Brian Bix - Jurisprudence
Brian Bix - Jurisprudence
Jurisprudence
Theory and Context
bix 6e cap fmt pages 6/26/12 9:24 AM Page 2
bix 6e cap fmt pages 6/26/12 9:24 AM Page 3
Jurisprudence
Theory and Context
Sixth Edition
Brian Bix
K230.B5786A348 2012
340'.1--dc23 2012025898
This edition of
Jurisprudence: Theory and Context, 6th edition
is published by arrangement with
Sweet & Maxwell
part of Thomson Reuters (Professional) UK Limited
Aldgate House, 33 Aldgate High Street,
London EC3N 1DL
“To make this discovery with Holmes is to be with a guide whose words may
leave you unconvinced, sometimes even repelled, but never mystified. Like our
own [John] Austin . . . Holmes was sometimes clearly wrong; but again like
Austin he was always wrong clearly.”2
1
Unlike some writers, e.g. William Twining, “Academic Law and Legal Philosophy: The
Significance of Herbert Hart”, (1979) 95 Law Quarterly Review 557, at pp. 565–580, I do
not distinguish between “jurisprudence”, “legal theory”, and “legal philosophy”, and I
will use those terms interchangeably.
2
H. L. A. Hart, “Positivism and the Separation of Law and Morals”, 71 Harvard Law
Review 593 (1958).
3
H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (2nd ed., Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1994), p. vi.
are less ambitious: the present text is a book meant to inform readers
what other books contain—the idea being that the primary texts are not
always as accessible as they might be. However, this book is distinctly
not meant as a substitute for reading those primary texts: the hope and
the assumption is that readers will go to the primary texts first, and will
return to them again after obtaining whatever guidance is to be offered
in these pages. Additionally, there are a number of places in the text
where I go beyond a mere reporting of the debate, and try to add my
own views to the discussion. This is especially true of Chapters 2 and 11,
but, in smaller ways, throughout the other chapters of the book as well.
why jurisprudence?
One can find entire books on many of the topics discussed in the present
volume in short chapters (or parts of chapters). I have done my best to offer
overviews that do not sacrifice the difficulty of the subjects, but I fear that
some mis-reading is inevitable in any summary. In part to compensate for
the necessarily abbreviated nature of what is offered, a list of “Suggested
Further Reading” is offered at the end of each chapter (and there are foot-
note citations to the primary texts in the course of the chapters) for those
who wish to locate longer and fuller discussions of certain topics.
A related problem is that in the limited space available, I could not
include all the topics that are associated with jurisprudence (a course
whose content varies greatly from university to university, and even from
teacher to teacher in the same university). The variety of topics included
in one source or another under the category of jurisprudence is vast, so
inevitably there always seems to be more missing from than present in
any text. Through my silence (or brevity), I do not mean to imply that
the topics not covered are not interesting, not important, or not properly
part of jurisprudence.
It is inevitable that those using this book will find some chapters more
useful for their purposes than others, even (or especially) if they are stu-
dents using this book to accompany a general jurisprudence course. In
particular, the topics in the first part of the book are usually not covered
in university courses, though I believe that thinking through some of the
questions raised there might help one gain a deeper or more coherent
view of jurisprudence as a whole.
One caveat I must offer is that references to legal practice offered in
this book will be primarily to the practices in the American and English4
4
I am following the usual convention of using the term “English legal system” to refer to
the legal system that extends over both England and Wales.
legal systems, as these are the systems with which I am most familiar.
It is likely (though far from certain) that any comments based on those
two legal systems would be roughly generalised to cover all common law
systems. The extent to which my lack of familiarity with civil law systems
biases my views about legal theory and about the nature of law I must
leave to others to judge.
I take seriously the obligation that comes with publishing a new
edition of an existing book. I believe that any new edition should offer
resources that the prior edition did not have. While there is rarely time
to revisit and rewrite everything, in the preparation of the sixth edition
of this book, many of the chapters have been expanded, discussions of
the most recent scholarship has been added throughout, and many topics
have been significantly rethought. While there are changes throughout
the book, the most extensive changes are located in Chapters 2, 3, 7, 9,
15, 18, 21, and 22.
Where possible, I have tried to include references (especially in each
chapter’s “Suggested Further Reading” list) that are readily accessible:
e.g., articles in well-known journals that would be available in most law
libraries or from electronic law journal collections (like Hein OnLine), and
articles from Internet sources (like The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
(plato.stanford.edu) and the Social Services Research Network (www.
ssrn.com)) that are available without cost (at least at the time of writing).
Work on this book often overlapped with work I was doing for other
smaller projects: sometimes work done for the book was borrowed for
other projects, and sometimes I found that work done for other projects
could be usefully incorporated in the book. An earlier version of parts
of Chapter 2 appeared in “Conceptual Questions and Jurisprudence”,
1 Legal Theory 415 (1995); earlier versions of parts of Chapters 5, 6, and
7 appeared in “Natural Law Theory”, in A Companion to the Philosophy
of Law and Legal Theory (D. Patterson, ed., Blackwell, Oxford, 1996,
2nd ed., 2010); an earlier version of brief sections of Chapters 1 and 7
appeared in “Questions in Legal Interpretation”, in Law and Interpretation
(A. Marmor, ed., Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1995), pp. 137–154; and an
earlier version of parts of Chapters 1, 2, and 14 appeared in “Questions
in Legal Interpretation”, 18 Tel Aviv Law Review 463 (1994) (translated
into Hebrew). I am grateful to the publishers of these texts for allowing
me permission to use material from those articles.
I would like to thank the following for their helpful comments and sug-
gestions: Mark Addis, Larry Alexander, Jack Balkin, Lisa Bernstein, Scott
Brewer, Keith Burgess-Jackson, Kenneth Campbell, Tom Campbell,
Richard Delgado, Anuj Desai, Anthony M. Dillof, Neil Duxbury, Neal
Feigenson, John Finnis, Stephen Gilles, Martin P. Golding, Aristides N.
Hatzis, Alex M. Johnson, Jr., Sanford N. Katz, Matthew H. Kramer,
Kenneth J. Kress, Brian Leiter, Andrei Marmor, Jerry Mashaw, Linda
R. Meyer, Martha Minow, Thomas Morawetz, Martha C. Nussbaum,
Pragmatism 280
Postmodernism 284
Suggested Further Reading 287
Bibliography 291
Index 329