Christiano, Thomas - Philosophy and Democracy-172-202
Christiano, Thomas - Philosophy and Democracy-172-202
William Riker
Arrow's Theorem
Kenneth Arrow published Social Choice and Individual Values in 1951. Although
his theorem initially provoked some controversy among economists, its profound
political significance was not immediately recognized by political scientists.1 In
the late ip6os, however, a wide variety of philosophers, economists, and political
scientists began to appreciate how profoundly unsettling the theorem was and
how deeply it called into question some conventionally accepted notions—not
only about voting, the subject of this work, but also about the ontological validity
161
162 Philosophy and Democracy
of the concept of social welfare, a subject that, fortunately, we can leave to meta-
physicians.
The essence of Arrow's theorem is that no method of amalgamating individ-
ual judgments can simultaneously satisfy some reasonable conditions of fairness
on the method and a condition of logicality on the result. In a sense this theorem
is a generalization of the paradox of voting, for the theorem is the proposition
that something like the paradox is possible in any fair system of amalgamating
values. Thus the theorem is called the General Possibility Theorem.
To make the full meaning of Arrow's theorem clear, I will outline the situ-
ation and the conditions of fairness and of logicality that cannot simultaneously
be satisfied.2 The situation for amalgamation is:
1. x y z 7. x (y z) 10. (x y) z 13. (x y z)
2. y z x 8. y (z x) U.(yz) X
3. z x y 9. z (x y) 12. (z x) y
4. x z y
5. z y x
6. y x z (7-1)
Finally, the condition of logicality is that the social choice is a weak order,
by which is meant that the set, X, is connected and its members can be socially
ordered by the relation, R, which is the transitive social analogue of preference
and indifference combined. (This relation, as in x R y, means that x is chosen
over or at least tied with y.) In contrast to the method of amalgamation or choice,
F, which simply selects an element from X, it is now assumed that F selects
repeatedly from pairs in X to produce, by means of successive selections, a social
order analogous to the individual orders, D;. And it is the failure to produce such
an order that constitutes a violation of the condition of logicality.2
Since an individual weak order or the relation R, is often spoken of as in-
dividual rationality, social transitivity, or R, is sometimes spoken of as collective
rationality—Arrow himself so described it. And failure to produce social transi-
tivity can also be regarded as a kind of social irrationality.
Arrow's theorem, then, is that every possible method of amalgamation or
choice that satisfies the fairness conditions fails to ensure a social ordering. And
if society cannot, with fair methods, be certain to order its outcome, then it is
not clear that we can know what the outcomes of a fair method mean. This
conclusion appears to be devastating, for it consigns democratic outcomes—and
hence the democratic method—to the world of arbitrary nonsense, at least some
of the time.
Naturally there has been a variety of attempts to interpret and sidestep this
conclusion. One line of inquiry is to raise doubts about its practical importance;
another is to look for some theoretical adjustment that deprives the theorem of
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 165
its force. The rest of this essay is devoted to a survey of both branches of this
huge and important literature.
I will begin with inquiries about the practical importance of the theorem.
One such inquiry is an estimate of the expected frequency of profiles, D, that do
not lead to a transitive order.
Each such order is a potential D,.. When each of n voters picks some (not nec-
essarily different) D,, a profile, D, is created. Since the first voter picks from ml
orders, the second from ml, . . . , and the last from ml, the number of possible
different profiles, D, is (ml)", which is the number of members of the set, D, of
all profiles, when voters have only strong orders.
A calculation that yields some estimate of the significance of cycles is the
fraction, p(n, m), of D in D without a Condorcet winner:
Number of D without a Condorcet winner
p(n, m) = ——
(ml)"
If one assumes that each D is equally likely to occur (which implies also that, for
each voter, the chance of picking some order is i / ml), then p(n, m) is an a priori
estimate of the probability of the occurrence of a top cycle. Several calculations
have been made, as set forth in display y-i 3 As is apparent from the display, as
the number of voters and alternatives increases, so do the number of profiles
without a Condorcet winner. The calculation thereby implies that instances of
the paradox of voting are very common. Most social choices are made from many
alternatives (though often we do not realize this fact because the number has been
winnowed down by various devices such as primary elections and committees
that select alternatives for agendas) and by many people, so the calculations imply
that Condorcet winners do not exist in almost all decisions.
But, of course, there are a number of reasons to believe that such calculations
DISPLAY 7.1 Values of p(n, m): Proportion of Possible Profiles Without a Condorcet
Winner
n = Number of Voters
m = Number
of Alternatives 3 5 7 9 n Limit
The entry in the row for four alternatives and in the column for seven voters—namely, .150—is the ratio of the
number of profiles without a Condorcet winner to the number of profiles possible when seven voters order four
alternatives.
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 167
1. x y z 4. x z y
2. y z x 5. z y x
3. z x y 6. y x z (7-2)
The entry in the row for four alternatives and in the column for seven
voters—namely, .150—is the ratio of the number of profiles without a Condorcet
winner to the number of profiles possible when seven voters order four alterna-
tives.
Cycles occur when voters concentrate on one or the other of these sets of
three orders. But suppose voters are induced by, for example, political parties, to
concentrate heavily on, say, (i), (2), and (5). Then there is no cycle. Furthermore,
there is good reason to believe that debate and discussion do lead to such fun-
damental similarities of judgment. Calculations based on equiprobable choices
very likely seriously overestimate the frequency of cycles in the natural world.
On the other hand, it is clear that one way to manipulate outcomes is to
generate a cycle. Suppose that in display 7-2 profile D exists and that person 2
realizes that his or her first choice, y, will lose to the Condorcet winner, x. Person
2 can at least prevent that outcome by generating a cycle (or a tie) by voting as
if his or her preference were y z x as in D'.
The tendency toward similarity may thus reduce the number p(n, m), while
the possibility of manipulation may increase the number. It seems to me that
similarity probably reduces the number of profiles without Condorcet winners on
issues that are not very important and that no one has a motive to manipulate,
while the possibility of manipulation increases the number of such profiles on
important issues, where the outcome is worth the time and effort of prospective
losers to generate a top cycle. Neither of these influences appears in the calcu-
lations and thus renders them suspect from two opposite points of view.
D D'
D,: x yz D[: x y z
D2: yx z D'2: yz x
D3: z x y D'^. z x y
vertical axis is measured the degree of preference from lowest at the origin to
highest at the top. On the horizontal axis is placed some ordering of the alter-
natives in X, an ordering appropriately chosen to depict one particular D, as a
single-peaked curve. This is always possible if D, is a strong order (with indiffer-
ence not allowed). The general definition of single-peaked curves (with
indifference permitted at the top) is, as displayed in figure 7.2, reading from left
to right: (i) always downward sloping, (2) always upward sloping, (3) sloping
upward to a particular point and then sloping downward, (4) sloping upward to
a plateau and then sloping downward, (5) horizontal and then downward sloping,
(6) upward sloping and then horizontal. Curves that are not single-peaked are
shown in figure 7.3.
A profile, D, is single-peaked if some ordering of alternatives on the hori-
zontal axis allows every D,, in D to be drawn as a single-peaked curve. As already
observed, for a single D,, it is always possible to find such an ordering. But with
three or more D,, an ordering that renders D;, single-peaked may preclude that
Dk be single-peaked. Indeed, it is exactly when cycles exist that single-peakedness
cannot be attained for D. In Figure 7.4 assume there are three persons who have
chosen different preference orders in the forward cycle (7-2). Then all possible
orderings of X = (x, y, z) on the horizontal axis result in a set of curves that fail
to be single-peaked, as in Figure 7.43-4^ where the axes are all the m\ permu-
tations of {x, y, z}. The same is true of the backward cycle. So to say a profile,
D, is single-peaked is to say it does not admit of cycles. In general, if D is single-
peaked, then:
FIGURE 7.3. Non-single-peaked curves
1. If all D, are strong orders and n is odd, the social ordering is strong.
2. If all D, are weak orders, n is odd, and no D, involves complete
indifference over a triple, the social ordering is a weak order.5
So single-peakedness implies transitivity and hence ensures the existence of a
Condorcet winner.
It is furthermore a remarkable fact that, if D is single-peaked and n is odd,
the Condorcet winner is immediately identifiable as the alternative on the hori-
zontal axis beneath the median peak.6 (If n is even, the winner is some alternative
between the n/2th peak and the (n/2) + ith peak, if such an alternative exists.
And, if none exists, the alternatives at these peaks tie.) In Figure 7.5, with five
peaks, the alternative beneath the median peak (3) is identified as xmed. If xmed is
put against some alternative to its left, say x t , then xmed wins because a majority
consisting of voters 3, 4, and 5 prefer xmed to x, (that is, their curves are upward
sloping from x, to xmed). Similarly, xmed can beat any alternative to its right, say
x4, with a majority consisting of voters i, 2, and 3, whose curves are downward
sloping from xmed to x4, which means they prefer xmed to x4. Hence xmed can beat
anything to its right or left and is a Condorcet winner.
Single-peakedness is important because it has an obvious political interpre-
tation. Assuming a single political dimension, the fact that a profile, D, is single-
peaked means the voters have a common view of the political situation, although
they may differ widely on their judgments. Person i may choose D,. = x y z, and
person j may choose Df — z y x; yet they agree that x is at one end of the scale,
z at the other, and y in the middle, which means they agree entirely on how the
political spectrum is arranged. This kind of agreement is precisely 'what is lacking
in a cycle, where voters disagree not only about the merits of alternatives but
even about where alternatives are on the political dimension.
attack has been focused on logicality. One fairness condition, independence, has,
however, often been regarded as too strong.
The independence condition has at least three consequences:
1. It prohibits utilitarian methods of choice.
2. It prohibits arbitrariness in vote-counting, such as lotteries or methods
that work in different ways at different times.
3. It prohibits, when choosing among alternatives in a set 5, which is
included in X, reference to judgments on alternatives in X — S.
It seems to me that one can defend the independence condition for each of
these consequences. As for consequence I, since interpersonal comparisons of
utility have no clear meaning, the prohibition of utilitarian methods seems quite
defensible, although a weaker form of Condition I might accomplish the same
result. With respect to consequence 2, earlier in this chapter it was shown that
arbitrary counting is just as unfair as violations of Conditions U, P, and D. It is
difficult to imagine that any weaker form of Condition I would accomplish what
I does, because the arbitrariness must be prohibited for any set.
Most attention has been given to consequence 3, because many people be-
lieve that judgments on alternatives in X — 5 are germane to judgments on 5
itself.9 In a presidential preference primary, for example, choice among several
candidates may depend on judgments of still other candidates. For example, in
the 1976 Democratic primaries, in thinking about a decision between Carter and
Udall as if they covered the whole spectrum of party ideology, a mildly left-of-
center voter might prefer Udall. But if the voter thought about Jackson also, so
that Udall appeared as an extremist, that same voter might have preferred Carter
to Udall. So "irrelevant" alternatives (here, Jackson) may really be "relevant."
The question is whether there should be some formal way to allow judgments
on the "irrelevant" alternatives to enter into the choice. And the difficulty in
answering is: How can one decide which nonentered candidates are relevant?
Why not allow consideration of still other, even a hundred, irrelevant alternatives?
But if no irrelevant alternatives are considered, then y might beat x\ but with
such consideration, if there is no Condorcet winner, x might beat y. Thus mean-
ing and coherence depend on variability in the voting situations (on the size, that
is, of X and 5) as much as on voters' judgment.
There seems, unfortunately, no wholly defensible method to decide on de-
grees of irrelevance.10 In the absence of such a method, Condition I seems at least
moderately defensible. Furthermore, while some might argue about the desira-
bility of consequence 3, Condition I seems necessary because consequence 2 is
indispensable for fair decision.
anthropomorphism to ask that the social relation, R, be transitive also.11 Still, there
is some reason to seek transitivity for outcomes.
Without transitivity, there is no order; and without order, there is no coher-
ence. Social outcomes may in fact be meaningless, but one would like to obtain
as much meaning as possible from social decisions. So the obvious question is:
Can one, by modifying the definition of coherence, obtain some lesser coherence
compatible with fairness? Unfortunately, the answer is mainly negative.
The social relation, R, which generates a weak order in Arrow's logicality
condition, combines social preference, P, and social indifference, /. And R is useful
for the purpose Arrow had in mind—namely, social judgments involving com-
parisons and ordering of all feasible social policies, such as distributions of income.
Suppose, however, that one does not require quite so general a result. For pur-
poses of making a social choice, one does not need to impose a complete order
on the whole set X merely to find a best alternative in X. We can think of a best
element in X as one that is chosen over or tied with every other alternative.12
The best alternative is then the choice from X or C(X).13
A requirement, weaker than transitivity, that nevertheless ensures the exis-
tence of one best alternative is quasi-transitivity—that is, the transitivity of P, but
not of R or /. This means that, if x P y and y P z, then x P z; but if the antecedent
does not hold (e.g., if x I y), then the consequent need not hold either. For
example, quasi-transitivity allows (as in note 12) y P z, z I x, and x I y, which
is clearly intransitive in both R and /, although it is enough to establish that the
choice from X = (x, y, z) is C(X) = (x, y).
Another, even weaker requirement for a choice, is acydicity, which is the
requirement that alternatives in X can be arranged so that there is no cycle.14 It
turns out that, by using the logical requirement of acyclicity rather than transi-
tivity, it is possible to find social choice that satisfies all of Arrow's fairness con-
ditions as well as the revised condition of logicality. A. K. Sen offers an example
of such a method: For a set X = (a, b, . . . , ) , let a be chosen for C(X) over b if
everybody prefers a to b and let a and b both be chosen if not everybody prefers
a to b or b to a.15 This rule satisfies Condition U because all individual orders are
allowed. It satisfies Condition P because it is based on the principle of unanimity.
It satisfies Condition I because the choice between any pair depends only on
individual preferences on that pair, and it satisfies Condition D because the only
way a can be better socially than b is for everyone to prefer a to b. Finally, it is
always acyclic. So even if one cannot guarantee an order with fair procedure, it
appears that one can at least guarantee a best choice.
Unfortunately, however, something very much like dictatorship is required
to guarantee quasi-transitivity or acyclicity. Quasi-transitive social outcomes can
be guaranteed only if there is an oligarchy.16 (An oligarchy is a subset of choosers
who, if the members agree, can impose a choice, or, if they do not agree, enables
all members individually to veto the choice.) If one modifies Condition D from
no dictator to no vetoer, then even a quasi-transitive social outcome cannot be
guaranteed.17 As for acyclicity, Donald Brown has shown that acyclic choice re-
quires a "collegium" such that alternative a is chosen over b if and only if the
whole collegium and some other persons prefer a to b. Thus, although a collegium
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 175
lation that transitivity does, but that would not attribute to society the ability to
order possessed only by persons. Hopefully, one would thereby avoid all the prob-
lems of the possibility theorems put forth by Arrow and his successors. Unfor-
tunately, however, it turns out that these consistency conditions also cannot be
satisfied by social choice mechanisms that satisfy the fairness conditions. Conse-
quently, although the problem can be elegantly restated in terms of choice rather
than ordering, the main defect of the methods of amalgamation is unaffected by
the new language. Just to say, for example, that x Pl y and x P2 y lead to C(x, y)
= x rather than to say that they lead to x P y does not solve the problem of
amalgamation. Some kind of inconsistency is ineradicable.
Consistency requirements on choice have been discussed in two quite dif-
ferent ways, which, however, turn out to be substantially equivalent in this con-
text. I will discuss both ways here, despite their equivalence, because their verbal
rationales are complementary.
A. K. Sen and subsequently many others have imposed on social choice con-
ditions of logicality that were originally devised as standards for individual choice
behavior. This procedure has the advantage of relating consistency in groups to
consistency in persons, but it is subject to the same charge of anthropomorphism
that was leveled against the use of ordering conditions. Charles Plott, however,
has devised a consistency condition for social choice itself, one that could not
easily be applied to persons but captures the spirit of Arrow's insistence that the
final choice ought to be independent of the path to it. It is interesting and re-
markable that Sen's and Plott's conditions turn out to be closely related and almost
equivalent.21
Looking first at Sen's conditions, let 5 and T be sets of alternatives in X =
(x^, x2, . . . ,xm) and let S be a subset of T. Sen's conditions are restrictions on the
choice sets from these two sets of alternatives, C(S) and C(T):
1. Property OC: For sets 5 and T, with 5 a subset of T, if x is in both
C(T) and 5, then x is in C(S).
2. Property j3 +: For sets 5 and T, with 5 a subset of T, if x is in C(5)
and y is in S, then, if y is in C(T), so also is x in C(T).
The meaning of these conditions is easily explained: Property OC requires that, if
the choice from the larger set is in the smaller set, then it is in the choice from
the smaller set as well.
To see the rationale of OC, consider a violation of it: A diner chooses among
three items on a menu, beef (B), chicken (Q, and fish (F), which are the set {B,
C, F}. The diner chooses beef (B); then the restaurant runs out offish (F). The
new menu is the set {B, C}, whereupon the diner chooses chicken (C) in vio-
lation both of property OC and of apparent good sense.22
Property OC guarantees consistency in choices as the number of alternatives
is contracted because in going from T to 5 the choice does not change if it is in
both sets. Property (3+, on the other hand, guarantees consistency in choices as
the number of alternatives is expanded. It requires that, if any element in the
smaller set is the choice from the larger set, then all choices from the smaller set
are choices from the larger set. Thus, in going from S to T, if any choices
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 177
from S continue to be chosen from the larger set, all such choices continue to
be chosen.
The rationale of (3+ can be appreciated from a violation of it: For a seminar
with students S = (a, b, c, d), a teacher ranks d best. Then another student en-
rolls making T = (a, b, c, d, e), whereupon the teacher ranks c best. Doubtless
student d discerns an inconsistency and believes that if he is the best or among
the best in 5 and if some other member of S is best in T, then he (d) ought to
be among the best in T also.
As I have already noted, property OC and property (3+ apply as well to in-
dividuals as to society. Plott, however, attempted to embody Arrow's notion of
"independence of the final result from the path to it" directly in a condition on
social choice. Plott justified his condition, which, appropriately, he called "path
independence," thus:
The definition of path independence is that, for any pair of sets 5 and T, the choice
from the union of the sets is the same as the choice from the union of the separate
choices from each set.24 Manifestly, if S and T are any ways of breaking up the
set of alternatives, X, then to equate the choices from their union with the choice
from the union of their choice sets is to say that it makes no difference to the
final outcome how X is divided up for choosing.
Path independence (PI) can be broken up into two parts—PI* and *PI:
1. PI* is the condition that the choice from the union of 5 and T be
included in or equivalent to the choice from the union of their choice
sets.
2. *PI is the converse of PI*. Specifically, *PI is the condition that the
choice from the union of the choice sets of S and T be included in
or equivalent to the choice from the union of S and T.25
1856, the agrarian expansionism of Jefferson and Jackson won most of the time;
indeed it was clearly beaten only in 1840. From 1860 to 1928, the Republican
program of commercial development won most of the time; it was clearly beaten
(in popular vote, but not in the election itself) only in 1876. From 1932 to the
present, Democratic welfare statism won most of the time; it was clearly beaten
only in 1952, 1956, 1972, and 1980.31 Can it not be said that these repeatedly
endorsed clusters of ideas have been, though rather vague, the true and revealed
popular will? In a very narrow sense they have indeed been approved because x
(one of these three clusters) has beaten some y (not always the same y) a number
of times, frequently in two-party contests. But x has never won over all relevant
alternatives. No party program has ever been approved in general.
The Jefferson-Jackson program of agrarian expansion was approved two-
thirds of the time from 1800 to 1856; but it failed to obtain a majority whenever
it was effectively shown that agrarian expansion entailed approval of slavery: in
1840, 1844, 1848, 1856, and 1860. The election of 1852 and its aftermath are
instructive. In 1852, Whigs, themselves in office, did not raise the slavery issue;
the Free Soil party was weak; and the Democratic party, again united on its
traditional economic platform, won by a clear majority. Democratic leaders, as-
suming they had a mandate, then produced the Kansas-Nebraska Act (1854),
which, though ostensibly mere agrarian expansion and free soil at that, actually
promoted the expansion and approval of slavery. Thereafter, and directly as a
consequence, the Democratic party did not get a national majority for more than
20 years. Though this party with its policy of approval of slavery for the sake of
expansion was apparently endorsed overwhelmingly in 1852, only a slight varia-
tion in its program resulted in savage repudiation in the next five elections. The
point is clear: x (agrarian expansion and slavery) was approved against y (com-
mercial development of Federalism and Whiggery) but lost by a huge margin to
z (commercial development and free soil, ultimately the Republican combina-
tion) .
In the next period, between 1860 and 1928, the Republican platform of
commercial development usually triumphed against a dying agrarianism. But
again, there was no general mandate for commercialism alone. Initially it suc-
ceeded (except in 1876, when, however, technically it did win) because it was
associated with free soil; in its heyday it succeeded because, I believe, its com-
mercial ideal was clearly linked to social welfare. When the welfare aspects were
forgotten in an excess of commercialism (especially around the i88os, when the
old Democratic combination of agrarianism and repression of blacks was not yet
fully rejected), the Republican party failed to maintain its majority: in 1876, 1880,
1884, 1888, 1892, 1912, and 1916. Notice that even the interlude of Wilson's
presidency was occasioned by an internal Republican split that presumably re-
flected Theodore Roosevelt's distaste for Taft's pure emphasis on commerce. Thus
the mandate often thought to be overwhelming was at best conditional on an
appeal to interest wider than commerce alone.
Finally, in the third period, from 1932 to the present, welfare statism appeared
to receive a huge mandate under Franklin Roosevelt and thereafter as long as
welfare rather than statism was emphasized. But whenever statism dominated, as
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 181
It seems worthwhile to point out just how little is contained in the liberal
interpretation of voting. In some sense it is very close to the cynical view that
counting heads is better than breaking heads to solve the problem of succession.
Let me point out some of the things that the liberal interpretation is not, simply
to show how easy it is for liberalism to survive the criticisms of social choice
theory. For one thing, liberalism does not require that society itself act. In the
liberal interpretation, society is an anthropomorphized entity that cannot order or
choose anything either consistently or inconsistently. Rather it is thought that
individual people in the society choose, and what they individually choose is
whether to support or oppose candidates. The social amalgamation of these
choices need not be fair or just. It may even be part of a social cycle. But if it
results in a decision on candidates, it is, from the liberal point of view, adequate.
Since social decisions are not, in liberal theory, required to mean anything,
liberals can cheerfully acknowledge that elections do not necessarily or even usu-
ally reveal popular will. All elections do or have to do is to permit people to get
rid of rulers. The people who do this do not themselves need to have a coherent
will. They can be—and often are—strange bedfellows. Voters on the far right and
the far left, for example, can combine to throw out a ruler in the center. The
liberal purpose is then accomplished, even though one could not make a coherent
ideological statement about what these voters did and even though their majority
might be cyclical. The Indian rejection of Indira Gandhi in 1997 was accom-
plished by just such a coalition, the Janata party, which was, however, so inco-
herent in its combination of right and left that Mrs. Gandhi was able to win again
in 1979.
The liberal interpretation of voting thus allows elections to be useful and
significant even in the presence of cycles, manipulation, and other kinds of "er-
rors" in voting. Since it is precisely cycles, manipulation, and "error" that render
populism meaningless, the fact that liberalism can tolerate them demonstrates that
184 Philosophy and Democracy
liberalism can survive the revelations of social choice theory, while populism
cannot.
The kind of democracy that thus survives is not, however, popular rule, but
rather an intermittent, sometimes random, even perverse, popular veto. Social
choice theory forces us to recognize that the people cannot rule as a corporate
body in the way that populists suppose. Instead, officials rule, and they do not
represent some indefinable popular will. Hence they can easily be tyrants, either
in their own names or in the name of some putative imaginary majority. Liberal
democracy is simply the veto by which it is sometimes possible to restrain official
tyranny.
This may seem a minimal sort of democracy, especially in comparison with
the grandiose (though intellectually absurd) claims of populism. Still, modest
though liberal democracy may be, it fully satisfies the definition of democracy I
favor. To begin with, it necessarily involves popular participation. Though the
participation is not the abstract self-direction of a corporate people, it is the con-
crete self-direction of individuals who vote and organize voting to make the
democratic veto work. Furthermore, since the veto does exist—even when ma-
nipulated or cyclical—it has at least the potential of preventing tyranny and ren-
dering officials responsive.
Since officials are not responsive to some imaginary popular will, this popular
participation is not the act of making policy. At best officials are responsive to a
(possibly random) threat of expulsion from office. But this may lead them to avoid
gross offense to groups of citizens who can eject them from office. Participation
in this sense is then the act of placing a curb on policy, a veto at the margin.
Nevertheless it is participation. Furthermore, it can engender that self-direction
and self-respect that democracy is supposed to provide because candidates, trying
to construct winning platforms in the face of that potential veto, also try to
generate majorities, at least momentary ones.
Furthermore, the liberal veto generates freedom because of the very fact that
it is a curb on tyranny. Whether one thinks of freedom as the absence of restraint
("negative liberty" in Isaiah Berlin's terms) or as the ability to direct one's own
life ("positive liberty"), it is apparent that oppression by rulers eliminates either
kind of freedom. Suppose freedom is simply the absence of governmental restraint
on individual action. Then the chance to engage in vetoing by rejecting officials
and the chance that the rejection actually occur are the very essence of this
freedom, which is substantially equivalent to liberal democracy. Suppose, how-
ever, freedom is defined as the ability to use government to work one's will—
the populist expectation. The agent of this (imaginary) will is government—that
is, rulers who can oppress both the minority and the very majority whose will
they are supposed to work. An extreme example is socialist rulers who, in order
to free workers from the supposed bondage to owners, subject them to the own-
ership of the state and the terrorism of the police. But conventional populists
turned dictator (for example, Vargas, Gandhi, and Peron) are often just as op-
pressive. Liberal democracy, insofar as it allows people to restrain and reject, is
the main sanction against this majoritarian oppression also.
Sometimes populists argue that the true meaning of democracy is not to be
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 185
found in voting, party organization, and the like, but rather in the democratic
ideals of civil liberties, tolerance, and humane concern for popular rights. No one
doubts that these ideals are indeed truly central in democratic thought (although
I suspect that efforts to distinguish them from voting are often the first step—a
la Marx—to some kind of coercive enterprise). Still, these democratic ideals de-
pend on a vigilant citizenry. What permits a citizenry to be vigilant is the liberal
method of regular elections. In that sense liberal democracy is a necessary part of
what populists claim to want.
In the same way, liberal democracy promotes a kind of equality. Equal chances
to restrain, to reject, and to veto inhere in the very idea of using votes to control
officials. This is the notion of the equality of the right of democratic participation,
which is the essence of the idea of juristic equality. Equality has many other
derived meanings, including notions such as equal shares of the national treasure
and equality before the law (that is, in the courtroom). But equality in these
derived senses cannot occur unless juristic equality exists. In that way, juristic
equality is primary, and that is what liberal democracy provides.
So the liberal interpretation of voting, however much it admits of "unfair"
voting methods, manipulation, cycles, and the like, still contains the essential
elements of democracy. It may, from the populist view, be a minimal kind of
democracy; but this is the only kind of democracy actually attainable. It is the
kind of democracy we still have in the United States; and it is the kind of de-
mocracy so much admired by those who live in closed societies.
elections are preserved. Then, even though the populist ideal may be unattainable,
populism need not destroy freedom. So the question really is: Can liberal insti-
tutions (that is, the ability to reject rulers) be maintained when the populist in-
terpretation of voting and populist institutions are adopted?
To answer, I will first define briefly the institutions appropriate for each
interpretation of voting.
Populist Institutions. The populist ideal requires that rulers move swiftly and
surely to embody in law the popular decision on an electoral platform. Consti-
tutional restraints that retard this process are populistically intolerable. The appro-
priate institutions are those that facilitate speedy embodiment, and the simplest
such institutions are so-called constitutional dictatorships, by which I mean dic-
tatorial executives who submit to real elections or plebiscites but rule by decree
or through a complaisant legislature. Latin American governments often have this
form. Mexico is perhaps an example, though, since Mexican presidents never
stand for reelection, the one-party plebiscites may not be real elections.
More complex populist institutions are those that develop out of parliamen-
tary governments when they degenerate into a sovereign self-regenerating legis-
lature run by a leader (who is also the executive) of a disciplined majority party.
For the legislature to be sovereign, there cannot be external restraints like an
externally selected executive and independent courts; nor can there be internal
restraints such as multiple houses with different constituencies. For the legislature
to be disciplined members of the majority party dare not defy the party leader.
Furthermore, at least one party must be a majority alone. With such arrangements
the party leader can then ensure that party platforms are quickly adopted in true
populist fashion. Finally, since the legislature is self-regenerating, this leader can
manipulate the time and conditions of elections to facilitate his or her own con-
tinuance in office.
The closest current approximation to this ideal is Great Britain as it has
developed over the last generation. External checks on the House of Commons
have been removed. The House of Lords was effectively countered by the Par-
liament Act of 1911, and the last attempt at ever personal freedom in the Crown
was repulsed at the abdication of Edward VIII in 1937. Strong third parties, a
characteristic feature of nineteenth century Parliaments (for example, the Radicals,
Irish, and Labour), were eliminated with the decline of Liberalism after the 19205,
though they may be reappearing in the new Liberalism or Social Democracy. The
national leaders of the two main parties acquired control of nominations so that
the members became disciplined. And finally the national leadership of the ma-
jority party was lodged in the prime minister, who, once in office, could usually
control all factions of his or her party and, within wide limits, ensure his or her
continuance in office. What has so far saved the British system from constitutional
dictatorship is, I believe, a three-century-old liberal tradition of free and regular
elections. But even that tradition now seems threatened. The ideal of new elec-
tions when the government loses in the House of Commons has degenerated
into the government's selection of a propitious time within the limits of a five-
year term. (And that term has twice been doubled with the excuse of war.) More
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 187
tegrity of elections, it seems unlikely that the liberal sanction can survive populist
institutions. Indeed this empirical regularity suggests to me that there is a profound
theoretical reason that populism induces rulers to ensconce themselves in office.
At any rate, on the practical level at least, the answer is clearly negative to the
main question of this section: Is liberal rejectability compatible with populist in-
corporability? No: because the constitutional restraints practically associated with
liberalism must be destroyed to achieve populism.
5. Limited tenure and regular elections. This is the fundamental restraint, but
it is not a self-enforcing limitation. It depends rather on the force of
tradition and on the other restraints previously listed.
About the only important restraint commonly found in other constitutional de-
mocracies and not included in this one is a system of more than two political
parties so that no single party is ever a majority by itself. Something of that
restraint, however, is provided in the American system by decentralized parties.
Madison was correct, I believe, in his assertion that constitutional limits pre-
serve liberal democracy. Fortunately the limits he helped provide retain most of
their original force. Yet in the American political tradition there has always been
a strong strand of populism, usually expressed as the notion that the winners of
an election ought to be able immediately to embody their platform in law and
policy. This was, for example, the basis for the attack by Jacksonians on bureau-
cratic tenure, for the attack by populist political philosophers (such as Charles
Beard and J. Allen Smith) on constitutional limitations of all sorts, for the per-
sistent advocacy of a rigid system of two disciplined political parties (thus allowing
a "majority" immediately to enact its program), and finally in recent decades for
the idealization of "presidential leadership"—a euphemism for transcending con-
stitutional limitations by the domination of a populistically endorsed, quasi-
monarchical president.
Along with the populist notion of an unfettered agent (whether party or
president) of the popular will, there is also the notion that the popular will can
express itself directly, as in legislation by referenda and even by public opinion
polls. The device of referendum was developed in the progressive era—an epoch
of the populist spirit—to provide a "truer" expression of the popular will than
statutes produced by legislatures, which were, it was argued, merely distorting
intermediaries of the popular will. Since that time there has been considerable
disillusionment with referenda because they have produced both inconsistent and
bizarre legislation. Still, the populist belief in direct democracy dies hard, even
though it can in no wise escape the defects of manipulation. So now there is
considerable enthusiasm for using cable television to conduct elections on the
content of statutes and even of administrative policy. Presumably citizens will
listen to debate and then vote by push button, supplanting thereby the need for
any kind of legislature.
Many current proposals for institutional reform are populistically intended
to nullify constitutional limitations. In spite of disasters with the "imperial"
presidencies of Johnson and Nixon, people continue to search for ways to en-
hance presidential leadership—by tightening presidential control of the bureauc-
racy and by elaborating presidential influence in the party. The decentralization
of political parties, the fundamental restraint in federalism, is under constant at-
tack with proposals for frequent policy-making conventions to be dominated by
national leaders and proposals for centralized national financing of campaigns.
While at the moment proposals to eliminate legislatures with direct law-making
over cable television or to substitute (a la Marcus Raskin) instructions from
grand juries for legislative judgment seem bizarre, I have no doubt that, as
ipo Philosophy and Democracy
technology and opportunity combine, such populist proposals will be taken se-
riously.
The present situation in the United States is, therefore, that, although the
fundamental constitutional limitations remain, populists persistently seek to un-
dermine them. Since the twentieth century is a populist era worldwide, our
homegrown populists may well succeed.
Populism puts democracy at risk. Democracy requires control of rulers by
electoral sanctions; the spirit of populism and populist institutions allows rulers to
tamper with this sanction, thereby rendering it a weak defense against the tyranny
of officials. The maintenance of democracy requires therefore the minimization
of the risk in populism.
How can we minimize the risk? This is the great question of political pru-
dence forced on us by the revelations of social choice theory. I will conclude this
survey with some remarks on this practical problem.
The main defense against populist excesses is the maintenance of the consti-
tutional limitations inherited from eighteenth-century Whiggery. It would prob-
ably help also to have a citizenry aware of the emptiness of the populist inter-
pretation of voting. And surely a wide dissemination of the discoveries of social
choice theory is a desirable additional defense. But the dissemination of a rather
arcane theory is a task for generations. (It took me a score of years of reflection
on Black's and Arrow's discoveries to reject the populism I had initially espoused.)
Consequently, the fundamental method to preserve liberty is to preserve ardently
our traditional constitutional restraints—decentralized parties and multicameral
government.
Almost everyone who has written about American politics has emphasized
its peculiar style. Except for the one great disaster of the Civil War, the nastiest
features of political scarcity have seldom flourished. One group has not persistently
tried to do in another, probably because political coalitions are always shifting and
constitutional restraints make it difficult to organize zero-sum situations. Conse-
quently, there are no elaborately rationalized ideologies that carry with them a
logically clear and intricately arranged set of public policies. Instead, political
leaders are almost always engaged in constructing petty and pragmatic compro-
mises for marginal adjustments in policy. Only in a few great crises have great
leaders emerged, and great leaders have always disappeared as the crises have
subsided.
The reason for this style is, I believe, the existence of constitutional limita-
tions. In his famous defense in The Federalist, No. 51, of the notion of the sepa-
ration of powers, Madison remarked:
The experience of the subsequent two centuries has reinforced the teaching to
which Madison referred. And the reason is this: Liberal democracy almost guar-
antees some circulation of leadership so that great power is usually fleeting and
Social Choice Theory and Constitutional Democracy 191
no vested interest lasts forever. The constitutional restraints have always reinforced
this style. Multicameralism and federalism have enforced localism in parties, and
this in turn has forced rulers to persuade rather than to control. The total effect
is that policy does not change either rapidly or sharply enough to hurt anyone
very badly, which is why we have usually—except in the Civil War—avoided
the worst features of political scarcity. That the system has worked in this moderate
way is due partly to luck; but it also is due to that happy mixture of liberal
democracy and constitutional restraints that has so far preserved us from the ha-
treds and oppression implicit in populism.
Notes
1. William H. Riker, "Voting and the Summation of Preferences," American Polical
Science Review, Vol. 55 (December 1961), pp. 900-911.
2. Since many proofs are easily available to those who wish to follow up the subject,
I will not reiterate the proof here. For Arrow's proof, as revised by Julian Blau, see Kenneth
Arrow, Social Choice and Individual Values, 2nd ed. (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1963), pp. 96-100. A refined form of Arrow's proof is to be found in Amartya K. Sen,
Collective Choice and Social Welfare (San Francisco: Holden-Day, 1970), chap. 3. See also
Peter C. Fishburn, The Theory of Social Choice (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1973),
p. 206. Bengt Hansson, "The Existence of Group Preference Functions," Public Choice, Vol.
28 (Winter 1976), pp. 89-98, contains a topological proof. An informal sketch of Arrow's
proof is contained in William H. Riker and Peter C. Ordeshook, An Introduction to Positive
Political Theory (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1973), pp. 92-94.
3. See Duncan Black, The Theory of Committees and Elections (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1958), pp. 50-51, where the calculation was first proposed. Calculations
are set forth in Richard Niemi and Herbert Weisberg, "A Mathematical Solution for the
Probability of the Paradox of Voting," Behavioral Science, Vol. 13 (July 1968), pp. 317-323;
Mark Gorman and Morton Kamien, "The Paradox of Voting: Probability Calculations,"
Behavioral Science, Vol. 13 (July 1968), pp. 306-316; Frank DeMeyer and Charles Plott, "The
Probability of a Cyclical Majority," Econometrica, Vol. 38 (March 1970), pp. 345—354. See
also R. M. May, "Some Mathematical Remarks on the Paradox of Voting," Behavioral
Science, Vol. 16 (March 1971), pp. 143-151; Peter C. Fishburn and William V Gehrlein,
"An Analysis of Simple Two-Stage Voting Systems," Behavioral Science, Vol. 21 (January
1976), pp. 1-12; Fishburn and Gehrlein, "An Analysis of Voting Procedure with Nonranked
Voting," Behavioral Science, Vol. 22 (May 1977), pp. 178-185; Gehrlein and Fishburn, "The
Probability of the Paradox of Voting," Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 13 (August 1976),
pp. 14-25; and the essays cited in note 8 of this chapter.
4. Duncan Black, "On the Rationale of Group Decision Making," Journal of Political
Economy, Vol. 56 (February 1948), pp. 23-34; Black, The Theory of Committees and Elections,
chaps. 4 and 5.
5. Fishburn, The Theory of Social Choice, p. 105.
6. Black, The Theory of Committees and Elections, chap. 4.
7. Fishburn, The Theory of Social Choice, pp. 111-144. See also Sen, pp. 166-186. A
somewhat different kind of condition for transitivity (not involving restrictions on D,) has
been identified by Rubin Saposnik, "On Transitivity of the Social Preference Relation
Under Simple Majority Rule," Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 10 (January 1975), pp. i—
7, where it is shown that, if the number of voters in D having orders constituting the