Strotz (1955-1956) - Myopia and Inconsistency in Dynamic Utility Maximization
Strotz (1955-1956) - Myopia and Inconsistency in Dynamic Utility Maximization
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Oxford University Press and The Review of Economic Studies, Ltd. are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to The Review of Economic Studies.
http://www.jstor.org
I. INTRODUCTION
This paperpresentsa problemwhichI believehas not heretoforebeen analysed2and
providesa theory to explain, under differentcircumstances,three related phenomena:
(1) spendthriftiness; (2) the deliberateregimentingof one's futureeconomicbehaviour-
even at a cost; and (3) thrift. The sensesin whichwe deal with thesetopics can probably
not be very well understood,however,until after the paper has been read; but a few
sentencesat this point may shed some light on what we are up to.
An individualis imaginedto choose a plan of consumptionfor a futureperiodof time
so as to maximizethe utilityof the plan as evaluatedat the presentmoment. His choiceis,
of course,subjectto a budgetconstraint. Our problemariseswhen we ask: If he is free
to reconsiderhis planat laterdates,will he abideby it or disobeyit-even thoughhis original
expectations offuture desires and means of consumptionare verifed ? Our answer is that
the optimalplan of the presentmomentis generallyone whichwill not be obeyed,or that
the individual'sfuturebehaviourwill be inconsistentwith his optimalplan. If this incon-
sistencyis not recognized,our subjectwill typicallybe a " spendthrift,"a termwhich has
had no meaningin existing utility theory but which becomes explicatedin the theory
presentedhere. If the inconsistencyis recognized,the rationalindividualwill do one of two
things. He may " precommit" his futurebehaviourby precludingfutureoptions so that
it will conformto his presentdesireas to whatit shouldbe. Or,alternatively,he maymodify
his chosen plan to take account of future disobedience,realizingthat the possibilityof
disobedienceimposes a furtherconstraint-beyond the budget constraint-on the set of
plans which are attainable. It is in this way that the individualbecomes " thrifty"-a
termwhichalso acquiresmeaningin the contextof the analysis. Whatis crucialto all this
is that the discountappliedto a futureutilityshoulddependon the time-distancefrom the
presentdate and not upon the calendardate at whichit occurs. In a final section,we shall
have some thingsto say about the meaningof " consumersovereignty" in the framework
of dynamic choice.
1 I am indebtedto many colleagues at NorthwesternUniversity and elsewherewho have commented
helpfullyon this manuscript,and I am especiallyindebtedto Mr. Fred Westfieldand Dr. Alvin Martyfor
many sustainedand fruitfuldiscussionsof the subjectas well as to M. JacquesDreze, Prof. HarryJohnson,
Prof. R. Solow, Mr. S. A. Thore, Professor Gerhard Tintner, Professor H. Wold, and members of the
seminar of the Departmentof Applied Economics, CaTbridge University, for criticismsrendered. The
usual caveat protectingthese courteous people from furtherresponsibilityis, of course, in order.
The paper was completedwhile the author was visiting the Departmentof Applied Economics, Cam-
bridge University, on a Rockefeller Grant.
2
But it has been alluded to by Paul A. Samuelson," A Note on Measurementof Utility," Reviewof
EconomicStudies,IV, 2 (Feb., 1937),esp. p. 160. See also FriedrichA. Hayek, ThePure Theoryof Capital
(1941), p. 218, and M. Allais, L'Economieet Int&ret,Annexe 3.
165
\ AC Ci
- -- 3=c3(t)
%\ .C..'
C =C (t)
' t
0 T
Figure 1
to assume that the individual has only'idle curiosity in what happens after several millenia.
Each function C(t) is, of course, single-valued and bounded from both above and below,
and time is treated as a continuous variable.'
The next step is to assume that an individual who faces the alternatives C, (t), C2(t),. ..
1There is no difficultyin regardingtime as discreteand one can then employ the method of Lagrange
multipliersratherthan the Calculusof Variationsused here. I find that some issues can be treated more
smoothly by dealing with the continuous case, however, and prefer the approach taken here.
from 0 to 'r. For the especially simple functional given by (2), the value of ?X(t-r)
"0
u[C(t),t] dt is historicallygiven. In the moregeneralcase, however,this is not technically
necessary,becausethe u functionmight contain as one of its argumentsa lead value of
C, e.g., C(t + 0). We prefer,therefore,to integratefrom 0, noting that the budgetcon-
straintto be introducedlater requiresthat CO) } be taken as given, anyway. This
of the future act of consumption. The weight I assign to my pleasure (u function) in drinking
champagne next September 26 may depend either on the fact that that date is a certain
length of time away from the present or on the fact that that is my birthday. To the extent
that time-distance is important, I may assign a different (and probably higher) weight to
September 26 as it draws nigh ; if only the calendar date is important, the weight will not
change as that date approaches.1 Both bases for discounting a future date are included in
the functional (2). The importance of the calendar date enters through the appearance
of t in the instantaneous utility function, whereas the importance of time distance is given
by X(t - -). The distinction between these two causes of discounting is commonly over-
looked, because it has no consequence in those theories which regard the present date as
fixed.2 A truly dynamic theory of utility maximization must, however, assume that the
present date changes, and, as we shall see, the distinction is then an important one.
The reader may wonder whether the instantaneous utility function could be replaced
in (2) with any monotonically increasing function thereof; the answer is that it cannot.
It is determined up to a linear transformation.3 Just as the von Neumann-Morgenstern
utility function is determined up to a linear transformation by assuming that the individual
behaves so as to maximize the probability-weighted sum of the utilities resulting from the
various outcomes of a gamble, so too is this function specified by assuming that an indi-
vidual acts as if to maximize a weighted sum of instantaneous utilities arising at different
points of time.4
- X(t - 0) - u [C(t), t] dt
(3) (Do0
1Of course, it could drop to zero once the date is passed. This possibilityis excludedin the functional
(2), as is any interactionbetween the time-distanceand calendar-datebases of discounting; otherwise
either X or u or both would have both t - T and t as arguments.
1 rather assume that in speaking of economic myopia (The Economicsof" Welfare)Professor Pigou
2
had the time-distanceconcept in mind. CertainlyJevons did when he wrote: people of good sense will
not discount the future except for uncertainty-but people do discount the future in accordancewith its
remoteness." (The Theoryof Political Economy,pp. 77-80), and Bohm-Bawerk: " It is one of the most
pregnantfacts of experiencethat we attach a less importanceto future pleasuresand pains simply because
they are future, and in the measurethat they are future." (ThePositiveTheoryof Capital,tr. by W. Smart,
p. 253). For other examplessee also Alfred Marshall,Principlesof Economics,8th ed., p. 120, Adolphe
Landry,L'Interetdu Capital(1904),ch. X, §150and E. C. K.Gonner, Interestand Saving(1906), p. 36.
3 See, on this point, Paul A. Samuelson, op. cit.
4There is no presumptionthat these two measuresof utility are the same. Measurementis arbitrary
and for differentpurposesdifferentmeasuresmay be the most convenient. Cf. my statementin " Cardinal
Utility," AmericanEconomicReview,XLIII, 2 (May, 1953), p. 397 : " Furthermore,the acceptanceof
the von Neumann-Morgensternmeasure does not preclude the definition of still other measures. It is
true that the von Neumann-Morgensternmeasureis convenientand manageablefor the class of problems
involving risk, but it need not prove convenient for all classes of utility problems that may conceivably
arise. Nothing rules out the usefulnessof anothermeasurefor anotherpurpose."
If we were to introducerisk explicitly into the present analysis, we would have to write:
rT r00
·^D= X -(t - [) .u [ p(C,t) - v(C) dC, t] dt,
wherep(C,t) is the probabilitydensityat t of consumptionC and where v(C) is the von Neumann-Morgen-
stem measureof the utility of C. Probabilitiesare, of course, introducedhere in a very special way, being
made to depend only on C and t.
which, upon substituting C(t) for y(t) and letting Uc(t) = a u[C(t), t]/KC, is:
(10) X(t)uc(t) + uc(t) X°(t) =- 0, 0 < t < T.
(10) may be written as:
(11) X°(t)/ X(t) = - lC(t)/Uc(t) 0 < t < T,
or as:
(12) d In X(t)/dt = -d In uc(t)/dt, 0 < t < T.
The solution to this differential equation is simply:
(13) A(t) * uc(t) = constant, 0 < t < T,
"
with the constant dependent on K(0). This i's to say that the stock of consumption"
K(0) must be distributed over the interval 0 to ITso that the discounted marginal utility of
consumption is the same for all dates. This is, of course, a quite obvious condition, and,
in view of the absence of intertemporal complementarity, will assure us of a maximum for
0oprovided that the instantaneous utility function displays a diminishing marginal rate
of utility. This would be the case for any consumer who does not concentrate his entire
consumption for the period at a single point of time.
1 Often, for a constraintof this sort (as in the case of a man who must ration fresh water to himself
during an ocean voyage), there is the additionalrequirementthat C(t) > 0 for all t, but such a condition
is not imposed in what follows.
14) X (t - T) u[C.(t), t] dt
I C(t)dt= K(T),
where:
rationalif that planis not the optimalone at the presentdate. The bestplanwill generally
change with a change in -x, and there is nothing patentlyirrationalabout the individual
who findsthat he is in an intertemporaltusslewith himself-except that rationalbehaviour
requireshe take the prospectof such a tussle into account.
Should the individualre-evaluatehis plan periodically,his actual behaviourcould
be describedin termsof the graphbelow. C0 may be his best plan at -r= 0; C1 may be
his best plan at X = r ; C2 at r =-r2 ; etc. If he does not reconsiderhis originallybest
planduringthe period0 < r < r,, he abidesby it and follows C0duringthat periodas is
indicatedby the heavypart of the curve. At xr, however,he reconsidersand, takinginto
account that the " stock of consumption" availablefrom then until T is the original
amountminuswhat he has alreadyconsumed,he chooses C1as his best plan and follows
it (along the heavyportion)until -r2when he reconsidersonce more, etc. This meanshis
actualbehaviouris representedby the sequenceof heavy arcs shown in the figure. The
integralof this sequenceof arcs must, of course,be K(0).
Cl
~---C2
0 T, T2 13 T
Figure 2
r't rT
(21a) X(t-O)-u[C(t), t]dt + -\ (t-O) u[C(t), t]dt
rD ,* f T
subject to C(t)dt
( = K(0), then { C*(t) 1
should maximize
.T
(21b) I X(t-,')-u[C(t)]dt
JT
Tr r r T )
subject to | C(t)dt = K(O) - C*(t)dt, or that { C*Qt)
Returning to the narrow framework of our consumption problem, let the best plan
of consumption be given by the function 4 (t) . As a solution, N(t) has the property
is a maximum of:
.TT - t T
+ u(t-T) u [Z(), t] di
*T+AT
rF+Atq
with respect to the function i y(t) ) when the individual at T can force himself to
I T J
follow during the period T to T + A' any plan which he may select subject to the con-
-T+ A I'T ,'T
straint that y(t)dt = K(O) _- 2(t)dt - z(t)dt, a constant.
·/T ,0 ,'T+AT
To maximize (26) requires only that the middle term be maximized. This gives:
(27) X°(t- T)/ X(t - T) - - uc(t)/uc(t), T < t < r+AT,
so that as AT --> 0, the condition on 2(t) becomes:
(28) X°(o)/ x(0) = --t 'c /uc(:).
Since this must hold for every T it may be written:
(29) X°(0)/ X(0) = - uc(t)c(t), 0 < t - T,
which is the solution to the " harmony case," given by:
Again, this should not be in any way surprisingbecause only those plans that maximize
a functional such as (30) are attainable (will be obeyed). The individual must, therefore,
first substitute for his true discount function one that is linear in the logarithm and then
maximize. The appropriate value for k has already been determined by the analysis which
has preceded. At each point of time the individual equates - uc(t)/Uc(t) to X°(0)/X(0),where
X(t - r) is his true discount function. Since, when acting in this way he also equates
dkt'-r
-uc(t)/uc(t) to -,t-- /kt-T it follows that:
Consequently:
(32) In k = X0(O)/X(O)= X'(0)
(the second equality by normalization) or:
(33) k = antilog 'A(0).
The subscript X is deleted from (D because (F is the same functional for all -X under these
circumstances.
A graphic interpretation of this result is given by Figure 3. For the one-parameter
family of functions kt-r, that one is chosen which is tangent at t = X to the true discount
function X(t - r). For the " strategical" man who cannot precommit his future conduct
it is now clear that the only relevant characteristic of his true discount function is the rate
at which it changes at the present moment (at t 4'
-
[antilog P(o)tT
1
~~~~(t-T)
t
r ~~~~~~~~T
Figure 3
'A word on the rationaleof this solution is in order. We think of all deliberateaction through time
as involving precommitmentsover successive intervals,if the intervalsare sufficientlysmall ; and in the
mathematicaltreatmenthere we are simply consideringthe limit form of such behaviourwhere those small
intervalsapproachzero. Actually, it is impossiblefor an individualto choose his rate of consumptionat
every time independentlyof his consumption-timepath immediatelyprecedingand still have piecewise
X
differentiability,for then we brush up against Taylor's Theorem. (Consider the person who can vary
manuallythe flow of waterout of a tap and the deliberationof which he is capable while letting waterflow
out.) The solution we have obtainedin this section is, however,entirelyconsistentwith Taylor'sTheorem.
In the discretecase two differentinterpretationsof the problem are possible: (1) Each period the
individual selects his consumptionfor that period and there is no intra-perioddiscountingor allocation
problem. (2) At alternativeperiods the individual selects his consumption for that period and the next
and allocatesthis amount betweenthe two periods. It is only the latter interpretationwhich is comparable
with our continuous model.
A theory based on interpretation(1) appearsto be more complex and less fruitful in its implications,
although similarto the presenttheory in that strategiesof precommitmentand of consistentplanningarise.
The author's work on this alternativeapproachis, however, not yet complete.
VII. GENERALIZATION
What becomes of our results if more general utility functionals and budget constraints
are considered ?
Suppose that:
(T
(35) D = *-
X(t-T-) U[..., t]dt
these constraints, except that {C(t) , C2(t), ... are taken as historically given.
What is the necessary and sufficient condition on X(t - r) in order that planning
should be consistent ? This requires that whatever maximizes hD should maximize
+ iA X, for any A,7 0 < r + A: < T. For this to occur D+ A , must be a monotonic
increasing function of ID. Since T does not enter in u [ . . . , t] we need not concern
ourselves with that function. The question then is, how must X(t -M - A'r) be related
to X(t - r)? It is not enough that these should be monotonically increasing functions
of one another because of the variational nature of the problem. Each must be a positive
scalar multiple of the other, so that the scalar can be factored out of the integrand function
and placed in front of the integral sign. Thus, if x(t - T - A') = constant x ;(t - 4),
the solution to which is x(t - x) = kt-T, with the constant ratio equal to k-A T, we have:
-
:+A l X(t - - -A) u[. . , t]dt
(36) Jo
- k- A
= k-AT x(t - T) u[..., t]dt 0,
and this is the same solution as was obtained for the illustrative case treated earlier. The
important thing is that the relative weights of different dates should be invariant, and no
harm is done to the analysis by considering this more general type of functional and
constraint.
The qualifications underlined two paragraphs above are the significant ones. Should
T enter the problem in a more general way than by merely causing a linear shift of the
discount function, the problem of consistent planning becomes more involved. However,
even though the instantaneous utility function or the basic constraints do change with the
passage of time, if the individual does not take these future changes into account in deciding
what to do now, our analysis will still have validity for any fixed point of time.
Special attention should be given, I feel, to a discount function, such as that shown
in Figure 3, which differs from a logarithmically linear one in that it " over-values" the
more proximate satisfactions relative to the more distant ones.' Such a funiction suggests
that individuals who precommit their future actions or who naively resolve now what
they " will do " in the future, commonly do not schedule the beginning of austerity until
a later date. How familiar the sentence that begins, " I resolve, starting next . . ."' ! It
seems very human for a person who decides that he ought to increase his savings to plan
to start next month, after first satisfying some current desires ; or for one to decide to
quit smoking or drinking after the week-end, or to say that " the next one is the last one."
It has been customary for the United States Army to offer voluntary enlistees a
furlough starting with the date of enlistment. This practice is not needed to enable a
man to put his affairs in order-he can do that first and then enlist-but it does serve
as an enticement to those who want the paternalism (" security ") of the army, but do not
want it right now.2 The many schemes for instalment buying (notably of used automo-
biles in the U.S.) which require " no down payment and nothing due for two months "
are evidence of the effectiveness of enticements of this same kind. Indeed, all purchases
on credit can be viewed as precommitments that often (although not always) exchange
future costs for a present pleasure.3
My own supposition is that most of us are " born " with discount functions of the
sort considered here, that precommitment is only occasionally a feasible strategy (because
of risk and uncertainty), and that we are taught to plan consistently by substituting the
proper log-linear function for the true one. Children are known to discount the future
most precipitously and the " virtue " of frugality is something to be instilled when building
" character." True discount functions become sublimated by parental teaching and
social pressure, and the inconsistency problem considered in this paper becomes lost from
sight. There is a rationale for discounting at a constant rate of interest. In some cases
training may be so effective that the individual's original discount function can no longer
be said to be his " true" one. His tastes have changed and his discount function has
become log-linear or perhaps even constant. His is the " harmony " case. Precommitment,
therefore, is never attractive to him-even under certainty. In other cases,4 however, we
may say instead that a person has been taught to plan and behave consistently and not
that his tastes have been molded. His is not the harmony case. Such a person will, from
time to time, depart from the consistent pattern of behaviour, sometimes because pre-
commitment becomes feasible (and this is always his preferred strategy under conditions
because precommitment becomes feasible (and this is always his preferred strategy under
conditions of certainty) and sometimes because of lapses that result when the true weight
1 As an empirical supposition, there is a precedent for this in Bohm-Bawerk,op. cit., pp. 257-258,
the originalsubjectiveundervaluationsare, in the highestdegree,unequaland irregular. In particular,
so far as the undervaluationis caused by defects of will, theremay be a strong differencebetweenan enjoy-
ment which offers itself at the very moment, and one which does not; while, on the other hand, there may
be a very small difference,or no differenceat all, betweenan enjoymentwhich is pretty far away, and one
which is fartheraway." In context it is clear that he is referringhere to changes in the rate of discount.
This same possibilitywas consideredby Marshall,op. cit., MathematicalAppendix, Note V.
2
Since marriage was mentioned earlier alongside joining the army as a possible precomm-niitmenit
strategy, I cannot avoid remarkingfacetiously that marriagetoo is commonly preceded by a period of
engagement!
3 There are, of course, other importantreasons for buying on credit.
4 For the distinctionmade here I am indebtedto Mr. W. B. Reddawayand others in attendance at a
seminar on this paper at the Departmentof Applied Economics, CambridgeUniversity.
function becomes momentarily ascendant. These lapses are the splurges, binges, and
extravagances which we all know.1
This picture is typical, I suppose for most of us, but there are no doubt some who,
either through lack of training or insight, have never learned to behave consistently and
for whom the intertemporal tussle remains unsolved. These people we call " spend-
thrifts."2 By contrast, those who have taken on log-linear discount functions have
learned to be " thrifty."
Spendthriftiness, in the general sense of inconsistent or imprudent planning,3 is by
no means insignificant. It is especially among the lower-income classes, where education
and training are commonly blighted, that one would expect to find imprudent behaviour
of this sort.4 In America, lower-income people tend to gorge themselves with food after
pay-day ; overheat their homes when they have money for a bucket of coal ; are extrava-
gant, going on sprees on pay-day, not budgeting their money, and engaging in heavy
instalment buying ; do not keep their children in school ; and are freer in the expression
of their sexual and aggressive impulses.5 Their high birth rate is well-known. All these
behaviour characteristicscan be explained as a failure to cope intelligently with the problem
of the intertemporal tussle. Obviously, this is not the entire story; but the observations
are consistent with the hypothesis presented, and it would be upsetting if the facts werc
otherwise.
The character of behaviour under precommitment is more difficult to label. Its
results are somewhat ambiguous. Sometimes precommitment causes an individual to
sacrifice future pleasures heavily for the sake of present ones, e.g., to go into debt to make
possible an expenditure providing mostly present gratification. But at other times precom-
mitment seems more " wholesome,"6 as when a person contracts to save a certain amount
each month or goes into debt to buy a house. The distinction, I feel, is this: in the one
case the present is heavily favored at the expense of the future; in the other an allocation
is made among various dates of the future in accordance with weights given by the lower,
but more level portion of the X(t- r) function, as depicted in Figure 3. Precommitment
then has the effect of precluding grossly unequal allocation withinthat future period of time
once it moves into the present.
1 To one who would say that to discount the future for remotenessat all scems to him foolish and
irrational,I should reply that he is one who received very strong trainingas a child which went beyond
simply teaching him the strategy of consistent planning and effected such a change in his tastes that he
now finds it unnaturalto discount the future on this account. Moralizingagainst discountingthe future
in this way has, of course, found its way into the prominentliteratureon this subject. See, e.g., Bohm-
Bawerk,op. cit., pp. 253-255.
2
If the x(t--) function rose to the right of -r,inconsistencybetweenplans and behaviourwould lead
to " miserliness" with the individualsaving for a future plannedexpenditurewhich he continuouslypost-
pones. True miserlinesswould, however, appear to be better explained in other terms, money or wealth
becoming an object of desireper se.
* The " spendthrift" might, of course, also be definedas anyone who discounts the future because of
its remoteness,but I think this catches somewhatless satisfactorilythe essence of the term because such a
person may behave quite prudently-empty moralizingaside. Mr. Thore has pointed out, however, that
my spendthriftmight display more conservativebehaviourthan anotherperson who has a lower k even
though he plans consistently.
4 Perhaps in some underdevelopedeconomies this problemwould take on its most serious dimensions.
The notion that the incidenceof the sharp discounting of the future is greater among " primitiveraces,
children, and other uninstructivegroups in society" was asserted clearly by Fisher in The Theoryof
Interest,ch. IV, § 9, and earlier by Jevons irt The Theoryof Political Economy,ch. II and Bohm-Bawerk,
op. cit., p. 244.
5 See W. Allison Davis, "Child Rearingin the Class Structureof AmericanSociety " in The Familyin
a DemocraticSociety: AnniversaryPapersof the CommunityServiceSocietyof New York,1949and Robert
F. Winch, The ModernFamilv, 1952, pp. 93-94. These authors ascribe these behaviourpatternsto anxiety
feelings stemming from the insecuritythat results from low and irregularincome. It is not clear to me
why this anxietyshould lead to spendthriftinessratherthan to miserlinessor to painstakingfamilybudgeting.
If the facts were the opposite, would one feel any less comfortablewith the explanationgiven?
6
The word is in quotes becausewe do not intend to provide moraljudgmentsat this point.
The strategy of using a log-linear function also seems to have some appeal from the
" social" point of view. It means that the individual always decides what to do now
on the assumption that he has no authority over his future self. The individual cannot
decide what C(t) shall be for t > r, except that he can decide now what K(t) shall be for
t -X + dt. If the derivative of A(t- r) equals zero at t = r, then, of course, this case
reduces to that of" no myopia," the situation which Ramsay regarded as best. But, these
remarks notwithstanding, my own view is that the ethical issues presented by the problem
of dynamic choice remain basically unanswered if not unanswerable.
X. SUMMARY
To summarize, we have said that the optimal plan of future behaviour chosen as of a
given time
(A) may be a plan which will be followed under conditions of certainty (the harmtiony
case), or
(B) may be inconsistent with the optimizing future behaviour of the individual (the
intertemporaltussle). In this latter case
(1) the conflict may not be recognized and the individual will then be spendthrifty
(or miserly), his behavior being inconsistent with his plans, or
(2) the conflict may be recognized and solved either by
(a) a strategy of precommitment,or
(b) a strategy of consistent planining.
We have, moreover, hypothesized that the typical discount function has the shape
of X(t - r) as shown in Figure 3, and have argued that this hypothesis is consistent with
observed behavior.
Finally, we have challenged the meaning of the concept of consumer sovereignty
in this context of dynamic utility maximization.'