0% found this document useful (0 votes)
14 views

Conflict War and Revolution 1 Introduction Conflict War Revolution and The Chara

Uploaded by

tessa.giannone
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
14 views

Conflict War and Revolution 1 Introduction Conflict War Revolution and The Chara

Uploaded by

tessa.giannone
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 29

Introduction

Paul Kelly

Introduction from

Paul Kelly

CONFLICT,
WAR and
REVOLUTION

Suggested citation: Kelly, Paul. (2022) ‘Introduction’, in Paul Kelly, Conflict,


War and Revolution: The problem of politics in international political thought.
London: LSE Press, 2022. https://doi.org/10.31389/lsepress.cwr.a

© Paul Kelly 2022. Published under a Creative Commons Attribution


NonCommercial licence allowing users to distribute, remix, adapt, and build
upon the material in any medium or format, so long as attribution is given
to the creator. The license does not allow for commercial use.
CH A PT ER 1

Introduction
Conflict, war, revolution and the character
of politics

We live in interesting times! Apocryphally, this is a Chinese curse, although


there is little evidence that the English version, ‘May you live in interesting
times’, matches any precise Chinese aphorism. Be that as it may, the times we
live in are interesting, in that many very recent political preconceptions and
trends of history are being turned on their heads, and this is happening in
both confusing and troubling ways, the victims and beneficiaries of which are
unclear. When Francis Fukuyama published his famous article ‘The End of His-
tory’ in 1989, it coincided with the collapse of the USSR, the fall of the Berlin
Wall and the end of the Cold War. Although too much triumphalism has been
unfairly attributed to Fukuyama’s subtle argument, the title certainly chimed
with the age. It was also pretty much clear to everyone who the beneficiar-
ies and losers of that historical moment were. Globalisation (and U.S. military
power) defeated ‘really existing socialism’, and with the subsequent first Gulf
War in 1991 the western military and economic order looked as if it had the
blessing of history. This, coupled with what is often called the ‘great modera-
tion’, the period of stable and steady economic growth in western developed
economies unleashed by economic deregulation and globalised trade during
the 1990s and the early 2000s, further vindicated globalised finance and the
‘Washington consensus’ on growth – an economic policy stance that is called
globalisation by its supporters and neo-liberalism by its critics. In Europe and
the European Union, many of the more enthusiastic EU backers saw a move

How to cite this book chapter:


Kelly, Paul. 2022. Conflict, war and revolution: The problem of politics in international
political thought. London: LSE Press, pp. 1–28.
DOI: https://doi.org/10.31389/lsepress.cwr.a License: CC BY.
2 Conflict, War and Revolution

away from the model of nation states as the ‘end of history’ to a post-state order
modelled on closer cooperation and integration: again. Although his argu-
ment is more subtle and qualified than this, we can see this optimism in the
great German social and political philosopher Jürgen Habermas (Habermas
1998; 2005). Books were being written about the rise of ‘cosmopolitan’ democ-
racy, world politics and the new political configurations needed to govern this
new order.
Yet all was not quite what it seemed. The terrible events of 11 September
2001 unleashed the most significant attack on the continental USA in its his-
tory when a group of suicide bombers weaponised domestic airliners to bring
down the World Trade Center in New York City and attack the Pentagon, head-
quarters of the U.S. Department of Defense. An essentially low-technology
attack, by a previously little-known terrorist group, Al-Qaeda, had challenged
the most technologically sophisticated military ever seen in history. The U.S.-
led response in Afghanistan (where the Taliban gave succour to Al-Qaeda) and
then Iraq (where Saddam Hussein did not) unleashed nearly two decades of
struggle in the Middle East. A nuclear-armed USSR was replaced as the domi-
nant enemy of ‘the west’ by an asymmetrical struggle against a jihadist enemy
indifferent to the fear of death and which had no prospect of victory in any
conventional sense. Al-Qaeda is not a military structure with a territory, gov-
ernment or a return address.
Other events quickly followed the triumph of neo-liberal globalism and the
rise of global terrorism, with Al-Qaeda and then more recently ISIS/Daesh,
ensuring that international affairs became even more ‘interesting’ and urgent.
These included the global financial crash in 2007–2008, the rise of China as the
default backer of the global financial order (as the largest holder of U.S. debt),
the subsequent rise of populism in the U.S. and Europe with the election of a
protectionist and nationalist President Trump, and the vote by the UK (one of
the largest and most important economic and political players in the European
Union) to leave the EU following a domestic referendum (Brexit). The global
institutions considered necessary for a stable world order, and which had deliv-
ered the great moderation, were now seen to be lacking political legitimacy.
They faced a concerted backlash from political forces on a scale that had not
been seen since the 1930s, and which threatened the domestic political struc-
tures of states that were supposed to be exemplars of democratic stability.
This complex pattern of events spanning four decades thus saw the triumph
of the west and the rise of the east; the triumph of globalisation and the resur-
gence of protectionism and economic nationalism; the end of the Cold War
and the launch of the global War on Terror. The pace of change has been bewil-
dering even in a new century that has seen unprecedented transformations
in human affairs (to 2021). This shift from an historical trajectory of liberal
dominance and global order might seem challenging, and it is, but is it unique?
Or is it not just a case of history – which perhaps naively we thought had
Introduction 3

ended – forcing its way back onto the agenda? International affairs and the
thinking about it have always fluctuated between periods of progressive opti-
mism and revolution, retrenchment and irredentism. Whilst there remains
much about which we should remain optimistic, the challenges of the present,
and the echoes of past crises, raise questions about the ways in which we think
about and frame political action and agency, and especially about the adequacy
of the dominant paradigms of international political thinking.
In this book, in a timeframe spanning the ancient world to the present, I
examine the sources of some of those intellectual paradigms by exploring the
ideas of a number of significant figures who illuminate ways of thinking about
the challenges of politics and the prevalence of crisis and conflict. By study-
ing 10 paradigmatic thinkers – Thucydides, Augustine, Machiavelli, Hobbes,
Locke, Rousseau, Clausewitz, Lenin and Mao, and Carl Schmitt – I examine
important debates in international political thought. The particular focus
here is on those who wish to challenge or qualify the hope of redemption and
order in human affairs by overcoming politics, versus thinkers who address the
ineradicable necessity and challenges of politics, war and conflict. This may
sometimes look like a ‘history’ of what international theorists and international
relations scholars refer to as a tradition of realism, but my purpose is different.
Positing traditions such as realism already presupposes an answer to the
question of how to read these thinkers and assumes that they conform to a
single narrative (cf. Doyle 1997), but this is a narrowly circumscribed can-
vass. This book sets these key thinkers in a wider context, using them to iden-
tify and explore different ways of conceiving of the activity of politics as an
autonomous way of acting in the world. The concept of realism falls within
that domain because some of the thinkers discussed have been seen by some
scholars as adherents of versions of this view. But, as we shall see, describing
all these thinkers as ‘realist’ in the sense used either by international relations
or by international political theory raises questions about the value and scope
of that concept (see Chapter 11 for more on this).
The other reason this book is not a simple ‘history’ is that it does not aim
to be comprehensive. There are clearly other ways of conceiving of interna-
tional politics, and other narratives that may better explain the development of
doctrines in the western tradition and beyond. To write such a comprehensive
overview would be a considerably longer book, and it would also raise ques-
tions about the idea of a single history, issues that I mostly deliberately avoid
(but see chapter 11). It is sufficient for this book to present a canon of thinkers
whose ideas and approaches inform and illuminate some of the central ques-
tions of international politics and its contemporary challenges.
Precisely because it paints on such a large canvas, international political
thought is a peculiarly valuable approach to understanding some of the most
important questions about politics. It also leaves open precisely the sorts of ques-
tions, concepts and approaches that the 10 major thinkers here explored. They
4 Conflict, War and Revolution

all tackled fundamental questions about the nature of political activity and
the vehicles through which political agency is exercised at different times
and places – without privileging the development or priority of any particu-
lar mode of organisation, whether polis, empire, principality, multitude, state,
nation, class or nomos.
The perspective of international theory helps transcend the narrow confines
of domestic politics as the distribution of ‘who gets what, where, when and
how’ (Lasswell 1936). Instead, it focuses attention on what might be called a
meta-level where the real and fundamental work of delineating political agency
takes place. In some standard introductions to political thinking, the explana-
tion begins with human actors, then moves up to the state or political com-
munity level, and terminates with the way those communities interact in the
international realm. This is the model of the domestic and the international so
fundamental to standard international relations theory, but it is also common-
place in political theory courses.
Focusing on international theory allows one to look at the bigger picture
out of which much domestic politics emerges. It does not presuppose the pri-
macy of domestic politics and see the international as a problematic remainder.
Instead, it conceives of the challenges of the international realm as, if not prior
or autonomous, then at least co-present with the challenge of delimiting politi-
cal communities and sites of political agency. It is not surprising that much
political theory and philosophy regards the perspective of international theory
as secondary or an afterthought. That is indeed the legacy of Hobbes’s work on
political thought and international relations, a legacy that can be seen echoed
in the work of the most important late 20th-century political philosopher, John
Rawls. But this was clearly not the view of Augustine and Machiavelli, to take
only two examples, for whom this distinction between domestic and interna-
tional would have made no sense.
The narrative in this book deliberately eschews the term ‘history’ because
it does not attempt to provide an overview of all the approaches one may find
in international political thought courses. Indeed, if one refers back to my
list of modes of organisation of political agency above, I deliberately left out
organising categories such as the individual, society or economy, all of which
would feature in some way in a comprehensive account of international politi-
cal thought in the western canon. This choice is perhaps controversial, but it is
a deliberate attempt to range beyond reductive approaches that reduce politics
to morality, or to the economy and society. Too much contemporary think-
ing about our current global predicament suggests that there is a progressive
unfolding of order that culminates in the triumph of the modern Westphal-
ian state system and its international institutions alongside a globalised market
economy. These approaches to international politics privilege the individual
person as a right-holder or bearer of a unique ethical dignity, or as an individ-
ual utility maximiser with a clear preference order. In much academic debate
Introduction 5

and in much political theory and science, this conception of the person has
been taken to be a true account of moral and economic agency, and as the basis
of all other political arrangements and groups. This has led to the prevalence of
an unchallenged but apolitical cosmopolitanism that has marginalised some
of the most fundamental challenges facing contemporary politics.
In this book, I do not seek to reject individualism or cosmopolitanism as
systems of value. Indeed, elsewhere I have written to endorse a version of this
perspective as liberal-egalitarianism (Kelly 2005). But in the current climate,
with challenges to the conception of agency that underpins such an approach,
I am more interested in the challenges to that world view that are arguably
returning to centre stage. This individualistic and cosmopolitan view of the
domain of the political has not only shaped contemporary political science and
international relations. It has also done so to the exclusion of perspectives that
force us to confront different ways of doing politics, exercising power, force and
violence, and conceiving of the goals of political activity and its fundamental
purpose. This book attempts instead to introduce political thinking and inter-
national political theory without indirectly presupposing that political agency
and institutions must have a settled character and structure that conform to
moral individualism and converge on liberal constitutionalism as the best form
of political organisation.
My purpose is to let a set of thinkers speak in their own voices rather
than reducing them to a settled historical and cultural narrative, or to pre-
established traditions such as realism, or ideologies such as liberalism. So, the
linking narrative here must be abstract and general and stay at a high level. Nev-
ertheless, there are important linkages between the chapters that explain the
juxtaposition of these particular thinkers, as opposed to an alternative canon
or narrative. All of them take as fundamental the role of violence, conflict and
coercion. Violence and conflict are either the perennial experience of human-
ity beneath the thin veneer of civilisation or an aspect of human experience
that morality and society attempt to discipline and obscure but which remains
the basic stuff of political action and agency. For others still, these experiences
are characteristic of life beyond the protections offered by state sovereignty in
the anarchic world of international or interstate politics. Some of the thinkers
conceive of violence as an ineradicable problem. For others, violence is morally
ambiguous as a feature of experience that can be manipulated and channelled
to achieve different ends and goals. We tend to think of both violence and con-
flict as bad things that must be avoided or mitigated. But at a more fundamental
level one might also argue that these are merely natural forces that we can con-
demn under some descriptions whilst also praise under others. After all, is it
not the case that order entails coercion (for all except anarchists), as indeed does
the law – as indeed (if we follow St Augustine) does peace? Finally, under the
headings of war and revolution we find approaches to politics that channel vio-
lence into pursuing goals that cannot be achieved by negotiation, deliberation
6 Conflict, War and Revolution

and compromise. In the case of revolution, they use violence to remove the
existing order so as to (in theory) make way for a world beyond the violence
and coercion of politics.
Discussing and contrasting these paradigmatic thinkers provides a theoretical
introduction to international political theory. But what precisely is interna­
tional political theory and how, if at all, does it differ from the study of inter­
national relations, and its sub-division international relations theory, or from
the study of the history of political thought? International relations theory
and the history of political thought are recognised academic activities. So it is
important to show that international political theory is not simply a confused
renaming of an already-familiar activity, or a more primitive and less clearly
defined version of academic sub-divisions. In the next two sections I make a
substantial argument in favour of defending international political theory and
distinguishing it from the history of political thought. But, before turning to
that argument, I want to distinguish international political theory from inter-
national relations theory.
The distinction between international relations theory and international
political theory developed over the last few decades as a consequence of the
disciplinary development of international relations on the one hand and
the growth of normative political theory and applied ethics in political sci-
ence and philosophy on the other. Chris Brown provided the most compelling
account of how international political theory separated out from mainstream
international relations theory. He linked it to the development in social sci-
ence of a dominant turn towards positivism, which is an explanatory form
of enquiry assuming that the facts or objects of study are stable and can be
examined in ways analogous to the natural sciences (Brown 2015; Brown and
Eckersley 2018). This positivist turn is exemplified in the application of formal
modelling and economistic forms of theorising (such as rational choice theory)
to traditional questions of national and state interaction and bargaining, as
illustrated by leading theorists such as Kenneth Waltz (Waltz 1979). According
to Brown, international political theorists are authors who see this as an unfor-
tunate departure from humanistic approaches to the study of international
relations that characterised its early origins as a distinct form of enquiry.
However, the issue is not just a war of methods between quantitative and
formal theory against qualitative or historical approaches. It also relates to the
point and style of international relations arguments. The turn to positivism and
the primacy of explanation at the expense of normative and prescriptive argu-
ments coincided with a resurgence of normative arguments in political theory
and applied ethics under the influence of major theorists such as John Rawls,
Michael Walzer and Peter Singer (Forrester 2019). These thinkers launched
debates or rekindled questions about distributive justice and state legitimacy,
the justification of war and what obligations we owe to distant others in the face
of famine or global poverty. All of these questions have an element that links
them to the familiar intellectual territory of traditional international relations
Introduction 7

theory. But they also depart from it because they either challenge its apparent
statist assumptions or attempt to provide normative and prescriptive accounts
for what states or other international agents ought to do, irrespective of what
they may be likely to do in relation to their interests. It is often the case that
disciplinary development happens because of the recognition that something
interesting and intellectually exiting was happening elsewhere, just beyond tra-
ditional disciplinary boundaries – see, for example, the way in which modern
behavioural economics has turned to experimental psychology. That is also true
with the development of international political theory. Yet, at the same time
there is not simply a turn to familiar normative political thought, which is often
poorly informed about the reality of international affairs and politics. It is pre-
cisely a critical engagement with normative and prescriptive arguments about
the international domain that makes the study of international political theory
important and vital. It also explains the particular selection of paradigmatic
thinkers in this book. International political theory does not merely dismiss, or
wilfully overlook, normative and prescriptive arguments as methodologically
primitive, in the way it claims that standard international relations theory per-
haps does. Rather, it brings them back to the forefront of engagement with the
sorts of challenges that shape and unsettle our times. In so doing, international
political theory also raises questions about the vocabulary, source and scope of
approaches, languages and concepts – precisely what this book considers.

Texts, contexts, thoughts or thinkers?

Studying the work of groups of thinkers from the past is often referred to as cre-
ating a canon. The approach has been a recognisable part of the study of politics
since the emergence of the discipline of political science in the late 19th cen-
tury (Boucher 1985; Kelly 1999). For most of that time, a series of great think-
ers were gathered together to illustrate the dominant story of the emergence
of the modern state. Reflecting on those past thinkers was part of a forward-
looking activity that suggested arguments, principles and institutional models
that could then be contrasted with current developments – all with the purpose
of legitimating or improving the contemporary liberal state system. Just as in
early international relations, many arguments based on this kind of enquiry
were both prescriptive and normative. As the modern discipline of political sci­
ence developed in the post-World War II period, the importance of political
thought gave way to the study of political behaviour, political institutions and
the development of comparative politics. The broad and eclectic study of politi-
cal thinkers came to seem intellectually crude as it either lacked the robust-
ness of a method or else followed the dictum of the 19th-century Cambridge
constitutional historian F.W. Maitland that political science is ‘either history or
humbug’. The new field had a method but it was one that already had an intel-
lectual home in the discipline of history. For radical critics of the modern state,
8 Conflict, War and Revolution

history also enabled the critique of the present by showing how contemporary
political values and institutions were tainted by their origins in colonialism or
patriarchy. With the subsequent development of normative political theory
(exemplified by Rawls, Walzer and Singer), the study of past political ideas
seemed a distraction. We should instead be ‘doing our thinking for ourselves’,
to paraphrase Brian Barry, one of the most uncompromising of British norma-
tive political theorists (Barry 1965; Forrester 2019).
In this context, the revolution in the methodology of the history of politi-
cal thought associated with Quentin Skinner and his colleagues claimed the
whole terrain of past political thought for historians of thought. In magiste-
rial essays – including ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’
(Skinner 1969) and his now-classic two-volume study The Foundations of Mod-
ern Political Theory (Skinner 1978), he set a benchmark for any credible history
of political ideas and deprecated any alternative uses of ‘historical’ texts for
studying political or international political thinking. Skinner’s 1969 article pro-
vides a forceful criticism of both textualism and contextualism as appropriate
objects of enquiries.
In his view, textualists are guilty of the mythology of coherence by claiming
that a single book or text is the appropriate object of enquiry. This raises general
questions about the appropriateness of reducing a writer’s thought to a specific
work, especially when many writers (including a number in this book) author
a number of works. Not least amongst these questions is that about the coher-
ence between earlier and later work. In the case of Thucydides, I focus on a
single authoritative text, but by contrast both Machiavelli and Rousseau devel-
oped their arguments over a number of very different books. Does textualism
impose a mythical uniformity across very distinct arguments?
The point can be more radical still if we question the coherence of an author’s
thought within a single text. Are texts, by which we normally mean books, con-
stituted by a single argument or position? For Skinner, that begs the question of
historical inquiry. By contrast, contextualists look beyond the boundaries of a
book in order to understand its meaning. Books are seen as epiphenomena of
broader social and economic forces, which in turn explain their meaning and
power. For example, Skinner criticises C.B. Macpherson’s interpretation of the
English 17th-century philosophers Thomas Hobbes and John Locke as expo-
nents of ‘possessive individualism’ or the rationalisation of the emerging class
politics of early modern capitalism (Macpherson 1962).
The problem with this form of contextualism, however, is that it is reduc-
tionist. It shifts attention away from texts as autonomous worlds of ideas to
their social context, but without adequately specifying the causal connection
between these forces and the logic and form of a specific argument. In short,
it says little about why Hobbes’s arguments have the precise form that they do.
After all, many contemporaries of Hobbes wrote books that do not rationalise
the individualism associated with capitalism in the same way.
Introduction 9

In response to the inadequacies of these rival approaches, Skinner offers


his own methodology of linguistic contextualism, drawing on the speech-
act theory of linguistic philosophers such as J.L. Austin and John Searle and
the logic of question and answer underpinning the philosophy of history of
R.G. Collingwood (Collingwood 1939).
Underlying Skinner’s historical method is a claim about the priority of the
historical approach to past political thought and an attempt to distinguish
the authentic understanding of a past thinkers’ utterances (speech-acts) from the
impositions and distortions imposed on them by the ideological predilections
of later interpreters. Utterances are a term of art derived from linguistic phi-
losophy, but in Skinner’s case these include the arguments, propositions and
positions in complex works. So, Hobbes’s Leviathan can be an utterance, as
can his particular arguments about the state of nature, or indeed particular
claims in those arguments that may be reducible to a passage or sentence. The
historical question is one about what these utterances mean. This question is
then answered by reconstructing the linguistic context, as opposed to a social
and economic context. This step sets limits on what those utterances could have
been understood to mean by the author’s contemporary audience and thus in
turn determine what the author could have been taken to be doing in making
the utterance in the way he does (it is always a ‘he’ at this stage). Political lan-
guage is always the result of someone’s attempt to do something via speech and
language. For Skinner, what that action is is an historical question and anything
else is irrelevant.
Skinner’s method has not been left unchallenged, and I will continue
that challenge in what follows. Yet, the undoubted power of his arguments
and intellectual agenda has transformed the study of past political thought and
continues to be an inspiration for subsequent scholars. Aspects of his approach
remain powerful tools of enquiry even if one does not accept his arguments
for the priority of history. A variant of this linguistic-historicist approach has
recently been extended into international theory in the work of David Armitage
(Armitage 2012).
This book focuses on single texts, combinations of texts and in some cases
combinations of thinkers who I argue make complimentary contributions to
particular debates and perspectives. The chapters make little reference to lin-
guistic contexts, albeit they also make little reference to other kinds of contexts
as primary explanations, although each thinker is situated in an historical con-
text. The arguments here also range beyond historically specific claims to assess
the logical and trans-historical value of arguments and perspectives and the
ways in which that thought is still deployed in contemporary debates and argu-
ments. At best this might seem a crude and simplistic approach, perhaps suited
to an introductory primer but one that should soon be put aside once serious
enquiry begins. At worst, my approach may seem simply a category mistake,
collapsing history into practice and advocacy.
10 Conflict, War and Revolution

In defending this approach and commending it to readers and students, I do


not claim that Skinner’s method of recovering historical meaning is incorrect,
although I think it is too narrowly focused. Instead I want to reject Skinner’s
elevation of an historical use of past texts as the only intellectually respectable
one. That position reinforces the idea that political thought and criticism cannot
be liberated from the sources from which it emerges, and therefore cuts both of
them off from the activity of political theorising. The consequent disregard for
the arguments of past thinkers, now considered to be of only historical interest,
has had a deleterious effect on contemporary political and international politi-
cal theory. A narrowly historical account of political enquiry, especially one
that effectively denies any authority to non-historical accounts of the mean-
ing, scope and the fecundity of great political texts, seriously impoverishes our
ability to engage with the challenges the world poses. Assigning priority to an
historical approach to past thought only makes sense if this is the only credible
way of approaching texts and thinkers from the past. That can only be shown to
be right if there is something special about the historical-linguistic interpreta-
tion of meanings that Skinner advocates. If an historical-linguistic approach is
only one amongst a number of valid ways of construing a text, then the special
privileging of the historical over any other mode of interpretation does not hold
and the possibility of creative interpretation remains part of political thinking.
Without getting into too technical a discussion at this stage, it is clear that
the meaning of complex texts (even construed in the variety of ways that Skin-
ner advocates) is not exhausted by the particular linguistic context of an utter-
ance in the way that a specific verbal speech-act might be. Written texts are
not exhausted by the range of meanings that an author might have consciously
intended, or by a particular interpretation of the range of intentions that the
discourse used might be interpreted to have. Because many texts are mediated
through the passage of time, they accumulate meanings that are not simply
imposed on a text but equally are not simply contained within the limits of a
given linguistic context. Texts are not identical to spoken utterances, which
are historically particular, contingent and fleeting. Texts have a life beyond the
confines of their authors’ lives, or the experiences of those who were the first
readers. Linguistic contexts are themselves made up of constellations of speech-
acts that in turn are parts of broader languages that transcend the historically
local. This does not mean that anything goes in interpreting major texts, but it
does problematise the issue of determining the linguistic context. My point is
not simply that linguistic contexts are not self-identifying and determinate. I
also want to claim that meaning in written texts is more than what is said in a
particular context, as it is also shaped by readers, interpreters and critics even
over long expanses of historical time. Furthermore, the historical-linguistic
questions one can ask of a text are not the only questions. Ideological and phil-
osophical use is an important part of what any particular reader could under-
stand by the arguments of a text.
Introduction 11

This is not to make the over-hasty claim of some postmodernists about the
death of the author and the open texture of all texts, suggesting that anything
goes. Instead, I want to follow Paul Ricoeur in asserting that there is surplus
meaning in texts beyond authorial intention or the understanding of imme-
diate audiences. So I make a claim for the idea of the overstanding of texts,
which is associated with the American literary critic Wayne Booth (Booth
1979; 1988). Indeed, if we look at literary criticism it does seem ludicrous that
the only relevant approach to the meaning of a text is a narrowly historical
one. No one would make that claim of a literary canon. Of course, literary
texts such as novels, plays and poems are different things to political texts,
although that difference can be overstated and was not always seen as essen-
tial (Boucher 1985). The point I want to emphasise is that, just as with literary
texts, the removal of improper readings (to use Booth’s phrase) is not sim-
ply done by focusing on the specific historical context in which the text was
situated. For Booth, the very idea of improper interpretations is not simply
a problem to be eradicated but is actually part of the process of overstanding
or arriving at interpretations that reflect the uses to which readers and critics
put texts, uses that can in their turn withstand critical scrutiny. So, without
diverting into a long theoretical discussion about the appropriate methodol-
ogy of criticism (which Booth as a defender of pluralism and ethical reading
denies can be given a single and final statement), we can identify intellectually
credible practices and discourses that do not attach priority to an historical
mode of understanding.
Whilst Skinner is correct to argue in his essays that many interpreters of
political texts distort the meanings of thinkers they address, this is often done
in the way any critic would operate, by critically engaging with the argument
as opposed to a narrowly historical judgement. One can say a lot about the
distortions of Hobbes as a possessive individualist without a linguistic con-
textual argument, and in doing so reinforce the view that quite a lot can be
understood by careful reading, comparison and contrast with other texts and
thinkers. Whilst it is easy to belittle careful reading – and Skinner does belittle
the scholarship of John Plamenatz, just because he suggests we can make sense
of a thinker’s argument by careful and repeated reading – Plamenatz was not
actually wrong (Plamenatz 1963). One can read Thucydides in translation and
understand an enormous amount about the intricacies of his arguments about
the significance of historical events and ideas. It would no doubt be better to
be able to master him in the original Greek, but it is just false to suggest that,
unless one reads them in their original languages and only alongside their con-
temporaries, one cannot properly understand an author’s meaning and value
as utterances. The concerns of international political theory are also norma-
tive, and in some cases prescriptive. For example, many arguments advocate as
well as explain the idea of the right of war, and these are normative arguments
that require normative criticism. In this way it is clear that our enquiry is not
12 Conflict, War and Revolution

simply a form of literary criticism, unless of course that involves ethical and
normative engagement.
I also reject the false binary between thinkers and texts. Some chapters below
are focused on texts, some on a number of texts from the same thinker, and
some compare two texts and thinkers as a way of introducing a broader theory
or position. In so doing I am not making exhaustive arguments about the his-
torical identity of a thinker or text and the theory or ideas contained therein. I
limit historical claims to historical evidence and I am aware that all such inter-
pretations are partial and incomplete, although that is true of any interpretation:
it can never be final. Instead, these interpretations and critical engagements
should be seen as akin to Weberian ‘ideal types’ and Kuhnian paradigms. They
self-consciously place in brackets aspects of a complete description for ease of
explanation and comparison, but they also account for the normative force
of an approach to political agency (Kuhn 1962).
Thomas Kuhn introduced the idea of paradigms in his social epistemology of
scientific understanding and theory-change, instead of providing a criterion
of what counts as science such as Popper’s falsifiability test (Popper [1934]
1959). For Popper, the mark of a genuine scientific claim is that it can, in prin-
ciple, be falsified by experience and counterexamples, and, where it has not,
that fact provides the measure of its credibility. Claims that could not in prin-
ciple be falsified, especially those that include all possible counter arguments,
are non-science propositions – such as religion, myth or comprehensive social
theories such as Marxism. Kuhn adopted an account of science that he claimed
was closer to the practice of science, where normal science is based around the
working through of problems within the context of an overarching paradigm
or conceptual framework. Scientific change is marked by the incremental accu-
mulation of knowledge within a given paradigm, punctuated by the occasional
revolutionary transformation that changes the overall framework in response
to ineradicable anomalies within the previous paradigm. The idea is illustrated
by the way in which Copernicus’s heliocentric view of the universe changed the
questions being asked by cosmologists and astronomers, and in turn enabled
the new physics of Galileo and Newton to supersede the Ptolemaic universe
of the ancient world. The Newtonian paradigm then served as a successful
framework until Einstein and the quantum revolution of the early 20th century.
In each case, Kuhn focuses on how the world view of a new paradigm reframes
the normal practice of scientists, most of whom work on small incremental
problems without considering the overall coherence of their work with that
of all other scientists. It is the revolutions and paradigm shifts that provide
the explanation of scientific progress and questions that are living and dead in
normal science.
Kuhn developed his language of paradigms, and normal and revolutionary
science, in the specific context of the sociology of knowledge and the practice
of rigorous scientific enquiry. That said, the looser idea of paradigms as broad
world views or frameworks that shape the structure of ordinary activity and
Introduction 13

understanding has meant that many scholars use it as a shorthand for self-
contained intellectual frameworks that influence the way in which the
problems and languages of activities can be characterised. In political and inter­
national theory, this allows for the framing of distinct ways of characterising what
politics is, without falling into the trap of assuming that there is a single uncon-
troversial object of enquiry that is progressively revealed over the historical
development or evolution of political theory. By characterising the texts, argu-
ments and thinkers in this book as paradigmatic, I emphasise the way in which
they provide frameworks for thinking about the nature of political agency and
its institutional and territorial manifestation – without assuming that each
thinker or argument is engaged with progressing beyond or overcoming the
ideas of the previous thinkers in my narrative. These free-standing paradig-
matic views may indeed be challenged and overcome by the ideas of other
paradigmatic thinkers in this narrative. But their value is primarily as exem-
plifications of different ways of thinking about and organising violence, force
and conflict as contributions to an understanding of the various challenges of
politics. The justification for these ideal typical interpretations is how useful
they are for the arguments that they are illuminating or exemplifying, and not
whether they are simply accurate accounts of the intentions of particular his-
torical figures, whether authors or their contemporary readers.

Traditions are not necessarily historicist

In one obvious sense, my reluctance to offer a history to underpin my identifi-


cation of a ‘canon’ of major works (originally meaning sacred texts) is curious.
After all, there is a chronological sequence here beginning with the ancient
Greeks in the 5th century bce and ending with 20th-century thinkers such as
Schmitt. If this narrative is not a history, what is? However, a chronology is
just a list of texts in the order of their authorship or publication. It does not
involve treating the past ‘as past’ by bringing it under any practical or phil-
osophical mode of understanding in a way that emphasises the significance
of its ‘pastness’ (Oakeshott 1983). I have argued above that the pastness of a
text is not definitive of its interpretation and critical use. There is, however,
another dimension of a history (as opposed to just a chronology), namely that
the sequence is also ordered in terms of a philosophical category.
There are a number of possible ordering narratives that could be given for
a canon that I explicitly reject, hopefully in an effective way – it will be for
the reader to decide. For instance, we could interpret the movement through the
chapters as a ‘progress’ in thought, a positive development from the Greeks to
the modern state or its postmodern replacement. Many histories of political
or international thought illustrate a progressive narrative, often referred to as
‘Whig histories’. Historically, ‘Whig history’ is associated with the 19th-century
historian Thomas Babington Macaulay, who saw the development of English
14 Conflict, War and Revolution

constitutional politics as the historical triumph of the principles of the Glori-


ous Revolution growing from 1688 to 1832. Whilst attractive for political and
ideological purposes, such an approach subordinates the details and complex-
ity of actual historical thought and events to a predetermined political goal,
in the Whig case the triumph of English political liberalism. They claim that
history has a purpose that led to and legitimates the dominant political order of
the present. I am particularly sensitive to this risk. As the author of a book on
political liberalism (Kelly 2005), it would be only too easy for me to fall into a
trap of arguing that history supports the triumph of those values – in the same
way that a crude reading of Francis Fukuyama’s thesis about the end of history
is supposed to show. Of course, Fukuyama’s subtle argument did not actually
argue for this sort of naïve historical determinism. Yet, many contemporary
and historical neo-liberals, neo-conservatives and Marxists do hold such crude
views about the logic of history and try to dress them up in the arguments
of Hegel or Marx. Liberals assume the progressive triumph of constitutional
states and free markets, whereas Marxists offer a mirror image of the progress
through successive crises towards an ultimate socialist revolution supposed
to overthrow all exploitation and conflict. Although the narrative is differ-
ent, both approaches assume that history has a logic, one that leads to human
redemption. The problems around progress, historical change and the idea of
redemption are themes explored in a different way here. All the thinkers in this
book challenge or repudiate and seek to overthrow liberal and Marxist theories
of modernisation and redemption.
To avoid any confusion, then, let me state boldly that history does not have
a logic, whether liberal, Marxist or otherwise. If one wants to defend liberal or
conservative values, or democracy or authoritarianism, then those arguments
have to be free-standing and cannot be read from the narrative of history. I
would like to believe that some kind of ‘improvement’ justification can be given
for pacific, liberal and humane values, but these claims need independent justi-
ficatory arguments. History can play a part in providing those justifications but
it is not a complete argument. It is open to the possibility of alternative non-
progressive narratives that deny the existence of any path of liberation from
oppression and ignorance, and provide accounts of history as the continued
unfolding of oppression and domination – with historical political ideas pro-
viding successive ideological justifications for that.
Another way of reading ‘Whig’ or progressive histories of thought, culmi­
nating in the triumph of human emancipation, upends them to show that the
same people billed as advocates of liberty are at the same time justifiers of colo-
nial expansion and domination, racial subordination and orientalism (Said
1979). History here only uncovers a narrative of domination and conflict.
Advocates of decolonising the canon often point out that many early mod­
ern western political theorists such as Hobbes and Locke were associated with
the colonial and imperial expansions of their countries, even if they did not
explicitly defend final-stage colonial and mercantile imperialism. The history
Introduction 15

of colonialism and empire can provide an important interpretative context


even if it does not explain what the author was trying to do. A more complex
question is whether this association vitiates the arguments of such thinkers,
especially when discussing their arguments that do not expressly support or
justify colonial domination. If one is trying to defend a set of political values
by building on the arguments of a past thinker, then it might well be the case
that such a context challenges that case. But the wider social and economic
context or the use to which a work is put should not necessarily determine the
meaning of the work. This Janus-faced character of progressive histories has
led postmodernists such as J.-F. Lyotard to reject all meta-narratives (Lyotard
1984). Just as the canon of thinkers here clearly eschews a progressivist read-
ing of international political theory, it is also not endorsing a postmodernist
critique, even though it clearly recognises the value in undermining naïve his-
torical optimism.
Avoiding implicit meta-narratives is a challenge, but it is possible, unless one
believes in a naïve historical reductionism that subordinates the actual ideas
of individual texts and thinkers to such trans-historical ideas. By juxtaposing
a series of thinkers, I intend to open a space for comparison and contrast, to
enlighten debates about the nature and scope of political agency in the interna-
tional realm, rather than to construct a pre-existing tradition such as ‘realism’
through which international politics should be understood. Meta-narratives
such as realism, idealism, liberalism and Marxism are political constructions
that take the ideas of thinkers or key concepts associated with groups of think-
ers and combine them to serve the task of political motivation. This kind of
political discourse is best described as ideological thinking (Freeden 1996). For
many scholars of political thought, ideological thinking is disparaged as a false
history, a category mistake, or a practical distortion of a thinker. This criticism
can also be overblown. There is nothing intellectually disreputable about ideo-
logical narratives such as ‘liberalism’ or ‘realism’, as long as one does not make
unjustifiable causal claims about them.
But, if one rejects any single ordering narrative and rejects ideological con-
structions of the canon, does that just leave us with a mere list of thinkers
arranged in a crude chronology? More philosophically sophisticated histories
of thought that do not wish to confine attention to the interpretation of par-
ticular thinkers often deploy the idea of ‘traditions’ in some kind of dialectical
relationship, whereby different theoretical positions develop out of the concep-
tual oppositions between their implications and their ‘negation’ or antithesis: a
classic example is the struggle between individualism and communitarianism.
Here the history of thought is explained in terms of new perspectives develop-
ing as traditions in response to contradictions in the perspectives of philosophi-
cal predecessors. One can see this approach in the sequence of three traditions
identified by Martin Wight, namely realism, rationalism and revolution –
which he subsequently named, after thinkers exemplifying those stances, as the
Machiavellian, Grotian and Kantian traditions (Wight 1994).
16 Conflict, War and Revolution

A more sophisticated and explicitly philosophical history of this kind is also


offered by David Boucher with his distinction between empirical realism, uni-
versal moral order and historical reason. For Boucher, these constructions are
not simply derived from groupings of pre-interpreted theorists, as is the case
with Wight. Rather, they use philosophical concepts that derive from but are in
turn vindicated by their contribution to the interpretations of those thinkers.
These ordering concepts, in turn, have a philosophical standing. They explain
the development of ideas not in terms of an external causal account of his-
torical events but in terms of the dialectical movement between arguments
overcoming their own internal contradictions. Such philosophical histories
have a value in that they explain the paradigmatic importance of great think-
ers within a canon by distinguishing them from minor or second-rate think-
ers. They also acknowledge the significance of genuine philosophical dialogues
between thinkers. For instance, whatever else he might also have been doing,
Rousseau was indeed reacting to Hobbes. Triadic narratives (such as Wight’s
and Boucher’s) are not the only ordering traditions. Although using it to order
contemporary theorising and not the broad sweep of history, Brown proposes
a similar dialectical confrontation between cosmopolitan and communitarian
thinking (Brown 2002). And one could make a similar case between the famil-
iar confrontation between realism and idealism that preoccupied international
relations theory in the early years of that discipline. One interpretation of the
canon in this book is that it outlines a ‘realist’ tradition that could be contrasted
with others in just such a historical dialectic.
It is very easy to subvert the classical traditions of liberal or state-based pro-
gressivism by portraying them sublimated justifications of colonialism or cul-
tural imperialism, which privilege the perspectives of western or white-occi-
dental thinkers. A history of international theory (even a partial one covering
a sub-tradition such as realism) that only includes white male thinkers raises a
serious and genuine question about its claims to universality as the site of truth
or reason. If the western canon is not the sole repository of reason and truth,
then why does it not include non-western thinkers in its account of history? A
simple, but hasty response, might be to qualify the history by geography and
argue that there can only be partial histories – there can be no complete global
history of international political thought. Even that position leaves open a
question of inclusion. Any account that claims to provide a complete overview
is always subject to the criticism that it includes some over others; it reinforces
claims about importance, marginality and absence because of who is included
and who is not. Some grounds for selective inclusion are benign because text-
book canons are often constrained by the availability of accessible texts that
students can use in the classroom. It is unrealistic to assume that any cohort
of students can acquire the books (mostly in translation) that would allow a
genuinely inclusive global curriculum of international and political thought. In
other cases, selection is less benign because it assumes that there is an underly-
ing rationale for creating a distinct canon of texts, not to merely illustrate the
Introduction 17

variety of thought but to converge on the right way of living and ordering poli-
tics and international affairs. In this version, common in political philosophy,
the individual chapters are stages on the way to the truth or a right answer.
Selection poses a serious challenge to any author of a book like this one
because merely denying that this is my self-conscious goal is never going to
be enough. It will always be possible that the criteria of inclusion and the
overall narrative contain implicit ‘exclusions’ or meta-narratives. Indeed, the
much-maligned approach of ‘deconstructionism’ is concerned with precisely
this issue: uncovering the ways in which conceptual languages always embody
exclusions of various kinds. An obvious criticism, for instance, is that all the
thinkers considered here are men.

Where are the women?

Is the omission of any women in my set of authors just an oversight or preju-


dice on my part? Have I left them out of this canon because of prejudices about
the significance and sophistication of women thinkers? Am I working with a
testosterone-fuelled view of international politics and affairs as overly conflict-
ual, an approach that is primarily masculine – so where the high theory or
important philosophising is done by men? I certainly hope that is not the case
but this book remains an exclusively male canon of thinkers: that needs an
explanation and justification.
The composition of the canon is not the only legitimate place to ask the ques-
tion ‘where are the women?’ If we look at the arguments and texts of almost
all those authors discussed here, the very place of women in the world they
describe is at best problematic and at worst invisible. Thucydides’ History of
the Peloponnesian War contains no women amongst its cast of actors. There are
no women generals, orators, demagogues or regular soldiers, and when they
appear at all it is either to be slaughtered or sold into slavery as a class. Other
historical or philosophically inclined thinkers (such as Machiavelli or Hobbes)
fare no better. Women do not feature in any important way in the events, insti-
tutions, moral practices or conceptions of politics that are addressed by these
exclusively male theorists. Alternatively, they do feature yet are subsumed
under heavily gender-loaded categories such as ‘man’, which is supposed to just
mean human but clearly does not. So, what is going on, and more importantly
how can one explain and justify presenting a canon of enquiry that not only
excludes women but seems also to deny the experience of approximately half
or the human species?
To begin, I need to turn to feminist theory. Feminist theory is a relatively
recent perspective, although there have been genuinely feminist political (if
not international) theorists, such as Mary Wollstonecraft, since the 18th cen-
tury. And of course there are many unjustly neglected women writers in earlier
ages on some of the issues covered in this book (Owens and Rietzler 2021).
18 Conflict, War and Revolution

Amongst those early feminist theorists, often known now as first-wave theo-
rists, the emphasis was on extending rights and privileges enjoyed by men to
women, who had been traditionally excluded from such rights. Wollstonecraft,
for example, argues that the rights of man popularised by Thomas Paine or
the French Declaration should be extended to women. Later movements argu-
ing for the extension of the franchise are similarly concerned with equalising
a common set of rights, liberties and privileges rather than explaining under-
lying structures of power that shape and dominate gendered identities. They
are about opening access to opportunities, not addressing the shaping of those
opportunities. First-wave theory was a corrective to the unequal application
of traditional political theories of freedom and equality. It was not until the
development of second-wave feminism and feminist theory from the 1950s
to the 1970s that feminism began to mount a full critical assault on the con-
cepts, theories and vocabularies that are used to understand social, political
and international relations.
The legacy of first-wave feminism has done much to unlock the academy to
women by equalising access to the resources of advanced education and aca-
demic positions even if first-wave theorists have been most focused in domestic
politics. The significance of these changes should not be underestimated but
they do not address the whole problem. This can be seen in relation to the
canon of thinkers. I need to show that I have not discriminated against women
by focusing on male thinkers when equally qualified women authors are avail-
able. Is there a canon of equally qualified women who could be included that
I have merely chosen to overlook? This question is relatively easy to address
in the negative – although it remains for the reader or subsequent student to
decide whether they are ultimately persuaded by my choice (Zerelli 2008).
Whilst there are exceptional female authors who wrote on politics, law and
international affairs, these women are truly exceptional given the social, politi-
cal and physical exclusion of women from education, politics and public life
for much of western history (and indeed the history of most other recorded
literary civilisations: patriarchy is not simply a problem for the west). Conse-
quently, with honorary exceptions such as philosophers like Christine di Pisan
and Mary Wollstonecraft, or travel writers and diarists such as Mary Wortley
Montagu, there is no existing canon of major international theorists that I have
ignored or discriminated against at least until the 20th century. Indeed, the fact
of male power excluding women (or patriarchy, as it is known) fully explains
the absence of significant women authors in this canon until the 20th century.
This is not to ignore the fact that some exceptional women – Cleopatra, Eliza-
beth I, Catherine the Great – did exercise political and military power.
The substance of the book is not an example of overt discrimination and
exclusion of equally qualified voices, but is that a sufficient justification for this
enquiry? Although I am not making this claim, a not uncharitable inference
from what I have said would be that it will take millennia to find gender-balanced
Introduction 19

canons of historical political and international thought. Until then, male


authors can just carry on with our gendered canon until female political and
international theorists can catch up on the lost ground! Underlying this point
is the assumption that the human experience, institutions and events captured
in the theories and concepts examined in this canon are somehow universal. If
so, the problem is merely one of who is writing about it, which can be addressed
by randomly distributing gendered pronouns – as if the ideas were being devel-
oped and discussed by women, when that was clearly not the case. But, if we
return to the example of Thucydides and the place of women in his History,
primarily as victims of violence, we can see a greater issue of concern than
simply exclusion from contributing to a philosophical canon. This is what is
captured by second-wave feminists and feminist theorists and their turn to the
discussion of patriarchy as a social construction of power.
From the 1960s and 1970s, the second wave of feminism has led to a sophis-
ticated body of theory that addresses the underlying power structures that
constitute gendered identities and their social and political consequences. As
a result, the concepts that we use to think about the social and political world
are shaped by the power relations between men and women. Complex power
relations are exercised through language, discourse and theory, as well as being
constituted by discourse. Thus, conceptual language about human nature and
human rights can appear emancipatory, whilst at the same time presupposing
conceptions of humanity that are essentially masculine and which therefore
disadvantage and exclude women and contribute to their oppression. One way
to characterise the relationship between first-wave and second-wave feminist
theorists would be to see the latter as reacting against the former’s view of eman-
cipation as making women more like men and assisting women to compete in
a competition that privileges masculinity. The criticism of first-wave feminists
is that they see the problem as equalising opportunities rather than challeng-
ing the hidden power structures that create those gendered-opportunities in
the first place. Feminist care theorists often criticise natural and human rights
individualism as masculinist because it privileges autonomy and independence
over moral considerations of relationality, care and empathy. Care theory can
seem to reduce these perspectives to inherently feminine attributes that fol-
low from women’s biological role in nurturing and childrearing, in contrast to
masculine identities of protector and provider. But care theory does not have to
be biologically reductive. Even if some moral responses are socialised through
gendered roles in caring, it might nevertheless be the case that these can be
liberated from socially constructed women’s experience, and used to challenge
and reshape social and political relations that are unduly distorted by mascu-
line moral categories that reflect the predominance of male power. Such a per-
spective is a valuable source of criticism of the paradigms of political agency
discussed in this book. Yet, taking that further to excluding such theorists is
not a denial of their importance but merely of their relevance given that the
20 Conflict, War and Revolution

point of the book is not to provide a full critical survey of all the ways of under-
standing political agency. As I have said earlier in this introduction, the canon
here deliberately excludes perspectives that make the concept of ‘the political’
derivative of moral notions such as care or justice.
Second-wave theory has turned feminist analysis into a critical and norma-
tive theory, which sees social and political relationships as social construc-
tions that need to be analysed and transformed rather than as immutable facts.
Power structures and discourses are malleable and can be transformed. Femi-
nist gender analysis is a tool for that transformative politics which now ranges
beyond the distribution of opportunities, rights, liberties and privileges and
instead focuses on the power relations of domination and subordination that
work through our conceptual and philosophical languages.
One of the implications of the success of second-wave feminist theory is the
development of identity politics, which acknowledges the diversity of human
identity and the power structures that are reflected in the plural nature of per-
sonal identity. People are not just men or women; they also have racial, national,
sexual, gender, age and class identities in combination that link them to social
groups who may be the beneficiaries of power relations in some respects, whilst
being victims of overt and covert oppression in other respects: think of young,
black, middle-class, university-educated women and white, working-class,
non-graduate older men. Power relations include and exclude, oppress and
dominate groups in different ways, but none are totally free from the play of
dominant power structures in society. For some identity theorists, this fact has
downplayed the importance of feminism as an emancipatory project, because it
is focused on one amongst many sites of oppression and domination. Yet there
is something profoundly important and historically resilient about gendered
oppression that many feminists capture through the idea of intersectionality,
which emphasises the ways in which various sources of social and personal
identity are irreducibly interlinked for the most marginalised groups and voices
in society.
In light of this second-wave and identity-based critique, histories of thought
cannot simply be a long list of male authors. Such histories are also gendered in
the sense that the conceptual languages and discourse covered by these things
will inevitably reflect gendered social relations and patriarchal dominance.
At its most obvious, this will be seen in the absence of women as agents in
Thucydides, or in the overt sexism of Machiavelli. But it is also present in the
predominantly masculinist discourse of human nature, natural law and rights
in Hobbes or Rousseau. Even radical thinkers such as Lenin and Mao reduce
women’s oppression to a mere epiphenomenon of the more real class relations
that shape late capitalism. So described, might it seem that books such as this
one are guilty as charged?
In response, I acknowledge the importance of the second-wave feminist cri-
tique but do not think it vitiates the conception of the book. That the narrative
of this book is open to feminist critique does not vitiate its point, because I am
Introduction 21

not offering a defence of the substance of each argument from all or any criti-
cism. Work is being done on exploring a feminist canon in international rela-
tions and political theory, especially in the 20th century (Owens and Rietzler
2021). The task here is to show that there is no deliberate exclusion and also
to recognise that the main questions are not in the choice of canonical texts
but rather in how they are read. After all, there is no set of thinkers from the
past who are free from gendered power relations, and there is no prospect for
future theory that is also not in some way implicated in the social construction
of discourse. Feminist theory, or any other criticism of this kind, is a second-
order activity that operates upon pre-critical interpretations. A book of this
kind that is designed to set out a number of distinct perspectives is therefore
logically prior to this second-order activity. Reducing one to the other would
not only result in a different book but would still leave open that prior activity
of interpretation as ostension (the act of showing or presenting), after which
criticism follows.
I do not offer a feminist study of international political thought, or speculate
whether the approaches discussed in this book must collapse under feminist
scrutiny. However, I acknowledge that the real challenge for this book will be
how far it lends itself to critical engagement with the discourses of power that
are immanent within the thought and thinkers discussed, and acknowledges
the ways the theories and concepts discussed can reinforce or explain those
relationships of power and domination.

Overview of the argument

The book comprises nine substantive chapters and a concluding essay. Each
chapter is presented as a distinct paradigm of politics in the international
realm, rather than a stage in the unfolding of a single narrative explaining or
legitimising the current world order. Whilst these paradigms may rise and
fall, the overall argument of the book is that they remain effective sources and
structures for thinking about international politics and agency. None of them
can be simply confined to the past as of no more than historical or antiquarian
interest. I have followed a rough chronological order but this is not supposed to
illustrate an unfolding historical development.
The book begins with the most famous ancient Greek writer on the modern
field of international affairs. Thucydides’ History of the Peloponnesian War is
one of the few foundational texts in international political thought. The chap-
ter introduces Thucydides’ work and his influence on theory and history and
considers his role as a theorist of realism. I examine the nature of and basis
of realism as the default perspective of international politics. Thucydides also
provides an account of the collapse of Athenian democracy under the pressure
of war, so the chapter explores the themes of democracy, strategy and leader-
ship in wartime. Thucydides gives an account of a system of Greek political
22 Conflict, War and Revolution

communities (poleis) operating in the absence of an overarching hegemonic


power. This is a model of international order that continues to dominate inter-
national affairs and diplomacy. It is an account of the dynamics of international
politics that is still thought to have lessons for present-day international politics
and a changing world order.
The second chapter turns to the late Roman period and the rise of Christian-
ity in the work of Augustine of Hippo. Augustine is considered to be one of
the most important thinkers of the Christian era. He is an important source
of ideas about the nature of politics, war and peace and a critic of theories
of historical progress. Augustine’s political thinking is located in an overview
of his theology and the impact of his understanding of the Christian story of
redemption on thinking about the nature, scope and claims of political and
moral authority. The central question is whether the fundamental teachings
of Christianity tend towards a utopian and pacificist view of political relation-
ships, or is the legacy of Christianity in politics and international affairs more
properly understood as a form of realism? Augustine’s thought is central in the
development of ’just war’ theory and had a big impact on the development of
20th-century Christian realism and the marked anti-utopianism of post-Cold
War liberalism.
Machiavelli is tackled in Chapter 4. He is one of the most controversial of
political thinkers because his ideas ran counter to many traditional concep-
tions of politics, such as the primary role of the common good and the need for
political power to be constrained by moral or ethical obligations. In the context
of international political thought, Machiavelli is presented as a realist and an
originator of the idea of raison d’état (reason of state). I advance the stronger
claim that Machiavelli challenges the idea of any stable political societies or
peoples. Instead, he focuses attention on the founding or refounding of politi-
cal communities in a world of constant change and revolution. Machiavelli is
also concerned with the character of leadership and the ways in which tempo-
rary and fleeting political power should be exercised to create and maintain
regimes. Rather than steering a careful path around the idea of ethics in poli-
tics, he explores the nature of political life outside of a moralistic, ethical and
legalistic framework. In this way, he poses one of the most striking challenges
to the conceptual framework of modern politics.
Thomas Hobbes is covered in Chapter 5. He is one of the first great theorists
of the concept of sovereignty and of the modern state, and the original theorists
of the state system that lies at the heart of contemporary international relations.
His theory of the sovereign state is set out in Leviathan and the chapter explores
Hobbes’s place in modern international relations theory alongside his intellec-
tual context and wider materialist philosophy of humanity. He offers an account
of human nature and the state of nature, as well as a contractarian account
of the origin of sovereign power. The nature and extent of Hobbes’s account
of absolutism is another focus, and his rejection of international political
Introduction 23

society derived from early modern papalism. He sees international relations


as solely between sovereign states, explaining the way in which contemporary
international relations theory has absorbed him into the tradition or realism
and interstate anarchy.
The second of the great social contract theorists is John Locke. In contrast to
Hobbes, Locke is considered an early liberal because he argued for a constitu-
tionally limited conception of sovereignty that protects individuals’ rights to
life, liberty and property. The sixth chapter begins with an overview of Locke’s
social contract theory and his account of the constitutional sovereign state. On
the state of nature, the law and right of nature, and the theory of consent, Locke
differs importantly from Hobbes. He also formulated a right of revolution and
a theory of property that is linked to trade and colonial acquisition. Locke’s
connection to colonialism and its impact on his theory has been highlighted
by what is known as the ‘colonial turn’ in modern political theory. I also dis-
cuss Locke’s state theory and his views on the normative status of non-consti-
tutionally limited powers and the extent to which they should be recognised by
legitimate states, Although he is often thought of as a source for liberal idealism
because of his moralistic natural law theory, his relationship to the realism/ide-
alism distinction is more subtle, and he defended a militant or crusading liberal
order in the international realm.
The seventh chapter gives an overview of Rousseau’s writings and his influ-
ence on international thought and theory. Once again, the central concept is
sovereignty and its political and international implications. However, Rous-
seau’s main arguments concern the idea of popular sovereignty, and how the
concept of sovereign power can be maintained and exercised collectively by a
free sovereign people who remain free citizens. In this respect, it is a criticism
and a development of the concept as deployed by Hobbes or by Locke. Rous-
seau is critical of the concept of state sovereignty as a distinct juridical or law-
like entity. Instead, sovereignty for him can only be a power of a people acting
in accordance with a general will. In order to be a sovereign people, the citizens
need to think of themselves as more than a multitude or collection of individu-
als trying to secure and protect their private interests. To maintain that idea of
a sovereign general will, the people need a strong conception of identity and to
avoid the corrupting power of commercial society and cosmopolitan engage-
ment. Rousseau’s arguments are a precursor of an inward-looking nationalism
and anti-cosmopolitanism that has seen a recent recurrence in anti-globalisa-
tion movements, political and economic nationalism, national solidarity and
the rise of identity politics.
Clausewitz is an unfamiliar figure in histories of political thought and, when
he is discussed, it is mostly as a footnote to discussions of the state or as a mar-
ginal figure of interest only to a small professional readership concerned with
strategy and military affairs. The eighth chapter focuses on Clausewitz’s great
work On War, a book as much a work of political theory as any of the other
24 Conflict, War and Revolution

texts I discuss. I begin by situating Clausewitz in the climate of state and mili-
tary theory that grew up in Prussia in response to the French Revolution, the
idea of the rights of man and the citizen, and the consequent wars for national
liberation. I explore the methodology of his military theory as a development of
a new policy science, and discuss his account of the concept of war and the place
of genius and friction, which aligns with a Romantic critique of crude Enlight-
enment rationalism. The concept of the ‘paradoxical trinity’ (which covers the
interplay between the people, the army and the government) is examined next,
especially the question of whether there are actually one or two ‘trinities’ at play
in Clausewitz’s work. The concept of the ‘trinity’ illustrates Clausewitz’s analysis
of the deep interplay of hatred, chance, and reason or policy as the dynamic
forces that explain war and drive international relations. The chapter moves on
to consider the priority of offence and defence in the conduct of operations and
concludes with an extended discussion of Clausewitz’s influence in a modern
age characterised by violence and war.
Whilst Marx has undoubtedly had a significant impact on the development
of social and political theory, it is through his followers, especially Lenin and
Mao, that his doctrines have had the greatest impact on international thought
and affairs. Marx theorised (or, for some, predicted) the revolutionary over-
throw of capitalism, but it was actually Lenin in 1917 and Mao in 1949 who
presided over the two great socialist revolutions of the 20th century. The ninth
chapter explores their writings on the theory and practice of revolutionary
politics that have had the most impact on international political thinking. A
brief introduction to the Marxist framework precedes a discussion of Lenin’s
theory of the vanguard party as the vehicle for establishing a dictatorship of
the proletariat, an idea he took seriously and placed at the centre of revolution-
ary struggle. Marx’s theory of imperialism as the latest phase of capitalism and
the role of violence in the revolutionary overcoming of the state is examined
next. Mao’s thought, in turn, transformed the legacy of Leninism in the specific
contexts of the Chinese struggle against imperialism by theorising the peasant
masses as a revolutionary class, which transformed his account of revolution.
I also explore Mao’s writings on revolutionary war and the role of guerrilla
forces. The chapter concludes by assessing how both Lenin’s and Mao’s think-
ing about the practice of revolutionary politics has impacted on contemporary
political and international theory.
Carl Schmitt rejects the optimism of the contemporary liberal internation-
alist view of the global order that has been dominant since the end of World
War II. Reviewed in Chapter 10, Schmitt is an uncompromising conservative
thinker who has influenced theorists of the left and right. He saw the interna-
tional system of states as a bulwark against the violence and conflict that he
saw as underlying the universalist and globalist tendencies of liberal and revo-
lutionary politics. His ideas are a response to the decline of European power,
the rise of Cold War ideological opposition, and the emergence of new global
hegemons such as the United States. Schmitt both provided a critique of liberal
Introduction 25

optimism and globalisation and at the same time attempted to salvage essential
concepts such as sovereignty, war and enmity as a way of disciplining politics
and responding to the decline of state power. I cover Schmitt’s criticism of lib-
eral democracy, and the concept of ‘the political’ as an examination of what
sovereignty is and where it now resides following the abandonment of liberal
popular sovereignty theories and nationalism. Finally, I consider his critique of
global liberalism and international law.
Each chapter is free-standing and can be read and understood on its own.
However, the juxtaposition of these paradigmatic approaches to the nature,
scope and organisation of international politics and agency also shows the
importance of three linking issues that frame the overall narrative. These are
violence and politics, temporality and change, and the meaning and signifi-
cance of history. These issues recur across the distinct treatments of individual
authors, and are also illustrated in the methodologies deployed in shaping the
discussion of these issues, whether these are historical, philosophical or polit-
ical-theological. The final chapter examines the re-emergence of realism as an
approach to political theory and how this ‘realist turn’ illuminates or compli-
cates international political theory, which has been suspicious of the hegemony
of realism in the wider discipline of international relations.

Using this book

Each of the chapters on a paradigmatic thinker gives a free-standing introduc-


tion to their perspective on the international realm, and so I have deliberately
avoided narrative themes that span multiple chapters. I hope that readers will
want to read all chapters but also that it will be useful to students studying just
some of the authors covered here, and to general readers interested in particu-
lar authors. Each chapter outlines the context that the thinker operated in, the
structure of their argument, and its implications for their views of politics – as
an activity prior to the challenge of critical analysis and engagement. Covering
an author does not entail endorsement of any of their arguments, but rather
highlights the need to understand their structure before they can be critically
analysed or (more importantly) organised into a distinctive interpretative nar-
rative such as political realism.
Each chapter also outlines an historical introduction to the relevant texts
being addressed, looking at critical themes and debates that provide the inter-
pretation of the argument. A thinker like Hobbes wrote a number of works, but
I am concentrating on the argument in Leviathan (1651) and its implications.
In the case of Rousseau or Schmitt, I link a number of works to identify their
main arguments, but even here I am not providing a complete overview of all
of the thinkers’ works. Augustine, Machiavelli, Rousseau and Schmitt each have
a large corpus (or body of work), not all of which is relevant for understanding
the position set out here. My treatment does not presuppose that readers are
26 Conflict, War and Revolution

already familiar with the thinker, nor do I require students to master all the
intricacies of an individual’s thought. Some scholars in political thought spend
their entire careers working on a single author or a small part of one author’s
output. This book cannot cover everything. It will have achieved its purpose if
it inspires readers to go back to the main texts or to become familiar with the
continuing scholarly debates.
It is not necessary to read chapters in their chronological order. Indeed, I
am explicitly not claiming that there is an unfolding historical narrative that
informs an argument about the triumph of a particular way of organising pol-
itics or international affairs. In principle, the book’s narrative could be read
backwards, with later thinkers providing insights and questions that can be
used to frame the interpretations of their predecessors. Whilst reading the past
in light of the present is a familiar basis for philosophical critique, there is also
paradoxically some scope for this at the interpretive level.
All of the interpretations and arguments set out here are built on a vast
scholarship that exists in the case of each thinker and text. It would be easy
and unhelpful to overload readers with summaries and lists of the scholar-
ship on each thinker. Each sentence could be accompanied by extensive bib-
liographic referencing because the act of scholarly writing always involves a
complex synthesis of what has been read or argued elsewhere. Some of the
readings I offer will be familiar and potentially controversial because they
involve my taking sides in interpretive and scholarly debates and reflect my
own studies over a number of decades. I hope that readers will challenge and
debate those readings in time. For that reason, each chapter has a minimum
of internal references. Where they occur, these references are to key posi-
tions in debates and not simply sources of a specific idea that underpins my
interpretation of paraphrase. I have tried, but not always succeeded, in reduc-
ing the references to the work of my peers as I try to focus attention on the
main text.
The bibliographies at the end of each chapter identify some of the more
important scholarly works I have drawn on, or which best address the issues
covered in the chapter. They are not intended to be comprehensive – indeed,
that would not be possible – but to help readers with university or public library
access to follow up and question my exposition. For the main texts, I have cho-
sen easily available scholarly editions that are also authoritative. I have quoted
relatively extensively, subject to the normal constraints of scholarly fair use. The
quotations are sufficient to guide the reader in making sense of the key argu-
ments. That said, none of the arguments or claims made for any of the thinkers
discussed depends upon a particular translation or edition and that is why I
have not linked digitally to those text versions. Any available online version
will be adequate to the task of building a first understanding and familiarity
with the main thinkers. There are no references that are time-dependent and no
data sets or empirical materials that need a direct link or which could become
unavailable.
Introduction 27

The end of chapter references also includes a brief bibliography of key sec-
ondary literature about each main thinker,
Finally, the LSE Press guide at the end of the book has some advice on finding
open access versions of the main texts for readers without such backup.

Bibliography

Armitage, David. (2012). Foundations of Modern International Thought. UK:


Cambridge University Press.
Barry, Brian. (1965). Political Argument. UK: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Booth, Wayne C. (1979). Critical Understanding: The Powers and Limits of Plu-
ralism. USA: University of Chicago Press.
Booth, Wayne C. (1988). The Company We Keep: An Ethics of Fiction. USA:
University of California Press.
Boucher, David. (1985). Texts in Context. Netherlands: Martinus Nijhoff.
Boucher, David. (1998). Political Theories of International Relations. UK: Oxford
University Press.
Brown, Chris. (2002). Sovereignty, Rights and Justice: International Political
Theory Today. UK: Polity Press.
Brown, Chris. (2015). International Society, Global Polity. UK: Sage.
Brown, Chris; and Ainley, Kirstin. (2005). Understanding International Rela-
tions, 3rd edn. UK: Palgrave.
Brown, Chris; and Eckersley, Robyn. (eds) (2018). The Oxford Handbook of
International Political Theory. UK: Oxford University Press.
Bull, Hedley. (2002). The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics,
3rd edn. UK: Palgrave.
Collingwood, Robin G. (1939). An Autobiography. UK: Clarendon Press.
Doyle, Michael W. (1997). Ways of War and Peace. USA: Norton.
Forrester, Katerina. (2019). In the Shadow of Justice: Postwar Liberalism and the
Remaking of Political Philosophy. USA: Princeton University Press.
Freeden, Michael. (1996). Ideologies and Political Theory a Conceptual Approach.
UK: Oxford University Press.
Fukuyama, Francis. (1989). ‘The End of History?’ The National Interest, vol. 16,
pp. 3–18.
Fukuyama, Francis. (1992). The End of History and the Last Man. USA: Free
Press.
Gaddis, John Lewis. (2018). On Grand Strategy. UK: Allen Lane.
Habermas, Jürgen. (1998). The Postnational Constellation. UK: Polity Press.
Habermas, Jürgen. (2005). Old Europe, New Europe, Core Europe, ed. Daniel
Levy, Max Pensky and John C. Torpey. UK: Verso.
Kelly, Paul. (1998). ‘Contextual and Non-Contextual Histories of Political
Thought’, in J. Hayward, B. Barry, and A. Brown (eds) The British Study of
Politics in the Twentieth Century. UK: British Academy, pp. 37–62.
28 Conflict, War and Revolution

Kelly, Paul. (2005). Liberalism. UK: Polity.


Kuhn, Thomas S. (1962). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. USA: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press.
Lasswell, Harold. (1936). Politics: Who Gets What, When and How. UK:
McGraw Hill.
Lyotard, Jean-Francois. (1984). The Post-Modern Condition: A Report on
Knowledge. USA: University of Minnesota Press.
Macpherson, Crawford B. (1962). The Political Theory of Possessive Individual-
ism. UK: Oxford University Press.
Moller-Okin, Susan. (2013). Women in Western Political Thought. USA:
Princeton University Press.
Nye, Joseph. (2015). Is the American Century Over? UK: Polity.
Oakeshott, Michael. (1983). On History and Other Essays. UK: Blackwell.
Owens, Patricia; and Rietzler, Katharina (2021). Women’s International Thought:
A new History. UK: Cambridge University Press.
Plamenatz, John P. (1963). Man and Society, 2 vols. UK: Longmans.
Popper, Karl. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. UK: Routledge.
Said, Edward. (1979). Orientalism. UK: Penguin.
Skinner, Quentin. (1969). ‘Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas’
History and Theory, vol. 8, pp. 3–53.
Skinner, Quentin. (1978). The Foundations of Modern Political Theory, 2 vols.
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Strauss, Leo; and Cropsey, Joseph. (1987). History of Political Philosophy. USA:
University of Chicago Press.
Voegelin, Eric. (1952). The New Science of Politics: An Introduction. USA:
University of Chicago Press.
Waltz, Kenneth N. [1979] (2010). Theory of International Politics. USA:
Waveland Press.
Wight, Martin. (1994). International Theory: The Three Traditions, ed. Gabriele
Wight and Brian Ernest Porter. UK: Leicester University Press.
Zerelli, Linda. (2008). ‘Feminist Theory and the Canon of Political Thought’, in
John S. Dryzek, Bonnie Honig and Anne Phillips (eds) The Oxford Hand-
book of Political Theory. UK: Oxford University Press, pp. 106–124.

You might also like