the European Union’s energy policy. Journal of Contemporary European
Research 4 (2): pp. 70–89.
Nyman, Jonna. 2014. ‘Red storm ahead’: Securitisation of energy in US–China Rela-
tions. Millennium – Journal of International Studies 43 (1): 43–65.
OOG TV. 2015. Protest en toezeggingen bij bezoek minister Kamp. Available from www.
oogtv.nl/2015/01/protest-en-toezeggingen-bij-bezoek-minister-kamp. Accessed 9 October
2016.
Pasqualetti, Martin J. 2011. The competing dimensions of energy security. In The
Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool, 275–290.
London and New York: Routledge.
Plas Bossinade Advocaten Notarissen. 2015. Beroep instemmingsbesluit januari 2015.
Namens GBB; Milieudefensie; Stichting Natuur en Milieufederatie Groningen; Landelijke
Vereniging tot Behoud van de Waddenzee. Groningen: Plas Bossinade Advocaten N. V.
Provincie Groningen. 2013. Standpunt inzake aardbevingsgevoeligheid Groningse gasveld.
2013–05059/5, BJC.
Roe, Paul. 2008. Actor, audience (s) and emergency measures: Securitization and the
UK’s decision to invade Iraq. Security Dialogue 39 (6): 615–635.
RTL Nieuws. 2014. Groningers zetten protest voort in ander dorp. RTL Nieuws. Avail-
able from www.rtlnieuws.nl/nieuws/binnenland/groningers-zetten-protest-voort-ander-
dorp. Accessed 9 October 2016.
RvS. 2015a. Uitspraak 201501544/4/A4. ECLI:NL:RVS:2015:1712. The Hague: Raad
van State.
RvS. 2015b. Uitspraak 201501544/4/A4. ECLI:NL:RVS:2015:3578. The Hague: Raad
van State.
Schokkend-Groningen.nl. 2013. Available from http://schokkend-groningen.nl/website/
schokkend-groningen-nl. Accessed 19 May 2016.
Schouten, Peer. 2014. Security as controversy: Reassembling security at Amsterdam
Airport. Security Dialogue 45 (1): 23–42.
Sovacool, Benjamin K. 2011. Introduction: Defining, measuring, and exploring energy
security. In The Routledge handbook of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool,
1–42. London and New York: Routledge.
SSM. 2013. Aardbevingen in de Provincie Groningen. 13010015. The Hague: State Super-
vision of Mines.
SSM. 2014a. Aanbieding advies ‘wijziging winningsplan Groningen 2013’ en ‘meet- en moni-
toringsplan’. 14005929. The Hague: State Supervision of Mines.
SSM. 2014b. Risico analyse aardgasbevingen Groningen. The Hague: State Supervision of
Mines.
Valentine, Scott Victor. 2011. The fuzzy nature of energy security. In The Routledge hand-
book of energy security, edited by Benjamin K. Sovacool, 56–73. London and New York:
Routledge.
Van den Berg, Jurre. 2015. Hoogstens zou het servies een keertje rammelen. De Volksk-
rant, 18 February 2015, sec. Ten Eerste.
Van der Steen, Martijn, Nancy Chin-A-Fat, Jorren Scherpenisse and Mark van Twist.
2013. Van een zachte landing naar een verlengde vlucht: Een reflectie op het Kleinevelden
beleid. The Hague: Nederlandse School voor Openbaar Bestuur.
The Dutch natural gas debate 219
Van der Voort, Nick, and Frank Vanclay. 2015. Social impacts of earthquakes caused by
gas extraction in the Province of Groningen, The Netherlands. Environmental Impact
Assessment Review 50: 1–15.
Van Eck, Torild, Femke Goutbeek, Hein Haak, and Bernard Dost. 2004. Seismic hazard
due to small shallow induced earthquakes. De Bilt: Koninklijk Nederlands Meteorologisch
Instituut.
Van Gastel, Marcel, Geert van Maanen, and Wim Kuijken. 2014. Onderzoek toekomst
governance gasgebouw. The Hague: ADBTOPConsult.
Van Hamersvelt, Willem. 2013. Van der Sluis had gelijk maar sloeg onzin uit. Dagblad
van het Noorden, 2013–2–2 edition.
WEC. 2015. Priority actions on climate change and how to balance the trilemma. World
Energy Trilemma. London: World Energy Council & Oliver Wyman.
Wibben, Annick T. R. 2016. Opening security: Recovering critical scholarship as polit-
ical. Critical Studies on Security 4 (2): 137–153.
Van Wijk, Josef, and Itay Fischhendler. 2016. The construction of urgency discourse
around mega-projects: The Israeli case. Policy Sciences 50 (3): 469–494.
Winzer, Christian. 2012. Conceptualizing energy security. Energy Policy 46: 36–48.
Yergin, Daniel. 2012. The quest: Energy, security, and the remaking of the modern world.
Updated revised edition. New York, NY: Penguin.
8 Conclusion
Performativity, disclosure and the
politics of energy security
A [performative] response is not, then for all its purported relativism, axio-
matically apolitical or amoral: It is in fact an attempt to understand –
without resort to external authorities or transcendental values – why one
moral or political system attains a higher status and exercises more influ-
ence than another at a particular historical moment.3
reading of energy security allows one to reflect on how such security concerns
evolve and what their impacts are. Following from this, second, a performative
approach enables scholars to disclose the inherent assumptions in such a ‘system’
or materialdiscursive assemblage of relationships. For many, questions like these
and the resulting understanding on how humans act socially are enough to
justify a critical performative approach (together with any follow-up questions).
For others, the lack of modelling and applied theorization means that these
understandings might be interesting but less than useful in real life. Clearly, this
book argued for the former, if only for the awareness to exclusions that these
performative studies offer citizens, consumers, policymakers, economists, scien-
tists and so forth, and thereby highlights the importance of disclosing the self-
evident and find other ways to perform our materialdiscursive society.
What results is an understanding of energy security that is both (re)produced
and productive. Among others, it is produced by the theories and observations
that claim to observe it. It is produced by the ontological politics of security that
try to imagine, define and control surprising events and undesired futures. It is
produced by individuals who use both descriptive and proscriptive elements in
their definitions. It is produced through policies of diversification, contract law
or price fluctuations in energy markets. It is produced in the construction of new
back-up capacity, the installation of reverse flow techniques and the overhaul of
the electricity infrastructure from fossil fuels to renewable sources. In short,
energy security is continuously produced and reproduced with each iterative use
of the concept, its practices and the energy system itself. These practices are
inherently fragile and always open to resistance and change. Energy security
proliferates, not because it cannot be defined but because its usage changes
constantly. Simultaneously, energy security is productive. It reifies concerns of
Conclusion 227
absolute scarcity and the neorealist geopolitical concerns that come with this. It
reifies inherent assumptions on passive consumers that justify a further govern-
ing of them.8 It reproduces a technical and capital-intensive mode of reasoning
to solve fundamental social problems. Most importantly, it conserves current
ways of life, even if it has to change itself to make that happen.
Counterintuitively, by studying the practices that shape energy security, the
search for a fuller understanding of what energy security does also results in a new
understanding of what energy security is. What emerged in this book was a mul-
tiplicity of energy security, as energy security is simultaneously energy insecurity,
a speech act with strong normative consequences, a risk calculation, a teleology
(a goal to be reached if one behaves in a particular way), a discourse that struc-
tures thought, a localized node of actor-networks within a network of actor-
networks, a materialdiscursive phenomenon based on an agential cut, a set of
relations with strategic intent, and a way to govern the present by conducting
the conduct of people in their relationship with things. It is all of these in addition
to the more traditional understandings of security of supply and the security of
energy systems, resources, services and so on, which together bring energy
security into being as a distinct desirable reality. With this in mind, it can be
concluded that even though the proliferation of energy security definitions is
driven by demands for a more emancipated, complete and truthful definition, the
closure offered by such a perfectly emancipated definition of energy security will
always remain incomplete as it hides the multiplicity of energy security.
I myself have spent some time in the past trying to show ‘the lack of scientific
certainty’ inherent in the construction of facts. I too made it a ‘primary
issue.’ But I did not exactly aim at fooling the public by obscuring the cer-
tainty of a closed argument – or did I? After all, I have been accused of just
that sin. Still, I’d like to believe that, on the contrary, I intended to emanci-
pate the public from prematurely naturalized objectified facts. Was I fool-
ishly mistaken? Have things changed so fast? … While we spent years trying
to detect the real prejudices hidden behind the appearance of objective
statements, do we now have to reveal the real objective and incontroverti-
ble facts hidden behind the illusion of prejudices?20
Notes
1 Achterhuis 1988, 106–107.
2 Barad 2007.
3 Der Derian 2009, 193 (emphasis in original).
4 Bridge 2015; Elden 2007, 2013.
5 Boyer 2011, 5, 2014; Mitchell 2009, 2013.
6 Butler 1993, 2.
7 For an alternative performative, deeply theoretical and practical analysis focused on
natural gas security in the UK, see: Forman 2017, 2018.
8 Kester 2016a.
9 Barry 2002, 270–271.
10 See Byrne and Toly 2006.
11 Barad 2007.
12 Bellacasa 2011, 100. Booth 2005.
13 De Goede 2012.
14 Kester 2016a, 2018.
15 Kester 2018.
16 Kester 2016b.
17 Forman 2017, 2018.
18 Balzacq 2011, xiii.
19 Patterson 2008.
20 Latour 2004, 227.
21 Cherp 2012, p. 841; Sovacool 2011. Also Sovacool et al. 2012.
Bibliography
Achterhuis, Hans. 1988. Het Rijk van de Schaarste: van Thomas Hobbes tot Michel Foucault.
Baarn: Ambo.
Balzacq, Thierry, ed. 2011. Securitization theory: How security problems emerge and dissolve.
PRIO New Security Studies. London and New York: Routledge.
Barad, Karen. 2007. Meeting the universe halfway: Quantum physics and the entanglement of
matter and meaning. Durham, NC, and London: Duke University Press.
Barry, Andrew. 2002. The anti-political economy. Economy and Society 31 (2): 268–284.
Bellacasa, Maria Puig de la. 2011. Matters of care in technoscience: Assembling neg-
lected things. Social Studies of Science 41 (1): 85–106.
Booth, Ken. 2005. Security. In Critical security studies and world politics, edited by Ken
Booth, 21–25. London: Lynne Rienner.
Boyer, Dominic. 2011. Energopolitics and the anthropology of energy. Anthropology News
52 (5): 5–7.
Boyer, Dominic. 2014. Energopower: An introduction. Anthropological Quarterly 87 (2):
309–333.
Conclusion 235
Bridge, Gavin. 2015. Energy (in)security: World-making in an age of scarcity. The Geo-
graphical Journal 181 (4): 328–339.
Butler, Judith. 1993. Bodies that matter: On the discursive limits of ‘sex’. London and New
York: Routledge.
Byrne, John, and Noah Toly. 2006. Energy as a social project: Recovering a discourse. In
Transforming power: Energy, environment and society in conflict, edited by John Byrne,
Noah Toly and Leigh Glover, 1–32. New Brunswick, NJ, and London: Transaction.
Cherp, Aleh. 2012. Defining energy security takes more than asking around. Energy
Policy 48: 841–842.
De Goede, Marieke. 2012. Speculative security: The politics of pursuing terrorist monies.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Der Derian, James. 2009. Critical practices in international theory: Selected essays. London
and New York: Routledge.
Elden, Stuart. 2007. Governmentality, calculation, territory. Environment and Planning
D: Society and Space 25 (3): 562–580.
Elden, Stuart. 2013. Secure the volume: Vertical geopolitics and the depth of power.
Political Geography 34: 35–51.
Forman, Peter J. 2017. Securing natural gas: Entity-attentive security research. PhD thesis,
Durham University.
Forman, Peter J. 2018. Circulations beyond nodes: (In)securities along the pipeline.
Mobilities 13 (2): 231–245.
Kester, Johannes. 2016a. Conducting a smarter grid: Reflecting on the power and security
behind smart grids with Foucault. In Smart grids from a global perspective, 197–213.
Cham: Springer.
Kester, Johannes. 2016b. Securing abundance: The politics of energy security. PhD hesis,
Groningen: University of Groningen.
Kester, Johannes. 2018. Governing electric vehicles: Mobilizing electricity to secure
automobility. Mobilities 13 (2): 200–215.
Latour, Bruno. 2004. Why has critique run out of steam? From matters of fact to matters
of concern. Critical inquiry 30 (2): 225–248.
Mitchell, Timothy. 2009. Carbon democracy. Economy and Society 38 (3): 399–432.
Mitchell, Timothy. 2013. Carbon democracy: Political power in the age of oil. London:
Verso.
Patterson, W. 2008. Managing energy wrong. Energy, Environment and Resource Govern-
ance Working Paper. Managing Energy: for Climate and Security. London: Chatham
House.
Sovacool, Benjamin K. 2011. Evaluating energy security in the Asia Pacific: Towards a
more comprehensive approach. Energy Policy 39 (11): 7472–7479.
Sovacool, Benjamin K., S. V. Valentine, M. Jain Bambawale, M. A. Brown, T. de Fátima
Cardoso, S. Nurbek, G. Suleimenova, J. Li, Y. Xu and A. Jain. 2012. Exploring propo-
sitions about perceptions of energy security: An international survey. Environmental
Science & Policy 16: 44–64.
Index
accountability 126, 131, 143; and risk black boxing (Latour) 132, 134, 143, 147,
91–92; see also unaccountability 184, 225
accountants 92, 182–183 blackouts 21–22, 48, 130–131
actants 133–134, 135–136, 137, 139, 147 Bohr, Niels 141–142, 154n200
actor-network theory (ANT) 114, Booth, Ken 56, 70–71, 77–78, 145, 148
132–138, 139, 141, 147, 232; and Dutch Bridge, Gavin 30, 213n35
natural gas debate 202 brittle star (sea creature) 143–144
actors in securitization theory 76–77, Bryant, Levi R. 137, 139–140, 228
78–79, 84–85, 86 Butler, Judith 84, 91, 143, 144;
affordability 13, 14–16, 25–26, 28, 41, performativity 129, 130, 179, 224
44 Buzan, Barry 56, 58, 61, 75, 76, 78
agency 114, 124, 125, 127, 128, 133–134;
distributed 131, 180 capital 71; risk as form of 89, 92
agential cut, the 142–144, 145, 147, 227 capitalism 131, 135, 177–178
Amoore, Louise 88, 91, 93, 104n251, 171, Cartesian dualism 115–116, 122–123, 126,
182–183; on risk logic 94, 95 138, 144, 179
artefacts 116, 126, 141, 146; in ANT 132; catastrophe 61–62
in materialdiscursive ontology 140; Cherp, Aleh 16, 29, 40, 198; classification
politics of 128 of threats 43; on logic of security 47,
assemblages 61, 130–131, 134, 145, 226; 48–49
in materialdiscursive ontology 132, 146, Chester, Lynne 15, 17, 44
147, 148, 184, 226; performative circulation processes 45, 90–91, 163, 166,
224–225, 228, 229 170, 172, 186, 222; freedom of 7,
audience in securitization theory 76–77, 173–174; security of 90–91, 171,
79, 81, 83, 85, 86, 200 184–185, 228–229
Ciută, Felix 13, 29; on logic of security
Barad, Karen 122, 129, 141–145, 147, 47–49, 77, 79
154n199, 155n212, 228 climate change 22–24, 46, 77, 93
Barry, Andrew 139, 140–141, 183 climate security 22
behaviour 165; and freedom 166, 167, 171, coal 13, 16, 18; electricity source 23; and
175; and risk 88, 91–93, 94, 95 oil 19, 20
Bennett, Jane 61; North American commodification of contingency 89–91,
blackout analysis 130–131, 132, 146 178, 230
biopolitics 164, 167, 168–171, 181, 186, conduct of conduct (Foucault) 164–165,
227; and governmentality 174, 175 176, 179, 180, 181, 196
biopower 164, 167, 168, 191n172; and consumer countries 21, 44; economic
government 174 insecurity of 19, 20
Index 237
Copenhagen School 75–76 energy poverty 24–25
counter-conduct (Foucault) 174–175 energy security: definitions of 13, 14–16,
critical infrastructure protection (CIP) 19, 28–30, 197–198, 220–221, 233–234;
27, 141; origins of 32–3n86, 93 theoretical analyses of 45–49, 47
critical realism 117–118, 121, 123 energy trilemma 2, 46–47, 47, 200
critical security studies (CSS) 3–4, 68–71, entanglement 124–125; materialdiscursive
75, 87–89, 96, 184, 199, 221 143, 145
entities, folded 139
danger 61–62, 69, 87, 174, 175, 232; and environmental security 22–23, 24
freedom 176; and risk 88, 91, 99n22 environmentalism 22, 28, 45, 140
Darwinism in Foucault 170, 174 epistemological theories 114–117,
Dean, Mitchell 91, 169, 171, 173; on 120–121, 123, 142
biopolitics 174, 176–177; on conduct epistemological relativism 118
165; on insurance 89; on rationality essentialism 127; see also social
187n10; on risk 92, 103n206 essentialism
dependency 12, 19–20, 28, 48, 51n48, essentialization 151n82
80–81 ethics 223–229; and accountability 126,
desecuritization, logic of 78–79, 82–83 131, 132; defined 70; and observation
desire 220, 228; biopolitics and 170–171, 141, 143, 145, 147–148, 228; of security
174, 186, 227; fear and 72; liberalism 56, 79, 96, 230
and 176 ethics of security 68–75
deterrence, logic of 65–66 European Union (EU) and Russian gas
diffractive reading (Barad) 143 80–84
Dillon, Michael 69, 71, 126, 168, 184; events 138–140, 200, 225, 226; contingent
radical uncertainty 58, 60–61, 173, 89–91, 93, 94, 178; and meaning 114,
178–179 116–119, 148, 211; regularity of and risk
discipline 166–167, 171 88–89; see also surprise, events as
discourse/material dualism 125, 130–132, Ewald, François 88–89, 91, 93
143, 163, 179–180 exceptionality in political decisions 76,
dualism 115–117, 120–121, 123, 126, 77–78, 85, 86
149n5, 150n38 exclusion, political strategy of 78, 92, 96
Dutch earthquakes 197, 198, 201, 223, exogeneous and endogenous fears 73
230; as political issue 202, 203–208,
209, 210, 211; related to gas extraction facts, material and institutional 116, 118,
203, 204, 229, 230; see also Huizinge 127
earthquake fear 59, 60, 66–67, 69, 72–75; culture of
Dutch gas-industrial complex 199, 202, 77, 97; political use of 73–75, 76, 84,
204, 206–208, 210 95–97, 174, 220
Dutch natural gas extraction 197, 198, folds 139, 147, 224–225
202, 205, 207–208, 209–210 food: politics of 180–181; shortages 169,
Dutch Safety Board (DSB) 198, 206, 210 173, 182–183, 185
food security 43, 229
ecological security 22 food systems 177
economy, liberal 172–173 foreign dependency 18, 19, 20, 45, 80–82
electricity grid: maintenance 33n91; fossil fuels 12, 17, 22, 23, 27, 82
vulnerability of 22, 27, 130–131 Foucault, Michel 7, 88, 90–91, 163–164,
emancipatory security theory (Booth) 185–187, 222; biopolitics 168–170;
70–71 circulation, processes of 184–185; on
empiricism 116, 118 governing 164–165; governmentality
energopower 224 171–175; and liberalism 175–179; and
energy: concept of 12, 13, 28, 40; materiality 179; milieu and government
definitions of 12–13; infrastructure 170, 177–178, 179; on power 166–167;
18–19 power/knowledge nexus 181; on security
energy dependency 16, 81, 220 apparatus 184
238 Index
freedom: and individuals 78, 170, 171, 70–71; and markets 21; and Russia 80,
176; and politics 7, 71, 171, 172, 82; types of 60–62
173–176, 186 insurance 67, 88–89, 92–96, 97, 178
futures, undesirable 57, 96–98, 200, 225; International Energy Agency (IEA) 13,
ethics and security measures 68–71; fear 19, 21, 231; insecurity definition 20;
and 72–75; and insecurity 58–62; logics security definition 15, 28
of 65–68; prediction of 62–65; intersubjectivity 75, 79, 117, 118, 122,
securitization theory and 76–79, 84–87 123
gas reserves 44, 183, 205, 206 Jevons, William Stanley 13, 18
gasquakes see Dutch earthquakes Jewell, Jessica 16, 29, 40, 198;
geometrics 191n172, 224 classification of threats 43; on logic of
geopolitics 13, 29, 30, 45–46, 81–83, 224 security 47, 48–49
geopower 191n172
globalism 19–20, 23–24 knowledge 146–148, 163, 172, 222, 228;
good/bad dichotomy 46, 165 and critical realism 117–118; and
government: police and 168–169; dualism 115–117, 124–126, 144; and
rationalities of 165, 166, 170–171 power 179, 180, 181–183, 186–187,
governmentality 75, 91, 163–165, 200; and radical constructivism
171–175, 186; and collective interest 118–121; and social essentialism
176; and environment 177; of fear 84, 121–123, 150n52
174; of risk 6; strategies of 225
greenhouse gas emissions 22, 23, 188n34 La Perriere, Guillaume de 179–180
Groningen gas field 197, 203–204, 205, language 60, 85, 120–123; role of 115,
210 116–117, 129–130
Groninger Bodem Beweging (GBB) 202, language games 119–120, 123
208 Latour, Bruno 61, 122, 130; and ANT
132, 133, 135–136, 202; on events 139;
Harman, Graham 135–136, 137, 151n83 on materialism 151n83, 152n121; on
Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle matters of fact 232; on morality and
141–142 technology 144–145; social-material
Hildyard, Nicholas 12, 27–28, 30 duality 151n62
household: energy security of 25–26, 197, liberalism 169, 170, 172–173, 174–177,
231; uses of energy 26 178–179
Huizinge earthquake 197, 198, 199, 203, linguistic philosophy 119–121
205, 209 linguistic structures 122–124
human-centric perspective 24–26, 41 Lohmann, Larry 12, 27–28, 30
hybrid quasi-objects 133 Luhmann, Niklas 59, 62, 67, 150n36;
systems theory 120, 137, 150n38,
ignorance and undesirable futures 65 151n58
indeterminacy 60, 142, 143, 154n199
individuals: and energy supply 25–27; and Malthusianism 22, 45, 64, 168
power 74, 166–167, 168, 171–177; and market dynamics 17, 19, 21, 23, 45–46,
risk 88–89, 91, 92–93, 95, 97 170, 173, 177
infrastructure 93, 113, 128, 154n195; market-based energy security policy 20–21
Dutch 196, 197, 201; EU programme on Massumi, Brian 66, 68–69, 71; ecological
81, 82; introduction of new 22, 140; theory of power 177–178; on fear 73–74
Marxist perspective of 27–28; North material, the 70, 115, 118, 126, 127, 132,
American blackout 131; protection of 152n115
27, 32–3n86, 67; self-correcting 141; material objects 125, 132, 152n114
smart grids 196–197; vulnerability of materialdiscursive ontology 114, 124, 140,
18–19, 26–27, 48 142–144, 147–149, 222, 224–225; and
insecurity 24–26, 57, 58–59, 68, 227; entanglement 124, 145; relations 5,
definitions of 13, 14, 20; and ethics 223, 226
Index 239
materialism 149n2, 149n11, 151n83 decolonization 19; demand for 17, 45;
materiality 122, 127, 130, 138, 141, dependency 18–19, 20–21, 26, 45, 82,
221–222; of earthquakes 198, 201–202, 185; reserves 44, 183; Russian exports
210; and power 179–180, 186–187; 61, 80, 83
Wittgenstein 123 ontic politics 163; see also ontopolitics
materialization 125, 127, 130, 132, 140, ontic uncertainty 60, 66, 68, 97, 99n22
181–182; politics of 141, 145 ontological politics 7, 125, 140–141,
matter 126–128, 129, 143 147–148, 226, 231; see also ontic
matter-knowledge duality 115, 222 politics; ontopolitics
mattering 127, 128, 129, 131–132, 144, ontology 4, 115–117, 120–122, 125,
148, 222 182–183; and hypotheticals 59–60, 66,
meaning as use (Wittgenstein) 119, 120 222; materialdiscursive 114, 124, 140,
mediators in ANT 134, 135 142–144, 147–149, 222, 224–225;
mentalité 165, 171–172, 175 object oriented (OOO) 114, 141;
mercantilism 168, 169, 184–185, 188n50 relational 130, 131–139, 141, 201; in
milieu in biopolitics 168, 170–171, 176, systems theory 120
177–179, 184, 186–187; governing ontopolitics 89–90, 96, 113–114, 145; see
through 164, 177, 178–181, 182, 222 also ontic politics
mind/body duality 115–116, 124, 129–130,
179 performative reading of energy security
monism 124 (PRES) 2, 6–7, 223–229, 232–234
performativity 130–132, 139, 141,
national security 78 147–148, 185–187, 196, 226
natural resources 18, 29, 126; debates 3–4; physicalism 115–116, 149n5
politics of control over 45; threats 41, physiocrats 169, 170, 172
42 police 168–169; and government 172
naturalism 116, 127, 149n11 politicization 77–78, 80, 183
nature/culture dualism 126, 129 politics and security 68, 70, 199–200, 227
neo-liberalism 20, 21, 27–28, 29, 45, 183, politics of biopower see biopolitics
185; of European Union 83; form of politics of ontology see ontological politics
governmentality 164, 175–177, 178 populations and power 186, 163, 166–172,
neorealism 45, 82, 227 174, 176, 180–182
new materialism 113–114, 122, 123–126, positivism 114, 116, 117, 121, 122, 124,
143, 146–149, 201–202, 222; and ANT 228
132–138, 141, 198; and mattering 127; posthumanism 114, 124, 126, 133–134,
and performativity 129–132; and 141
vibrancy 138–140; see also materialism postpositivism 114, 116, 117, 118–119,
nodes in ANT 133, 136, 137, 185, 202 122–124; linguistic 119; and materiality
141–143, 146
obesity 180–181 power/knowledge nexus (Foucault) 163,
objectification 88, 133 181–183, 186
object-oriented ontology (OOO) 114, 141 practice theory and securitization 84–85
object-oriented philosophy (OOP) 124, precaution, logic of 41, 65, 67, 93–95
135 pre-emption, logic of 66–68, 104n252
observation 147–148, 154n199, 222, premediation 64
224–227, 226, 228; and dualism preparedness, logic of 65, 67–68
115–117, 150n37; in Latour 139, prevention, logic of 65–66, 68, 93–94,
153n133; and materiality 124, 127, 137; 104n252
politics of 140–145; in radical
constructivism 120–121; in systems radical constructivism 115, 117, 118–121,
theory 120 123, 146
oeconomia (the household) 25–26, 135, radical uncertainty 60–61, 178–179
164, 168, 169, 225 referent objects 61, 69, 72, 76–77, 79, 90;
oil: crises 4, 13, 17, 19–20, 63; and ‘the other’ as 83–84, 96
240 Index
relational ontology 130, 131–139, 141, social constructivism 118, 122, 148–149
142–143, 201 social essentialism 121–123, 150n52
relations: actor-networks of 142, 147; social-material duality 113–114, 118, 122,
between humans 173, 184; between 124, 140; bridged 128, 131; in Foucault
humans and things 169–170, 180 179–180; in IR theory 115; in new
renewables 12, 17, 23–24, 226 materialism 126–127, 129–130, 132
resilience, logic of 48, 65, 67–68, 175, social probability 60
189n104 society 120, 132, 172–173, 175, 222, 228;
resistance and power 165, 174, 228–229 in securitization theory 76, 78; and
responsibility 131 security 58–59, 62, 68, 71–75; total
Richter scale 203, 213–14n52 dependence on energy 13, 220
risk 60, 62, 87, 97–98, 104n251, 178–179, speech acts in securitization theory 75,
230; accountability and 91–92, 94–95; 76–77, 81–82, 84, 85–86, 97
calculation of 64–65, 67, 88–89, 90, state-centrist perspective 30, 45
92–93, 103n199, 182–183; and State Supervision of Mines (SSM) 199,
contingent events 89–91, 93–94; cost- 204, 205, 208, 209
benefit analysis of 174, 202, 210; and statistics 64–65, 88–89, 95, 168–169, 172,
culture of fear 73–74; definitions of 88; 182–183
and ethics 68–69; and political decision supply, security of 13, 18–19, 20, 28, 47,
making 91–94, 95, 201, 204–205, 208; 196–197; in Netherlands 198, 200–201,
underwriters composing 91, 95 204–207, 208, 210–211, 223
risk rationality 67, 178 surprise, events as 7, 60, 89–90, 138–139,
rump materialism 118 140, 225
Russia-Ukraine gas crises 80, 81–82 sustainability 22–24, 28, 47
systems theory see Luhmann, Niklas
scarcity 169, 173, 182–183, 185; see also
food: shortages threats 61–62, 68–69, 103n185, 211; logic
scenario planning 63–64, 94, 232 of 77–78, 83, 85, 93–94; perception of
scientific method and critical realism 117, 75–76, 201; and securitization 83, 230;
121 stated as self-evident 81
securitization theory 71, 84–87, 97, tightrope walker metaphor 220, 227–228
102n135, 148, 199–201; and
EU-Russian natural gas relations 79–83; unaccountability 94–95
and exceptionality 75–79 uncertainty 63, 89, 91, 99n22;
security: apparatus of 168, 170–171, 184, epistemological 141–142; Foucault on
186; definitions of 56–57, 67–68, 221; 169–170, 184; ontological 140; radical
effects of 69–70; logic of 40, 47–49, 56, 60–61, 178–179; of scientific models
59, 65–68, 96, 98; political concept 56, 209–211
78–79, 86, 211; scope of 49–50; of supply
and demand 17, 21, 28, 41, 50, 71 vulnerability 73, 74
self-government 165, 180
shale gas 17, 23, 213n52 war logic 61, 78
simulation as security technique 65 worst case scenarios 61, 93–94