Unit 4
Unit 4
Structure
4.0 Introduction
4.1 Objectives
4.2 Definition of Criminal Responsibility
4.2.1 Assessment of Criminal Responsibility
4.2.2 Mens Rea
4.2.3 Mens Rea in the Indian Penal Code 1860
4.2.4 Appropriate Age Limits and Criminal Responsibility
4.3 Criminal Responsibility and Mental Disorder
4.3.1 Definition of Mental Disorder
4.3.2 Patterns of Criminality and Mental Disorder
4.3.3 Different Types of Personality and Mental Disorders
4.3.4 Criminal Responsibility and Schizophrenia
4.4 Delinquent Act
4.4.1 Criminal Responsibility and Delinquent Act
4.4.2 Psychopath and Criminal Responsibility
4.5 Insanity
4.5.1 Legal Use of the Term Insanity
4.5.2 Legal Insanity
4.5.3 Incompetency and Mental Illness
4.5.4 Rules of Appreciation
4.5.5 Mens Rea and legal Insanity
4.6 Civil Cases vs. Criminal Cases - Key Differences
4.6.1 Civil Cases
4.6.2 Criminal Cases
4.7 Types of Crime
4.7.1 White-Collar Crime
4.7.2 Blue-Collar Crime
4.7.3 State-Corporate Crime
4.7.4 Organised Crime
4.7.5 Juvenile Sex Crimes
4.7.6 Political Crime
4.7.7 Public Order Crime
4.7.8 State Crime
4.7.9 Victimless Crime
4.8 Factors that have to be Considered in Regard to Criminal Responsibility
4.9 Let Us Sum Up
4.10 Unit End Questions
4.11 Glossary
4.12 Suggested Readings
62
Criminal Responsibility
4.0 INTRODUCTION
In this unit we will be dealing with criminal responsibility which means that
whether a person who has committed the act or perpetrated the crime is responsible
enough to know that whatever he or she has done is legally incorrect, unlawful
and will entail punishment. Whether the person is aware of the crime committed
and was the crime committed with complete awareness and insight and also full
knowledge of the consequences. In what way criminal responsibility is considered
in terms of age, mental health and mental illness etc. Whether a mentally ill
person can be asked to appear in the court and defend self and whether a person
suffering from certain typical problems such as epilepsy can defend self in the
court etc.
4.1 OBJECTIVES
After completing this unit, you will be able to:
• Define criminal responsibility;
• Explain criminal responsibility in terms of age factor;
• Describe criminal responsibility and its characteristic features;
• Analyse criminal responsibility in terms of mental disorders; and
• Elucidate the various factors that have to be considered in regard to criminal
responsibility.
The precise definition of criminal responsibility varies from place to place but,
in general, to be responsible for a criminal act implies that the perpetrator must
understand what they are doing and that it is wrong. An individual may not be
considered responsible for having committed a crime if the person is a child who
does not understand what he or she is doing. Let us say two children of age 3
years or so are playing near a bath tub with water and one child pushes the other
child into the water playfully and the other child dies in the process. In such a
case the child cannot be held responsible for the killing of the other child because
both of them were playing and in play without any understanding of the
implications the first child pushed the second and the second child died. Here
there was no intention to kill but just play activity. The age factor thus plays an
important role in criminal responsibility.
Another aspect in which one cannot consider a person responsible for committing
a crime is mental disorder. Let us say a person suffering from paranoid disorder
(highly suspicious when suspicion is not at all warranted) feels threatened by
persecutors and runs for life from those persons. He is so scared of the persecutors
and imagines a person in his office being at the root of it. He is convinced that by
63
Approaches to killing that person he could be saved from being persecuted. Such a person who
Understanding Criminal
kills is doing so because of a delusion (false belief) that he is getting persecuted
Behaviour
by villains under the orders of a person in his office. This is a mental illness and
under this condition a person can go and kill another but is not aware of the
various consequences. Hence such a person cannot be held responsible for killing.
A landmark case occurred in 1843, when Daniel M’Naghten shot and killed the
secretary to Britain’s Prime Minister Robert Peel. The medical evidence found
M’Naghten to be insane. This led to the famous M’Naghten Rule where someone
could evade criminal responsibility if it could be proved that they did not
understand the “nature and quality” of the act they were committing. Equally,
they were not held responsible if they did understand what they were doing, but
did not know or realise that it was wrong.
Persons suffering from a psychosis may be so out of touch with reality that at the
time of the crime, the person may not realise what he is doing and what
consequences such a criminal action will have. Disorders of impulse control
may mean someone is unable to stop himself or herself from attacking someone.
People whose actions and judgment are affected by prescription drugs may also
not be fully responsible. Crimes with no apparent or rational motive may also be
committed by those who are not fully responsible for their actions.
The underlying principle of the doctrine of mens rea is expressed in the Latin
maxim actus non facit reum nisi mens sit rea – the act does not make one guilty
64
unless the mind is also guilty. Those who actually perform the criminal act (e.g., Criminal Responsibility
wielding the weapon that strikes the fatal blow) are often called principals in the
first degree. Those who assist at the time of the commission of the offense (e.g.,
holding the victim down while the principal in the first degree strikes the blow)
are principals in the second degree. And those who assist before the crime takes
place (e.g., by lending the weapon or by providing information) are accessories
before the fact.
Usually, the law considers all equally responsible and liable to the same
punishment. In many cases, though, the accessory before the fact is considered
more culpable (e.g., if he has instigated the offense and arranged for it to be
committed by an associate), and in some cases the person who actually performs
the criminal act is completely innocent of all intent (e.g., a nurse who unknowingly
administers to a patient, on a doctor’s instructions, medicine that turns out to be
poison). In the latter situation, the person who carries out the act is an innocent
agent and not criminally responsible, and the person who caused the innocent
agent to act is considered the principal in the first degree.
The mere commission of a criminal act (or bringing about the state of affairs that
the law provides against) is not enough to constitute a crime, at any rate in the
case of the more serious crimes. These generally require, in addition, some element
of wrongful intent or other fault.
Guilt in respect of almost all the offences created under the IPC is fastened either
on the ground of intention, or knowledge or reason to believe. Almost all the
offences under the IPC are qualified by one or other words such as ‘wrongful
gainer or wrongful loss’, ‘dishonestly’, ‘fraudulently’, ‘reason to believe’,
‘criminal knowledge or intention’, ‘intentional cooperation’, ‘voluntarily’,
‘malignantly’, ‘wantonly’, ‘maliciously’. All these words indicate the
blameworthy mental condition required at the time of commission of the offence,
in order to constitute an offence. Thus, though the word mens rea as such is
nowhere found in the IPC, its essence is reflected in almost all the provisions of
the Indian Penal Code 1860. Every offence created under the IPC virtually imports
the idea of criminal intent or mens rea in some form or other.
65
Approaches to The minimum age of criminal responsibility (minimum age) refers to the
Understanding Criminal
minimum age below which children shall be presumed not to have the capacity
Behaviour
to infringe the penal law. The establishment of such a minimum age means that
if a child below that age breaks the law, it cannot be held criminally responsible.
While article 40 of the Convention on the Rights of the Child (CRC) requires
that State Parties establish a minimum age, it leaves the specific age to be decided
by the individual state.
“Moral” means according to societal rather than individual moral code of the
accused. It is insufficient that the individual simply chooses to follow their own
moral dictates when they have the capacity to understand that it is wrong in the
eyes of the law and wrong according to society’s usual standards. The accused
must have the ability to apply that knowledge rationally.
The subjects of most forms of paranoia are liable to commit crime, usually violent,
which may lead to their being tried for assault or murder. The question of their
responsibility before the law is therefore one of the first importance (see also
Insanity: Law). The famous case of McNaghten, tried in 1843 for the murder of
Mr. Drummond, private secretary to Sir Robert Peel, is, in this connexion, highly
important, for McNaghten was a typical paranoiac labouring under delusions of
persecution, and his case formed the basis of the famous deliverance of the judges
in the House of Lords, in the same year, on the general question of criminal
responsibility in insanity. The judges’ deliverance contains the following statement
of law:
If “he labours under such partial delusion only and is not in other respects insane
we think he must be considered in the same situation as to responsibility as if the
facts to which the delusion exists were real. For example, if under the influence
of his delusion he supposes another man to be in the act of attempting to take
away his life, and he kills that man, as he supposes, in self-defense, he would be
exempt from punishment. If his delusion was that the deceased had inflicted a
serious injury to his character and fortune, and he killed him in revenge for such
supposed injury, he would be liable to punishment.”
69
Approaches to 4) The true paranoiac is a person of an anomalous mental constitution apart
Understanding Criminal
from his insanity; although he may to outward appearances be able, on
Behaviour
occasion, to converse or to act rationally, the moment he is dominated by
his delusions he becomes not partially but wholly insane; when in addition
his mind is distracted by ideas of persecution or hallucinations, or both, he
becomes potentially capable of committing a crime, not because of any
inherent vicious propensity but in virtue of his insanity. There is therefore
no middle course, from the medical point of view, in respect to the criminal
responsibility of the subjects of paranoia; they are all insane wholly, not
partially, and should only be dealt with as persons of unsound mind.
Schizophrenia
Schizophrenia is a mental disorder characterised by a disintegration of the process
of thinking and of emotional responsiveness. It most commonly manifests as
auditory hallucinations, paranoid or bizarre delusions, or disorganised speech
and thinking, and it is accompanied by significant social or occupational
dysfunction. The onset of symptoms typically occurs in young adulthood.
Differentiating between the form and contents of the micro psychotic state is of
marked importance in schizophrenia. In addition, identifying the form facilitates
the distinction between behaviours while sane and those during schizophrenic
episodes. Practically, the activating stimuli, which are likely to trigger the micro
psychotic state, are applied in the interview to establish the psychiatric testimony
based upon the activation-recurrence phenomenon. After the diagnosis of
schizophrenia has been confirmed, the examinee is exposed to the stimuli possibly
activating the micro psychotic state during the criminal act.
Observing the recurrence of the micro psychotic state and its frequency enables
estimation of the susceptibility to the occurrence of the activation-recurrence
phenomenon and the mental state during the criminal act. Therefore, if a micro
psychotic state during the criminal act can be confirmed, the inability to be held
legally responsible is postulated.
In contrast, if a micro psychotic state during the criminal act cannot be confirmed,
the specialist giving the psychiatric testimony should conclude that the crime
was most likely undertaken while sane, taking into account the objective
circumstantial evidence and the suspect’s coherent actions during the crime.
Self Assessment Questions
1) How are criminal responsibility and mental disorders related?
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
70
Criminal Responsibility
2) Discuss McNaughten trial and indicate why was it necessary to lay down
certain laws in this regard? What are the criticisms against the same?
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
3) Define mental disorder and bring out the differences between personality
disorders and mental disorders.
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
4) What are the various types of mental disorders? How is schizophrenia
affect criminal responsibility?
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
...............................................................................................................
Psychopaths seem to have in abundance the very traits most desired by normal
persons. The untroubled self-confidence of the psychopath seems almost like an
impossible dream and is generally what “normal” people seek to acquire when
they attend assertiveness training classes. In many instances, the magnetic
attraction of the psychopath for members of the opposite sex seems almost
supernatural.
Psychopaths can be brilliant, write scholarly works, imitate the words of emotion,
but over time, it becomes clear that their words do not match their actions. They
are the type of person who can claim that they are devastated by grief who then
attend a party “to forget.” The problem is: they really DO forget.
Being very efficient machines, like a computer, they are able to execute very
complex routines designed to elicit from others support for what they want. In
this way, many psychopaths are able to reach very high positions in life. It is only
over time that their associates become aware of the fact that their climbing up
the ladder of success is predicated on violating the rights of others.
By definition, an agent who is not morally responsible for behaviour does not
deserve moral blame and punishment for it. Indeed, the degree to which moral
and legal responsibility should be identical is of course controversial. Our criminal
law contains numerous instances of strict liability in which punishment, often
potentially severe, is imposed without any proof of moral fault. For the most
part, however, as we have seen, the doctrines that excuse or mitigate criminal
responsibility closely track the variables commonly thought to create moral excuse
or mitigation.
The justification for the law’s view that psychopaths are responsible may be
briefly stated.
First, psychopathy does not prevent agents from acting as the law defines action,
nor does it prevent psychopaths from forming prohibited mental states.
A psychopath who kills another human being intentionally is fully prima facie
criminally responsible.
Further, psychopaths are not excused because they do possess many rational
capacities. They usually know the facts and are generally in touch with reality.
They understand that there are rules and consequences for violating them, which
they treat as a “pricing” system, and they feel pleasure and pain, the anticipation
of which can potentially guide their conduct. This is a relatively thin conception
of rational capacity, but the law deems it sufficient to justify punishment on
desert and deterrence grounds.
In short, the law views the psychopath as bad, and not as mad. Psychopaths are
not morally responsible and do not deserve blame and punishment.
There are two potential theories for why this should be so: a specific and a general
theory concerning the psychopath’s rational capacities.
The specific theory concedes the law’s thin view of the psychopath’s rational
capacities, but suggests that the psychopath has particularised deficits of rationality
when moral concern and respect for others is in question.
As a normative matter, the best reasons people have for not violating the rights
of others are that the potential wrongdoer fully understands that it is wrong to do
so and has the capacity to empathize with the potential pain of their possible
victims and to use that as a reason for refraining.
If a person does not understand the point of morality and has no conscience or
capacity for empathy, only fear of punishment will give the person good reason
not to violate the rights of others.
As has been recognised at least since Hobbes, however, social cooperation and
safety cannot be secured solely by the fear of state punishment.
Internalised conscience and fellow feeling are the best guarantors of right action.
The psychopath is not responsive to moral reasons, even if they are responsive
to other reasons. Consequently, they do not have the capacity for moral rationality,
at least when their behaviour implicates moral concerns, and thus they are not
responsible.
The broader theory, most ably advanced by Paul Litton, denies that psychopaths
are rational at all because they lack any evaluative standards to assess and guide
their conduct.
They do not even possess evaluative standards related to the pursuit of excitement
and pleasure.
Psychopaths are like Frankfurt’s concept of the “wanton.” They do not feel regret,
remorse, shame, and guilt, feelings that are typically experienced in reaction to
our failure to meet the standards we have set for ourselves.
They may feel frustration and anger if they fail to get what they want, but these
are not reactive emotions. Such frustration or anger does not entail negative self-
evaluation.
Moreover, severe psychopaths are out of touch with ordinary social reality. They
say that they have goals, but act in ways inconsistent with understanding of what
entails having and achieving a goal.
Again, psychopaths know the facts and the rules and are capable of manipulation
of others to achieve their own ends, but they do not get the point of morality.
It is as if they are color blind to moral concerns. The rights and interests of others
have no place on their practical reasoning.
An interesting issue is whether psychopaths would also meet the criteria for
“control” tests for legal insanity, such as the inability to conform one’s conduct
to the requirements of law.
4.5 INSANITY
Insanity, craziness or madness is a spectrum of behaviours characterised by certain
abnormal mental or behavioural patterns. Insanity may manifest as violations of
societal norms, including becoming a danger to themselves and others, though
not all such acts are considered insanity. In modern usage insanity is most
commonly encountered as an informal unscientific term denoting mental
instability, or in the narrow legal context of the insanity defense. In the medical
profession the term is now avoided in favour of diagnoses of specific mental
illness such as schizophrenia and other psychotic disorders. When discussing
mental illness in general terms, “psychopathology” is considered a preferred
descriptor.
There are four kinds of persons who may be said to be non compos mentis (not
of sound mind) and these are:
1) an idiot – an idiot is one who from birth had defective mental capacity. This
infirmity in him is perpetual without lucid intervals.
2) one made so by illness – by illness, a person is made non compos mentis.
He is therefore excused in case of criminal liability, which he acts under the
influence of this disorder.
3) a lunatic or a madman – lunatics are those who become insane and whose
incapacity might be or was temporary or intermittent. A lunatic is afflicted
by mental disorder only at certain period and vicissitudes, having intervals
of reason; and
4) one who is drunk – this is covered under IPC.
Cognitive tests ask whether, at the time of the crime, the defendant was disabled
by mental disorder from knowing, appreciating, or understanding the nature of
his conduct or that it was morally or legally wrong. Control tests ask whether, as
a result of mental disorder, the defendant was unable at the time of the crime to
control his conduct or to conform his conduct to the requirements of the law.
None of the cognitive or control tests for legal insanity is self-defining. All require
substantial interpretation. To begin, how should the threshold requirement of a
mental disease or disorder or defect be defined? The Supreme Court has made
clear that the definition of mental disorder as a legal criterion for insanity is a
legal question and within the discretion of the states. Thus, states are free to limit
legal insanity to cases involving severe mental disorder or to define mental
disorder in a non-traditional way, as long as the definition is minimally rational.
They need not be bound by the definitions used by the mental health science
disciplines, such as psychiatry and psychology.
77
Approaches to Moreover, there is substantial leeway in whether the tests should be read narrowly
Understanding Criminal
or broadly. Control tests are often characterised as volitional, as if mental disorder
Behaviour
has somehow disabled the agent’s volitional capacities, but this locution is
confusing and should be abandoned.
There is no consensual definition of volition or will in any of the relevant
disciplines, such as psychology or philosophy, and this formulation quickly
dissolves into the intractable issues of how the brain enables the mind and how
intentions are related to actions. Perhaps one helpful way of thinking about volition
is as the executory mental state that produces an action in response to an intention.
Viewed in this way, however, virtually no one with a mental disorder has a
volitional problem because people with disorders are fully able to execute the
intentions that their disordered thoughts, perceptions, and desires may motivate.
Despite the definitional and empirical difficulties, however, some criminologists
and legal philosophers nevertheless believe control tests are necessary for crimes
committed by defendants with impulse disorders, such as Intermittent Explosive
Disorder, or “disorders of desire,” such as Pedophilia.
The problem in cases of alleged lack of self-control is distinguishing the disordered
person from any other agent who also wants to do something very badly that the
agent should not do, such as the very greedy person tempted terribly to steal.
Simply characterising the desire as disordered in one case but not the other cannot
resolve the question of control; it simply begs that question.
Why should we ever excuse someone who acts wrongly in response to a very
strong desire, whether that desire is normal or abnormal? Moreover, what theory
or account allows us to characterise desires, as opposed to perceptions and beliefs,
as irrational? How do we distinguish between an irresistible desire and a desire
simply not resisted? Concerns like these led both the American Bar Association
and the American Psychiatric Association to recommend abolition of an
independent control test during the insanity reform movement that occurred in
response to the Hinckley verdict.
The relevance of mental disorder to legal insanity tests is conceptually
straightforward, although evidentiary problems can arise. Insanity tests address
normative issues concerning responsibility that are broader than claims involving
action or mens rea, which are more factual.
The finder of fact needs the thickest possible description of the defendant’s
perceptions, thoughts, and feelings at the time of the crime in order to determine
whether the legal standard for insanity is met. The fact-finder employing a
cognitive or control test must thus evaluate how mental disorder affects
perceptions, thoughts, beliefs, desires, and feelings. While anatomical,
physiological, and other kinds of non-behavioural evidence may help the finder
of fact make inferences about the defendant’s psychological phenomenology,
the ultimate test is behavioural, making mental disorder evidence crucially
relevant.
People are found legally insane because they lack rational capacity or, more
controversially, because they cannot conform their behaviour to the requirements
of law.
Further, the “causal role” that mental disorder may play in criminal behaviour
78 must be properly understood. Causation in this instance means that mental
disorder produced distorted perceptions, thoughts, or desires that influenced the Criminal Responsibility
defendant’s reasons for action. It does not refer to “mechanical” causation. It has
nothing to do with determinism or free will. The actions of people motivated in
part by abnormal perceptions, beliefs. and desires are actions, but they may be
excused if the abnormality renders the agent sufficiently irrational. Causation of
behaviour by abnormal beliefs, for example, is no different from, no more “causal”
than, causation of behaviour by normal beliefs. The only difference is that in the
former case, the agent may be irrational and should therefore be excused.
Competency largely deals with the defendant’s present condition, while criminal
responsibility addresses the condition at the time the crime was committed.
In the United States, a trial in which the insanity defense is invoked typically
involves the testimony of psychiatrists or psychologists who will present opinions
on the defendant’s state of mind at the time of the offense. Mental health
practitioners are restrained from making a judgment on the issue of whether the
defendant is or is not insane or what is known as the “ultimate issue”.
Depending on the jurisdiction, other elements need to be proven, for the court to
accept that the mental disorder was responsible for the criminal act, that is, it
must be shown that the defendant committed the crime because of the mental
disorder. For example, the mental disorder interfered with his ability to determine
right from wrong at the time the offense was committed.
It would unduly stigmatize a person with a diagnosed mental illness to say that
because of the mental illness he is not responsible for his behaviour. Therefore,
persons whose mental disorder is not in dispute will be determined sane as the
court will decide that despite a “mental illness” the defendant was responsible
for the acts he committed and he will be treated in court as a normal defendant.
79
Approaches to If the person has a mental illness and it is determined that the mental illness
Understanding Criminal
interfered with the person’s ability to determine right from wrong, and other
Behaviour
associated criteria a jurisdiction may have, and if the person is willing to plead
guilty or is proven guilty in a court of law, some jurisdiction have an alternative
option known as either a Guilty but Mentally Ill (GBMI) or a Guilty but Insane
verdict. The GBMI verdict is available as an alternative to, rather than in lieu of,
a “not guilty by reason of insanity” verdict. Michigan (1975) was the first state
to create a GBMI verdict.
Sometimes a person without mental illness can be found to be insane; for example,
a person who was in a medical state of delirium at the time of the crime, or a
person who is acting under the influence of a drug that was involuntarily
administered (though voluntary intoxication has been rejected by most
jurisdictions as a defense to crime).
The House of Lords asked the judges of the common law courts to answer five
questions on insanity as a criminal defence, and the formulation that emerged
from their review—that a defendant should not be held responsible for his actions
only if, due to his mental disease or defect, he (i) did not know that his act would
be wrong; or (ii) did not understand the nature and quality of his actions—became
the basis of the law governing legal responsibility in cases of insanity in England.
Under the rules, loss of control because of mental illness was no defense. The
M’Naughten rule was embraced with almost no modification by American courts
and legislatures for more than 100 years, until the mid-20th century. In 1998, 25
states plus the District of Columbia still used versions of the M’Naughten rule to
test for legal insanity.
Civil suits are brought in both state and federal courts. An example of a civil
case in a state court would be if a citizen (including a corporation) sued another
citizen for not living up to a contract.
In India, The Courts shall (subject to the provisions herein contained) have
jurisdiction to try all suits of a civil nature excepting suits of which their
cognisance is either expressly or impliedly barred. A suit in which the right to
property or to an office is contested is a suit of a civil nature, notwithstanding
that such right may depend entirely on the decision of questions as to religious
rites or ceremonies. It is immaterial whether or not any fees are attached to the
office or whether or not such office is attached to a particular place.
Individuals, corporations, and the federal government can also bring civil suits
in federal court claiming violations of federal statutes or constitutional rights.
For example, the federal government can sue a hospital for overbilling Medicare
and Medicaid, a violation of a federal statute. An individual could sue a local
police department for violation of his or her constitutional rights—for example,
the right to assemble peacefully.
In some criminal cases, there may not be a specific victim. For example, state
governments arrest and prosecute people accused of violating laws against driving
while intoxicated because society regards that as a serious offense that can result
in harm to others.
When a court determines that an individual committed a crime, that person will
receive a sentence. The sentence may be an order to pay a monetary penalty (a
fine and/or restitution to the victim), imprisonment, or supervision in the
community (by a court employee called a U.S. probation officer if a federal
crime), or some combination of these three things.
When senior levels of a corporation engage in criminal activity using the company
this is sometimes called control fraud.
States will define as political crimes any behaviour perceived as a threat, real or
imagined, to the state’s survival including both violent and non-violent
oppositional crimes. A consequence of such criminalisation may be that a range
of human rights, civil rights, and freedoms are curtailed, and conduct which
would not normally be considered criminal per se is criminalised at the
convenience of the group holding power.
Thus, while the majority of those who support the current regime may consider
criminalisation of politically motivated behaviour as an acceptable response when
the offender is driven by more extreme political, ideological, religious or other
beliefs, there may be a question of the morality of a law which simply criminalises
ordinary political dissent.
84
4.7.7 Public Order Crime Criminal Responsibility
In criminology public order crime is defined a crime which involves acts that
interfere with the operations of society and the ability of people to function
efficiently, that is, public order crime is a behaviour that has been labelled criminal
because it is contrary to shared norms, social values, and customs. Generally
speaking, deviancy is criminalised when it is too disruptive and has proved
uncontrollable through informal sanctions.
Public order crime should be distinguished from political crime. In the former,
although the identity of the “victim” may be indirect and sometimes diffuse, it is
cumulatively the community that suffers, whereas in a political crime, the state
perceives itself to be the victim and criminalises the behaviour it considers
threatening. Thus, public order crime includes consensual crime, victimless vice,
and victimless crime. It asserts the need to use the law to maintain order both in
the legal and moral sense.
For example, in cases where a criminal act subverts or undermines the commercial
effectiveness of normative business practices, the negative consequences extend
beyond those at whom the specific immediate harm was intended. Similarly, in
environmental law, there are offences that do not have a direct, immediate and
tangible victim, so crimes go largely unreported and unprosecuted because of
the problem of lack of victim awareness. In short, there are no clear, unequivocal
definitions of ‘consensus’, ‘harm’, ‘injury’, ‘offender’, and ‘victim’.
Green & Ward (2004) adopt Weber’s Thesis of a sovereign “state” as possessing
a monopoly on the right to use force. Thus, the criteria for determining whether
a state is “deviant” will draw on international norms and standards of behaviour
for achieving the state’s usual operating goals. One of those standards will be
whether the state respects human rights in the exercise of its powers. But, one of
the definitional difficulties is that the states themselves define what is criminal
within their own territories, and as sovereign powers, they are not accountable to
the international community unless they submit to international jurisdiction
generally, or criminal jurisdiction in particular.
86
Criminal Responsibility
4.8 FACTORS THAT HAVE TO BE CONSIDERED
IN REGARD TO CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY
Let us first take up the biological factors. Neurochemicals are responsible for the
activation of behavioural patterns and tendencies in specific areas of the brain.
There have been attempts to determine the role of neurochemicals in influencing
criminal or antisocial behaviour. Included in the list of neurochemicals already
cited by researchers are monoamine oxidase (MOA), epinephrine, norepinephrine,
serotonin, and dopamine. Monoamine oxidase (MAO) is an enzyme that has
been shown to be related to antisocial behaviour. Specifically, low MAO activity
results in disinhibition which can lead to impulsivity and aggression.
Social learning theory has been cited as way to explain how the environment can
influence a child’s behaviour. Using this theory to explain the aggressive or
antisocial behaviour of a child means that a child observes aggressive behaviour
between parents, siblings, or both. As a result, the children believe that this
aggressive behaviour is normal and can therefore use it themselves because they
do not see the harm in acting similar to their parents.
The exposure to such high levels of aggression and other environmental factors
greatly influences and reinforces a child’s behaviour. A significant point that
should be known however is the fact that other research has supported the notion
that genetics do influence levels of aggression, which stands in opposition to the
social learning theory (Miles & Carey, 1997).
Researchers, however, have certainly come far in their progression, to the point
where there is a large consensus of the fact that genes do influence behaviour to
88
a certain extent. Although not as widely publicized, it is the belief of the author Criminal Responsibility
that these same researchers also believe that environmental factors account for
what cannot be explained by genes. Therefore it seems obvious to reach the
conclusion that an individual’s antisocial or criminal behaviour can be the result
of both their genetic background and the environment in which they were raised.
One researcher has proposed a theory relating to sociopaths and their antisocial
behaviour. According to the theory, a primary sociopath is lacking in moral
development and does not feel socially responsible for their actions. This type of
sociopath is a product of the individual’s personality, physiotype, and genotype.
A secondary sociopath develops in response to his or her environment because
of the disadvantages of social competition. Living in an urban residence, having
a low socio-economic status, or poor social skills can lead an individual to being
unsuccessful in reaching their needs in a socially desirable way, which can turn
into antisocial or criminal behaviour. The first type of sociopath is dependent on
their genetic makeup and personality, while certain factors of the second type
can also be heritable. Notwithstanding, the second type has a greater dependence
on environmental factors (Miles & Carey, 1997). Perhaps from this review of
both genetic and environmental factors, it seems clear to support the idea of the
secondary sociopath type. An individual can inherit certain genes and when
combined with the right environmental factors can lead them to engage in
antisocial or criminal behaviour.
Although not mentioned extensively in the text of the paper, there is a great need
to try and identify those individuals, especially children, who may become
susceptible to certain disorders or personality traits that can lead into antisocial,
delinquent, or criminal behaviour. Society should not try to imitate the era of
controlled breeding, but rather focus on the treatment and rehabilitation of those
individuals in need. Certain educational, environment enrichment programs have
been shown to have a lasting effect on children if given by a certain age (Raine,
Mellingen, Liu, Venables, & Mednick, 2003). If more of these programs could
be developed, society could help prevent the future antisocial or criminal
behaviour of children.
89
Approaches to
Understanding Criminal 4.11 GLOSSARY
Behaviour
Automaton : Moving mechanical device made in imitation of a
human being.
Executor : A person appointed by a testator to carry out the
terms of their will.
Fallacy : Mistaken belief or a failure in reasoning which
renders an argument invalid.
Fraudulent : Done by or involving fraud.
Hysteria : Exaggerated or uncontrollable emotion or
excitement or convergence of psychological stress
into physical symptoms or a change in self-
awareness.
Perpetrate : Carry out or commit (a harmful, illegal or immoral
action).
Persecute : Subject to prolonged hospitality or ill-treatment.
Personality Disorder : Deeply ingrained and mal-adaptive pattern of
behaviour typically causing long term difficulties
in social relationships.
Psychosis : A mental disorder in which thought and emotions
are so impaired that perception of external reality
is severely affected.
Transient : Lasting for a short while.
Vandalise : Deliberately destroy or damage property.
90