The George Grant Reader
The George Grant Reader
Edited by
WILLIAM CHRISTIAN
and
SHEILA GRANT
Printed in Canada
Acknowledgments ix
Introduction 3
LOUIS-FERDINAND CELINE
Celine: Art and Politics (1983) 369
Index 483
Acknowledgments
Life
year of study but felt increasingly guilty in the aloof comfort of Oxford.
Though a pacifist, he decided to remain in England and, in the sum-
mer of 1940, joined an ambulance unit. When the Battle of Britain
started, he became an air raid precautions warden in Bermondsey in
the east end of London, one of the most heavily bombed parts of the
capital. It is an understatement to say that it was during this period that
he grew up. His life of privilege was over.
The gruelling experience of violence and death broke him forever
from the comfortable liberalism in which he had been raised. It also
destroyed his health. The nightly bombing stopped when the Germans
invaded Russia. Under enormous pressure from his family and friends
to do his duty to king and country, he attempted to join the merchant
marine, although this compromised his pacifist principles. He was
turned down because the medical examination revealed signs of tuber-
culosis. Not waiting for a formal discharge, he ran away and worked on
a farm, saying later that it was a way to be left alone and also to get food
(since he was without a ration book). It was at this point, in December
1941, while bicycling to work one morning, that he experienced a sud-
den total conviction that beyond the chaos of the world there was
eternal order, that God existed, and that we are not our own. This cer-
tainty lasted all his life.
After being nursed back to health in Toronto, he spent two years
working for the Canadian Association for Adult Education. This job
involved much travelling across Canada, writing, and speaking. The
experience proved a useful preparation for his later career as a univer-
sity teacher, and he probably owed to it much of his ease in writing and
speaking to the public, and perhaps also something of his powerful
radio personality. (The selection with which this reader begins, a radio
talk on philosophy, exemplifies his skill at clarifying complicated issues
for a mass audience.)
After the war, he returned to Oxford, but he had decided not to
pursue a legal career. He wanted instead to explore the implications of
his religious experience and to find out more about Christianity. The
master of Balliol College, A.D. Lindsay, suggested that he write a DPhil
thesis on the philosophy of a Scottish Presbyterian theologian, John
Oman. Grant had never heard of Oman and his lack of enthusiasm for
his subject probably accounts for the small progress he made on his
thesis. However, he threw himself into reading Plato, St Augustine,
and other philosophers. After two years in Oxford, he married Sheila
Allen, a student of English literature and a fellow pacifist, who had also
Introduction 5
Not being a person who would naturally (whatever that means) have
turned to speculation - that is having been driven to it - I am simply flab-
bergasted at where philosophy has taken me. Just not at all the sort of
course I expected. It is like setting out on what one expected to be a jaunt
across the Arm 2 - finding oneself shipwrecked time after time and yet
knowing one has no alternative but to go on - moods of dereliction -
moods of amusement and moments of joy - but above all sheer unadul-
terated amazement. I just could have expected anything of life, but not
this. Above all the dereliction is when philosophy is in direct conflict with
ambition. For a variety of reasons my adolescence was taken up by the
idea of fame as the summum bonurrt and it is really shattering to me to
have to face it for what it is.4
During this time at Dalhousie, he and Sheila had six children, three
girls and three boys, and Grant made many lasting friendships. As well
as his formal teaching, Grant continued to be active in adult educa-
tion. He gave numerous speeches to teachers, delivered papers at all
kinds of gatherings, and spoke on many radio programs (which had
the added advantage of helping to supplement his meager academic
salary.) After their third child was born, the Grants acquired a second-
hand car and life became a little easier. Grant found Nova Scotian stu-
dents wonderfully open to thought. They had not been 'wised up' at
high school, and so they did not have to unlearn a lot of progressive
modern dogma.
By 1958 Canada's economy was booming and Grant was still weigh-
ing the character of the progressive society that was forming. James
Doull, a learned friend and colleague, had taught him how to under-
stand Plato and was leading him through the maze of Hegel's thought.
The good students he encountered also gave him reason to hope for a
better future. This optimism was apparent in Philosophy in the Mass Age,
originally presented as a series of radio lectures for the CBC's first Uni-
versity of the Air, the predecessor of the program Ideas. Philosophy in the
Mass Age was an immediate and immense success.
6 Introduction
By the end of the 1950s Grant was eager for a change. He accepted an
offer to head the philosophy department at the newly founded York
University in Toronto, but he resigned before having taught a class. (See
his letter to Murray Ross in Part 2.) After fearing for over a year that he
might have to move to the United States to find a teaching job, he was
finally offered a promising position in the new department of religion
at McMaster University in Hamilton. The next twenty years there were
rewarding ones. By the mid-1960s his thought had become more coher-
ent and more confident. He had explicitly rejected Hegel's philosophy
and was avidly reading the German-American political philosopher Leo
Strauss, and he was also planning to write a book on the French mystic
and philosopher Simone Weil. Philip Sherrard's The Greek East and the
Latin West helped to clarify his misgivings about Western Christianity.
Living in southern Ontario was itself an educational experience. The
booming technological world was all around him and he worked at a
university that had its own nuclear reactor. In 1966 he read Jacques
Ellul's The Technological Society, and he felt as if a new planet had swum
into his ken. It further clarified the meaning of the political events with
which he had dealt in his best-selling book Lament for a Nation. In 1969,
with the help of poet and editor Dennis Lee, he put together a collection
of essays on mainly political themes, Technology and Empire.
It might appear that in this great flurry of activity in the mid-1960s
Grant had changed some of his views dramatically. The admiration for
Hegel seen in Philosophy in the Mass Age and renounced in 1966 would
seem to be an example of this. But in fact the change had been grad-
ual and his view of Hegel had been ambivalent, as is clear from a 1956
notebook. Grant did not have a cut-and-dried system and did not seek
to create one. 'One thing about life: how is one to suppose that one's
position at the moment is final, when one already knows so much from
life and has learnt it on the way? Presumably one is going to learn
more.'0 Grant had indeed learnt more since the 1950s, but his pro-
found adherence to Christianity and to Plato never wavered. His
understanding of both was enriched by his continuing study of Simone
Weil, who could herself be described as a Platonist within Christianity.
Grant's next book, Time as History (1970), was a study of Nietzsche's
thought and its influence on modernity. It was originally delivered as
the 1969 Massey lectures on CBC. In the middle of revising it for publi-
cation, Grant and his wife were nearly killed in an automobile acci-
dent. His injuries required a long convalescence and he never quite
regained his old zest for life.
Introduction 7
The question that haunted him during the early 1970s was how one
could think about the Good (or God) when technology had destroyed
the very language by which such thought could be expressed. He
started to use the word 'justice' rather than 'good,' since he thought
that justice was a word that still had resonance. He struggled with this
dilemma in two unfinished manuscripts, 'Good and Technique' and
Technique and the Good.' They contained some of the ideas that
appeared much later in Technology and Justice (1986). In 1977 he com-
pleted the revision of the Wood lectures he had delivered at Mount
Allison University in 1974. English-Speaking Justice was a devastating cri-
tique of modern liberalism and its deterioration under the corrosive
influence of the very technology it had made possible.
Towards the end of the 1970s Grant became increasingly frustrated
by the direction the department of religion at McMaster was taking. It
had once centred on the great religious traditions of East and West. Its
teachers explored these from within the traditions themselves and
raised with students the universal questions inherent in them. Now,
Grant thought, the department had come to concentrate on historical
scholarship at the expense of raising philosophical questions (see 'The
Battle between Teaching and Research' in Part 2). In 1980 Grant left
McMaster and returned to Dalhousie, where he taught classes in politi-
cal science and classics until his retirement in 1984. He still had close
friends at Dalhousie, though he found the university itself changed for
the worse.
Many honours came to him during this period: the Chauvais Medal
from the Royal Society, several honorary degrees, and an appointment
to the Order of Canada. These honours were curious, since most influ-
ential Canadians did not share his views, particularly his critique of
technology, and his Christianity was not fashionable in the secular
atmosphere of the modern university. As his former student and col-
league Louis Greenspan expressed it: 'As one who loved his country,
he welcomed this recognition, but not without the dismay that Tertul-
lian or Justin Martyr or any other early Christian might have felt had
their indictments of the Roman gods as demons been greeted with
thunderous ovations from the Roman Senate.'6
During the early 1980s Grant's main philosophical experience was
reflecting on Jean-Jacques Rousseau's Discourse on the Origins of Inequal-
ity among Men. Grant had come to believe that Rousseau's importance
as a maker of modernity had not been fully understood. To explore
this theme, he started writing a work on history and justice. His other
8 Introduction
great experience was a literary one: he read and re-read the three last
novels of Louis-Ferdinand Celine, about which he made voluminous
notes towards a possible book. His last book, Technology and Justice
(1986), was a collection of essays which he revised for publication.
Poor health and frequent visits to the hospital took up a great deal
of his time and energy after he retired. However, he became more and
more interested in the writings of the German philosopher Martin
Heidegger and began work on what he hoped would be his magnum
opus, a defence of Christianity and Platonism against Heidegger's
attack. In August 1988 he began the preliminary chapter, but on 6 Sep-
tember he learned he had pancreatic cancer. He died on 27 Septem-
ber 1988.
Why is the first section of this reader titled 'Politics and Morality?'
George Grant was usually described as a political philosopher, and he
accepted that description. Why then 'morality?' In his last book, Tech-
nology and Justice, he portrayed himself as one who in political philoso-
phy was above all 'a lover of Plato within Christianity.' This position is
implicit in his writings from beginning to end. He would not, and per-
haps could not, separate political philosophy from the central ques-
tion of how it is good for human beings to live together. His thought
about political subjects was necessarily part of his thought about the
whole. If political thought is concerned with judgments about good-
ness, it must depend on what one believes human beings to be.
For the ancients (particularly Plato and Aristotle), wisdom and the
virtue that led to it and flowed from it was the highest achievement of
human beings and constituted their excellence. In the modern world,
especially since Machiavelli, freedom and equality have replaced wis-
dom and virtue as the highest goods for men and women. Grant had
no doubt that the conceptions held by the ancients were more pro-
found than those of the moderns. He always questioned the position
that freedom defined the essence of human beings. Are we free to
make our own values? If so, whose values are to determine how we
should be governed? Is there an eternal order which defines and limits
us, as Plato believed, or is it our destiny to make ourselves and our
world? Is there any truth that it is incumbent upon us to know, or is
truth simply a means of dominating the world as an extension of our
limitless freedom?
Introduction 9
him soon after he had received his DPhil from Oxford in 1950. He was
invited to contribute a research essay on the state of philosophy in
English-speaking Canada to the Massey royal commission on arts and
letters (See his article 'Philosophy') At this time Grant was inexperi-
enced in academic politics. His essay offended many influential Cana-
dian philosophers, not least because he wrote about the teaching of
philosophy in Canada with supreme confidence in the justice of his
disapproval of the prevailing approaches. We can see in it a brilliant
statement of a conviction that the next forty years would in no way
invalidate. Nor was this emphasis on the fundamental role of philoso-
phy reserved only for his professional colleagues. In 'What Is Philoso-
phy,' a radio talk which serves as a prologue to this book, the style is
much less academic and, although the talk ends rather as the earlier
report had begun, the approach is gender. In the former essay, the
word God is thrown down like a challenge in the first sentence. Here it
comes as a climax, defining an experience open to us all if we choose
to meditate on the mystery and meaning of human life.
Through the 1950s Grant spoke frequently about the unrecognized
dignity of the teacher's vocation. 'I learned early that there is no more
honourable or skilled profession, nor any more open to temptation in
a society such as ours.' He never refused when schoolteachers invited
him to speak, mainly because of his almost unlimited hope as to what
might be achieved through genuine education. In 'The Paradox of
Democratic Education,' written in 1955, he was able to say about the
activity of thinking: 'It will teach you what is real, it will give you the
vision of God.' He used the words 'real' and 'God' as if they were syn-
onymous. And to him they were. What could either word mean if sepa-
rated? It was to be many years before Grant learned to be more
cautious about the word 'God' and to find alternatives that had more
resonance for his audience. It was already quite acceptable to hear
God called 'the supreme value'; that could mean anything or nothing
at all. But to identify God with reality is quite another matter.
When Grant moved to Ontario in 1960 he realized gradually that he
had much to learn about society's view of education. He had not been
able fully to experience the technological world in the Maritimes; he
hoped to be able to do so in Ontario. His own early hope for progress
had been hard to give up, and his sense that Hegel might be right had
reinforced the confidence with which he had faced the teaching pro-
fession in those years. It is interesting to note that, when in 1969 he
republished an article on religion in the state school system that had
12 Introduction
Sein und Zeit'm the 1950s and taught Heidegger's writings in the 1960s;
but it was not until the 1970s that he realized how brightly Heidegger's
understanding of technology illuminated the modern condition. His
understanding of Heidegger had been aided by his acceptance of the
genius of Heidegger's master, Nietzsche, whose greatness as a philoso-
pher of the modern fell on Grant like a revelation. Only in the 1980s
did he seriously come to terms with the early writings of Jean-Jacques
Rousseau, who clarified for him the historical character of being
human in the contemporary world.
Grant was not without personal ambition (though he considered self-
assertion a vice he had to fight); yet what he really sought was always in
some sense outside himself, and outside even the greatest of his teach-
ers. It was a wonderful joy to learn what Plato believed about the Beau-
tiful Itself; but, as he said to his students, the final reason for studying
Plato is the question of whether or not the Beautiful Itself exists. Reflec-
tion on the thought of Kant was a fascinating intellectual experience,
but what mattered most was that Kant, for all his contradictions, clari-
fied certain aspects of reality in a way no other thinker did.
Since Grant never published traditional scholarly expositions of
Augustine, Plato, or Kant (though he lectured about them in great
detail), it is difficult in this volume to make their importance to his
thought sufficiently explicit. Many highly original lectures exist, but
most are not in publishable form.
Grant's interest in St Augustine is shown here in a radio talk about a
distinguished classics professor, Charles Cochrane. In 1941 Cochrane
published a book, Christianity and Classical Culture, which showed how
Augustine had unified Christianity with the truths of classical philoso-
phy and in so doing had founded the Western Christian church and
the civilization that flowed from it. Grant's reading of Cochrane taught
him how to approach the complex relationship between philosophy
and revealed religion. St Augustine's City of God and De Trinitate were
fruitful texts in teaching, because they raised the most fundamental
and perennial questions, such as the relation of time and history, of
necessity and the good, and freedom and will. Grant found that the
students responded passionately, for example, to Augustine's paradox
that to be able not to sin is a great freedom, but not to be able to sin is
the greatest freedom.
Although he later became convinced, partly by his study of Philip
Sherrard's The Greek East and the Latin West, that Augustine had been
the source of a fatal misunderstanding that has permeated Western
16 Introduction
was that he had himself in his youth come to the conclusion that
Nietzsche was unjustly underrated or ignored by English-speaking phi-
losophers. He devoted his Massey lectures of 1969, Time as History, to
an exposition of Nietzsche's role as the great philosopher of a new
vision of existence. Here he clearly expresses a principle that regulated
all his teaching and writing: it is not useful to reject a philosopher until
one has first attempted to think his thought as clearly and consistently
as possible. Even when expounding a thinker whom one considers a
teacher of evil, it is both wrong and ineffective to try to innoculate stu-
dents by presenting them at the outset with one's own negative conclu-
sions. To do so is to deny that the students are free and rational, and
also to deny the dialectic method, which lay at the heart of Grant's
pedagogy.
Nietzsche so embodies the modern conception of the world that it is
necessary, contrary to Strauss's view, to teach him in careful detail. At
the end of 'Time as History' Grant explains this necessity. Many people
who have never heard of Nietzsche may yet be thinking his thoughts.
'If one listens carefully to the revolt of the noblest young against bour-
geois America, one hears deeper notes in it than were ever sounded by
Marx, and those are above all the notes of Nietzsche.''0 It is important
that these notes be known for what they are. The love of one's fate for
which he calls is not a passive acceptance but a dynamic willing.
According to Nietzsche, the ability to will for the sake of willing is the
very height for human beings. If we can overcome our ressentiment and
our desire for revenge, and claim the earth as our true home, we may
be able to love our fate and to know that we live beyond good and evil.
In Time as History Grant defends his decision to teach Nietzsche to
the young. And in 'Nietzsche and the Ancients' he defends his own
final rejection of Nietzsche. There, he goes so far as to say that this
denial expresses his rejection of the whole modern project. Could it be
that such a rejection on his part necessarily involves a failure to be open
to the whole, a disposition that Grant held to be essential to a philoso-
pher? He answers this question by asserting what he calls in Philosophy
and the Mass Age 'the test of the limitless.' Nietzsche's failure is that he
recognizes no limits beyond which we may not go. No other modern or
ancient philosopher explicitly taught that there are human beings to
whom nothing at all is due. In his constant denial of equality, Nietzsche
does just that. Grant reminds us that Nietzsche's terrifying definition of
what he calls 'justice' should be a warning to us as to what might be
done to some other human beings if we go beyond good and evil.
22 Introduction
The first item in this section, a short review of a study of Francis Bacon,
is interesting for two reasons. Grant wrote it soon after taking his first
teaching appointment at Dalhousie in 1947. It shows how early in his
career he became interested in the questions that would later come to
dominate his thought: the rise of modern science and its impact on
society. However, the review is interesting for another, more personal,
reason. Fulton Anderson, the author of the book, was head of the phi-
losophy department at the University of Toronto and one of the most
powerful academic philosophers in Canada. Anderson was furious
when he read the criticism by a novice philosopher in faraway Halifax
and telephoned Dalhousie's president to demand an apology. Later,
when Grant wrote his article on philosophy for the Massey commis-
sion, he added to the offence he had given in his review, and from that
time on Anderson was implacably hostile.
Grant learned from this experience and began to write more cau-
tiously, or indirectly as he called it. His article on Bertrand Russell
was, as he explained to his mother in a letter, a firm but oblique reply
to Anderson's criticisms of him: 'The real substance of my disagree-
ment with Anderson and Co. is that philosophy is not really a theoreti-
cal subject to be held in the confines of a university but a way of life
that all men must strive for.'17 'Anderson's words were written too
much in anger to answer them. I will answer them in the long years of
writing philosophy. Controversy generally gets beclouded and I have a
Introduction 23
and so identified with the social workers. In his essay 'In Defence of
North America' Grant pointed out that our continent is the dynamic
heart of modernity, the spearhead of technique in the Western world,
and he described the increasing difficulty we experience in our
attempts to think outside it.
In 1966 he encountered the writings of the French social theorist
Jacques Ellul, who in The Technological Society presented the character
of modern technology in disturbing detail, and his review of this vol-
ume was important in extending Ellul's influence among Canadian
critics of technology. Grant now understood much better the apparent
meaninglessness of society. He was particularly moved by Ellul's
account of how technique is self-augmenting and autonomous. 'Tech-
nical progress tends to act, not according to arithmetic, but according
to a geometric progression.'21
For Ellul, technique was still a 'thing,' however dominant it had
become. As Grant pondered the writings of Heidegger, however, he
saw clearly what he had previously only intuited: technology had
become a mode of being, the ontology of the age. Grant developed
these thoughts in a speech he was invited to give to the Royal Society of
Canada. His paper, 'Knowing and Making,' was addressed to the scien-
tists who were the vanguard of technology. He warned them that they
were quite likely to be creating a monster. A new relation had arisen
between the arts and the sciences. Making, or art as it used to be
called, had been transformed by the methods and discoveries of mod-
ern science. The interdependence (Grant called it co-penetration) of
knowing and making had led to important scientific discoveries but at
the same time had made these discoveries quite outside any consider-
ation of human good. They claimed to be value free. The question that
was driving Grant, and that he painfully tried to answer, was how it was
possible even to think about goodness when the language with which
we had invoked it had been taken from us. Biotechnology was a classic
example of the feebleness of the language of good or justice in the
modern world: through it human beings could transform human
nature itself. Where was the standpoint from which we could assess this
change, know that it was good - or evil? In this address to Canada's
most distinguished scientists, Grant's appeal was passionate because it
was inspired by a real and growing fear.
The next selection was written in the 1970s and presented in slightly
different forms to many audiences before being published in 1986 in
Technology and Justice as 'Thinking about Technology.' Unlike 'Know-
26 Introduction
ing and Making,' it was intended to alert the thoughtful public, rather
than specialists. Its relevance in the 1990s is overwhelming. Those who
believed that it was still possible for human beings to control technol-
ogy would issue calming reassurances such as 'the computer does not
impose on us the way it should be used.' Grant reflected on the
thought contained in that sentence. He took it apart almost word for
word, and the result is not easily forgotten. His conclusion is that com-
puters can arise only in a particular type of society, and the fact of their
appearance against this background makes them far from neutral
instruments.
The last piece in this section is the little known 'Justice and Technol-
ogy,' originally published in a large American anthology not readily
available in Canada. (It is reprinted here with corrections and addi-
tions Grant made to the original version.) Grant says that his intention
in this article is to discuss the relation between technology and two
statements about justice: Christ's 'happy are those who are hungry and
thirsty for justice' (Matthew 5:6) and Socrates's dictum that it is better
to suffer injustice than to inflict it (Gorgias 474b).
From some points of view, these two statements would be in per-
fect harmony with technology. Grant always acknowledged that one of
the reasons for technology's triumph was that many people, begin-
ning with Francis Bacon, had believed that control over nature was
necessary in order to fulfil the biblical injunctions to be both good
stewards and good shepherds, to husband the resources of the earth
and make them prosper so that the sheep might be protected and
fed. Many of the achievements of technology did help make human
life better: penicillin healed the sick, the green revolution fed the
poor, labour-saving devices relieved people, especially women, of
much drudgery.
However, in this essay, Grant comes to terms with a terrible ambigu-
ity about technology: it 'came into the world carrying a hope about jus-
tice, [but] has in its realization dimmed the ability to think about
justice.' One may ask: Why is it so important to be able to think about
justice when technology is bringing it about in the world? Who needs
an ontology of justice, or for that matter an ontology of anything? Why
does Grant so often call 'transcendence' a dangerous word?
It is not possible to dismiss such questions. Grant makes it clear that
the most important knowledge is given us in the ordinary occurrences
of daily life, and through the concrete more readily than through
philosophical abstractions. If a word like ontology - the science of
Introduction 27
With the next essay, 'A Platitude,' we return to the subject of tech-
nology. Why was it not put with the other writings on that subject? It is
here because of the lucid note of hope with which it ends. We live in
the dynamo of the technological world all around us. Yet many of us
are aware that we lack certain things that were once considered neces-
sary to a fully human life. How can we be aware of such deprivations
unless we somehow remember the good that we now lack? As Grant
had put it in Lament for a Nation: '"I cannot but remember such things
were / That were most precious to me." In Mozart's great threnody,
the Countess sings of la memoria di quel bene. One cannot argue the
meaninglessness of the world from the facts of evil, because what could
evil deprive us of, if we had not some prior knowledge of good?'24
These intimations are precious and should be treasured, because they
may be the way that the good for human beings, unspeakable in public
terms in the contemporary world, may yet appear to us in the darkness
of our situation. They may even lead us to see the beautiful as the
image, in the world, of the good.
In the article 'Jelte Kuipers - An Appreciation' the Beautiful and the
Good is present in terms of one particular individual. This was a beau-
tiful young man at the height of his potentiality for action and thought.
He married a woman of his own calibre and a few weeks later was killed
in a chance road accident. The distance between the necessary and the
good leaves us, as it often does, with unanswerable questions.
In an early writing Grant had put forward as descriptive of religion,
or of a religious experience, the act of loving someone (or something)
with a love that does not want them to be in the slightest degree differ-
ent from what they are. He ended by asking: 'How do we make the reli-
gious act of not having it otherwise, that somebody we would not have
otherwise - should be mortal?'20
The book review of Torture in Greece might seem out of place here,
rather than in the section on politics and morality. Is it merely para-
doxical to put it under the Beautiful and the Good? No, because Grant
understood clearly that torture is a thing supremely ugly, a thing in
which the Good does not participate in any way. Just as we could not
know what evil is without some idea of the good of which it deprives us,
so our vision of the good may be sharpened by remembering its most
appalling absence. In Philosophy in the Mass Age, Grant related a
thought experiment. Suppose a man had hidden a hydrogen bomb in
NOTES
1 Eugene Forsey, A Life on the Fringe: The Memoirs of Eugene Forsey (Toronto:
Oxford University Press 1990), 32.
2 A narrow local inlet of the ocean.
3 Highest good.
4 George Grant to Murray Tolmie, 29 March 1954, in George Grant Selected Let-
ters, ed. William Christian (Toronto: University of Toronto Press 1996), 185.
5 George Grant personal papers, Halifax, N.S.
6 Louis Greenspan, 'George Grant Remembered,' TaPanta, vol. 6:1.
7 Quoted in William Christian, George Grant: A Biography (Toronto: University
of Toronto Press 1993), 271.
32 Introduction
Robert Oppenheimer (1904-67), director of the Manhattan Project and known as the
father of the atomic bomb.
The Reverend J.W.A. Nicholson, a retired United Church clergyman, who had earned,
in Grant's eyes, a certain cachet because the United Church had once tried him for
heresy.
Prologue: What Is Philosophy? 35
held very simply by some clearly defined religion. If they take that reli-
gion seriously it tells them directly what is important about living. It
gives them such certainty that they feel no need to think deeply about
the meaning of life - that is, to ask philosophic questions. They live in
tradition. And when I speak about religion I do not mean only as
ancient and wise a tradition as Christianity. It is equally true of the great
political religions of the twentieth century. In Soviet Russia, for
instance, there is practically no philosophy, for the religion of commu-
nism provides for many people a simple Sunday school faith which tells
them how to live.
Philosophy is for those who have moved beyond any simple certainty.
It is for those who have come face to face with the mystery of existence
and who have seen how profound a mystery it is. Philosophy is the
attempt to fathom that profundity - that is, to find the wisdom which
will enable us to live as we ought.
Now the sense of mystery arises for people in two ways; first from just
plain wonder at the world around them, and secondly from the
anguish of their own lives. That glorious man Plato - the greatest of all
philosophers - said once that philosophy begins in wonder. We look at
the immense spaces of the night - the worlds beyond worlds beyond
worlds that the astronomers tell us about, and how can we not wonder
what it is all for, where it all came from? We look at human history - at
all the vast numbers of civilizations and billions of people who have
existed, the traces of whom have entirely disappeared from the world -
and we ask what human life is for. Certainly it exists in all children.
When I say to my six-year-old daughter that God made the world, she
looks up in wonder to ask who then made God. When we meet a blind
person my four-year-old son^ asks why did God make some people
blind — or why did God make mosquitos or sharks? Of course, the
tragedy is that we kill that wonder in our children. We fill them with
complacent conventional opinions and tame them to accept unques-
tioningly. We make them adjusted little members of the ant commu-
nity. But still that spontaneous wonder in children is evidence that it is
deeply in all of us. It is just our humanity that we desire to know, and
that desire to know is the very root of philosophy.
Rachel Grant.
William Grant.
36 Prologue: What Is Philosophy?
phers of all time, a Frenchman named Pascal, once expressed this bril-
liantly. He said: 'Man is but a reed, the weakest thing in nature; but a
thinking reed. It does not need the universe to take up arms to crush
him; a vapour, a drop of water is enough to kill him. But, though the
universe should crush him, a man would still be nobler than his
destroyer, because he knows that he is dying, knows that the universe
has got the better of him; the universe knows nothing of this.'
This means that philosophy is something inescapable to being a
man. It is an activity rooted in the very nature of our humanity - not a
pleasant academic exercise reserved for a few professors and students
in a university. The farmer must find himself as much as the teacher;
the businessman as much as the coal miner. It also means that philoso-
phy is something that a man must do for himself. Nobody can make
another man's philosophy for him. Other people can grow our food for
us; other people can make our atom bombs for us; somebody else can
cure us when we are sick - but nobody else can do our thinking for us.
This is the ultimate truth of freedom. A man must do his own believing
as he does his own dying.
This indeed takes me to one of the most commonly heard criticisms
of philosophy - that there is no development in it, as, for instance,
there is in the progressive development of the natural sciences. Sci-
ence, it is said, is always growing in knowledge, philosophy is not. But to
say this is to miss the whole point of philosophy- to fail to see what it is.
It is not concerned with how men manipulate the public objects of the
world - it is concerned with the journey of each individual's mind into
the infinite. Therefore, philosophy must be lived through again and
again in the life of each person. In science we are further ahead than
the ancient Greeks or people at the time of Jesus. But philosophically
our minds are not far ahead of the minds of Socrates or Jesus. Indeed,
even the best of us only begin to touch at the hem of their garments.
We must live through the same thought, the same agony they lived
through, if we are to come to the majesty of their wisdom. That is why
there is no progress in philosophy as there is in science. It is an activity
which each new generation - indeed each new person - must live
through for himself that he may find the ultimate vision for himself.
This, again, is the very truth of freedom.
Another commonly heard criticism, related to this one and based on
by the study of natural science and useful techniques - studies that are
popular because they lead to comfort and power. It is a sad fact but it
must be admitted that we are a continent which has almost entirely
given up the idea of philosophy.
Yet we must never despair for none of us is a slave to our society. The
life of philosophy is open to all of us. And its reward is in truth infinite.
For as we face the mystery of existence and pass in thought beyond a
superficial view of the world, there will come to us, out of the mystery
and the anguish, the certainty which is rooted not in foolishness but in
truth. There will come to us indeed God - not God as he is so often
thought of, as an insurance policy for the next world, or as a comfort-
ing drug - but God in his real and terrible presence. For that is finally
what philosophy is - the practice of the presence of God.
This page intentionally left blank
Parti
Politics and Morality
This page intentionally left blank
THE CHARACTER OF CANADA
Grant's grandfathers, Sir George Parkin and Principal G.M. Grant, were
active in the Imperial Federation movement in the last two decades of the nine-
teenth century; they believed that Canada could not survive as an independent
nation in North American without the counterweight of the British empire.
Between 1943 and 1945, while Grant worked for the Canadian Association for
Adult Education, he prepared two pamphlets exploring Canada's post-war
future in a world, that, looked likely to be dominated by the superpower rivalry of
the United States and the Soviet Union. These excerpts from The Empire: Yes
or No? explore many of the themes that he would develop in his political writ-
ings over the next twenty years, culminating in Lament for a Nation in
1965.
George Grant, The. Empire: Yes or No? (Toronto: Ryerson Press 1945).
Now called the Constitution Act, 1867.
44 Politics and Morality
the faith that not only for the progress of the civilized world, but also
for the existence of our nation as a free and democratic state, our mem-
bership in the Commonwealth is essential. Indeed, our reasons for
remaining in the Commonwealth are not based on colonialism, or
attachment to the past, but on the cold logic of the present. In this year
1945, every interest of Canada demands that we should remain inti-
mately attached to the other British nations.
The first job in seeing our role in the British Commonwealth must be
to look at what is happening in the world today. The first fact of the
world today is that the United Nations have won complete victory over
the forces of the fascist axis. This coalition of United Nations now
comes out of the war as a possible nucleus for future world order. The
gradual and organic development of the United Nations, from a mere
coalition of powers in 1942 towards greater and greater unity, has spo-
ken well for the sagacity of its leaders. In this the atomic age the failure
of world order is too appalling to contemplate.
Imperialism
But though the first and most hopeful fact of the modern world is this
developing new world order, let us not blind ourselves to the fact that
the development of this world order into perfection will not happen
overnight, and that every step of the way will be fraught with dangers
and difficulties. Only if we recognize how difficult the job will be, shall
we be clear enough and tough enough to accomplish it. The creation
of the United Nations will by no means take us over into an ideal world.
Friction between great and small powers will still remain. Self-interest
and self-complacency will continue to beset nations and groups of
nations, as they have beset individual men and nations in the past.
Merely by vaguely inveighing against such words as imperialism and
power politics we will not destroy them. By the very nature of life itself,
power exists. By the very existence of life, it will be necessary to balance
the stresses and strains of that power within the United Nations. Only if
we recognize this will we be able to move forward gradually to the more
perfect world order we desire.
The three great dominating powers of the world after the war will be
three great empires. The two immense continental empires of the
U.S.A. and the U.S.S.R, and the maritime empire of Great Britain.
The Character of Canada 45
There will be other powers. Perhaps in the near future France will
return to its former noble stature, or China and India will become
other great empires. But at the moment there is little doubt that these
three are the mainspring of the United Nations. The U.S.A. will
remain the dominant power in this hemisphere, and in most of the
Pacific. The U.S.S.R. clearly is going to hold and expand its imperial
sway from Central Europe to the Far East. The British Empire and
Commonwealth will continue to encircle the globe. However much
people may inveigh against such imperialism, in this spring of 1945, it
is clearly the emergent pattern.
Those people who wish Canada to retire from the British Common-
wealth and Empire, and thereby greatly weaken that great organiza-
tion, should think of a world in which it did not exist. What would such
a world be like?
The Character of Canada 47
Andre Siegfried (1875-1959), author of The Race Question in Canada (1907) and Le
Canada, Les Deux Races; Problemes politiques conlemporains (1906).
Paul Cohen-Portheim (d. 1932), author of England, the Unknown hie (1935).
48 Politics and Morality
we are not part of the U.S.A. is because we have remained in the British
orbit. The U.S.A. broke its ties with Western Europe. We never did. We
kept our close connection, not alone with the United Kingdom, but
with Europe in general. It is that difference that kept us separate from
the U.S.A. It is that difference that made us a nation. It is that differ-
ence that preserved our individuality. Let us not fool ourselves. The
same factors will continue to operate in our history in the future as they
did in the past. If we have no link with the British Commonwealth we
will soon cease to be a nation and become absorbed in the U.S.A. On
the other hand, within the Commonwealth we will be able to develop
the form of government and social order that we desire.
Those who want to destroy our membership in the British Common-
wealth in the name of a greater Canadian nationhood are fooling
themselves. They are really destroying our nation. Because without that
membership no power on earth can keep us from being absorbed by
the U.S.A. And with that we cease to be a nation.
What Is Canada ?
Of course, in the final analysis this question boils down to what we con-
sider Canada to be. There are now, and have always been in the past,
two distinct versions of this. One is that it is only an unfortunate acci-
dent that we were ever created and that the sooner we join the United
States, the better. The other (and what seems to the present writer a
much nobler version) is the vision of Macdonald, Laurier, and Borden,
that on the northern half of this continent has been created a nation,
raised in a different tradition from the U.S.A. and dedicated to the
extension of certain different political and social concepts.
But what are these concepts? It is always difficult to define such
things in bald and general terms. We Canadians feel them in our daily
lives, and we see them in intimate and immediate ways. We understand
them in particular instances as they affect us, rather than rationalizing
them into generalizations. But now that they are challenged they must
be enunciated. The essential principle around which Canada has been
established is embodied in the age-old struggle in human society as to
how free each individual can be and yet live in an ordered society
where that freedom is not so abused that it infringes on the freedom of
others. Where does freedom for one person to do what he likes mean
The Character of Canada 49
alone (however well these are satisfied,) but on the highest criteria of
political morality. For today in the modern world, with it more than
with any other political institution, lies the hope of Christian man, of
ethical man, of man the reasonable, moral being who stands before
God and history. One can indeed say that ethical man, reasonable man,
is a last remaining fragment of the dark ages, and that the new man is
one ruled by marxian economics or Freudian sex - a man, in fact, who
is brutal and unreasonable, unethical and material, and who is ruth-
lessly dominated by his appetites. Then we can disavow the British
Commonwealth. But if we believe in Christian man, the finest flower of
all that Western civilization has produced, then there can be no doubt
that our chief hope in the survival of such values is in the survival of the
British Commonwealth. Canada has a vital responsibility. Canada must
choose.
MASS SOCIETY
Grant continued to believe in the importance of adult education after he took his
teaching position at Dalhousie. William Grant, his father, had been active in
setting up the annual Couchiching conferences, which brought together business
people, academics, and politicians to discuss important contemporary political
and social issues, and George Grant himself addressed the conference in 1955.
On this occasion as on others, he demonstrated that among his many strengths
as a philosopher was an ability to communicate complicated ideas. A member of
the audience at Couchiching in 1955 recalled his reaction to Grant's talk:
'What I remember particularly was that this speech appeared to challenge many
fundamental theological precepts of the Christian religion — although I felt at
the end of his speech that I had never before listened to such a profoundly reli-
gious man ...It was the first time I had ever listened to anyone who seemed to be
driven by spiritual, almost mystical, imperatives which profoundly affected his
perception of the world around.' (Paul Roddick to William Christian, 25 Febru-
ary 1991).
The whole of one's effort at everything seems extremely 'sub specie atomic
bomb'; any effort must be directed to control of that. The bomb seems to
stand over one like damnation.
- George Grant to Maude Grant, 1945
Mass Society 51
'The Minds of Men in the Atomic Age,' in Texts of Addresses Delivered at the Twenty-Fourth
Annual (^ouchiching (inference (Toronto: Canadian Institute on Public Affairs and the
Canadian Broadcasting Corporation 1955; repr. 1985), 39-45.
52 Politics and Morality
the economy of organized obsolescence and high returns for the sales-
man, the broker, and the engineer, public technical education and
social standardization, mass stimulated sexual life and mass popular
entertainment, this is the world which must find an ever fuller incarna-
tion in Canada. I do not know what forms of the human spirit this new
world will produce - but one thing I do know - no sensible person can
believe that the same kind of people are going to come out of this envi-
ronment as came out of the old Canadian towns and farms.
Now there is no doubt that the mass society is here to stay - unless the
bombs really start falling. Nor have I any doubt about the great good it
has brought. It is obviously good that women should have automatic
washing machines; it is almost as good that we men should have cars.
The fact that machines do our work means we have more free time and
human freedom requires this time. In the old days leisure was some-
thing reserved for the privileged. Now it is open to more and more and
surely what we need for ourselves we must see as necessary for others,
and this possibility of leisure for all does involve the machine. Even
modern medicine, however much of a sacred cow it has become, we
must judge as good. Let anyone who has a child in pain doubt that.
Indeed, at the profoundest level we must welcome the mass scientific
society, despite all its horrors. For it has put us in a new relation to
nature. We can now as never before choose to make our world, to use
nature and abuse her, but less than ever before need we submit to her
as necessity. More and more life becomes an open decision of the spirit.
But let us also be certain what a terrible price is being paid all over
North America for the benefits of the mass society. And what that price
is can easily be stated. Economic expansion through the control of
nature by science has become the chief purpose of our existence. It has
become the goal to which everything else must be subordinated, the
God we worship. Indeed, for the last three hundred years there have
been a band of thinkers telling men to worship the world. Now at last in
North America this has become the dominant religion, which shapes
our society at nearly every point. What is wrong with this religion? The
plain fact that man's real purpose in life is not this. The goal of human
existence is not to be found in the world of nature - but in freedom.
Indeed, to be a man at all and not just an animal who looks like a man
but is not, is to strive to become free. And a free man is a person who is
not ruled by fear or passion - or the world around him - but by the eter-
nal world of truth and goodness which is there to be realized by every
thought and action in our lives. The freest of all men once said: T have
Mass Society 53
overcome the world.' Arid this is what life is for, to overcome the
world, as we live in it deeply.
This is our human destiny, because our environment of nature
depends upon an absolute environment - call it if you will God - and to
live in the presence of that absolute and to judge the world by it is what
it is to be free. I do not mean by this that a free man will turn away from
the world in aloof isolation. After all, the man I have called freest lived
in no ivory tower, but met the world most directly on a cross. What I do
mean is that the free man is he who does not abandon himself to the
mood of his age, who lives at the point where the passing moments of
his life are met by the urgent present of the eternal. Such a man is not
sheer animal or, worse, a machine.
Therefore, the price we have paid for the expanding economy is that
by making it God men turn away from their proper purpose in this life.
There is nothing wrong with automobiles and washing machines, but
they must be known as simply means - means of richness of life for indi-
viduals and society.
But the expanding economy is no longer a means to us - a means for
the liberation of the spirit - it has become an end in itself and as such
is enslaving us. It so sets the tone and pattern of our society that the
standards it imposes close people off from knowing what life is for.
Look at the wives of our executives; look at the young men in the sack
suits who have taken the vow to success; look at the girls in Woolworth's
selling all day till they are exhausted and then being peddled a dream
of heaven from Hollywood and NBC. The boom world creates like an
aura its own standard of success - of what really matters in life — and
that aura lies over everything, choking people with the fear of failure in
terms of those standards, and cuts us off from any truer vision of life.
If you want to see just how much the expanding economy has
become our God read a book called Canada's Tomorrow* It is an
account of a conference in the Westinghouse Company called together
to discuss the future of our country. Leaders of all kinds from business
and labour and government, from the universities and science and
journalism were present. Well, the unanimous report of that confer-
ence was just more and more of the expanding economy - more trade,
more production, more scientific research, more people. Its motto was
the bigger the better; or size is greatness. The book should have been
called The Messiah Machine. There was no attempt to look at what all the
expansion is for or what kind of people are produced by such a world.
It was just taken for granted that the true happiness of persons is always
to be found in short-term economic gain. No questions of quality were
asked; only questions of quantity. No ultimate questions were asked at
all. If this is Canada's tomorrow, count me out of it.
And why I mention this book is that the people at this conference
were the leaders of Canada - the men who are making our society and
whose thoughts about our future are therefore really important. If
these people think this way, this is the kind of Canada we are going to
have. For let's have no soft democratic soap. It is the powerful and the
influential who shape the short-term destiny of a country. If this 'the
bigger-the-better' spirit prevails among these educated leaders, it grad-
ually shapes all of us.
One comic side of this conference Canada's Tomorrow was that
though there was the usual talk about the dangers of communism and
Russia, the kind of society outlined at it doesn't seem very different
from the society the Russian leaders are building for their people. If a
conference of this sort had been called among Russian managers and
university presidents and officials, the pattern of Soviet Tomorrow
would probably have been very much the same - the same quantitative
judgment of success.
Indeed, one of the communist myths which most of our businessmen
and government leaders wholeheartedly accept - though they would
loathe it to be known as a marxist myth - is 'seek ye first the kingdom of
the boom and all shall be added unto you.' What they say is that eco-
nomic development must come first and it will inevitably bring in its
trail the pursuit of truth and beauty. Indeed, the very words 'truth and
beauty' are seldom used now to denote realities, but rather a confused
blend of sentiment and culture. Nice for those who have the time, but
less real than the 'hard facts of life' - 'the business of living.' Just as it
takes a while for the new rich to learn to spend their money with taste,
so it will take time for culture to flower in our new rich society. Like
much marxist theory, this is so much liberal illusion. What should be
perfectly obvious is that if you pursue economic prosperity at the
expense of everything else, what you will get is economic prosperity at
the expense of everything else.
To see our minds in the atomic age, it is particularly necessary to look
at our schools, our universities, and our churches. For the schools, the
Mass Society 55
universities, and the churches are the chief institutions which can lead
men to freedom in the truth. Love and art, thought and prayer are after
all the activities which distinguish men from the other beasts, and it is
the school, the university, and the church upon which we are chiefly
dependent for stimulation of these activities. Our political and eco-
nomic institutions have a function which is largely negative - they exist
to prevent bad things happening: the schools and universities and
churches have the positive role, they exist to stimulate the good.
Now our schools have been going through a terribly difficult period.
When I criticize them I do not mean to lay all the blame on any partic-
ular shoulders. All of us, our ancestors and ourselves, are corporately
involved in the guilt of what our schools have become. The mass dem-
ocratic society has insisted on mass education. This, of course, has been
the only possible and right course. But let us have no doubt that this
process has meant a falling away of quality. What has happened is that
the schools have been trying to carry on their job in a society which by
and large does not think that education is important. What parents in
the mass society are interested in is that their children should be fitted
for success and adjustment, not educated. And what has been particu-
larly sad is that so many educational administrators have not only given
in to that pressure but have accepted the philosophy of worldly success
and adjustment as a true account of what the schools are for. This is
where I agree one hundred percent with Hilda Neatby. The accep-
tance by so many educationalists of the philosophy of John Dewey^ has
in general meant the surrender by the teacher and the school of their
proper function. If you say with Dewey that the intellect is solely a ser-
vant of social living, then you are saying that human beings have no
transcendent purpose beyond society - no need for liberation of the
mind. Indeed, such liberation is now no longer considered even a
respectable goal. How can it be, since it is almost the exact opposite of
the adjustment which the psychologists and the progressive educators
teach us to aspire to? Nowadays, who really minds about prejudices,
illusions, myths, and superstitions as long as they are the right ones, the
Hilda Neatby (1904-75) called for a return to basics in primary school education in her
controversial So Little for the Mind (1953).
John Dewey (1859-1952), American educationalist and philosopher. He was a member
of the pragmatist school, which treated education as a training for problem solving. His
best-known works include The, School and Society (1899) and Experience and Education
(1938).
56 Politics and Morality
socially acceptable ones, the mentally healthy ones, the good Canadian
ones?
What is meant by successful democratic living is conformity to the
lowest common denominator of desire in our society. With such a phi-
losophy the schools exist to pander to that mediocrity of desire rather
than to lead children to know what is truly worth desiring. No wonder
school teaching is a despised and underpaid profession. Teachers are
seen as servants of the desires of the multitude.
To go a step downward, the surrender of the universities to the boom
spirit is overwhelming. I watch it every day of my life. Universities are
now places where young people can insure their entrance into the pros-
perous part of society by learning some technique, and where staff
employees (once known as professors) increase the scope of some
immediately useful technique. Intellect is respected, if at all, as a tool
which can help one to do certain things in the world more efficiently. It
is no longer valued for its relation to its proper object, truth. For there
is no truth which it concerns us to know, there is only the truth with
which we are concerned to do things. Indeed, three powerful forces in
our society, business, government, and the democratic many, all have
used their power to kill the university as a place of truth seeking and
turn it into a successful technological institute. The businessmen who
rule our universities naturally see them as places to perpetuate in the
young the desires of the market place and of competition. Govern-
ments break down the balance of the university by encouraging those
studies useful for defence and prosperity. It would be foolish, for
instance, to blame the government for setting up the National
Research Council - an institution perfectly valid in itself - but let us
face the consequences of its existence for the university and the nation.
It means we are channelling our ablest students into a narrow training
in physical science and this will mean finally a nation which knows
nothing else and believes there is nothing more to know but this. Per-
haps the disappearance of the liberal university was an inevitable
accompaniment of the expanding economy but let us not fool our-
selves as to what this disappearance means to the kind of world that is
coming into existence.
Last and saddest we come to the churches. Let me say immediately
that when I speak of the churches I speak only of my own tradition, the
Protestant. And here we come to the heart of the matter. For what
men believe to be ultimately true is what makes them what they are and
through them their society. And Protestantism is the basic issue
Mass Society 57
An American popular psychologist and author of the best-selling book The Power of Posi-
tive Thinking (New York: Prentice-Hall 1952).
Kitimat in British Columbia was the site of a major aluminum smelter built by Alcan.
In Technology and Justice, Grant describes this as a Spanish proverb. He first mentions it in
his /ournalof 1942. See George, Grant: Selected Letters, ed. William Christian (Toronto: Uni-
versity of Toronto Press 1996), 106.
58 Politics and Morality
In 1960 Grant was invited to join with Michael Oliver, Pierre Trudeau, and
others to help chart the direction of a nezv progressive political party to replace the
Co-operative Commonwealth Federation (CCF), soon to be called the New Demo-
cratic Party (NDP). Together they produced a book, Social Purpose for Can-
ada. Although he was initially drawn to the party because it challenged the
materialism and vulgarity of capitalism, his strong pacifist beliefs forced him to
break with the NDP when it voted to defeat John Diefenbaker's Conservative gov-
ernment in 1962 on the issue of whether to accept nuclear weapons for Canada.
And, while he welcomed a strong alternative to the capitalist parties, he never felt
Equality and the NDP 59
completely comfortable with the NDP since most of its members did not accept his
view that equality had to be grounded in the equality of souls before God.
In the last twenty years we Canadians have achieved the biggest eco-
nomic expansion of our history. We have been able to impose our
dominion over nature so that we can satisfy more human desires than
ever before. We have moved from producing primarily raw materials to
being an industrial society of mass production and mass consumption
such as the United States. Every year a higher percentage of Canadians
lives in the new environment of the mass society. This achievement has
been due partially to special Canadian circumstances - the vigour and
initiative of our people, the rewards from new resources on the northern
frontier of this continent - but even more has it been due to the world-
wide scientific and technological revolution of the twentieth century.
The organizing genius of the American applied the scientific discoveries
of the European with great vigour to the problems of production and so
created the first mass consumption society in history. We now recognize
that this form of society will spread to all parts of the world.
What is even more fundamental about our society than its structure
of 'state capitalist' power is that it is a 'mass society.' The term 'mass
society' is inadequate shorthand for the radically new conditions under
which our highly organized technological society makes us live. These
new conditions are experienced most profoundly in the growing urban
conglomerations such as Toronto and Los Angeles, but nearly all the
people in North America now have a share of them. The farmer listens
to television and drives a car and may even organize his supply of rain;
he may not experience the mass society quite so directly as does a resi-
dent of Toronto, but he still experiences it. What makes this aspect of
modern life more fundamental than the capitalist structure of power is
that this is the condition of life towards which all human beings are
moving, whether their institutions are capitalist or not. Certain prob-
lems produced by these conditions are common to any mass society.
Indeed, even if our capitalist structure disappears in Canada we will still
live in a mass society. It seems imperative, therefore, to try to distin-
George Grant, 'An Ethic of Community,' in Social Purpose for Canada, ed. Michael Oliver
(Toronto: University of Toronto Press 1961), 3-26.
60 Politics and Morality
guish between those problems which are directly a product of our cap-
italist institutions and those which are indigenous to any mass society.
The term 'mass society' is used to summarize a set of conditions and
experiences so new and so different from the past that nobody can
describe them adequately or fathom accurately what is coming to be in
the world. Nevertheless, certain generalizations must be attempted.
This is a society in which high individual acquisition and consumption
of goods and services is increasingly open to most in return for compar-
atively short hours of work and in which an immense variety of com-
modities is ready to attract and to encourage a vast diversity of human
desires. It is a society which requires a high technical competence from
many to keep it operating efficiently and where therefore what is
demanded of most people is to be skilled at one small part of the whole
enterprise but not necessarily knowledgeable about the whole. It is a
society in which most people live within and under the control of mas-
sive organizations (private and governmental), the purposes and direc-
tion of which are quite external to them. The population is more and
more concentrated in the big cities, that is, in environments so com-
plex that they must remain unfathomable to the individual and in
which the individual's encounters with other persons cannot always or
even frequently be with neighbours he knows, but are rather with
strangers who are likely to appear as impersonal units to him. It is only
necessary to compare shopping in a supermarket and in a country
store, or driving to work in a small town and on a metropolitan freeway,
to see the different human relations which arise in this new life.
The result of living in such a society is that individuals experience a
new kind of freedom and independence, and also a new kind of control
and dependence. The freedom is not only that in a high-consumption
economy a multitude of new choices and experiences is open to peo-
ple, but also that in this environment the traditional standards of con-
duct become less operative. The high technical competence required
and the kind of education necessary to produce it takes men to the
point of technical reason where they see themselves as 'wised up' and as
not bound by the old ethical and religious standards. Authorities such
as the family and the church become less powerful so that individuals
are free to make their own standards. At the same time as the mass soci-
ety produces this new sense of freedom, it also produces new imper-
sonal authorities which bind the individual more than before, at the
level both of action and of opinion. In large cities the maintenance of
order in the vast tangle of conflicting egos requires a determined gov-
Equality and the NDP 61
ernment and police force which must inevitably treat the individual
arbitrarily and as a cipher. The individual is also coerced in what he
desires and what he believes to be true by the instruments of mass com-
munication which press on him from every side, presenting forcefully
standards which suit the purposes of big organizations. Indeed, this
control of action and opinion has been intensified by the fact that the
cold war has made North America something of a garrison state.
What is central to this new experience and what distinguishes it from
living in the old small town and rural worlds is that the individual is at
one and the same time more dependent on big institutions and yet less
organically related to them. This has meant inevitably a dying away of
the individual's effective participation in politics. The institutions
which control us are so powerful and so impersonal that individuals
come to believe that there is no point in trying to influence them; one
must rather live with them as they are. The result is that more and more
people think of the state as 'they' rather than as 'we.' In great cities
where so much of existence is public, individuals find their most real
satisfaction in private life because here their freedom is operative,
while in the public sphere they know their actions to have less and less
significance. Thus, the mass society calls into question the possibility of
democratic government, founded as it was on the idea that each citizen
could and should exert his influence on the course of public affairs.
In general it can be said that the mass society gives men a sense of
their own personal freedom while destroying the old orders of life
which mediated meaning to men in simpler environments. Indeed, as
men sense their freedom to make themselves, unhampered by the old
traditions, they may find it difficult to give content and meaning to that
freedom, so that more easily than in the past their lives can reflect a sur-
render to passivity and the pursuit of pleasure as a commodity. When
men have no easily apprehendable law of life given them by tradition,
the danger is that their freedom will be governed by an arbitrary and
external law of mediocrity and violence which will debase their human-
ity rather than fulfil it. This relation between increased freedom and
the lack of well-defined meanings is the essential fact with which any
politics of the mass age must come to grips. The capitalist structure of
our institutions undoubtedly gives this problem its own peculiar tint,
but basically the same problem will be present in all societies, whatever
their economic structure, once they have reached a mature stage of
technological development.
Despite the inadequacies of present economic arrangements, a
62 Politics and Morality
greater cause for criticism of our society can be found in areas which
are not simply economic but extend over the whole range of human
well-being. In these areas it is more difficult to judge what is good and
bad in our society and thus more difficult for socialists to state clearly
and realistically how their goals differ from those now served. This can
be seen as soon as one compares the goals of socialism in a society of
scarcity with its goals in a society of affluence. On what grounds does a
socialist party ask people to vote for it under high-consumption condi-
tions? It is clear, for example, that if there were a major economic catas-
trophe in North America the power of a socialist party would be vasdy
increased. But no sane person desires such a catastrophe. Nor does it
seem likely. What seems likely is that technology will continue to bring
us growing prosperity and that our present institutions, though not
dividing that prosperity fairly, will do a sufficiently adequate job of
management to prevent any widespread or bitter discontent. In such a
society there may not be the goads of hunger to provoke dissent. This
being so, by what criteria of human well-being would the socialist criti-
cize such a society?
It becomes more and more important for socialists to have a pro-
found view of human good as society's most pressing problems become
less simply quantitative and begin to involve qualitative distinctions. If a
child is undernourished, if a family is living in one room, if a man has to
do hard or boring physical work for twelve hours a day, it is easy to see
what is needed for greater well-being: more food, more room, shorter
hours. There is still a multitude of such direct quantitative problems in
Canada and the old socialist ethic of egalitarian material prosperity is
the principle under which they can be solved. Nevertheless, it is clear
that as we move to greater technological mastery (a movement that can
only be stopped by war) the most pressing social questions will call
forth judgments as to which activities realize our full humanity and
which inhibit it. What can be done to make our cities communities in
which the human spirit can flourish? How far can we go in seeing that
in all work, particularly in large factories, construction jobs, and offices,
the dull or even degrading element is cut to a minimum and the cre-
ative responsible part brought to a maximum? How far can we make
the association of experts and power elites sufficiently open for large
numbers of people to take part in those decisions which shape their
lives? How can we stimulate education (in its broadest sense) so that
the new leisure will be more than a new boredom of passive acquies-
cence in pleasures arranged by others? How can we see that in right-
Equality and the NDP 63
its leaders are chosen from those who pursue that self-interest more
ruthlessly.
Indeed, the most dangerous result of state capitalism is that our soci-
ety recruits its chief leadership from the executives who have been most
successful in living out the capitalist ideal. As later essays will show in
more detail, the top executives of the corporations will not only control
our economic life, but also decisively control other institutions of our
society - our political parties, our universities, our churches, our chari-
ties. For example, the leaders of the great corporations are an over-
whelming majority of the members of the governing boards of our
universities. The higher education which they control must therefore
be in the last analysis the kind which their vision of life dictates. Is it
likely that men trained to manage corporations whose chief end is max-
imum profit will be people of wide social vision? Can it be hoped that
they will fully understand the subtle problems that the mass society of
high consumption now faces? Yet at every point where these new prob-
lems are arising the structure of our capitalism gives men with this lim-
ited view the deciding power in dealing with them. It produces a
leadership impotent to take the obvious next step forward in our soci-
ety. And this question of leadership applies not only to domestic issues,
but to the relation of our society to the rest of the world. In 1945 the
business elite in North America had in their hands the unquestioned
leadership of the world. Because of their restricted vision that leader-
ship is now passing more and more away from North America and
more and more into the hands of a tough communist elite. With all its
initial advantages the capitalist leadership could not compete against
the also limited communist ideal, because it could only put up against
it the motives of corporate and personal greed and the impulses for
personal publicity and prestige hunting. It is, of course, not only the
business community in North America which will pay for this failure of
leadership, but all free men who care about the traditions of the West.
Our state capitalism is indeed more than a practical system for pro-
ducing and distributing goods; it is also a system of ideas and ideals
which determines the character of leadership and inculcates a domi-
nating ethic in our democracy. When socialists criticize it, therefore,
they must recognize that they are concerned not only with alternative
governmental techniques in economic affairs but with profound ques-
tions of what constitutes right and wrong for persons and for society.
They are maintaining that not only capitalist arrangements but the very
capitalist ethic is quite unable to come to grips with the problems of the
66 Politics arid Morality
William Lyon Mackenzie King (1874-1949), leader of the Liberal Party, 1919-48, and
prime minister of Canada, 1921-6, 1926-30, 1935-48, had become a symbol to opposi-
tion parties of unprincipled shifts of political position for partisan advantage.
Equality and the NDP 67
lives. The political technicians of the old parties are in a position to say
that they are simply 'honest brokers' and therefore need not think
about issues of ultimate human good; actually their aim, of course, is to
stay in power and work things out within the limits of the present capi-
talist structure. Indeed, they seriously delude themselves in thinking
they are balancing in the name of democracy. What they are really
doing is becoming servants of an ever more powerful corporate capital-
ism and what they call balancing is doling out minor concessions so
that interests other than the capitalist will not make too great a fuss.
Socialists have now the alternative of this amoral theory of politics
because what they are interested in is not simply power within the
present system, but the art of using power to make men free. They can-
not play the role of flatterers to a disappearing democracy, because
they are the friends of a true and continuing democracy. A policy of
drift in matters of theory about ultimate human good (which is the
upshot of moral cynicism) has nothing to offer socialists because it sim-
ply serves to perpetuate the status quo.
The cement which binds together the ethical system of socialism is
the belief in equality. It is the principle which tells us whom we are talk-
ing about when we speak of human well-being. We are not speaking of
some rather than others, or of some more than others - but of each
person. This assumption of equality may seem so commonplace in Can-
ada that it hardly needs discussing as a principle. Is not equality an
assumed article of faith for all true Canadians? Every political orator
must speak of it; even our capitalism must justify itself by calling itself
'people's capitalism.' At a deeper level, is not the central achievement
of modern political theory the enunciation of the principle of equality,
as against the principle of hierarchy which was central to the classical
world? The chief driving force behind the social reforms of the last two
hundred years has been this principle. Is not, then, a discussion of
equality the simple rehashing of a platitude which every decent man
accepts and to which the indecent have to pay lip service?
Yet is this so? As we move into the mass world, how much is the belief
in equality sustained in our thought or practice? It is indubitable that
theoretical criticisms of equality are increasingly prevalent. Is not
equality the enemy of liberty? Will not the striving for equality produce
a dead-level society? Is not the search for equality something we should
eschew economically, as making us unproductive by holding back the
energetic, the responsible, and the intelligent? Has it not produced
mediocrity in our education? Wealthy men with no knowledge of moral
68 Politics and Morality
for equality seems to me the only adequate one, because I cannot see
why one should embark on the immensely difficult social practice of
treating each person as important unless there is something intrinsi-
cally valuable about personality. And what is intrinsically valuable about
all persons except their freedom as moral agents? At the level of effi-
ciency it is surely more convenient to treat some persons as having no
importance, and thus to build a society of inequality in which some
people matter and some do not. If individuals are only accidental con-
glomerations of atoms, why should we respect their rights when it does
not suit our interests or inclinations to do so?
It is clear that marxism, as the dominant Western philosophy in the
East, appeals to the sense of equality. The question is not whether this
is good, but whether within marxist materialism there is any consistent
place for this belief; whether, indeed, one of the reasons why the marx-
ists in power have been so willing to sacrifice persons ruthlessly has not
been that moral personality has no place in their theory. So also in the
West ideals such as 'the survival of the fittest,' when taken over from
biology and used about society, led to an undermining of respect for
the individual. How often has one heard business people justify the
results of the market by such an appeal to Darwin? What must be
insisted upon is that in mass society the practice which sustains the
rights of persons qua persons is very difficult to preserve. It will surely
only be sustained by those who have thought clearly what it is about
human beings which makes them worthy of being treated with respect.
To state this is, of course, in no way to imply that socialists who dis-
agree as to the ultimate justification of equality cannot work together.
Religious believers from various traditions will hold that in the hard
pinches only such belief will make equality a possibility. The non-
religious who are egalitarian may feel this is only superstition and have
some other basis for their belief. But this need not prevent them work-
ing together. For, as the history of Canada manifests, common political
ends can be sought without theoretical agreement.
It may still be argued (and has been) that although we should treat
ourselves and others as of absolute worth, this does not imply equality
in the day-to-day doings of life. A man is as free to save his soul in a slum
as in a mansion, we are sometimes told, and therefore there can be no
argument from this religious account to any particular worldly condi-
tions. The truth of the first part of this statement may be admitted; the
second part, however, must be categorically denied. The justification of
equality must then make this denial. It is based on two facts about
Equality and the NDP 71
does not change the basic fact that the scientific economy of North
America can only be healthy if it is set towards a basic policy of eco-
nomic equality.
Secondly, and more important, the very form of human existence
created by the mass society makes imperative a struggle for equality of
participation in mind; imperative, that is, if we are to escape the civili-
zation of the ant-heap. If it be probable that in the future human
beings grow up in conditions where physical survival does not take
most of their time, what then will give life its meaning and purpose?
What is worth doing when the robots are doing the work in the facto-
ries? In a society of widespread leisure, aimlessness and boredom will
be much more likely than in the past when leisure was the privilege of
the few.
To meet such a situation, our democracy must consciously stimulate
the equality of participation in mind, in ways that it has never dreamed
of in the past. When leisure is open to all, then education must be open
to all. To overcome the impersonality of the mass society, new relation-
ships in work and leisure must be developed and lived out; indeed, new
relationships at every level of existence - in art, in sex, and in religion.
It would be folly, of course, to think that these new experiences will
come easily or inevitably. Human sin is a historical constant, however
much the forms of it may vary from era to era. Under any conditions it
is hard for us to make a success of living. Nevertheless, one thing is cer-
tain. North America is the first continent called to bring human excel-
lence to birth throughout the whole range of the technological society.
At the moment, the survival of its capitalist ethic, more than anything
else, stands in the way of realizing that opportunity. The only basis on
which it could be realized is a clearly defined ethic of community which
understands the dignity of every person and is determined on ways of
fulfilling that dignity in our new conditions.
NOTES
Lament for a Nation was the book that made George Grant famous and imme-
diately established him as one of Canada's leading political thinkers. It is still the
work for which he is best known. In ninety-seven pages he wove together themes of
politics, history, philosophy, and religion. He was driven, he later said, by sheer
anger that Lester Pearson's Liberals had brought down Diefenbaker's govern-
ment so that they could yield to American pressure and bring nuclear arms into
Canada. Although Grant foretold the demise of Canadian independence,
Lament inspired a generation of Canadians of all political beliefs to make one
last nationalist effort to save their country.
I have written a piece called A Lament for a Nation of about 25,000 words. It is,
therefore, too long to publish in a quarterly. I write to know whether there is
any monographic publication in Canada for pieces this length. It would be
better to publish it in Canada than the United States as it is entirely about
Canadian life.
Its content may be such as to exclude it from your press, because it is the
Canadian established classes (particularly the Liberal party) who are consid-
ered most responsible in what I consider Canada's demise. Diefenbaker is
criticized, but not from within liberal assumptions. Neither will it be favourably
received by any socialist as it does not presume the world is getting better and
better. It may be, therefore, that it is just too direct a publication for your
press, but I write to ask.
- George Grant to Frances Halpenny, 25 February 1964
Never has such a torrent of abuse been poured on any Canadian figure
as that during the years from 1960 to 1965. Never have the wealthy and
the clever been so united as they were in the joint attack on Mr John
Diefenbaker. It has made life pleasant for the literate classes to know
John George Diefenbaker (1895-1979), leader of the Conservative Party, 1957-67, and
prime minister of Canada, 1957-63. His government was defeated in 1963 on a parlia-
mentary motion criticizing his defence policy, especially his refusal to accept nuclear
weapons for Canada's armed forces.
George Grant, Lament for a Nation: The Defeat of Canadian Nationalism (Toronto: McClel-
land and Stewart 1965). Used with permission.
Canada and Nationalism 77
Richard Hooker (1554P-1600), British political theorist, author of the Laws of Ecclesiasti-
cal Polity.
Canada and Nationalism 79
ditions of Canada may be allowed to lament what has been lost, even
though they do not know whether or not that loss will lead to some
greater political good. But lamentation falls easily into the vice of self-
pity. To live with courage is a virtue, whatever one may think of the
dominant assumptions of one's age. Multitudes of human beings
through the course of history have had to live when their only political
allegiance was irretrievably lost. What was lost was often something far
nobler than what Canadians have lost. Beyond courage, it is also possi-
ble to live in the ancient faith, which asserts that changes in the world,
even if they be recognized more as a loss than a gain, take place within
an eternal order that is not affected by their taking place. Whatever the
difficulty of philosophy, the religious man has been told that process is
not all. ' Tendebantque manus ripae ulterioris amore.'^
NOTES
Grant was a pacifist during the early stages of the Second World War and he
returned to his pacifism in the 1950s. As American involvement in Vietnam
escalated, so did Grant's outrage and he soon found, himself in active alliance
with fellow academics and students of the New Left. The speech he gave to a
'teach-in' at Varsity Arena at the University of Toronto in 1965 was his most
powerful and effective public presentation. However, it soon became clear that the
students in the New Left disagreed with Grant about tactics. Grant did not
accept the need for civil disobedience in a parliamentary regime that was still
open to reasoned opposition.
84 Politics and Morality
In the November issue, in which you published a speech of mine, you also said,
'In effect, he (G.P. Grant) seems to be suggesting that real change will only
come about within the power structures of society, not over against them.' It
amuses me how such a deduction could be drawn from my words. I certainly
think that real change is going to take place within the power structures, but it
is going to be changed for the worse. I was not saying to the protesting young
that they should not fight the present power structures. To imply that the
present power structures will change for the good is to misjudge completely
their present activity in Vietnam. What seems to be implied in your editorial is
that change for the good (e.g. progress) must happen. This proposition I
would entirely deny.
- George Grant to the editor, Christian Outlook, 29 December 1965
I enclose a draft letter which has been jointly worked out by some students
(members of the Student Union for Peace Action) and myself. It will be the
basis for a presentation to all members of parliament in the week starting Mon-
day, February 28. We are going to have a silent vigil of 48 hours at the beginning
of that week in front of parliament for its presentation. This letter is asking you
whether you would sign this document^ (or something very close to it) and
indeed whether you would take part in that silent vigil. I am going to do both.
The reasons for doing this seem to me something like the following:
(1) For whatever motives, it seems to me that the U.S.A. has got into a position
where it is massacring masses of Vietnamese. Canada is more and more impli-
cated in this, and the thought of us being implicated in a long and growing war
between Asia and North America is too terrible to contemplate. (2) I think it is
important that those of us of the older generation who are Canadian national-
ists should join these young people and show them that there are some older
people in this country who are willing to speak about this matter - and not sim-
ply the older radicals.
- George Grant to Kenneth McNaught, 11 February 1966
George Grant, 'Realism in Political Protest,' Christian Outlook, vol. 21, no.2 (November
1965): 3-6.
A pamphlet.
George Grant, 'A Critique of the New Left,' in Canada and Radical Social Change (Mont-
real: Black Rose 1966).
The Vietnam War 85
start here for the following reason. To speak of the moral responsibility
of the citizen in general is impossible; the question entirely depends on
the kind of regime in which one is a citizen. The United States is a
world empire - the largest to date. Its life at home is controlled by
mammoth corporations, private and public, and through these bureau-
cracies it reaches out to control a large proportion of the globe and
soon beyond the globe. The nineteenth-century idea of the democratic
citizen making the society he inhabits by the vote and the support of
political parties must have less and less meaning. In local matters, the
citizen of an empire can achieve some minor goals. But he cannot
shape the larger institutions or move the centres of power. Democratic
citizenship is not a notion compatible with technological empires. Now
Canada moves more and more to being a satellite of that empire. And
Canadians live much of their lives under the same imperial bureaucra-
cies. The institutions of Toronto are much the same as those of Detroit.
Yet despite this there is a sense in which we still have more citizenship
here than in the U.S.A. because we have some political sovereignty, if
we fight for it. Traditional democratic means - the vote and support for
political parties - have more meaning in our smaller sphere. Political
choice is both more real and more possible in Canada. This might be
truly useful to the world, if we in Canada could use it to see that North
American relations with Asia did not always simply follow Washington.
But to pass to the broader question of what it is to be a citizen in
North America in this era, let me start from the position of the New
Left in North America, that is, the movement which has public signifi-
cance because of what it did in the civil rights struggle. I find myself in
agreement with the account the leaders of this movement give of the
inhumanity of the institutions of North America. When I read Profes-
sor Lynd in Liberation speaking of what the institutions of his society do
to human personality both at home and abroad, I agree with his
account of those institutions. When I hear what Mr Savio in Berkeley or
Mr Drushka' in Toronto write about the inhumanity of our multiversi-
ties, by and large I agree with them. How can a conservative not feel
sympathy with their outrage against the emptiness and dehumaniza-
tion that this society produces?
But when the New Left speaks of overcoming these conditions by
Staughton Lynd, an American anti-war activist who spoke at the 'teach-in' at Varsity
Arena in 1965.
New Left students and anti-war activists.
86 Politics and Morality
to the greater and greater realization of that system. All other societies
move at various speeds to the same kind of society we are creating. We
are the first people who will have to learn what it is to be citizens in a
society dominated by technique. Because that system is most fully real-
ized with us, we are the first people who can look it in the face and we
are called upon to see it for what it is and not fool ourselves about it. We
must face the laws of its necessity - its potential to free men from natu-
ral necessity, its potential for inhumanity and tyranny. We must not
delude ourselves and we must not throw up our hands. We must define
our possible areas of influence with the most careful clarity. Where in
this mammoth system can we use our intelligence and our love to open
up spaces in which human excellence can exist? How can we use the
most effective pressure to see that our empire uses moderation and
restraint in its relations with the rest of the world? I end where I began,
that our greatest obligation as Canadians is to work for a country which
is not simply a satellite of any empire.
NOTE
1 J. Ellul, The Technological Society, trans. John Wilkinson (New York: Knopf
1964).
Although Grant did not believe in civil disobedience in the Canadian context, he
strongly believed in the right and the duty of every person to take a public stand
on important moral issues in the hope of influencing public opinion.
The desire to stop the war in Vietnam should not be limited to people
of any political party or any political philosophy. It should be common
to all men who hate crime and injustice. And as Senator Fulbright' has
George Grant, 'The Vietnam War: The Value of Protest,' an address delivered on 14 May
1966 in Toronto at a demonstration for peace in Vietnam.
American Senator J.W. Fulbright (1905-95) at first supported the Vietnam war; how-
ever, by the beginning of 1966 he had begun to criticize the war and by 1967 was openly
in opposition.
The Vietnam War 91
made clear, it should be common to all North Americans who have the
long-range interests of this continent in their minds.
All decent people, if they look at the facts, must know that what is
being done in Vietnam by President Johnson and his legions is the
waging of an unjust war, by atrocious means. It is war which can only be
won by the terrible means of genocide. What the American govern-
ment is saying to a country, thousands of miles from their shores, is that
Vietnam must do what we want or it will be destroyed. Let us remember
that the bombing of the northern half of the country is not as terrible
as the bombing of the southern half. In the current year twice as many
bombs as were dropped in the whole of the Korean war are going to be
dropped in the southern part of Vietnam - the country the Americans
are supposedly saving. A few months ago I met some American profes-
sors who were in favour of their country's policy, and I asked them what
was their policy for Vietnam and they said 'We are going to pave it.'
That is, rather than let it out of the American grip, they will totally
demolish its civilization.
All the complex problems of international politics - the confronta-
tion of the American and Chinese empires, the meeting of industrial
and non-industrial cultures - do not cloak the central fact about the
Vietnam War, which is this: we of this continent have in the last year
unequivocally embarked on a policy which means the extermination of
masses of the Vietnamese people. It is this which makes this war the
most horrible thing that has happened in the world since the destruc-
tion of the European Jews. It is this fact which requires that all North
Americans of good conscience should protest and protest till this war is
brought to an end. The horrors of the twentieth century have been
manifold; but this must be the worst one for North Americans because
we are doing it.
Canadians cannot escape from their involvement in this crime. Obvi-
ously, most Canadians want to use what independence we have left to
keep ourselves from being any more directly implicated in that war than
we already are. But morally our position is a queer one. In the same
week that our prime minister makes a cautious move towards peace,
Lyndon B.Johnson (1908-73), president of the United States, 1963-9. Johnson suc-
ceeded to the presidency on John F. Kennedy's assassination. Although he was a propo-
nent of an expanded welfare state in his domestic policies, his presidency became
increasingly entangled in the Vietnam War and his unpopular policies eventually forced
him to withdraw from the 1968 presidential campaign.
92 Politics and Morality
W.L. Morse (1900-74) sat in the U.S. Senate from 1945 to 1969, first as a Republican,
then as an Independent, and finally, from 1956, as a Democrat. His opposition to the
Vietnam War brought about his defeat in 1968.
Robert F. Kennedy (1925-68), brother of John F. Kennedy. Attorney general from 1961
to 1964, and a senator from 1965, he was assassinated in 1968 during his campaign for
the presidency.
94 Politics and Morality
protest even if you can't change events. We must keep alive in our soci-
ety the recognition that there is a difference between lies and truth.
Ours is a society where the most enormous pressure can be brought to
hide the truth and to make lies seem like truth. The weight of televi-
sion, press, and radio can be used to convince people that lies are truth.
The liberal society keeps itself going above all by propaganda, by sub-
merging people with propaganda. A society that feeds on propaganda
soon cannot tell the difference between lies and truth. The kind of peo-
ple who get to the top politically in a liberal society are those who have
learned that if it helps their cause to say something they will say it even
if they know it not to be true Nowhere has this been more evident than
in the speeches of Secretary of State Rusk and Vice President Hum-
phrey.^ When one hears some of the things they have been willing to
say about Vietnam, can one believe that they think they are telling the
truth? Perhaps Humphrey is dumb enough and corrupted enough by
his years of liberal rhetoric, but that cannot be the case with Rusk. Let
me take the simplest fact about Vietnam. By the Geneva accords it was
not meant that Vietnam should long be divided into southern and
northern sections. Yet the American officials have continually spoken
as if North and South Vietnam were separate countries and most peo-
ple in North America now believe this.
A society in which the difference between truth and lies disappears is
a society doomed for debasement. Because you can't make even fairly
reasonable decisions if you can't sort out facts from illusions. In private
life this is what we call madness, when people can't distinguish facts
from illusions. And it is just as much madness when it applies to whole
societies as when it applies to individuals. This is what happened in Ger-
many, enough people came to believe illusions about the Jews. This is
one service the protest movement must perform in this society. It must
break through the curtain of lies and half-truths and tell what is really
happening in Vietnam. For we will be truly lost if we bring up our chil-
dren in a society where lies are not called lies.
To finish, the worst thing about Vietnam is the terrible suffering of
the Vietnam peasants; the second worst thing is the lies and perversion
of the truth which is eating away at the soul of our society.
Dean Rusk (1901-89), American secretary of state, 1961-70. Rusk served under presi-
dents Kennedy and Johnson and was a dedicated opponent of communist expansion.
He was closely associated with the American involvement in Vietnam.
Hubert H. Humphrey, Jr (1911-78), vice-president of the United States under Lyndon
Johnson 1965-9. He lost the 1968 presidential election to Richard Nixon.
The United States as a Technological Society 95
Lyndon Johnson ran for presidency of the United States in 1964 on the slogan
'The Great Society,' a domestic program that was to include the Civil Rights Act
of 1965 and Medicare and Medicaid in 1965. However, for Grant, American
domestic achievements paled beside U.S. military actions in Vietnam. In 1967 he
returned to Couchiching to take his warnings about the Vietnam War and what
it implied for the United States to a larger and more mainstream audience than
student radicals.
As a Canadian I have always believed in the use of the national state as a means
of protecting Canadian independence. On the other hand, in the general eco-
nomic situation of North America I dislike the concentration of power that is
taking place in the hands of Washington. I would not have found it impossible
as an American to have voted for Senator Goldwater on domestic, but not on
international issues. I unequivocally would have voted for General Eisenhower^
in both elections. - George Grant to George Hogan, 26 April 1965
Barry Goldwater (1909- ) was the conservative Republican candidate for the presidency
in 1964. He was soundly beaten by Johnson.
Dwight Eisenhower was Republican president of the United States, 1953-61.
George Grant, Comments on the Great Society at the 35th Annual Couchiching Confer-
ence, in Great Societies and Quiet Revolutions, ed. John Irwin (Toronto: Canadian Broad-
casting Corporation 1967). 71-7.
96 Politics and Morality
North America, I must avoid any implication that all the evils of the
international order can be laid at the door of Washington. I do not
intend to minimize the difficulties that any government of the Ameri-
can empire would have in its confrontation with the Soviet and Chinese
empires. It must be recognized, however, that as the Great Society
develops it exercises extreme violence in its relations with the rest of
the world. Look at the growing number of military regimes among the
satellites of the American empire in South America and Africa. Above
all, we cannot disassociate what is happening in Vietnam from the prin-
ciples of the Great Society. That ferocious exercise in imperial violence
must surely be part of our pointing. Mastery extends to every part of the
globe.
Nevertheless, it is not through looking at these particular applica-
tions of principles that we come to a final judgment of these principles.
Not only could the supporters of the Great Society point to certain
good results, which would turn the debate into a simple listing of black
and white, but with more force its supporters could claim that the bad
results of the Great Society are but temporary aberrations or faulty
applications of the principles, and will be overcome at a later stage on
the road of progress. For example, if these supporters of the Great Soci-
ety were marxists (and even Johnson's speeches are often good marx-
ism coated with Billy Graham ) they could say that once the Great
Society frees itself from the anomalies of the old capitalism, it will rid
itself of many of its domestic evils. Again, they might claim that the
impersonality of the big cities will be overcome by the more careful use
of social science. We need more social science to cure the ills which sci-
ence has created. Or, if they are liberals, they could say with the vice-
president that once America is freed from the necessity of standing up
against the aggression of a relentless communist imperialism, it will be
possible for it to enjoy the full glories of the Great Society both domes-
tically and internationally. In short, the argument from results does not
allow us really to get at the principles of the Great Society and to judge
them as they are in themselves.
The true issue in this discussion turns around the first principle of
the Great Society as I enunciated it earlier. That was the claim, that, by
the application of those sciences which lead to the mastery of human
and non-human nature, we will be able eventually to build a society of
Billy Graham (1918-), a charismatic evangelical American clergyman who used radio,
television, and movies to reach a large audience.
98 Politics and Morality
free and equal men. This is the proposition that must be discussed.
Before doing so, let me say two things about it. (1) That proposition
embodies the religion of this society. Religion means what men bow
down to, and the great public religion of this society is the bowing
down to technology. It is never easy to discuss the truth or falsity of a
society's religion when in the midst of that society. (2) This religion,
which is most completely realized in North America but which is com-
ing to be in all parts of the world, has deep roots in the most influential
thought of the West in the last centuries. It is the essence of modern lib-
eralism and that liberalism has been the dominating influence of mod-
ern thought for three or four hundred years. We are living in the era
when the great thoughts of Western liberalism are being actualized.
For these reasons the question I am asking about this idea of technolog-
ical progress and mastery is not whether it is going to survive. Certainly
the mass of men cannot be turned back from the realization by argu-
ment. To debate whether this principle should dominate the future
would be like debating whether water should run downhill. What I am
questioning is whether societies dedicated to this pursuit of technolog-
ical control are going to find it indeed a means to their final end;
whether the application of this principle can in fact result in a Great
Society of free and equal men, a society that promotes human excel-
lence; or whether the nature of the means will not determine an end of
quite another complexion.
We may be born with Downs Syndrome. We find ourselves in a world
where we are the victims of chance, chance which limits the possibility
of our partaking in human excellence. Modern science which issues in
mastery arose above all from the desire to overcome chance. Let me say
here what I mean by human excellence. There are two purposes to
human existence: to live together well in communities and to think.
These two ends are distinct, because thinking is not simply a means for
living together. I will not go into the conflict that often in actuality
arises between these two ends. I mean by human excellence the realiza-
tion in people of the various virtues necessary to the achievement of
these two purposes. It is no accident that the modern experiment
should have arisen in the religious ethos it did, in the sense that mod-
ern science is so closely related to charity. Science was turned from con-
templation to mastery so that by the overcoming of chance the good
life would be made open to all. Yet we should contemplate the ambigu-
ity that in the achievement of that mastery we have built a monolithic
apparatus which becomes ever more tyrannous. Tyranny is, of course,
The United States as a Technological Society 99
the greatest political foe of excellence. It denies both the chief ends of
man - living well together and thinking.
Let me illustrate. To overcome economic chance we have built our
economic system. This leads to the birth of enormous numbers of peo-
ple. The need arises to limit the population, both in what we call
underdeveloped nations in the first stage of industrialization, and also
in highly developed nations. Beyond quantitative proliferation, there
is also the question of quality. Why should we leave to chance (and
indeed as we all know to some very strange chances) the quality of peo-
ple coming into the world. Modern scientific studies mean that sun
and man need no longer generate men haphazardly. But both quanti-
tative and qualitative control must mean enormously powerful institu-
tions to exercise that control. Is a man who has to get a licence to have
children a free man? Of course, what is replied here is that the mod-
ern masters will not control others by force (except when absolutely
necessary) but by the use of social sciences will adjust people so that
they will want the socially useful. It is claimed that it will be possible to
avoid tyranny by the inculcation of the truths of social science through
mass communication. 'This Hour Has Seven Days.' But will not this
central thought control be just as tyrannous as the old methods? If one
believes that the needs of the soul are the most important it will be
more tyrannous. And beyond that the question remains whether
adjustment to socially useful attitudes can be equated with the good-
ness once defined as the cultivation of the virtues. Can living together
well be produced by mass propaganda or can it only be achieved by
free men pursuing virtue through their own motion? Beyond living
well together, the mass stimulation of socially useful attitudes can cer-
tainly not be conducive to the other end of man - thinking. To put the
matter generally: can men live well together within the enormous insti-
tutions necessary to the massive overcoming of chance? To take but
one point: I assume that one aspect of human excellence is to take part
in the major political decisions of one's community. Is this possible
under modern institutions? Professor McLuhan suggests that the new
democratic politics will consist in men learning the facts on an issue
over television, and then regularly, perhaps daily, registering a plebi-
scite on a great computer system. This does not seem to me at all the
same thing as the traditional partaking by free men in political activity.
Who will control the televisions? Who will decide what are the facts?
A satirical Canadian current-affairs television program, which ran from 1964 to 1966.
100 Politics and Morality
Solitary men living in megalopokis, not being able to know their leaders,
pushing computer buttons are not free men, or equal men. To sum
up: the overcoming of chance to which we are committed builds insti-
tutions which more and more negate the freedom and equality for the
sake of which the whole experiment against chance was undertaken.
And the ambiguity goes deeper: the building of the universal and
homogeneous state by mastery was the chief ideal of Western liberal
theory. If the achievement of that end can now more and more be
seen as the achievement of tyranny, then the theory can no longer be
accepted.
I cannot, in a short space, deal with the difficulty in which we are left.
Man has to overcome chance to some degree to form communities at
all; yet the drive for the total overcoming of chance leads to tyrannies.
What degree of the overcoming of chance is necessary for the good
society? The anthropologist Levi-Strauss says that the best order for
man was what we call the neolithic era in which man had gained suffi-
cient control to build organic communities and to give him time to
contemplate. I do not know what the answer is.
Despite my diagnosis of potential tyranny, I am not advocating the
dreaming of anti-social dreams. The immoderation of technique can-
not be met by the immoderation of retreat from society. At all times
and in all places it always matters what we do. Man is by nature a social
being, therefore it is a kind of self-castration to try to opt out of the soci-
ety one is in. There are going to be many wounds to be bound up in our
world. Who cannot admire those young people who work among the
Metis or who work for almost nothing in poverty projects, or who care
for truth in the multiversity? When I read the new journal This Magazine
Is about Schools produced in Toronto by young men who care desper-
ately that education be more than our provincial efficiency nightmare,
and who are willing to forgo the world of acquisition and prestige to
produce such a magazine, I cannot doubt that such things are worth
doing. Just because our fate is to live in a concrete empire - half garri-
son and half marketplace - we cannot opt for that mysticism, LSD or
otherwise, which tries to reach the ultimate joy by bypassing our imme-
diate relations and responsibilities in the world.
Finally I would tentatively suggest that the virtue most necessary for
this era is what I would call openness. This quality is the exact opposite
of control or mastery. Mastery tries to shape the objects and people
around us into a form which suits us. Openness tries to know what
things are in themselves, not to impose our categories upon them.
Openness acts on the assumption that other things and people have
their own goodness in themselves; control believes that the world is
essentially neutral stuff which can only be made good by human effort.
Openness is a virtue most difficult to realize in our era as it requires
daily the enormous discipline of dealing with our own closedness,
aggressions, and neuroses, be they moral, intellectual, or sexual. To be
open in an age of tyrannical control will above all require courage.
Let me say that I think that if you have a highly technological society
it has to be very largely corporate. This is why I have very great sympathy
for what is going on in Quebec.
I would point out that the Great Society is an idea that really grew in
the United States. Let us start in 1932 with Roosevelt. Since 1932 the
United States has become the greatest empire in world history, greater
than Rome. In the last few years, it has been able to upset the govern-
ment of Brazil, the government of the Argentine, been able to upset
governments all over Africa - do you not call that an empire? It seems
to me to be indubitably an empire, although obviously a different kind
of empire from the colonial empires the English and French had. The
Nation magazine calls U.S. action in Vietnam, 'welfare imperialism.'
We surely must face the fact that, as Marx said and as I have observed,
social progress in America has always been impeded by great outbreaks
of nationalism.
On the other hand, a society that is committed to technology is com-
mitted to continual change. This is why other societies like the English
do not commit themselves to technology; they do not want continual
change. In the three religions I know best, Hinduism, Buddhism, and
the Greek religion, the intellectuals turned their backs on technology.
The Greeks were aware there was such a thing as algebra, which is the
basis of technological training, but they literally refused to allow it into
their society. I imagine you would find similar objections from some of
the Buddhists in Vietnam. They are terrified by what is coming, obvi-
ously, terrified of the technological society.
PIERRE TRUDEAU
In the late 1960s the Quebec terrorist organization, the Front de liberation du
Quebec, began to accelerate its campaign for Quebec independence. It kidnapped
a British diplomat and a Quebec cabinet minister in October 1970, and Prime
Minister Pierre Trudeau put the country under martial law. Grant opposed this
assault on civil liberties, which he thought was a manifestation of Trudeau's
technological understanding of the world. His hostility to Trudeau increased
over the years.
distrust of traditional French Canada and I fear his naivety about the nature of
English-speaking society.
- George Grant to Hugh MacLennan, 27 March 1969
As for Trudeau, he incites me to rage. It is very good that now all the provinces,
except Ontario, know that he is trying to destroy their autonomy as societies.
- George Grant to Gaston Laurion, 19 March 1981
George Grant, 'Nationalism and Rationality,' Canadian Forum, January 1971, 336-7.
104 Politics and Morality
The Montreal world's fair of 1967 coincided with Canada's centenary and was the focus
of the year's celebrations.
Daniel Johnson was the Union Nationale premier of Quebec, 1966-8, and a strong
defender of Quebec's powers against federal encroachment.
Charles De Gaulle (1890-1970), president of France, 1958-69.
106 Politics and Morality
Grant was invited to deliver the 1974 Wood lectures at Mount Allison Univer-
sity in Sackville, New Brunswick. Over tfie next three years he revised the manu-
Rene Levesque (1922-87), a former Quebec Liberal cabinet minister who formed the
Parti Quebecois in 1968 and led it to successive election victories in 1976 and 1980.
108 Politics and Morality
script for publication and the result, English-Speaking Justice, was his most
sustained piece of political and philosophical analysis to date. He brought
together what he saw as the decay of liberalism in the United States with his
increasing concern for the right to life. The event that stimulated this analysis
was the American Supreme Court decision Roe v. Wade (1973), which virtu-
ally legalized abortion on demand. Grant was particularly worried by Mr Justice
Blackmun 's decision, which denied any legal status to the foetus. From this time
on, the right-to-life movement was one of Grant's hading concerns and the right
to life was one of the shibboleths of his politics.
I would like to write-out at the moment the reasons why the 'contractualism'
which lies at the basis of English-speaking liberal moral philosophy seems to
me a failure and why one must try and understand morality as natural rather
than contractual. This would be a general lecture but it would centre around a
book which is very influential in the English-speaking world at the moment.
The book is called A Theory of Justice by ]o\\n Rawls - professor of philosophy at
Harvard. It is a brilliant attempt to talk of moral philosophy within the analyti-
cal tradition. I would like to take this book as a starting point and move out to
talk about what was good and what was inadequate in the tradition of English-
speaking liberalism. Would this be an appropriate lecture?
- George Grant to Alex Colville, 24 May 1973
George Grant, English-Speaking Justice, the Josiah Wood Lectures, 1974 (Sackville, N.B.:
Mount Allison University 1974; repr. 1985 by House of Anansi and University of Notre
Dame Press with an 'Introduction' that states: 'The text is essentially the same as the
Mount Allison edition, except for the expansion of certain citations in the footnotes').
Excerpt. Used with permission.
In Roe v. Wade (1973), the American Supreme Court ruled by a 7-2 majority that women
have a constitutional right to abortion and that the foetus is not a person within the
meaning of the American constitution.
Justice and the Right to Life 109
Harry A. Blackmun (1908- ), appointed by Richard Nixon to the Supreme Court of the
United States in 1970. He wrote the majority opinion in Roe v. Wade.
0liver Wendell Holmes }r (1841-1935), one of the great American Supreme Court jus-
tices whom Grant had much admired in his vouth.
110 Politics and Morality
Mnrbfth.Act 1, Sc. 7.
The Greek words for knowing and making, from which our word technology derives.
112 Politics and Morality
Christians. (Of the last name it is perhaps better to apply the not so dif-
ferent label - secularized Jew.) The reason why an academic such as
Professor Rawls has been singled out for attention in this writing is as
an example of how late that civilizational contradiction has survived in
the sheltered intellectual life of the English-speaking peoples.
Indeed, the appropriateness of calling modern contractualism
'secularized Christianity' may be seen in the difference between mod-
ern contractualism and the conventionalism of the ancient world.
Although the dominant tradition of the ancient world was that justice
belonged to the order of things, there was a continuing minority report
that justice was simply a man-made convention. But what so startlingly
distinguishes this ancient conventionalism from our contractualism is
that those who advocated it most clearly also taught that the highest life
required retirement from politics. According to Lucretius, the wise
man knows that the best life is one of isolation from the dynamism of
public life. The dominant contractualist teachers of the modern world
have advocated an intense concern with political action. We are called
to the supremacy of the practical life in which we must struggle to estab-
lish the just contract of equality. When one asks what had been the
chief new public intellectual influence between ancient and modern
philosophy, the answer must be Western Christianity, with it insistence
on the primacy of charity and its implications for equality. Modern con-
tractualism's determined political activism relates it to its seedbed in
Western Christianity. Here again one comes upon that undefined pri-
mal affirmation which has been spoken of as concerned with 'will,' and
which is prior both to technological science and to revolution.
This public contradiction was not first brought into the light of day
in the English-speaking world. It was exposed in the writings of
Nietzsche. The Germans had received modern ways and thought later
than the French or the English and therefore in a form more explicitly
divided from the traditional thought. In their philosophy these mod-
ern assumptions are most uncompromisingly brought into the light of
day. Nietzsche's writings may be singled out as a Rubicon, because
more than a hundred years ago he laid down with incomparable lucid-
ity that which is now publicly open: what is given about the whole in
technological science cannot be thought together with what is given us
concerning justice and truth, reverence and beauty, from our tradi-
tion. He does not turn his ridicule primarily against what has been
handed to us in Christian revelation and ancient philosophy. What was
given there has simply been killed as given, and all that we need to
114 Politics and Morality
Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spoke Zamthustra Book, I.v., 'Of the Higher Men,' trans. RJ.
Hollingdale (Midddlesex, U.K.: Penguin 1961), 297.
Justice and the Right to Life 115
quick name for this is 'technology.' I mean by that word the endeavour
which summons forth everything (both human and non-human) to
give its reason, and through the summoning forth of those reasons
turns the world into potential raw material, at the disposal of our
'creative' wills. The definition is circular in the sense that what is 'cre-
atively' willed is further expansion of that union of knowing and mak-
ing given in the linguistic union of 'techne' and 'logos.' Similar but
cruder: it has been said that communism and contractual capitalism
are predicates of the subject technology. They are ways in which our
more comprehensive destiny is lived out. But clearly that technological
destiny has its own dynamic conveniences, which easily sweep away our
tradition of justice, if the latter gets in the way. The 'creative' in their
corporations have been told for many generations that justice is only a
convenience. In carrying out the dynamic convenience of technology,
why should they not seek a 'justice' which is congruent with those con-
veniences, and gradually sacrifice the principles of liberty and equality
when they conflict with the greater conveniences? What is it about
other human beings that should stand in the way of such convenience?
The tendency of the majority to get together to insist on a contract
guaranteeing justice to them against the 'creative' strong continues
indeed to have some limiting power. Its power is, however, itself lim-
ited by the fact that the majority of that majority see in the very techno-
logical endeavour the hope for their realization of 'the primary
goods,' and therefore will often not stand up for the traditional justice
when it is inconvenient to that technological endeavour. The majority
of the acquiescent think they need the organizers to provide 'the pri-
mary goods' more than they need justice.
In such a situation, equality in 'primary goods' for a majority in the
heartlands of the empire is likely; but it will be an equality which
excludes liberal justice for those who are inconvenient to the 'cre-
ative.' It will exclude liberal justice from those who are too weak to
enforce contracts - the imprisoned, the mentally unstable, the
unborn, the aged, the defeated, and sometimes even the morally
unconforming. The price for large-scale equality under the direction
of the 'creative' will be injustice for the very weak. It will be a kind of
massive 'equality' in 'primary goods,' outside a concern for justice. As
Huey Long put it: 'When fascism comes to America, it will come in
*
H.P. Long (1893-1935), Louisiana governor and U.S. senator, who in 1934 seized almost
dictatorial powers in his home state. He was assassinated the next year.
118 Politics and Morality
NOTES
1 To put the matter politically: the early public atheism of Europe generally
came from 'the left.' Its adherents attacked the traditional religion while
taking for granted almost unconsciously that 'the right' would continue to
live with its religious allegiances. 'The left' could attack religion partially
because it relied on 'the right' having some restraint because of its religion.
Philosophers cannot be subsumed under their political effects, but with
Nietzsche the atheism of 'the right' enters the Western scene. One defini-
tion of national socialism is a strange union of the atheism of'the right' and
of the left.'
2 It is well to remember that the greatest contemporary philosopher, Heideg-
ger, published in 1953 An Introduction to Metaphysics in which he wrote of
National Socialism: 'The inner truth and greatness of this movement
(namely the encounter between global technology and modern man).' One
theoretical part of that encounter was the development of a new jurispru-
dence, which explicitly distinguished itself from our jurisprudence of rights,
because the latter belonged to an era of plutocratic democracy which
122 Politics and Morality
In 1976 Rene Levesque led his separatist Parti Quebecois to power in the Quebec
provincial election, a victory that represented the greatest threat yet to the sur-
vival of the Canadian state. Grant often spoke out publicly in the next few years
in an attempt to moderate English-speaking Canadians' response to the hopes
and fears of their French-speaking compatriots.
I saw a map (Europe &) the world from the U.S.A. - black for fascism, white for
democracy. Quebec was grey.
- George Grant to Maude Grant, 1937
We drove into Magog through the wonderful township country with the hills
all around. Glorious countryside in the two essentials: it is lived in, fertile &:
with the mark of man's touch and at the same time it is powerful, strong &
wild. Magog was a typical French town, recently industrialized, enjoying its
Sunday. (The townships that used to be 3/4 English, 1/4 French, are now 80%
French.) We had an ice cream cone & then went to the meeting. The platform
was on the steps of the main RC church with microphones planted in the west
windows & the Bourbon fleur-de-lis & cross everywhere & the tricolor draped
around the front of the platform. The priests looked on (six or eight of them
from the upstairs gallery of the presbytery next door). A large crowd spread
around and out into the street - a crowd of both industrial workers & farmers.
A lovely gay French crowd, with its humour and stupidity, its highly respectable
farm women and its tart like industrial ones. Well, first the candidate from
Montreal-Carder spoke, then Choquette for Stanstead - both dull and short.
Then Barre^ ... spoke as you would never hear (or at least rarely hear in
J.-A. Choquette (1905—?), president of the Union catholique des cultivateurs, elected to
the House of Commons in the Stanstead by-election of 9 August 1943 for the Bloc Pop-
ulaire Canadien.
Laurent Barre (1886—1964), farmer and politician, first president of the L'Union
catholique des cultivateurs (1924).
Canada and Quebec 123
English Canada) with humour, wit at first, then gradually bringing it all up to a
climax - far better than we can do. Then, suddenly, in the middle of one of his
rising polemics, a honking of horns £ in an open car - the old man [Henri
Bourassa] arrived. Against all my judgment it was the most moving moment I
have ever had in Canada. The first feeling of being a Canadian since returning
from England. He stepped from the car - the old man helped along by a
young man. HisfineGallic face - white beard - and the crowd - not very
excited up to that - going wild - & wild with a feeling that this was their man Be
they really loved him. He walked down the centre aisle - shaking hands with an
elderly cultivateur here & another one there - and as he reached the platform
they sang (£ mind you everybody sang O Canada, deeply moved). Compared
to the fat King or the pompous Bennett,' this really was a man. He was not only
a leader of a party - who had kept power, to whom power was real. This man
had an idea. A bad idea, a pernicious idea, but at least an idea. He was some-
thing in the realm of morality, not merely a man whose end was office. Woods-
worth+ was the only other Canadian who has ever given me that feeling & these
people believed in him. He represented in some basic way the aristocrat of
'leur pays.'
A young man got up to introduce him. Here was a danger. A young fellow
called Laurendeau, editor of Action Catholique, bitter, Catholic, the real fascist,
evidently the brains behind the Bloc. Far too urban, too smooth, too passionate
without solidity, for the agricultural audience. Obviously deeply moved at the
last meeting of the grand old man of their movement.
Then Bourassa. Again wild cheers. An old man's voice - 'Je viens de la cama-
raderie de vous voir'"' - tired, but what a show - up and down the platform -
gesticulating - and humour. Magnificent entertainment. King being seduced
by the Queen - feeding her cognac, but being duped. ' Je respecte le roi - mais
le roi du Canada - pas le roi d'Angleterre.' The Queen departs bored stiff
with poor old King a real royalist, etc., etc. King is only an expert on farming
with the sheep he has in Parliament, [illegible] wild, great cheers, the biggest of
the afternoon other than Bourassa's arrival. Then 'ce brave Paulliot' - what
scorn. Then back to King. He had a grandfather, I had one - 'Louis Joseph
Papineau' - wild cheers. King has deserted his grandfather. I have remained
loyal to mine. Foreign policy, for years dictated by G.B., 'mais maintenant plus
servant a Washington.'' (Solitary cheers from George Grant.) King going to
London via Washington, to Washington via London, but [pour] le Canada
jamais etc., etc. Then suddenly and very effectively from melodramatic humour
and exaggeration to dramatic seriousness - quietly and with terrific force, 'I
have never lied to my people.' Wild cheers. We must look to our rights - we
must be Canadians etc., etc.
Then, he sits down amid prolonged applause - we left hastily.
I think because this particularly county is 40% English they stressed the
Canadian nationalism rather than the French-Canadian. But what impressed
me most-this was a show - a mixture of festival in honour of the great man and
a circus for entertainment. This was alive, real, vital. Whatever party wants to get
anywhere in Quebec, it seems to me, must put on such a show. Thirdly, where
the CCF were allowed to rent the RC parish hall for their candidate, who is the
RC mayor of Magog, these people had the steps of the church with micro-
phones from inside.
- George Grant to Maude Grant, summer 1943
I simply do not get near what is happening in Canada at the moment. Living
in a vulgar Americanized institution I have some sympathy for nationalism in
Quebec, but the more one watches the new government it seems to want to
just produce further modern vulgarity, but just speaking French. I was in
Montreal for a couple of days after Xmas staying with some priests. They are
rather vague nationalists, but the impression I got above all was that they were
just living their lives (men of between sixty and forty) with little sense of the
continuance of their order when they are gone. At the best one could say that
after the quiet revolution they were reculer pour mieux sauter/ but they
seemed to be reculering for ten years and with little sense of what went
beyond.
- George Grant to Derek Bedson, January 1977
L.J. Papineau (1786-1871) was leader of the 1837 rebellion in Lower Canada against the
British. Mackenzie King's grandfather, William Lyon Mackenzie (1795—1861), led the
rebellion in Upper Canada.
But now more subservient to Washington.
Drawing back in order to jump better.
Canada and Quebec 125
George Grant and Maurice Lamontagne, On National Unity (Cemasco Management for
Constellation Life Assurance Gompany of Canada 1977).
126 Politics and Morality
hearts and minds of Quebec. I don't think you come to sensible con-
tracts from out of such self-delusion.
The first priority for English-speaking Canadians is to think what we
want, and first in that is to think whether we want to be a country in
the northern half of this continent and what we need to do if we want
to continue as such a country.
(Let me say forcibly in parenthesis that I do not think that the only
difficulty here is the business community, for scientists and other aca-
demicians have been just as equivocal in their relation to their country
as have some business people. Universities in English-speaking Canada
have increasingly tried to model themselves on Michigan State or Cal.
Tech. or Yale with little sense of the responsibility to anything unique
this country has to offer.)
I just do not know what the consensus of English-speaking Canadi-
ans will be to this question. Do we care to contract to be a country in
the light of this constitutional crisis?
I do know that if English-speaking Canadians do have enough sense
of wanting to be a country - then we have to get down to reaching a
contract with Quebec in which what both parties need can be put
together.
In that process what will be required above all will be moderation. I
do not mean by moderation - weakness. Moderation is clear firmness.
It is the opposite of intemperance and confrontation.
Let me give you an example of how intemperance fails: The federal
government and its leaders at several TV reported meetings went in for
confrontation with premiers Daniel Johnson and Bertrand of Que-
bec. They made a lot of political capital out of these confrontations
with these moderate nationalists. In November 1976 the sons^ of both
premiers, Johnson and Bertrand, were elected as Parti Quebecois
members. I think that is a lesson about confrontation that needs to
sink it.
Moderation is not only needed from our political leaders - but from
the rest of us. I admire the Globe and Mail, but when its chief corre-
spondent in Quebec heads its lead story with the words: 'Premier
Levesque from his bunker in Quebec City' - my heart sinks. The
CLASSICAL LIBERALISM
It was not easy for me to leave the Canadian academic establishment and it was
not easy to face the intolerance of that establishment - particularly as that
intolerance claimed for itself the name of 'liberalism.' I think the most savage
words ever spoken to me by an older man I had respected were said by W.A.
Mackintosh and I identified his opinions with your own. For an ambitious per-
son such as myself, it is easier to take such remarks today when one is secure
than at the time they were made, when I was without a job. When English-
speaking liberalism seemed to have the world at its feet in the 1950s, it was not
tolerant of anything which lay outside its vision and nowhere was it more intol-
erant than in its academic manifestations.
- George Grant to J.A. Corry, 17 February 1972
George Grant, review of John Stuart Mill: The Collected Works, vols. 18 and 19, ed. J.M. Rob-
son (Toronto: University of Toronto Press). Globe and Mail, 6 August 1977, 31.
L.B. Pearson (1897-1972), deputy minister of external affairs, 1946; secretary of state
for external affairs, 1948-57; winner of the Nobel Peace Prize, 1957; leader of the Lib-
eral Party from 1958 and prime minister from 1963 to 1968.
O.D. Skelton (1878-1941), Queen's political scientist and under-secretary of state for
external affairs from 1925 until his death.
130 Politics and Morality
secular expositor laid before us in such clear and handsome form. Pro-
fessor J.M. Robson is to be congratulated as the chief textual editor of
this collected edition. All the labour of presenting the works efficiently
and accurately has been well done. The volumes have been completely
and pleasantly printed by the U of T Press. They are not expensive,
considering the price of things these days.
It is all too easy for a person of my temperament, thought, and con-
victions to describe J.S. Mill as a figure of high comedy. Through the
decades from 1830 to 1870 he lectured the English people on how they
must improve themselves. This is, of course, a very familiar role for
'intellectuals' in a society with Protestant traditions, and would not
alone make Mill a figure suitable to the talents of Aristophanes or Jane
Austen. Rather, it is that he dons the robes of justice, while at the same
time his account of the whole leaves no reason why anybody should
take seriously an appeal to justice. The mantle of the tireless preacher
is worn without any seeming recognition that if what he is preaching is
taken seriously there is no reason why it is good to be just. Mill is
indeed the very archetype of the secularized Protestant. He wants it
both ways. He is part of the long tradition of English empiricism, and
affirms that pleasant life in space and time is what matters; at the same
time he affirms a call to justice as right, which comes forth from the
very Protestantism which he rejects theoretically. Indeed, in his
attempt to have it both ways, he decently tried to improve the utilitari-
anism of Bentham and his father, in which he had been educated.
In their utilitarianism, happiness meant the sum of pleasures, and
pleasures were to be calculated quantitatively. Although the anointed
successor of this doctrine, Mill cannot quite accept it, because to him
some pleasures are to be encouraged in society, while others discour-
aged. He therefore introduces into his utilitarianism the doctrine of
higher and lower pleasure. But by wanting at the same time both a
teaching about higher and lower pleasures and his empiricism, he
becomes inconsistent. He is too secularist to give up utilitarianism; he
is too Protestant to give up higher pleasures. The comedy is for a phi-
losopher to sacrifice consistency to decency. He continually inveighs
against the reactionary results stemming from the dogmatic religion of
his country (that is, Protestantism), while his intuitive and imaginative
responses are tied to the very religion he inveighs against. The ped-
antry of his expository style combines the exhortations of the pulpit
with the flat substance of secularism, so that he achieves the very diffi-
Classical Liberalism 131
Alexis de Tocqueville (1805-59), a French nobleman and social critic whose Democracy
in America is considered a classic liberal analysis of American society.
132 Politics and Morality
The object of this Essay is to assert one very simple principle, as entitled
to govern absolutely the dealings of society with the individual in the
way of compulsion and control, whether the means used by physical
force in the form of legal penalties, or the moral coercion of public
opinion. That principle is, that the sole end for which mankind are war-
ranted, individually or collectively, in interfering with the liberty of
action of any of their number, is self-protection. That the only purpose
for which power can be rightfully exercised over any member of a civi-
lized community, against his will, is to prevent harm to others.
CONSERVATISM
John Diefenbaker remained in Parliament for sixteen years after his defeat in
1963. In spite of Grant's criticisms of Diefenbaker's administration, Grant was
seen by the media as one ofttiefew Canadians academics who had anything at
all good to say about the former prime minister. When Diefenbaker died, in 1979
Grant was asked to write this brief assessment. He found Diefenbaker pro-
foundly flawed as a politician and statesman, but he still admired the prairie
politician's great political courage.
I have never felt such political loyalty as I feel for Green and Dief. Whatever the
PM lacks, he spoke unequivocally for Canadian independence. When Mac-
millan purred while he was being raped; Dief. fought. And of course Green has
deeply cared for the most important political cause of all - disarmament - and
has been willing to risk the wrath of big business on this issue. Whatever Dief s
failings, he has in the clinch spoken for Canada. All this leads me to loyalty to
the Conservatives.
- George Grant to Derek Bedson, 1962 1
I feel such a debt to the Conservatives for sticking up for Canada's indepen-
dence. Whatever else Dief has done - this has been fine. So many people
around here just talk as if Canadian independence was a romantic notion from
the past.
- George Grant to Derek Bedson, 1 October 1963
134 Politics and Morality
George Grant, 'Diefenbaker: A Democrat in Theory and in Soul,' Globe and Mail,
23 August 1979, 7.
Conservatism 135
and inarticulate people and persuaded them that he was on their side.
What was surprising to political analysts was that he did this as leader
of the Conservatives when socialists were not able to achieve that iden-
tification. He did this despite the formality of his dress and manners in
public. He still wore Homburg hats and elegantly formal suits. I sup-
pose he did it finally because he really did care for all kinds of people
in their authentic individuality. The excluded and the inarticulate rec-
ognized this and responded. He was indeed an honest politician; he
was a democrat not only in theory but in his soul.
Diefenbaker's principles were grounded in primary loyalties, and
loyalty is the great virtue for political leaders. That it is a virtue is often
denied in modern political thinking. Intellectuals are apt to believe
that leaders should have well thought out 'philosophies,' which have
arisen by putting all primary loyalties in question. But this is nonsense
for the following reason. The virtues necessary for the political life are
not altogether the same as those necessary for the contemplative life.
The latter requires that one be open to everything, and this includes
putting everything in question.
In the practical life one is continually faced with making moral deci-
sions, and in doing so one must not put one's fundamental principles
in question, because that only leads to callous opportunism. Diefen-
baker's strength was that his fundamental principles were loyalties
which he did not put in question. He did not debate his beliefs in free-
dom within the law, patriotism, social egalitarianism. He just lived
them out as best he could. People therefore knew where they stood
with him and loved him for it.
In the fast changing world of calculation, 'loyalty' is often consid-
ered outdated and useless for administration. It is therefore becoming
a rare virtue in our society. But people were wise to recognize it in
Diefenbaker and knew they could rely on him.
Diefenbaker's loyalties came straight out of our particular Canadian
tradition. Take his populism as an example. It has been said that Dief-
enbaker was simply a Canadian William Jennings Bryan, with his
appeal to 'the people' against the big interests in the east. But that
misses the distinctly Canadian flavour of Dief's populism. It misses the
fact that he combined his populism with the British tradition of the
primacy and nobility of law.
WJ. Brvan (1860-1925), Democratic presidential candidate in 1896, 1900, and 1908,
Bryan was a populist politician known affectionately as 'The Great Commoner.'
136 Politics and Morality
In the opening of the west, individuals went first in the United States
and made their own law. In Canada, the federal Government went
before the immigrants, and the immigrants inherited a tradition of
law. Diefenbaker was part of our tradition. He advocated populism, he
believed in the rights of individuals, but always within the primacy of
law. This was why he gave such strong loyalty to the crown and to Par-
liament. Like Macdonald he did not see our democracy as a pale imita-
tor of the American, but as something richer, because it understood
better the dependence of freedom upon law.
Diefenbaker's nationalism was not ideological; he just took it for
granted. It was something given -just as parents are given, both for
good and for ill. Because it was not something he constructed as he
went along, it had real bite. After all, the nuclear arms crisis of 1963
was the first time since 1935 that a Canadian government really
offended the Government of the United States so that it directly
entered Canadian politics. (The next time could be if a Canadian gov-
ernment were to find itself forced over energy.)
But Diefenbaker was speaking honestly when he said T am pro-
Canadian, not anti-American.' He was much too aware of what a dan-
gerous and complex world it is to be ideologically anti-American. He
was much too rooted in everyday life, in Prince Albert and Ottawa, not
to belong to the continent we share with the Americans. He just
assumed that Canada is our own, and that the United States is not. He
assumed that if we have any pride in our own we must be in some sense
sovereign.
When John F. Kennedy told Diefenbaker in Ottawa that Canada
could not sell wheat to China - and he meant 'could not' quite
literally - Diefenbaker replied: 'You aren't in Massachusetts now Mr
President.' He was expressing that Canadians must take for granted
their sovereignty or else have no pride. This was of course a much
less worldly-wise assumption than Pearson's recognition that we are
finally part of the American empire. Nevertheless, it is a necessary
basis if we mean anything more than rhetoric about Canada being our
country.
Because Diefenbaker's nationalism was a given loyalty, it often
showed inadequacies when he tried to express it in office. He was not
able to formulate feasible policies necessary to that nationalism in a
technological era. But to be fair to him: Who since his day has been
able to formulate such feasible policies? Even the wisest patriot of this
Conservatism 137
era, de Gaulle, was not able to prevent France from being integrated
into the homogenized modern culture.
The great criticism of Diefenbaker was always that he was 'out of
date.' In his last years when he had become a respected elder states-
man, no longer to be feared, this criticism became a kind of patroniz-
ing of him as a fine old dear who was really irrelevant. I always found it
unpleasant that Trudeau used to patronize him from this superior
standpoint.
But what does 'out of date' mean? It is the language of those who
think that our humanity can be made totally intelligible in terms of
such concepts as 'progress,' 'history,' 'evolution.' What such words
generally come down to in practice is that anything that is technologi-
cally and administratively necessary is also good. This expresses that
oblivion of eternity which now defines the West.
But Diefenbaker's loyalties were not defined within such a context
of calculation. Indeed, it is not surprising that his greatest political
humiliation should have been arranged by a public relations executive
- the very type of job which incarnates the absoluteness of calculation.
This is why Diefenbaker was so loved by many of my generation -
particularly by those of us less clever and less successful. Despite all his
bombast, all his egocentricity, all the wild failures of his judgment,
one sensed in him a hold on certain principles which cannot be 'out
of date' because their truth does not depend upon dates. Despite his
almost juvenile engrossment in the day to day excitement of the politi-
cal scene, one sensed some deep hold on certain good things that do
not change. About such good things there has to be calculation, but
their essence is beyond all bargaining. It is to be hoped that the politi-
cal scene will continue to allow such men to be produced.
The cadence of Milton's poetry is not the greatest in the English lan-
guage, but it is very good. It can catch the rhetoric, the tensions and
the nobilities of the battling Baptist lawyer from the prairies.
Not everybody is false in the modern world, but there are great
pressures on all of us in that direction. At the political level Diefen-
baker was always a lesson. Whatever else he may have been, he was not
false.
138 Politics and Morality
BRITISH CONSERVATISM
Sir John A. Macdonald had built Canada, in Grant's view, under the inspira-
tion of the conservatism of Benjamin Disraeli, the great mid-Victorian British
Conservative prime minister. Disraeli's Conservative Party stood for modera-
tion, fairness, and good, sense, and these were the virtues, as Grant had
explained in The Empire: Yes or No? that distinguished Canada from the
United States. Yet, however admirable Disraeli's conservatism may have been,
Grant thought that it lacked the strength to withstand the new combination of
liberalism and technology that was becoming the sole public value.
Gladstone & Disraeli were titans, absolute titans. I started with a great bias for
Gladstone, but now I have absolutely no idea whom I prefer. I read four of Dis-
raeli's novels and one of his political writings; the great life (abridged slightly)
by Monypenny & Buckle. I think for a while Disraeli was the great Victorian
statesman and Gladstone the highly limited and bigoted politician. Then I read
something about Gladstone and I say he was the colossus, he was the great
statesman who dominated England with supreme greatness; then I think Dis-
raeli was a crafty opportunist politician. What giants they were. Colossuses. I
practically burst into tears when I read the story of Bismarck at the Congress of
Berlin in 1878 and he turned to someone and said, 'Der alte Jude, der ist der
Mann.'t A superb story.
But then the polemic of Gladstone on ideals and Armenian massacres. Ideals
rather than necessity and selfishness in foreign policy. Ireland and his con-
science. Power and the Midlothian campaign.
Then Disraeli laughs (oh so humanly) at the utilitarians who tried to form
society around a formula, a principle. Philanthropic Disraeli.
- George Grant to Maude Grant, spring 1938
plete as seems possible, and then laying the letters before the reader
with all the aids of scholarly clarity so that they are a delight to read.
The University of Toronto Press has produced beautiful books at a rea-
sonable price for these expensive days. This is scholarship at its best.
When one thinks that these two volumes only take Disraeli up to his
entrance into Parliament in 1837, and that the great man goes on until
1881, what a treat awaits us. These volumes are not only useful for peo-
ple who want to study the nineteenth-century European world profes-
sionally, they will be a delight for anybody who wants to contemplate
the life of a great political leader.
Politics is, as Plato showed, the royal art. In the golden afternoon of
England's authority as the first of the industrialized nations, she was
fortunate to have such outstanding practitioners of that art as William
Gladstone and Benjamin Disraeli. When one compares their level of
education and character with that of the people who run our societies
today (Canada included), one may have a word to say for aristocracy as
against the undiluted triumph of capitalist democracy. For my part, I
put Gladstone slightly higher because he had the perspicacity to try to
limit English imperialism at the height of its power.
But Disraeli was also a splendid politician. Even more than Peel, he
was the founder of the modern Tory Party, and through all the cata-
clysms and aberrations of the modern era, that party more often than
not has stood for good sense. That is a lot to say of any institution. To
take a small influence: one cannot understand the conservatism of
Canada (Macdonald, Whitney, Borden, Ferguson, Bennett, Diefen-
baker) without thinking of Disraeli. This may be a tradition that has
decayed in Canada before the ravages of capitalist liberalism, but it was
a great part of this country. Another Canadian connection in these vol-
umes is that there is a nasty picture of Lord Durham, whose report did
much harm in Canada by failing to recognize the French for what they
were. These two volumes only take us through the early years, culmi-
nating in the disappointment of the unfair failure of his maiden
speech in Parliament. A sweet letter from his school in Blackheath is
followed by accounts to his sister of trips around Europe and the
Levant. These are followed by letters in which he tries to establish him-
self in the literary and political scene of the New World that is coming
forth after the Reform Act of 1832. He has difficulties with his publish-
ers, he has continued failures at the polls, but he never flags in his
determination to establish himself in the ruling class. Why shouldn't
he? Neurotic ambition can be a corrupting vice, but Disraeli's ambi-
140 Politics and Morality
don seems singularly free of the neurotic. He just wants to get on and
achieve what he knows himself capable of, in a country which he thor-
oughly likes. Compared to Gladstone again, he does not start with an
established position. He has to make his place in the world and he
does so in a direct and healthy way.
What comes forth from these letters is a very worldly human being.
By worldly, I do not mean a non-religious man. He seems to take reli-
gion for granted, as something quite given in the nature of things and
to be properly respected. What I mean is that he likes the riches of
experience. This comes out in his long letters from abroad. He
describes what he has been doing and seeing with external gusto -
often in a way that may bore us moderns who are more used to subjec-
tive analysis. But this love of the surface and of the immediate is the
mark of his health. Many successful politicians are often neurotic inso-
far as they pursue power to assuage their subjectivity, but the best poli-
ticians are those who like the world. One trusts Disraeli because his
shrewd and interested acceptance means that he is not a hater. It
seems natural that he should be the fellow countryman and near con-
temporary of the delightful and insightful Jane Austen.
One particular mark of his health is how much Disraeli loved
women. I do not mean by this that he was in pursuit of the continual
Giovannian orgasm which in our age is often implied when one says
that somebody loves women; such pursuit is for much less sane human
beings than Disraeli. What I mean is that he writes to all kinds of
women with a delicious interest in their doings and his own. Some of
the best letters in the first of these volumes are to his sister Sarah (he
addresses her sweetly as Sa), and there is a halcyon quality about their
obvious mutual affection. Clearly from the later letters, he used his aris-
tocratic mistress Lady Sykes to advance his career, but there is no sign
that there was anything particularly nasty in this. It is often said that Dis-
raeli manipulated Queen Victoria for his own purposes. We will obvi-
ously have to wait for the later letters to see whether this was the case.
But from these letters, I doubt whether manipulation is the right
word. Interest in and understanding of other people is the basis of inti-
macy. Disraeli had interest and understanding for many ladies, from
his grandmother to his sister and a wide variety of intelligent and aris-
tocratic women. To take that as manipulation is to miss the point that
he had empathy for their worlds. To state the obvious: it is surprising
to consider how few human beings really like the members of the
opposite sex.
Liberalism and Tyranny 141
When the Canadian Supreme Court struck down Canada's law governing abor-
tion, Grant concluded that another step had been taken in the decay of the lib-
eral tradition of justice. He began increasingly to fear that the universal and
homogeneous state was approaching more quickly than he had previously
thought. Normally he was an advocate of moderation in politics, but in this
selection Grant's anger flames forth as he compares the philosophical basis for
the pro-choice movement to the essential element that drove the Nazis. However,
there is little doubt that Grant genuinely believed that the coming technological
state would be a tyranny.
We have just had a Supreme Court decision here on abortion. The majority
was, if possible, worse than Roe v. Wade but luckily we've a health care system
where the money comes from the federal government but where administra-
tion is in the hands of the province. Some of the provinces have refused to
142 Politics and Morality
allow their hospitals to finance non-medical abortions. But you can imagine
how the press is attacking them as 'rednecks' etc., etc. What is so extraordinary
about our politics is that some of the left-wing politicians who speak most often
about rights are just those who speak most loudly in favour of abortion on
demand.
- George Grant to David Bovenizer, 6 March 1988
George Grant, 'The Triumph of the Will,' in The Issue Is Life: A Christian Response to Abor-
tion in Canada, ed. Denyse O'Leary (Burlington, Ont.: Welsh Publishing, 1988).
Liberalism and Tyranny 143
Bertha Wilson (1923- ),justice of the Supreme Court of Canada from 1982 to 1995.
Leni Riefenstahl (1902- ), German actress and filmmaker who became notorious for
her Nazi propaganda films, especially The Triumph of the Will (1934), one of the most
powerful propaganda films ever made.
Liberalism and Tyranny 145
Of course, ever since patriarchal society began all women have had
to face the fact that the enjoyment of sexuality left them with the pro-
digious possibility of pregnancy, while men could go forth free from
that enjoyment. Perhaps this was even resented by some women in
matriarchal times, in which the whole society turned on the recogni-
tion of birth as central. (We just do not have the records of matriarchal
society and its overthrowing.) In earlier patriarchal societies, religious
control had some effect sometimes, in forcing men to assume some
responsibility for pregnancy. Where land was the essential cause of
wealth, owner families had a very great interest in forcing men to bear
responsibility.
In modern technological society, most bourgeois women, and those
who wish to become bourgeois, find themselves in a position where at
one and the same time the emancipation of sexual desire is advocated
from the earliest age, and yet where, if they are to be anything socially,
they must go out to work in the world where what matters is the eman-
cipation of greed. This is achieved under corporate capitalism through
mastery over oneself and other people. How can such modern women
put up with unexpected pregnancies (whether within marriage or
without) which can demolish their place in the corporate market and
push back their ambitions in relation to the ambitions of other people
at the same level? Abortion on demand, then, appears a necessity
under the conditions of corporation capitalism, as it presumably also
does under corporation communism. Indeed, women's position as
potential mothers becomes particularly pressing in all advanced indus-
trial societies, because their skilled or unskilled labour, their low or
high ambitions are wanted in the marketplace. This happens at a time
when the overcoming of the unfairness of their sexual position seems
at last possible.
It is no wonder, then, that the leaders of the women's movement
take on the language of the triumph of the will when they are seeking
to get the state to fulfil their purposes, and when they are opposed by
those who must be against abortion on demand for the clearest rea-
sons. The ambiguity is that the famous feminist phrase 'biology is not
destiny' must be true for all Christians, because we have been told that
in Christ there is neither male nor female. At the highest reaches of
human life and love, gender is simply unimportant. The question is, at
what levels of life and love is gender important, and how should that
difference manifest itself?
It is not that the women's leaders say that to be truly free, women
Liberalism and Tyranny 147
must get rid of their gender. They do not seem to want to build an
entirely androgynous society. It seems rather that, in their desire for
liberation, they want not only to keep their gender, but also to use it as
they will. But their ability to use their gender, and not to be controlled
by it, requires their life and death control over beings other than
themselves. For the 'given' which their wills need to control is those
individual members of their own species within their bodies. 'Other-
ness' which must be dominated has always been that thing in terms of
which the language of the triumph of the will arises. In this case, the
need for liberation arises not against the absence of the vote, or ine-
quality in the marketplace, but against developing infants. This is the
terrible pain which leads certain women to the language of the tri-
umph of the will. They feel trapped by their gender but the means of
liberating themselves from this entrapment must often include killing.
The language of the triumph of the will is a means of escaping from
that trap, because it frees one from the traditional restraints against
killing.
What is saddest for the modern future is that belief in the triumph
of the will seems to bring with it an intensity of propaganda in which
the general public is prepared for the killing which is to ensue. For a
decade the National Socialists had been saving that the Jews were not
truly human, that they were parasites living off the healthy society. It
hardly needs saying that the Jews are as truly human as the rest of us.
Nevertheless, the fact that the opposite was a lie did not prevent its dis-
semination and influence. Those who disseminated it believed it. The
most effective dissemination of lies is by those who believe them. So in
the coming of mass abortion in our society untruths have been spread
by those who do not know they are untruths. Current scientific knowl-
edge tells us that a separate human life is present from conception,
with its own unique genetic pattern, with all the chromosomes and
genes which make it human. It is of the very heart of fascism to think
that what matters is not what is true, but what one holds to be true.
What one holds to be true is important because it can produce that
resolute will tuned to its own triumph.
However, it must be said that where the clarity about truth which
belongs to modern science has allowed us to know what the fetus is in
a matter-of-fact way, more difficult implications arise when modern sci-
ence is used as if it provided the whole truth about life. This has some-
times led to a belittling of human life and to the arising of the doctrine
of the triumph of the will. All this has often been denied or refused by
148 Politics and Morality
To say all this is not to imply that North American society is yet close
to fascism as a form of government. There are many influences in our
society which hold us back from that. Obviously, all sane people hope
that these influences will continue to prevail. What I am implying is
that these influences are fragile in the face of the doctrine of the tri-
umph of the will. Nor am I saying that North American fascism would
be, in outward appearance, much like the National Socialism of
Europe. The trappings of romanticism in North American fascism
would be quite different from the trappings of German romanticism.
It is interesting that, alone among Western countries, West Germany
has a law which gives the fetus a legal right to life, with some condi-
tions. The Constitutional Court says that this is to make plain the Ger-
man historical experience and 'the present spiritual-moral confron-
tation with the previous system of National Socialism.' In 1988 West
Germany has forbidden surrogate motherhood and the production of
human embryos for research. The Germans have the great advantage
over us of already having faced the political incarnation of the triumph
of the will.
I am, however, saying two things: The triumph of the will as an indi-
vidual view of life passes over into politics, and even in government, in
advanced industrial societies, when those societies see themselves as
threatened or fading or even at the point of defeat. It was certainly the
smashing of Germany by the Allied powers in 1918, and the ruthless-
ness of the defeat imposed upon them, which led to fascism in Ger-
many. The unequivocal victory of American capitalism in 1945 meant
that we had no need of fascism. But if in some unpredictable future
the power of American capitalism seems to be fading before the power
of Japan and China, and if the economic powers in America recognize
the consequences of that threat, then very different forms of govern-
ment might arise within the bounds of their democratic constitution.
Secondly, the living forth of the triumph of the will among the stron-
gest advocates of complete liberty for abortion does not imply that
such advocates are in any sense a core for fascist politics. They simply
give us a taste now of what politics will be like when influential groups
in society think meaning is found in getting what they want most
deeply at all costs. They illustrate what pressure this puts upon a legal
system rooted in liberalism, whose leaders have riot been educated in
what that rootedness comprises. Even in its highest ranks the legal sys-
tem in its unthinking liberalism simply flounders in the face of those
who find meaning in the triumph of the will. This has been shown in
150 Politics and Morality
NOTES
1 Note: I do not intend to show in this writing that the fetus is a developing
individual of our species from conception. This was shown beyond doubt in
the testimony of the famous French geneticist, Jerome Lejeune, before a
committee of the American Senate.
2 The more the justices quote philosophy or religious tradition the less they
give the sense they understand what they are dealing with.
FREE TRADE
ible] maple leaf flag put on top. You rarely meet people who are outside the
determining power of that American dream. It is for this reason that I detest
[NDP leader Ed] Broadbent's supposed nationalist rhetoric. It is just the Dem-
ocratic Party North. As Mulroney is the Republican Party North.
- George Grant to Gaston Laurion, 21 July 1988
George Grant, review of Ij You Love This Country: Facts and Feelings on Free Trade, ed. Lau-
rier LaPierre (Toronto: McClelland and Stewart, 1987) in Books In Canada vol. 17, no. 1
(January-February 1988). 18-19.
152 Politics and Morality
role of the state in Canadian life.' Or again: 'The fact remains that the
proposed treaty not only embodies but, if implemented, will further
encourage a conception of government and society different from the
one that Canadians currently enjoy. Canada will be a less relaxed, a less
gentle, a less tolerant place in which to live.' He of course realizes that
this is not an absolute difference between Canada and the United
States. I wish he had carried over his splendid argument about the pri-
macy of the political into how the three Canadian parties destroyed
their nationalist wings: the squashing of Walter Gordon by Lester
Pearson when the former annoyed the business community; the
removal of the Waffle^ from the NDP when it angered the unions; the
destruction of Diefenbaker and his followers by Camp+ and the busi-
ness Tories. At the level of the immediate issues, Stairs's statement
about the necessary primacy of the political over the economic should
be central to any argument about free trade.
There is one statement in the book that moves quite outside the
careful assumptions of practical decision. This is Farley Mowat's. He is
not concerned with how we should deal immediately with the Ameri-
cans. He recognizes the arrival of cosy totalitarianism at the centre of
the American empire, and hates it. This is the statement with which I
feel the greatest sympathy. It is not filled with progressive talk about
free human beings being able to make the world as they choose. He
sees what corrupts the possibility of politics at this stage of raging tech-
nological change. His statement just expresses clear hatred. Hatred is
not a typical Canadian emotion or one that Canadians admire - greatly
to their credit. Nevertheless, some things deserve to be hated - the
friendly tyranny of corporation capitalism and the consequent Boden-
losigkeit. (The English word rootlessness catches less well what is happen-
ing than does the German.) Love and hate are necessary to each other
except among the saints.
There is one phrase that recurs in this book that I find unwise: 'Our
two countries.' This is what might be called the rhetoric of Broadbent
- the rhetoric he has used since he was used to drive the nationalists
out of the NDP. But it is also the 'liberal' rhetoric by which American
Philosophy (1951)
George Grant, 'Philosophy: An Essay Prepared for the Royal Commission on National
Development in the Arts, Letters and Sciences 1949-1951' (Ottawa: Edmond Cloutier
1951). This material originated in the Privy Council Office and is reproduced with the
permission of the Minister of Public Works and Government Services, 1996.
158 Philosophy and Education
men are to relate their particular functions to the general ends which
society desires.
Philosophy is not, then, confined to a subject found in university cal-
endars. Yet at the same time universities are the focal points upon which
will depend in large measure the state of rational contemplation in the
rest of society. In the universities, society allows scholars the time and
the freedom to contemplate the universe, to partake of the wisdom of
the past, to add their small measure to the understanding of that wis-
dom, and to transmit the great tradition to certain chosen members of
the younger generation. If the universities are not rich in the practice of
philosophy it is unlikely that less favoured parts of the community will
be much touched by it. Therefore, what follows will be concerned with
the teaching and practice of philosophy as it is carried on in our
universities.
In writing of this question it is only realism to pose the problem pes-
simistically. Why do our universities fail in providing a place where
young Canadians are encouraged to think about their world in the
broadest and deepest way? That the universities are not providing such
a place is but to state a truism. Can it be doubted that Canadian univer-
sities today exist essentially as technical schools for the training of spe-
cialists? They turn out doctors and physicists, economists and chemists,
lawyers and social workers, psychologists and agriculturalists, dieticians
and sociologists, and these technicians are not being called upon in any
systematic way to relate their necessary techniques to any broader
whole. Even the traditional humane subjects such as history, the clas-
sics, and European literature are in many cases being taught as tech-
niques by which the students can hope to earn their living, not as useful
introductions to the sweep of our spiritual tradition.
Indeed, behind the character of our classrooms lies the fact that this
production of technicians is being encouraged by the dominant forces
that shape society. The general voting public (that is, the parents of
the young) think of the university as a place where the child can
become a specialist and so equip himself to enter or to remain in the
more economically fortunate part of society. Governments — provincial
and federal - use their influence to see that practical training is
encouraged, so that the society will not be ill-equipped in any neces-
sary technique, whether that technique be appropriate to a university
or not. Anyone who has sat on a faculty of graduate studies knows well
that the ablest students are being encouraged by our government (in
Philosophy and the Perfection of God 159
in the search for faith. Society suffers the tragedy of their youth finding
faith in such childish hopes as marxism, in such unbalanced cults as the
Jehovah's Witnesses. It would seem clear, then, that only as philosophy
finds its roots in religious faith will it once again have a profound influ-
ence on young Canadians. The teaching of philosophy in our Canadian
universities is not only bound up with the question of what our univer-
sities are to be but also with the larger question of what our churches
are to be.
To face as the primary thesis of this essay that philosophical studies
are in no healthy state in Canada must not prevent mention of the
good things that have been done and are being done. The Roman
Catholic tradition in English-speaking Canada may be mentioned first
because it has always been numerically smaller and because it has main-
tained relatively unbroken its traditional attitude to the role of philo-
sophic speculation. It has always maintained its ancient trust in the
activities of speculative reason for certain carefully chosen of its mem-
bers, so long as that speculation is carried on within the limits of its
closely defined faith. The Roman Catholic colleges and universities
have always insisted that their best pupils go out into the world with
some grounding in the traditions of scholastic philosophy - that is, in
the reasonable framework of the theology of their church. They have
been insistent that the training of rational Roman Catholics was at least
as important as the training of efficient economists or physicists. Often
the technicians have made the claim that students from these universi-
ties have not as adequate a technical knowledge as students trained
elsewhere. The philosopher can but ask whether this lack of technical
width (if it be a fact) is not more than counterbalanced by the other
ends that their education has served.
A notable step in Roman Catholic philosophic activity was the recent
establishment of the Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies. This insti-
tution is connected with St Michael's College and through it to the Uni-
versity of Toronto. It calls together Roman Catholic scholars of the first
magnitude to pursue their studies in the fields of medieval history and
political thought, medieval philosophy and theology. To it come post-
graduate students who can pursue their own studies in this field under
scholars of first-rate calibre. Concentration is laid on the study of St
Thomas Aquinas, so that students have the possibility of mastering
a great system of thought. From such an institution as this, well-
disciplined teachers go back into the undergraduate fields equipped to
Philosophy and the Perfection of God 163
from which it had sprung. It did this in the hope that it could thereby
play a wider role in the national life. Did the men responsible for this
decision visualize that philosophy would then be taught as a study
unconnected with the faith? In looking at the documents of the time it
is difficult to suppose that the men who advocated this course did so
intend. Yet half a century later the content of the teaching in the Fac-
ulty of Arts at that university is found to be almost entirely secular. The
universities controlled by their respective provincial governments raise
another problem. If to be non-denominational means to be non-reli-
gious, is philosophy (as a general university subject) to be taught as a
secular study?
The churches themselves have a great stake in this question of the
teaching of philosophy. In the past presumably they have thought of
the universities to which they have sent their young members (whether
laymen or incipient members of the clergy) as institutions closely
related to the Church. Yet in the past, the study of philosophy in these
institutions has just as often served as a destroyer of the faith rather
than the creator of the rational groundwork to that faith. It must be
admitted that the Protestant churches have been remarkably uncon-
cerned with a state of affairs which has done much to vitiate their
strength.
Indeed, the prime difficulty in estimating what our philosophic ideas
have been is that Canada during the period that those ideas were form-
ing has witnessed the change among influential sections of the popula-
tion from being Protestants to being secularists. Though this has not
been true of the majority of Canadians, it has been true of a large per-
centage of the intellectually gifted people who shape our society and to
whom reasoning is a possibility. Such a remarkable and deep-seated
change in our national life has naturally confused our philosophizing.
Despite the difficulties of understanding what philosophy has meant
within the Protestant tradition, certain real achievements must be rec-
ognized. These have been generally accomplished by men of Great
Britain, educated in the Christian and classical studies of that country.
Many of these scholars did noble work in revealing the value of such
studies to many generations of Canadians. Two fine examples of this
kind of teaching may be singled out: the work of Professor Watson at
John Watson (1847-1939), Canada's foremost philosopher of his time. He began teach-
ing at Queen's in 1872 and served under Grant's grandfather. Grant was a student at
Queen's when Watson died and he served as a pallbearer at his funeral.
Philosophy and the Perfection of God 165
Queen's around the turn of the century, and the work of Professor
Brett at Toronto University in the third and fourth decades of this cen-
tury. Because these men had been trained in European philosophy
with its faith in human reason's pursuit of the Good, they could bring a
tradition to Canada far more profound and ordered than the pragma-
tisms which were influencing us from the south. They had been
brought up in societies that had been for centuries Protestant and so
could help keep alive in Canada those ideas out of which the English-
speaking forms of our society had been born.
One difficulty of having Englishmen as our leading teachers of phi-
losophy must, however, be mentioned. As has been said earlier, these
men were teaching at a time when the conception of the contemplative
arts was being radically assailed in Canada. The fact that the men who
were deeply involved in keeping this conception alive were generally
men bred in Great Britain often meant that they were unable to trans-
pose the vital issue of philosophy into sufficiently Canadian terms to
make them of burning interest to young Canadians. This failure
became increasingly important as the forms of life in Canada became
more differentiated from those in Great Britain. To say this is in no
sense to stand on the dogmas of a narrow Canadian nationalism, or to
imply that Canadians have not important things to learn from men
trained in Great Britain. It is, however, to say that a philosophy depart-
ment must not only have the conservative aim of acquainting students
with ideas from our past, but also the prophetic aim of showing what
those ideas mean in our actual present existence. It is certainly true
that in any Canadian department of philosophy there is ample room
for teachers from Europe who will almost certainly understand the past
of Europe better than will Canadians. But their work must be carried
on within a context of Canadian teaching impregnated with our history
and the form of our institutions and ideals. Often in the past, philoso-
phy has seemed a pursuit which turned out cultured Europeans, but
hardly an absolutely necessary activity for Canadians.
During the last years there have appeared the first signs of an indige-
nous Canadian approach to the problem of philosophy. All over the
Western world, the multiplying tragedies that have occurred since 1914
have turned more sensitive minds to a new assessment of human exist-
ence. The dimming of the optimistic hopes that characterized that first
industrial expansion has led men to seek a faith that has a fuller answer
to the tragedies of experience. In this world there was little need to
speculate deeply. As optimism declines, there is more reason to do so.
The evidence for this new awakening to our problem is indeed hard
to assemble. Yet it is impossible to be with young Canadians and not
feel an eager and questioning curiosity, a dissatisfaction with easy
answers, out of which a truly Canadian philosophy might be born. This
possible awakening is seen at a further level in the scholarly writings
that are appearing. Canadian scholars are beginning to produce works
of a profounder nature than studies of the wheat trade and the devel-
opment of responsible government in Canada. It must be noted that
these new works are not so much coming from men in the philosophy
departments proper as from men whose studies are in one of the spe-
cialized fields. Such studies have led men to understand the limits of
their fields seen in isolation, and so to an attempt to relate that field to
the problem of human existence as a whole. Thus, their thought has
become philosophical. Too often those in the philosophy departments
proper have not been to the same degree challenged by the modern
world so as to face the problems of philosophy in this living way.
The work of the late Professor C.N. Cochrane of Toronto may be
taken as a noble example of this new Canadian interest in the problems
of philosophy at their most profound and necessary level. His magnum
opus, Christianity and Classical Culture (1940), shows how interest in a
particular field of human study drives the sensitive thinker out into the
very midst of those spiritual problems that beset the modern world. In
his early writings it is clear that he considered the historian's job was
simply to say what had happened and to leave to other men the deeper
judgments as to the meaning of history. As in most of this scientific
investigation, the values that sustained the society were assumed, by an
implicit faith, to be certain, and therefore not the concern of the
scholar to defend. Yet in Christianity and Classical Culture Cochrane goes
far beyond this 'objective' tradition and raises the profoundest ques-
tions about human destiny. He questions the very possibility of the
aloof scholarship that he had once practised. To read the work is to
understand that the history of the ancient world has been illuminated
for him by the predicaments of his own society, and that he uses the
example of the ancient world to throw his light towards the solution of
the modern predicaments. A work such as Christianity and Classical Cul-
ture is not one to fall under the heading of light reading, even to the
trained mind. It is the kind of work that will not influence large num-
bers at one time, but will influence and continue to influence the few.
Such indeed must always be the role of significant philosophy - to
affect the spirits of the intellectually gifted and through them to filter
down into society as a whole.
One may cite other examples of specialists who in moving beyond
the limits of their techniques see the broader questions of knowledge.
In Professor Frye's recent work on William Blake - Fearful Symmetry -
full recognition is given to the fact that Blake's writing cannot be
understood through the criteria of literary criticisms alone, but must be
judged within the wider reference of the interpretation of experience
that Blake attempts. Thus, his work is not limited in interest to the
scholar of English literature, nor does it merely maintain that a cul-
tured man should be interested in poetry. Rather, through the study of
one poet it raises basic problems about the nature of man with which
all are concerned whether they will it or not. Yet another example is
Professor Woodhouse's Puritanism and Liberty* Even Professor Innis, +
who in his early work rigidly confined himself to technical questions of
economic history, has expanded his recent lectures on Empire and Com-
munications (1950) to relate the questions of economics to their wider
philosophical background.
These examples of Canadian thinkers who have shown themselves
willing to go beyond scholarship to more general questions of human
importance are encouraging to those who would hope for a native tra-
dition of Canadian philosophy. They are signs that Canadians are no
longer willing simply to accept from the more important nations of the
Western world their assumptions about human life. There is the begin-
ning of a recognition by Canadian scholars that we cannot count on
our spiritual tradition remaining alive automatically. There is a realiza-
tion at the intellectual level that Canadians can no longer afford to play
Northrop Frye (1912-91) was a Canadian literary critic who taught at Victoria College at
the University of Toronto and whose work achieved international renown. His first
important book was Fearful Symmetry (1947). See Grant's later review of The Great Code,
Part 4 of this volume.
A.S.P. Woodhouse (1895-1964), head of the department of English at University Col-
lege, Toronto, 1944—64, and author of Puritanism and Liberty (1938).
^Harold Innis (1894-1952), Canadian economist and communications theorist, headed
the Department of Political Economy at the University of Toronto 1935-52. See Grant's
later discussion of Innis in Part 4 of this volume.
168 Philosophy and Education
the role of debtor nation to the Western tradition, but must play their
part in conserving and enlivening that tradition. Even more so, there is
the understanding - and here the work of Cochrane must be especially
noted - of how much the wisdom of that tradition has already been
trodden under foot in our concentration on developing the mass soci-
ety. Cochrane makes clear that only in realizing how close the intellec-
tual life of Canada has come to losing the wisdom of a pre-scientific age
will the strength and vitality be found to work towards the rediscovery
of such wisdom.
At the more immediate level, these examples of a renewed interest in
philosophical and theological wisdom point to some conclusions as to
how philosophy could better fulfil its unifying role among our various
necessary techniques. First and foremost it lights up the fact that most
of our ablest teachers and students must perforce be technical special-
ists. Those who recognize the need for philosophical studies in Canada
must work within the limits that are imposed by the hard facts of our sit-
uation. To put it historically, it is not possible in Canada to recreate the
medieval idea of the university, or to copy the form of Classical Greats
which held so great an influence over the education of the privileged
classes of Great Britain in the nineteenth century. If philosophic stud-
ies are to be revived, it must be by reviving them among students and
teachers whose first duty is the pursuit of some specialism such as law or
history, economics or medicine. The hope is that specialists may see the
interdependence of their specialty and the general questions of human
existence. This philosophic interest must not be confined to those who
are going to be academic practioners of their specialism, but must
include those students who are to become more active members in
society, whether as judges, doctors, civil servants, or scientists in the
great industries. The tragic split between the men of action and the
men of contemplation must be overcome; the philosophers must rec-
ognize the relation of philosophy to the problem of society, and the
spirit of philosophy must be infused into those who must act. Such an
end is clearly an ideal impossible of achievement but a move towards it
is the only hope of reviving the contemplative life.
At the undergraduate level, something in this direction is already
carried out in most Canadian universities. A majority of students who
are studying for the BA are at one time or another exposed to some
philosophy. To a lesser degree this is true of those working towards a
BSc. Courses in philosophy for engineering and medical students are
becoming more of a commonplace in our calendars. It may be said,
Philosophy and the Perfection of God 169
can buy cheaply - a pleasant extra that coats the real business of
improving the standard of living.
More important than sheer numbers are the subtler questions of
what kind of teachers one wants and how they may best be trained. The
teachers of philosophy, if they are to have influence, must be men who
are not only steeped in the wisdom of the past but who are also aware of
society as it is. Above all, they must be aware of the meaning of the var-
ious other studies in the university. Only in this way can they fulfil their
special responsibility for making clear to the university community that
their subject is not another specialism but related to all studies. Noth-
ing has done the practice of philosophy more harm than the idea of
some scientists that philosophy is another science of the same kind as
theirs. The narrow vocabulary and approach of certain philosophers
has been largely responsible for that illusion. Therefore, our teachers
must be men able to expose that illusion by teaching philosophy in a
broad and living way.
A chief step, then, must be in the setting up of graduate schools in
which this narrow approach to philosophy can be broken down. Here
the Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies must once more be referred
to. For all institutions now existing in Canada, it seems to point most
surely in the right direction. There one sees a graduate institution
which approaches the activities of the human spirit in a unified way,
and all in relation to a particular tradition. Philosophy is not seen as an
isolated technique but as something related to the other facets of the
Catholic life - history and theology, art and liturgy. To repeat, the stu-
dents from such an institution have a wholeness about their attitude to
learning not found among many of the students who have done their
work in the atomized graduate schools of our country.
Immediately the question arises about the cost of establishing such
institutions. One advantage of the Roman Catholic Church over others
is the economic saving of a celibate priesthood. But the cost in other
traditions should not be prohibitive, especially when it is compared to
the money spent on the researches of physical science. The enormous
money spent on guaranteeing the physical health of our society would
not be necessary in establishing institutions such as these which would
guard our spiritual health. The question is simply whether a society
gains more from its M.I.T.s or from its Institutes of Medieval Studies.
The difficulty immediately arises of whether these institutions in
non-Roman Catholic education should be secular or professedly Chris-
tian. This, however, need not be a difficulty. Those universities which
172 Philosophy and Education
now admit they are simply secularist will probably be quite content with
their graduate schools as they already are. If not, they could set up Insti-
tutes of Humane Study or some such title. Protestant universities or col-
leges that maintain their Christian affiliations could set up schools for
Christian study very much like the Institute for Medieval Studies. From
what has been said earlier there can be no doubt which of these two
types of institutions the present writer would expect to be the more
effective. The dependence of philosophy upon theology makes such a
conclusion necessary. From such institutions a start might be made in
seeing that our spiritual traditions were once more in close relation to
the life of actions. Thence would come the vitality which might recreate
our universities into what they should always have been - centres of
rational thought about the universe.
Inevitably in such a young country as Canada, one must write about
the teaching of philosophy in the spirit of things hoped for, not in the
pride of what has been accomplished. Upon what is likely to be accom-
plished, it would be folly to speculate. As in all the slow intangible
accomplishments of the human spirit, its quality will depend on
whether men look for the long-term or the short-term results. In the
short view, the advantages are clearly with the continued production of
technicians by our higher education. The question will be decided by
whether our political leaders and civil servants, our businessmen and
educators come to see more clearly the long-term advantages of train-
ing our able youth in a contemplative as well as an active approach to
life. It will depend indeed on whether they see the incalculable advan-
tages that will pertain to any society which has a contemplative tradition
strong enough to act as a brake on the rightly impetuous men of action.
In the world we live in, the need of such an influence should become
increasingly apparent.
The tragedy must be admitted that, just as the controlling forces in
our Western world are beginning to understand how deeply our spiri-
tual traditions need guarding, and that some of our energy must be
diverted from technology towards that purpose, our society is being
challenged to defend itself against a barbaric empire that puts faith in
salvation by the machine. This must inevitably mean that a large per-
centage of Western wealth be spent on the mechanism of defence.
As this essay is addressed to a Royal Commission, something must be
said in closing of how interdependent is the progress of philosophy
with the progress of the arts. The practice and enjoyment of the arts has
only flourished in the past among men who have had some understand-
The Role of Education 173
ing of the wholeness of life, and who therefore could see the true pur-
poses of art in relation to the other necessary activities of human
existence. A supreme artist such as J.S. Bach could use the techniques
of his craft to the full because he understood the purpose of his art
within the wider range of human function. Equally, the community for
which Bach wrote could appreciate his music because they had some
vision of what music meant in the total progress of the human soul. Phi-
losophy cannot produce that intuition of the beautiful out of which art
arises, but it can help to promote that unity of mind in which such intu-
ition will best flourish. The same may be said of letters. Though it is sug-
gested in this essay that applied science is already overdeveloped in
Canada, philosophy can give that unity of mind out of which the spec-
ulations of pure science arise. The development of the philosophical
disciplines in our universities would provide the kind of integrated
minds among educated Canadians through which the arts of civiliza-
tion could flourish in some balanced proportion.
In closing, the present writer has no alternative but to repeat once
again his conviction that the practice of philosophy (and for that mat-
ter, all the arts of civilization) will depend on a prior condition -
namely the intensity and concentration of our faith in God. It is a
great illusion that scepticism breeds thought and that doubt is the
producer of art. The sceptic fails in that courage which alone can but-
tress the tiring discipline of being rational. Why should those who
believe there is so little to know spend their energy in the hard activity
of contemplation? As the late A.N. Whitehead wrote, it is in the ages
of faith that men pursue truth and beauty. It would be impudence
indeed in this essay to suggest how and when we Canadians will reach
a fuller and more balanced intuition of God. It is not impudence,
however, to point out that without such faith it will be vain to expect
any great flowering of our culture in general and of our philosophy in
particular.
Ever since working with the Canadian Association of Adult Education from
1943 to 1945, Grant was passionately interested in education. He rarely
declined an opportunity to speak to teachers' groups and he constantly reminded
174 Philosophy and Education
them of the dangers of losing sight of the fundamental truths that gave teaching
its importance.
You mentioned before I went to the 'old country' that I might look around
for somebody (preferably Scottish) to help teach philosophy. I came across
nobody who seemed suitable. Indeed the more I saw of young European philos-
ophers the more I wondered how they would understand and fit into the Nova
Scotian pattern. Science is so objective and certain that the background of the
teacher is not of its essence. Philosophy because it deals with such personal mys-
teries does depend on the teacher understanding and sympathizing with the
background of his pupils. So many of the young English and Scottish teachers
I have met were able, but I doubted their ability to transfer that ability to a
Canadian setting. This is not to say that I do not believe that Canadians have
endless things to learn from the great tradition of European life and thought -
but it does seem to me that somebody who was a Canadian and yet knew
Europe would be better in the university teaching philosophy than somebody
from the United Kingdom.
- George Grant to A.E. Kerr, late summer 1950
which we must give loyalty; on the other hand, isn't there something in
democracy which we must fear as the enemy of true education?
It is of course impossible in short space to give a close definition of
democracy. In the present context I mean simply the kind of society we
have here in Canada. By so defining it, I do not intend to describe all
the forms of our society as democratic, for that is clearly contradicted
by our economic forms. Nevertheless, in a general sense we can speak
of our society as democratic.
Now, to state the one side of the paradox, I for one am clear about giv-
ing loyalty to that democracy, particularly as it is seen against possible
alternative systems of society abroad in the world. This allegiance must
be limited, of course, for it is idolatry to give more than limited alle-
giance to anything as relative as the ordering of society. And when I
speak of loyalty to that democracy, I do not only mean to its political
forms, but to its social forms as well. For instance, the idea of social equal-
ity, which is so much a product of the North American as against the
English tradition, is something to which I give wholehearted allegiance.
It is necessary to make this distinction between social and political
democracy, for these days there is a new conservatism abroad which
supports the political forms of democracy while attacking its social
forms. This conservatism has a great appeal, for it is based on the truth
that men are not equal in talents. And this truth certainly needs stress-
ing as against certain vacuous talk of our more naive progressive demo-
crats. It has, however, been the genius of Christianity, at its richest, to
hold together in tension both sides of the truth at this point. It has
remained clear that men are not equal in talents and yet has insisted on
the more mysterious truth that all persons being called by God to salva-
tion are equal before His majesty. If I may say a word in praise of the
Puritans, who have been so cheaply abused in recent years by the
humanists, it was this mystery of equality that they so well understood.
It is, indeed, at this point as much as any that I find the secular dem-
ocrat difficult to understand. If, as they do, one holds that man's des-
tiny is only in this world, how is it possible to believe in equality? In a
worldly sense, men are so obviously unequal. Therefore, if one is a con-
sistent secularist one should certainly not believe in social democracy.
Social and educational democracy is a doctrine which only has mean-
ing when seen to be rooted in a theological mystery. That mystery is the
recognition of both sin and love. Aristocratic forms of government are
rejected because the Christian is at once cynical of the ability of the
ruler to free himself from corruption, and hopeful of the possibility of
176 Philosophy and Education
the love of God in the life of the ordinary person. The value of the ordi-
nary person, socially and educationally, is recognized because he is an
object of the divine love. A tradition which knew that the Saviour of the
world was a crucified Palestine carpenter and his disciples certainly not
aristocrats, was one which recognized that the love of God can pour
into the hearts of the many. It is ultimately in terms of this idea alone
that any allegiance to social democracy can be maintained.
Nevertheless, once this side of the paradox has been stated, it seems
to me that the other side must be stated too. Is it not equally true that
democracy can openly and obviously be an enemy of true education? I
think this side of the case can be put most clearly by stating what Plato
says about the matter in his Republic.
You will remember that at the end of the Republic Plato describes the
decline of society and the soul. Having described the ideally good soci-
ety and the ideally good soul, he now describes the ideally bad, which
he calls despotism. He does not believe that the ideally good or bad are
possible in this world. They are described simply as ethical principles of
attraction and repulsion. And in the scale between the good and the
bad he places the democratic society and soul very low - as indeed the
last step before the descent of man into the depths of despotism. He
describes democracy as that state in which the lowest common denom-
inator of desire rules and where every institution is dominated by this
lowest common denominator of desire. By lowest common denomina-
tor of desire, he means that the desires arising from the appetites have
taken over the person, and have become the ruling principle. Reason
has been dethroned. Democracy must therefore destroy itself because
it will become a chaos. It will become a chaos because, as people give
themselves ever more and more to the pursuit of the immediate claims
of appetite, the ordering power of reason disappears. In short, by defi-
nition democracy is the purest and most blatant love of the world as an
end - that is, secularism.
And surely once we look at the present education situation in Can-
ada, don't we see how true is what Plato says? I have not time here to
describe in detail the situation in our schools and universities as I see it.
Of the universities, suffice it to say that in general they have become
servants of the expanding economy. They are places where our young-
sters go to be taught certain techniques which will allow them to enter
or remain in the more prosperous part of society. They are largely ser-
vants of that appetite which is dominant in the cleverer part of our soci-
ety - namely greed. Any idea of education which transcends that is the
The Role of Education 177
merest minority report. And though I cannot speak of the schools from
inside knowledge, my view of them, certainly those in Nova Scotia, is
that in large measure they are places where youngsters are taught to
adjust themselves to the lowest common denominator of achievement.
I will allow myself simply one example to illustrate how our modern
education leads us to take this distrust of democracy seriously: the
degree to which the philosophy of John Dewey has been influential.
Only a society which already accepted a very low view of human nature
and destiny would have responded the way it did and does to what
Dewey said about human existence and the purpose of education. For
whatever is valid in Dewey at the level of practical techniques, the phi-
losophy which underlies it is nothing more finally than that worship of
the lowest common denominator of appetite which Plato describes.
This is explicitly spelled out in Dewey's position. The world of space
and time is seen as the ultimately real. Reason is, therefore, defined as
the instrument whereby we learn to adjust ourselves to that world. And
if adjustment to the world can in effect mean anything else than adjust-
ment to the lowest common denominator of desire, then I wish some-
body would show me. What Plato sees as the tragedy of democracy,
namely the gradual abdication by the higher faculties of their rule over
man, Dewey accepts as the true end of education. About one thing I am
crystal clear: if, as the Deweyites claim, their philosophy of education is
the truly democratic view, then democracy is a state of society in which
true education cannot flourish. And what I must emphasize again is
that the very fact that pragmatism should have had such power over the
minds of so many people influential in our democratic school system
could only have been possible if our view of man had already degener-
ated under democracy; and that shows us how seriously we must take
the claim that such a low view is implicit in the system.
To return to the paradox: what I have said I hope illustrates how
much it is a real paradox and not just a dilemma I am putting up to
knock down. The more I think about the question, the harder it is to
find reconciliation either at the level of thought or action. How does
one reconcile one's deep loyalty to the tradition of democracy with the
undoubted debasement of education that our democracy brings?
Of course, one can get out of the dilemma in two ways - by dropping
either side of the difficulty. One can simply just not recognize the ten-
dencies towards debasement and to see the democratic system as a glo-
rious progressive affair - broadening down from precedent to
precedent. This is what so many school and university teachers and
178 Philosophy and Education
The democratic society of North America is based upon certain moral val-
ues which were first formulated in the Judaic-Christian tradition. There-
fore, because one of the chief aims of our school system is to teach
allegiance to the democratic society, we must try by any means appropri-
ate to inculcate those values into the minds of our youngsters. Neverthe-
less, this must not mean that the schools should touch the field of
ultimately reality - that is, the field of religion. This is a personal matter
with which the schools cannot interfere. Indeed, it would be against true
democracy to teach about religion, for as people disagree as to what is ulti-
mately real, to teach about it would be to infringe the personal freedom of
the individual to reacb his conclusions on this matter. In short, ethical val-
ues are a common ground where the public schools can act with authority
- that is, endeavour to inculcate; religious truth, however, is a personal
matter and thereon the public schools must not be allowed to speak.
gettable truths about our society. The mass society is here and there-
fore we are committed to the problem of mass education. Moreover,
the report maintains that we should be committed to that task in joy
because of the value of each person, and as I have said earlier I entirely
agree with that. It predicts that technological advances will give the
majority more leisure than ever before in history. It recognizes that in a
society of such varying traditions it is inevitable that the state, as the
only common institution, should play a central role in education. I
have not time to discuss in detail the extraordinarily subtle question of
church and state in a society which is religiously pluralist, and though I
disagree with much that the report says on this matter, it is still right
when it says that North American democracy is committed to pluralism
and that therefore the state schools must respect it. This respect will
insure that the school shall not encroach on the duties of the church
and the home. Lastly, we can even admit that this document expresses
one side of the truth when it says that one's religion is a personal mat-
ter. This is true in the sense that final reality, being spirit, can only be
encountered in a free act of the spirit. However, that is only half the
truth as traditions, education, institutions, and authority are, of course,
also necessary to that encounter.
Nevertheless, as soon as one has stated the truth in this report, it is
necessary to state with full force its basic falsehood. I am going to illus-
trate this falsity in two ways: (i) with regard to the proper ordering of
studies; (ii) with regard to the divorcing of values from reality.
First, then, why is this position shown to be false when we look at the
question of the proper ordering of studies? To prove this I will have to
lay down certain basic propositions. The school is the chief instrument
in our society for the cultivation of the human reason - particularly the
theoretical reasons as distinct from practical reason which is cultivated
at all points in our life. Now, why do we count it good to cultivate the
theoretical reason in ourselves and others? There are many subsidiary
purposes for that cultivation, but the fundamental purpose is, as Aristo-
tle says, that all men desire to know the real and that therefore the final
object of the cultivation of reason is that we may know what is ultimately
real - that is, God. Now, this proposition, which is obviously central to
the philosophy of education, cannot be justified at length here. It is the
ultimate truth of human existence and therefore the hardest truth to
prove to oneself or to others. I may say, however, and this will seem to
some of you extreme arrogance, that I do not count this truth to be
mere opinion, something of which I am not certain. I am certain of it in
the sense that, though I cannot prove it to be true, I can prove all dif-
180 Philosophy and Education
sis of your curriculum will be entirely different and what students think
important to study will be entirely different. I am sure you all see this
every day of your lives as I do. One of the reasons for the existence of
the university in which I work is that it is a great exporter of commercial
lawyers to the temples of Bay Street in Toronto. Now, to be successfully
adjusted to the world of Bay Street you do not need any knowledge of
classical history or philosophy (a certain attenuated culture may be
necessary but that can be picked up at a session of the Harvard School
of Business Administration and by careful attention at cocktail parties).
Therefore, classics and philosophy are not considered important either
by the administration or by students. The same example could be given
by our export of research physicists or chemists to the government lab-
oratories in Ottawa.
How are we to speak to students clearly outside some philosophy as to
what is ultimately real? Are we to encourage students to study this or that
and yet not be able to tell them the purpose of studying this or that?
Now, of course, the answer we give to younger students may have to be
of an indirect or even allegorical kind. We may have to say to them you
can't yet see why mathematics is important, if one is to advance to
higher studies, but trust me that it is. Yet all the same we have to be clear
in ourselves or else the brighter the student the more he will see educa-
tion as pointless and chaotic.
There is a popular modern position which tries to escape any state-
ment about ultimate reality by that wonderful platitude that the pur-
pose of the school is to teach people to think. A dean of education from
western Canada was down in Halifax saying this to our teachers last
week and I hear it from many quarters. This position has the advantage
of seeming to be a compromise which appeals to both the traditionalist
and the progressive. But, of course, it entirely breaks down as soon as
one asks the simple question - why is it good to think? Won't I be hap-
pier if I don't think, if, for instance, I don't go near the study of philos-
ophy? And when one tries to answer that question one is forced to some
view of what really matters in life. Either one says one should think
because it will help one to get on in the world and that is what matters;
or think because it will teach you what is real, it will give you the vision
of God. And I would point out again that only the second answer has
any value in persuading youngsters to study any subject which takes one
beyond the palpably useful.
What I have been saying is that a philosophy is necessarily implied in
the schools. Students will study subjects, institutions will teach subjects
182 Philosophy and Education
cheat, why shouldn't one try to amass more nuts than the other squir-
rels? And what always seems most amazing to me in this is how little
these professors see that what they have been teaching students over
the years about ultimate reality (namely that man can be fully known as
a biological object) has had a direct effect in producing the kind of
doctors they now dislike.
Obviously, the same thing applies in the schools. If you have schools
where the best teachers assert that what is real is the world of space and
time, as so many teachers do, then it is foolish to try and impose in that
school a set of values which come from a very different view of reality.
All you do then is to produce chaos. The clever children see the incon-
sistency and the stupid are meanly tricked. One is saying to them that
brotherhood matters in terms of this world. When they go out into the
world they soon find that brotherhood does not bring success in
worldly terms - that it just means they get taken. Then the inference
from that is that the value of brotherhood is just part of that pious non-
sense which schools put over but which nobody means.
This is the basic failure of this document of the National Edvication
Association. Its failure is at the level of philosophy and theoretical con-
sistency. There is nothing wrong with the document at the level of prac-
tical virtue. (It has, indeed, more pious exhortations to virtue per
square inch of print than any other document I have ever read.) But
the proposition that we can hope to inculcate Judaic-Christian values
while eliminating any systematic teaching and thought about what is
real must be criticized philosophically. For if what I said is true: namely
that values are the flowers, the roots of which are our affirmation about
metaphysics, then this document is telling us that the flowers can be
kept alive when they are cut off from their roots. If you can believe that,
you can believe anything.
But though this is what this report states explicitly, really what is
implied is a deeper philosophy than that. What is implied in every line
of this document is a profound irrationalism. Positively, this irrational-
ism takes the form of saying that the natural and social sciences are the
way we find out what is real, while religion and values are concerned
with subjective preferences arising largely from the emotions. Religion
is thought of as a kind of emotional certainty and volitional commit-
ment a la Billy Graham, and values are thought of as the right emo-
tional attitudes the democratic society wants to inculcate. Reality is
thought of as the sensuous world of space and time, and truth about
reality as the accumulation of facts through the sciences. Negatively,
184 Philosophy and Education
that is, the document denies the basic proposition of Western thought
that the reason, practical and theoretical, is the faculty by which man
apprehends ultimate reality and that therefore that reality is supersen-
sible. The assumption throughout is that values and religion are mat-
ters of opinion, not matters where truth can be discovered by proper
use of the mind. The position is something like this. On the one side
you have a world of facts of reality gained by the sciences; on the other
hand you have an emotional world of value and religion. The human
being is broken down the middle. Reason operates for dealing with the
world but not for giving one truth for how one should act or what one
should worship.
In other words, however much this report tries to escape any accusa-
tion of Deweyism, by an avowed friendship to religion and values, it
really is in exactly the same position. For the basic proposition of Dewey
is still there - namely that reason is only an instrument for manipulat-
ing the world. The religious, ethical, and metaphysical questions of
mankind are a realm where reason cannot operate. And, of course, if
this presupposition of the document is true then all its practical pro-
posals logically follow. But this proposition cannot possibly be justified
in thought. You cannot by reason show that reason has no power.
I have spoken of the position advocated in this report at length
because it illustrates a truth which tends to be forgotten in a society
such as ours. That truth is this: a position which, practically, seems both
decent and feasible in the short run, may still be false philosophically
and so can only be disastrous in the long run.
But, of course, if the philosophy of education is to be of service it
must not put itself outside the awful responsibilities of time. And that
means that the short run and the long run must be brought together.
In relation to the position in this report the tension of our minds
must be to see in unity its short-term truth and its long-term falsity.
How are we to recognize that mass democracy is here and that in love
we must care about it? How are we to take that seriously and still rec-
ognize that the purpose of education is the movement of the mind to
God and that therefore all activities in the schools must be seen in
that context?
And as I have said, this question presents to me no easy solution. I
do not see any coordinated plan of group action (the kind of thing
that we in North America are so fond of) that can take us off the hook
of this predicament. It is a tension which all of us have to live through.
Therefore, I am in no position to end this talk by introducing some
The Role of Education 185
plus nothing (even a million times) is still nothing. That is, as teachers
we must cultivate our aloneness so that when we come to a group, we
come as somebody.
Secondly, I would like to say that the temptation we must watch
above any other is despair. In England there is a tombstone of a seven-
teenth-century Puritan divine who lived through the agonies of the
civil war and on his tombstone is written: 'He did the best things at the
worst times and hoped for them in the most calamitous.' Let that be
written on ours. Despair for the teacher these days may so often lead to
what I would call a Brahmin view of education - that is the view that we
can touch a few choice spirits, but that the rest of the world is lost in
ignorance.
A figure out of our history whom I like to contemplate in this connec-
tion is St Augustine - the African philosopher and theologian. August-
ine lived at a period when it was hard to believe that history was to some
purpose - the dissolution of classical society was all around him. He saw
clearly that the principles abroad in that society necessarily meant its
degeneration into increasing chaos. But in that situation he did not
despair; nor, what is more important, did he take a wrongly other-
worldly view. It was, indeed, in this terrible crisis of the classical world
that Augustine affirmed with greater clarity than had ever been stated
before that God is not alone the God beyond the world, but is also
working in each moment of the historical. So from this hope the seeds
of new meaning in the world as well as beyond it were planted not only
for himself, but for others. He knew that despair was wrong, because
despair always assumes that the issue of history lies finally with our-
selves. Bui clearly it is not with ourselves that the ultimate issue lies. Our
hope lies rather in One who is power and reason and love, Who has
indeed most manifestly shown us that power and love and reason are in
Him, One - eternally.
courses chosen by others. This letter outlines the reasons for his decision.
Although it was not published, Grant intended it as a formal statement.
encourages them to say here are a lot of opinions about this subject and
that, but it does not encourage them in the real task of trying to make
true judgments about those matters.
I would like to include a paragraph about Professor Long's relation
to religion and my own, because I am sure you have heard it said that I
confuse religion and philosophy and that you will now hear it said that
my objection to Professor Long's book comes from my religion. Let
me make it clear that I consider the practice of religion and the prac-
tice of philosophy two distinct human activities. I do not think that phi-
losophy can prove or disprove Christian doctrine. My position on this
matter is illustrated by the fact that the philosopher I admire most in
North America is Leo Strauss at Chicago. He is a practising Jew and I
would have no hesitation in saying that he is a better philosopher than
any practising Christian I know on this continent. Some of my best
graduate students have been practisingjews and I have had no difficul-
ties with them on this score. Of course, though religion and philoso-
phy are distinct activities, their relation is a philosophic question of
magnitude and Professor Long inevitably deals with it. Unfortunately
he does not deal with it accurately. If, for instance, you turn to what
Professor Long says about the relation between philosophy and the
idea of revelation in certain religions on p. 23 of this book, I do not
think one could find any trained philosophers who are either believing
Protestants or Catholics or Jews who would say that it is an accurate or
adequate account of the matter. I did not ask that the textbooks I use
should be directed towards the spread of my religion. (I suggested the
works of Plato and Russell neither of whom are in any way identified
with the Christian church and neither of whom are in any way identi-
fied with the true.) But I could hardly be expected to use a textbook
which misrepresents the religion of my allegiance. I would also point
out that though Professor Long deplores the influence of faith on cer-
tain philosophers, he has no hesitation in closely identifying the claims
of his faith with the facts of the case. It is in my opinion just this which
above all makes Professor Long's book so poor an instrument for
introducing youngsters to philosophy most of whom will have been
born since 1940 in modern industrial Canada. Professor Long's faith
was obviously formed by the experience of his break with a limited Cal-
vinism in light of certain philosophic and scientific ideas. This was a
very moving and formative experience for the English of the 1890s, for
the Americans of the early 1900s, and for Canadians in the 1920s, but it
has little bearing on the situation of Canadians growing up in Ontario
at the moment.
190 Philosophy and Education
THE MULTIVERSITY
thought that they had lost any sense of a unity of knowledge. And did not believe
that the growing fragmentation of knowledge was an innocent trend: it served,
the interests of the dominant elites in North American society.
George Grant, The University Curriculum and the Technological Threat,' in The Sci-
ences, the Humanities, and the. Technological Threat, ed W. Roy Niblett (London: University
of London 1975), 21-35. Written first in 1968.
192 Philosophy and Education
time resisting the forces of power which press in upon them from with-
out their community.
Within the last hundred years it has become increasingly clear that
the technological society requires not only the control of non-human
nature, but equally the control of human nature.
For the social scientists to play their controlling role required that they
should come to interpret their sciences as 'value-free.' This clarification
has been carried out particularly by sociologists, and, indeed, it is inev-
itable from its very subject matter that this science should be magisterial
among the social sciences. The use of the term 'value' and the distin-
guishing of judgments about values from judgments about facts enables
the social scientist to believe that his account of reality is objective, while
all previous accounts (which were not based on this distinction) were
vitiated by their confusion of normative with factual statements. It is not
appropriate in this writing to describe the history of the idea of 'value-
free' social science as it came to be in the European tradition, particu-
larly under the influence of Kant and Nietzsche, and was so elegantly
formulated by Weber. Nor is it necessary to describe how it has been
reformulated in liberal Protestant terms by such men as Parsons and
Lasswell' to suit the American scene. What is important to understand
is that the quantification-oriented behaviourial sciences which have
arisen from this methodological history are wonderfully appropriate for
serving the tasks of control necessary to a technological society. Indeed,
where the fact-value distinction was originally formulated by Weber as a
means whereby the academy could hold itself free from the pressures of
the powerful, it has quickly become a means whereby the university can
make itself socially useful. Social sciences so defined are well adapted to
serve the purposes of the ruling private and public corporations.
Indeed, the distinction between judgments of fact and judgments of
value has been thought to be favourable to a pluralist society. The
Talcott Parsons (1902-79), Harvard-based American sociologist, one of the most influ-
ential theorists of the twentieth century.
H.D. Lasswell (b. 1902), distinguished American political scientist.
The Multiversity 193
of knowing that one way of life was nobler than another. Those who
studied the humanities were led to a great uncertainty about what con-
stituted the good life, and whether this was a real question at all. The
public hope that the humanities would fulfil a positive moral role was,
therefore, vitiated by the fact that the best professionals of these disci-
plines did not see their activity in this way. Indeed, it is a fact of North
American history that the spread of professional teaching in the
humanities has been a means whereby the scepticism of Europe has
penetrated the more innocent traditions of North America.
The professional practitioners of the humanities have justified their
studies quite differently from the popular rhetoric. They have increas-
ingly said that the humanities are non-evaluative sciences. The cruder
form of this justification has led those disciplines to become highly
research-oriented, so that they could cover themselves with the mantle
of science and Protestant busy-ness. An enormous amount of energy
and money has been channelled into research projects. In English lit-
erature there are many great factories pouring out editions, commen-
taries, and lives on all but the minuscule figures of our literature. (The
equivalent of the expensive equipment of the scientist are the rare
manuscript libraries.) If one has a steady nerve, it is useful to contem-
plate how much is written about Beowulf in one year in North Amer-
ica. One can look at the Shakespeare industry with perhaps less sense of
absurdity; but when it comes to figures such as Horace Walpole^ having
their own factory, one must beware vertigo. The difficulty in this
research orientation is that whereas research in the progressive sci-
ences produces discoveries which the public see as useful, this is not so
in the humanities. The historian may claim that all the careful work
that goes into small areas can be justified as useful in that it makes up
the totality of a mosaic from which those who are educated in the disci-
pline may better know the past and so make more prudent judgments
in the present. He may even claim that the formal discipline of Name-
rian+ history is in itself a good training for potential rulers. Both these
justifications may be true, although the proof of this would require a
discussion of the place of historical judgment in the training of rulers.
What is, however, paradoxical at the practical level about the vast appa-
tive science, what would seem to be the most important question can-
not be raised within the study: that is, whether de Sade or Tolstoy is
nearer the truth about the proper place of sexuality. In the same way in
'philosophy' the study of ethics tells one much of how language is used
and can be used consistently in ethical discourse. But it no longer
claims to be concerned with what are the highest possibilities for men.
Such studies are impotent to lead to what was once considered (per-
haps and perhaps not naively) the crucial judgments about 'values' -
whether they are good or evil. Their scholars have gained their unas-
sailable status of mastery and self-justification by surrendering their
power to speak about questions of immediate and ultimate meaning -
indeed generally by asserting that such questions only arise through
confusion of mind. Such a position provides immunity within the aca-
demic fortress, but it can still be asked whether the impotence of mind
towards meaning is man's necessary condition.
Be that as it may, the central role of the humanities will be increas-
ingly as handmaiden to the performing arts.
The tight circle then in which we live is this: our present forms of
existence have sapped the ability to think about standards of excellence
and yet at the same time have imposed on us a standard in terms of
which the human good is monolithically asserted. Thus, the university
curriculum, by the very studies it incorporates, guarantees that there
should be no serious criticisms of itself or of the society it is shaped to
serve. We are unable seriously to judge the university without judging
its essence, the curriculum; but since we are educated in terms of that
curriculum it is guaranteed that most of us will judge it as good. The cri-
teria by which we could judge it as inadequate in principle can only be
reached by those who through some chance have moved outside the
society by memory or by thought. But so to have moved means that
one's criticism will not be taken seriously from within that society.
It would be presumptuous to end by proposing some particular ther-
apy by which we might escape from the tight circle of the modern fate.
The decisions of Western men over many centuries have made our
world too ineluctably what it is for there to be any facile exit.
After twenty years at McMaster, Grant grew tired of fighting losing battles
against what he called 'research.' His resignation started a national controversy,
and this article in the Toronto Globe and Mail was meant to clarify what he
thought had gone wrong at research-driven universities.
George Grant, 'The Battle between Teaching and Research,' in Globe and Mail, 28 April
1980, 7.
Research and Resignation 201
was also the nobler positive affirmation: Let us see that everybody in
society can reach his highest potential through education; let us expand
the frontier of knowledge; let us build a noble technological society of
highly skilled specialists who are at the same time people of vision.
It came to be believed that the university would become central in
building a humane and liberated technological society. Ontario natu-
rally followed the continental pattern and established a great network
of universities.
The new university system came into existence at a time when the
account of knowledge which had dominated the Western world for
three centuries had reached its height of influence. Every civilization
has produced its own account of what constitutes knowledge, and has
been shaped by that account. Such accounts spring forth from a partic-
ular aspiration of human thought in relation to the effective means of
its realization. Our dominant account of knowledge in the West has
been positive and progressive science. The aspiration of thought from
which it sprang was, above all, the desire to overcome chance so human
beings would be the controllers of nature.
The effective condition for its realization was what we now call
research. Research is the method in which something is summoned
before the court of human reason and questioned, so we can discover
the causes for its being the way it is as an object. Research made its
appearance on the public scene of history when Galileo ran balls down
an inclined plane. Now research is applied to everything from matter to
human beings, from modern society to past societies.
The amazing achievements of research are before us in every lived
moment - in the achievements of modern medicine and communica-
tions, of modern food production, and warfare. If one ever has doubts
about the goodness of many of its achievements, it is well to remind
oneself of penicillin. It is the method of scientific research that had
made Western civilization a world civilization. It is at the heart and core
of our lives, and as such at the heart and core of our education.
Yet there are great questions which present themselves to all think-
ing human beings and which cannot be answered by the method of
research. What is justice? How do we come to know what is truly beau-
tiful? Where do we stand towards the divine? Are there things that can
be done that should not be done? One just has to formulate these ques-
tions to see they cannot be answered by research. Yet thinking people
need to be clear about such questions and therefore they cannot be
excluded from the university.
202 Philosophy and Education
than by any other source. Flexner is the man most associated with that
influence. On the other side, dialectical education was stronger in
England than anywhere else, largely because of the powerful influence
of Oxford and Cambridge. Canadian higher education was more
shaped before 1945 by English influences than by any other. The influx
of American professors in recent decades has brought a powerful push
toward the research-oriented university. The nature of that influence
does not turn on the particular nationality of particular people. No
decent human being should judge another solely in terms of the acci-
dent of where he was born. But the problem still remains. The influx of
American professors brought with it certain German ideas which have
greatly cut across many of our traditions.
When I was growing up in university circles in the 1930s, it was taken
for granted that Canadian universities were probably better than (at
least different from) their American counterparts. Since 1945, Cana-
dian confidence in its own traditions has continually weakened,
because of our belief that the American model is determinative.
This abstruse question of educational principle may seem far away
from the realities of life. Yet it is not. You cannot have a free and vibrant
society unless there are free and vibrant people in it. Obviously there
are large numbers of free people in Canada who have no touch with
higher education. Their freedom has other sources. Nevertheless, it is
important for the health of any society that there are people in it whose
sense of freedom is sustained by having thought in a disciplined way
about the supreme questions of human life.
When our Arts faculties are centred around research they produce a
culture which is essentially a 'museum culture.' Museums are places
where we see past life as objects - as flies in amber. We do not see them
as existences which light up our existence.
Never has so much money been spent on the organized study of the
past, and never has the past had less meaning in shaping the real life of
our present. Art arid religion and the passion for justice will continue,
but they will be more and more cut off from the rationality that the uni-
versities should offer them. Technological excellence plus museum
scholarship are not enough. When they are considered sufficient, the
mass of students will become listless. Scholarship is a means to thought,
not a substitute for it.
Simon Flexner (1863-1946), American scientist and head of the Rockefeller Founda-
tion, 1920-35.
This page intentionally left blank
PartS
Thinking Their Thoughts
This page intentionally left blank
PLATO (427-369 B.C.)
For Grant, Plato was a thinker much too profound merely to write about.
Through Plato's dialogues, Grant glimpsed an eternal and transcendent reality.
He gave frequent lectures and seminars on Plato and Plato's influence on
Grant's own writings ivas pervasive. It lay behind almost everything he wrote,
but was implied rather than formally stated. Grant was not an antiquarian
and he did not believe that it was sufficient merely to reconstruct Plato's
thought. He needed Plato as a guide who might help him see reality through the
mist of the modern world.
... Let me start with a simple remark. What I find is most perfect in
Plato is that there is a total union in his thought of what is in lesser phi-
losophers either separated or part of which is not present. That is, he
combines in a staggering unity the cosmological approach with the
ethical-religious approach. What I mean by these two is the following:
the cosmological approach is the question: 'What is the nature of the
universe - what is real and how can I know what is real?' Or, to use
other language, it puts the philosophic question as 'What general
not far away. In the Phaedrus we are nearer the unity of the two, so we
shall study it last. But we are not studying the great cosmological dia-
logues of which the Sophist and the Parmenides are, in my opinion,
the greatest. Nor are we studying the last great dialogues in which
the cosmological and the ethical-religious are at one - the greatest of
which in my opinion is the Phikbus - that supreme philosophical
writing. Nor should we think that the immense generality of meta-
physics is higher than the practical - because the last work of Plato,
The Laws, is concerned with such concrete subjects as how much wine
a man should drink at different ages, and at what age one should
marry.
Now, I have said this to begin to talk about the Good, and to point
out that the Good as seen in the Symposium is seen as the supreme
object of desire.
But let us remember that the Good and the One are the same.
In the Republic the argument for the speculative life - the argument
from knowledge for God's existence - is combined with the argument
from desire so that the Good is not only seen (a) as the highest object
of desire, but also (b) the cause of knowing, that is, that which makes
the world intelligible and our minds intelligent, and also (c) as the
cause of being, that is, the cosmological and ethical-religious are very
closely bound together.
In the Symposium we are chiefly concerned with desire. But in
the Symposium, though what we concentrate on is desire or love, we
must always be aware that the Good is both the supreme object of
desire and of knowledge. They are at one. The One and the Good are
the same.
Let me say also that I interpret Plato as unequivocally believing
in the One or the Good as transcendent — that which is the
supreme object of our love is absent. Let me quote to you the
Republic 508-9.
To make this clear I would have to comment on Parmenides at great
length and, as that is impossible, let me only say this. What does it
mean to say that the highest object of desire and of the intellect is ulti-
mately unknowable?
Philosophers mostly agree that it belongs to the nature of mind to
seek unity. Now, they seem to disagree at this point as to the nature of
that unity - or see it from the side of desire to seek meaning.
Those who I may quickly characterize as the immanentists would say
210 Thinking Their Thoughts
* Charles Williams, The Descent of the Dove (London: Faber and Faber 1950, 1963).
^George Grant to Margaret (Grant) Andrew, after May 1952.
Plato 211
back to find that the basis of liberalism, if carried far enough, was the
right basis for action. In other words, what Plato is teaching me is not
that I disagree with the tradition of liberalism in which I was raised,
but that the tradition in which I was raised hadn't really sufficiently
examined itself to find on what principles it did exist.
Well, after this preliminary, an historical note. I thought it unfair in
your letter to mention T.S. Eliot and Augustine in the same connec-
tion. Eliot seems to me a quite good poet (though capable of extreme
cheapness, e.g. The Cocktail Party), but a man hardly capable of sys-
tematic thought, and one who simply accepts the Catholic position
with particular emphasis on the givenness of revelation. This is
indeed the picture of Augustine that, for differing motives, certain
Catholic and sceptical writers have put abroad. But it is an untrue pic-
ture. Augustine, for instance, said several times that the whole of
Christian truth was present in Plato and the best of the Greek philos-
ophers. In fact, the whole of his system is a defence of the unity of
reason and revelation as against the position (which one finds per-
fectly expressed by St Thomas) that there is a gulf between what we
know by our reason and what is thrust upon us (they are never clear
how) by God.
I mention this only because it seems to me that it was on the ground
of this reason that Augustine sought some measure other than conve-
nience by which to judge that thoughts were true or false, actions right
or wrong. When you say that this tradition exalts some transcendent,
unknowable power over against man, and thereby denigrates man, I
do not think that is what people who believe in the final unity of the
world are doing. It is because of the form of human life - not to escape
from the form of human life - that they say that Reason, Love - call it if
you will God — is the measure, and not the pleasure or convenience of
man. And this answer arises from two questions and two questions
alone. (1) What is knowledge? That is, what is the difference between
truth and falsehood, or, to put it better, knowledge about which we are
certain and opinion which varies from minute to minute. E.g. The
Pythagorean theorem is within certain assumptions always true, it is
knowledge; while the opinions of most Nova Scotians about politics is
not knowledge. (2) What standards can we find by which our reason
can judge whether our actions are right or wrong? That is the question
of morality. That is, the question of God's existence arises entirely
from an attempt to answer those two primary questions. What is knowl-
212 Thinking Their Thoughts
edge? What is morality? And these really boil down to one: What is the
place of reason in our lives, whether speculatively in knowledge or
practically in action?
I think the whole classical and modern tradition would here agree
that for knowledge to be possible, there must be some unity between
our minds and the external world we know, for otherwise our minds
could know nothing of the world. Yet science shows us that we do.
Therefore, the world and our minds must be at unity. So equally with
reason in action, for there to be any standards on which we can act.
Our reasons must be able to apprehend in some dim sense their place
in the order of the world. For what else is morality but fulfilling one's
proper purpose? (Of course, the place of reason in morality raises
other difficulties of a kind that do not appear in the case of knowl-
edge.)
Now here is where I think the great split comes in the history of
thought (whether classical or modern, eastern or western.) There are
those who say an immanent principle of unity is sufficient to account
for the existence of knowledge and morality (e.g. Spinoza, Hegel, and,
I think, Aristotle) while others say that the principle of unity is tran-
scendent (e.g. Plato, Plotinus, Augustine, Kant). I would stand here.
Now my argument for the transcendence of unity as against its imma-
nence would be based on any number of arguments by taking the con-
tradictions between various categories and showing that they can only
be reconciled in terms of such a transcendent unity - e.g. mind and
body, universals and particulars. But finally, my chief argument against
those who find an immanent principle of unity sufficient would be that
they cannot properly account for human imperfection. If the world is a
unity in itself, why, then, is that unity broken by nearly all of us in our
actions - selfishness, ignorance, etc.? Men like Spinoza answer that, of
course it is not that human imperfection is an illusion, or, as Hegel
said, the individual evil is the universal good. But such phrases just
seem to me paradoxes, not explanations, and they still leave one with
the fact of human imperfection; and that drives one to say that the
unity of the world finally rests upon a unity which is transcendent...
Now, you may well ask with this philosophy, where does the specifi-
cally Christian tradition fit in? First and foremost, I would say that
where the Christian tradition substantiates the philosophical one is in
its greater and profounder understanding of the problem of how all
men can come to see the unity of the world and their proper partaking
St Augustine 213
of that unity. That is the great point where I find [St] Paul sees more
deeply than Plato. How all men are within this unity and, therefore,
must freely be brought to it; and that all men learn in direct ways as
well as the inferential way and, therefore, the language of primitive
Christianity is so supremely open to all men. Of course, the greatest
symbol to any of us is another human being's life and, therefore, you
have at the centre of Christianity a symbol or image of the final unity
of the world in a concrete life through which men can come to find
that unity for themselves. This is what I think Jesus's life must have
meant to men like Paul (who must have been trained in Platonic
thought, and, for that matter, the Mosaic thought which in so many
ways is like Platonism): the giving to men in concrete pictorial way that
end or unity towards which they strive and in terms of which men
alone can find happiness, health, or call it if you will, salvation.
Now I would agree as much as anybody that the difficulty of this sym-
bolic, imaginative part of Christianity is that it so easily gets cut off
from its real basis and gets turned into a lot of nonsense that may do a
lot of people harm. I think a great deal of the Roman church's system
of rewards and punishments is just that. And, of course, at the
moment, the Christian tradition of European Protestantism is largely
worn out. What it was saying, basically, in its day was of eternal signifi-
cance, but so much of the eternal has been lost and only a weak frame
is left. But some frame has to be found both at the basic philosophical
level and at the level of corporate religious institutions that will pass on
the tradition. Tradition does not seem to me the end; it is simply a lad-
der we use when we are young and which we must finally pass beyond
as our knowledge of perfection is always greater than its incorporation
in any particular tradition. Yet because our existence is at a low level of
biology and, therefore, of continuity, we need these traditions to sus-
tain us and prevent us becoming beasts ...
Grant was profoundly influenced by St Augustine. From family friend and Uni-
versity of Toronto classics professor Charles Cochrane (1889-1945) he learnt of
Augustine's synthesis of classical philosophy and Christianity and hence of
214 Thinking Their Thoughts
"This talk was given by George Grant in the series Anthology, broadcast on the radio sta-
tion CBL to the Trans-Canada Network, 26 October 1954.
St Augustine 215
form in the poet Virgil. He used all the seductive power of his art to
convince men that the destiny of eternal Rome was to build this per-
fect earthly city. That is, men such as Augustus and Virgil claimed for
Rome a uniqueness and finality - that it was the incarnation of the
divine purpose in the world.
The history of Christianity is in Cochrane's eyes largely a criticism of
those claims of Rome. It was quite impossible, said the Christians, to
attain this perfection through political action and trust in political
leadership. 'To them the state, so far from being the supreme instru-
ment of human emancipation and perfectibility, was a strait-jacket to
be justified at best as a remedy for sin. To think of it otherwise they
considered the grossest of superstitions.' Against the idea of eternal
Rome - the city of the world - they raised up the city of God. A city
which could not be brought in by the superficial methods of politics,
but by the wills of men as illumined by God through the vision of the
crucified Jew.
But Cochrane sees that this difference between classical and Chris-
tian thinkers about political questions originated in a difference that
was far deeper than politics. It lay in the very difference between the
two visions of the nature and destiny of man. It lay in what Cochrane
calls the defective logic of classical naturalism - the view of man and
his place in nature constructed by classical science. What the Chris-
tians claimed was that the Roman world was defective at the very deep-
est level - the level of first principles - and what they demanded was a
revision of those first principles.
As Cochrane writes: 'The basis for such a revision they held to lie in
the meaning of Christ, conceived not as a revelation of new truth but
of eternal truth - and saw in it the illumination which would be the
basis for a new physics, a new ethic and, above all, a new logic - the
logic of human progress. In Christ, therefore, they claimed to possess
a principle of understanding superior to anything existing in the clas-
sical world. By this claim, they were prepared to stand or fall ...' They
formulated this principle in the doctrine of the Trinity which they saw
as no obscurantist mystery (as do most of our present-day theologians)
but as that in terms of which all else could be understood.
The main part of Cochrane's book is concerned with the gradual
formulation of this principle and its use as an instrument whereby to
criticize the failures of the Roman Empire as they became increas-
ingly apparent. He traces the story from the early cruder thinkers
St Augustine 217
Grant had an abiding interest in Kant's thought and taught courses on him at
both Dalhousie and McMaster. For Grant, Kant's importance lay in his under-
standing of the inwardness of morality and the importance of moral freedom.
These phenomena lay, for Grant, at the heart of the modern world and consti-
tuted great achievements and even greater dangers.
Does the distinction between necessity and good really lead to the fact-
value distinction?
This seems to me the question: are all dualistic ways of thought the
same?
I think we can best start from what one thinks the moral judgment
to be. My immediate difficulty is that I do not understand how Weber
analyzed the making of moral judgments. (You could help me here
with an account and with references.) I do think I understand what
Kant says. What is the difficulty in that account for me (and with as
great a thinker as Kant, one has to say that the difficulty may be that
one has not grasped the doctrine) is that I do not understand the rela-
tion between freedom and reason in his teaching. On the one hand,
the very idea of reason presents itself to us so that we know directly that
certain actions contradict that very idea. It presents itself to us in the
imperative mood; he indeed expresses that presentation with the word
Achtung.^ Yet, at the same time, we self-legislate this commanding law
of reason, and are capable of disobedience, that is, we are free in the
sense that Weber means (?). Did Weber take from Kant the idea of
freedom without the idea of reason?
As I see it, the great advantage of any dualistic system (Kant's e.g.) is
that it squarely faces the problem of suffering and does not swallow it
up in any easy explanation. By this I mean that any position must start
from a recognition that to exist is to suffer and in human terms it is to
learn that we cannot have what we want. (See Plato, Christ, Freud, etc.)
In other words, from the human standpoint the first thing a philoso-
pher must try and understand is what is the purpose (if any) in the fact
that our immediate desires are broken and trampled on from the earli-
est age. Kant's answer of duty, that is of putting aside one's immediate
desire in the name of universal purpose, seems to me a very great
Letter to Rod Crook, 19 July 1965, in George Grant: Selected Letters, ed. William Christian
(Toronto: University of Toronto Press 1996).
Respect (German). I owe this translation to one of the University of Toronto Press's
anonymous readers.
220 Thinking Their Thoughts
answer, and, of course, puts him in some sense squarely in the Chris-
tian tradition, the overwhelming power of which was to bring suffering
into the Godhead, to be in fact the religion of slaves.
(Let me say in parenthesis that your very wise criticism of a
debauched Protestantism could, it seems to me, lead you off certain
tracks, important for the truth, if it leads you away from understanding
the strength of Christianity as the religion of suffering. For, not only
Christianity, but all the great religions, have great insights about the
negation of desire as part of the human condition.)
Of course, this account of the moral judgement for Kant had to go
with the possibility of science, and that for Kant meant a nature freed
from purpose. Therefore, reason commanded us rather than nature
giving us the law.
Now, it is at this point that I would like to write down why I cannot
give a satisfactory answer to your question. I hope that it will not simply
be of interest as my stage, but raising some important questions.
Looking back from Kant to Plato and Aristotle (for reasons part of
which will be evident in the foregoing, but part of which would take
too long in a letter) I am faced with an ambiguity. I think (but am not
sure) that there is in Plato a much greater understanding of the suffer-
ing of man than in Aristotle. The transcendence of the forms the criti-
cism of which in Aristotle is badly parroted by nearly every modern
student of philosophy with one year's training ('Plato hypostatized
concepts, etc, etc.') does appear to me very similar to Kant in the sense
that the good by which we act comes to us somehow from beyond
nature - call it if you will by that hated word supernaturally - and
demands the death of worldly desires. All the psychological or socio-
logical reductions of that position in the name of accusing it of repres-
sion, aberration and perversion does not seem to me to get around its
appeal for two reasons: (a) the meaning of the whole does not seem to
be understandable in the light of evil in an immanent way; (b) the
question of the meaning of the whole cannot easily be put aside either
existentially or scientifically.
The ambiguity this presents to me may be put historically in two
ways: (a) I am not sure I am interpreting Plato correctly; (b) I am at
last realizing that there are certain arguments on the Aristotelian side,
which I have not met and which means that I have to study at a more
than student level Aristode's Ethics and Politics.
(a) The interpretation of Plato. At the beginning of the Republic
there is the statement of Glaucon about the sufferings of the just man;
Immanuel Kant 221
is the man who knows that he knows not.' Also Pascal: 'We know too
much to be sceptics; we know too little to be dogmatists.' Kant cer-
tainly says that in the preface to the 2nd edition of the 1st Critique.
Beyond this - and here I know nothing; it is evidently possible accord-
ing to the mystics to come to an understanding of the beauty of neces-
sity as we submit to its afflictions and love others who are so submitted.
But about that I must repeat that I know nothing. In my book (which
was a popular book) I make clear that I spoke simply from the position
of the person who must proceed in the practical life from the position
that the order of morality and the order of necessity cannot be known
as proceeding from the Good.
I make another point concerning Kant simply for the sake of interest
and in no way to take away from the genius of Simone Weil or from the
nobility of your book. Kant was the thinker who first explicitly made
the autonomy of the will central to western moral philosophy. Such a
doctrine is clearly denied in Plato and is not even present in Aristotle.
Kant says directly that Greek philosophy fails because it does not
understand the autonomy of the human will. Also I can see great con-
tradictions between Simone Weil's account of society and Kant's. Kant
is unflinchingly contractualist. As he writes in the first supplement to
Perpetual Peace. 'The problem of organizing a state, however hard it
may seem, can be solved even for a race of devils, if only they are intel-
ligent.' I have had to think through the basis of European contractual-
ism and its baneful results because no societies have so suffered from it
as ours in North America. Also if one takes into account Kant's contin-
ual references to his debt to Rousseau, it becomes clear that he is
entangled in all that has harmed the modern world in the conception
of 'history' and which Simone Weil has so wonderfully criticized. I take
it as a fact that the origin of the concept of 'history' is first clearly
expounded in its modern sense in the 2nd Discourse of Rousseau.
Admittedly Kant is to be preferred to Hegel who carries this way of
thinking further into that strange enquiry 'the philosophy of history.'
Nevertheless, the seeds of Hegel are already in Kant. He has journeyed
very far from Plato. Indeed The Critique of Pure Reason is dedicated to
Letter, 3 April 1975, George Grant: Selected Letters, ed. William Christian (Toronto: Univer-
sity of Toronto Press 1996).
Immanuel Kant 223
Francis Bacon and ends with a section entitled 'The history of pure
reason.'
Lecture (1977/8)*
Lecture (1977/8)f
Lecture notes, McMaster University, 1977/8, George Grant personal papers, Halifax.
lbid.
224 Thinking Their Thoughts
purpose is to see what the liberation for this new freedom is. Only
when it is entirely before one could one speak about whether its
unfolding, its coming to be, has been for good or ill...
To be immediate, this says something about philosophy and life as
we have to live it. For example, in our practical life we are faced now in
every lived moment with the unfolding of that liberation to a new free-
dom. A very good example of that liberation is recombinant DNA
research. Insofar as such research is our business, then we can practi-
cally say 'no' to the unfolding of that new liberation. But to do that is a
different thing, though part of the same life, from knowing philosoph-
ically whether that liberty's unfolding is for good or ill. In short, we can
neither say that philosophy and life are separated, nor can we affirm
the unity of thought and practice ...
But what lies behind this? What was the primal affirmation from
which both Descartes and Bacon arose? Suffice it to say here that the
subject (human beings as subject) became that before which must be
led everything which is, and through which everything that is is justi-
fied for what it is. The human being (call it if you will in the generic
sense 'man') based on his own authority becomes the foundation and
the measure of all that is ... The world is represented to us as an object
that we as subjects interrogate and over which we have jurisdiction.
One must see that this is a new way of representing the world to us,
and we could see this well if we were to compare it with the older
receptive views of perception in the ancient tradition.
Modern science and morality came out of this new view of the sover-
eignty of man as subject. As I have said, the unfolding of all this, man
as subject, the world as object, is the liberation of man for a new lib-
erty. As I have also said, the fundamental basis of this human event
from which pours forth the new liberty is not clear to me, as I have
tried to say in what I wrote about in English-Speaking Justice.
But what can be seen with clarity is that the account of reason so bril-
liantly expounded in the Critique of Pure Reason, which holds the world
before itself, representing it to itself as object, which is the basis of
truth - positive truth - is the basis of the new liberty which is going to
establish its domination over the whole earth. Man establishes himself
as sovereign over the totality of all that is. What Kant says in the Critique
of Pure Reason and what he says about the autonomy of the will in the
Grundlegung are at one, as they are both man taking his fate into his
own hands. Henceforth, man sets out from himself and for himself.
It could be said at a certain level that for Kant 'to know' and 'to will'
are held apart. We are commanded to will the categorical imperative
Immanuel Kant 225
indeed since his day that turning back has been a central fact of the
intellectual and practical life of the best. I tried to say in the piece I
wrote about English-speaking justice why that was for the Western
world the very incarnation of that turning back.
When Nietzsche calls Kant the great delayer, one can well reply:
Does one not want to delay the realization of the account of justice in
Nietzsche? (Not indeed that the account of justice in Nietzsche is the
perfect statement of what is implied in the modern account of the
essence of truth, but it moves in that direction.)
Why one is filled with foreboding concerning the doctrine of justice
given in the modern account of the essence of truth is of course
another question ...
As well as reading for my work I have read a life of Karl Marx with long extracts
from the writer. I find that I try to answer his questions to prove that he is
wrong. I cannot. I am not advanced enough. But, at the same time, I am posi-
tive that one cannot answer certain statements that he makes. That if one is not
prejudiced by a 'good upbringing' one must believe some of the things he says.
- George Grant to Maude Grant, 1938
than anyone else's, the Western spirit of progress has gone out into the
countries of Asia and has become the dynamic religion of the East.
Study of this thought is, therefore, pressed upon us in the West. Yet
just as this understanding of marxism is most important to us, it has
become most difficult, because in the last decades there has been a
campaign of vilification against Marx and of suspicion of those who
study his thought in any systematic manner. He has been attacked as
the prophet of the worst abuses of the Soviet empire; as the subverter
of the achievements of capitalism; as the enemy of godliness and
morality. Although this campaign has draped itself in the flags of patri-
otism and of religion, it is not surprising that it has been inspired
largely by those whose basic interest was the maintenance of our
present property relations. [I remember when his picture was put on
the cover of Time. The resulting misrepresentation is what we have
been led to expect from Time when it wants to blacken a reputation.
The story inside was of a jealous, half-educated, ambitious and neu-
rotic man driven to his hatred of capitalism by the pain from the car-
buncles on his behind.] The contradictory nature of this attack stems
from the mixture of fear and contempt with which it has been moti-
vated. Why should the blackeners of Marx try to prevent systematic
studying of his writings, if they consider these such a jumble of non-
sense? What is especially strange in the behaviour of those who attack
Marx in this wild way is that they have generally asserted their faith in
God. Do they not believe then that this faith includes the belief that
the truth will make men free and that therefore only in careful study
can the chaff be divided from the wheat?
The contempt for Marx has not been confined to the irresponsible
rich and their demagogues. It is heard from responsible businessmen
and government officials and from their servants in the universities.
This educated contempt is more dangerous to Western interests
because it takes the form not of abuse but of patronizing aloofness.
These people claim that the important thing is Russian and Chinese
imperialism, not the spread of marxism. To those who pride themselves
on their realism, Marxism need not be taken more seriously than any
other faith. They assert that what matters is power and not ideas. This
position naturally appeals to the civil servants of Washington, London,
and Ottawa who like to be considered too sophisticated in the ways of
The material in square brackets has been restored to the published version from the
radio lectures.
228 Thinking Their Thoughts
the world to take theory seriously, and believe that history is ultimately
shaped by the ad hoc decisions that make up their lives. This supposed
realism is, however, one-sided and short-sighted. If the word power is to
mean anything, the social and ideological structure of that power must
be analyzed and understood. It is the pettiest view of human history to
believe that the intellectuals of Asia are moved by a philosophy that is
simply a tissue of wild imaginings. We must understand Marx as well as
the power of Russia and of anti-colonialism if we are to understand the
continued victories of communism in Asia. We must understand,
indeed, how much marxism has contributed to the present political
and technological power of Russian society.
It must be insisted, however, that Marx is worth studying not only
because of his influence in the history of Asia, but also because of what
he is in himself: a social theorist of the first rank, who reveals to us the
diverse currents that make up the progressivist river. Indeed, it must
be recognized that marxism is a much profounder river than the lim-
ited canals of theory dug by the officials of the Communist Party in the
East or West. As has been the inevitable fate of great prophets, his dis-
ciples have consistently neglected and misinterpreted those aspects of
his thought that did not serve their purposes. This process started even
with his intimate friend Engels, who is inclined to interpret Marx as a
disciple of Darwin. The narrowing was carried even further by such
men of action as Lenin and Stalin. Marx must be studied not so much
as a political-economic propagandist than as a theorist who brought
together the varying streams of the humanist hope and in whose syn-
thesis, therefore, the value of the doctrine of progress is most clearly
exposed to us.
Marx is essentially a philosopher of history, that is, one who believes
he knows the meaning of the historical process as a whole and derives
his view of right action therefrom. In a certain sense the philosophy of
history is the modern equivalent of what in olden days was known as
theodicy, the vindication of the divine providence in view of the exist-
ence of evil. The search for meaning becomes necessary when we are
faced with evil in all its negativity. In Marx's search the starting point
is the indubitable fact of evil. Reality is not as it ought to be. Men are
not able to live properly, because their lives are full of starvation,
exploitation, greed, the domination of one man by another. Our
present society is not such that it permits men to fulfil themselves. As
Marx says: 'Men are for other men objects.' No thinker ever had a
more passionate hatred of the evils men inflict on each other, nor a
Karl Marx 229
greater yearning that such evils should cease. It is perhaps not surpris-
ing that he should have been so aware of evil, living as he did in the
early years of the industrial era, when new ways of work were insti-
tuted with little respect for those who did the work. What is more sur-
prising is how few of his contemporary intellectuals rebelled against
the crimes that were being committed against working men, women,
and children.
Marx proceeds from the present evil to criticism of the religious
solution of that evil. He says that the religious solution is to maintain
that all is really well, despite the evident evil. This solution has pre-
vented men from dealing with the evils of the world. The idea that
there is a God who is finally responsible holds men from taking their
responsibility sufficiently seriously. If there is going to be pie in the sky
when you die, then the evils of the world are not finally important. In
this sense, religion is the opium of the people. Religion and its hand-
maiden, traditional philosophy, have said that reconciliation can be
found in the here and now - if men will only seek God. In fact, they say
that evil is not what it seems and that despite it, all is well. But this is
not the case: all is far from well. To pretend anything else is simply to
disregard the sufferings of others. Therefore, the first function of
thought must be the destruction of the idea of God in human con-
sciousness.
As Marx wrote: 'The philosophers up to now have been concerned
with understanding the world; we are concerned with changing it.'
What he means is that the philosophers have sought the meaning
already present. They have sought God. He is not concerned with the
meaning already present; he is concerned with the creation of mean-
ing in the future by man. He is concerned with the practical overcom-
ing of the suffering he sees all around him. Therefore, man must take
his fate into his own hands and to do that he must overcome the idea
of God.
Marx's criticism of religion, however, is more profound than that of
others who have said the same thing. For he recognizes that if man is
to pass beyond belief in God, religion must not only be denied, but
also its truth must be taken up into the humanist hope. The truth of
religion for Marx was the yearning of the human spirit to overcome its
evil - or, in his language, to overcome its own alienation. By 'alien-
ation' he means that man's situation in society estranges him from the
proper fulfilment of his freedom. He has never been able to live as he
ought in society. Marx claims that he has freed this religious yearning
230 Thinking Their Thoughts
man both is and is not what he is. Spirit, then, has a different logic
from the logic of identity proper to nature. History is the coming to be
of spirit in the world. Marx takes over this Hegelian way of thought,
and limits it by finding the whole meaning of history in the relation of
human freedom to nature. There is for him no nature without human
significance; there is no significance to human freedom apart from the
domination of nature. 3 To Marx, therefore, the way that men have
organized their economic relations is the key to history. In the eco-
nomic organization that expresses our relation to nature, he sees the
cause of human evil in the past; in the creation of a new relation he
sees the overcoming of that evil.
To state this in more detail: from the earliest days of history, men
found themselves in a position of scarcity. There was just not enough
food, shelter, and clothing for everybody to have an abundance.
Because of this a society of class dominance was necessary. A minority
group in society gained control of the economic life, the means of pro-
duction. And as they controlled the means upon which everybody
depended for sustaining life, they controlled society as a whole, and set
the pattern of its government, its art, its religion, its morality. In other
words, in a world of scarcity, society was necessarily divided into classes.
Class in Marx is defined in a strictly economic sense, in relation to con-
trol or lack of control over the means of production.
This division of society has meant class struggle between those who
wanted to maintain their control over the source of wealth and their
consequent position of privilege, and the majority, who were excluded
from that control. But at the same time as one dominant class has
been imposing its control over society through its control of the
means of production, people have also been seeking greater power
over nature through technology, and therefore introducing new forms
of social wealth. This continually changing relation of men to nature
has prevented any one class from long being able to impose its domi-
nance over the means of production, and so over society as a whole.
The new forms of wealth have produced new classes to challenge the
power of the old rulers. For example, in medieval society the means of
production were chiefly land, and therefore the ruling class was the
landlords. But as there came to be more and more commerce and sim-
ple manufacturing, the new middle class arose in the new towns. This
class challenged the power of the landowners. The times of quick and
radical change in history have been when a new class, produced by
new economic conditions, has come to sufficient power to challenge
232 Thinking Their Thoughts
the old ruling class, which in turn does all it can to retain its dying
supremacy.
Marx also believed that as man's control over nature becomes more
complete, so the dominant classes who come to power progressively
serve a more universal interest of mankind. They serve the gradual
emergence of freedom in the world. In the modern era it has been the
historic role of the capitalists and their capitalist society to bring tech-
nology and economic organization to the point where, ideally, the
conditions of scarcity might be once and for all overcome. The
achievement of the capitalists has been to destroy the old natural
world in which human freedom could not come to be. They have ratio-
nalized society.
At the same time, however, as capitalist society has created the con-
ditions of liberation, it has intensified the conditions of enslavement.
The very form that the ownership of the means of production takes in
capitalism sharpens the class struggle to its peak. For as capitalism
solidifies, it moves, because of the profit motive, to the concentration
of economic control into fewer and fewer hands. The mass of mankind
are cut off from control over the conditions of their own work as they
are cut off from any control over the means of production. The contra-
diction that capitalist society creates is that it has produced the possi-
bility of overcoming scarcity - that is, the conditions for overcoming
class dominance and inequality have arrived; yet at the same time it has
chained the mass of men to uncreative labour, work for which they
have no responsibility. It has taken to the extreme the division between
the owners of the economic apparatus and servants of that apparatus.
In such a situation where liberation is possible and where alienation is
actual, there can be only one result. The mass of men will not allow
themselves to be excluded from the liberation that technology has now
opened for them. They will take the means of production out of pri-
vate control and place them under social control. They will destroy
capitalism and create socialism. In this new society the basic cause of
evil will be overcome. Men will no longer be for each other objects of
economic exploitation. Human beings will be able to give themselves
over to the free play of their faculties, to the life of love and art and
thought.
The mass of people who are increasingly separated from control
over their own work and over the economic apparatus as a whole,
Marx calls the proletariat. Few conceptions in Marx generate so much
confusion. People think that the proletariat means the hungry, the
Karl Marx 233
ragged, the destitute. As today in North America there are not many
people who are destitute, the inference is drawn that Marx has been
proven wrong about capitalism. Of course, Marx hated the grinding
poverty and the degrading division between physical and intellectual
work that characterized the capitalism of his day. He said that indus-
trial workers were turned into the living counterparts of a dead mecha-
nism. But the idea of destitution is not necessary to the idea of the
proletariat. The proletariat consists of those who have no creative
responsibility for the society through their work, because they do not
own the means of production with which they have to work. They are
employees serving the private interests of their employers. For Marx,
the proletariat is not one class amongst other classes, one class against
other classes. It is the universal condition in which the vast majority of
men find themselves in the age of the machine, when the machines
and the machines that make machines serve private interests. The pro-
letariat cannot liberate itself by producing another class society, but
only by destroying the very existence of economic classes themselves.
The mass of society are driven to recognize that in a machine age all
work is social and rational and that therefore what must be created is
an appropriate economic apparatus, not one given over to the irratio-
nal ends of private profit.
Those people who first become conscious that this is the historical
position of the age will become the leaders of that liberation, the pro-
letariat conscious-of-itself. They are the Communist Party, the party
that will direct the bringing in of a classless society of equality. Thus,
the sufferings of the proletariat are seen as the Christian sees the pas-
sion of Christ, necessary to the redemption of mankind. It is this idea
(at some level of explicitness) that has enabled countless ordinary peo-
ple to endure suffering - with such high fortitude - for the sake of the
communist cause. The suffering is seen as meaningful.
It is not possible to assess here this remarkable vision of human his-
tory. There are many things to be said about it both as economic and
philosophic doctrine. For instance, to assess it as an economic doctrine
it would be necessary to discuss its dependence on the labour theory of
value; to assess it as a philosophic doctrine, discussion of the causes of
human evil would have to be introduced. Nor is it possible to describe
the development of marxist doctrine in the last century or the ques-
tion of how far the Russian Revolution and the consequent regime of
the Soviet Union can be said to be the socialist society of which Marx
was talking. It is, for instance, arguable that it is with us in North Amer-
234 Thinking Their Thoughts
ica that the conditions that Marx prophesied are most clearly fulfilled,
and therefore Marx is more the prophet of North America than of
Russia. These are intricate questions to which no short answer can be
given.
What must be insisted on, however, is that Marx's philosophy has
been the most powerful of modern humanisms, for two reasons above
all. First, it was a humanism of universal salvation, and secondly, it
seemed very concrete and practical about the means to that salvation.
With regard to the first point: the marxist hope is not for the isolated
individual but for society as a whole. His humanism is not for a few
rare, fine spirits in exceptional positions, but promises the good life
for all. So often humanist liberalism has been made ridiculous by its
individualism that disregarded the dependence of the individual on
the community, and seemed little concerned with the way the mass of
men lived. But how can the human spirit find any moral fulfilment in
such individualism? There can be no perfected freedom in a world
where others have not found it. What kind of a heaven can be enjoyed
while others are in hell? The power of marxism has lain in the fact that
it foretold a concrete overcoming of evil in the world, which would be
for society as a whole. Here Marx's dependence on the Judaeo-Chris-
tian idea of history is obvious. His humanism retains the idea of history
as salvation, but rejects its theological framework. This makes it incom-
parably more powerful than those humanisms that are liberal and indi-
vidualistic.
The second reason for the power of marxism is its claimed practical-
ity. Instead of leaving the worldly hope up in the air, it describes in
concrete how it is to be brought about. It relates its achievement to the
forces already around us in modern society. There is much that could
be said about the superiority of marxism over other doctrines of
progress, on account of its direct application to the world as it is, but I
will single out one connection - the significance Marx gave to the nat-
ural scientists.
The fact to be explained is why many scientists in this century have
been followers of Marx or have been deeply influenced by him.
Because governments must concern themselves with treason, this fact
has been surrounded with a miasma of anxiety in the last years. But the
first problem is to give a serious explanation of why it has been so. The
answer is surely this: marxism gave so satisfactory an account of science
as essentially an ethical, indeed a redemptive activity, the means by
which men were to be freed from the evils of pain and work.
Karl Marx 235
NOTES
1 The difficulty of studying Marx in his own writings must be emphasized. His
master work, Capital, consciously imitates the structure of Hegel's Logic, with
its scheme of being, essence, and idea. Also, some of Marx's profoundest
thought is to be found in his early writings which are not easily available in
English. For instance, his philosophy of history begins to take shape in a
magazine article protesting a German law which penalized the collection of
firewood by the poor. The reader is therefore advised to approach the study
of Marx through such modern commentaries as A. Cornu's K. Marx etF.
Engels, vol. 1 (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France 1955), vol 2 (Paris:
Presses Universitaires de France 1958), andj. Hyppolite's Etudes sur Marx et
Hegel (Paris: Riviere 1955).
2 It is difficult for English-speaking peoples to admit the spiritual greatness of
the Germans. In our last two wars we have been taught to despise their civili-
zation. Nevertheless, the fact remains that the highest European achieve-
ments in music and philosophy have come from the Germans. Indeed, the
ambiguity of German history is that these people have been capable of the
most appalling evil, but also of the highest reaches of the human spirit. In
Western philosophy, for instance, two periods of thought stand out as the
most brilliant: the fourth century B.C. in Greece, which we associate with
Plato and Aristotle, and the late eighteenth century in Germany, whose mas-
ters were Kant and Hegel. There are no more remarkable books on human
history than Hegel's Philosophy of History and his Phenomenology of Mind. Marx
is the heir to this tradition of German philosophical genius. I write about
Marx in these essays because his thought is the most influential way that Ger-
man philosophy has gone out into the world, but under his thought at every
point lies the much profounder genius of Hegel.
Simone Weil 237
3 I need hardly stress what a different view this is of man and nature, and their
relationship, compared with the Greek view of natural law.
Simone Weil was a French philosopher whom Grant admired more than any
other contemporary thinker because she combined philosophic thought of the
highest order with a life of saint-like denial and asceticism. Born into a secu-
lar Jewish family in Paris, she received an elite French education and worked
for a while as a schoolteacher. However; after the German invasion of France,
she was forced to flee, first to the south of France, then to New York, and
finally to London, where she worked for the Free French. She published littte
during her lifetime, but the posthumous publication of her notebooks estab-
lished her as one of the leading philosophical and religious thinkers of the
twentieth century. Grant was deeply influenced by her from the 1950s and his
last great work, 'Faith and the Multiversity,' shows how much he had learned
from meditating on her writings for over thirty years. Grant did not consider
the writings reprinted here to be anything more than an invitation to read
Weil herself.
Let me say also that although my debt to Strauss is great as a teacher of what
makes up modernity, Simone Weil is the being whose thought is to me the
enrapturing. It is indeed true that I am scared of her because the unequivocal
saints are scaring to somebody like myself who loves comfortable self-preserva-
tion, but nevertheless her thought is next to the Gospels the highest authority
for me. Quite a different level of authority from Strauss. I can imagine being
capable of writing something as perceptive & lucid as Strauss, but I cannot
imagine loving God & being possessed by Christ as S.W. was. That is why I
write of the same questions as Strauss and do not write of S.W. because she
was divinely inspired and one can only approach that with fearful hesitation.
She can be wrong about little scholarly details in a way that Strauss would not
be, but on the greatest matters in the last years, she is writing out of the
extraordinary event of being possessed by the second person (??) of the Trin-
ity. If I can ever become quite a different person, I might be able to write
something about her, other than just pointing to her writings.
- George Grant to Joan O'Donovan, 19 January 1981
238 Thinking Their Thoughts
before 1914. But it was that culture in its finest form. Whatever else she
was to become, it must be remembered that she partook of two
remarkable traditions; both her Frenchness and her secularized Jew-
ishness gave her that intense love of learning and cultivation of the
intellect, which may not of themselves be enough, but are the seed-
ground from which even higher activities can proceed, and without
which society and individuals are likely to become mediocre or even
base. French education for the very clever is prodigiously difficult and
highly competitive. Her achievement is therefore remarkable in taking
her baccalaureate at the age of fifteen (the usual age being seventeen
or eighteen) and in receiving the mark of nineteen out of twenty,
when the usual youngster considers fifteen a high mark. She pro-
ceeded to the lycee and the College Henri IV and on to the Ecole
Normale Superieure. Alain, the famous teacher of philosophy, con-
sidered that she had philosophic genius of the first order. That is, in a
country where the achievement of the elite was the best the West has
produced, she was known as having shining intellectual eminence.
There is in her, however, from the beginning, something beyond
the pattern of French brilliance, or for that matter beyond any intellec-
tual brilliance. No sooner had she become a teacher of philosophy
than she became part of a group of workers who produced a paper
called The Proletarian Revolution, and soon after she took leave of philo-
sophical teaching and became a worker in the Renault motor works.
The best comment on that life is what she wrote later to her friend,
Father Perrin; 'What I went through (in the factory) marked me in so
lasting a manner that still today when any human being, whoever he
may be and in whatever circumstances, speaks to me without brutality,
I cannot help having the impression that there must be a mistake and
that unfortunately the mistake will in all probability disappear. There I
received for ever the mark of a slave, like the branding of the red-hot
iron which the Romans put on the foreheads of their most despised
slaves.'
In 1931 and 1932 she had been in Germany, and writing (at the age
of twenty-one) in the proletarian magazine she made clear the reasons
for the inevitable fact that the Nazis must win the struggle for power -
as in fact they did a year later. In 1936 she went to Spain to work for the
Republican army on the Catalonian front and experienced war in its
Emile Auguste Chartier (1868-1951), French philosopher and one of the most impor-
tant earlv influences on Weil's thought.
240 Thinking Their Thoughts
savagery. In 1937 her parents moved in and took her out of the public
world, as by this time she was physically broken and was to suffer for
the rest of her life from that hideous curse, migraine.
With the fall of Paris to the Germans in 1940 she moved to unoccu-
pied France, working as a farm labourer for twelve hours a day and con-
tinuing her studies in Greek and Sanskrit. She was later involved in
clandestine activities. In 1942 she was persuaded to move to New York by
her parents, who as Jews obviously had to emigrate. But the six months
in New York she considered a mistake, and immediately began to pester
her friends who were high officials in General de Gaulle's entourage to
send her on some mission to France. She was brought to London in
December 1942 but her obviously Jewish physique and the brokenness
of her health would not allow the officials to send her into France. She
worked in London on reports about the kind of society which should be
established in France after the war. One of her greatest writings, The
Theory of the Sacraments, was a private letter to Maurice Schumann, now
Foreign Secretary. In the spring of 1943 she was in hospital, and dead in
August 1943. Cause of death listed as 'suicide, not eating.'
This capsuled account of her life sounds singularly uninspiring, and
my failure saddens me. I now must turn to that aspect of her life which
is even harder to describe than outward events - what I would call the
possession and distinction of her existence by God. This difficult sub-
ject cannot be avoided because it is in this fact that the greatness of her
writings can only be understood. What gives her writings their startling
force is that she writes of the divine (call it, if you will, reality) with an
immediacy, certainty, and directness. Let me explain what I mean by
this quality of her writings by making a comparison between two writ-
ers of our era. Both people like Masters^ in his reports and D.H.
Lawrence* in his novels write of sexuality. Masters from his science
knows a lot about the outlets and climaxes of American men and
women. But he clearly knew almost nothing about human sexuality in
itself. Can anybody imagine going to Masters to deepen their con-
sciousness about the place of sexuality in their own life? The very idea
is high comedy. Lawrence, on the other hand, knows what sexuality is
Maurice Schumann (1911-), the chief official broadcaster on the BBC French service
during the Second World War.
W.J. Masters and his wife A.E.Johnson published a landmark study of sexuality, Human
Sexual Response (1966).
D.H. Lawrence's (1885—1930) most famous novel, Lady Chatterley's Lover (1928), was
banned in both Great Britain and the United States as pornographic.
Simone Weil 241
because he has existed as a sexual being and knew others who have
also so existed. My analogy is that Simone Weil writes about the divine
like Lawrence, not like Masters.
It is therefore necessary for me to say something of those events
between 1936 and 1943 whereby God's perfection became immediate
to her. (And I use the word 'immediate' in the sense that we see each
other right now.) But let me say that in doing so I have very great hesi-
tation - and would like to cover my head with a cloth as Socrates did
when he spoke with Phaedrus about most difficult matters. Let me
begin by quoting her words which set the context of the problem:
I may say that never at any moment in my life have I sought for God - I do
not like this expression and it strikes me as false. As soon as I reached
adolescence I saw the problem of God as a problem of which the data
could not be obtained here below, and I decided that the only way of
being sure not to reach a wrong solution, which seemed to me the great-
est possible evil, was to leave it alone. So I left it alone. I neither affirmed
nor denied anything. It seemed to me useless to solve the problem, for I
thought that being in this world, our business was to adopt the best atti-
tude with regard to the problems of this world.
Let me read you one extract about these events. In doing so one
must remember it is part of an account written to an intimate friend
which she never thought would pass beyond him.
In 1937 I had two marvellous days at Assisi. There, alone in the little
twelfth-century Romanesque chapel of Santa Maria degli Angeli, an
incomparable marvel of purity where Saint Francis often used to pray,
something stronger than I was compelled me for the first time in my life
to go down on my knees.
In 1938 I spent ten days at Solesmes, from Palm Sunday to Easter Tues-
day, following all the liturgical services. I was suffering from splitting
headaches; each sound hurt me like a blow; by an extreme effort of atten-
tion I was able to rise above this wretched flesh, and leave it to suffer by
itself, heaped up in a corner, and to find a pure and perfect joy in the
unimaginable beauty of the chanting and the words. This experience
enabled me by analogy to get a better understanding of the possibility of
loving divine love in the midst of affliction. It goes without saying that in
the course of these services the thought of the Passion of Christ entered
into my being once and for all.
242 Thinking Their Thoughts
There was a young English Catholic there from whom I gained my first
idea of the supernatural power of the Sacraments because of the truly
angelic radiance with which he seemed to be clothed after going to com-
munion. Chance - for I always prefer saying chance rather than Provi-
dence - made of him a messenger to me. For he told me of the existence
of those English poets of the seventeenth century who are named meta-
physical. In reading them later on, I discovered the poem of which I read
you what is unfortunately a very inadequate translation. It is called Love. I
learnt it by heart. Often, at the culminating point of a violent headache, I
make myself say it over, concentrating all my attention upon it and cling-
ing with all my soul to the tenderness it enshrines. I used to think I was
merely reciting it as a beautiful poem, but without my knowing it the reci-
tation had the virtue of a prayer. It was during one of these recitations
that, as I told you, Christ himself came down and took possession of me.
In my arguments about the insolubility of the problem of God I had
never foreseen the possibility of that, of a real contact, person to person,
here below, between a human being and God. I had vaguely heard tell of
things of this kind, but I had never believed in them. In the Fioretti the
accounts of apparitions rather put me off if anything, like the miracles in
the Gospel. Moreover, in this sudden possession of me by Christ, neither
my senses nor my imagination had any part; I only felt in the midst of my
suffering the presence of a love, like that which one can read in the smile
on a beloved face.
I had never read any mystical works because I had never felt any call to
read them. In reading as in other things I have always striven to practise
obedience. There is nothing more favourable to intellectual progress, for
as far as possible I only read what I am hungry for, at the moment when I
have the appetite for it, and then I do not read, I eat. God in his mercy
had prevented me from reading the mystics, so that it should be evident
to me that I had not invented this absolutely unexpected contact.
Yet I still half refused, not my love but my intelligence. For it seemed to
me certain, and I still think so to-day, that one can never wrestle enough
with God if one does so out of pure regard for the truth. Christ likes us to
prefer truth to him because, before being Christ, he is truth. If one turns
aside from him to go towards the truth, one will not go far before falling
into his arms.
and discuss with me in detail what she has said about affliction and the
beauty of the world in her notebooks. Let me also say that I think that
official, institutional Christianity has been quite right in being so
firmly suspicious of those claims to direct contact which we call mysti-
cism, because of the obvious and manifold abuses to which they may
lead. But when it happens, I am sure it happens, and I am convinced it
happened here.
To turn from these absurd little comments of mine, I will now
describe her published writings. First, I must mention several compli-
cations in sorting them out, which make it difficult to approach her
thought at all or to understand it as a consistent whole. These stem
from the fact that the most important of her writings were written in
notebooks for her own purposes, not those of publication, and have
only seen the light of published day since her death and under the edi-
torial hands of other people. The comparison can be made between
her writings and Pascal's Pensees. After 1945 her friends in the south of
France, Monsieur Gustave Thibon and Father Perrin, published some
of the manuscripts she had left in their hands. Thibon produced Grav-
ity and Grace, a set of extracts from her notebooks; Perrin, Waiting on
God, which are her letters to him and certain of her essays. These pub-
lications by her Catholic friends presented a particular difficulty.
When they appeared in France they were met by the highest adulation.
French writers of all kinds - whether believers or not - heralded them
as the work of genius. In this fact Catholics were faced with an inevita-
ble ambiguity. Here was a writer of clear genius and one who had
entered the heights of the Christian life, and yet who had unequivo-
cally and at great length stated that obedience did not call her to mem-
bership in the Catholic Church - indeed one who had written
penetrating attacks on the form of the Church and some of its most
authoritative teaching.
She remained, she has told us, at the intersection of Christianity and
everything that is not Christianity: all the ancient wisdom of mankind
of the Enlightenment that the Church had repudiated and excluded,
the traditions banned as heretical, even the limited goods that resulted
from what we hypostatize of the Renaissance. T remain beside them all
the more,' she wrote to Father Perrin, 'because my own intelligence is
numbered among them.' In her eyes the Church fails as a perfect
incarnation of Christianity mainly because it is not truly Catholic. 'So
many things are outside it - so many things that God loves - Christian-
ity being Catholic by right but not in fact, I regard it as legitimate on
Simone Weil 245
her adult life as a labourer, her writings are voluminous. Since the end
of the war this immense mass of material has been brought out by the
French presses. Let me say that many of the theologians who have writ-
ten books or articles about her have singled out certain aspects of her
thought at the expense of others and therefore have interpreted her
totality in a very limited way. Some of the descriptions of her in Ameri-
can journals could only have been written by people whose reading
had been to say the least partial. There is such a desire on the part of
scholars these days to get into print that they sometimes write about
that of which they do not know enough.
For the sake of clarity I will divide her writings into two main classes:
her political and social writings and her philosophical, scientific, and
religious writings. Obviously this division is arbitrary because each
depends on the other.
There are three main books about politics and society. First, L'Enra-
cinement (The Need for Roots). (In giving an English title, I am not imply-
ing any lack of French in my audience, but simply stating that there is
an English translation of the work. Where there is no translation I will
give only one title.) This is the only book that she wrote for a public
purpose — indeed her only book which is not a collection of pieces. It
was written as a report for the Free French government in London as
to the principles on which French society should be based after the
war. It is divided into three sections: (a) the needs of the soul in any
society, (b) the cause of modern uprootedness, and (c) the possibility
of enrootedness in advanced industrial society. By 'uprootedness' she
means what Marx means by alienation, but uses it in a wider context
because she has a fuller understanding than him of the demonic
aspects of bureaucracy. This is the least absolute of her books
because it was written as a report to practical men, who knew they
would soon have responsibility for the reconstruction of a conquered
society. Second, Oppression et Liberte (Oppression and Liberty). This group
of essays is in my opinion her most remarkable writing about politics,
and is a good place to start the study of her thought. Albert Camus
also thought it was one of the masterpieces of European political phi-
losophy. At its centre is a long essay called 'Reflections on the causes
of liberty and social oppression,' which is at base an understanding
not only of the causes of social oppression in general, but of the par-
ticular forms of oppression which arise in societies which are oriented
to the future, that is, which are progressive. This volume also con-
tains her amazing critique of marxism. I must emphasize that this crit-
Simone Weil 247
language, try and read some of her in French.) This I think is the
most remarkable but the most difficult of all her writings. What are all
these notebooks about, taken as a whole? They are a sustained com-
mentary on what she has been thinking, reading, and experiencing.
She continually returns to such themes as the history of philosophy,
the nature of ethics and religion, the Indian writings and Christian
scriptures, northern and ancient mythology, French literature, the
worship of the future, mathematics, physics, art, war, work, industrial-
ism, and sexuality. Perhaps if one were to single out one subject that
more than any other binds the whole together one could put it in
her own words: T am ceaselessly and increasingly torn both in my
intelligence and in the depth of my heart through my inability to con-
ceive simultaneously and in truth, the affliction of men, the perfec-
tion of God and the link between the two.' Or, in other of her words:
'As Plato said, an infinite distance separates the good from necessity
- the essential contradiction in human life is that man, with a strain-
ing after the good constituting his very being, is at the same time sub-
ject in his entire being, both in mind and in flesh, to a blind force, to
a necessity completely indifferent to the good.' This contradiction
above any other is for her the means by which the mind is led to
truth. I quote again:
Karl Rahner (1904-84), German-born theologian who played a key role in the reforms
of the Second Vatican Council. His thought was deeply influenced by Martin Heideg-
ger.
252 Thinking Their Thoughts
mass. The rational creatures who do not love God are only fragments of
the compact and dense mass. They also are fully obedient, but only in
the manner of a stone which is falling. Their souls are matter, psychic
matter, subject to a mechanism as inexorable as gravity. Even their belief
in their own free will, the illusions of their pride, their defiances, their
rebellions, are, simply, phenomena as strictly determined as the refrac-
tion of light. Considered in this way, as inert matter, the worst criminals
are part of the order of the world, and for that reason, part of the beauty
of the world. Everything obeys God; everything is therefore, perfectly
beautiful.
This universal love belongs only to the contemplative faculty of the
soul. He who truly loves God leaves to each part of his soul its proper
function. Below the faculty of supernatural contemplation is found the
part of the soul that responds to obligation, and for which the opposition
of good and evil must have as much meaning as possible. Below this, is
the animal part of the soul, which must be carefully instructed by a skillful
combination of whip-lashes and lumps of sugar.
George Grant, review of Simone. Weil by Simone Petrement, trans. Raymond Rosenthal
(Random House 1977), Globe and Mail, 12 February 1977, 43.
Simone Weil 255
The Republic is, at the least, a drama about how Socrates cures Plato's
brother of righteous anger. I need to remember the benefits of that
cure in reviewing this book. Dr Coles has written a book about Simone
Weil in the Radcliffe Biography series. He is a professor of psychiatry at
the Harvard Medical School. His book is in a biography series but is in
* George Grant, 'In Defence of Simone Weil,' The. Idler, no. 15 (January - February 1988),
36—40, in response to Robert Coles, Simone. Weil: A Modern Pilgrimage (Reading, Mass.:
Addison-Wesley 1987).
Simone Weil 257
but rather with what had been continually rejected by official Western
Christianity.
Apart from these comments about the history of religions, it is
necessary to touch upon the particular details of 'her Jewishness.' I am
hesitant to do so, because the details of the lives of thinkers are unim-
portant compared to the universal truths in which they participate. But
sanctity is not the same thing as philosophy, and in describing sanctity,
details matter. Coles writes of these details in such a way as to impugn
that sanctity. Also, the relation between Weil and her parents is one of
the tender parts of her greatness, and it is discussed by Coles with a sin-
gular lack of feeling. He writes of the hurt to her family when she left
Judaism. I talked to Mme Weil at length about this matter. I cannot
speak about Dr Weil because I did not meet him, but Mme Weil had
obviously been very attached to her husband, and therefore had some
right to speak of his opinions. Mme Weil came from a family which had
moved west from Russia under the influence of the Enlightenment.
Paris was after all the centre of that movement, and of the revolution
that had attempted to realize its ends politically. She belonged to the
France that believed that human freedom required putting away the
superstitions of religion, whether those of Christianity or of Judaism.
She early recognized that she had produced two remarkable children.
(Her son, Andre Weil, is considered in many quarters to be the greatest
mathematician of this century.) She loved the greatness in her daugh-
ter, and devoted herself to protecting Simone from its consequences. It
was not always easy. When Simone Weil had Trotsky to stay with her
family, her mother accepted this because her daughter's 'left-wing'
opinions seemed only an extension of her particular brand of modern
French nationalism. Like many of her generation, Mme Weil had
learned to loathe war between 1914 and 1918, particularly from her
connection with the wounded patients of her husband, who served the
French army as a doctor during the first great massacre. Being a decent
rationalist, she had thought of herself as French without any religion.
It was almost inconceivable to her to find suddenly that the racism of
the gutter had come to power in Germany in 1933. This was a common
experience of many progressive Western Europeans. Gershom Scho-
lem has described it well in his autobiography. Something had come
to be in their midst, which they did not identify with a Western country
Gershom Scholem, From Berlin toJerusalem, trans. Harry Zohn (New York: Scholem Books
1980).
Simone Weil 261
That was not the act of somebody who had been wounded by her
daughter's acceptance of Christ. I have before me Mme Weil's
account, in her own handwriting, of when and where her daughter
wrote the 'Prologue,' in which she describes how Christ came to her.
Mme Weil wrote it out for me, because there had been some historical
confusion as to when the event had occurred. It cuts across what Coles
has written about Simone Weil having wounded her parents. It is a
document of lucidity and joy. Any confusion she may have experi-
enced by having brought into the world this eagle was utterly subordi-
nated to her acceptance that her daughter had been visited in the
flesh directly by Christ.
The silliest thing in Coles's book is what he writes about her letter to
Xavier Vallat, who had the appalling title of Commissioner of Jewish
Affairs in the Vichy government. Weil wrote that she could not get a
teaching job in Vichy because she was considered Jewish. She says that
it is irrational to consider her as Jewish because her intellectual tradi-
tions are entirely classical and French. Coles maintains that this was a
weaseling letter of a coward denying her Judaism at a time when Jews
were being persecuted. It is a long letter of ironic contempt from a
well-known Frenchwoman to a powerful man in a position that Weil
knew should not exist in any constitutional government. Of course,
such an extreme difference of interpretation could only be decided by
a long 'explication du texte,' which is not possible in a short review. Two
things can be said. 1. Could Weil possibly have expected to get a job
after writing such a letter? 2. Does Coles imply that Judaism is a given
that one cannot leave?
Petrement describes accurately the content of this letter: 'If in this
letter Simone boldly affirms that she doesn't consider herself a Jew, it
is not in order to disassociate herself in practice from the Jews - she
would not disassociate herself from anyone, above all not from people
being persecuted, and in Marseilles she did much to help Jews - nor in
any way to deny her origins; nor is it to affirm a religious conviction
that would have no interest for the Commissioner of Jewish Affairs.
Instead, she did this in order to emphasize again the difficulty of defin-
ing the word Jew,' and to show quite clearly that she does not under-
stand its significance and considers the statute concerning the Jews
absurd and incomprehensible.'
Of course, the high style of irony is hardly the forte of Americans.
The public spirits of the United States are capitalism, imperialism,
and a certain form of democracy. Irony is too high a style to be conso-
Simone Weil 263
nant with any of these spirits. The mordant wit that suggests contra-
diction requires too great an attention for that swift-moving society.
American-popularized Freudianism has not added to the capacity for
irony. This book is indeed a warning to those who write about any
'kalos kagathos from the position of superiority. One is apt to expose
oneself.
Of course, Coles has the right and perhaps the duty to defend Juda-
ism. (I use 'perhaps' because I do not know whether he is a Jew. If he
is, he obviously has the duty to defend Judaism.) Catholics have the
right and the duty to defend Western Christianity against Weil's criti-
cism of it. But the combination of the defence of Judaism with the
patronizing tones of the Harvard Medical School is repellent. I am
sure that the theologians of Judaism (for example, the Roth brothers
in England) have a lot to say about where Judaism is correct and
Simone Weil is wrong. Theological debate does not sit well with psychi-
atric imputation as to motive. Beyond matters of debate, it is absurd to
impugn the courage of this undaunted woman.
Enough about this book. As Simone Weil's writings are largely in the
form of notebooks and essays, it is hard to find one's way into them.
Therefore I hope it will not seem impertinent to mention means of
doing so. Simone Petrement's biography is much the best. Before
sanctity one can either be silent or matter-of-fact. Petrement's life is
astringent French scholarship at its best. Theoretical comprehension is
of course easier than writing about sanctity. For such comprehension,
M. Veto's La Metaphysique Religieuse de Simone Weil is the most careful
among many good books. As Professor Veto is now at Yale, it is to be
hoped that his book will be translated into English.^
The centre of what Simone Weil writes is something that human
beings must learn for themselves in the terror of thought and prayer.
To read her sentence 'matter is our infallible judge' is to understand
what Christ meant when he said, T come not with peace but with a
sword.' At a more theoretical and exoteric level, at a less immediate
and therefore more palatable level, she is saying something about what
is happening in the Western world. She returns continually to Plato's
statement: 'How great is the real difference between necessity and the
good' (Republic, 493c).
Noble and good (Greek).
M Veto. La Metaphysique religieuse de Simone. We.il (Paris: J. Urin 1971). As Grant hoped,
the book was published in English: The Religious Metaphysics of Simone Weil (Albany, N.Y.:
State University of New York Press 1994).
264 Thinking Their Thoughts
NOTES
1 'The account written for herself. '-This is published in Simone Petrement's La Vie
de Simone Weil (Simone Weil: A Life); in the French, vol. 2: 11-14; in the Ameri-
can translation, 219-22. It must be said that the American translation is often
poor. In this passage,''jouissance is translated as 'pleasure.' If possible, it is well
to read it in French, especially when it comes to Weil's own words. She wrote
the most luminous of Western languages with a clarity that is breathtaking.
Nothing seems to stand between the words and what they are about.
2 'Her letter to Xavier Vallat.' - For the letter in full, see Petrement's Life; in
the French, vol. 2: 377-9; in the English translation, 443-4.
King of fearful majesty (Latin), from the 'Dies Irae,' a thirteenth-century hymn used in
masses for the dead.
266 Thinking Their Thoughts
I have read and re-read The City and Man. I wonder if sometime you were free I
could come to Chicago and take a very short bit of your time to ask you two
questions. It would not be in the immediate future, as the questions about
Socrates and the Christian tradition I have not yet properly formulated. The
other question is concerning Aristotle and Plato's dialogues. I must express to
you again my enormous sense of gratitude for every word you have written.
- George Grant to Leo Strauss, 21 January 1965
In reissuing an old book of mine I tried to pay you a compliment in a new intro-
duction. I am enclosing my words on another page because my sense of debt is
so great.
- George Grant to Leo Strauss, 25 April 1966
It was through Straus that I came upon Kojeve. Let me say that I think Doull
knows more about Strauss than Kojeve (not having written much, Doull is only
known to his friends.) It was to escape Hegel I found Strauss & through Strauss
I found Kojeve.
Let me say also that although my debt to Strauss is great as a teacher of what
makes up modernity; Simone Weil is the being whose thought is to me the
enrapturing ... I can imagine being capable of writing something as perceptive
& lucid as Strauss, but I cannot imagine loving God & being possessed by Christ
as S.W. was.
- George Grant to Joan O'Donovan, 25 January 1981
Leo Strauss and Alexandra Kojeve 267
I have for quite awhile believed that one of the deepest strands in Strauss's writ-
ing about Plato has been to criticize the long hold of Xian Platonism in the
western and eastern interpretation of Plato. He has done this wisely & with no
foolishly polemical spirit. I have wanted to write about this, but have been held
back because I see no good purpose served (as he did not) in emphasizing
these days the difference between Jews & Xians. As he saw clearly it stems from
the deep difference concerning the nature (I mean more than the content) of
divine revelation. He was deeper & wiser about this than some of his epigones.
I may write about this someday, but fairly indirectly.
- George Grant to Ed Andrew, 27 December 1983
'Tyranny and Wisdom,' in Technology and Empire (Toronto: House of Anansi 1964), 82-
96. Used with permission.
268 Thinking Their Thoughts
of a science that issues in the conquest of nature and the belief in the
possibility of the popularization of philosophy and science. Both these
possibilities were known to the ancient philosophers. 'But the classics
rejected them as "unnatural." i.e., as destructive of humanity. They did
not dream of present day tyranny because they regarded its basic pre-
suppositions as so preposterous that they turned their imaginations in
entirely different directions.' In terms of this historical assertion, both
Strauss's affirmations can be made. Classical political science was not
familiar with modern tyranny, but it was familiar with the assumptions
which distinguish it from antique tyranny. Strauss is obviously asserting
the classical view that tyranny is a form of government common to all
ages and that the political philosopher can have knowledge of what is
common to these governments of disparate ages so that he can cor-
rectly call each of them tyrannies. The contemporary social scientist
may criticize such a position, but his disagreement is a philosophical
one. It does not arise from an obvious mistake about the facts on
Strauss's part.
It is difficult to know where to plunge into the controversy. Such
uncertainty is inevitable once the incipient political philosopher has
recognized that his study cannot avoid being metaphysical and that
therefore he must try to learn from those who can think more widely
and consistently than himself. For whatever else may be said about the
philosophers who related their doctrine on political matters to their
desire to have knowledge of the whole, among the best of them there
has been a monumental consistency which related their doctrine on
one issue to what they taught on all others. Both Strauss and Kojeve
have studied the masters with great care and therefore know in detail
the political teachings of the metaphysicians. They are both aware of
the wide extent to which the difference between classical and Hegelian
political teaching involves a difference of doctrine on nearly every
major issue of political theory. Indeed to state the obvious, the contro-
versy implies throughout a difference of opinion about the object and
method of philosophy, in the more than political sense of that word. I
do not want simply to check off these differences in detail, yet on the
other hand I do not feel competent to define the central principles
which divide classical from Hegelian metaphysics. For these reasons I
take the plunge into the controversy at the point of a concrete political
teaching.
Kojeve affirms that the universal and homogeneous state is the best
social order and that mankind advances to the establishment of such
270 Thinking Their Thoughts
It is the idea of the fundamental equality of all those who believe in a single
God. This transcendental conception of social equality differs radically
from the Socratic-Platonic conception of the identity of beings having the
same immanent 'essence.' For Alexander, a disciple of the Greek philoso-
phers, the Hellene and the Barbarian have the same title to political citi-
zenship in the Empire, to the extent that they have the same human
(moreover, rational, logical, discursive) 'nature' (=essence, idea, form
etc.) or are 'essentially' identified with each other as the result of a direct
(='immediate') 'mixture' of their innate qualities (realized by mean of
biological union.) For St Paul there is no 'essential' (irreducible) differ-
ence between the Greek and the Jew because they both can become
Christians, and this is not by 'mixing' their Greek and Jewish 'qualities,'
but by negating them both and 'synthesizing' them in and by this very
negation into a homogeneous unity not innate or given, but (freely) cre-
ated by 'conversion.' Because of the negating character of the Christian
'synthesis,' there are no longer any incompatible 'qualities,' or 'contra-
dictory' (=mutually exclusive) 'qualities.' For Alexander, a Greek philoso-
pher, there was no possible mixture of Masters and Slaves, for they were
'opposites.' Thus his universal State, which did away with race, could not
be homogeneous in the sense that it would equally do away with 'class.' For
St Paul on the contrary, the negation (active to the extent that 'faith' is an
act, being 'dead' without 'acts') of the opposition between the pagan Mas-
Leo Strauss and Alexandra Kojeve 271
Men will have very good reasons for being dissatisfied with the universal
and homogeneous state. To show this, I must have recourse to Kojeve's
more extensive exposition in his Introduction a la kcture de Hegel. There are
degrees of satisfaction. The satisfaction of the humble citizen, whose
human dignity is universally recognized and who enjoys all opportunities
that correspond to his humble capacities and achievements, is not com-
parable to the satisfaction of the Chief of State. Only the Chief of State is
'really satisfied.' He alone is 'truly free' (146). Did Hegel not say some-
thing to the effect that the state in which one man is free is the Oriental
despotic state? Is the universal and homogeneous state then merely a
planetary Oriental despotism? However this may be, there is no guaran-
tee that the incumbent Chief of State deserves his position to a higher
degree than others. Those others then have a very good reason for dissat-
isfaction: a state which treats equal men unequally is not just. A change
from the universal-homogeneous monarchy into a universal-homoge-
neous aristocracy would seem to be reasonable. But we cannot stop here.
The universal and homogeneous state, being the synthesis of the Masters
and the Slaves, is the state of the working warrior or of the war-waging
worker. In fact, all its members are warrior workers (114, 116). But if the
state is universal and homogeneous, 'wars and revolutions are henceforth
impossible' (145, 561). Besides, work in the strict sense, namely the con-
quest or domestication of nature, is completed, for otherwise the univer-
sal and homogenous state could not be the basis for wisdom (301). Of
course, work of a kind will still go on, but the citizens of the final state will
work as little as possible, as Kojeve notes with explicit reference to Marx
(435). To borrow an expression which someone used recently in the
House of Lords on a similar occasion, the citizens of the final state are
only so-called workers, workers by courtesy, 'There is no longer fight nor
work. History has come to its end. There is nothing more to do1 (114,
385). This end of History would be most exhilarating but for the fact that,
according to Kojeve, it is the participation in bloody political struggles as
276 Thinking Their Thoughts
well as in real work or, generally expressed, the negating action, which
raises man above the brutes (378n., 490-492, 560). The state through
which man is said to become reasonably satisfied is, then, the state in
which the basis of man's humanity withers away, or in which man loses his
humanity.10
Here again one sees the combination of Strauss's two purposes. The
showing forth of the classical position as consistent combines with the
description of modern theory as including assumptions which are
Leo Strauss and Alexandre Kojeve 277
It seems reasonable to assume that only a few, if any, citizens of the uni-
versal and homogeneous state will be wise. But neither the wise men nor
the philosophers will desire to rule. For this reason alone, to say nothing
of others, the Chief of the universal and homogeneous state, or the Uni-
versal and Final Tyrant, will be an unwise man, as Kojeve seems to take for
granted. To retain his power, he will be forced to suppress every activity
which might lead people into doubt of the essential soundness of the uni-
versal and homogeneous state: he must suppress philosophy as an
attempt to corrupt the young. In particular he must in the interest of the
homogeneity of his universal state forbid every teaching, every sugges-
tion, that there are politically relevant natural differences among men
which cannot be abolished or neutralized by progressing scientific tech-
nology. He must command his biologists to prove that every human being
has, or will acquire, the capacity of becoming a philosopher or a tyrant.
The philosophers in their turn will be forced to defend themselves or the
cause of philosophy. They will be obliged, therefore, to try to act on the
Tyrant. Everything seems to be a re-enactment of the age-old drama. But
this time, the cause of philosophy is lost from the start. For the Final
Tyrant presents himself as a philosopher, as the highest philosophic
authority, as the supreme exegete of the only true philosophy, as the
executor and hangman authorized by the only true philosophy. He
claims therefore that he persecutes not philosophy but false philoso-
phers. The experience is not altogether new for philosophers. If philoso-
phers were confronted with claims of this kind in former ages, philosophy
went underground. It accommodated itself in its explicit or exoteric
teaching to the unfounded commands of rulers who believed they knew
things which they did not know. Yet its very exoteric teaching under-
mined the commands or dogmas of the rulers in such a way as to guide
the potential philosophers toward the eternal and unsolved problems.
And since there was no universal state in existence, the philosophers
could escape to other countries if life became unbearable in the tyrant's
278 Thinking Their Thoughts
NOTES
1 L. Strauss, What Is Political Philosophy1? (Glencoe, 111.: The Free Press 1959).
In the English version of the essay, Strauss has cut out certain passages
included in the earlier French version. These deletions do not radically
change the English version. I regret them, however, because their inclu-
sion in the French argument does bring out some of the implications in
the controversy.
2 What an author has written at one place is inevitably illumined by what he
has written at another. It is therefore impossible to write of Strauss or
Kojeve without having in mind their other writings. Nevertheless, in this
paper I will stick as much as possible to their writing about Hiero. When
their doctrine about a particular matter is taken from elsewhere, this will
be made clear in the notes.
3 On Tyranny, 1.
4 What Is Political Philosophy ? 96
5 On Tyranny, 2.
6 Ibid., 1.
7 What Is Political Philosophy? 96
8 Ibid., 273-4. The English translation of Kojeve's essay has been made by
Michael Gold. This translation has now been published with Strauss's writ-
ings on the matter. (L. Strauss, On Tyranny, revised and enlarged, Glencoe:
The Free Press 1963).
9 That the first purpose of Strauss's argument is to stress the consistency
between all aspects of classical philosophy might well have been made
clearer. The difficulty of understanding his purpose is indeed increased for
English readers by the fact that he does not include in the English edition
of his work the last paragraph of the French edition, in which his purposes
are beautifully described. Elsewhere in his writings Strauss has criticized
historicism in its late-nineteenth-century form and shown the conse-
Friedrich Nietzsche 279
Before the 1950s Friedrich Nietzsche was little known in the English-speaking
world. His writings had been celebrated by the Nazis and this taint delayed the
reception of his thought into North American academic circles. Grant's Time as
History was broadcast originally as the CBC Massey Lectures for 1969. In
them Grant praised Nietzsche's philosophy, assigning it a central place in the
history of Western thought and declaring Nietzsche to be the thinker who had
thought most profoundly about the character of modern civilization as techno-
logical. Publication of the lectures was delayed by a near-fatal car crash in
which Grant was seriously injured. Consequently, Grant's work has not received
the attention it deserved, though it has inspired several studies of Nietzsche,
mainly by Canadian political scientists.
Lately I have been reading Nietsche (?). To say that he is completely misun-
derstood by most people would be an absurd understatement. To say that he is
the forerunner to such bestiality and cruelty as the Nazis is absurd. 'I love he
whose soul is deep even for wounding and whom a slight matter may destroy.'
'Pity is the cross upon which he is nailed who loveth mankind.' That kind of
thing is not like what he is supposed to be. He uses the theory of 'the blond
animal' in utter derision yet people say that that is the basis of Nazidom.
- George Grant to Maude Grant, 14 November 1939
There is no doubt that for Plato the only rival to be taken seriously to philoso-
phy is tragic and comic poetry, and the very heart of his writings is trying to
show that philosophy takes you to the heart beyond tragic and comic poetry. In
the modern era, it seems that the rival to philosophy becomes modern physics,
but it is the supreme genius of Nietzsche to see that in what he considers the
death of philosophy, what arises in its place for the greatest men is a new kind
of tragic and comic poetry.
- George Grant to Dennis Lee, 10 June 1974
George Grant, Time as History, ed. William Christian (Toronto: University of Toronto
Press 1995), 57-69. Used with permission.
Friedrich Nietzsche 281
*In this selection, the material in square brackets has been restored to the original pub-
lished text from the broadcast typescript.
284 Thinking Their Thoughts
ferent from what has been affirmed about morality in the last centu-
ries. The attempt to argue for my propositions would require a very
close historical analysis of how the use of such words as 'desire' and
'reason' have changed over the last centuries. It would require, for
example, what the ancients meant by 'passion.' Whatever the differ-
ences between what has come to us from Plato and from Christianity,
on this central point there is commonness. The height for man could
only come forth out of a 'passion.' Yet in using such a word, the enor-
mous difficulty of thinking outside the modern account can be seen.
When we use the word 'pathetic' we may be thinking of a defeated
character in a movie [like Ratso in Midnight Cowboy], or the perfor-
mance of the quarterback for the Hamilton Tiger Cats football team
this season. [As for the word suffering, that means simply pain, which
sensible men have always wished to avoid.] The word 'passion' has
come to be limited for us to little more than an emotion of driving
force, particularly intense sexual excitement. [The experiences of
receptivity having dropped from our vocabulary, we think of art and
thought and morality quite differently. We talk of what the artist does
as creation, not as imitation, a begetting on the beautiful.] To say that
philosophy arises from the suffering of astonishment would bear no
relation to our present understanding of thought, because the arche-
type of thought is now that science that frames instrumental hypothe-
ses and tests them in experiment, a kind of willing. How can we think
of 'morality' as a desiring attention to perfection, when for the last
centuries the greatest moral philosophers have written of it as self-
legislation, the willing of our own values? Therefore, my affirmations
in the previous paragraph use language in a way that can hardly be
appropriated. [As an example of the poverty of modern language, let
me say how partial it is to speak of Tolstoy as creating War and Peace, or
Mozart his piano concertos. The disappearance of the words of recep-
tivity, the words of passion, from the modern account of thought,
shows what a wide separation there is between the ancient and the
modern. It clarifies what it means to say that modern thinking is always
a kind of willing. Because we are always surrounded in every conscious
minute of our lives by the modern conception of thought, we cannot
take what is given to us from the past as intelligible. If we take it at all,
we take it more and more as sheerly arbitrary. Therefore, fewer and
fewer people can appropriate it.]
Indeed, beyond this, there is a further turn of the screw for anybody
who would assert that amor fati is the height, yet cannot understand
Friedrich Nietzsche 285
how that height could be achievable outside the vision of our fate as
enfolded in a timeless eternity. The destruction of the idea of such an
eternity has been at the centre of the modern project in the very scien-
tific and technical mastery of chance. As a great contemporary, Leo
Strauss, has written in What Is Political Philosophy: 'Oblivion of eternity,
or, in other words, estrangement from man's deepest desire and there-
with from the primary issues, is the price that modern man had to pay,
from the very beginning, for attempting to be absolutely sovereign, to
become the master and owner of nature, to conquer chance.' And the
turn of the screw is that to love fate must obviously include loving the
fate that makes us part of the modern project; it must include loving
that which has made us oblivious of eternity - that eternity without
which I cannot understand how it would be possible to love fate.
To put the matter simply: any appeal to the past must not be made
outside a full recognition of the present. Any use of the past that insu-
lates us from living now is cowardly, trivializing, and at worst despair-
ing. Antiquarianism can be used like most other drugs as mind
contracting. If we live in the present we must know that we live in a civ-
ilization, the fate of which is to conceive time as history. Therefore, as
living now, the task of thought among those held by something that
cannot allow them to make the complete 'yes' to time as history, is not
to inoculate themselves against their present, but first to enter what is
thought in that present.
What has happened in the West since 1945 concerning the thought
of Marx is an example of inoculation. Our chief rival empire has been
ruled by men who used Marx's doctrine as their official language,
while we used an earlier form of modernity, the liberalism of capitalist
democracy. The thought of Marx, therefore, appeared as a threaten-
ing and subverting disease. The intellectual industry in our multiversi-
ties produced a spate of refutations of Marx. Most of these, however,
were written with the purpose of inoculating others against any conta-
gion, rather than with thinking the thoughts that Marx had thought.
These books have not prevented the reviving influence of Marx's
thought among many of the brightest young, anymore than the official
marxism of the East has been able to stop the influence of existential-
ism among its young elites. [Why? Marx's thought abides because he
thought some of what is happening in the modern world. His writings
could therefore help other men to think about what was happening.
What we were doing in Vietnam seemed to be explained by marxism.]
Men may have to attempt this inoculation if they are concerned with
286 Thinking Their Thoughts
must have been pressed upon him) what had been given him about
the unfathomable goodness of the whole, from his good fortune in
having partaken in a tradition of reverence. In the inadequate modern
equivalent for reverence and tradition, his remark might be called
'religious.'
In an age when the primacy of the will, even in thinking, destroys
the varied forms of reverence, they must come to us, when and if they
come, from out of tradition. 'Tradition' means literally a handing
over; or, as it once meant, a surrender. The man who was dying was in
his remark surrendering to me his recollection of what had been sur-
rendered to him, from the fortune that had been his, in having lived
within a remembered reverence - in his case, Christianity. [He surren-
dered to me the affirmation that the whole is in some unfathomable
sense good. The absurdities of time, indeed also its joys as well as its
diremptions, are to be taken not simply as history but as enfolded in a
meaning (call it if you will a transcendence) that is beyond potential-
ity, that is beyond change. I do not imply that what is handed over in
tradition must be in conflict with reason or experience. The belief that
reason and tradition are at loggerheads is only a product of modern
thought. It comes from the doctrine of progress, that the race as a
whole is becoming increasingly open to reason by shuffling off its irra-
tional past. The traditions that came to us from Athens and Jerusalem
claim to be, in the main, reasonable, but what was handed over in
them is now accepted, if accepted at all, less and less as thought-filled
because it is so assailed by the modern account of reason, and all of us
are increasingly enclosed by that modern account. The core of the his-
tory of the last three hundred years has been the criticism of the
ancient account of thought and the coming to be of the new account.
As that criticism has publicly succeeded what comes to us from the past
is received as unintelligible, as simply arbitrary.] In the presence of
death, my friend had collected out of that remembrance an assertion
for me that stated how he transcended conceiving time as history.
By distinguishing remembering from thinking, I do not imply that
this collecting was unthoughtful, but that what this man had there col-
lected could not have been entirely specified in propositions. For
nearly everyone (except perhaps for the occasional great thinkers)
there is no possibility of entirely escaping that which is given in the
public realm, and this increasingly works against the discovery of any
reverence. Therefore, those of us who at certain times look to grasp
something beyond history must search for it as the remembering of a
288 Thinking Their Thoughts
which it has carried to us. Individuals, even with the help of their pres-
ently faltering institutions, can grasp no more than very small seg-
ments of what is there. Nor (to repeat) should any dim apprehensions
of what was meant by perfection before the age of progress be used
simply as means to negate what may have been given us of truth and
goodness in this age. The present darkness is a real darkness, in the
sense that the enormous corpus of logistic and science of the last cen-
turies is unco-ordinate as to any possible relation it may have to those
images of perfection that are given us in the Bible and in philosophy.
We must not forget that new potentialities of reasoning and making
happen have been actualized (and not simply contemplated as mis-
trusted potentialities, as for example in Plato) and therefore must be
thought as having been actualized, in relation to what is remembered.
The conception of time as history is not to be discarded as if it had
never been.
It may be that at any time or place, human beings can be opened to
the whole in their loving and thinking, even as its complete intelligibil-
ity eludes them. If this be true of any time or place, then one is not,
after all, trapped in historicism. But now the way to intelligibility is
guarded by a more than usual number of ambiguities. Our present is
like being lost in the wilderness, when every pine and rock and bay
appears to us as both known and unknown, and therefore as uncertain
pointers on the way back to human habitation. The sun is hidden by
the cloud and the usefulness of our ancient compasses has been put in
question. Even what is beautiful - which for most men has been the
pulley to lift them out of despair - has been made equivocal for us
both in detail and definition. [The very bringing into being of our civi-
lization has put in question the older means of finding one's way, with-
out discovering new means for doing so. Nevertheless, it is also clear
that this very position of ambiguity in our civilization presents enor-
mous hope for thought, if not for life. The questions whether the mod-
ern project opens out new heights for man, or whether at its heart it
was a false turning for man, is so clearly before us. Questions that were
settled, and therefore closed over the last centuries, are now open to
us once again. Perhaps the essential question about the modern
project is not that of Nietzsche - Who deserve to be the masters of the
earth? - but the very question of mastery itself]
Nevertheless, those who cannot live as if time were history are called,
beyond remembering, to desiring and thinking. But this is to say very
little. For myself, as probably for most others, remembering only occa-
290 Thinking Their Thoughts
sionally can pass over into thinking and loving what is good. It is for
the great thinkers and the saints to do more.
The subject matter of this book is of central significance for those who
study political philosophy. Socrates is the primal figure for that
uniquely Western activity. More than any other modern thinker,
Nietzsche placed Socrates at the centre of Western history as the cre-
ator of rationalism, and claimed in his own thought to have overcome
that rationalism. Therefore, in Nietzsche's view of Socrates we are near
the centre of thinking about the nature of political philosophy. For
somebody from outside the U.S.A. (such as myself) it is a happiness to
find that a professor of government at Cornell should devote his
thought to so central a subject for our Western self-understanding.
I am even happier to say that Professor Dannhauser's book is very
well done. He has read Nietzsche's writings carefully and comprehen-
sively; he has also read the accounts of Socrates which are given us in
Plato, Xenophon, and Aristophanes. Because of the political and eco-
nomic conflicts between the English-speaking and German peoples in
the last generations, English-speakers have not paid sufficient atten-
tion to modern German philosophers - the greatest of whom is
Nietzsche. Now that Nietzsche is becoming powerful in our society
(particularly among the young) his influence often comes to us in the
form of a quick and one-sided apperception of his teachings. Indeed,
Nietzsche's enchanting (if terrible) rhetoric encourages that one-sid-
edness. Therefore, Dannhauser's care must be highly praised. He has
obviously read Nietzsche over many years and knows the extensive and
complex corpus intimately. This is a scholarly book in the best sense of
that term. The form of this book is to trace carefully Nietzsche's view
of Socrates from the early writings, when Nietzsche was taken up with
positivism and modern science, to the last writings where his final
encounter with Socrates is put before us. Dannhauser wisely leaves to a
separate chapter what Nietzsche says by implication about Socrates in
Thus Spoke Zarathustra. He treats with proper caution the endless irony
of the ambiguous speeches which largely make up that work.
'George Grant, review of Werner J. Dannhauser's Nietzsche's View of Socrates (Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press 1974), in American Political Science Review, vol. 71 (1977), 1127-9.
Friedrich Nietzsche 291
(c) Most important. In the last pages of his book, where he makes
clear that he is a follower of Socrates and not of Nietzsche, Dan-
nhauser writes: Nietzsche's 'critique of dogmatisms and systems may
hit Hegel, but it misses Socrates and Plato; and many of the attacks on
reason, rationality, and rationalism may hit Descartes, but they miss
Socrates and Plato' (p. 272). I wish Dannhauser had greatly expanded
this passage, and said why this is so. However difficult such questions
are, it is to be hoped that Dannhauser will turn to them in subsequent
writings. In this book he presents us with plenty of evidence that he is
capable of casting light on these extraordinarily complex issues.
Part II
George Grant, 'Nietzsche and the Ancients: Philosophy and Scholarship,' Dionysius 3
(December), 5-16 (reprinted in 1986).
294 Thinking Their Thoughts
Leo Strauss.
Friedrich Nietzsche 295
the rejection of Nietzsche? Is not this the very denial of that openness
to the whole which is the fundamental mark of the philosophic enter-
prise? Is it not to fall back into that dogmatic closedness which is one
form of enmity to philosophy? I will attempt to answer that by discuss-
ing Nietzsche's teaching concerning justice. As a political philosopher
within Christianity, my willingness to teach Nietzsche within an under-
standing of rejection, while at the same time I am not capable of the
complete refutation of his historicism, turns around my inability to
accept as true his account of justice. At least we need have no doubts as
to what Nietzsche's conception of justice is, and the consequences of
accepting it.
A caveat is necessary at this point in the argument. I am not making
the mistake that is prevalent in much condemnation of Nietzsche -
namely that there is no place for justice in his doctrine. His teaching
about justice is at the very core of what he is saying. To understand it is
as fundamental as to understand the teaching concerning 'the eternal
recurrence of the identical.' It is said unequivocally in a fragment writ-
ten in 1885, towards the end of his life as writer: 'It happened late that
I came upon what up to that time had been totally missing, namely jus-
tice. What is justice and is it possible? If it should not be possible, how
would life be supportable? This is what I increasingly asked myself.
Above all it filled me with anguish to find, when I delved into myself,
only violent passions, only private perspectives, only lack of reflection
about this matter. What I found in myself lacked the very primary con-
ditions for justice.'
This quotation does not give content to Nietzsche's conception of
justice. Its nature appears in two quotations from the unpublished
fragments of 1884. 'Justice as function of a power with all encircling
vision, which sees beyond the little perspectives of good and evil, and
so has a wider advantage, having the aim of maintaining something
which is more than this or that person.' Or again: 'Justice as the build-
ing, rejecting, annihilating way of thought which proceeds from the
appraisement of value: highest representative of life itself.'
What is the account of justice therein given? What is it to see
'beyond the little perspectives of good and evil'; to maintain 'some-
thing which is more than this or that person?' What is 'the building,
rejecting, annihilating way of thought?' What is being said here about
the nature of justice would require above all an exposition of why the
superman, when he is able to think the eternal recurrence of the iden-
tical, will be the only noble ruler for a technological age, and what he
296 Thinking Their Thoughts
must be ready to do to 'the last men' who will have to be ruled. That
exposition cannot be given in the space of an article. Suffice it to speak
popularly: what is given in these quotations is an account of justice as
the human creating of quality of life. And is it not clear by now what
are the actions which follow from such an account? It was not acciden-
tal that Nietzsche should write of 'the merciless extinction' of large
masses in the name of justice, or that he should have thought 'eugeni-
cal experimentation' necessary to the highest modern justice. And in
thinking of these consequences, one should not concentrate alone on
their occurrence during the worst German regime, which was luckily
beaten in battle. One should relate them to what is happening in the
present Western regimes. We all know that mass feticide is taking place
in our societies. We all should know the details of the eugenical exper-
imentation which is taking place in all the leading universities of the
Western world. After all, many of us are colleagues in those universi-
ties. We should be clear that the language used to justify such activities
is the language of the human creating of quality of life, beyond the lit-
tle perspectives of good and evil.
One must pass beyond an appeal to immediate consequences in
order to state what is being accepted with Nietzsche's historicist
account of justice. What does a proper conception of justice demand
from us in our dealings with others? Clearly there are differences here
between the greatest ancient and modern philosophers. The tradition
of political thought originating in Rousseau and finding different ful-
filments in Kant and Hegel demands a more substantive equality than
is asked in Plato or Aristotle. What Hegel said about the influence of
Christianity towards that change is indubitably true. But the difference
between the ancients and the moderns as to what is due to all human
beings should not lead us to doubt that in the rationalist traditions,
whether ancient or modern, something at least is due to all others,
whether we define them as rational souls or rational subjects. What-
ever may be given in Plato's attack on democracy in his Republic, it is
certainly not that for some human beings nothing is due. Indeed, to
understand Plato's account of justice, we must remember the relation
in his thought between justice and the mathematical conception of
equality.
In Nietzsche's conception of justice there are other human beings
to whom nothing is due — other than extermination. The human creat-
ing of quality of life beyond the little perspectives of good and evil by a
building, rejecting, annihilating way of thought is the statement that
Martin Heidegger 297
politics is the technology of making the human race greater than it has
yet been. In that artistic accomplishment, those of our fellows who
stand in the way of that quality can be exterminated or simply
enslaved. There is nothing intrinsic in all others that puts any given
limit on what we may do to them in the name of that great enterprise.
Human beings are so unequal in quality that to some of them no due is
owed. What gives meaning in the fact of historicism is that willed
potentiality is higher than any actuality. Putting aside the petty per-
spectives of good and evil means that there is nothing belonging to all
human beings which need limit the building of the future. Oblivion of
eternity is here not a liberal-aesthetic stance, which still allows men to
support regimes the principles of which came from those who had
affirmed eternity; oblivion of eternity here realizes itself politically.
One should not flirt with Nietzsche for the purposes of this or that
area of science or scholarship, but teach him in the full recognition
that his thought presages the conception of justice which more and
more unveils itself in the technological West.
NOTE
Grant considered Martin Heidegger the greatest philosopher of the twentieth cen-
tury. Heidegger's early masterpiece, Being and Time (1927), was the most
influential existentialist work. However, in the 1930s, Heidegger joined the Nazi
Party and his refusal to repudiate his membership after the war or to comment on
the Holocaust made him an extremely controversial figure. Grant first took an
interest in Heidegger in the late 1950s, but his meditations on Heidegger became
central to his thought after the translation into French of Heidegger's four-vol-
ume study on Nietzsche. Heidegger's writings on technology influenced much of
Grant's thinking on technology in the 1970s, and Grant returned to these vol-
umes when David Krell's English translation was published in the early 1980s.
At the time of his death, Grant had begun work on a book to defend Plato against
Heidegger's attack.
298 Thinking Their Thoughts
I have found in Martin Heidegger, the most famous of the German existential-
ists - indeed, the founder of existentialism as a philosophic movement - an
interpretation of Greek philosophy which is very similar to some of the remarks
I have been making this year. Not in his early works - but in his later works
which are only now becoming available. What he says at great length and great
subtlety is that Western thought has floated out upon a great tide of nihilism,
and the origin of that nihilism is what happened to philosophy somewhere
between the time of Parmenides and Plato. For Parmenides, being and aware-
ness were one, and according to Heidegger human existence was rooted in that
oneness; man was deep in Being, drew his life from the appearance of Being,
which was truly appearance, not illusion; for the being of Being was again at
one with Being, not the mere flux which modern interpretations of Heraclitus
have led us to think it was.
What he is saying is that all our traditional separations like subject/object,
substance/accident, etc. - in fact all the words we use to talk about philosophi-
cal problems - are so many veils over Being, so many chasms between ourselves
and Being. To understand the pre-Socratic insight we must penetrate far into
the first roots of our own language, cutting out all the deceiving growth of the
centuries. For the pre-Socratics, truth was what Heidegger calls the unhidden-
ness of Being.
- George Grant, notes for a lecture, Dalhousie 1958
I have been reading parts of Heidegger - what a master. Above all (in my
own way) I would like to write like that. He seems not to be writing about
things, but to summon up directly the things themselves, as if he was not
thinking about what others had thought about things, but about the things
themselves.
- George Grant to William Christian, 1982
I spend a great deal of life reading Heidegger. He is certainly the greatest phi-
losopher of the modern era. Perhaps with the collapse of Europe, because of
the last wars, he is the last philosopher, as philosophy is so essentially a western
phenomenon. He is, of course, an ultimately modern philosopher & if I can
summon the courage I would like to write an account of why his criticism of
Plato is not true. But I doubt that I will ever have the skill to do it. One thing
that makes it so difficult is that he is such a remarkable commentator on the
history of philosophy. Of all the great German philosophers he is the only one
who was by origin Catholic. If you ever feel any desire to read him, I think the
best way is either through his book on Leibniz The Principle of Reason or
through 'The Question concerning Technique.' I don't think Sein und Zeit is
the best because that is the classic account of existentialism & he spent the rest
of his life writing where he thought that inadequate.
- George Grant to Peter Self, 1987
For myself it is only in the last two decades that I have been ready to bring
Heidegger into my writings. He is, after all, a very consummate thinker and
also very prolific writer. It took me years to find the time to read H. compre-
hensively. The Nietzsche book is now the catalyst to write a longer piece
directly about him. Let me say clearly that H. must be for me a writer who ridi-
cules Christianity Sc therefore, to write about him is to say a great 'NO.' His
criticism of Plato is related to his ridicule of Christianity, but that is not of the
same centrality for me. His Nietzsche book has been a great catalyst for me as it
has come out in English.
- George Grant to John Siebert, 29 June 1988
Martin Heidegger, Nietzsche, ed. David Krell (San Francisco: Harper and Row 1979-87).
300 Thinking Their Thoughts
what technology is, and seen it with prodigious attention. I mean mod-
ern in the sense that there wasn't anything like what we call technology
in the ancient world. There was technique, and there were arts, but
technology is essentially a modern phenomenon, and it is to me the
overwhelming phenomenon. Heidegger expressed this in a marvelous
way when people asked him about capitalism and communism, and he
said that capitalism and communism are just predicates of the subject
technology. I think that is true. They make a difference; they are pred-
icates and they are very different predicates. One can speak very pro-
foundly against communism and, indeed, speak very profoundly
against capitalism and their different vices; but I think Heidegger has
seen that the essential event of Western civilization at its end is mod-
ern technology, which is now becoming worldwide.
Cayley: Heidegger, in a very beautiful passage, says that we're 'too late
for the gods and too early for being.' 'Being's poem, which is man,' he
says, 'has just begun.' So 'we must be claimed by being, we must be will-
ing to dwell in the nameless.' And this reminds me of your own insis-
tence that we must be willing to really experience the darkness of our
time, and listen for what you have called 'intimations of deprival.'
Grant I have to say that, for me, this is like talking about Mozart: I am
honoured when you say I share anything with Heidegger, but here one
is in the presence of genius I could never be near, and I must say that.
Heidegger does say that 'we're too late for the gods,' but he also said
towards the end, 'Only a god will save us.' Now, in the Western world,
if you use an article before God, you're not talking about the god of
the Bible, who is just God. You're talking about gods, in the sense that
Apollo was a great god; and I think Apollo was a great god, and not
just, as we now say, a 'myth.' Now, I think it is indubitably true that
Heidegger is in some sense reaching for polytheism again. When he
says we are too late for the gods, he does agree that we are too late; but
in a way he is hoping, because he thinks that polytheism, the return to
the gods, would be a wonderful thing.
I can't really speak about this without coming back to technology
because it seems to me he is speaking about passing outside the posi-
tion where everything is an object and our relation to it is to summon
it before us to give us its reasons. What he means by 'being here' is very
close in a certain sense to the ancient tradition, expressed not just in
Christianity but in India, and in a different way in China, and the Med-
iterranean world. He is speaking against a view of life in which we are
totally summed up in technology, in which all our relations are rela-
302 Thinking Their Thoughts
and this means to me that in Christianity there is always not only the
presence of God but also the absence of God. I would say that this is
central to Christianity, and that all the talk about what it is and what it
isn't has often been an argument between the presence and the
absence of God. Now, my question is how much the absence of God is
maintained in Heidegger, and how much the absence of God is main-
tained in polytheism. I want to be very careful because the very sub-
stance of what I have thought about anything would go if I couldn't
believe in the absence of God. And I'm not sure that this is maintained
in Heidegger. This takes us to Simone Weil, who understood the
absence of God with consummate genius.
It may be slightly opportunistic, but what I have learned from
Heidegger is the meaning of technology. Nobody has written about it
comparably or in such wonderful detail. Beyond that, I haven't really
gotten that far with Heidegger, but I am inclined to think that the
absence of God is not present. That's immediately talking in a contra-
diction, but emphasis on the absence of God seems to me to be neces-
sary for Christianity and for anything which attempts to be true.
It may seem strange that I pay tribute to a friend (to whom my debt is
great) by making some comments about a commentary. But the very
nature of that debt is expressed in these comments, Professor Doull
has never reduced his study of the past to antiquarianism. Although a
remarkable and careful student of the past, he has always known that
philosophy is an activity practised now, and that its end is far higher
than that of scholarship. The present commentary being discussed
here is masterfully achieved at the level of scholarship, but is far more
than that. It is a philosopher confronting another philosopher and in
that confrontation bringing to explicitness what he considers to be the
great tasks of thought in the present.
One task of thought today is to try to understand the claims of the
moderns concerning the novelty of their experiments. To use Platonic
language, it is necessary to think about the novelness of those novel-
ties. A hundred years ago Nietzsche's writing made explicit (whatever
George Grant, 'Confronting Heidegger's Nietzsche,' intended for a collection of essays in
honour of James Doull. This is a preliminary draft, unfinished at the time of Grant's
death.
304 Thinking Their Thoughts
Sir A.}. Ayer and Gilbert Ryle were prominent Oxford philosophers of the analytical
school, who discounted the importance of metaphysics.
306 Thinking Their Thoughts
Volume I
The title of volume I, The Will to Power as Art, is the title of the fourth
chapter of the third book of Nietzsche's posthumous work. Before pro-
ceeding to the direct discussion of art, Heidegger states the basic
philosophical intention of his interpretation of Nietzsche.
The inquiry goes in the direction of asking what the being is. This tradi-
tional 'chief question' of Western philosophy we call the guiding ques-
tion. But it is only the penultimate question. The ultimate, i.e. the first
question is: what is Being itself? This question, the one which above all is
to be unfolded and grounded, we call the grounding question of philoso-
phy, because in it philosophy first inquires into the ground of beings as
ground, inquiring at the same time into its own ground and in that way
grounding itself. Before the question is posed explicitly, philosophy must,
if it wants to ground itself, get a firm foothold on the path of an episte-
mology or doctrine of consciousness; but in so doing it remains forever
on a path that leads only to the anteroom of philosophy, as it were, and
does not penetrate to the very centre of philosophy. The grounding ques-
tion remains as foreign to Nietzsche as it does to the history of thought
prior to him. (67)
and brought to an original and basic position with a view to the funda-
mental questions of philosophy in the dialogue Phaedrus.' (167)
It hardly needs saying that the commentaries on these passages are
written from out of that closeness of attention which characterizes
Heidegger's writing about other philosophers. Yet it must also be said
that the exposition of what Plato is stating in these passages is inevitably
expressed by Heidegger from within (the very preposition seems pre-
sumptuous) what he thinks thinking to be. At this point it is hard to
clarify the implications of this sentence. Suffice it to say that on the one
hand I must avoid any implication that what Plato is saying can be laid
before others from out of some neutral stance of 'objectivity.' Nobody
is clearer than Heidegger that the account of one philosopher by
another cannot be simply a matter of 'objective' scholarship. Whatever
else may be true of philosophy, it transcends the stance of 'objectivity.'
On the other hand, to state this must not cloud the fact that what Plato
is saying in these passages is, in the very moment of its exposition by
Heidegger, placed within the Heideggerian universe of discourse. For
example, the Greek aktheia, which has been traditionally translated as
'truth,' is there used as that 'bringing out of concealment,' which is
Heidegger's translation of the word. Beyond such translations, these
commentaries assume throughout that Plato is philosophizing without
raising what is for Heidegger the ultimate question of philosophy:
'What is Being (to be)?'
This does not imply anything about Heidegger as trivial as that he begs
the question. Indeed, the fact that he so little begs any question is what
raises these accounts of Plato to the immediacy of confrontation. To put
it barely: the very clarity of Heidegger's incomparable thinkingof histor-
icism, from out of his assertion that human beings are only authentically
free when they recognize that they are thrown into a particular historical
existence, meets here the clarity of Plato's insistence that thought, at its
purest, can rise above the particularities of any historical context, that
indeed philosophy stands or falls by its ability to transcend the historical.
Describing this as the central theoretical division in all Western thought
is perhaps a mere expression of my struggling uncertainty as to who
misses what in this greatest of confrontations.
Volume II
Of the four volumes, The Eternal Recurrence of the Same is most con-
cerned with the direct exposition of Nietzsche's teaching. By calling it
310 Thinking Their Thoughts
Volume III
It has been frequently said that in the lectures of 1939 and 1940, which
constituted volumes III and IV, Heidegger is turning away from
Nietzsche and is less concerned with laying him before us than in the
first two lecture courses. Be that as it may, the lecture course of Vol-
ume III, The Will to Power as Knowledge, is a wonderful exposition of
what is involved in Nietzsche's account of truth as a form of illusion. I
can only stand by my own experience, which is that these lectures have
made clear to me in a quite new way what it is to think of Nietzsche's
account of truth as a kind of error. Heidegger states as 'the all-decisive
question': 'What happens when the distinction between a true world
and an apparent world falls away? What becomes of the metaphysical
essence of truth?' (134).
The confrontation with Plato in this Volume III is only partially
explicit, but is of course always present. These lectures are in this sense
very close to Heidegger's work of 1947: Plato's Teaching Concerning Truth.
Jean-Jacques Rousseau 311
Throughout the 1970s Grant had been satisfied that Nietzsche's account of mod-
ern consciousness, time as history, was the deepest. However, in the later 1970s
he began to study Rousseau's second discourse, On the Origins of Inequality
among Men, and concluded that Rousseau had influenced the formation of
the modern consciousness even more profoundly than Nietzsche. As always,
Grant's strategy was that of a negative theologian. He wanted first to expose the
true basis of modernity and then to show the inadequacy of that basis. This talk
was delivered to a meeting of the Canadian Political Science Association in
Halifax at a session in honour of Jim Aitchison, a long-time Dalhousie political
scientist and New Democratic Party activist in Nova Scotia. Grant undoubtedly
considered a paper on Rousseau to be a fitting tribute to his social-democratic
friend.
... it is only this year that I discovered that Rousseau was a greater former of the
modern than even Nietzsche. The result is that at the moment I am writing a
long piece called 'History and Justice' which is an attempt to understand the
atheism of the left better than previously. Rousseau takes my breath away with
how clever he is in destroying the old tradition by saying that reason is acquired
by human beings in a way that can be explained without teleology. To try to
demolish Rousseau (and, therefore, marxism) seems to me essential these days
to free people from that which can hold them from ever thinking that Chris-
tianity might be true.
- George Grant to Joan O'Donovan, 1982
his life Rousseau said that the 2nd Discourse was his boldest writing. It
was in it that he risked most to say openly what he meant.
Why we must read Rousseau is that when we look at the sciences
today we see that they are everywhere historical. I have quoted before
the title of von Weizsacker's book Die Geschichte der Natur. And when
we seek the originating moment of that idea of history we come upon
Rousseau. Indeed, to use for a moment the modern way of talking
which distinguishes the words 'philosophy' and 'science,' it seems to
me that always when there is a great outpouring of scientific activity -
in my present example the nineteenth-century historicizing of nature
- there lies behind that activity some philosopher who in his thought
about the whole had made a breakthrough as against all previous
thought. When I say 'breakthrough' please do not think I am speaking
in terms of the progress of truth. To put it extremely simply, break-
throughs can be into error. To say whether Rousseau's idea of modifi-
cation was true or false is not a question I am qualified to answer. But
to bolster my amour propre: Who is? We must wait and perhaps see.
What I am able to say, however, is that Rousseau as the originator of
that idea of history is an example of another strange fact. Often the
originator of a great breakthrough in thought understands the
thought he is thinking in its implications more comprehensively than
those who follow him and live within that thought, modifying it and
clarifying it. In its primal moment - or, to quote Heidegger, in its com-
ing out into unconcealment - that thought appears in all its ambiguity.
What makes Rousseau such a master is that he ponders the implica-
tions of the idea of history with such care. If one reads, for example,
one of Rousseau's most influential epigones, Marx, one does not find
that battling with the contradictions raised by the idea of history that
one finds in Rousseau. It is indeed this balding with these contradic-
tions which has often led English-speaking commentators to take
Rousseau as a weak thinker whose inconsistencies can be pointed out
in some desultory tutorial at Oxford or Harvard. The contradictions
which professors of philosophy often find in Rousseau come forth
from his refusal to avoid the ambiguities which he finds in what he is
given to think.
To praise Rousseau is not to forget his critics; to remember his crit-
ics is to speak of Nietzsche. Nietzsche may have had greater targets
Carl Friedrich von Weizsacker, The History of Nature., trans. F.D. Wieck (Chicago: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press 1949, 1959).
316 Thinking Their Thoughts
such as Plato for his contempt-laden rhetoric, but in terms of his own
era it is Rousseau whom he singles out as most responsible for the dec-
adence of European thought. Rousseau is the thinker who attempted
to Christianize secularism. He is the epitome of that secularized Chris-
tianity which Nietzsche despises more than authentic Christianity
itself. Yet, and it is a great 'yet,' a 'yet' which shows one the very power
of Rousseau, Nietzsche accepts from Rousseau belief in the fact that we
are historical, that we acquire our abilities in the course of time in a
way that can be explained without teleology. Nietzsche indeed thinks
that he is the first human being who has understood 'the finality of
becoming' in a historical way. I am always loath to think that as a
teacher of philosophy I can in any way transcend my betters. Neverthe-
less, I often wonder whether it be the case that in his anger towards
Rousseau, Nietzsche fails to recognize how much of what he is think-
ing in the finality of becoming has already been thought by Rousseau.
After all, we have been taught in the greatest book of political philoso-
phy that anger is an emotion that corrupts the ability to be open to the
whole. Nietzsche's hatred of equality, democracy, socialism, etc., how-
ever brilliant, often seems to fall over into anger - indeed, perhaps
finally into madness. Did that anger obscure for him his debt to Rous-
seau? Perhaps somebody here with greater learning than myself knows
for certain whether Nietzsche had read the 2nd Discourse. We could,
of course, never know whether this is not the case. But it would be
interesting to know whether it is the case.
The understanding that human beings acquire their abilities
through the course of time expresses itself contemporaneously in that
doctrine we call 'historicism,' and historicism is the fate of all
branches of knowledge in our era. It is only necessary to remember
that the outstanding thinker of this era is an historicist from begin-
ning to end, however much some of his thought appears to be a quar-
rel with that fate. Indeed, Heidegger has expressed the consequences
of historicism for the history of thought with greater clarity and pro-
fundity than any other writer. The attempts to refute historicism from
within the tradition of English-speaking liberalism (for example, Sir
Karl Popper's The Poverty of Historicism) are well intentioned, but fee-
ble. Even Wittgenstein's effort in this direction is one of the most
inadequate moments in his thought. It is sufficient reason why we
should read Rousseau carefully that all efforts to know what it
behooves human beings to know are today touched with the deaden-
ing hand of historicism.
Jeanjacques Rousseau 317
Today we are faced with the paradoxical situation where the mob
accepts as its priesthood those men we call scientists, when at the
same time this very priesthood leads the mob shouting to the cliff. It is
therefore extremely provoking to read a study of the thought of
Francis Bacon, who, as much as any other, stimulated men to that
study of nature, which on the one hand has given us ether and
penicillin, and on the other hand mass production and scientific
war. One may be allowed to say in the present journal, that it is
especially interesting to read such a study by a distinguished graduate
of Dalhousie.
Professor Anderson's study is not a popular essay for those who want
to garner a few vague generalizations about Bacon. It is a careful and
exact examination of all Bacon's writings. In the last chapter Prof.
Anderson describes Bacon's contribution to thought under three head-
ings which are worth quoting. '(1) freeing science from learning and
George Grant's review of F.H. Anderson's The Philosophy of Francis Bacon (Chicago: Chi-
cago University Press 1949), Dalhousie Review, vol. 28 (1948-9). Used with permission.
322 Reviews and Essays
Although Lord Russell was one of the leading philosophers of the early twentieth
century, especially celebrated for his contributions to mathematical theory, Grant
was not particularly interested in his thought. In this essay Grant uses Russell as
an eminent stalking-horse for a type of philosophy, common in Canada, which
Grant thought banal and confused. He also uses his attack on Russell to dis-
guise his assault on the Canadian philosophers, especially those in Ontario, who
had criticized his essay 'Philosophy' for the Massey royal commission. Russell
claimed that reason and philosophy could say nothing about questions of con-
duct yet wrote constantly about such questions.
Bertrand Russell 323
be silent about these questions or else openly admit that what he writes
about them has no rational content. And, of course, if he admits the lat-
ter, then there is no reason why any man should take what he writes
about conduct seriously. We do not listen attentively when the brilliant
mathematician is talking baby talk to his children.
It is this contradiction that makes difficult any systematic analysis of
Russell's recent broadcast talks, Living in an Atomic Age. Does he claim
for them any of the persuasive power of reason, or are they just
intended as so much rhetoric that will stir us emotionally? As to Rus-
sell's intention, it is hard to answer this question one way or the other.
Indeed, the strange division in Russell's soul is particularly evident
throughout these talks. I would say he must be a man with the worldly
wit and cultivated style of the aristocrat, combined with a preacher's
hatred of man's sin and desire to improve men; but that these excellent
qualities were marred by continual contradictions and a failure to
reduce any question to principles. Indeed, I would say that the author
was a good man and a clever man, but not a philosopher. This is the
dilemma in which Russell is inevitably entangled by the contradiction
between the moral scepticism which he holds in principle and the
moral fervour which he adopts in practice. Because of his moral fer-
vour he wants to speak out and convince men to be good; because of
his moral scepticism he cannot speak in principles and therefore can-
not speak clearly.
Let me illustrate what I mean from Russell's writings on the problem
of conduct. First an example from these broadcasts. Russell is describ-
ing the present state of the world and discusses what should happen in
the future. One of his chief points is that modern industry is 'a kind of
rape,' and that men are using up the natural resources of our planet
frivolously. He condemns this state of affairs and demands that men
'should' think of posterity. Now, of course, I am not here arguing with
Russell as to the facts. I quite agree with him as to what men are doing
and that we should carefully husband our resources for the sake of
future generations. I am not arguing with him as an economist, but as
a philosopher. Within his own philosophical position, what does Rus-
sell mean by the word 'should?' The word 'should' presumably means
men ought to do this or that. It is one of the fundamental words that
Western men have used about their conduct. But if Russell is right and
reason cannot speak about the fundamentals of conduct, then he is
using the word 'should' with no rational significance. What, then, does
Bertrand Russell 325
II
tell us what is the proper end of all conduct. We must rely on our emo-
tions for that central direction. According to Russell, the role of reason
is confined to logical and empirical concepts, and does not extend to
the regulation of our wills by principles.
In criticizing this view, up to this point, I have simply tried to make
clear some of its consequences. The consequences for society are
clearly that, when disagreement arises over ultimate principles of con-
duct, the issue must be decided by force or passion. If one American
likes to lynch Negroes and another American says it is wrong, the issue
can only finally be decided by force. The American who hates lynching
can indeed say with reason that such and such are certain conse-
quences of lynch law. If, however, the other American is ready to accept
these consequences and still likes lynching, there is nothing further
that reason can say. In personal life there is no point in using our intel-
ligence to judge what persons we should accept as examples. There is
no meaning in saying that Copernicus or Socrates or Milton chose wor-
thier ends than Himmler or Napoleon or Mickey Spillane.'
Any argument from consequences is, of course, only of limited value.
It must be supplemented by some positive grounds for thinking other-
wise. Clarity about consequences is, however, necessary, for down the
ages it has led men desperately to inquire whether there is not some
intellectually respectable position other than moral emotionalism. In
the Platonic dialogues, Socrates returns again and again to the conse-
quences of scepticism, so that he can persuade the young men to see
how in fact reason does operate in their lives.
It is necessary now to turn to the positive reasons why philosophers
have believed that our practical life can be regulated by reason. In stat-
ing these grounds I would point out to those readers who are not phi-
losophers by profession (it will be obvious to those who are) that
nothing I say has any originality. It has all been said, once and for all, in
that most brilliant of philosophic works, Plato's Republic. In modern
philosophy much the same argument has been put by Kant. Also, it will
be clear that what I say on this matter is not meant as a complete state-
ment of the case for ethical rationalism. That could only be done in
greater compass than this article allows. It is simply an outline of the
rationalist position, given to make clearer the difference between it and
Russell's irrationalism. Anyone who wants a systematic account of ethi-
image of God in all men. The denial of this by Russell and others is the
denial of the only possible theoretical grounds for democracy.
The second point I wish to make is that the formulation of the prin-
ciples of morality is in some ways similar and in some ways different
from the formulation of the principles of logic. It is necessary to make
this point, because sceptics such as Russell always emphasize the
greater public agreement about logical principles, and infer therefore
the invalidity of moral principle. Looking both at the differences
among logicians and at the broad acceptance of the idea of the highest
good in Western philosophy, I am not impressed by any idea of total
divergence. Nevertheless, it is true that the formulation of moral prin-
ciples is more difficult than is those of logic. It is therefore necessary to
discuss in what ways I consider them similar and in what ways different.
They are similar in the following sense. We can think scientifically
before we have formulated the principles of scientific thought; we can
act morally before we have formulated moral principles. Yet, in both
cases, the highest principle of the theoretical reason and the highest
principle of practical reason, when they are formulated, are seen to be
necessary to the proper functioning of thought and of conduct. So the
idea of the highest good is a necessary idea. Yet, having stated that
firmly, I would also state that their formulation varies in difficulty. In
the formulation of the principles of conduct our wills and our desires
are more deeply involved than in the formulation of theoretic princi-
ples. When we formulate mathematical principles we can use those
principles in physiology or physics (in one part of our lives), while we
do not use them in our relations with our wives or neighbours or the
world in general. Having formulated, on the other hand, the princi-
ples of the practical reason, we are committed to a total way of life. We
are committed to the effort to apply those principles universally. So, in
the practical reason, what we have to surrender for the sake of clarity is
the whole body of our habits. The commitment is not partial but com-
plete. It is, therefore, only by the profoundest effort of our wills, the
greatest discipline of our habits, that we can sufficiently face the prob-
lem to come to the recognition of the highest good. It is just the
understanding of this difficulty that led philosophers such as Plato and
Augustine humbly to insist that their ability to isolate the principles of
conduct was not finally due to their own efforts, but was a gift, or in
other words, grace.
If seeking the psychological and historical causes of other men's lives
were not generally just mud-slinging masquerading as science, I might
332 Reviews and Essays
///
The following are two passages from Russell's writing. The first is from
an essay he wrote in 1902 called A Free Man's Worship. The basic argu-
ment is summed up in the final passage. I quote:
Brief and powerless is Man's life; on him and all his race the slow, sure
doom falls pitiless and dark. Blind to good and evil, reckless of destruc-
tion, omnipotent matter rolls on its relentless way; for Man, condemned
to-day to lose his dearest, to-morrow himself to pass through the gate of
darkness, it remains only to cherish, ere yet the blow falls, the lofty
thoughts that ennoble his little day; disdaining the coward terrors to the
slave of Fate, to worship at the shrine that his own hands have built;
undismayed by the empire of chance, to preserve a mind free from the
wanton tyranny that rules his outward life; proudly defiant of the irresist-
ible forces that tolerate, for a moment, his knowledge and his condemna-
tion, to sustain alone, a weary but unyielding Atlas, the world that his own
ideas have fashioned despite the trampling march of unconscious power.
The second passage is the final words of Living in an Atomic Age, spo-
ken in 1951:
Man now needs for his salvation only one thing: to open his heart to joy,
and leave fear to gibber through the glimmering darkness of a forgotten
past. He must lift up his eyes and say: 'No, I am not a miserable sinner; I
am a being who, by a long and arduous road has discovered how to make
intelligence master natural objects, how to live in freedom and joy, at
peace with myself, and, therefore, with all mankind.' This will happen if
men will choose joy rather than sorrow. If not, eternal death will bury
Man in deserved oblivion.
I have not quoted these two passages because there may seem on the
surface a contradiction between Russell's appeal to doom and to joy.
In my opinion, when one threads one's way through the rhetoric one
finds much that is true and much that is false in both passages. Even if
upon analysis these passages could in no way be reconciled, a man has
a right to change his mind at least every fifty years. I quote them rather
Bertrand Russell 333
What final value is there in any clarity about logical principles or any
appreciation of wit (both debts we owe to Russell), if men are per-
suaded by his philosophy that they are not rational animals, but clever
beasts with a facility for mathematics? For though men are not simply
clever beasts, the fact is that when they are persuaded over a length of
time that they are such, they more and more act as if they were. Surely
the last years are an illustration that the ground of civilized life is the
assertion of our essential rationality.
Of course, to a philosopher the denial that man's rationality is his
essence is particularly distressing, for it denies the use or indeed the
possibility of his study. Philosophy means simply the love of wisdom,
and wisdom means knowledge of the true end of life. If men are not
rational they cannot reach such knowledge and therefore the attempt
is the pursuit of an illusion. This is why Russell is such a confused
thinker. Calling himself a philosopher, he has tried to convince men
that philosophy is a waste of time.
NOTE
1 If anyone doubts that I have stated Russell's position correctly, I would refer
him to The Philosophy ofBertrand Russell— in the Library of Living Philoso-
phers - vol. 5, 531-5, 720-7. There he will find a plethora of quotations from
Russell on this subject.
Sigmund Freud was the founder of psychoanalysis and one of the leading intel-
lectual figures of the twentieth century, and his influence was ubiquitous espe-
cially in North America after the Second World War. Before Freud there had been
few treatments available for mental illness and little understanding of its ori-
gins. Although many of Freud's theories have been discredited, for a while in the
1950s, 1960s, and 1970s they appeared to offer a theoretical basis upon which to
develop cures for individuals and to forge a better society. Freud's ideas, such as
his theory of the Oedipus complex, passed into general intellectual currency, and
Grant had lingering suspicions that perhaps they explained somehow his close
relationship to his own mother. However, he completely rejected Freudian-based
Sigmund Freud 335
You would leaf over the articles, the technical psychiatric details, muttering
'God-God,' then shaking yourself, having worked yourself up into a state, your
hair by this time falling again over your forehead, your eyes gleaming, you
would rise from the couch, swaying, braced and clenched, throwing the book
down, throwing one trench-clad arm out saying 'What they need is Love!'
-Alice Boissonneau, 'In My Room,' unpublished, c. 1945.
... To start from a traditional platitude: Health and disease are gener-
ally described in relation to each other, and therapy is defined with
emphasis on one or the other. Thus, in the Oxford Dictionary one
finds under 'therapy' phrases such as 'the art of healing' and 'the cura-
tive treatment of disease.' The verbs 'to heal' and 'to cure' are both
defined as 'to restore to health.' To restore is to give back, and so cur-
ing implies the loss of something that is normally present and that now
through therapy is given back. We are inclined, however, to look at the
matter the other way around when we are being practical. We think of
our breathing only when it is obstructed. Health is thought of as the
absence of disease. Indeed, in the disease-therapy-health progression,
therapy inevitably looks both ways, and in the various moments of its
activity fastens its gaze now this way, now that. This is true of all the
influential systems of therapy, both in the past and in the present. From
the Western tradition I single out the two most influential - the Pla-
tonic progression, 'ignorance-conversion to dialectic-illumination,'
and the Christian progression of 'sin-repentance through grace-salva-
tion.' These two have often been united; they have often been thought
of as one. Without discussing this subtle matter, I will for the present
purposes distinguish them. From the modern world I single out the
medical pattern, 'neurosis-psychotherapy-normality.'
In these systems, therapy has its positive and its negative moments.
The philosopher must be continually aware of his ignorance if he
would persevere in the pursuit of wisdom. If the Christian is to be in
true repentance before the Cross, he must face some of his past acts as
sins. The patient must admit the unconscious source of some of his acts
if the analysis is to be a success. On the other hand, philosophy will be
frustrated by misologism if its dialectical struggles are not known as
leading to the Good. The Christian's repentance will leave him a Stoic
or a Pharisee if it is not seen as preparation for the divine love. The
modern patient must give some meaning to the idea of normality.
Indeed, one aspect of the art of the therapist is to find a rhythm
between these positive and negative moments suitable to the individual
case.
As modern psychotherapists have made their art central to North
American society and established an institutional framework appropri-
ate to their social power, two phenomena about their theory and prac-
tice become increasingly evident - the certainty of their conceptions of
disease, the vagueness of their conceptions of health. To account for
this would require a book of social history and is not my purpose here.
Some generalizations about it can, however, be made.
1.) In the work of the master himself, therapeutic pessimism is con-
tinually present. This seems to me to arise above all from Freud's
ambiguous relationship to modern science and the modern assump-
tions about man and civilization which are the framework of that sci-
ence. He writes of himself as one of the dedicated priesthood of science
who have put aside the ancient religious and metaphysical superstitions
and who can, therefore, distinguish provable knowledge from mythol-
ogy. Basic to this positivism is the identification of knowledge with
human power to change the world. At the same time, one result of his
science was an account of the structure of the mind in which reason is
viewed both phylogenetically and ontogenetically, as arising from the
suppression of the instinctual in man. That suppression of the instinc-
tual is seen as the very cause of personal and social disease. The gaining
of power over nature, central to modern science, is the very cause of
disease when applied by man to himself.
This ambiguous relation toward science is illustrated in the very his-
tory of Freud's work and in his account of that work. In his writings
before 1919, he is firm in stating the methodological principle that his
conceptions are not final, but are hypotheses to be changed readily in
the light of observation and practice. Yet even these earlier techniques
and conceptions are themselves based on something extrascientific -
his own self-analysis of the 1890s. To see that this self-analysis is extrasci-
entific in psychoanalytical terms, it is only necessary to state that since
Sigmund Freud 337
itive content to their concept of health and justify that account within a
philosophy of nature and history. They are those who have attempted
to unite the thought of Freud and Marx. For the rest of this paper I
intend to describe and comment on these thinkers. I do so because in
them the assumptions of modern humanism about man and society are
enunciated in a most explicit way and also because in them much that
is unsystematically assumed in official therapy is openly asserted.
To put the matter historically: Since 1914 it has surely become obvi-
ous that the truth of the assumptions of modernity cannot be taken
with quite the uncritical certitude that they were previously. (I use 'the
assumptions of modernity' in the broad sense to distinguish them
from those of the antique world and from those of Christianity.) Yet
modern psychotherapy is essentially a product of that modernity. And
in these thinkers this modernity is given its widest scope. Therefore, in
them the assumptions of modern psychotherapy are most openly
explicit. I am also quite confident that the view of existence of these
thinkers is becoming and will become increasingly a popular faith in
our society.
this debased sense) and one in which there can be no final overcoming
of evil.
the main. To admit this greatness on the part of Freud, however, must
not allow us to forget that his account of man denies the essential prac-
tical truth about us - namely, that we are beings who must choose
between virtue and vice. Nor must we minimize or sentimentalize this
theoretical denial, because society has and will continue to pay a steep
price for it. That this denial is made by Freud is most easily seen in his
account of the structure of the mind as id, ego, and superego. The id is
the determinative aspect of us all. The ego and the superego arise from
it through historical circumstances. Thus, for Freud, thought is some-
how artificial to man, something forced on him by necessity. In his own
words it is 'a detour from the memory of gratification.' But even within
this assumption, he does not think of thought in a way that would make
possible virtue and vice. Thought for him is simply technical reason as
conceived by nineteenth-century scientism. For where the ego is made
the seat of reason, the superego is made the seat of morality. Thus, it is
not reasonable to be moral, and morality belongs less truly to man than
his ability to calculate. If reason is simply a calculating instrument and
cannot teach us to choose between virtuous and vicious acts, then there
is no objective morality in the public or personal sphere.
The orgastic gnostics bring out this theoretical implication with the
greatest clarity, for they openly deny the platitudes of the old rational
morality. The traditional morality presented itself in day-to-day practice
as two simple statements that were taken as self-evident: (i) men should
care not only for themselves but for others; (ii) they should sometimes
control their instinctual appetites in the name of some greater good.
These great platitudes were the court to which the doctrine of virtue
and vice publicly appealed. Of course, the denial of virtue and vice is
part of the whole tradition of modernity. One sees its beginnings in the
arrogant immanentism of Spinoza (i.e., in his attack on the act of
repentance as unworthy of a rational man). But it has never been made
more clearly than in these orgastic gnostics. We may thank them for
this lack of equivocation, for it brings out (what is elsewhere often
slurred over) that the assumptions of modernity cannot consistently
include a doctrine of right and wrong.
Of course, these gnostics have an answer to this criticism that is tradi-
tional among all gnostics. When people achieve genital primacy or
orgastic potency, there will be no need for the idea of virtue, because
the activities that the tradition called vicious will just disappear. Just as
the marxists, true to their dogma that the cause of evil lies in property
relations, believe, therefore, that evil will largely disappear when that
Sigmund Freud 343
cause has been eliminated, so these gnostics unite as the cause of evil
bad property relations and sexual repression and believe that the over-
coming of both will lead to the good society. Here indeed we come
close to the very centre of modern man's image of himself. Evil is not in
the free will, but arises from the realm of necessity. The most obvious
implication of this is that it cannot be called sin.
b) Although this account of health must be condemned as having
no moral doctrine, it has great religious advantages compared to the
other types of humanism (educated and uneducated) that character-
ize our society. The chief of these is that it is a doctrine of hope, and
Christians must believe that true hope is a virtue even when it has an
inadequate object, just as true charity in an atheist is supernatural.
There is no doubt that the young who read Mailer or Miller' are
attracted to this worship of the orgasm because it seems a true affirma-
tion compared to what they have heard elsewhere. The young are,
after all, reared in a society avid in its concentration on the mortal and
the immanent. Yet in these days of tightened organization and the pos-
sibility of technological nightmare, an immanentism of despair is all
too easy. Such an immanentism is the most influential philosophic
basis for therapy in Europe today (Daseinsanalyse).+ Moreover, in the
tightened society, sexuality is often the only form of creativity left open
to persons and is certainly a more universal foundation of hope than
the aestheticism of the culture addict or the worldly-wise empiricism of
the social engineer. This is true even if we take this orgastic gnosticism
at the point where it is more horrifying to the believer: Reich's^ tech-
niques of overtly sexual therapy (horrifying particularly when applied
to children). Is there riot more hope even here than in the widespread
and indeed indiscriminate use of insulin and electric shock treatment
carried out by order of the social engineers in the name of short-term
adjustment?
Moreover, sexuality is for many the road not only to gratification but
to ecstasy. 'With my body I thee worship.' The object of worship among
the orgastic may be limited to the immanent and may therefore be
justly characterized as idolatry. Nevertheless, in their very worshipping
they seem to discover something of the sacred in nature that has been
lost by those held by the philosophy of human power and self-confi-
dence. The rediscovery of that sacredness may be a condition for the
rediscovery of a worship that is more than natural. For all its dangers,
idolatry may be the only road back to worship. To carry this train of
thought further, it would be necessary not only to criticize the modern
view of nature but also to consider why our North American Christian-
ity was so influenced by that view of nature that it failed to have any ade-
quate theology of human love.
Having praised this concept of health for its hope, I must end by
insisting that it fails religiously by placing its hope in life alone. The
truism need hardly be supported here that suffering and death are as
much facts as life and gratification. Yet this gnosticism cannot include
these facts within itself despite all its efforts. The concept of health
given us by Him who says, 'Take up your gallows tree and follow me' is
complete in a way that no modern conception is, because it includes
suffering and death in health, recognizing them not simply as the
negation of happiness, but as the voluntary shedding of the mortal
necessary to the putting on of immortality. Christianity may too often
have forgotten a proper affirmation of life and gratification (and mod-
ern therapy has done well to remind it of this forgetting); but its
incomparable truth has been never to forget that suffering and death
must be included in health as much as life and gratification. Nowhere
has modern psychotherapy more mirrored and influenced our society
of progress than in the way it disregards death or looks at it with
stoicism.
A Swiss psychoanalyst and a rival of Freud, Jung drew widely on myth and
developed the concept of the collective unconscious. His thought was often seen as
religious, in contrast to Freud's aggressive atheism. This essay was the third
broadcast Grant delivered for CBC radio's 'Architects of Modern Thought'
series. The earlier were on Sartre and. Dostoevsky.
... I am deep in Tolstoy and Jung and am finding all sorts of things about myself
that I should have known years ago. In the business of the last years my intellect
Carl Gustavjung 345
had got detached from my roots and it is wonderful to begin to feel more whole
and less driven by neurotic tension of one kind and another.
- George Grant to John Graham, 12 December 1967
In modern psychology two men have been dominant: first the towering
figure of Sigmund Freud and close behind in influence Carl Jung. The
chief mark of our modern civilization has been what we call science. By
this word we mean a particular set of procedures by which men come to
understand the world and so have mastery over it. The application of
these procedures to the study of mind came late in the history of mod-
ern science. They were first used for the study of the physical world and
of the living world. It is only in the last hundred years that they have
been applied to the study of mind. But psychology is a product not only
of science, but also of the art of medicine - the art which is concerned
with the cure of disease - to use a beautiful Greek word, the therapeutic
art. Because medicine these days is so intimately connected with sci-
ence, we often think of the two as if they were the same. But, of course,
they are not, because clearly one can understand something without
wanting to cure it of all its ills. The expert advertising man or the com-
munist brain-washer may have consummate understanding of the
mind, but rather than want to cure he may wish to add to its ills that of
enslavement, so that the enslaver may add to his bankroll or power.
The psychologies of Freud and Jung were as much a product of the
therapeutic art as of scientific understanding. As Jung himself has writ-
ten, 'Our psychology is - practical science. We do research not for the
sake of research but because of our immediate aim of helping. We
could just as well say that science was a by-product of our psychology,
not its main goal, which constitutes a great difference between it and
what is understood by 'academic science.' Neither Freud nor Jung,
therefore, ever divide their account of what the mind is like from what
they think its condition should be - its health, its integration - use what
terms you will. They are not pure scientists and it is indeed a good ques-
tion whether psychology can ever be a pure science - that is, if the truth
George Grant, 'Carl Gustavjung,' in Architects of Modern Thought, 5th and 6th series,
twelve talks by various scholars for CBC Radio (Toronto: Canadian Broadcasting Corpo-
ration 1962), 63-74.
346 Reviews and Essays
about mind can ever be understood if detached from the desire of the
therapist to move minds to their health.
As is true of all intellectuals, the outward events of Jung's life are not
what is important, but rather what he thought and wrote. He was born
in 1875 in Switzerland - the son of a Protestant pastor. In 1900 he grad-
uated in medicine and immediately took up the psychiatric branch of
the art in Switzerland. In 1907 came his first meeting with Freud; he
recognized that Freud's psychoanalytical techniques and theory had
discovered facts which were becoming more and more central for his
own understanding of mental disease. During the next years he worked
closely with Freud in the development of psychoanalysis. In 1913 the
break with Freud came. Jung had criticized some of Freud's theories of
the unconscious in his famous book The Psychology of the Unconscious.
Freud and his disciples were a closed group and intolerant of any dis-
agreement about the central doctrines. They were quite unwilling to
continue co-operation with therapeutic techniques which stemmed
from different dogma. Jung, therefore, had to withdraw from the psy-
choanalytical movement and from then on he called his psychology
'analytical psychology' to distinguish it from dogmatic Freudian psy-
choanalysis. From that day on, Vienna and Zurich became rival Romes
of the psychological church in Europe.
Jung did not die till about a year ago at the age of eighty-six and he
continued as a productive scientist right up till his death. From 1914 to
1960 he carried on his investigations of the unconscious. His output of
work was simply staggering. I think it is fair to say that the output of few
scientists of our era can compare in range and quantity to that of
Jung's. Not only did he continue as a practising therapist, but he con-
stantly lectured on fundamental theory at the great universities of both
East and West. Because he came to believe that the mind was an incom-
parably more complex entity than Freud or the Freudians had thought
it to be, his researches took him into areas far from what is generally
considered psychology. He became, for instance, the greatest inter-
preter of Asian religion to the West, because he saw in Asian religion
remarkable techniques whereby the mind freed itself from ills. Any-
body today who wishes to understand Asian religion would seem to me
to have no alternative but to read Jung. He became an expert on prim-
itive peoples and travelled widely among them because he saw a close
relation between the contents of the unconscious of his Western
patients and the manifestations of the primitive mind in myth and leg-
end. He studied the medieval alchemists because he believed their doc-
Carl Gustavjung 347
Buddhism with its central doctrine of the cycle of rebirths which are
necessary to the law of karma and from which the enlightened alone
escape. How different is his way of speaking from 'the once and for all'
event language of Christianity.
The ordering content of the 'collective unconscious' Jung calls the
'archetypes.' The Oxford dictionary defines the word 'archetype' as
'original model.'Jung means by it 'self-portrait of the instincts.' But by
instincts he does not mean anything individual but rather universal -
the very patterns of behaviour which have been with man always. As the
language of the unconscious in dreams is that of imaginative symbol,
they appear in dreams as universal figures. Thus, for instance, the
archetype 'mother 1 or 'great mother' appears in dreams in many
forms. But what makes it an archetype is that 'mother' pre-exists in our
unconscious every worldly manifestation of the motherly, and has
existed in the unconscious of man so long as man has been man. We
must not turn these archetypes into concepts and make out that the
archetype of 'mother' is the universal concept of 'motherliness.'
Rather, the archetypes are universal psychic forces which we can only
begin to touch in experience.
When we experience these archetypes at all consciously, we are
touching in our individual lives the whole task of humanity at all times
and so are in a sense outside time. Jung indeed says that when we re-
activate the contents of the collective unconscious by opening our-
selves to the archetypes we have experience of the eternal. The word
eternal is here used in no transcendent sense. It is timeless but in the
world. What I think he means is that in re-activating the collective
unconscious we cease to be simply individual human beings and par-
take of 'human beingness' in general. And the more archetypes we re-
activate through analysis, the more we have entered into the fullness of
being men. The neglect of them is the final cause of all neurotic and
psychotic disorders.
Such an account of the collective unconscious clearly distinguishes
Jung from Freud both in their science and in their therapy. It can not
just be added on to the personal unconscious, as if Freud and Jung
agreed about the conscious and the personal unconscious and then on
top (or better at the bottom) Jung added the collective unconscious.
On the contrary, it leads to clear distinction between their two accounts
of the human condition - healthy or unhealthy. Freud is clearly here a
Western man, moulded by the tradition of Semitic religion, and there-
fore thinks that what is ultimately real is the individual and his instincts.
350 Reviews and Essays
This is not so for Jung. A man becomes a man as he re-activates the eter-
nal archetypes, as he partakes in them. In this sense the individual per-
son is not an ultimate any more than he is an ultimate in the great
religions of the East. This very profound difference is apparent in what
a Freudian and Jungian would mean by a successful analysis - or to put
it simply, what is the goal of psychoanalysis?
To a Freudian the goal is to come to terms with one's own instincts.
In Freudian language the 'ego' and the 'super-ego' and 'id' can
through analysis come to live together. But such a living together can
only be a compromise because the pleasure seeking of the id has to be
limited by the reality principle so that people can go on living in the
world. This is why there are such stoical and ironical undertones in
Freud - to be successfully analyzed is to make the best of a bad job - to
reach some compromise between reality and pleasure seeking. The
goal of a successful analysis with Jung, on the other hand, is integration,
that is, the combination of all the mental forces into a whole. And this
immensely optimistic goal is possible because of his postulated eternal
experience of touching the universal archetypes. Just compare Freud's
Civilization and Its Discontents with Jung's Modern Man in Search of a Soul
and one sees how incomparably more optimistic Jung is about the goal
of analysis - and please let me make it quite clear that I do not use opti-
mistic as a word of praise or blame. To say that a person's account of
the human condition is more optimistic than another's is to say noth-
ing about its truth.
From the foregoing it is easy to see why Jung has devoted so much
time to the study of myth. He came to realize that the same material
manifested itself in the mythic religion of primitive peoples as it did in
the unconscious. The 'great mothers,' the 'trees of the world,' the 'wise
old men,' which he had discovered in the unconscious, are of course
the very stuff of the primitive peoples. Also, archaic religions have
always been immensely aware of the need to integrate the soul and have
been full of differing ways of achieving such integration. Jung studied
such phenomena as a means of improving his techniques of therapy,
and also to learn more of the very content of the unconscious.
Indeed, Jung believes that it is just because Western man has cut him-
self off from the depths of the unconscious that he has become irreli-
gious and so lives in confusion. Our world is emptied inwardly as we
think of religion as either nothing or else concerned with non-dynamic
intellectual convictions; it is rationalized outwardly in a society domi-
nated by its technical apparatus. So, cut off by such rationalism from
Carl Gustavjung 351
the eternal archetypes, man in the West must become ever more prone
to outward violence and inward meaninglessness. At this point Jung is
particularly condemnatory of Western Protestantism which cut itself off
from the whole world of symbol and myth and ritual and so con-
demned itself to be out of touch with the wholeness of archetypes. Jung
is more friendly towards Catholicism because it has never attempted so
to rationalize itself. When in the 1950s the Pope promulgated the doc-
trine of the Assumption of the Blessed Virgin, Jung hailed it as one of
the crucial acts of our era because in it the feminine was taken back
into the Godhead.
But - and this is a very large but - in thinking aboutjung's interest in
religion or in myth one must be clear that it is a very particular kind of
interest. He always views religion or myth (and I do not use the words
synonymously) as they serve the mental health of human beings. I think
this is important because many clerics and theologians have main-
tained that Jung is a truly religious psychologist while Freud is essen-
tially irreligious. I am not sure that the people who make these
statements are really looking for their allies in the right place. These
statements are made because it seems at first sight clear that Jung gives
a more creative role to myth and religion than Freud does. To Freud all
religion was mythical and the mythical arose as a response to a diseased
psychological condition. The domination of the patriarchal father led
to a belief in the existence of the first person of the Trinity. Such super-
stitions will drop away if we have had a successful analysis. Religion is a
corporate neurosis of mankind which falls away from the wiser mem-
bers of society in the age of scientific enlightenment. Compared to this
negative approach to religion, Jung's insistence on the wisdom of reli-
gious cultures is refreshing to the believer and it is because of this that
Protestant and more often Catholic clerics have seen him as an ally.
I think those who talk this way often seem to forget that Jung is not
concerned with the truth or falsity of any particular religion; nor, as far
as myth is concerned, with what transcendent reality is manifested in it.
It is surely clear that the men of the ancient religious cultures when
they apprehended myth thought they were apprehending the real and
knew that the real so apprehended always led them to particular forms
of conduct. They thought they were being opened to an absolute and
universal reality. Now it is clear that Jung does not think this. When
men come upon the archetypes of the collective unconscious they are
concerned with the integration of their own psyches, not with being
lifted to another realm of reality, the realm of the spirit. In other words,
352 Reviews and Essays
Jung is concerned with myth in quite a different way from those who
live in myth. They are concerned with being opened to reality; he is
concerned with it as a psychological aid.
And this distinction becomes even more important when we pass
beyond the limited subject of Jung's relation to myth and look at his
relation to the living religions of the Western world. He is concerned
with them insofar as the practice of them is an aid to the mental health
of the practitioner. But he is not concerned with whether the affirma-
tions these religions make about reality are true or false. Indeed,
although he is cagey about this point in his voluminous writings, I think
it can be fairly deduced that he thinks that the affirmations of Western
religion about reality are nonsense. Now it does not seem to me that any
serious adult practitioner of a religion can simply disregard whether
what his religion says about ultimate reality is true or false. Can he just
practise it for the good of his mental health if he think what it says is
nonsense? It is surely particularly difficult to take this attitude to the
Semitic religions of the West-Judaism and Christianity - both of which
clearly involve making statements about reality. In other words, I don't
think we can get away from the fact that Jung's relation to Western reli-
gion is one of patronizing. Is one more a friend of Western religion if
one directly assails it like Freud or if one covertly patronizes it like Jung?
I have emphasized Jung's doctrine of the collective unconscious and
his interest in myth and religion because it is relevant to the chief way
in which Jung is an architect of modern thought. He is the leading
exponent of Asian religion in the West. I don't see how anyone can
take at its face value Jung's claim to be an empirical scientist - in any
clearly defined sense of the word empirical - any more than one can
take Freud's claim to be chiefly a scientist and not essentially a meta-
physician and a prophet. Nevertheless, Jung must be regarded with the
utmost seriousness because more than any other man of this century
he has made Asian religion a living force in the West. And surely one of
the key developments of our age is the spreading of the thought of the
Orient through the Occident. The Western invasion of the world in the
last centuries is such an obvious fact that we are inclined to forget how
much influence has been reciprocal. And this process has been going
on for some time. As early as 1625 there was a Chair of Oriental Studies
at the University of Utrecht. Since that time, Asia has been a growing
influence in the lives of European intellectuals. In our era it has
become a flood touching not only the intellectual elite but all parts of
our society. We are influenced not so much by such open missionaries
Carl Gustavjung 353
D.T. Suzuki, author of Studies in Zen Budhism and in Grant's words, 'The chief missionary
of Buddhism in the United States.' See George Grant, 'Philosophy and Religion,' in The
Great Ideas Today, 1961 (Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1961), 362.
J.D. Salinger (1916- ), American novelist and short story writer, author of Catcher in the
Rye (1951). 'Zen artists paint Zen pictures and Zen poets compose Zen poems. The voice
of Zen is heard in the novels of J.D. Salinger and Jack Kerouac.' Grant, 'Philosophy and
Religion,' 362.
A.J. Toynbee (1889-1975), influential British historian, author of A Study oj History, 12
vols. (1934-61). Grant met Tovnbee at Oxford earlv in the Second World War.
354 Reviews and Essays
Nietzsche's attack on Semitic religion went more to the heart than any
other of the many attacks which have characterized the last centuries;
and it was made exactly at this point - man should pass beyond good
and evil. The only time that Jung ever spoke unequivocally and at
length about his antipathy to Biblical religion was in his brilliant and
witty commentary on the book of Job.
Those clerics and theologians who say that Jung is an essentially reli-
gious psychologist are then right - but it depends on what religion they
are talking about. For the common liberal platitude that all religions
are the same is an obvious fallacy. Now it may be that the Catholic theo-
logians in France are right and that in our era the greatest task of Chris-
tianity is not to take marxism into itself or to come to terms with the
Prometheanism of science but to include Buddhism within the univer-
sal faith. It is not easy to speak quickly about such matters because they
raise subtle matters of principle and anything one says may sound on
the one side like ignorant imperialism or on the other like vague eclec-
ticism. One thing can, however, be said with certainty. As one looks at
the history of the race, two figures tower above the rest-Jesus the Christ
and Siddharta Gotauma, the Sammasambuddha, that is, the fully self-
enlightened one. Presumably also, if a religion is catholic, all may and
can be included within it. But certainly this is not what is present in
Jung's mind. It is implied in every line he writes that what is true in
Western religion can be included in the much richer religions of the
East. In this sense he is an incomparably greater radical than Freud; for
he is attacking the roots of Western civilization. Freud, after all, only
attacks Semitic religion from within its own assumptions. But Jung, for
all his surface conservatism and appeal to the past, attacks these very
assumptions - the concrete historical person in the face of the transcen-
dent. Those who do not see this radial centre of Jung's thought have
chiefly been prevented from seeing it because they have accepted, in
most cases unconsciously, Hegel's and Marx's accounts of Asian history.
Harold Innis was the first Canadian-born social scientist to achieve an interna-
tional reputation. He was a distinguished economic historian, and in his later
work he tried to understand the reasons for the decay and collapse of civilizations
Harold Adams Innis 355
H.A. Innis was a Canadian who was outstanding at what he did, by any
standards anywhere in the world. He became a famous historian of the
fur, fish, and lumber trades early in his life. But he did not stick with his
specialism. By the end of his life he was writing books which looked
deeply at the question: What is human being? For example, his
thoughts about the different means of communication (speech, books,
radio, TV) and what can be communicated by each particular means
was the influence from which the writings of Marshall McLuhan' have
come forth.
But beyond such particulars, anybody who has read his last books will
know that they cannot look at human history quite the same way again.
He became a famous man in the Western intellectual world and was
offered big jobs in the powerful American academia and the cultivated
British version. He stayed in Canada because it was his own and he
ambiguously loved it. His admirers were grateful to the University of
Toronto when it gave his name to one of its colleges after his death in
1952.
George Grant, review of The Idea File of Harold Adams Innis, ed. William Christian (Tor-
onto: University of Toronto Press 1980), Globe and Mail, 13 May 1980, E12.
Marshall McLuhan (1911-81), Canadian social critic and communications theorist who
was deeply indebted to Innis's communication studies for his own insights.
356 Reviews and Essays
John Le Carre (David Cornwell) (1931- ), probably the greatest writer of Cold War spy
stories and one of Grant's favourite novelists.
Northrop Frye 357
ence came from the ancients. He was at one and the same time both
toughly cynical about modern social science, and sadly doubtful about
the claims of the older science. The result is a kind of sadness in his
work - even if it is a sadness well penetrated by wit and anger. Perhaps
it is this ambiguity which has prevented Innis from having the continu-
ing influence appropriate to a person of his high style. Nevertheless, it
would be a shame if Innis did not continue to be read, particularly in
the light of how tedious modern social science often is. His writing con-
tinually lights up whole areas of human history. And we need this light.
Northrop Frye was the foremost Canadian literary critic of his generation and his
work was renowned around the world. However, Grant did not admire Frye's
style of criticism. He had praised Frye's work in his 1951 'Philosophy' article, but
he later became more critical. He thought thatFrye's literary treatment of the Bible
was a form of secularized Christianity that debased the spiritual greatness of the
Gospels.
I hope I did not attack Protestantism in my review of Frye, but only secularized
Protestantism - quite another matter. I disliked the book because he was supe-
rior about the Gospels, which in my opinion are perfect.
- George Grant to Jonathan Mills, 19 March 1982
George Grant, review of Northrop Frye's The Great Code: The Bible as Literature, Globe and
Mail, 27 February 1982, E17.
William Blake (1757-1827), British poet, artist, and visionary. Frye's Fearful Symmetry was
the classic stuck of Blake.
358 Reviews and Essays
Indeed, Frye's interest in these writings both aids and stands in the
way of his science as objective. It stands in the way because what often
seems to lie before him is not those writings as they were in their origi-
nating moment, but rather as the Protestant Bible, which has come
down to us from five centuries of English-speaking Calvinist reading.
This may seem to be contradicted by the amount of time that Frye gives
to arguing with contemporary fundamentalists. But this is rather the
impatience one feels toward relations who have not arrived socially. Be
that as it may, Frye's passionate interest in the Protestant Bible gives a
bite to his science. I think chapters six and seven are the best in the
book because here the Bible itself is most present.
To repeat, there is much in the book beyond the science of litera-
ture. There are many general theological pronouncements. (By 'theo-
logical pronouncements' I do not mean statements about theological
pronouncements, but direct theological statements.) Some of these
hit the nail right on the head with that fine shrewdness which is so
much a part of Frye's writing. But in a way which is again very Protes-
tant, he makes these statements (for instance, his remarks on proph-
ecy) as though they were factual rather than his interpretation. That
is, he writes theology as though it were not dependent on philosophy.
When these theological obiter dicta are directly philosophical, the
confusion in his method and material is compounded. For example,
Frye uses the words 'the master-slave dialectic on which the whole of
human history turns.' Presumably, he knows that in making this state-
ment, he has affirmed that modern political philosophy is superior to
ancient political philosophy. After all, it is this affirmation more than
any other which distinguishes modern from ancient political philoso-
phy. In saying this, Frye shows he is judging the Bible through the eyes
of modern philosophy. Why, then, does he then not say so? It would
make things easier.
This comes out clearly in Frye's relation to the seventeenth-century
Italian philosopher, Vico. He uses Vice's account of three stages in the
history of language. With a philosopher of the order of Vico, one can-
not accept such a part of his thought without being in closeness to his
thought as a whole. Frye understands this because, later in his book, he
expresses agreement with Vice's verum factum (we only know what we
make). But in such agreement, he has committed himself to look at
the Bible in a certain way - that is, through modern spectacles. To put
the same point in another way: one has chosen to look at the Bible not
as its writers looked at it.
360 Reviews and Essays
Dennis Lee is one of Canada 's leading contemporary poets - Grant especially
admired his Civil Elegies andThe Death of Harold Ladoo — and one of the
country's finest editors. He was largely responsible for the shape of Grant's first
collection of essays in 1969, and he also assisted Grant greatly with his last col-
lection in 1986. In return, Grant helped Lee to understand his visions into the
unfolding of the modern world. This essay is one of Grant's rare forays into liter-
ary criticism.
In a passage that seems to refer to this criticism, Frye wrote: 'There seems little interest
in reviving gods or nature spirits: in contemporary academic journals references to
Nietzsche and Heidegger are all over the place, but nobody seems to want to buy
Nietzsche's Antichrist Dionysus or Heidegger's murky and maudlin polytheism.'
Northrop Frye. 'The Expanding World of Metaphor' (1984), in Myth and Metaphor:
Selected Essays 1974- 19HH, ed. R.D. Denham (Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press
1990). 121.
George Grant, 'Dennis Lee - Poetry and Philosophy,' in Tasks of Passion: Dennis Lee at
Mid-C.areer. ed. Karen Mulhallen, et al. (Toronto: Descant Editions 1982), 229-35.
362 Reviews and Essays
nis Lee as a friend because friendship is a form of love and love illumi-
nates the intellect. In that illumination we come to know things about
other people. The Platonic affirmation that our intelligences are illu-
minated by love has been darkened in our era both because our chief
paradigm of knowledge concerns objects, that is, things held away from
us so that we can master them, and also because the preeminence we
give to sexuality leads us to interpret all forms of love as too simply
dependent on instinct. For example, Laurel and Hardy have been
interpreted as completely understandable as homosexual lovers. Such
a Procrustean statement prevents us from understanding the many
forms of love. I mean by friendship a relation between equals interested
in certain common purposes which transcend either partner of the
friendship. Such a relation allows one of the parties to see things about
the other party. When one of the parties is a poet such things are of
more than personal interest.
Yet I am very hesitant to write of Lee just because he is a poet. The
accidents of my life have left me with a deeply neurotic fear of poetry.
Apart from the uninteresting personal reasons for this, it is clear that
the rejection of poetry in its completeness is widespread in modern
society, and is closely related to the rejection of philosophy as more
than analysis and ideology. The central reason for those rejections is
that the control which is necessary to human beings who would be mas-
ters of the earth is the enemy of receptivity, without which there cannot
be poetry or philosophy. By receptivity I do not chiefly mean that which
is necessary in listening to poetry, but that which is necessary to writing
it. Plato was indeed exalting poetry when he said that it was imitation;
moderns denigrate poetry (indeed make it impossible) when they say
that it is creation. To talk of 'the creative artist' is a contradiction in
terms. For the poet is the being who must be immediately open to all
that is, and who proclaims to others the immediate truth of what is.
That openness, that receptivity, that imitation, is an ability difficult to
sustain in a world where control for mastery is the paragon of human
endeavour. Of course, poetry is so fundamental a stance, belonging to
the deepest level of what it is to be human, that it cannot be destroyed
amongst us; but it is liable to appear in our society as entertainment, as
a turfing of the grave. As such its proclamations can neither be easily
proclaimed nor heard.
Indeed, at the heart of the tradition there has been a debate (of cen-
tral importance in understanding politics) about the relation between
the proclamations of poetry and those of philosophy. Is Heidegger
Dennis Lee 363
right in saying that poetry and philosophy live at the top of two separate
mountains? Or is Plato right that politics demands that poetry be min-
isterial to the truths of philosophy? But this debate can only be private
and even secret in this era where only with the greatest difficulty can we
participate in philosophy or poetry, as they are in themselves. When
people have to hang on to what little they can make of these saving
graces in the midst of the drive to change the world, it is hardly neces-
sary to debate their relation. What is needed is to experience their heal-
ing balm.
My hesitation in writing about Lee's poems is, then, because the
modern drive to control has vitiated my listening to what poetry pro-
claims. Therefore, I must proceed to thinking about them through the
memory of meeting him when he was a young man. Memories can, I
trust, throw light on his poetry.
It was in the baleful glare which the Vietnam War threw on the
United States and Canada that I first had the good fortune to become a
friend of Lee's. In a fast-changing technological society, memory is put
in question. It is difficult even to remember how many people were illu-
mined by the sinister light of that war, whatever little public conse-
quence that illumination has had. What struck me about Lee at that
time was that of all the academics who were rightly moved by the
searchlight of that war, he was the one who saw that at the heart of
those events was an affirmation about 'being.' That affirmation (call it,
if you will, a statement about the nature of the whole) shaped what
came forth in the actions of our dominant classes. Along with many
others he saw that Canada was part of an empire which was trying to
impose its will by ferocious means right around the other side of the
globe. He saw with many others that Canada was complicit in the acts of
that empire and that that complicity was expressed in the politics of
Lester Pearson. He saw with some others that the technological multi-
versity was not outside that complicity but central to it. This was true
not only in the obviously technological parts of the university, but had
taken hold in the very way that the liberal arts were practised.
It is more difficult to express what Lee so evidently saw beyond this.
As words fail, let me try. He understood that at the heart of our civiliza-
tion lay an affirmation about 'being' which was that civilization's neces-
sity. The rampaging decadence of imperial war was not to be explained
(within liberalism) as an aberration of our good system; it was not to be
explained (within marxism) as something understood in terms of the
dynamics of capitalism. In the very roots of Western civilization lay a
364 Reviews and Essays
for to secular men there is not given the glory of tongues, yet it is
better to speak in silence than squeak in the gab of the age
and if I cannot tell your terrifying
praise, how Hallmark gabble and chintz nor least of all
Noam Chomsky (1928—), American linguist and conspiracy theorist; a fierce critic of the
Vietnam War.
Dennis Lee 365
It is Lee's openness to the whole which enables him to face the posi-
tion from which as poet he must struggle to be. The question of the
whole is present for him in all the parts including the parts which are
his own living. What is meant by openness to the whole has been
dimmed because the modern era has become a self-fulfilled prophecy.
Modern scientists like the modern thinkers in Swift's Battle of the Books
explain nature, human and non-human, without the idea of soul, and
not surprisingly they have produced a world where it is difficult to think
what it is to be open to the whole. Ancient thinkers are compared to the
bee which goes around collecting honey from the flowers; modern
thinkers are compared to the spider which spins webs out of itself and
then catches its food in that web. If the search for honey is not the
source of poetry, what is?
Indeed, Lee has described that openness beautifully when he
described his vocation as listening to a cadence ('Cadence, Country,
Silence,' Open Letter, Fall 1973, Toronto). The importance of the idea of
cadence for understanding what poetry and music are can be seen in
the fact that the most appropriate comment on it are the words about
his own art by a genius of the supreme order.
The question is how my art proceeds in writing and working our great
and important matters. I can say no more than this, for I know no more
and can come upon nothing further. When I am well and have good sur-
roundings, travelling in a carriage, or after a good meal or a walk or at
night when I cannot sleep, then ideas come to me hest and in torrents.
Where they come from and how they come I just do not know. I keep in
my head those that please me and hum them aloud as others have told
me. When I have all that carefully in my head, the rest comes quickly, one
thing after another; I see where such fragments could be used to make a
composition of them all, by employing the rules of counterpoint and the
sound of different instruments etc. My soul is then on fire as long as I am
366 Reviews and Essays
not disturbed; the idea expands, I develop it, all becoming clearer and
clearer. The piece becomes almost complete in my head, even it if it a
long one, so that afterwards I see it in my spirit all in one look, as one sees
a beautiful picture or a beautiful human being. I am saying that in imagi-
nation I do not understand the parts one after another, in the order that
they ought to follow in the music; I understand them altogether at one
moment. Delicious moments. When the ideas are discovered and put into
a work, all occurs in me as in a beautiful dream which is quite lucid. But
the most beautiful is to understand it all at one moment. What has hap-
pened I do not easily forget and this is the best gift which our God has
given me. When it afterwards comes to writing, I take out of the bag of my
mind what had previously gathered into it. Then it gets pretty quickly put
down on paper, being strictly, as was said, already perfect, and generally
in much the same way as it was in my head before. (Mozarts Briefe, ed. L.
Nohl, 2nd edition, pp. 443-44.)
These words are perhaps not a perfect fit for what Lee is saying about
cadence. Yet I always hold both statements together because in both of
them the difficult question of the relation between hearing and seeing
- the sense so related to time, the sense so related to space - is under-
stood as this relation is illuminated in poetry and music. (I never
reached Lee's poems so well as when I heard him read them.) Both
these accounts cut through the ghastly language about 'creative artists'
found now on the pens of journalists and professors of English, of uni-
versity officials and Canada Council executives. Obviously artists make
things (not create them) but if anything great is to be made they do so
by paying attention - by listening and seeing. (This is the trouble with
Irving Layton's poetry.) To repeat: creation is a dangerous word,
because it denies the primacy for art of what is listened to or seen.
The expression of Lee's openness is evident not only in his writings,
but practically in his work as editor. That wonderful English word 'gen-
erosity' (for which there is no German equivalent) penetrated his work
in setting up the Anansi Press and his editing a vast variety of writings.
Whether for good or ill, a tiresome old manic-depressive such as myself
would never have put the writings he cared about into a book if it were
not for Lee's sane encouragement. And he dealt with equally queer
types among the young and the middle-aged, always with that generos-
ity which in human dealings is the mark of openness.
With hesitation I must now turn to Lee's long poems - the hesitation
of my impotence before the proclamations of poetry. What I will say is
Dennis Lee 367
at a lower level than the essential. There is a great change from Civil Ele-
gies to The Gods and The Death of Harold Ladoo. To compare the rhythm
and form of Civil Elegies with that of The Death of Harold Ladoo is to know
that much more immediately happens in the second poem than in the
first. My comment upon this must be made in the accents of philosophy
(ich kann nicht anders). To put the matter perhaps too simply: existen-
tialism is the teaching that all thought about serious matters belongs to
the suffering of a particular dynamic context; while traditional philoso-
phy taught that thought was capable of lifting that suffering into the
universal. Both teachings require openness, but traditional philosophy
taught that thought was capable of lifting that suffering into the univer-
sal. Both teachings require openness, but traditional philosophy
believed that the truth present in existentialism was only a preparation
for its transcending. It would appear to me that Civil Elegies is written
out of the struggle which makes human beings existentialists, while the
two later poems have somehow raised up the sufferings of the particu-
lar dynamic context. The Death of Harold Ladoo moves back and forth
with the fluidity of music, from 'the dynamic context' of a particular
friend's particular death to the statements of self and other-ness, love
and hate, living and dying. Never does the particular dissolve into the
merely general, nor does the universal flatten out into abstractions.
Because the later poems are more universal, they are more immediate.
Cadence is more upon the page. This is not meant paradoxically in any
sense. Immediacy and universality require each other. Even at the end
when Mozart writes that 'the ice is around my soul' he is still able to
receive and imitate that which includes even that ice. It is dangerous
and indeed pompous to try to state what is universal in the Iliad, Las
Meninas, the clarinet concerto, or King Lear* but to say that there is
nothing such present in them is just the modern denial of the procla-
mation which is the work of art. Certainly the truth of existentialism is
included in them all, but it is also transcended in them all. The beauti-
ful is the image of the Good, and this includes the truth of existential-
ism because the perfectly beautiful has been crucified.
It is easier to write of Savage Fields for the simple reason that Lee has
written about it so lucidly himself. ('Reading Savage Fields Canadian
Journal of Social and Political Theory, Spring 1979.) Lee spells out there as
LOUIS-FERDINAND CELINE
(LOUIS-FERDINAND DESTOUCHES)
(1894-1961)
Celine, a French doctor and writer, wrote two important novels, Journey to the
End of Night and Death on the Installment Plan, in the 1930s. However,
he also wrote a number of violently anti-Semitic diatribes. The French Left con-
sidered him a collaborator and, fearing execution after the defeat of the Nazis,
Celine fad France. He Tuas imprisoned after the war but later acquitted of collab-
oration. In the 1970s a friend had lent Grant his copies of Celine's war trilogy,
and Grant was immediately and permanently enraptured by Celine's imagina-
tion. Although he took much pleasure from these books and did much to establish
a following for the French writer among Canadian academics, he abhorred
Celine's politics.
Celine is a mystery, just to me in the same way that Heidegger is a mystery. Both
so great £ yet both tied to the criminality of National Socialism. When Celine
says 'Europe died at Stalingrad,' well, I am quite willing for Europe to die if it is
at Stalingrad under these auspices. But nevertheless they both see so much.
- George Grant to William Christian, 7 January 1981
I have got engrossed in writing something about S. Weil, but I find it very slow,
but my heart will be easier when I get back to that darling bastard Celine.
-George Grant to William Christian, 8 January 1985
(O saisons, 6 chateaux,
Qiielle dme est sans defauts?)'
George Grant, 'Celine: Art and Politics,' Quern's Q_uarlerly, vol. 90, no. 3 (Autumn 1983):
801-13. Used with permission.
O seasons! O castles! / What soul is without its faults? (Arthur Rimbaud. 1854-91, a pio-
neer of the symbolist movement in French literature).
370 Reviews and Essays
by reading, one might simply leave the answer to this statement as ' tolle,
lege? The answer to such attacks can only be in the reading and above
all the reading of this last trilogy. To all the contempt that has sur-
rounded Celine the central answer is just to say, 'Read.'
To say this, however, is not to deny that questions arise if one reads
Celine with any knowledge of his life. In light of all the nonsense that
has been written about him and in the light of his greatness, it is neces-
sary to proceed carefully in the formulation of the question. At its most
simple, the question might be: How can one be enraptured by the art of
somebody who wrote anti-Jewish pamphlets in the thirties? But this is
not the best formulation. Dostoevski's dislike of the Jews does not stand
in the way of being enraptured by his novels. To go farther with the for-
mulation: the present writing is not a life of Celine and therefore I can-
not go into the details of the three pamphlets at issue. The one that
appears to me the most distorting - L'Ecole des Cadavres — is about the
approach of the War of 1939. It is quite beyond the limits of discourse
acceptable in a constitutional regime. Even if Celine's plea for peace at
all costs between Germany and France was sensible, even if he was cor-
rect that the Jews were in favour of war between the two nations, even if
he could not be expected to predict what crimes the National Socialists
would come to before they were through, it is nevertheless wrong to
publish such inflammatory writings against fellow citizens at any time.
It is wrong because constitutional regimes require a certain modera-
tion of discourse between the citizens of the society if they are to exist.
Indeed, the French regime of the time understood this and banned the
book. But lack of political moderation in an artist is not enough to con-
demn him to the extent Celine has been condemned. Degas's painting
has not been excluded from the canon because he was anti-Jewish. At a
much lower level, the absurdities of Shaw's political and philosophical
assertions do not prevent us from laughing at his plays. In an era such
as ours, in which Western thought and tradition lie in ruins, it is not
surprising that artists should be subject to the confusions of the age,
and therefore should be more than usually excused.
The question can be best formulated in a slightly different way.
Celine's judgments of the thirties make suspect for us the actuality we
seem to be given in the trilogy about the fall of Germany. We are forced
to ask as we drink from the chalice of his art whether its ingredients are
not poisoned and therefore not to be commended to our own lips. If in
*J.-P. Sartre.
Louis-Ferdinand Celine 373
Of the novelists Marcel Proust, fames Joyce, Henry James, and D.H. Lawrence, Grant
had a particular love for James, whose work he discovered while at Oxford after the war.
'What [Henryjames] has done for me above anything else is that by his tremendous pes-
simism, he has shown one that to whatever depths one sinks one is not as he so often
describes his characters as "a man without an alternative." One cannot in fact for what-
374 Reviews and Essays
ever reasons do what Milly Theale did in the Wings of the Dove, that is, turn one's face to
the wall. However much one may believe one is beyond the grace of the love of God,
that is a mere romantic conception and one can never escape from hope. Anyway read
him right away. Read the great novels The Wings of the Dove, The Golden Bowl and then
read the great short stories like the Beast in the Jungle and The Altar of the Dead. They are
of such greatness.' George Grant to Alice Boissonneau, Oxford, 1946, Selected Letters, ed.
William Christian (Toronto: University of Toronto Press 1996).
Marshall Henri Philippe Petain (1856-1951), head of France's Vichy government dur-
ing the German occupation in the Second World War War.
Louis-Ferdinand Celine 375
describes it in the account of his youth in Death on the Installment Plan. 'If
you haven't been through that you'll never know what obsessive hatred
smells like ... the hatred that goes all through your guts all the way to
your heart.' But are hatreds a mark of madness? Aren't all of us, other
than the saints, full of hates of one kind or another? To deny that most
human beings hate is to confuse the immediate facts with the highest
end, and to deny that that end is supernatural.
To return to the centre of the question: Is reality distorted in the tril-
ogy by Celine's madness? Those who think so fail to grasp what the
book is. Celine is telling the story of himself and his wife and his cat
wandering around a bomb-wrecked Germany. He is there as a story-
teller, and he is there acting in the story. It is not some novel where the
writer lives 'standpointless' outside the book. Celine's art may give the
impression of madness because he is able to hold inwardness and out-
wardness together in a marvellous way. Celine is always present in the
1950s as well as in the 1940s. For example, the first hundred and twenty-
five pages of the trilogy are about his enforced retirement in the sub-
urbs in the 1950s. The old storyteller emerges as he goes on about the
tricks of his publisher, the cold, the anguish of his patients, the nuts
who come out to interview him, the memories of the hole in Denmark,
the good sense of his wife, and always the animals. It culminates, when
he has a return of malaria, in a vision of Charon taking people to the
underworld. Then when the storyteller is there in all his concreteness
the 1950s drop away and we come to Celine in the midst of Germany in
its collapse. The old dying genius is there to tell us the story as we move
into the chronicle itself. Or again, often he will drop away from some
intense moment when Lili and he are nearly getting their throats cut,
back into the France where he is now recollecting. The intensity of the
chronicle overwhelms the storyteller and he comes back to the
moment of telling. Near the very middle of the trilogy he once calls Lili
by her full name, Lucette, as if her courage in the story brings back his
love for her at the time of recollection. When at the height of the high-
est of the three books, Rigadoon, he is in the midst of the destruction of
Hanover by the flying fortresses, we are present in his hallucinations
when he is hit by a brick. But is this madness? How can one better tell
what it is like to be in the midst of saturation bombing? When one says
this, it is well to remember that English-speaking people have done
most of the bombing in this era, not so much suffered it.
Celine's inwardness is not madness, but the art whereby he is
present in the books both as storyteller and participant. Old men like
376 Reviews and Essays
to tell stories about the events of their lives. In comparison with the
unity of the inward and outward in Celine's writing, Proust seems a
Trollope of the Faubourgs and Joyce's Mollie Bloom a literary device.
This is not somebody who would qualify as the idea of what psychiatric
social workers want us to become. But it is worth remembering that the
society which lives under this ideal is not one which seems to produce
great works of art.
If I were to use a colloquial title for this writing, it would be Up Yours,
Matthew Arnold. To see life steadily and see it whole is an admonition
that is likely to be self-defeating for poets. Yet those who call Celine
mad would have liked to have lived by it. To repeat: it is reported that
the saints in prayer can at moments touch that love wherein 'the tears,
the agony, the bloody sweat' can be loved. But for the rest of us, all too
often the attempt to see it steadily is a method for not seeing it whole.
Only a well-heeled bourgeois whose country and class were the most
powerful in the world could have united the two, outside the supernat-
ural love. Those who devote themselves to practice have to see life
steadily to the extent that they have to get on with the job. It means,
however, that they have to cut themselves off from trying to see life
whole. This is why poets and philosophers know they are always in con-
flict with the workings of society, however much they must try to hide
this fact. They must try to see life whole, but parts of that whole can
hardly leave them steady. Celine was a dedicated doctor who at the
height of his poetic art wrote of technological war with incredible ten-
derness. A steady story of what he had lived through would have been a
distortion and corruption.
The definition of poetry as 'emotion recollected in tranquility' must
be given greater respect than the 'steadiness' business, because it
comes from a greater poet' than Arnold. After Celine had been cleared
by the court, he had enough immediate tranquility to write his epic
poem. Recollection certainly required tranquility at that basic level. But
why should the storyteller in the suburbs pretend in his recollecting
that he is some jolly old reconciled gent who has put on a mantle
deemed appropriate by those who feed our academic fodder machines
in cosy universities? Indeed, it appears to me that those who write of
Celine's madness and how it vitiates his art are in fact trying to put aside
* Matthew Arnold (1822-88), British poet and social critic who rejected vulgarity in favour
of culture and 'sweetness and light.'
^William Wordsworth (1770-1850), leading British romantic poet.
Louis-Ferdinand Celine 377
the truth he is telling us. They often seem to go further and wish for
him to be mad so that what is told herein can be emasculated. This is of
course closely related to the option that he must be mad, for how else
could he have held such political opinions?
What then of Celine's politics? I must first state that it seems to me
unimportant to take seriously the political judgments of most of us.
They are caused mainly by necessity and chance - occasionally a little
by good. They are better understood in terms of comedy than by behav-
ioral science. And this still remains the case despite our extreme politi-
cization in the technological age. It certainly applies to Celine's
politics. They are only to be described because they have stood in the
way of the proper recognition of his art - particularly in the English-
speaking world. It is useful therefore to look at his politics - albeit they
have no contemporary significance and are an historical curiosity.
Celine's first political principle was that war between France and Ger-
many should be avoided at all costs. As a youngster he had been thrown
into the carnage of the 1914 War, and had been badly wounded. He
wanted the Europeans to stop killing each other before they were swal-
lowed up by the alien empires which surrounded them. His account of
the European situation was very close to Heidegger's statement of 1935:
'This Europe, in its ruinous blindness forever on the point of cutting its
own throat, lies today in a great pincers, squeezed between Russia on
the one side and America on the other. From a metaphysical point of
view, Russia and America are the same; the same dreary technological
frenzy.'- Celine wanted to save Europe (for him above all France) from
tearing itself up, and from invasion by the two continental empires
which wait in the east and west. It must be remembered that some
English Conservatives shared this opinion. One of Chamberlain's rea-
sons for the Munich pact was to keep both America and Russia out of
Europe. Clearly by 1939 a majority of English followed Churchill's
acceptance of Canning's principle of bringing in the new world to
redress the balance of the old. This was not, however, possible in the
same way for French traditionalists, because they did not speak the
same language as the Americans. Bismarck had said, a century before,
that the chief fact of European politics was that the United States spoke
English. Celine was no lover of the church or of the army. But he was a
French traditionalist, in that his loyalty was given to the small-bourgeois
life of his country. As war approached, Celine thought that the Jews and
the English were trying to push the French into war with the Germans,
and that this should be avoided at all costs.
378 Reviews and Essays
would have been a large German empire in Russia, and a slave empire
at that. Whatever may be said against Soviet society, Russia as a German
colony is surely as appalling as the Soviet conquest of Europe. It was of
course a German argument that as the English and the French had
world empires it was only fair that the Germans should not be excluded
from empire. Moreover they maintained that the English and the
French could only hold on to theirs if they let the Germans take part in
the common European imperialism. At a wider level it was claimed that
either in 1914 or 1939 the Americans and the English, the Germans and
the French should have come together to set up an international sys-
tem which would have been incomparably more secure than the
present one. Something like this seems to lie behind Celine's opinion
that this era marks the collapse of the 'white' races.
What seems so extraordinarily absent in this diagnosis is any recogni-
tion that in recent centuries the European races have been the
dynamic imperialists. European civilization had brought forth that uni-
versalizing and homogenizing science which issues in the conquest of
human and nonhuman nature. In Heidegger's dictum about Europe
lying in the pincers of two continental empires dominated by techno-
logical frenzy, he forgets that Europe itself had brought into being that
two-headed monster of technological science and dynamic imperial-
ism. To speak of Germany alone, one simply has to remember its theo-
retical contributions to that frenzy- relativity and quantum mechanics.
The U.S.A. obviously, and the U.S.S.R. through marxism, are but epig-
onal products of that Europe. After all, Marx said his thought was the
union of English political economy, French revolutionary politics, and
German philosophy. The chief influence on the American Constitu-
tion was the thought of Locke, which helped to loose technological
frenzy. At the core of Celine's loyalties is a love of particularity- in part
the particularity of the nation against the universalizing and homoge-
nizing power of the cosmopolis. Yet the natural and moral sciences
which would destroy particularity were themselves a creation of that
Europe which he wished to save. Celine's politics is an abstraction from
that science the consequences of which he describes so brilliantly in
detail. But failure of understanding at this point hardly puts the great-
ness of his art in question.
A more pressing political question is the relation of Celine's art to his
writings about the Jews in the 1930s. How seriously can one take the art
of somebody who could put such emphasis on the Jews in explaining
380 Reviews and Essays
the Jews, many intellectuals made the appalling step of basing their
attack on race, and so claimed to be giving it a 'scientific' underpin-
ning. The consequences of this secularism can be seen in the fact that
the great logician Frege wrote racialist pamphlets against the Jews. At
the other end of the scale, many of those who remained Christians
thought that the acceptance of the Enlightenment by intellectual Jews
was just a method whereby they could attempt to weaken religious
belief other than their own. It was believed that Jews wanted all faiths to
be weak save their own.
Beyond intellectual anti-Semitism lay nationalist anti-Semitism. The
Jews often appeared to take the side of internationalism and cosmo-
politanism in the life of their own countries, and so to hurt the inter-
ests of those countries. They could be disliked at one and the same
time as supporters of international revolution and as central to inter-
national capitalism. Both were cosmopolitan positions. This national-
ist anti-Semitism led into the deeper and more sustained levels of
populist anti-Semitism. This penetrated those classes particularly at
risk under the new regimes. The very solidarity of the Jewish commu-
nity helped them to be successful in the impersonal world of the new
technological states. It allowed them to be tough in the economic
world, because they were more freed from the straining loneliness
which was consequent on the impersonal world of mass civilization.
They could treat the public world without thinking of the conse-
quences of destroying it, because they had a nation other than the
nation which the public world manifested. They could retreat into
their national and religious community in a way that Christians could
not. The intellectual attack on Christianity was the more immediately
devastating to simple people because Christianity was not a nationalist
religion. People who were deprived of their particularism in techno-
logical society came to resent the Jews because their particularism had
so obviously not been demolished. The economically weak in the mass
cities saw their pasts taken away by finance capitalism. They came to
see the Jews as the masters and creators of a world in which they could
not function. Just read Hitler's account of his agony of loneliness in
the gaudy decay of pre-World War I Vienna, and his identification of
the Jews with that society, to understand an immediate cause of the
immense calamity.
Celine's dislike of the Jews was of this populist variety. (It is hard,
therefore, to know whether to call it anti-Semitism or anti-Judaism.)
He was to say that the Stavisky scandal in France and his work as a doc-
tor for the League of Nations brought it to life in his writings. It was,
however, essentially populist. What made it of such consequence for
the future recognition of his art was that it came to the surface at a
time when terrible events were brewing in Germany. Celine's intensity
of desire that there should be no repeat of war between Germany and
France led to his politicized writing, based on an inadequate premiss -
namely, that the overriding cause of the European crisis in the 1930s
was the Jews. He certainly must be credited with a major mistake in
political judgment and a great lack of moderation in writing about it.
Beyond this, he must certainly also be seen as somebody whose life and
art is packed full of the modern ideas that had come to flower in the
last centuries and which swept over Europe at the time of its collapse as
a civilization. But this last has been a state common to all Western art
and thought in this terrible era. Its consequences have, of course, been
worse for philosophy than for art. Celine at the best of times was, both
for good and for ill, a singularly unphilosophical being. He had all the
contempt of the deprived for theories. This was good in that the imme-
diacy of his art is not thinned by general ideas; it was for ill in that the
absence of philosophy left him open to the 'spirits' of the age.
Celine often spoke of his 'disaster' - the period of his life from 1930
to 1950. He seems to have meant that period when he wrote of the
public world, and the consequences he paid for it in persecution.
Indubitably that long disaster is something to be regretted in the life of
a great artist. In that disaster what is marred for us in Celine is his judg-
ment, albeit at a time when such failure was widespread. By the time
Celine is writing this trilogy in the 1950s he is all political passion
spent. His hopes have been burnt out of him by prison and persecu-
tion, by poverty and by age. The splendour of his art lays before us
Europe's collapse. Indeed, the very high splendour of his art is some-
how related to the fact that his hopes have been burnt out. In this
sense the question about this writing can be answered negatively. The
greatness of his art is not corrupted by the follies of his 'disaster.' His
trilogy is not a poisoned chalice. We drink from it the truth of the
human condition.3
A financial scandal in 1933-4 involving the French premier, Serge Stavisky, that led to
his resignation.
Louis-Ferdinand Celine 383
NOTES
Grant often discovered theoretical problems when faced with practical situa-
tions. He came to understand that the language of values was not just another
way of talking about the Good; it was a way of talking that facilitated the
progress of technology and increasingly foreclosed the possibility of understand-
ing what had been meant by Good in the past. He delivered this talk to a meet-
ing of social workers.
In turning to our society as it is, I do not want simply to run down the
list of the most important social problems which arise at the present
state of technological advance and proceed to discuss the problems of
value created by these new technological conditions.
These are all questions about each of which important papers could
be written. But you all know the facts of our society as well as I do, and
you all know incomparably better than I what special questions these
situations raise for your profession. It would be boring if I simply
repeated the platitudinous descriptions of the new sociology; it would
be impertinent if I told you how to do your work. In fact I do not want
to talk about values but about value itself, because the crucial thing to
see about our society is not simply that technology changes social val-
ues, but that it makes problematic the very idea of value itself.
What is it, then, about the age of progress which does not merely
change values, but makes the very idea of value problematic to large
numbers and particularly to those who are most explicitly part of the
age of progress. To give the most general answer to this question: the
cause lies in the fact that there is an almost complete separation for
many between their freedom and the myths. So to speak may seem to
you highly general and rather pedantic, but this is the central condition
of most modern human beings and therefore it is a fact with which your
profession deals in its daily work. What then is myth? It is an account of
existence in this totality which reveals to most men their own mode of
being in the world. Myths are the way that systems of meaning are given
to most human beings. And it is from systems of meaning that we make
judgments about what is valuable. Why is meaning given to most
human beings in myth? The greatest of all philosophers answered this
in saying that myths exist 'to enchant the soul.' Why is it necessary for
the soul to be enchanted?: so that it may be led to the true purposes of
human existence. The myths are not, then, the truth about human life,
they are the enchanting images by which most men are led to appre-
hend some purpose in their existence. They are the chief way that most
of us apprehend the beauty of the world. Being what we are - neither
gods nor beasts but human beings - we need to be enchanted into the
good way. Let me make clear that in speaking about myths, I am not
here discussing how we move through myth to truth. Truth is certainly
more than myth. For example, in my opinion Christianity is more than
myth, it is the truth. But it is certainly mythical in the sense that it has
revealed to countless millions their own mode of being to the world.
But insofar as I must be able to judge its relation to competing myths,
for example in the modern world the myth of progress, I must be able
to know it as myth, but more than myth. On the other hand, myths are
not altogether other than truth, because they are more than particular
tales. They carry with them the note of universality. The story of Oedi-
pus tells us something universal in which we can live. Yet again it is not
so universal as the story of the Bo tree or beyond that of the cross,
because they tell us of what is even more universal about human exist-
ence, about enlightenment and about dereliction.
By freedom is meant the modern account of self-consciousness: that
is, of the self as absolute. This is, indeed, the very heart of what modern
history has been and is - the belief that man's essence is his freedom.
Tradition has it that the Buddha was sitting under the Bo tree when he achieved enlight-
enment.
The Good or Values? 389
But now our bureaucrats are increasingly of a new kind. For one reason
or another, they have accepted the entirely modern and believe them-
selves to be the source of their own freedom. And the more sophisti-
cated these people are, the less they see themselves as part of a common
moral world and the more they see themselves as over against the world,
dealing with it as otherness, as a series of objects which they move
around as a means of proving to themselves that they are free. To put it
crudely, many of the products of these new bureaucracies seem less and
less able to imagine or to conceive that the objects with which they deal
are in fact human beings who exist in the same way that they do. This
atmosphere of solipsism will of course never be absolute, but insofar
as it exists, political activity becomes an assertion of self and sexual
activity a completion of one's own fantasies. This removal of the self
from the shared world of moral striving, this vision of everything other
as outside oneself, is in my Platonic book the source of many forms
of madness. This is not to say that many of these bureaucrats of which
I speak will be locked up; it is much more likely that they will do the
locking up.
But what, however, could upset us is something more inner than these,
this widespread separation from meaning (but as soon as we say that we
must remember that the Roman Empire kept itself in being for centu-
The Good or Values? 391
ries after any system of meaning had disappeared from its ruling
classes).
pie illustration, Mrs Friedan's book The Feminine Mystique. The book
says a lot of true things about women in North America. But it is written
as a sermon to encourage people to make their own lives and so puts a
terrible burden of compulsion on women to be absolutely sovereign in
their freedom.
Indeed, it can be said that this separation between freedom and myth
expresses itself most profoundly in our very use of the word 'value.'
Any neophyte in social science can tell one these days that it is self-
evident that we must distinguish between facts and values. What is
meant by this distinction between facts and values? What is meant by
this distinction is that there is a world of facts which we do not make but
which we discover and about which we can make objective judgements.
On the other hand, there are values which are made by human beings,
which are not part of the objective world and about which our judg-
ments are subjective, that is, relative to us. Man in his freedom makes
values - they are what he does with the facts. To illustrate: those who
make this distinction would say that when I state that Bessie Touzel'
weighs 135 pounds. I am stating a fact; but when I state that she is a
noble human being I am simply expressing my value preferences. But
this use of the word values is a symptom of the very split between free-
dom and myth of which I have been speaking. Value is seen as some-
thing external to the facts; something which is created by man and not
given in the world. This is to deny that the world apart from us is valu-
able, and to deny that the world is in itself good is the heart of blas-
phemy. In this sense the crisis of value in technology is nowhere better
seen than in the social sciences which make the fact-value distinction.
For in that very distinction is the denial that the world is in itself valu-
able. This is to leave the individual naked and alone in the dreadful
pressure of time. No wonder ours is the most dynamic society on earth
when we believe we have to make the meaning of our own lives. No
Betty Friedan (1921- ), American feminist, author of the landmark book The Feminine
Mystique (1963).
Bessie Touzel (1904-97), executive director of the Ontario Welfare Council, 1953-65,
vice-president for North America of the International Federation of Social Workers
(1956-8).
The Good or Values? 393
wonder the most explicitly modern men alternate between the rage to
live and despair about their contingency.
A few years ago there was a kick on in which people talked about the
dreadful results of conformity in our society.
This is indeed the chief cause of the ambiguity with which some look
at the age of progress (and I use ambiguity here literally). On the one
hand, one sees every day of one's life the convenience of that age - its
production of commodities which ease this life and enable masses to live
in the world with comfort and even affluence. On the other hand, one
sees that at the heart of society there arises this meaninglessness - this
sense of the atrophy of the soul. There are those who place the difficul-
ties of our age in more external questions. Can we bring the underde-
veloped nations to be like us quickly enough to prevent the population
explosion? Can we stop some nutty government from using the Bomb?
394 Technology and Modernity
etc., etc. If these external difficulties can be met then all will be well. But
I think this is to miss the real ambiguity of our age: what is the quality of
being in the age of progress? It is here above all in North America that
that ambiguity most clearly arises, because we have first realized what in
general everybody else is going to become. If you like to ride the crest
of the wave of the future, you're on it in Chicago or Toronto.
Jacques Ellul was a French Protestant sociologist whose work Grant encountered
in the mid-1960s. Until that point, Grant thought that, because of Marx, Mar-
cuse, and Kojeve, he had made some progress in understanding the coming into
being of modern technological society. However, Ellul's writings illuminated for
Grant the character of the society that had come into being. For this, Grant grate-
fully acknowledged Ellul's works on the subject of technology, but he did not gen-
erally admire Ellul's later writings.
Two books by Jacques Ellul, The Technological Society and Propaganda, are
the most important of all required reading for anybody who wants to
understand what is occurring in the 'advanced' societies during our
era. Modesty may require the words 'in my opinion' in the previous sen-
tence, but I hesitate to qualify such praise of greatness by the subjective.
Ellul is a professor of the history of law and of social theory at the Uni-
versity of Bordeaux. The Technological Society (called in French, La Tech-
nique ou I'enjeu du siecle) was published in France in 1954. It was
translated very ably (by John Wilkinson) and published by Knopf in
New York in 1964. Propagandas was published in France in 1962 and in
the U.S.A. in 1965. The Technological Society lays down the broad lines
within which Ellul understands modern society; Propaganda analyses
one of the dominant forces shaping that society. For that reason this
review will be concerned only with The Technological Society, although
George Grant, review of Jacques Ellul's The Technological Society (New York: Knopf 1964),
Canadian Dimension, vol. 3, nos. 3, 4 (March-April, May-June 1966), 59-60.
The Civilization of Technique 395
Propaganda is more closely written than the former book and greatly
illumines it.
The thesis of great writing cannot be encapsuled into a few smooth
phrases. The New Statesman or The New York Reviezv of Books to the con-
trary, the purpose of reviewing is not to show that the reviewer is clev-
erer than the author. Ellul's book is of 450 pages and all of it needs to
be read. The point of this review is to persuade others to read this won-
derful book, not to summarize it.
Ellul defines technique as 'the totality of methods rationally arrived
at and having absolute efficiency (for a given stage of development) in
every field of human activity.'1 Technique is not limited to particular
examples, of which the most massively obvious is machines. Ellul
includes within technique the sum of all rational methods used in any
society, e.g., the police, propaganda, modern education, etc. He anal-
yses (pp. 13-19) the leading definitions of technique found in mod-
ern sociological writing and shows that they are all too limited in that
they do not take full account of the facts. He describes the character
of technique in our society, how it has become both geographically
and qualitatively universal, how it is self-augmenting and autonomous.
To quote: 'Self augmentation can be formulated in two laws: (1) In a
given civilization, technical progress is irreversible. (2) Technical
progress tends to act, not according to an arithmetic, but according to
a geometric progression' (p. 89). In my opinion, the most important
part of the book is his account of how technique has become autono-
mous. What he means by autonomous is that technique is not limited
by anything external to itself. It is not limited by any goals beyond
itself. It is autonomous with respect to the areas of economics and pol-
itics - indeed, throughout society as a whole. It is the creator of its
own morality. 'It was long claimed that technique was neutral. Today
this is no longer a useful distinction. The power and autonomy of
technique are so well secured that it, in its turn, has become the judge
of what is moral, the creator of a new morality. Thus, it plays the role
of creator of a new civilization as well. This morality, internal to tech-
nique, is assured of not having to suffer from technique. In any case,
in respect to traditional morality, technique affirms itself as an inde-
pendent power. Man alone is subject, it would seem, to moral judg-
ment. We no longer live in that primitive epoch in which things were
good or bad in themselves. Technique in itself is neither, and can
therefore do what it will. It is truly autonomous' (p. 134). From other
writings it is clear that Ellul is a Christian, and in some of the wittiest
396 Technology and Modernity
1. If a general war breaks out, and if there are any survivors, the destruc-
tion will be so enormous, and the conditions of survival so different, that
a technological society will no longer exist.
2. If an increasing number of people become fully aware of the threat
the technological world poses to man's personal and spiritual life, and if
they determine to assert their freedom by upsetting the course of this evo-
lution, my forecast will be invalidated.
3. If God decides to intervene, man's freedom may be saved by a
change in the direction of history or in the nature of man.
The Civilization of Technique 397
NOTE
1 The page notes are taken from the English edition of the work (London:
Jonathan Cape 1965), xxxiii.
America: A New World 399
George Grant, 'In Defence of North America,' in Technology and Empire. (Toronto:
An an si 1969). Used with permission.
400 Technology and Modernity
has yet been. We can exert our influence over a greater extent of the
globe and take greater tribute of wealth than any previously. Despite
our limitations and miscalculations, we have more compelling means
than any previous for putting the brand of our civilization deeply into
the flesh of others.
Yet those who know themselves to be North Americans know they are
not Europeans. The platitude cannot be too often stated that the
U.S.A. is the only society which has no history (truly its own) from
before the age of progress. English-speaking Canadians, such as myself,
have despised and feared the Americans for the account of freedom in
which their independence was expressed, and have resented that other
traditions of the English-speaking world should have collapsed before
the victory of that spirit; but we are still enfolded with the Americans in
the deep sharing of having crossed the ocean and conquered the new
land. All of us who came made some break in that coming. The break
was not only the giving up of the old and the settled, but the entering
into the majestic continent which could not be ours in the way that the
old had been. It could not be ours in the old way because the making of
it ours did not go back before the beginning of conscious memory. The
roots of some communities in eastern North America go back far in
continuous love for their place, but none of us can be called autochth-
onous, because in all there is some consciousness of making the land
our own. It could not be ours also because the very intractability,
immensity, and extremes of the new land required that its meeting with
mastering Europeans be a battle of subjugation. And after that battle
we had no long history of living with the land before the arrival of the
new forms of conquest which came with industrialism.
That conquering relation to place has left is mark within us. When
we go into the Rockies we may have the sense that gods are there. But
if so, they cannot manifest themselves to us as ours. They are the gods
of another race, and we cannot know them because of what we are, and
what we did. There can be nothing immemorial for us except the envi-
ronment as object. Even our cities have been encampments on the
road to economic mastery.
It may be that all men are at their core the homeless beings. Be that
as it may, Nietzsche has shown that homelessness is the particular mark
of modern nihilism. But we were homeless long before the mobility of
America: A New World 401
our mobilized technology and the mass nihilism which has been its
accompaniment. If the will to mastery is essential to the modern, our
wills were burnished in that battle with the land. We were made ready
to be leaders of the civilization which was incubating in Europe.
Ernst Troeltsch (1865-1923), German historian who wrote on the history of Protestant-
ism and the social teachings of the Christian churches.
America: A New World 403
Now, when from that primal has come forth what is present before
us; when the victory over the land leaves most of us in metropoleis
where widely spread consumption vies with confusion and squalor;
when the emancipation of greed turns out from its victories on this con-
tinent to feed imperially on the resources of the world; when those
resources cushion an immense majority who think they are free in plu-
ralism, but in fact live in a monistic vulgarity in which nobility and wis-
dom have been exchanged for a pale belief in progress, alternating
with boredom and weariness of spirit; when the disciplined among us
drive to an unlimited technological future, in which technical reason
has become so universal that it has closed down on openness and awe,
questioning and listening; when Protestant subjectivity remains authen-
tic only where it is least appropriate, in the moodiness of our art and
sexuality, and where public religion has become an unimportant litany
of objectified self-righteousness necessary for the more anal of our
managers; one must remember the hope, the stringency, and nobility
of that primal encounter. The land was almost indomitable. The
intense seasons of the continental heartland needed a people who
whatever else were not flaccid. And these people not only forced com-
modities from the land, but built public and private institutions of free-
dom and flexibility and endurance. Even when we fear General Motors
or ridicule our immersion in the means of mobility, we must not forget
that the gasoline engine was a need-filled fate for those who had to live
in such winters and across such distances ...
When Calvinism and the pioneering moment have both gone, that
primal still shapes us. It shapes us above all as the omnipresence of that
practicality which trusts in technology to create the rationalized king-
dom of man. Other men, communists and national socialists, have also
seen that now is the moment when man is at last master of the planet,
but our origins have left us with a driving practical optimism which fit-
ted us to welcome an unlimited modernity. We have had a practical
optimism which had discarded awe and was able to hold back anguish
and so produce those crisp rationalized managers, who are the first
necessity of the kingdom of man. Those uncontemplative, and
unflinching wills, without which technological society cannot exist,
were shaped from the crucible of pioneering Protestant liberalism. And
still among many, secularized Christianity maintains itself in the rheto-
ric of good will and democratic possibilities and in the belief that uni-
versal technical education can be kind etcetera, etcetera. Santayana's
remark that there is a difference between Catholic and Protestant athe-
404 Technology and Modernity
ism applies equally to liberalism; ours is filled with the remnential ech-
oes of Calvinism. Our belief in progress may not be as religiously
defined as that of the marxist, but it has a freedom and flexibility about
it which puts nothing theoretical in the way of our drive towards it (or
in other words, as the clever now say, it is the end of ideology). In short,
our very primal allowed us to give open welcome to the core of the
twentieth century - the unlimited mastery of men by men ...
Indeed, the technological society is not for most North Americans, at
least at the level of consciousness, a 'terra incognita' into which we
must move with hesitation, moderation, and wonder, but a compre-
hended promised land which we have discovered by the use of calculat-
ing reason and which we can ever more completely inherit by the
continued use of calculation. Man has at last come of age in the evolu-
tionary process, has taken his fate into his own hands and is freeing
himself for happiness against the old necessities of hunger and disease
and overwork, and the consequent oppressions and repressions. The
conditions of nature - that 'otherness' - which so long enslaved us,
when they appeared as a series of unknown forces, are now at last
beginning to be understood in their workings so that they can serve our
freedom. The era of our planetary domination dawns; and beyond
that? That this is obviously good can be seen in the fact that we are able
to do what we never could and prevent what we have never before pre-
vented. Existence is easier, freer, and more exciting. We have within
our grasp the conquest of the problem of work-energy; the ability to
keep ourselves functioning well through long spans of life, and above
all the overcoming of old prejudices and the discovery of new experi-
ences, so that we will be able to run our societies with fewer oppressive
authorities and repressive taboos ...
That difficulty is present for us because of the following fact: when we
seek to elucidate the standards of human good (or in contemporary
language 'the values') by which particular techniques can be judged,
we do so within modern ways of thought and belief. But from the very
beginnings of modern thought, the new natural science and the new
moral science developed together in mutual interdependence so that
the fundamental assumptions of each were formulated in the light of
the other. Modern thought is in that sense unified fate for us. The
belief in the mastering knowledge of human and non-human beings
arose together with the very way we conceive our humanity as an
Archimedean freedom outside nature, so that we can creatively will to
shape the world to our values. The decent bureaucrats, the concerned
America: A New World 405
thinkers, and the thoughtful citizens as much conceive their task as cre-
atively willing to shape their world to their values as do the corporate
despots, the motivations experts, and the manipulative politicians. The
moral discourse of 'values' and 'freedom' is not independent of the will
to technology, but a language fashioned in the same forge together
with the will to technology. To try to think them separately is to move
more deeply into their common origin.
Moreover, when we use this language of'freedom' and 'values' to ask
seriously what substantive 'values' our freedom should create, it is clear
that such values cannot be discovered in 'nature' because in the light of
modern science nature is objectively conceived as indifferent to values.
(Every sophomore who studies philosophy in the English-speaking
world is able to disprove 'the naturalistic fallacy,' namely that state-
ments about what ought to be cannot be inferred solely from state-
ments about what is). Where, then, does our freedom to create values
find its content? When that belief in freedom expresses itself seriously
(that is, politically and not simply as a doctrine of individual fulfil-
ment), the content of man's freedom becomes the actualizing of free-
dom for all men. The purpose of action becomes the building of the
universal and homogeneous state - the society in which all men are free
and equal and increasingly able to realize their concrete individuality.
Indeed, this is the governing goal of ethical striving, as much in the
modernizing East as in the West. Despite the continuing power in
North America of the right of individuals to highly comfortable and
dominating self-preservation through the control of property, and in
the communist bloc the continuing exaltation of the general will
against all individual and national rights, the rival empires agree in
their public testimonies as to what is the goal of human striving.
Such a goal of moral striving is (it must be repeated) inextricably
bound up with the pursuit of those sciences which issue in the mastery
of human and non-human nature. The drive to the overcoming of
chance which has been the motive force behind the developers of mod-
ern technique did not come to be accidentally, as a clever way of deal-
ing with the external world, but as one part of a way of thought about
the whole and what is worth doing in it. At the same time the goal of
freedom was formulated within the light of this potential overcoming
of chance. Today this unity between the overcoming and the goal is
increasingly actualized in the situations of the contemporary world. As
we push towards the goal we envisage, our need of technology for its
realization becomes ever more pressing. If all men are to become free
406 Technology and Modernity
TECHNOLOGY AS WARNING
Werner Heisenberg (1901-76), one of the leading theoretical physicists of the twentieth
century and the formulator of a version of quantum theory known as matrix mechanics;
awarded the Nobel Prize for Physics in 1932.
Technology as Warning 409
can be seen by comparison with how they were once conceived in the
West. Our word 'art' comes from the Latin 'ars' which the Romans took
as their equivalent for the Greek word 'techne' One way of trying to fig-
ure out what the Greeks meant by 'techne is that it was a kind of 'poie-
sis' and 'poiesis' has generally been translated into English as 'making.'
But this does not help much, because making is one of those elementary
English words, which in its simplicity can hide from us what the Greeks
meant by 'poiesis.' We get closer to 'techne when we translate 'poiesis'
by the literal sense of the word production - a leading forth. 'Poeisis'
was a leading forth, and 'techne one kind of leading forth. The fish
hawk in the Atlantic storm would be for the Greeks a poiesis - a veritable
production - as much as this desk has been led forth. The difference is
that the chief cause of the osprey's production is not external to itself;
while the chief cause of the desk's production is external to itself, in an
artist, in this case a carpenter. Techne (call it if you will art) is the lead-
ing forth of something which requires the work of human beings. But
led forth and from where? To where? To use this language about the
present, we can make desks and microphones; so far we can only
unmake the production of the osprey by our use of chemicals which
unmake its reproduction. It remains to be seen whether we can remake
ospreys when they cease to reproduce themselves.
Let me make two comments about the older way of speaking. First,
there is in it none of that snobbish difference between the fine arts and
the ordinary arts which has so debased bourgeois culture. For example,
music just means the techne of the muses. In this language, then,
Mozart is an inspired artist, but not an artist in a difference sense from
a mechanic, a doctor, a politician, or a carpenter. Politics is the royal
art, not only because it has to control all the other arts, but because its
purpose is to lead into existence the highest thing here below - a good
society.
For the Greeks, art was indeed one kind of knowledge. As Plato said,
for something to qualify as an art the producer had to be able to give
his reasons for what he was doing. The artist had to know how to lead
things forth, not simply be an tinkerer. Nearly everybody in Canada
knows the difference between the garage man who tinkers with one's
car and the mechanic who can make it run. But although art was a kind
of knowledge, it was strictly distinguished from theoretical knowledge -
that 'theoretikeepisteme which through Latin was the origin of our
word 'science.' They were above all distinguished because they were
concerned with different entities. Art was concerned with what might
Technology as Warning 411
that something new has arisen in the world. It does not make clear that
technologies arise not from a scientific study of the arts which leaves
them systematized but essentially unchanged, but rather by the pene-
tration of the arts by discoveries of science which changes those arts in
their very essence.
What has changed is that the giving of reasons in the new way of mak-
ing now comes from modern science. To take a negative example: Pro-
fessor Northrop Frye has led the way in a new scientific study of
literature. In the literal sense of the word, one could call his work tech-
nology. But clearly his art of criticism does not turn that art into what
we now mean by technology. His science does not penetrate the art so
as to transform it. His science is that of Linnaeus, rather than that of
Newton or Planck. The art of criticism is not transformed at its very
heart as is the art of medicine by the science of chemistry. To illustrate
that transformation again: during the sixties many of us were required,
whether for good or ill, to hear a lot of rock music. Clearly science had
touched that art through the application of amplifiers, etc. But such
application had not transformed the very essence of the art of the
muses, the leading forth of the beautiful into existence. Quantum phys-
ics has transformed the production of energy at its very heart. Technol-
ogy comes to us as something new in the world, a production in which
science and art are co-penetrated.
I used to think that the French and German distinction between the
words 'technique' and 'technology' kept something that was lost in the
English use of the single word 'technology.' It maintained the distinc-
tion between the particular means of making (technique) and the stud-
ies from which they came (technology). I have now changed my mind
because the single word 'technology' brings out that the very horizons
of making have been transformed by the discoveries of modern sci-
ence. Technology may be a strange combination of Greek words, but it
expresses what is occurring in the world. I repeat: that this word should
have been achieved by the English-speakers also brings out the particu-
lar formative aspiration to making which has characterized our tradi-
tion of science. It is worth remarking that a man very enamoured of
that English tradition - P.B. Medawar' - should call science 'The Art of
Max Planck (1858-1947), German originator of quantum theory, received a Nobel Prize
for physics in 1918.
Sir Peter Medawar (1915-87), British zoologist and winner of the Nobel Prize for physi-
ology or medicine, 1960.
Technology as Warning 413
the Soluble.' Indeed, we can well say that in our world only those arts
which can be turned into technologies can publicly be taken seriously.
Fortunately it is not my job to say what this has done to the other arts.
They have above all been turned into entertainment, decoration, and
expressions of subjective fantasy.
I do not need to stress the more obvious side of the interdepen-
dence. The new inventions in these very arts make possible new discov-
eries in science.
These new arts inevitably call forth thought. Because they are new,
this thought is above all questioning. Among the manifold questions,
clearly the most important is: What is it in modern mathematical phys-
ics which brought into the world a new relation between making and
knowing? What are we told about the whole, from the fact that the new
algebraic equations have lent themselves so extraordinarily to giving us
knowledge of a kind which has placed the race in a new relation of con-
trol towards the world of objects - including the race itself as an object.
We often speak loosely of the distinction between theoretical and
applied science. 'Applied' means originally 'folded toward.' But the
question I am asking about modern physics is not asked as if the word
'applied' has to be added 'ab extra'^ to the word physics. What is it in
the very discoveries of physics that makes the world available to us in a
new way, so that the very nature of the knowledge leads us to new tech-
nologies? That this new availability is a fact is just a platitude; what it is
has never been completely fathomed. To put the matter in another
way: in the first sentences I said that the principles of different para-
digms of knowledge in different civilizations were to be found in the
relation between an aspiration of human thought and the effective con-
ditions for its realization. What is the central aspiration of modern
physics and what are the effective conditions for the realization of that
aspiration? What is it in the relation between that aspiration and those
conditions which leads to these new arts? That is what I mean by this
central question.
Let me repeat again as strongly as I can that it would be presumptu-
ous folly for anyone not engaged in modern mathematical physics to
believe that he could get very far with this question. It may very well be
said: Why does such a broad question need to be thought about? Have
not physicists and mathematicians enough to do for the progress of
their own study? Does not the modern world present us with enough
tasks that need to be worked at, without a kind of thought which would
necessarily involve a retreat from those tasks? Anyway, is it not already
clear enough to any practising scientist what is given in such words as
'experiment,' mathematics,' 'reasoning,' 'objects,' 'research' (the art
of the soluble), so that the relation between the sciences and the tech-
nologies is clear enough, and what matters is to work for the further
progress of the sciences and technologies?
In answer one might say that from the very origins of modern phys-
ics and mathematics a certain new relation between knowing and
making was already given. But what is given in any origin may become
hidden from those to whom it is given, and may only become clear in
the actualization of what was only potential in those origins. In the last
decades we have started to live in the full noon of this actualization, so
that what was given in our modern origins can now be thought more
clearly.
There is, moreover, a great practical incentive to such thinking -
namely the contemporary crisis concerning what should be made. The
crisis arises because of the invention of a vast new power of making,
and because of the absence of any clear knowledge of what it is good to
make or unmake. Both the positive and negative sides of this situation
are directly related to the achievements of modern scientists. As the
scientists' discoveries have made possible the new arts, so also the para-
digmatic authority of their account of nature has put in radical ques-
tion the original Western teaching concerning the frontier and
limitations of making. The story of what has happened concerning the
negative side has been told so many times that I will not spell it out in
detail again. Suffice it to say: for the ancients 'good' meant what some-
thing was fitted for. Our modern science does not understand nature
in these ideological terms. Knowledge of good cannot be derived
from knowledge of nature as objects. When the word 'good' was cas-
trated by being cut off from our knowledge of nature, the word 'value'
took its place, as something we added to nature. But now in our time
the emptiness of that substitute becomes apparent. The only great
achievement of the philosophical movement we call existentialism was
to expose that emptiness by showing that the language of 'values' has
nothing to do with knowledge.
The situation is often described by saying that morality has been put
in question. Such a description may be true, but it is misleading unless
it includes what men mean by morality. Morality was above all con-
Technology as Warning 415
cerned with the frontiers and limitations of making. What was meant by
traditional 'moral' philosophy or theology was the attempt to gain
knowledge of the proper hierarchy among the arts. As a modern, I was
for many years bewildered in reading Plato to find that the vast body of
his writings, which seem to be speaking of what we call 'morality,' was
taken up with detailed discussion of techne- the arts. For example,
what is the relation of the art of medicine to the art of politics? How is
the good life related to the arts of music, mathematics, mechanics, trag-
edy, etc, etc. What emerges from this greatest ancient authority is a
careful account of the arts in which the frontiers and limitations of
each art is claimed to be known in subordination or superordination to
all the other arts. It is claimed that some people can come to a detailed
knowledge of the frontiers and limitations of making.
The fact that that claim to knowledge has little surviving authority for
the modern world can be seen with startling clarity in Mr Justice Black-
mun's decision about abortion in the Supreme Court of the United
States. He states as self-evident that the Hippocratic oath comes from a
mythical and irrelevant past and therefore has no claim today on any
doctor. The Hippocratic oath is a statement concerning the frontiers
and limitations of one art. It is considered mythical and irrelevant by
the Justice because he believes that the account of the universe on
which it is based has been shown to be untrue and irrelevant by the dis-
coveries of modern science. Even if one were to grant some substance
to the Justice's shallow arguments, the question still remains: Where do
we find any positive knowledge in the modern world that can give fron-
tiers to the technological imperative - that imperative which was
expressed so lucidly by Robert Oppenheimer when he said: 'If some-
thing is sweet, you have to go ahead with it.'
The new technologies are taking us into realms of making which
occur as it were necessarily, that is, almost outside consideration of
human good. The thrust of these arts is now turned to the making of
our own species. Men cannot 'escape imitating nature as they under-
stand nature.' This making of our species is thought of as subsumed
under the ascent of man in evolution. But when making is directed
towards our own species, it becomes clear that one man's making may
be another man's unmaking. For example, what is one to think of the
making in the programmes of behaviour modification now so usual in
American prisons and asylums? Or again, I read recently the new med-
ical euphemism for the unmaking of the undesired aged - 'suicide by
proxy.' At my age one casts an interested eye on such phrases. Having
416 Technology and Modernity
cerning good and evil. But in our era it is just 'the soluble' which has
become ambiguous in this respect and is therefore before us to be rad-
ically questioned.
It would be foolish to judge that thought has much immediate influ-
ence on events in any era, let alone in ours when a particular destiny of
knowing and making moves to its climax. Our paradigm of knowledge
is the very heart of this civilization's destiny, and such destinies have a
way of working themselves out - that is, in bringing forth from their
principle everything which is implied in that principle. Most scientists
seem so engrossed within this paradigm (and at a lower level, so
engrossed, like everybody else, with their own advancement within
their community) that they seem unable to care to think beyond the
unfolding of the paradigm, let alone to think about it as a particular
aspiration of human thought and to relate it to the highest human aspi-
ration - knowledge of good. Yet in the presence of the obvious disre-
gard of thought in our era, the demand to think does not disappear.
The very glory of the scientific community is that it produces some
members who cannot avoid thinking beyond the dogmas of the scien-
tific paradigm. The scientific community cannot become an engrossed
irrationalism without committing suicide. It is therefore to be expected
that some scientists (let us hope including physicists) will go on think-
ing about the frontiers and limitations of their paradigm at the
moment of its most resplendent power, and in so doing help some of us
outsiders to think more clearly about the frontier and limitations of
making. The influence of such thought on the possible future of this
civilization could not now be predicted.
TECHNOLOGYAS ONTOLOGY
The position taken by many writers is that technology is a tool like any other and
can be used for good or ill. Grant rejected this position. He thought that technol-
ogy had so penetrated the modern world that it had become a nezv mode of being.
Modern human beings could not simply control technology, because technology
arose from particular historical conditions and social circumstances. The com-
puter, then, did impose on us how it should be used, because the pre-condition of
its existence was a certain view of reason and nature, one that cut most human
beings off from the divine and from transcendent justice. Grant delivered this
418 Technology and Modernity
paper in several different versions; its final version appeared as 'Thinking about
Technology' in Technology and Justice.
George Grant, 'The Computer Does Not Impose on Us the Ways It Should Be Used,' in
Beyond Industrial Growth, ed. Abraham Rotstein (Toronto: University of Toronto Press
1976), 117-31 (one of six Massey College lectures presented at Massey College in 1974-
5 and broadcast by CBC Radio).
C.D. Howe, an American-born businessman, was a senior cabinet minister in the Liberal
governments of Mackenzie King and Louis St Laurent. For Grant he symbolized the pro-
American, pro-business policies that had imperilled Canadian sovereignty.
Technology as Ontology 419
A proposed motorway through the centre of Toronto that would have destroyed many
neighbourhoods. It was cancelled after protests from civic activists.
Technology as Ontology 425
common source from which both forms of science found their suste-
nance. Indeed, to think 'reasonably' about the modern account of rea-
son is of such difficulty because that account has structured our very
thinking in the last centuries. For this reason scholars are impotent in
the understanding of it because they are trying to understand that
which is the very form of how they understand. The very idea that 'rea-
son' is that reason which allows us to conquer objective human and
non-human nature controls our thinking about everything.
It cannot be my purpose here to describe the laying of the founda-
tions of that interpenetration of the physical and moral sciences which
is at the heart of Western 'history' and now of world destiny. Such a
mapping of those foundations would require detailed exposition of our
past: what was made and thought and done by the inventors, the scien-
tists, the philosophers, the theologians, the artists, the reformers, the
politicians. Scholarship is very different from thought, although it
often pretends to be the same. But good scholarship can be a support
for thought, in the same way that good doctors can be a support for
health. Suffice it to say here that the root of modern history lies in a
particular experience of 'reason,' and the interpenetration of the
human and non-human sciences that grew from that root. It is an
occurrence which has not yet been understood. Nevertheless, it is an
event the significance of which for good or evil must now be attempted
to be thought. The statement, 'the computer does not impose on us the
ways it should be used,' hides that interpretation. To repeat, it simply
presents us with neutral instruments which we in our freedom can
shape to our Values' and 'ideals.' But the very conceptions 'values' and
'ideals' come from the same form of reasoning which built the comput-
ers. 'Computers' and 'values' both come forth from that stance which
summoned the world before it to show its reasons and bestowed 'val-
ues' on the world. Those 'values' are supposed to be the creations of
human beings and have, linguistically, taken the place of the tradi-
tional 'good,1 which was not created but recognized. In short, comput-
ers do not present us with neutral means for building any kind of
society. All their alternative ways lead us towards the universal and
homogeneous state. Our use of them is exercised within that mysteri-
ous modern participation in what we call 'reason.' Participation in that
particular conception of reason is the strangest of all our experiences,
and the most difficult to think in its origins.
To go further, because computers are produced from modern rea-
soning, the strongest ambiguity in the statement, 'the computer does
428 Technology and Modernity
not impose on us the ways it should be used,' is that our novelty is pre-
sented to us as if human beings 'should' use these machines for certain
purposes and not for others. But what does the word 'should' mean in
advanced technological societies? Is it not of the essence of our novelty
that 'shouldness,' as it was once affirmed, can no longer hold us in its
claiming?
'Should' was originally the past tense of 'shall.' It is still sometimes
used in a conditional sense to express greater uncertainty about the
future than the use of 'shall'; ('I shall get a raise this year' is more cer-
tain than 'I should get a raise this year.' The same is in that wonderful
colloquialism from the home of our language: 'I shouldn't wonder.')
'Should' has gradually taken over the sense of 'owing' from 'shall.' (In
its origins 'owing' was given in the word 'shall' when used as a transitive
verb.) In the sentence 'the computer does not impose on us the ways it
should be used' we are speaking about human actions which express
'owing.' If the statement about computers were in positive form 'the
computer does impose on us the way it should be used,' the debt would
probably be understood as from human beings to machine. We can say
of a good car that we owe it to the car to lubricate it properly or not to
ride the clutch. We would mean it in the same sense that we owe it to
ourselves to try to avoid contradicting ourselves, if we wish to think out
some matter clearly. If we want the car to do what it is fitted for - which
is, in the traditional usage, its good - then we must look after it. But the
'should' in the statement about the computer is clearly not being used
about what is owed from men to the machine. What is, then, the nature
of the debt spoken? To what or to whom do human beings owe it? Is
that debt conditional? For example, if men 'should' use computers
only in ways that are compatible with constitutional government and
never as instruments of tyranny, to what or to whom is this required
support of constitutional government owed? To ourselves? to other
human beings? to evolution? to nature? to 'history?' to reasonableness?
to God?
There have been many descriptions of our time as essentially charac-
terized by a darkening or even disappearance of any conception of
good. These have often been made by those who are dismayed by the
uncertainty of our era and find solace from the suffering of that dismay
in nostalgia for some other era. Indeed, as human beings have come to
believe that their affirmations of goodness are not justified by reason or
nature, history, or God, the effect upon many has been what some have
called 'nihilism.' This belief has had wide political significance because
Technology as Ontology 429
it has become possible for many through mass literacy. Mass training
has produced in North America that intensely vulgar phenomenon,
popular wised-upness. I include within mass training the present uni-
versity system. Nevertheless, it is incorrect to characterize the modern
West as a society of nihilism, that is, as if people had no sense of what is
good. If we used the word 'good' in its most general modern sense to
stand for that which we approve, and 'bad' for that which we deplore, it
is evident that the majority of modern people give their shared disap-
proval to certain forms of life. Can we not say that for most 'freedom' to
do what they want in such realms as sexuality is an evident good? Most
modern people consider good those political leaders who combine
seeming resolution with evident charm. The very influence of ideolo-
gies in our era, whether marxism, American liberalism, or National
Socialism, has surely not been a mark of nihilism, but rather a mark of
how much human beings wanted the evident goods that were put
before them evidently.
Therefore, it is deluding if we characterize our novel modern situa-
tion as nihilistic. But at the same time we have to be aware that some
great change has taken place. To characterize that change, it is best to
state that it has fallen to the lot of people who are truly modern to
apprehend goodness in a different way from all previous societies.
'Goodness' is now apprehended in a way which excludes from it all
'owingness.' To generalize this as clearly as I am able: the traditional
Western view of goodness is that which meets us with an excluding
claim and persuades us that in obedience to that claim we will find what
we are fitted for. The modern view of goodness is that which is advanta-
geous to our creating richness of life (or, if you like, the popular mod-
ern propagandists' 'quality of life').
What is true of the modern conception of goodness (which appears
in advanced technological societies and which distinguishes it from
older conceptions of goodness) is that it does not include the assertion
of an owed claim which is intrinsic to our desiring. Owing is always pro-
visory upon what we desire to create. Obviously we come upon the
claims of others and our creating may perforce be limited particularly
by the state, because of what is currently permitted to be done to oth-
ers. However, such claims, whether within states or internationally, are
seen as contractual, that is, provisional. This exclusion of non-provisory
owing from our interpretation of desire means that what is summoned
up by the word 'should' is no longer what was summoned up among
our ancestors. Its evocation alwavs includes an 'if.' Moreover, the
430 Technology and Modernity
ness inevitably comes the central theoretical question of this era. Can
our thinking be satisfied with the historicist universal? If the universal
appearing as historicism can be known as only a masquerading of the
universal, then it will be possible to ask the following question: In all
that has been practised and thought and made by Western human
beings in their dedication to the overcoming of chance, what has there
been of good? What has perhaps been found? What has perhaps been
lost? What have these possible losings and findings to do with what we
can know of the transhistorical whole?
It looks very likely that amidst the pressing calls for cybernetic orga-
nization in our immediate future, there will be little social patience for
those who think about these questions. Thinkers will be accused of
vagueness and uncertainty, impracticality, and self-indulgence in times
of crisis. For example, it is clear that the great intellectual achievement
of modernity is its physics, and that the scientific community which ulti-
mately feeds on that achievement is the most intellectually influential
in our midst. Yet in its pride, that community is, with rare exceptions,
contemptuous and impatient of any thought which is 'beyond' solu-
tions. Historicist scholarship is tolerated because it is unlikely to pass
over into thought. Therefore, I would predict that those who want to
think will have to develop a more than usual irony to protect them-
selves from this impatience.
In the face of the complexity, immensity, and uncertainty of that
which calls to be questioned, it may, indeed, seem that thinkers are
impotent as aids to the inescapable immediacies of the public realm.
The originating tradition concerning rationality in the West was that it
had something to do with happiness and therefore something to do
with throwing light upon the awful responsibilities of time. In the
ambiguous heart of Plato's dialogues, philosophy included political
philosophy. This relation to practice may seem to have been lost when
thinkers are called to wander in the chasms which have been opened
up by education for the overcoming of chance. It may seem that, when
thought wanders in these chasms, it becomes useless to the public
realm. Yet the darkness which envelops the Western world because of
its long dedication to the overcoming of chance is just a fact. Thinkers
who deny the fact of that darkness are no help in illuminating a finely
tempered practice for the public realm. The job of thought at our time
is to bring into the light that darkness as darkness. If thinkers are
turned away from this by becoming tamed confederates in the solution
of some particular problem, they have turned away from the occupa-
434 Technology and Modernity
don they are called to. The consequent division between thought and
practice is therefore even greater than at most times and places. That
division is a price that has to be paid by people given over primarily
either to practice or to thought, because of the false unity between
thought and practice which has dominated our civilization so long in
its dedication to the overcoming of chance. That false unity presses on
us in the two leading ideologies of our age - marxism and American lib-
eralism - in both of which thought has been made almost to disappear
as it was perverted into a kind of practice.
Those of us who are Christians have been told that there is some-
thing 'beyond' both thought and practice. Both are means or ways. In
their current public division from each other, the memory of their joint
insufficiency will be helpful to both. What is also necessary for both
types of life is a continuing dissatisfaction with the fact that the dark-
ness of our era leads to such a division between them. In this dissatisfac-
tion lies the hope of taking a first step: to bring the darkness into light
as darkness.
Christ said: Happy are those who are hungry and thirsty for justice
(Matthew 5:6). Socrates said that it is better to suffer injustice than to
inflict it (Crito 49b-e; Gorgias 474b ff). It is not my purpose here to discus
the relation between these two statements. That would be to raise the
question which in Jewish terms is the relation between Athens and
Jerusalem, and in Christian terms the relation between Socrates and
Christ. I will simply abstract from discussing whatever possible differ-
ences have been said to distinguish these two statements and take them
as saying something common aboutjustice. Nor is it my purpose to dis-
cuss the even more mysterious fact that one may be grasped by the
truth of Christ's proposition, even when one's own hungering and
thirsting is not much directed toward justice. It is never one's business
to concern oneself with other people's ultimate hungers and thirsts;
but I know something about my own, yet am still grasped by the truth of
that proposition. Put generally, this question is: If the intellect is
enlightened by love, and therefore access to the most important knowl-
edge is dependent on love, how is it possible to assent to the truth of a
proposition which is made from way beyond one's own capacities of
love?
My intention is to discuss the relation between 'technology' and the
statements of Christ and Socrates. I do not mean by 'technology' the
sum of all modern techniques, but that unique co-penetration of know-
ing and making, of the arts and sciences which originated in Western
Europe and has now become worldwide. Behind such descriptions lies
George Grant, 'Justice and Technology,' in Theology and Technology: Essays in Christian
Analysis and Exegesis, ed. Carl Mitcham and Jim Grote (Lanham, Md.: University Press of
America 1984). 237-46.
436 Technology and Modernity
culties, and want to carry that apprehension to its limits in the hopes of
making the world more congruent with justice. The enormous array of
cybernetic techniques being used by the environmentalists is an exam-
ple of what I mean. In so doing such people are denying that these
present difficulties constitute a real ambiguity in 'technology.' (Of
course, all of us as practical people living in our civilization must inevi-
tably be concerned in the name of justice with trying to do something
about one or other of these problems.)
The ambiguity with which I am here concerned is not that which
arises from difficulties such as these. Rather, it has to do with the fact
that the realization of technology has meant for all of us a very dim-
ming of our ability to think justice lucidly. The ambiguity is that tech-
nology, which came into the world carrying in its heart a hope about
justice, has in its realization dimmed the ability of those who live in it to
think justice. Something has been lost. It is for this reason that I started
with statements by Socrates and Christ.
At a common sense level it is clear what I mean by that dimming or
that loss. 'Happy are those who are hungry and thirsty for justice.' What
can the identity of the just and the fortunate mean to people who take
their representation of reality from the terms given in technology? At
all times and places, the unity between happiness and justice seems par-
ticularly incredible. (It is necessary to say in parenthesis why I have cut
out the completion of the statement. 'Happy are those who are hungry
and thirsty for justice because they will be satisfied.' I have done so to
leave out any discussion of what that satisfaction will be. I take for
granted that Christ did not mean any satisfaction or reward external to
or other than justice itself. One could translate 'they will be satisfied' by
'they will have their fill of it.' Often when I am feeling vengeful, as
Canadian Scots often are, for instance against the American oil corpo-
rations and their greed, I might say, T hope they have their fill of it.' So
one can say of the saints, 'Happy are those who are hungry and thirsty
for justice for they will have their fill of it.' Indeed, what makes one
tremble when one thinks about the saints is that one knows how painful
is going to be their journey to that joy.)
Most of our influential contemporaries would deny that anything
essential has been lost in our ability to think justice during the realiza-
tion of technology. At the centre of this denial would lie the pungent
assertion about justice which was in the heart of 'technology' from its
origins. Progress in the control of nature is essential for the improve-
ment of justice in the world. And what is justice apart from its exist-
438 Technology and Modernity
ence in the world? Progress in the control of nature has freed human
beings from such obvious injustices as labour and disease. It has not
only freed us from the bonds of necessity which held us in unjust situa-
tions, but also in that liberation has given us time to care about the
realization of justice in a way that was not possible when we were
bound to immediate tasks. Those who justify the modern with explicit
ethical doctrines would assert, beyond the practical claim, that justice
can now appear to thought with greater clarity than ever before,
because it can now be understood as utterly the work of human beings.
This assertion would be common to English-speaking liberals, to marx-
ists, to Nietzscheans, or to those who hold some combination of all
three. By saying that justice depends on a contract maintained in a for-
mal democracy, or on the proletariat when it has become conscious of
the needs of all human beings everywhere, or on the great persons
who want to use our conquest of nature beautifully and nobly, we have
allowed justice to appear 'authentically' by taking away from under it
those safety nets which guaranteed it as being in the nature of things.
As for hungering and thirsting for justice, that is more widely present
than ever before. Democrats hunger and thirst when they work to see
that the contract will become complete; marxists hunger and thirst
when they strive for a society in which justice is not only formal but
substantial; the noble and the beautiful hunger and thirst when they
think beyond being masters of the earth and impose beauty and nobil-
ity upon that mastery. Where is, then, the loss? We have been freed
negatively from those 'otherworldly' interests which diverted us from
and allowed us to put up with the injustices of this world. We have
been freed positively to take our lives into our own hands and to know
that it depends on us alone to give them a just and noble content.
What is, then, this talk of a loss concerning justice which has occurred
with the coming to be of modernity?
I long to be able to express it with superb clarity, but am quite
unable. The following, though inadequate, is as near as I can get: in
affirming that justice is what we are fitted for, one is asserting that a
knowledge of justice is intimated to us in the ordinary occurrences of
space and time, and that through those occurrences one is reaching
towards some knowledge of good which is not subject to change, and
which rules us in a way more pressing than the rule of any particular
goods. In the Phaedrus Plato writes of the beauty of the world, and
Socrates states that that beauty is what leads to justice. Beauty is always
seducing while justice often appears unattractive. If in this world we
Technology and Faith 439
A form (Greek).
440 Technology and Modernity
describe realized human love these days as if it were the height for
human beings; while some describe it as if it were not qualitatively dif-
ferent from our need for food. How difficult it is to see it neither as the
height nor as simply an appetite, but as an intimation of that immedi-
acy of justice which Plato has described as fire catching fire.
Let me say, in historical parenthesis, that this description tries to
avoid both Aristotle's and Kant's accounts of the matter. This may
seem like a remark of pride against such geniuses, and it would take
too long here to express clearly why I want to reject Aristotle's criticism
of Plato's account of idea, and Kant's assertion of the autonomy of the
will. My failure of description is bound up with three difficulties con-
cerning language. First, what is the point of speaking of this loss, in
which we live minute by minute, with language which no longer has
meaning for those minutes? When I said that Plato spoke ontologically
about i8ea, this used archaic language. Think what 'idea' means today.
Any use of the word 'soul' falls into the same danger. Or again, the
phrase 'oblivion of eternity' necessarily expresses the loss archaically.
Secondly, one must, on the other hand, beware of using language
about that loss which springs from the new forms of thought which
have caused it. For example, the word 'transcendence' is now popular
with many theologians. It seems to me a dangerous word because it
generally comes forth from that account of freedom as autonomy,
which is itself just part of the loss. 'Transcendence' has been so often
used in an existentialist exaltation of human beings' inability ever to
be at peace. Of course, there are more dangerous terms, used regu-
larly by theologians, such as 'historical consciousness.' The modern
world is full of language which arises inevitably and consistently from
'technology,' and which is better used by those who do not think the
loss a loss. The main task of thought is the purging of such language.
Rahner or Bultmann would have been of more use if they had read
and thought more, and written less.
Thirdly and more important, the question of language is difficult
because it must never move away from what is pressed upon us concern-
ing justice in our daily situations. This is the difficulty for all of us as
thinkers. If we are to speak about the essence of justice we must always
start from where it meets us in an immediate way every day. Put gener-
ally, this is to say that the language of ontology must proceed from the
NOTES
Grant was deeply moved by poetry and himself wrote poems from time to time. The
following is the only one he published. It is significant that the topic is Good Fri-
day, since Grant believed that Christ's sacrifice on the cross was the centre of the
Christian faith. He rejected the idea that the resurrection was somehow a trium-
phant reversal of the defeat of the crucifixion.
INTIMATIONS OF DEPRIVAL
This is one of Grant's most beautiful and profound essays. Written as a conclud-
ing piece for Technology and Empire, it addresses what Grant calls 'intima-
George Grant, 'Good Friday,' United Church Observer, vol. 14, no. 3 (1 April 1952), 3.
448 The Beautiful and the Good
tions of deprival,' the paradox that we are often most aware of justice and the
good when they are absent from a thing or a person where we would expect them
to be. The injustice of the death of a child, for example, often makes us aware of
the existence of justice and its claims. If there were no justice, how could we feel
that a child's death was unjust?
A Platitude (1969)*
George Grant, 'A Platitude,' in Technology and Empire (Toronto: Anansi 1969), 137-43.
Used with permission.
Intimations of Deprival 449
their fate into their own hands. This may be the case. What we lost may
have been bad for men. But this does not change the fact that some-
thing has been lost. Call them what you will - superstitions or systems of
meaning, taboos or sacred restraints - it is true that most Western men
have been deprived of them.
It might also be said that the older systems of meanings have simply
been replaced by a new one. The enchantment of our souls by myth,
philosophy, or revelation has been replaced by a more immediate
meaning - the building of the society of free and equal men by the
overcoming of chance. For it is clear that the systematic interference
with chance was not simply undertaken for its own sake but for the real-
ization of freedom. Indeed, it was undertaken partly in the name of
that charity which was held as the height in one of those ancient sys-
tems of meaning. The fulfilment that many find in the exploration of
space is some evidence that the spirit of conquest may now be liberated
from any purpose beyond itself, since such exploration bears no rela-
tion to the building of freedom and equality here on earth. What we
are can be seen in the degree to which the celebration of the accom-
plishments in space is not so much directed to the value of what has
actually been done, but rather to the way this serves as verification of
the continuing meaning in the modern drive to the future, and the pos-
sibility of noble deeds within that drive. Be that as it may, the building
of the universal and homogeneous state is not in itself a system of
meaning in the sense that the older ones were. Even in its realization,
people would still be left with a question, unanswerable in its own
terms: how do we know what is worth doing with our freedom? In myth,
philosophy, and revelation, orders were proclaimed in terms of which
freedom was measured and defined. As freedom is the highest term in
the modern language, it can no longer be so enfolded. There is there-
fore no possibility of answering the question: freedom for what pur-
poses? Such may indeed be the true account of the human situation: an
unlimited freedom to make the world as we want in a universe indiffer-
ent to what purposes we choose. But if our situation is such, then we do
not have a system of meaning.
All coherent languages beyond these which serve the drive to unlim-
ited freedom through technique have been broken up in the coming
to be of what we are. Therefore, it is impossible to articulate publicly
any suggestion of loss, and perhaps even more frightening, almost
impossible to articulate it to ourselves. We have been left with no
450 The Beautiful and the Good
words which cleave together and summon out of uncertainty the good
of which we may sense the dispossession. The drive to the planetary
technical future is in any case inevitable; but those who would try to
divert, to limit, or even simply to stand in fear before some of its appli-
cations find themselves defenceless, because of the disappearance of
any speech by which the continual changes involved in that drive could
ever be thought as deprivals. Every development of technique is an
exercise of freedom by those who develop it, and as the exercise of
freedom is the only meaning, the changes can only be publicly known
as the unfolding of meaning.
I am not speaking of those temporary deficiencies which we could
overcome by better calculations - e.g. cleverer urbanologists - failures
of the system which may be corrected in its own terms. Nor do I mean
those recognitions of deprivation from the dispossessed - either
amongst us or in the southern hemisphere - who are conscious of what
they have not got and believe their lack can be overcome by the
humane extension of the modern system.
Also, in listening for the intimations of deprival either in ourselves or
others we must strain to distinguish between differing notes: those acci-
dental deprivals which tell us only of the distortions of our own psychic
and social histories, and those which suggest the loss of some good
which is necessary to man as man. As I have said elsewhere, thought is
not the servant of psycho-analysis or sociology; but a straining for puri-
fication has the authority of the Delphic 'know thyself,' and of the fact
that for Socrates the opposite of knowledge was madness. The darkness
of the rational animal requires therapy, and now that 'philosophy' sees
itself as analysis, men who desire to think must include in their thinking
those modern therapies which arose outside any connection with what
was once called philosophy. This inclusion of what may be health-
giving in psychoanalysis and sociology will be necessary, even within the
knowledge that these therapies are going to be used unbridledly as ser-
vants of the modern belief that socially useful patterns of behaviour
should be inculcated by force. Anything concerning sexuality will serve
as an example of the distortions I am trying to describe, because such
matters touch every element of fantasy and the unconscious in our-
selves, so that judgments about good are there most clouded by idiosyn-
cracy. For example, if a man were to say that the present technical
advances were so detaching sexuality from procreation as to deprive
women of a maternity necessary to their fullest being, his statement
might be suspect as coming from a hatred of women which could not
Intimations of Deprival 451
Rod Crook, 'Loyalism, Technology and Canada's Fate,' Journal of Canadian Studies, vol. 5
(1970) 50-60.
452 The Beautiful and the Good
lives more fully in that division? Is there some force in man which will
rage against such division: rage not only against a subjectivity which cre-
ates itself, but also against our own lives being so much at the disposal
of the powerful objectifications of other freedoms? Neither can we
know what this unfolding potentiality tells us of the non-human. As we
cannot now know to what extent the non-human can in practice be
made malleable to our will, therefore we also do not know what this
undetermined degree of malleability will tell us of what the non-human
is. Is the non-human simply stuff at our disposal, or will it begin to make
its appearance to us as an order the purposes of which somehow resist
our malleablizings? Are there already signs of revolts in nature?
Despite the noblest modern thought, which teaches always the exal-
tation of potentiality above all that is, has anyone been able to show us
conclusively throughout a comprehensive account of both the human
and non-human things, that we must discard the idea of a presence
above which potentiality cannot be exalted? In such a situation of
uncertainty, it would be lacking in courage to turn one's face to the
wall, even if one can find no fulfilment in working for or celebrating
the dynamo. Equally it would be immoderate and uncourageous and
perhaps unwise to live in the midst of our present drive, merely working
in it and celebrating it and not also listening or watching or simply wait-
ing for intimations of deprival which might lead us to see the beautiful
as the image, in the world, of the good.
DEATH AS ABSENCE
Jelte Kuipers was a graduate student who showed promise. The Grants attended
in short succession his wedding and his funeral. This appreciation, written for the
McMaster student newspaper, shows one of the reasons why Grant was respected
as a great teacher: his profound respect for and understanding of his students.
Individual life is always the loser in nature. Because human beings are
tions of our institutions to see the central issue of our society in the
deep questioning of ecology. The greatest negation for him was the
dynamism of our conquest of the planet - a conquest which has
become so total that it threatens the very possibility of life for man in
that environment of which he is a part. The recognition of this nega-
tion above all brought him from youth to an early maturity.
He was brought to maturity in the face of that terrible vision because
he was able not to be swallowed up in that world of shifting personal
relations and of drugs (that is, the world of 'democratic' existentialism)
which has become the private retreat for so many of his generation.
Nor on the other side was he content with the reaction of marxism
because he saw clearly that much of the protest advocated was just part
of the system, and that the call to revolution in marxism had at its heart
a further extension of the modernity which has brought us where we
are. Because he had watched carefully, he had seen early that the crisis
of Western society was too total to be met by any 'ad hoc' solutions. It
needed a repossession of the roots of heaven through a deep under-
standing of nature and what is beyond nature. It was because of this
that he turned to the understanding and production of Greek drama,
and to the study of what was great in the ancient near east. It was
because of this that he could at the end of a short life become part of
the Roman Catholic Church. Qui verbum Dei contempserunt, etiam eis
auferetur verbum hominis.
The desire to partake through thought in the roots of wisdom did
not, however, turn him away from the practical world to a life of easy
solitude. In his impatience with injustice and his involvement in the
practical there could be seen his debt to the long line of Calvinist for-
bears in Holland. He knew clearly that the thought of those who have
not the courage to deal with the world is bound to become sterile and
even vacuous. He had learnt the lesson of the founder of philosophy
(repeated by its practitioners from Socrates to Wittgenstein) that phi-
losophy is not a value-free, analytical game, but a study which can only
be grasped as its truths are lived out in the world. Just before his death,
Kuipers had decided to put aside his studies in religion and to devote
himself to working full-time with those groups of people in Canada who
are determined to try to stop the pollution of nature. He would have
brought to that activity all the sharp determined will which was part of
They that have despised the Word of God, from them shall the word of man also be
taken away (as translated by C.S. Lewis in That Hideous Strength, 224).
456 The Beautiful and the Good
Torture (1977)
Makarios III (1913-77), archbishop of the Orthodox Church of Cyprus, elected presi-
dent of Cyprus iu 1959, 1968, aud 1973.
458 The Beautiful and the Good
BLISS
Of all his colleagues at McMaster, Grant felt closest to those who studied Hindu-
ism. His understanding of the meaning of the Gospels was informed not just by
Plato but also by what he had learned from Indian religion.
We can never touch in one's writings these moments of miraculous power and
glory- reasonless and triumphant. They just come; it is as if one had seen a
wonderful plumed bird. Katherine Mansfield gets the idea best in that story
'Bliss,' but how could one ever describe the deep and real warmth of feeling
Katherine Mansfield (1888-1923), New Zealand writer, author of Bliss: And Other Stones
(1920).
460 The Beautiful and the Good
one feels for Bare? It is not just sentimental, but based on the thousand inci-
dents of growing up. 'Oh love that interests itself in thoughtless heaven.'
- George Grant, Journal Entry, 1942
LOVE
Grant began work on this essay about 1977 and produced several versions of it
before the final one appeared in Technology and Justice. It is a difficult essay
because it deals with the absence of love in modern technological society, a great
subject in a small space.
through which the beauty of the world has been obscured for us. This
language was of theoretical use in the corning to be of technological
science; one of its prices, however, was to obscure beauty. To state the
literal meaning of 'objects' yet once again: it speaks of anything which
is held away from us for our questioning. Any beautiful thing can be
made into an object by us and for us and we can analyze it so that it will
give us its reasons as an object. But if we confine our attention to any
thing as if it were simply an object, it cannot be loved as beautiful. This
is well illustrated in the division between useful and non-useful criti-
cism by professors of literature and music who explicate the texts of
works of art. For example, many such explications of Shakespeare or
Mozart add to our understanding of the works concerned. But one
central way of dividing the useful from the non-useful among such crit-
icisms is the recognition by the critic that his work is a means to an
end, which is the further understanding of the beauty of what is being
studied.
When such writing appears stultifying, it is that the critic has stood
over the thing studied and therefore the thing has remained an object.
Its objectivity has not been a passing means but an end. (It may be said
in parenthesis that such failed works often seem to appear because the
professors concerned want to share the prestige of objectivity with their
colleagues from the mastering sciences.) Only as anything stands
before us in some relation other than the objective can we learn of its
beauty and from its beauty. To say this may seem no more than a lin-
guistic trick upon the use of the word 'objective.' But this is not so. The
language of 'subject' and 'object' can easily suffocate our recognition
of the beauty of the world. In stating that the beauty of otherness is the
central assumption in the aphorism 'Faith is the experience that the
intelligence is enlightened by love,' it is necessary to bring into con-
sciousness the sheer power of the contemporary language of 'subjects'
and 'objects,' so that the statement is not killed by that language.
Indeed, the central difficulty of using the language of beauty and
love, in the affirmation that one knows more about something in loving
it, is that in that language beauty was known as an image of goodness
itself. Yet through the modern paradigm of knowledge the conception
of good has been emptied into uncertainty. The first stage of this emp-
tying was when good came to be used simply in discourse about human
ethical questions. In the last century the emptying has gone farther.
'Good' has largely been replaced in our ethical discourse by the word
'value.' The modern emptying of 'good' can indeed be seen in the
466 The Beautiful and the Good
tion of trust. We start with trust in our knowledge of those things we are
presented with immediately, and doubt is the means of moving to an
understanding of what makes possible that trust in an educated human
being. The identity of doubt and systematic thought which lies in the
origin of the modern experiment was not present in Socrates's enter-
prise. The modern assertion that what we are is best expressed as
'beings towards death' would certainly have been in Socrates's mind in
what he said at the time of his execution. But it was not for him the final
word about what we are. At the moment when his death was immediate
he made clear that we are beings towards good. It was indeed for this
reason that in the scene of his death, Socrates asserts that the absence
of knowledge of good is not ignorance but madness.
The central cause of the modern emptying of the word 'good' is that
the new technological scientist defined the scopes and method of their
activity in terms of their criticism of the old Aristotelian science, which
had described things through the conception of purpose. The modern
understanding of things in terms of necessity and chance, through
algebraic method, has led not only to our conquest of nature, but to an
understanding of things outside the idea of purpose. The successes of
this method are a source of wonder (use the synonym 'admiration' if
you will) to any sane person.
The new science (however one may sometimes flinch at what it says)
had some appeal to certain Christians, in the very fact that it had
defined itself against the ideological science of medieval Aristotelian-
ism. When this science was used unwisely by official Christianity, in the
name of ecclesiastical power, to assert that purpose in nature pointed
to an overriding purpose given for the universe as a whole, it is under-
standable why many turned away from a science so triumphally used.
The more representable the purpose of the whole was said to be, the
more this natural theology became a trivializing, a blasphemy against
the cross. Some of the most depressing episodes in Christian history
have been the spilling of much silly ink to show that the universe as a
whole vouchsafed a representable purpose of design analogous to the
way that the purpose of the automaker is given in the design of the
automobile.
Nevertheless, it is obvious that faith cannot turn away from the idea
of good. Faith affirms that all that is, proceeds from beneficence. If
faith is said to be the experience that the intelligence is enlightened by
love, and love is said to be the apprehension of otherness as beautiful,
then the question must arise whether this definition is not the kind of
468 The Beautiful and the Good
blasphemy of which I have been writing. Is it not saying that the beauty
of the world gives us a representable purpose for the whole? Is it not
just the kind of distortion which turns us from the facts of the world so
that we seem able to affirm what is contradicted by the evident experi-
ence of living? Through it are we not led to assert that evil is good and
good is evil, and so lose what is essential to any love of truth - namely
the continual recognition that the world is as it is?
In writing about love of beauty, it is therefore necessary to say some-
thing of how the language of good and purpose is used about the
beauty of the world without trivializing suffering. It is best to start from
works of art, for here there is obvious purposiveness in that they are
made by human beings, in some sense comparable to the automobile,
in some sense not. They are both purposive in that means are arranged
in the light of a purposed end. We can speak both of a well-made car
and a well-made concerto. But it is certainly harder to represent to our-
selves the purpose of the work of art. Certain works of art can be par-
tially understood in terms of their well-defined external purposes.
Bach's Passions were written to help believers focus their attention and
their prayers around the originating events of Christianity. But when
we turn to Bach's concerto for two violins it is less clear that we can rep-
resent its purpose.
Nowadays much of our time is filled by works of art. Their purpose is
to entertain. Entertainment is the agreeable occupation of our atten-
tion - in the sense of what we happen to like. What was spoken in the
Greek technebecame the Latin ars. Plows and plays were both made by
human beings and the making was named by the same word. In our
world the activities called technical and artistic have separated between
the practically useful and the entertaining. In both cases means are
carefully adjusted to ends to produce a good car or computer, play, or
concerto. The skillful gathering together of means for the car is for the
purpose for getting us around; in the play for the agreeable occupation
of our attention. This account is everywhere in democratic capitalistic
societies.
It is against this account of art that it is necessary to write. It stands
between us and any proper apprehension of works of art and ruins our
partaking in their beauty. The purpose of a car can be represented
rightly as a means of getting us around; the purpose of a work of art is
not properly represented as merely entertainment. Indeed, the greater
the work of art the less can its purpose be represented at all. The stag-
gered silence with which we can watch King Lear is evidence that some-
Love 469
The question is how my art proceeds in writing and working out great
and important matters. I can say no more than this, for I know no more
George Gershwin (1898-1937), piano concerto in F major, opus 2 (1924).
Mozart's piano concerto in E flat.
Mozart's piano concerto in C minor.
470 The Beautiful and the Good
and can come upon nothing further. When I am well and have good sur-
roundings, travelling in a carriage, or after a good meal or a walk or at
night when I cannot sleep, then ideas come to me best and in torrents.
Where they come from and how they come I just do not know. I keep in
my head those that please me and hum them aloud as others have told
me. When I have that all carefully in my head, the rest comes quickly, one
thing after another; I see where such fragments could be used to make a
composition of them all, by employing the rules of counterpoint and the
sound of different instruments etc. My soul is then on fire as long as I am
not disturbed; the idea expands, I develop it, all becoming clearer and
clearer. The piece becomes almost complete in my head, even if it is a
long one, so that afterwards I see it in my spirit all in one look, as one sees
a beautiful picture or beautiful human being. I am saying that in imagina-
tion I do not understand the parts one after another, in the order that
they ought to follow in the music; I understand them altogether at one
moment. Delicious moments. When the ideas are discovered and put into
a work, all occurs in me as in a beautiful dream which is quite lucid. But
the most beautiful is to understand it all at one moment. What has hap-
pened I do not easily forget and this is the best gift which our God has
given me. When it afterwards comes to writing, I take out of the bag of my
mind what had previously gathered into it. Then it gets pretty quickly put
down on paper, being strictly, as was said, already perfect, and generally
in much the same way as it was in my head before.3
Latin tueor, to look. When Mozart says that after composing a piece of
music he sees it 'all in one look' and when he says he understands it all
at one moment, he is surely describing an act which can properly be
named 'intellectual intuition.' Secondly, it is worth remembering when
Mozart speaks of understanding (in German the very similar word ver-
steheri) he did so at a time when Kant was exalting reason above under-
standing, in the name of his account of human being as 'autonomous.'
This was to place on its head the teaching of Plato in which understand-
ing is the height for human beings. Indeed, the English 'to understand'
and the German verstehenvtere in their origins filled with that very sense
of receptivity which Kant lessens in the name of our freedom.
Critics who write within the historicist assumptions of our time might
choose to deconstruct this letter in one way or another. They say that
Mozart's music is a different matter from his justifying explanation of
his understanding of it. At another level it might be said in languages of
modern physiology and psychology that the language of gift and the
fire of love can now be better understood for what they are than in
Mozart's 'naive' words. Indeed, with our new knowledge it may be said
that we will be able to add to the Mozartian corpus by means of the
computer. Mozart's assertion that he understood the whole of a piece
in one look and heard it all at one moment can only be wiped away if we
speak entirely within the languages of the new sciences. What has been
lost as against what has been found in the self-definition of the modern
paradigm here appears to me evident.
What can be meant by the beauty of the world becomes more ambig-
uous when we pay attention to those things which have not been made
by human beings. At a common sense level, Vice's insistence that we
understand what we have made in a way we cannot understand what we
have not made seems correct. More importantly, it is difficult to par-
take in the beauty of the world because of the misery, the hardness, the
sadness of so much of our lives, which is caused not only by the ugliness
in ourselves, but by the very conditions of the non-human world. As has
often been said, the very drive to technological science arose with the
desire to overcome these vicissitudes. The key difficulty in receiving the
beauty of the world these days is that such teaching is rooted in the act
of looking at the world as it is, while the dominant science is rooted in
the desire to change it.
I am not saying that the beauty of the world is vouchsafed above all
when untouched by human making. It would be senseless to think of
cultivated land as unbeautiful. Race horses are beautiful. Neverthe-
472 The Beautiful and the Good
ity, that sexual desire can drive love out from its presence. It can
become the rock of 'reality' on which the search for the beauty of the
world founders.
In an age in which the paradigm of knowledge has no place for our
partaking in eternity, it is understandable that orgasmic fulfilment has
been made out to be the height of our existing - indeed, that which
gives our existing some kind of immanent justification. The materialists
have taken it as their heaven. But this modern union of individuality
and materialism has meant a transposition of older beliefs about the
relation of sex and love. In the older beliefs sexual desire was one
means through which love between human beings could abound; in
our era love seems sometimes to be thought of as a means for the
abounding of sexual enjoyment.
Because sexuality is such a great power and because it is a means to
love, societies in the past hedged it around with diverse and often
strange systems of restraint. Such restraints were considered sacred,
because their final justification (whatever other justifications were
present) was the love of the beautiful, and that was considered sacred.
Modern social scientists have changed the original meaning of 'taboo'
into the socially and psychologically 'forbidden,' in the attempt to
teach us that restraints are not sacred. This is of course useful to a cap-
italist society because everything must be made instrumental to the for-
warding of 'production,' and the sacred restraints cannot be made
instrumental. Social scientists follow their creator, because social sci-
ence was created by capitalist society.
It is the reversal in the hierarchy of love and sex which has led in the
modern world to the attempt to remove the relation between sexuality
and the birth of children. The love of the beauty of the world in sexual
life was believed to have some relation to the love of the beauty of the
world found in progeny. (In using the word 'some' before 'relation,' I
imply that I am not speaking against contraception.) But if orgasmic
fulfilment is the height of all existing, it has no need of such extension.
Obviously, love has to be protected by societies, because the human
condition is such that the tenderness of the flesh leaves everybody at
the terrible mercy of others. Yet at this time in 'advanced' societies, jus-
tice has been massively withdrawn from unborn children.
In the pre-progressive societies, however differently (and often per-
versely) love was brought within different orders, those loves were not
considered entirely blind, because they were the way that human beings
were moved out of self-engrossment to find joy in the world. Indeed,
474 The Beautiful and the Good
the words 'to love' and 'to know' were joined. For example, because of
the intensity and intimacy of orgasmic love, it was said when people
freely participated in it, they 'knew' each other. Love was not consid-
ered in its essence blind. It was for this reason that the family - in such
varied forms as polyandry, polygamy, monogamy, etc., -was given enor-
mous power (sometimes indeed too much) because it was believed that
in the main the family was a guardian of the interests of its members.
Indeed, one of the growing beliefs of our era is the idea that love in
its essence is blind. For people of my generation the great teacher in
matters sexual and familial was Freud. He seemed a writer who gave
sexual life its central place after the repression of the early industrial
era. But for all his concentration on love, he (like his master Nietzsche)
gave love poison to drink, because he so placed ambiguity at the centre
of love as to say that in its heart love was blind. His influence may not be
intellectually lasting. But he has been influential, particularly in North
America, in placing sexual and familial life under the hands of the
objectifiers. The 'helping' professions - psychiatrists, social workers,
etc., - are an important means of bringing people under that objective
control. This is largely done by the claim that they understand families
better than the families understand themselves.
Luckily many people are not much interested in such assumptions
and just go on loving or being indifferent or hating. But deep changes
in ways of looking at things slowly permeate, particularly in societies
whose democratic origins were bound up with the idea that philosophy
could be open to nearly everyone. Thus when a popularizer of philoso-
phy such as Sartre writes that 'hell is other people,' he makes starkly
open the modern division between love and intelligence.
The results of the division of love and intelligence are evident when
one speaks of knowledge of justice. In the older tradition, justice was
defined as rendering to anything what was its due. Political justice was
the attempt to render what was due among human beings. For our-
selves, justice was rendering what was due to every aspect of our own
being, body and soul, as we were then considered to be. In the non-
human world it was rendering the proper due to cattle and bears,
wheat and stones, to God or the gods. Justice was then not only arrange-
ments to be realized in any given society, but also a state of the individ-
ual which was called a virtue. Of course, the question arose to thought,
why is anything due to anything? Once any due had been granted, the
question came to be what was properly due to any being. Socrates shows
in his debate with Callicles in Gorgias that life demands the idea of due.
Love 475
ularly when that interference is in the name of some virtue which seems
completely alien to us.
Nevertheless, it seems necessary to state what has been lost theoreti-
cally in the modern definitions of justice. What has been lost is the
belief that justice is something in which we participate as we come to
understand the nature of things through love and knowledge. Modern
theories of justice present it as something human beings make and
impose for human convenience. This is done in a physical environment
which is understood in terms of necessity and chance. Obviously the
traditional belief, as much as the modern, included cognizance that
human beings were responsible for doing things about justice. Human
beings built cities, empires, etc., and some regimes were better than
others. To use the favorite expression of the Enlightenment, human
beings have in modernity taken their fate into their own hands. Their
theories of justice teach them that our institutions are what we make in
terms of our own convenience.
The central cause of this great change has been modern natural sci-
ence. Brilliant scientists have laid before us an account of how things
are, and in that account nothing can be said about justice. It is indeed
not surprising, therefore, that in the coming to be of technological sci-
ence the dependence of our objective science upon calculus has been
matched by the dependence for knowledge of justice upon calculation.
When the world is understood as necessity and chance, then justice has
to be made by the 'authentic' freedom of human beings, so that con-
flicts between our pleasure seekings can be worked out. It is not surpris-
ing that those studies in our multiversities which depended on our
intelligence being enlightened by love, and which were publicly sus-
tained because they taught people to participate injustice, should now
have faded into antiquarian research. After all it is not very difficult to
know these days what justice is, what beauty is. The first is the result of
interested calculation; the second is the means of entertainment.
The woman who wrote the definition of faith from which I have pro-
ceeded once also wrote: 'One can never wrestle enough with God if one
does so out of pure regard for the truth. Christ likes us to prefer truth
to him because, before being Christ, he is truth. If one turns aside for
him to go towards truth, one will not go far before falling into his arms.'
That is a great hope given us by a woman who had pure regard and who
480 The Beautiful and the Good
had gone far. But did she, in the sheer force of her intellect, know how
much the rest of us can be diverted by the modern paradigm from that
fearful wrestling - and indeed from the pure regard? How is it possible
to think that the modern paradigm is sufficient to the needs of human
beings? And yet how is it- possible, in the midst of that paradigm and its
stranger and wilder consequences, to reach into the truth that the
world proceeds from goodness itself?
NOTES
abortion 108, 115, 142, 146, 148, 149, 16, 17, 187, 211, 212, 312, 331, 398;
296, 415 City of God 15, 329; De Trinitate 15;
Action Catholique 123 and Plato 211,217
Aitchison, Jim 311 Augustus, Emperor 215, 217
Alexander of Macedon 270 Ayer, AJ. 305
Allport, Gordon 217
Amnesty International 456n, 457, Bach.Johan Sebastian 173, 468, 470
459 Bacon, Francis 22, 26, 38, 223, 224,
Anansi Press 366 321-2
Anderson, Francis 321, 321, 322 Barre, Laurent 122
Anderson, Fulton 22-3, 157, 190 'The Battle between Teaching and
Antigone 249 Research' 13
antiquarianism 285, 303 Battle of the Books 365, 477
anti-Semitism 380-1, 382 Bayleyjohn 370
Aquinas, Saint Thomas 211, 312, 477 Beautiful, the 28
Aristophanes 290 Beautiful Losers 368
Aristotle 8, 18, 38, 71, 81, 169, 179, beauty 253, 438-9, 464-72
188, 212, 221, 222, 236n, 266, 296, being 298, 363, 364, 442, 460
302, 362, 373, 440; as seen in the Being and Time 15, 297, 300, 302, 304
age of progress 82; and suffering Bennett, R.B. 123, 139
220 Bentham, Jeremy 130, 312, 398
Arnold, Matthew 376 Beowulf 195
art 358, 374, 410-11, 468; and enter- Bertrand, Jean-Jacques 127
tainment 468 Beyond Good and Evil292, 418
Assisi, Saint Francis of 241 Bhagavadgita 243, 251, 261
Atwood, Margaret 151 Bible, the 357-61, 462
Augustine of Hippo, Saint 4, 14, 15, Blackmun, Harry A. 109, 415
484 Index
of 69; in society 68-75; in the tech- Frye, Northrop 23, 167, 357-61, 412;
nological society 74 and polytheism 360
excellence, human 198, 200 Fukuyama, Frances; The End of His-
existentialism 298, 300, 360, 367, tory and the Last Man 19
414; philosophers of 333 Fulbright, J.W. 90, 92, 93
existentialists 286
Expo '67 105, 105n Gandhi, Mohandas Karamchand
(Mahatma) 89
Fackenheim, Emile 18 George Gershwin; Rhapsody in Blue
fact-value distinction 12, 120, 192, 469
193, 194, 219, 281, 392; and social Gladstone, William 138, 139, 140,
science 392 477
faith 251, 461, 463, 467 Globe and Mail 200
'Faith and the Multiversity' 16, 30, Glover, Edward 337
237 gnosticism 338, 344
Farrer, Austin 441 gnostics 342, 343
fascism 142, 147, 149; and North God 4,11, 35, 53, 59, 69, 80,148, 179,
America 149 180,187, 211, 227, 229, 237, 258,
fate, the love of 281-3, 284, 285, 286 391, 396, 428, 439, 474, 480; the
The Feminine Mystique 392 existence of 212; the love of 176
Flexner, Simon 203, 203n Goldwater, Barry 95
Forsey, Eugene 3 Good 7, 28, 207, 209, 221, 387, 456,
Franklin, Benjamin 401, 402 465-7
A Free Man's Worship 332, 333 'Good Friday' 28
freedom 8, 52-3, 82, 86, 89, 389-90, goodness 429
391, 393, 396, 405, 429, 430, 449, Gorgias 474
450; human 423; in a technologi- Gospels, the 14, 80, 243, 252, 358,
cal society 389; in the technologi- 360, 475
cal world 58 Graham, Billy 97, 183, 402
Free-Trade Agreement 150, 151 Grant, George Munro 3, 43
Frege, F.L.G. 381 Grant, George Parkin 294; as a Chris-
Freud, Anna 257, 259 tian Platonist; and Christianity 27-
Freud, Sigmund 23, 118, 219, 286, 8, 31; correspondence with Leo
333, 474, 334-44; 345, 346, 347, Strauss 19; and the crucifixion 28,
348, 349, 351, 354; Civilization and 447; defence of Plato against
Its Discontents 337, 350 Heidegger 20, 31, 297, 306; and
Friedan, Betty 392; The Feminine Mys- justice 27; and liberalism 211; and
tique 392 modernity 24; as a political philos-
friendship 361-2 opher 295; and religion 27; and
Front de liberation du Quebec 102 technology 25-7; The Battle
Index 487