What Are Emotions Really
What Are Emotions Really
James R. Averill
To cite this article: James R. Averill (1998) What Are Emotions, Really?, Cognition & Emotion,
12:6, 849-855, DOI: 10.1080/026999398379466
To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/026999398379466
James R. Averill
University of M assachusetts, Amherst, USA
Requests for reprints should be sent to Professo r James R. Averill, Department of Psychol-
ogy, Tobin H all, University of M assachu setts at Amherst, Box 37710, Am herst , MA 010 03±
77 10, USA .
7). This leads to an exam ination of the role of em otion in institutional life,
with an em phasis on the workplace (Chapter 8). W ith the interpersonal
nature of em otion thus explicated, Parkinson refocuses on the issue of how
emotional representations (ideas) ® t w ith the rest of em otional reality
(C hapter 9). Finally, he explores the implications for both theory and
research of treating the em otions as dyn am ic interpersonal episodes rather
than as momentary personal reactions (C hapter 10 ).
Em otion theorists have often been likened to the six blind m en of
Indostan, each of whom felt part of an elephant an d m istook that part
for the wh ole. Parkinson is no blind m an Ð he exam ines emotions from a
variety of perspectives, both philosophical and empirical, and his an alysis
is revealing. Parkinson acknowledges that his book is ``a partisan one’’ .
Increasingly, however, I believe that disagreem ents am ong theorists are
becom ing less partisan and more a matter of em phasis than of substance.
Be that as it may, wh at does the em otional elephan t look like, according to
Parkinson? The following propositions (each accompanied by a represen-
tative quotation from Parkinson’s book) trace its outline:
Instead of looking inside the psyche for emotional processes, it seems worth
attempting to construct at least a preliminary account solely by reference to
what is going on in the public social world, and what we understand about
this world as competent users of conversational tactics. (p. 289)
In this brief review, I will focus prim arily on those aspects of Parkinson’s
analysis that center around the conception of em otion as a form of
communication.
EMOTION AS COMMUNICATION
Every good thesis deserves an anti-thesis. The antithesis of ``em otion-as-
communication’’ is ``em otion-as-expression’’ . A ccording to the latter, em o-
tional behaviour is the outward m an ifestation of some inner stateÐ the
emotion proper. O ne problem with this particular antithesis is that no one
holds it, at least not in pure form . Ekman is often cited as a proponent, but
he, too, claim s that emotions are a mean s of com munication, a view which
he attributes even to D arwin (e.g. Ekm an , 1997 ). If emotion-as-expression
theorists also m aintain that emotions are (at least in part) a form of
communication, with what can we contrast Parkinson’s em otion-as-com -
munication point of view ? An answer must be found within the dom ain of
communication itself.
B ees comm unicate by dan ce the location of ¯ owers; birds com municate
by song a readiness to m ate; and dogs com municate by bared teeth an
aggressive intent. H um ans can com municate in sim ilar way s, for exam ple,
by bodily movem ents, tone of voice, an d facial expression. But humans can
also com municate by langu age. Is emotional comm unication more like that
of infrahum an anim als or is it m ore like hum an language? H ere, a clear
divergence of opinion em erges. Em otion-as-expression theorists, when they
speak of com munication, typically have the an im al model in m ind. By
contrast, when Parkinson speaks of em otions as com munications, he has
852 AVERILL
som ething closer to hum an langu age in m ind. For example, he states that
his general view with respect to nonverbal behaviour ``is analogous to
Vygotsky’s (1986, p. 118) about verbal expression of thoughts’’ . Parkinson
then qutoes Vygotsky to the effect that ``Experience teaches us that thought
does not express itself in words, but rather realises itself in them ’’ . A nalo-
go usly, em otions are not sim ply expressed, but are realised in both verbal
an d nonverbal ways.
How, then, do we account for the fact that em otions are often experi-
enced in the privacy of our ow n m inds, only to be expressed, if at all, in
disguised or truncated form ? Here, too, the analogy with langu age is
informative. O n any given day, we talk to ourseves more than we talk to
other people, an d m any of the things we say to ourselves we would never
say in public. H owever, before we can talk to ourselves, we must learn to
talk to others; private discourse is derivative of, and ultim ately dependent
on, public discourse. A nd so it is with the em otions, according to Parkin-
son. Exp eriencing an em otion in the privacy of our own m inds is a lean ed
skill, like talking or reading to oneself.
Another an alogy between emotion an d language is that an em otional
episode develops over tim e, as does a conversation. M oreover, what is said
or done during an em otional episode varies as a function of the intended
m essage, the au dience, an d the setting. T his theme, to wh ich Parkinson
returns repeatedly throughout the book, has important im plications for
research. Am ong other things, any investigation that neglects the target or
intended au dience of the emotion is necessarily partial an d potentially
m isleading.
W hen we look closely at the development of an emotional episode over
tim e, another im plication for research emerges. The analysis of em otional
episodes presents a form idable task. Parkinson cites Birdwhistle’s (1970 )
claim that it takes one hour to analyse fully one second of interactive
behaviour between two infants, an d Peery’s (1978) assertion that the true
nature of m any emotional episodes is only evident after a by frame-by-
fram e an alysis of a videotape. Few investigators have the tim e, energy, or
patience for such efforts. But perhaps the task m ay not be as form idable as
these exam ples suggest. W hat is needed is not so much an ``affective
m icroscope’’ (Peery’s term ) focused on m odes of expression, but an ``affec-
tive rhetoric’’ of the type exempli® ed by Aristotle (1941). (Im agine what
wo uld happen if, when an alysing a speech it wa s though t necessary to
scrutinise, second by second, every change in intonation, every phonem e,
every choice of word. D epartments of Com munication and Rhetoric would
soon be devoid of students an d faculty.)
In any case, rather than automatic and highly sterotyped behaviour,
emotional responses during an episode are ¯ exible and often creative.
W hat remains consistent, if anything, is the message, not the m edium .
WHAT ARE EMOTIONS REALLY? 853
Once again, the an alogy with language helps clarify the issue. The sam e
m essage can be conveyed in very different wo rds, som etim es with triteness
and banality, but som etim es w ith grace and style. And so it is with the
emotions.
O f course, the analogy between emotions and language is just thatÐ an
analogy. A nd like any analogy, this one has its lim itations. The real ques-
tion is not, In wh at ways are em otions like language? but, rather, In what
ways are emotions and langu age interrelated? Too often, Parkinson notes,
psychologists have taken the prim ary function of emotional language to be
descriptive. D escription, however, is only one, and seldom the most impor-
tant function of em otional language. M ore com m only, what a person says
when em otional is a m an ifestation of the em otion itself, not a comm entary
on it.
E motional language m ay be used to cajole, praise, blam e, cast asper-
sions, excuse, seek help, and so forth. In such instances, it is no more
m eaningful to ask, Is the assertion true? than it is to ask of a cry of pain,
Is it true? The sincerity of an avowal, Parkinson observes, is not the sam e as
the accuracy of a report. This does not mean that langu age is simply
another form of em otional expression. T he words we use to express our
emotions also em body our ideas about emotions. Thus, language has a
special power to construct and reconstruct an emotional episode as it
unfolds.
If it is granted that em otions are a form of com munication, what do they
communicate? That depends, of course, on the em otion: Anger conveys a
different m essage than does love or sadness. B ut in general, em otions
convey appraisals; that is, they indicate how a situation is being evalu-
atedÐ and what m ight be done ab out it, if anything. Even m ore generally,
Parkinson argues that em otions are a way of asserting one’s identity or
position within a relationship. ``T hus, it seem s that emotion does not
sim ply re¯ ect an evaluation of the situation but the com municative pur-
poses of an interpersonally de® ned position in a dialogue’’ (p. 276).
T he shift of emphasis from appraisal to the act of com municating m ight
at ® rst seem m inor, but it has important theoretical consequences. A mong
other things, the need to com municate, not cognitive appraisals, is now
seen as central to the cau sation of em otion. To illustrate, love com muni-
cates the desire for a certain kind of relationship; the appraised desirab ility
(idealisation) of the loved one is a m an ifestation, not a cause of the love. To
take an other exam ple, an ger com municates blam e and a desire for retribu-
tion. O f course, an an gry outburst will be m ore effective in achieving
compliance if the blam e is justi® ed (or at least if the an gry person is
convinced that it is justi® edÐ an d can convince the target), but such
justi® cation is not as necessary to the anger as is the need to com municate.
854 AVERILL
FINAL OBSERVATIONS
Parkinson considers his thesis to be ``a relatively radical one’’ , and in many
respects it is. D rawing on conversational and dram aturgical metaphors, he
wishes to change the way we think an d talk ab out emotions. It is a tribute
to Parkinson that by the end of the book his way of talking seem s m ore
reasonable than radical. I have tried to convey som e of that reasonableness,
but as with any good book, the bread th an d depth of Parkinson’s an alysis
de® es brief summ ary.
Parkinson provides a wide ranging and judicious review of the psycho-
logical literature on emotion. I found his an alyses of appraisal, expressive
behaviour, and emotional representations (ideas) particularly insightful. It
should be noted, however, that Parkinson does not try to cover all aspects
of em otion. H e intentionally omits any detailed discussion of biological
factors, on the one hand, an d of cultural in¯ uences, on the other, although
he clearly recognises the im portance of both. Returning to the m etaphor
used in the introduction to this review, Parkinson is not concerned with the
origins of the emotional elephantÐ its biological or social evolutionÐ but
with its appearance in interpersonal relationships.
WHAT ARE EMOTIONS REALLY? 855
N or is Parkinson concerned with the inner wo rkings of the elephant,
whether physiological or cognitive. Indeed, he anticipates that a major
criticism will be his neglect of cogn itive processes. In defence of this
om ission, he notes that current m odels of inform ation processing are not
well suited to the im provisational an d interpersonal nature of emotional
episodes. W hether one agrees with that assertion or not, Parkinson is
content to leave it to others to explore the internal m echan ism s that help
m ediate emotion. Som e division of labour is necessary.
E ven with the earlier cited om issions, Parkinson’s analysis is wide-ran-
ging an d com plex. The exposition is well organised, however, with frequent
preview s and summ aries. H ence, his arguments are seldom dif® cult to
follow. Ideas and realities of emotion wo uld make an excellent textbook
for a course on the social psychology of emotion. But it is much m ore than
a textbook. Even the m ost knowledgeable researcher will be inform ed an d
challenged by what Parkinson has to say.
REFERENCES
Aristot le (1941). Rhetoric . In R. M cKeon (E d.), The basic works of Aristotle. New York:
Rando m House.
Birdwhist le, R.L. (1970). Kinesics and context. Phildelphia, PA: Univers ity of Pennsyl vania
Press.
Ekman , P. (1997). Should we call it expressi on or com municat ion? Innovation: European
Journal of Social Sciences, 10, 333± 344.
Oatley, K. (1992). Best laid schemes: The psychology of emotion. Cam bridge, UK : Cam bridg e
University Press.
Peery, J.C. (1978). M agni® cation of affect usin g fram e-by-fram e ® lm analysis. Environmental
Psychology and Nonverbal Behavior, 3, 58± 61.
Vygotsky, L.S. (1986). Thought and language. Cambridge, M A: M IT Press.