0% found this document useful (0 votes)
14 views17 pages

Lec 2adasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf A

Uploaded by

slushienotslush
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
14 views17 pages

Lec 2adasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf Aadasdqwe Qewq Ew Adsf A

Uploaded by

slushienotslush
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 17

Mathematical Concepts (G6012)

Lecture 2

Proofs: direct, contrapositive, and


contradiction
(ft. the irrationality of 𝟐)

Niel de Beaudrap
[email protected]

[email protected]
Content and learning outcomes
• In this lecture I will discuss:
– Proving statements by chains of implications
– The contrapositive of an implication
– Proof by contrapositive
– Proof by contradiction
• Learning outcomes:
– You will understand different ways that
‘implication’ is used in mathematics
– You will know various proof techniques
Direct proof and implication
There are several approaches to proving a proposition
— and some are important enough, to have names.
e.g. ‘Direct’ proof:
Proving that 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋 by a chain of implications,
𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵 ⇒ 𝐶 ⇒ ⋯ ⇒ 𝑋. (𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵, and 𝐵 ⇒ 𝐶, and…)
• This is common enough that we often use the symbol ‘⇒’
to mean not just “if — then —”, but also ‘implies’
– ‘𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵’ = ‘if 𝐴 then 𝐵’ = ‘𝐴 implies 𝐵’
– But also: ‘𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵 ⇒ 𝐶 ⇒ ⋯’ could mean:
‘we know that 𝐴,
which implies 𝐵, which implies 𝐶, …
Recall ℚ : the rational numbers
𝑛
• ℚ={ ∶ 𝑛, 𝑑 ∈ ℤ , 𝑑 ≠ 0}.
𝑑
𝑛
For ∈ ℚ we call 𝑛 the ‘numerator’, and 𝑑 the ‘denominator’
𝑑

• If 𝑛 = 𝑘𝑎 and 𝑑 = 𝑘𝑏 for some integers 𝑎, 𝑏 ∈ ℤ ,


𝑛 𝑘𝑎 𝑎
then we may ‘simplify’: 𝑥 = = =
𝑑 𝑘𝑏 𝑏

• If 𝑛 and 𝑑 have no factors in common, we say


𝑛
that is in reduced form
𝑑

• Unlike ℕ and ℤ , there is never a ‘next’ element of ℚ :


Between any two rational numbers there is another.
Proof that between any two
rational numbers lies another
Let 𝑥 ∈ ℚ, and let 𝑦 ∈ ℚ be such that 𝑦 > 𝑥.
Strategy: consider 𝑦−𝑥
(𝑦 − 𝑥)/2

𝑥 𝑦−𝑥 𝑦
𝑥+
2

𝑦−𝑥 2𝑥 + 𝑦 − 𝑥 𝑥+𝑦
• Simplify: 𝑥 + = =
2 2 2

𝑥+𝑦
• It is rational: 𝑥, 𝑦 ∈ ℚ ⇒ 𝑥 + 𝑦 ∈ ℚ ⇒ ∈ℚ
2
Proof (cont’d) that between any
two rational numbers lies another
• Note that:
𝑥 𝑦 𝑥 𝑥 𝑦 𝑥 𝑥+𝑦
𝑥<𝑦 ⇒ < ⇒ 2
+2 < 2
+2 ⇒ 𝑥 <
2 2 2

• Similarly:
𝑥 𝑦 𝑥 𝑦 𝑦 𝑦 𝑥+𝑦
𝑥<𝑦 ⇒ < ⇒ +2 < +2 ⇒ < 𝑦
2 2 2 2 2
𝑥+𝑦
So: 𝑥 < < 𝑦 , which means that
2
there is an element of ℚ between 𝑥 and 𝑦 . q.e.d

(We say: ℚ is dense.)


Logical symbols again
• ¬𝐴 means “not 𝐴”
• 𝐴 & 𝐵 (or “𝐴 ∧ 𝐵”) means “𝐴 and 𝐵 ”
• “𝐴 ∨ 𝐵” means “𝐴 or 𝐵 ”
— i.e., inclusive or, which allows for both 𝐴 and 𝐵 to be true

• “𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵” means “ if 𝐴, then 𝐵 ”
— not cause-and-effect !
Just that: you never have 𝐴, without also having 𝐵.
Reasoning about implication
There is a specific name for this kind of “if — then —”
relation: material implication
• “You never get 𝐴, without also having 𝐵” :
– In symbols: 𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵 is equivalent to ¬(𝐴 & ¬𝐵)

• De Morgan’s Law: ¬(𝐴 & 𝐵) ⟺ ¬𝐴 ∨ ¬𝐵


¬ 𝐴∨𝐵 ⟺ ¬𝐴 & ¬𝐵
• So that means:
𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵 is equivalent to ¬𝐴 ∨ 𝐵
Turning around an implication
If 𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵, it is not necessarily true that 𝐵 ⇒ 𝐴
(the “converse” of 𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵)

• 𝑎 < 3 ⇒ 𝑎 < 5, but: 𝑎 < 5 does not imply 𝑎 < 3


— as we could have 𝑎 = 4 instead

But if 𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵, it does follow that ¬𝐵 ⇒ ¬𝐴


(the contrapositive of 𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵)
¬𝐵 ⇒ ¬𝐴 ⟺ ¬¬𝐵 ∨ ¬𝐴 ⟺ ¬𝐴 ∨ 𝐵 ⟺ 𝐴⇒𝐵
Proof by contrapositive
Idea: prove a statement of the form 𝐴 ⇒ 𝐵,
by proving that ¬𝐵 ⇒ ¬𝐴 .
• Example. Recall ℤ = {… , −2, −1, 0, +1, +2, … }
Define the even integers 𝐸 = 2𝑧 ∶ 𝑧 ∈ ℤ
and the odd integers 𝐴 = 2𝑧 + 1 ∶ 𝑧 ∈ ℤ .

– Prove that for any 𝑎 ∈ ℤ : 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐸 ⇒ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐸.

– Strategy: prove that 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐴.


Proof:
Use the fact that for 𝑧 ∈ ℤ, we have 𝑧 ∈ 𝐴 ⟺ 𝑧 ∉ 𝐸

• The contrapositive of 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐸 ⇒ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐸
is 𝑎 ∉ 𝐸 ⇒ 𝑎 2 ∉ 𝐸
which is equivalent to 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐴

• Suppose 𝑎 is odd, i.e., 𝑎 = 2𝑧 + 1 for some 𝑧 ∈ ℤ.


• Then 𝑎 2 = 2𝑧 + 1 2
= 4𝑧 2 + 4𝑧 + 1
= 2 ⋅ 2𝑧 2 + 2𝑧 + 1 ∈ 𝐴.
• So 𝑎 ∈ 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐴; then 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐸 ⇒ 𝑎 ∈ 𝐸. q.e.d
Proof techniques
• Direct proof:
Proving that 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋 by a chain of implications,
𝐴 ⇒𝐵⇒⋯⇒𝑋
• Proof by contraposition:
Proving that 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋, by showing that ¬𝑋 ⇒ ¬𝐴
— the contraposition of 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋

• Proof by contradiction:
Proving ¬𝐴, by proving that 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋
for some statement 𝑋 which is known to be false
(i.e., a logical contradition)
The square root of 2
Pythagoras’ theorem:
For a right-angle triangle with hypothenuse length 𝑐
and other side-lengths 𝑎 and 𝑏,
𝑎2 + 𝑏2 = 𝑐 2 .

• For a right-angle triangle 𝑐2 = 2


with 𝑎 = 1 and 𝑏 = 1,
this would imply 𝑐 = 2. 𝑎2 = 1 𝑎 𝑐
𝑏

We can show: 2 ∉ ℚ . 𝑏2 = 1
Proof of 𝟐 ∉ ℚ: by contradiction
We start by supposing that 2 ∈ ℚ
(and then finding out the consequences)
• Suppose 2 = 𝑎/𝑏 for some integers 𝑎, 𝑏 ∈ ℤ
▪ and suppose also that 𝑎/𝑏 is the reduced form,
so that 𝑎 and 𝑏 have no common integer divisors
𝑎2
• Then 2 = ⇒ 𝑎 2 = 2𝑏 2 .
𝑏2

• As 𝑏 2 is an integer, 𝑎 2 is an even integer: 𝑎 2 ∈ 𝐸.


▪ As we’ve already seen, that means 𝑎 ∈ 𝐸 as well:
so 𝑎 = 2𝑧, for some 𝑧 ∈ ℤ .
𝟐 ∉ ℚ (proof by contradiction)
• As 𝑎 = 2𝑧 for some 𝑧 ∈ ℤ, we have

2𝑏 2 = 𝑎 2 = 2𝑧 2 = 4𝑧 2
so that 𝑏 2 = 2𝑧 2 .
• That means 𝑏 2 is even too! Then 𝑏 is even as well,
so that 𝑏 = 2𝑦 for some 𝑦 ∈ ℤ .
• Wait: both 𝑎 and 𝑏 are multiples of 2?
But they’re not supposed to have divisors in common!

Contradiction!
⇒ 𝟐 is not rational. q.e.d
What just happened?
A demonstration of the ancient art of
Fooling* around and finding out
• We made a bold assumption: “ 2 ∈ ℚ ” (call this “ 𝐴 ”).
• The assumption 𝐴 implies a proposition 𝑋, which
cannot be true: that there are 𝑎, 𝑏 ∈ ℤ which
▪ have no common integer factors
▪ also, are somehow both multiples of 2

• As 𝑋, is false, it follows that


our assumption 𝐴 is also false.
Proof techniques
• Direct proof: prove 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋 by a chain of implications

• Proof by contraposition:
Prove 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋, by showing that ¬𝑋 ⇒ ¬𝐴

• Proof by contradiction:
Prove ¬𝐴, by proving that 𝐴 ⇒ 𝑋 where 𝑋 is false
• One more technique to come —
proof by induction:
prove 𝑃 𝑛 for all 𝑛 ∈ ℕ
… as if by a domino effect

You might also like