Must Read
Must Read
4 Decision-Making in
Clinical Medicine
solving behavior. Because of the diverse perspectives contributing to
this area, with important contributions from cognitive psychology,
medical education, behavioral economics, sociology, informatics, and
decision sciences, no single integrated model of clinical reasoning
CHAPTER 4
Daniel B. Mark, John B. Wong exists, and not infrequently, different terms and reasoning models
describe similar phenomena.
Intuitive Versus Analytic Reasoning A useful contemporary
Practicing medicine at its core requires making decisions. What makes model of reasoning, the dual-process theory distinguishes two general
medical practice so difficult is not only the specialized technical conceptual modes of thinking as fast or slow. Intuition (System 1)
assessment form,” which defines and standardizes the information the availability heuristic arise from several sources of recall bias. Rare
gathered. After quickly acquiring the requisite structured examination catastrophic outcomes become memorable cases with a clarity and
components and noting in particular the absence of fever and a clear force disproportionate to their likelihood for future diagnosis—for
chest examination, the physician prescribed a cough suppressant for example, a patient with a sore throat eventually found to have leuke-
The Profession of Medicine
acute bronchitis and reassured the patient that his illness was not seri- mia or a young athlete with leg pain subsequently found to have an
ous. Following a sleepless night at home with significant dyspnea, the osteosarcoma—and those publicized in the media or recently experi-
patient developed nausea and vomiting and collapsed. He was brought enced are, of course, easier to recall and therefore more influential on
back to the ED in cardiac arrest and was unable to be resuscitated. clinical judgments.
His autopsy showed a posterior wall myocardial infarction (MI) and The third commonly used cognitive shortcut, the anchoring heu-
a fresh thrombus in an atherosclerotic right coronary artery. What ristic (also called conservatism or stickiness), involves insufficiently
went wrong? Presumably, the ED clinician felt that the patient was adjusting the initial probability of disease up (or down) following a
basically healthy (one can be misled by the way the patient appears on positive (or negative test) when compared with Bayes’ theorem, i.e.,
examination—a patient that does not appear “sick” may be incorrectly sticking to the initial diagnosis. For example, a clinician may still judge
assumed to have an innocuous illness). So, in this case, the physician, the probability of coronary artery disease (CAD) to be high despite a
upon hearing the overview of the patient from the triage nurse, elected negative exercise perfusion test and go on to cardiac catheterization
to use the URI assessment protocol even before starting the history, (see “Measures of Disease Probability and Bayes’ Rule,” below).
closing consideration of the broader range of possibilities and associ- The fourth heuristic states that clinicians should use the simplest
ated tests required to confirm or refute these possibilities. In particular, explanation possible that will adequately account for the patient’s
by concentrating on the abbreviated and focused URI protocol, the symptoms and findings (Occam’s razor or, alternatively, the simplicity
clinician failed to elicit the full dyspnea history, which was precipitated heuristic). Although this is an attractive and often used principle, it
by exertion and accompanied by chest heaviness and relieved by rest, is important to remember that no biologic basis for it exists. Errors
suggesting a far more serious disorder. from the simplicity heuristic include premature closure leading to the
Heuristics or rules of thumb are a part of the intuitive system. neglect of unexplained significant symptoms or findings.
These cognitive shortcuts provide a quick and easy path to reaching For complex or unfamiliar diagnostic problems, clinicians typically
conclusions and making choices, but when used improperly, they can resort to analytic reasoning processes (System 2) and proceed method-
lead to errors. Two major research programs have studied heuristics ically using the hypothetico-deductive model of reasoning. Based on
in a mostly nonmedical context and have reached very different con- the patient’s stated reasons for seeking medical attention, clinicians
clusions about the value of these cognitive tools. The “heuristics and develop an initial list of diagnostic possibilities in hypothesis generation.
biases” program focuses on how these mental shortcuts can lead to During the history of the present illness, the initial hypotheses evolve
incorrect judgments. So far, however, little evidence exists that educat- in diagnostic refinement as emerging information is tested against
ing physicians and other decision makers to watch for the >100 cogni- the mental models of the diseases being considered with diagnoses
tive biases identified to date has had any effect on the rate of diagnostic increasing and decreasing in likelihood or even being dropped from
errors. In contrast, the “fast and frugal heuristics” research program consideration as the working hypotheses of the moment. These mental
explores how and when relying on simple heuristics can produce good models often generate additional questions that distinguish the diag-
decisions. Although many heuristics have relevance to clinical reason- nostic possibilities from one another. The focused physical examina-
ing, only four will be mentioned here. tion contributes to further distinguishing the working hypotheses. Is
When diagnosing patients, clinicians usually develop diagnostic the spleen enlarged? How big is the liver? Is it tender? Are there any
hypotheses based on the similarity of that patient’s symptoms, signs, palpable masses or nodules? Diagnostic verification involves testing the
and other data to their mental representations (memorized patterns) adequacy (whether the diagnosis accounts for all symptoms and signs)
of the disease possibilities. In other words, clinicians pattern match and coherency (whether the signs and symptoms are consistent with
to identify the diagnoses that share the most similar findings to the the underlying pathophysiologic causal mechanism) of the working
patient at hand. This cognitive shortcut is called the representative- diagnosis. For example, if the enlarged and quite tender liver felt on
ness heuristic. Consider a patient with hypertension who has head- physical examination is due to acute hepatitis (the hypothesis), then
ache, palpitations, and diaphoresis. Based on the representativeness certain specific liver function tests will be markedly elevated (the pre-
heuristic, clinicians might judge pheochromocytoma to be quite diction). Should the tests come back normal, the hypothesis may have
likely given this classic presenting symptom triad suggesting pheo- to be discarded and others reconsidered.
chromocytoma. Doing so, however, would be incorrect given that Although often neglected, negative findings are as important as
other causes of hypertension are much more common than pheo- positive ones because they reduce the likelihood of the diagnostic
chromocytoma and this triad of symptoms can occur in patients who hypotheses under consideration. Chest discomfort that is not provoked
do not have it. Thus, clinicians using the representativeness heuristic or worsened by exertion and not relieved by rest in an active patient
may overestimate the likelihood of a particular disease based on the lowers the likelihood that chronic ischemic heart disease is the under-
presence of representative symptoms and signs, failing to account for lying cause. The absence of a resting tachycardia and thyroid gland
its low underlying prevalence (i.e., the prior, or pretest, probabilities). enlargement reduces the likelihood of hyperthyroidism in a patient
Conversely, atypical presentations of common diseases may lead to with paroxysmal atrial fibrillation.
underestimating the likelihood of a particular disease. Thus, inexpe- The acuity of a patient’s illness may override considerations of prev-
rience with a specific disease and with the breadth of its presentations alence and the other issues described above. “Diagnostic imperatives”
may also lead to diagnostic delays or errors, e.g., diseases that affect recognize the significance of relatively rare but potentially catastrophic
multiple organ systems, such as sarcoid or tuberculosis, may be partic- conditions if undiagnosed and untreated. For example, clinicians should
ularly challenging to diagnose because of the many different patterns consider aortic dissection routinely as a possible cause of acute severe
they may manifest. chest discomfort. Although the typical presenting symptoms of dissec-
A second commonly used cognitive shortcut, the availability heu- tion differ from those of MI, dissection may mimic MI, and because
ristic, involves judgments based on how easily prior similar cases or it is far less prevalent and potentially fatal if mistreated, diagnosing
outcomes can be brought to mind. For example, a clinician may recall dissection remains a challenging diagnostic imperative (Chap. 280).
CHAPTER 4
sis. If, however, the chest x-ray shows a possible widened mediastinum, can present with specific symptoms and signs (differential diagnosis).
the hypothesis should be reinstated and an appropriate imaging test Active learning opportunities useful for those in training include
ordered (e.g., thoracic computed tomography [CT] scan or transesoph- developing a personal learning system, e.g., systematically reflecting
ageal echocardiogram). In nonacute situations, the prevalence of on diagnostic processes used (metacognition) and following-up to
potential alternative diagnoses should play a much more prominent identify diagnoses and treatments for patients in their care.