Brown and Miller Syntax 1980
Brown and Miller Syntax 1980
Introduction to Sentence
Structure
p
2*15
Syntax: A Linguistic Bi
Introduction to Sentence
Structure
HUTCHINSON
London Melbourne Sydney Auckland Johannesburg
Hutchinson & Co. (Publishers) Ltd
An imprint of the Hutchinson Publishing Group
24 Highbury Crescent, London N5 irx
Hutchinson Group (Australia) Pty Ltd
30-32 Cremome Street, Richmond South, Victoria 3121
PO Box 151, Broadway, New South Wales 2007
Hutchinson Group (NZ) Ltd
32-34 View Road, PO Box 40-086, Glenfield, Auckland 10
Hutchinson Group (SA) (Pty) Ltd
PO Box 337, Bergvlei 2012, South Africa
First published 1980
© E. K. Brown and J. E. Miller 1980
Preface 7
Introduction 9
Postscript 383
Further reading 386
References 388
Index 391
Preface
Constituent structure
1 Constituent structure
and so on.1 We also know that constituents like -ed, -ing and -5
occur with other verbs like KILL: kill-ed, kill-ing, kill-s. We
consider the analysis of words in due course; for the present we
need merely to acknowledge that the word is a traditionally
recognized unit, and that a unit of this sort indeed seems a
relevant constituent in English.
Our third assumption concerns the sentence. Suppose we use
the neutral term ‘string’ to refer to any sequence of constituents:
we can then refer to the words the dog or frightened the child or
indeed the whole of 1 as strings without a commitment as to
their status as constituents or any identification of the type of
constituents we believe them to be. What entitles us to refer to
the string 1 as a sentence, when the other strings mentioned do
not seem to be sentences? Unfortunately, as with the word,
there are considerable problems about the identification of
sentences: to call a string a sentence implies that it has a certain
sort of unity, but it is far from easy to describe exactly what sort
of unity a string needs to have for it to be referred to as a
The discussion also shows that constituents like the dog and the
child are constituents of the same type, whereas frightened is a
constituent of a different type. Following traditional usage we
call constituents like the dog Noun Phrases, abbreviated as NP,
and constituents like frightened a Verb, abbreviated as V.
Our first analysis, then, suggests that the sentence has three
constituents, which we can represent by the string:
13 NP + V+NP
(Note that we use string to refer both to strings of words, and to
strings of constituent names.)
We should now consider the constituents of these constituents
since the NP clearly has internal structure: it consists of the
word the followed by either child or dog. Child and dog appear
to be the same sort of constituent since they are mutually
substitutable for each other, and different from either frightened
or the since neither is substitutable for either of these words: we
will refer to them, again following the traditional terminology,
as Nouns abbreviated as N. We have already noted that the is a
different type of constituent from either of the Ns we have
identified or the V: we have noted that it does not co-occur with
26 Part one: Constituent structure
a V, and that it may co-occur with an N, but that if it does it
must precede the N in the NP: there are no strings *dog the or
* child the. Again following traditional terminology, we call the
an Article, abbreviated as Art.
14 NP + V + NP
15 Art + N
16 frightened is a V
dog and child are Ns
the is an Art
18 (((The)(dog))(frightened)((the)(child)))
NP(Art(the)N(child)))
Art N Art N
NP lNp-l
V
I
Figure 1 •s■
Art N V Art N
Figure 2
V NP
Art N Art N
Figure 3
Art N Pro
Comp NP V NP
/\ /\
Art N Art N
ii ii
the rumour that the dog chased the child frightened me
Figure 4
Technical terms
NP V
I
/\
Art N
etc. In these sentences the words fall into groups that are
mutually substitutable within the sentence structure shown in
Figure 5, as summarized in Figure 6.
Figure 6
A set of words like {dog, child, cat, bird} where the individual
words are mutually substitutable is known as a word class. Our
analysis has established three classes; the class containing the
one member {the}; the class containing {dog, child, cat, bird};
and the class containing {frightened, chased, killed, caught, hit}.
We have named them, following traditional usage, respectively,
Art(icle) N(oun) and V(erb).
Word classes are not the only classes of item needed in a
grammar, as is clear from the discussion in the preceding
chapter, where we saw that strings of words like the dog and the
child also need to be accounted for: we identified these as Noun
Phrases (NP). For this reason linguists have usually preferred
the more general term form class, since form may be applied
indifferently to words, parts of words, strings of words, etc. Our
substitution table can accommodate information about form
classes other than word classes by labelling and bracketing
within the table, as shown in Figure 7.
NP V NP
Art N Art N
Figure 7
34 Part one: Constituent structure
Two important and closely related points about form classes
are, first, the membership or the internal structure of the class
in question, and second, its distribution.
As far as word classes are concerned we can only list their
membership, since we are not considering here the internal
structure of words. Thus, the class of Articles consists of the
word {the} (so far the only article we have met); and so on. In
the case of other form classes it would be absurd and cumber¬
some to state their membership in terms of strings of words: the
class NP consists of the strings [the dog, the cat, the bird . . .};
etc. Instead we describe their internal structure in terms of other
form classes: the class NP consists of strings of the form
Art + N, leaving to our description of the membership of Art
and N a specification of what these classes contain.
We now turn to the question of distribution. By the
distribution of an item, we mean the set of environments in
which it occurs. In sentence 1 the distribution of frightened is:
5 NP_NP
6 NP (_N)
Art N
8 NP + V + NP (Figure 8)
PN + V + NP (Figure 9)
NP V
Art N
the
I I
dog frightened
Figure 10
NP V NP
PN
Fido frightened
Figure 11
Under this analysis the two sentences have the same structure at
the most ‘fundamental’ level since the constituents of the
sentence are, in both cases:
9 NP + V + NP
and the two sentences differ only in the internal structure of the
initial NP. This solution seems the more satisfactory on an
intuitive basis, and formal evidence supports it.
First of all, let us widen the data base further to include the
following sentences:
Form classes 37
10a The boy yawned
10b The dog slept
10c Fido yawned
lOd John slept
As before, we consider strings like the dog and the boy as strings
with the structure Art + N, and members of the class NP. Fido
and John are once more members of the class PN. Yawned and
slept also form a substitution class, traditionally called
Intransitive Verbs, which we abbreviate as VI. Members of this
class cannot be put into the same class as words like frightened,
chased, etc., since these items are not mutually substitutable -
there are no sentences:
13 NP + VI
NP + VT+ NP
16 NP + {vt + NP }
S S
VT NP VI
Figure 12 Figure 13
1 The symbol # indicates a ‘constituent boundary’: in this case the end of the
sentence. We use this symbol to indicate that VI does not occur with a following
NP, as distinct from VT.
Form classes 39
(Structure below the NP level is not shown since it is irrelevant
to the argument.) All the sentences are now analysed as having
the single structure:
17 NP + VP
Technical terms
distribution substitution table
environment word class
form class
3 Constituent structure grammar
2 Art: {the}
N: {dog, child, boy, cat}
PN: {Fido, John}
VT: {frightened, chased}
VI: {yawned, slept}
4 S —* NP + VP
5 A + B—»X + Y + Z
X Y Z
42 Part one: Constituent structure
X Y Z
8 A X + Y
B -» Z
9 A^ X
B -> Y + Z
10 A —> X + Y
X + Y
11 A
Y + X
X + Y
12 A
P + Q
Constituent structure grammar 43
13 A —> {X, Y, Z}
B Lexical rules:
4 Art —> {the}
5 N —» {dog, child, boy, cat}
6 PN —» {Fido, John}
7 VT —» {frightened, chased}
8 VI —» {yawned, slept}
Figure 14 NP VP
Art N
Figure 16 PN
Art N VT NP
I
PN
I
The boy chased Fido
Figure 17
Art N VT Art N
VT NP
chased cat
Technical terms
category lexical insertion
constituent structure rules lexical rule
expansion non-terminal symbol
generative grammar rewrite rule
grammatical terminal symbol
initial symbol
Exercises
This data introduces two new sentence types and hence two new
verb subclasses (and also includes further examples of struc¬
tures we have already analysed). What are the environments for
these two new verb classes? Use the additional constituent
labels PP (Prepositional phrase) and Part(icle), and use the
labels VbPP and VbPart for the two new classes of verb. A
Prepositional phrase has the constituents Prep(osition) + NP.
The class Prep includes items like {under, near, in, on . . .}.
The NP can be any NP as described earlier.
Example 14 in this chapter presented a grammar for a re¬
stricted set of English sentences. Extend this gramipar to in¬
clude the data from this exercise. The extended grammar should
generate all the sentences in the data and others of a similar
pattern and assign to each a constituent structure tree.
the, big, new, her, five, all, lovely, worn-out, woollen, blue,
spectacular, small, my, two, few, splendid, quite, silk, pale,
your, a, old, some, red, cotton, very
Constituent structure grammar 49
(The notions ‘head noun’ and ‘premodifiers’ are discussed further
on pages 254-5: in NPs of the sort you are asked to consider the
head noun is always the final, and obligatory, constituent,
which may be preceded by a number of optional premodifiers.)
2a John is a soldier
2b John is strong
3 He is a soldier
4 They are soldiers
5 *They are a soldier. *He is soldiers
6 _Pred
‘Intransitive’ verbs
8 _ #
9a The women wept
9b The children cried
‘Transitive’ verbs
10 _N P
11a The dog bit the man
lib The child thrashed the dog
With all true transitive verbs, for any sentence of the form:
13a NP + V + NP
13b The dog bit the man
2 The grammar discussed in the preceding chapter, and elaborated at the end
of this chapter, can be used to give a formal definition to the terms 'subject’ and
‘object’. The subject NP is that NP which is immediately dominated by S; the
object is that NP immediately dominated by VP. In these terms the NP
dominated by Pred which occurs after the copula verb be discussed in 1-7 is not
an object NP - in traditional terms it is referred to as a ‘complement’. Notions
such as subject, object, complement, etc. are discussed in more detail on pages
330ff.i
Some verb classes in English 53
‘Di-transitive’ verbs
16 _NP + NP
17 John gave Mary the book
20 _PP
21a The lamp stood on the table
21b The gun leant against the wall
23 _NP + PP
24 John stood the lamp on the table
25 Mary leant the gun against the wall
and so on.
An approach of this sort poses difficulties. It leads to the
establishment of a large number of verb classes: we already
have six, and with little difficulty can establish more. This makes
the second rule in our grammar cumbersome. Furthermore, we
find that a considerable amount of ‘cross-classification’ is
involved: i.e. many verbs occur in more than one class -
examples we have seen are the verbs STAND and LEAN. An
alternative approach is to have a lexicon listing the class
membership of each verb, and a lexical insertion rule as
discussed in the preceding chapter. This approach leads to the
listing in the lexicon of the different class memberships of each
verb, in the form:
33 STAND V.„ V ,
ll tl
and so on, but does not solve the clumsiness of the constituent
structure rules.
A different approach lists in the lexicon the environments in
which a particular verb can occur, without actually seeking to
name each individual verb class. Thus we list STAND as:
34 STAND V; _ (NP) PP
35 S —» NP + VP
Technical terms
Exercises
1
The text of this chapter distinguished six verb classes. To which
of these classes do the following verbs belong? Note that some
belong to more than one class. For each verb draw up a lexical
entry like that shown in the text for STAND:
We noted in the text that sentences like Moggy is a cat and Kate
bought a cat are, at one level of structure, apparently similar -
NP V NP - but that we need to distinguish between copular
verbs (like be) and transitive verbs (like buy). Summarize the
reasons for making this distinction.
58 Part one: Constituent structure
(This analysis will be defended in more detail later on.) For our
present purposes we describe the relevant environment as:
_ S
Given these two new environments, write lexical entries for the
following verbs. For example:
TALK and RIPEN in 7 and 8 are clearly verbs (they occur in the
verbal forms ripens and IS ripen ING, etc.); equally clearly RIPE
in 9 is an adjective (it occurs with the copula, BE, and in
constructions with the verb GET). We cannot use the verb
RIPEN with the syntax of an adjective, nor the adjective RIPE
with the syntax of a verb, as can be seen by comparing 8 and 9
with the ungrammatical:
10 *The fruit ripes; *The fruit is riping
11 *The fruit is ripen; *The fruit is getting ripen
1 This is not the whole story since tonal distinctions are also involved, and
these are not marked. However this account is adequate for our purposes.
62 Part one: Constituent structure
The fact that RIPE and RIPEN are lexically related, though
true, is irrelevant: RIPE is an adjective and RIPEN a verb. In
attempting to describe the grammar of a language, formal
criteria are to be preferred to notional criteria.
Members of a formally established form class may have a
common notional element; indeed this is often the case and is
no surprise if we hold that language is a system for communi¬
cating meanings. On the other hand the principles behind the
establishment of formal and notional classes are quite different,
and formal criteria are in general preferable.
The second sense of formal implies that the grammar should be
formalized, that is, presented in terms of a set of formal rules,
like those of the previous chapter, explicitly and economically. It
must be clear just what data is accounted for and how it is being
accounted for, just what assumptions are made about the nature
of the language, and just what claims about the structure of the
language are presented. In this sense formal is opposed to informal.
Formal in the first sense does not necessarily exclude
considerations of meaning: this would be impossible and un¬
desirable. Ostentatious attempts to expel considerations of
meaning have usually allowed meaning to creep surreptitiously
back under some other guise. We can see how meaning is
smuggled in if we consider the sort of problem sometimes
presented for analysis to beginning linguistics students. Such
problems often present data from a little-known language which
can sometimes be analysed without knowing the meaning of the
sentences, rather like a puzzle from a Sunday newspaper. Here
is an example from Scots Gaelic (we have omitted glosses to
demonstrate a formal analysis):
12 Bha an cu dubh
13 Bha an cat ban
14 Bha Calum mor
15 Bha an cu sgith
16 Bha Calum sgith
17 Bha Mairi beag
18 Bha an gille mor
19 Bha an cu beag
20 Bha Mairi ban
21 Bha an gille beag
22 Bha an cat mor
23 Bha Mairi beag
Formal grammars 63
We are provided with the additional information that these
strings are all sentences, and that no other word order is
possible for these sentences — the following, for example, are
impossible:
29 Bha an cu mor
D E B A
bha an cu dubh
cat ban
gille sgith
beag
mor
Figure 21
D C A
Calum dubh
bha
Mairi ban
sgith
beag
mor
Figure 22
D F A
E B
cu dubh
bha an cat ban
gille mor
beag
C sgith
Calum
Mairi
Figure 23
Formal grammars 65
Or we can write a little grammar for our data:
30 S —» D + F + A
E + B
F
C
Lexical rules:
D —> {bha}
E -> {an}
etc.
Article/Noun
Proper Noun
Lexicon:
an Art ‘the’
bha VCop ‘was’
cat N ‘cat’
ban Adj ‘white; fair haired (of people)’
etc., etc.
Technical terms
Exercises
The data in this and the following exercise are from Scottish
Gaelic.
Formal grammars 67
1
(a) Group the words into classes: use the class names
Art(icle); N(oun); PN (Proper Noun); VT (Transitive verb);
VI (Intransitive verb); Pro(noun).
3
The following data are from Kwahu, an Akan language from
Ghana:
(a) Group the words into classes: use the class names - Article
(Art), Noun (N), Proper Noun (PN), Verb Transitive (VT),
Verb Intransitive (VI).
(b) Find an appropriate translation meaning for each word
based on the English gloss. Since we are assuming that words
are the smallest constituents of interest to us, you will have to
identify a word like regoro as a member of the class VI and
give it a gloss like ‘is playing’.
(c) There are two types of Noun Phrase (NP) shown in the
data. What are the constituents of these NPs?
(d) Write a grammar for this data.
(e) Using your grammar, draw tree diagrams to represent the
grammatical structure of sentences 1 and 6.
6 Optional and obligatory
constituents
1 Some of these sentences are ambiguous. For example, 2 could be analysed as:
i The dog - bit - the man - in the bathroom
or as: ii The dog - bit - the man in the bathroom
In sentence i the constituent in the bathroom indicates where the man was
bitten, and can be related to sentences like:
iii It was in the bathroom that the dog bit the man
Where the dog bit the man was in the bathroom
Where did the dog bite the man? In the bathroom
In sentence ii the constituent the man in the bathroom is an NP. This sentence
is related to other sentences like:
iv It was the man in the bathroom that the dog bit
Who did the dog bite? The man in the bathroom
We are immediately concerned with the first of these analyses, i. (We return to
the other analysis later.) We also observe that constituents like in the bathroom
do not typically occur in sentences with copular verbs:
but not
15 S —> NP + VP (+ Adv)
VP^ V(NP) (jPPjj
Adv —> PP •
PP-^ Prep + NP
Art + N I
NP
PN J
16 John is running
17 John is running to school
19 John is reading
20 John is reading a book
22
34 S —» NP + VP (+Adv
,, . , , v manner (+Advplace>
(+Adv . )
v time7
NP
Art N PP
Figure 25
76 Part one: Constituent structure
Under this analysis we consider the constituent the man in the
bathroom to be an NP since it has the same distribution as an
NP:
where the constituent the man who was in the bathroom is also
an NP. We defer consideration of such NPs, involving what are
traditionally called ‘relative clauses’, to pages 137-44.
We can account for the structure of NPs like the man in the
bathroom by proposing the constituent structure rules:
NP
Art N PP
the house by the bridge over the river beyond the town
Figure 26
PP
Figure 27
78 Part one: Constituent structure
The rule correctly indicates the optional nature of adjectives,
captures the fact that adjectives ‘modify’ nouns (reflected in a
traditional characterization as ‘modifying adjectives’) and shows
that the scope of the modification is the NP. But as it stands it
does not allow us to account for NPs containing more than one
adjective:
NP
but rather by
47a *A car which is red and [which is] sports {compare 42)
47b *A car which is sports red (compare 46)
NP NP
Art Adj N
N N
NP + VP( +Advmanner)(+Advplace)(+Advlime)
Pred
(NP)
Pred
Manner adverb
Adv„
PP
Place adverb
Adv place
PP
Time adverb
Adv.;
PP
PP —* Prep + NP
NP Art(+Adj)* + N(+PP)
Figure 31 (OP)N —» N + N
Optional and obligatory constituents 81
We conclude the chapter with a brief discussion of syntactic
ambiguity, since this matter has arisen several times in our
discussion, and seems a natural consequence of the
organizational principles of language. We have already noted
that a sentence like:
Figure 32
Figure 33
NP VP Adv
manner
Manner Adverb
V Pred
Adj
I
Figure 35 she looked hard
claim that our grammar can deal with all kinds of ambiguity - it
can only cope with those that arise from labelling or bracketing
or both. Ambiguities such as those in:
fall outside our present scope. We shall try to deal with such
ambiguities by machinery introduced in later chapters.
Technical terms
adverb (of place, time, manner) non-nuclear constituent
ambiguity (of labelling and nuclear constituent
of bracketing) obligatory constituent
basic sentence optional constituent
cycle recursion
modifier scope
Exercises
1 Ambiguity
NP NP
Adj
Adj N N
1 I/agree/with John
2 I/went/to the cinema/with John/yesterday
3 The fifteenth Music Festival/will be held/in the
Assembly Rooms/in May 1979
4 John/went/to Bristol/in 1972
5 Harriet/always/plays/with a rubber duck/in the bath
6 Mary/will write/a letter/to mother/for you
7 Harriet/is/in the bath
8 They/elected/Charlie/president
9 We/sent/a parcel/to Mary/for Christmas
10 We/pierced/the membrane/with a needle
11 They/thought/Charlie/foolish
7 Selection restrictions
BOY, GIRL, CAT, DOG, etc.) has the feature [+animate] and
PICTURE (and other nouns like table, chair,
TYPEWRITER, etc.) has the feature [-animate]. We can now
use this categorization to specify a selection restriction for
FRIGHTEN and ADMIRE in much the same way as we
specified their strict subcategorization. ADMIRE can be inserted
into a structure of the form:
4 ^ p(N[+animate]) NP
5 NP p(N[+animate])
7 man N; [+animate]
PICTURE N; [-animate].
1 butter, and other mass nouns, can sometimes occur in sentences like Our
grocer stocks two butters, French and Danish. But note that in such sentences
butters has the sense ‘kind(s) of butter’. We discuss cases like this in more detail
on pages 242-4. For the present we assume that butter is a mass noun.
2 For any lexeme we have given only one specification. In some cases the
items in question have more than one possible use. Thus man in the sense
specified indicates ‘individual human male’; there is another sense of man as
‘mankind’: this use is [-count] and is not accounted for here. In the entry for
Selection restrictions 89
8 MAN N; [+concrete],[+count],[+animate],
[+human],[+male],[+common]
WOMAN N; [+concrete],[+count],[+animate],
[+human],[—male],[+common]
JOHN N; [+concrete],[+count],[+animate],
[+human],[+male],[—common]
BEAUTY N; [ - concrete],[ - count],[+common],
[—animate]
OIL N; [+concrete],[-count],[+common],
[—animate]
DOG N; [+concrete],[+count],[+animate],
[-human],[± male]
FALL V; _ #; Np(N[+concrete]) _
PRAY V; _ #; Np(N[+human]) _
Np(N[+human])
dog we have specified [±male] to indicate the sense where dog is used to
refer to a canine irrespective of sex. Another sense of dog would need to be
specified as [+male] in contrast to bitch [—male].
3 As with the nouns, the specifications are illustrative rather than exhaustive. A
full specification of the entries would require to account for all possible uses.
Even the examples as they stand need modification in some cases. For example
the entry for marry should indicate that if the subject N is [+male] the object
noun should be [-male] and vice versa. We could use the specification
[a feature], meaning ‘either + or — ’ and the specification [—a feature] to
indicate the opposite polarity. So if [a male] has the value [ + male], then
[—a male] has the value [—male].
90 Part one: Constituent structure
Together these descriptions account for the acceptability or
otherwise of the following:
10a The man/oil/dog fell
10b * Beauty fell {non-concrete subject)
10c The woman/dog is pregnant
lOd *The man/John is pregnant {non-female subject)
lOe *The dog prayed {non-human subject)
lOf *The woman flowed over the beauty {count subject,
non-concrete N in PP)
The examples show the sort of judgements that formally stated
selection restrictions force on us, and bring us back to a
question mentioned at the beginning of the chapter - is
‘figurative language’ to be considered in some way ‘deviant’?
Perhaps what we recognize as ‘metaphorical language’ is
language that ‘breaks’ a selection restriction. But since so much
of our ‘ordinary’ use of language is ‘metaphorical’ we might
question the validity of such an account - it is far from clear
where, or how, to draw the boundary.
The discussion so far has assigned features to nouns on a
semantic basis, in terms of some characteristic of the object, etc.
that the noun in question is typically used to refer to. So, for
example, we have assigned to woman the features
[+animate],[+human],[—male], etc. since this lexeme is indeed
used to refer to ‘animate human females’. We may now observe
that all the features we have discussed have relevance for
grammatical processes of one sort or another. For example, the
pronoun typically used for [—human] nouns is it; the pronoun
for [+human] nouns is he or she depending on whether the
noun in question is [+male] or [—male]. Similarly we note that
[—common] nouns do not usually co-occur with an article: Fido
but not *the Fido, *a Fido, etc. There is a complex web of
co-occurrence restrictions between articles, and nouns
characterized as [±count]. Some of these are illustrated in 11 for
NPs with no article, and with the articles a, the and some, when
pronounced /sm/.
11 [+count] [—count]
singular the chair the butter
a chair *a butter
*sm chair sm butter
* chair butter
Selection restrictions 91
[+count] [-count]
plural the chairs *the butters
*a chairs *a butters
sm chairs *sm butters
chairs *butters
13 ♦
N animate
•
^inanimate
N
human
non-human
etc.; but this will not do since nouns are typically not just
animate or human, but both animate and human etc. Perhaps
rules like 14 might be appropriate:
92 Part one: Constituent structure
14 N
anim
N
N.
man
N anim,hum
• K
N .
anim
N • u
anim,non-hum
15
hum
N
non-hum
N
hum,anim
N,
hum N
hum,non-anim
N
hum,anim,common
N,
hum,anim N
hum,anim,non-common
N,
N
1 anim, hum
Figure 36 N„anim,hum,common
16 NP + VP
V+ NP
Art + N
fN anim
. V
N.
man
MAN N
anim
PICTURE N.
man
frighten V;_NP; N_N .
’ anim
ADMIRE V;_NP; N . _N
’ anim
This grammar produces trees like that shown in Figure 37. The
subject noun is categorized as N. . We cannot therefore
17 S —» NP + VP
VP^ V(+ NP)
NP —> (Art+)N
Let us see how the rules will work. The constituent structure
rules of 17 can generate the tree of Figure 38:
NP
Art N
Figure 39 FRIGHTEN
S
NP VP
Art N V NP
Art N
NP NP
but hardly
even though what was being offered was similar - in the one
case a plate of segmented grapefruit and in the other a plate of
stewed plums. The categorization of nouns as [±count] is not
only to some degree idiosyncratic within a language; it is also
idiosyncratic between languages.
This point, the mismatch between a syntactic and a semantic
characterization, can be made even more clearly by reference to
a language that has a grammatical category of ‘gender’. In French,
for example, all nouns are categorized as being in one of two
classes (with a few exceptions which may be in both classes)
which are usually given the names ‘masculine’ and ‘feminine’. The
grammar needs to know the gender of a noun in order that
appropriate grammatical rules can be applied: for example the
rules of ‘concord’ that ensure that a masculine noun co-occurs
with the masculine form of the article, le, un, etc., and a
feminine noun co-occurs with a feminine form of the article, la,
une, etc. Gender distinctions in French are not typically a
semantic matter, since all nouns are assigned to one gender class
or the other (c.f. le stylo ‘the pen’, but la table ‘the table’) even
when the notion of sex is irrelevant. We could handle this by a
syntactic feature [±masculine], but that feature would hardly be
appropriate for stating selection restrictions. For the correct
Selection restrictions 99
Technical terms
Exercise
You are probably familiar with playground jingles like:
Figure 42
Figure 43
104 Part one: Constituent structure
We can alternatively state the relationship in formulaic terms as:
5 NP — Aux — V— NP2
All the sentences have the same subject NP (the dog) and the
same object NP (the cat). They differ in the internal structure
Relations between sentences 105
Figure 44 Aux V NP
10a The dog may have bitten the cat (but that’s unlikely)
10b The dog could have bitten the cat (but I hope it didn’t)
Such auxiliaries, and others like SHALL and MUST, are usually
known as ‘modal’ auxiliaries (because one of their principle
semantic functions is to mark the ‘modal’ distinctions of
probability, etc. noted above). They constitute a form class
insofar as they are mutually substitutable in a particular verb
group, but no verb group can contain more than one of them:
VP
e.g. (the cat) may have been being bitten (by the dog)
Figure 45
In all cases the first verb in the verb group shows the alternation
in tense, however many items there are in the group. Only this
first position in the verb group is open to this alternation, since
the form of verbs other than the first is determined by what
precedes them. This is most clearly shown in the last two pairs
of examples. In 24a and 25a the first verb in the verb group is
110 Part one: Constituent structure
the main verb itself, and this consequently shows the tense
alternation. In the corresponding passive sentences 24b and 25b
the passive auxiliary is introduced before the main verb: the
passive auxiliary is now the first verb in the verb group, and
consequently shows the tense alternation: the main verb itself
must be in the past participle form, since this form, as we have
seen, is the form that follows the passive auxiliary.
How are we to treat these facts? The description we adopt
(discussed further on pages 207-10) treats tense as a sort of
auxiliary, and, furthermore, as the first auxiliary in the verb
group. This entails saying that this tense auxiliary is not realized
itself as a discrete item, but that its presence is felt as a marker
on the first item to follow it within the verb group. This gives it
a status much like -ing and pp in our description of the
progressive and perfect auxiliaries. It also captures the
generalization that tense is shown on the first member of the
verb group. We must now modify our schematic constituent
structure representation for the verb group from that of Figure
45, to that shown in Figure 46:
VP
VP -> Aux + V
Tense
Figure 46
VP
Aux V
Tense
non-past BITE
VP
Aux V
I
non-past BE
A pp BITE past be pp BITE
is
\/
bitten
A/
was
\/
bitten
26 NP - Aux - V - NP2
Figure 51
Relations between sentences 113
Once again we can generalize to other syntactically similar
sentences:
Figure 52
In English the main verb itself cannot ‘hop’ the subject NP:
there are no sentences like * Left John?, *Leaves John?
have is somewhat more problematical; its syntax varies to some degree from
speech community to speech community. For some
She has a car Has she a car?
are acceptable. Other communities treat have more like a ‘main verb’, which
we discuss next:
X
34b Has John left? non-past have NP PP V
t
36b Will John be coming? non-past Modal NP BE -ing V
Figure 53
Figure 54
Figure 55
39 *John do be leaving
*Do John be leaving?
Figure 56
118 Part one: Constituent structure
Figure 57
Figure 58
passive
t
1
active
affirmative
negative
Figure 59
57 NP - Tense - MV - X<>Tense + DO - NP - MV + X
The following question now arises: in statements like 57, or
the other statements shown in 49-51, are we to suppose that the
structures are simply related, or is the one structure to be
derived from the other? In formulating these rules, we have
supposed that it is simply a relation between two structures: this
has been symbolized by the use of the double-headed arrow
which may be taken to mean ‘any structure of the form found
on one side of the rule can be matched by a structure found on
the other side of the rule’. If you find a structure as shown on
the left, you also find one as shown on the right; and vice versa,
for any structure as shown on the right, there is a corresponding
structure as shown on the left. This is a statement of relatedness.
We can, however, reinterpret such rules with minor modification
as rules of derivation, and symbolize the fact that the rules are
derivational by using a single-headed arrow =>. This we take to
mean that, given the structure on the left-hand side of the rule,
a structure can be formed as shown on the right-hand side of
the rule by performing the changes noted in the rule. Thus in
122 Part one: Constituent structure
Figure 60 (declarative)
Figure 61 (interrogative)
s NP + VP
VP Aux + V (+NP)
NP —» Art + N
Aux —> Tense (Modal) (Perf) (Prog)
as a daughter of S
ii A new constituent, Pass, expanded as be + pp,
is adjoined as a daughter of Aux, and the right
sister of all other Aux constituents
iii by is adjoined as left sister of NP^ to form a new
Figure 62
. Modal
HAVE
SC: X - jense(Tense + Neg) — BE - Y
. Modal.
SA: X - Tense - MV - Y
Relations between sentences 127
52 DO support (obligatory)
SA: X - Tense - Y
SC: X — Tense + DO — Y
i X and Y are any arbitrary constituents or none
(in the case of X), on condition that the left-most
constituent of Y is not a verb, main or auxiliary.
ii do is introduced as a right sister of Tense when
Tense is thus ‘stranded’ with no verb to its
immediate right.
There are a number of small changes in these ‘derivational’
rules as compared with the corresponding ‘relational’ rules in
49-51. Most of them are necessary precisely because these new
rules are derivational, and we must specify the derived con¬
stituent structure in detail. Note that we have also formulated
‘DO support’ as a separate rule, rather than including it in the
‘Negative’ and ‘Interrogative’ rules as previously. This enables
us to generalize about the circumstances that require ‘DO sup¬
port’: whenever Tense is ‘stranded’ - i.e. separated from an
immediately following verb, main or auxiliary - do is supplied
to ‘carry’ the tense marker. Making ‘DO support’ a separate rule
128 Part one: Constituent structure
means we can then use this rule (with some small further mod¬
ification) for other circumstances in which DO occurs. For
example, we find DO in negative imperative sentences:
53a Go!
53b Don’t go!
the time adverbial could occur either at the end of the sentence
(its ‘normal’ position) or at the beginning. A constituent struc¬
ture rule like:
60 S -* NP + VP (+Adv . )
v time
Technical terms
active negative
affirmative passive
aspect passive auxiliary
auxiliary verb perfective auxiliary
base component phrase structure
basic sentence progressive auxiliary
declarative structure analysis
derivation structure change
derived structure syntactic surface structure
DO support tense
interrogative transformation
main verb underlying structure
modal auxiliary verb verb group
Exercises
1 Dative movement
2 Phrasal verbs
3 Tag questions
Tags are constituents like those which follow the comma in the
sentences below; we call the constituent that precedes the
comma the main sentence:
Assume that the main sentence is the basic form, and that a tag
is derived by rule from the basic sentence. Formulate a rule for
the derivation of tags. At this stage ignore sentences that do not
contain an auxiliary verb (i.e. sentences like Mary came), or that
contain an auxiliary verb other than HAVE, BE, WILL,
WOULD, CAN, COULD, SHALL, SHOULD.
Now consider the formation of tags in sentences like:
7 He likes hamburgers,_?
8 Your mother died in 1969,_?
9 You don’t like punk rock,_?
10 John didn’t break the window,_?
Sentences like:
NP VP
PN
VP
Adj
is untrue
Figure 64
Figure 65
6 rumour: N;_S
8 BELIEVE: V; _ NP[S]
T tie woman You saw me with the woman last night is my wife
Figure 66
scWNPs([p™] "X"Y))
i Identify the NP in the embedded S that is
identical to the head.
ii Move this NP to the front of the embedded S.
iii Replace it by the appropriate relative pronoun.
rel
The symbol indicates ‘the appropriate relative pronoun’:
pr°_
who if the NP to be replaced contains a ‘human’ noun; which
for all other nouns. X and Y, as before, indicate any arbitrary
constituents, or none. In the case of ‘subject relatives’, X is null
(i.e. the NP in the relative clause is the first constituent in its
clause so X must be null); in the case of ‘object relatives’, X is not
Embedding and recursion 139
null (it includes the subject NP and the verb at least), but Y
may be null, since the object NP may be the last constituent in
the clause (the object need not, of course, be the final
constituent, as it isn’t in 10: in that case neither X nor Y is null).
Subject and object relative clauses are illustrated in 16. The
reader should try to derive the items in 16 using the rule 14.
Applying rule 14 to the relevant string in Figure 66 gives:
15 Figure 66: the woman (you saw me with the woman
last night) is my wife
Rule 14 i: the woman (you saw me with the woman
last night) is my wife
Rule 14 ii: the woman (the woman you saw me with
last night) is my wife
Rule 14 iii: the woman (iwho you saw me with last
night) is my wife
This produces the desired result. The rule 14 predicts the form
of infinitely many relative clauses:
16a The apples (the apples are ripe)
The apples which are ripe
16b The man (the man lives next door)
The man who lives next door
16c The girl (I love the girl)
The girl who I love
16d The knife (she stabbed her lover with the knife)
The knife which she stabbed her lover with
16e The girl (John gave the book to the girl)
The girl who John gave the book to
SC:
NP (NPs<P - X“Y»
1 We need to include the restriction that this rule applies only to cases where
the preposition is part of a PP in order to avoid producing nonsense when we
deal with ‘phrasal verbs’. Phrasal verbs are items like run up in the sense
‘amass, accumulate’ or put down in the sense ‘kill’. We describe these as
having a structure verb stem + particle. We can then distinguish between items
like up and down when they are used as particles (in phrasal verbs) and when
the ‘same’ items are used in prepositional phrases like up the hill, down the
drain, etc. For example, given the structure:
the cat (we put down the cat last week) was very old
we want to avoid producing:
*the cat down which we put last week was very old
while still allowing for the acceptable:
the cat which we put down last week was very old
The distinction between a ‘phrasal verb’ and a verb + PP string can be
observed in the following-
the bill (John ran up the bill) was enormous run up = ‘amass’
the bill which John ran up was enormous
*the bill up which John ran was enormous
the hill (John ran up the hill) was enormous run + PP
the hill which John ran up was enormous
the hill up which John ran was enormous
Embedding and recursion 141
We can go further still. In sentences 16c,d,e the relative
pronoun can be omitted without affecting the acceptability of
the sentences in question:
18 the girl (who) I love
the knife (which) she stabbed her lover with
the girl (who) John gave the book to
The relative pronoun cannot be omitted in 16a,b:
19 the apples which are ripe (need to be picked)
*the apples are ripe (need to be picked)
the man who lives next door (is the Lord Mayor)
*the man lives next door (is the Lord Mayor)
nor can it be omitted in the NP in 17:
20 The knife with which she stabbed her lover
*The knife with she stabbed her lover.
The general principle which governs the omission of the rela¬
tive pronoun may be formulated as:
SA:np<npsC] -Np-X»
SC: Np(NPs(NP-X))
SC:Np(NPs(Y))
Embedding and recursion 143
I Art + N
30b NP
(np + s
We do, however, have to ‘pay for’ this simplification. To
begin with there is the additional machinery of transformational
rules. We also note that not all adjectives go through the deriva¬
tion proposed. Some do not appear in relative clauses:
and conversely some can appear in relative clauses but not pre¬
ceding nouns:
in place adverbials:
34 You will find your book where you put it down last
night
in manner adverbials:
Technical terms
‘adjective shift’ recursion
complementation relative clause
complementizer relative clause reduction
constituent sentence relative clause rule
creativity relative pronoun deletion rule
embedding subordinate sentence
head matrix sentence superordinate sentence
noun complementation verb complementation
Exercise
The rules for wh- and that relative clauses are slightly different,
and to indicate this we distinguish between a 'Wh-rel rule’ and a
‘That-re\ rule’
See if you can formulate the differences between the two types
of relative clause forming rules by considering the different rela¬
tive clauses you can form from the following underlying struc¬
tures:
1 When John and Mary got back home, they found the
front door had been left open. 2 John accused Mary. 3
She denied it. 4 John asked her to shut it. 5 She
wouldn’t.
Figure 67
S and S
Now this is not the case for all co-ordinate sentences. Consider,
for example, the following:
23 S -*S*
sort (We went to the seaside last Sunday and we played on the
sands and Daddy bought us an ice cream and . . .). This
approach also allows us to treat binding expressions (of the sort
discussed at the beginning of this chapter) as a form of
conjunction, which in many cases they are! But the approach
does have problems. We cannot make distributional statements
about constituent sentences produced by such a rule since the
rule produces no distinct environments we can use. We also
need to postulate some set of rules to accommodate sentential
sequence, and these rules must take account of matters that go
beyond the simple sentence as we have so far considered it.
Rules relating to various matters of word order are taken up again
in Part three.
The arguments in the preceding paragraph lead to the
conclusion that conjoined sentences are not to be considered
part of the grammar at all, but are derived by text formation
rules. This conclusion is not wholly comfortable, but the logic of
the argument seems to force us into this position. It at least has
the advantage that it permits us to adopt the definition of the
sentence with which we began the chapter: the sentence is an
abstract unit, established in order to account for distributional
regularities of its constituents. The question of whether there
are further distributional regularities between sentences in some
larger unit, say the paragraph, is discussed in Part three.
Technical terms
Exercises
1
Make a transcription of the text for publication in a periodical.
You should make sure that your transcription follows the usual
orthographic conventions about punctuation, etc. and that you
write what, in the orthography, are considered to be
grammatical sentences.
2
Make a note of what sort of things you have left out of your
‘cleaned up’ version (pauses, filled and unfilled; repetitions;
false starts; . . .) and of the sort of things you have found it
necessary to add. See if you can formulate these as a set of
instructions to a secretary who was asked to do a similar task.
Morphology
11 Words and morphemes
Hitherto the word has been the smallest constituent with which
we have been concerned. It is clear, however, that many words
are susceptible to further analysis. Thus in the sentence:
the vowels are divided into two or more ‘sets’ and in any word
all the vowels are chosen from one set: Akan and Turkish
are instances. In these cases, however, the criteria for deciding
the extent of the unit over which the rules (of accent placement,
or of vowel harmony, or whatever) hold is not a simple
phonological decision - grammatical criteria also come into
consideration (the affixation of suffixes to a word, for example).
Such criteria, then, like potential pause, are useful indications,
but do not by themselves suffice to identify words.
The most satisfactory criteria are syntactic criteria, among
them the ‘internal cohesion’, and ‘external distribution’ of a
word, and its ability to stand alone as a ‘minimal free form’.
Together these criteria show that a word has a unity that
justifies its treatment as a unit. Consider, for example, the
structure of a word like uninterruptability. It is probably agreed
that we can segment this word as un-interrupt-abil-ity. The basis
of this segmentation is the recognition that each of these
segments can recur in other words, words given a related
meaning by the common segment (note that meaning slips in
here - it is hard to exclude!): thus we find U^-intelligent;
corrupt-ABIL-ITY; stupid-ITY, etc., and the form interrupt can
itself stand as a word. As far as the ‘internal cohesion’ of the
word is concerned, it is not possible to interpolate any other
segments between the segments we have isolated, nor is it
possible to rearrange the order of the segments we have
isolated. In other words the item is bound together into a unit.
This is not generally the case with strings of words - where it is
almost always possible to add new items or rearrange the items
within the sentence and still maintain a grammatical string. We
can see this if we compare black hat (black top hat, hat which is
black, etc.) with blackcap (in the sense ‘type of bird’): and we
can compare blackcap with black cap (black corduroy cap, cap
which is black, etc.).
Similarly in its external distribution a word operates like a
unit. Either the whole word must be moved round the sentence
or none of it can be moved round the sentence - you cannot
move part of a word about. Thus, as the example black hat
shows, each word is capable of a certain amount of independent
movement, but in the case of blackcap either the whole word is
moved or nothing is moved.
These two criteria are reflected in the ability of a word to
Words and morphemes 165
2 John loved Mary once, but he doesn’t love her any more
there are eleven words. We shall use the term word form for
166 Part two: Morphology
this usage: thus we shall say there are eleven word forms in 2.
From time to time it is convenient to make the further
distinction between a phonological and an orthographic word
form. Orthographic word forms, when used for exemplification
are italicized; phonological word forms will be represented in
‘phonemic brackets’ e.g. word forms, /w3d fomz/.
A different usage is illustrated by saying that in 2 loved and
love are different forms of the word love. This use of the term
‘word’ applies when we say we are going to look up the meaning
of a particular word in the dictionary: we do not expect to find
an entry for each of the different inflectional forms such as
loved, loves, loving, etc. We use the term lexeme to distinguish
this usage of the term word. To distinguish lexemes from word
forms we always use small capital letters to refer to lexemes, a
usage silently followed in previous chapters.
The status of these two terms is rather different. Word forms
can, in some sense, be regarded as substantial units, as actually
occurring forms; the words written on this page are word forms.
The notion of lexeme, on the other hand, is an abstract notion.
Word forms like love, loves, loved and loving can all be related
to the lexeme LOVE, but none of them can be considered actu¬
ally to be the lexeme love. If we associate the head word of a
dictionary entry with the notion lexeme, the lexicographer must
choose some word form by which to represent the lexeme in
question; the choice of word form is a matter of convention in
different languages. In English dictionaries, typically, verbal lex¬
emes are represented by the ‘infinitive’ form: i.e. LOVE is rep¬
resented by love. The same is true in French and Spanish, so we
find aimer in a French dictionary and amar in a Spanish dic¬
tionary. In Latin or Greek dictionaries, however, verbal lexemes
are typically represented by the ‘first person singular present
indicative’ form of the verb; thus we find amo rather than amare
(the ‘infinitive’ form) in a Latin dictionary, and cfiZXea) in a
Greek dictionary.
We might also note instances of ‘homography’: when two dif¬
ferent words (= lexemes) are orthographically represented by
the same word (= word form). Thus the same word form mace
may realize either the lexeme MACE (1) with the sense ‘spice’
or the lexeme MACE (2) with the sense ‘staff of office’ - a fact
usually recognized in dictionaries by according each lexeme a
different entry.
Words and morphemes 167
The difference between these two senses of word is clearly at
issue if the question is asked: ‘How many different words are
there in this chapter?’ If we mean word in the sense of word
form, then we count each instance of word forms like is, are, be,
was, were, as ‘different words’, and each instance of word forms
like word as ‘the same word’. If, on the other hand, we mean
word in the sense of lexeme, then all the forms is, are, etc. are
different forms of the same word (= lexeme) BE, and we need
to distinguish between WORD (1) (= word form) and WORD
(2) (= lexeme). It is by no means always clear in word counts
which of the two senses is at issue, but they need to be
distinguished.
There is, finally, yet a third use of the term ‘word’ that it is
sometimes useful to distinguish; it can be illustrated by com¬
paring the forms I wrote and I have written with the forms I
laughed and I have laughed. Viewed as word forms, wrote and
written are different word forms, but laughed and laughed are
instances of the same word form. However, from a different
point of view, we can describe wrote as the ‘past tense of
write’ and written as the ‘past participle of write’ and
analogously, the first instance of laughed as the ‘past tense of
LAUGH’ and the second instance of laughed as the ‘past partici¬
ple of laugh’. Syntactic descriptions such as these can be use¬
ful; they are called morphosyntactic words. Typically, but not
invariably, a morphosyntactic word consists of a lexeme and
some associated grammatical description, as in ‘past tense of
LAUGH’, and there is a direct correspondence between a mor¬
phosyntactic word and the word form by which it is realized, as
in the examples given.
So now we have identified three different senses: in different
circumstances we say that laughed and laughed in the examples
given are the same word (= word form); are different forms of
the same word (= lexeme); or are different words (= mor¬
phosyntactic word)! Unless the context makes it clear which
sense is at issue, we need to make a terminological distinction
between these three senses of word.
This brings us to another difficulty. The forms laughed and
wrote may, as morphosyntactic words, be described as, respec¬
tively, the ‘past tense of laugh’ and the ‘past tense of
write’. And from a strictly syntactic point of view we wish to
be able to describe them in this way. However, whereas laughed
168 Part two: Morphology
may, without disagreement, be segmented as laugh-ed, no com¬
parable segmentation is possible for the form wrote. Further¬
more, in the case of laugh-ed the segment laugh can be iden¬
tified with the lexeme LAUGH and the segment -ed with the
description ‘past tense’. The principle that permits us to do this
is that other word forms can be related to the lexeme laugh;
for example in laugh, laugh-s, laugh-ing we find the same seg¬
ment laugh; and other past tense forms contain the segment -ed,
e.g. kill-ed, walk-ed, attack-ed. This suggests the constituent
structure analysis of laughed shown in Figure 69.
Verb
V Tense
LAUGH past
I
laugh ed
Figure 69
Verb
Figure 70 wrote
V Tense V Tense
1
1
Morpheme: LAUGH past WRITE past
1 1
1 1
Morph: laugh ed wrote
Figure 71
Technical terms
derivational morphology morphosyntactic word
homographs orthographic words
inflectional morphology phonological words
lexeme potential pause
morph realization
morpheme word form
12 Morphemes and morphs
Morphemes
NP + VP
VP^ V + NP
Tense —» I ^aSt 1
1 non-past j
NP^ Art + N
N —» Noun + Number
Number
Lexical rules:
Noun —» {boy, dog, CAT, HOUSE, ■}
The grammatical words are all clearly English - and, the, did - it
is the lexical words that have ‘nonsense’ stems - tove, gyre,
gimble, wabe. Take slithy for instance; it is in the syntactic
position for an adjective (Art Adj N), and it has the morph -y, a
common marker of a derivational process deriving adjectives
from nouns (cf. slime: slimy, grime: grimy, etc.). There are
lexical classes truly open to new membership. On the other
hand it would probably be impossible to interpret ‘nonsense’
where the lexical stems were related to ‘regular’ English
lexemes, but where the ‘grammatical’ words were nonsense.
Morphs
If you check, the allomorphs for the possessive (e.g. wife’s), are
identical to those for plural.
We are thus forced to say that with items like (HOUSE) the
allomorph /hauz-/ is chosen in the environment {_ plural}.
When the selection of the appropriate allomorph is determined
by circumstances which cannot be described phonologically, then
these allomorphs are said to be grammatically conditioned.
Grammatically conditioned affixes in English include the
plural affixes -im and -en in:
kibbutz kibbutz-im
seraph seraph-im
ox ox-en
If this is the case, then /-d/ and /-t/ are in free variation as
realizations of the morphemes past and past participle in
construction with {BURN}.
The grammar may sometimes have a morphemic distinction
when there is no overt marker of this particular distinction in
actual word forms. In such cases a ‘zero’ morph or allomorph is
sometimes postulated. This is usually represented by 0. Zero
Morphemes and morphs 181
allomorphs are often postulated when the structure of a series of
related forms is such that there is a ‘significant absence’ of a
formal marker at some point in the series: e.g., with English
noun plurals we find:
but
We might then say that the form boy represented the two mor¬
phemes {BOY + sing}: and the form boys the morphemes
{BOY + pi}. Now {sing} is represented by the morph 0. Thus boy
consists of the two morphs boy-0, and boys of the two morphs
boy-s. Analogously grouse (singular) consists of the two morphs
grouse-0 and grouse (plural) of the two morphs grouse-0. In the
former case 0 is the invariant morph representing {sing} and in
the latter case 0 is an allomorph of {pi}!
Realization rules
Lexical rule:
2 NS ^ {BOY, cat, bus, grouse, sheep,
WIFE, DWARF, . . .}
/-z/ elsewhere
12 pi /-iz/ in the environment sibilant C_
/-s/ in the environment voiceless C_
/-z/ elsewhere
184 Part two: Morphology
1
2 BUS + pi + poss SHEEP + pi + pOSS
7 /bAs/ -I- pi + poss 5 /Jip/ + pi + poss
12 /bAS-iz/ + gen 12 /Jip-s/ + poss
11 /bAS-IZ-lz/ 11 / fip-s-iz/
(rule 10 cannot apply since the
environment in which it ought
to have applied is gone)
Morphemes and morphs 185
Technical terms
2 singular plural
boy boys
girl girls
NP Art + Noun
Noun N + Number
f sing}
Number
IPI J
Lexical rule:
N -> {BOY, GIRL . . .}
Art Noun
N Number
Figure 72 Figure 73
4 sing pl
man men
mouse mice
goose geese
The analysis of words 189
We call rules like this ‘fusional’: fusional rules have two mor¬
phemes on the left-hand side of the rule matched to a single
morph on the right-hand side. A rule like this seems to capture
well the fact that men is unsegmentable, and that it realizes two
morphemes.
Rules like 7 are no longer simple ‘rewrite’ rules, as defined on
pages 40-3, since there are two items on the left-hand side of
the rule. A rule like this is in fact a transformational rule. We
shall find that morphological realization rules are of a ‘mixed’
nature, but this will not detain us here.
Let us now turn to the singular forms. There are a number of
possible solutions. We can suggest a fusional type of realization
rule here too:
9 N + sing —» N
10 NP -»> Art + N
N -» N (+ pi)
NP NP
N N pi
BOY BOY
Lexical insertion:
N -» {BOY, GIRL, man, mouse, . . .}
The verb forms shown are often called the ‘regular’ forms of the
verb, since these forms are most common, and are used with new
borrowings or coinings. As far as a morphological analysis is
concerned, there are three distinct word forms, which can be
analysed as yawn, yawn-s and yawn-ed. The formal identification
of these morphs can be reinforced by semantic criteria. The forms
12c, 12d are appropriately applied to a situation which happened
at some time previous to the time of utterance, whereas the forms
12a, 12b are more appropriately applied to a situation describing
either a general truth or habit (it is the habit of boys to yawn,
etc.) or possibly to a situation actually happening at the moment
of utterance - rather in the fashion of a commentary.
Let us characterize this distinction as one between past 12c, 12d
and non-past time, 12a, 12b. A morphemic analysis (an analysis
into morphemes) needs to postulate the same distinction, which
we can, following tradition, identify as the category of tense, as
we have already noted.
Now consider the pair of forms yawns and yawn in 12a, 12b.
We have already identified the distinction between boy and boys
as involving the grammatical category of number: we now note
that the distinction between yawn and yawns correlates with this.
We find sentences like 12a, 12b, but we will not find:
Verb Verb
Figure 76 Figure 77
but this is open to the same objection as the comparable rule for
the singular forms of nouns discussed in 8: it misses an obvious
generalization. More realistically we could have a rule for the
lexeme yawn:
17 YAWNyaw/T
194 Part two: Morphology
and then consider realization rules for the grammatical
morphemes. Here a fusional rule may seem appropriate for the
singular form:
but what of the plural form? Neither {non-past} nor {pi} have any
realization. We can have a rule:
19 V + non-past + pi —» V
20 V + non-past —> V
sing —» -s
V + pi -» V
YAWN —> yawn
nHp"8}
V —> V + Tense
Tenser | Past 1
[non-past J
Lexical rules:
V —> {yawn, . . .}
N {boy, girl, . . .}
Art -* the
Subject-verb concord:
Figure 78
NP VP
sing non-past
Figure 79
no particular boy is in the mind of the speaker and any boy will
serve. This characterization suffices for our present purposes, and
we postulate morphemes {def(inite)} and {indef(inite)} to account
for the distinction. What then of the plural forms 24b and 24d?
Consider first the forms 24a, 24b. The article morph is the same
in both cases: the. We encounter the problem discussed with
respect to agreement in the verb: do we wish to analyse the in the
a sentence as ‘the singular form of the definite article’ and the in
the b sentence as ‘the plural form of the definite article’. This
analysis suggests that the forms correspond, respectively, to
morpheme strings {def + sing} and {def + pi}. Alternatively we
can say that the is simply the definite article, realizing the mor¬
pheme {def} and no question of number arises. This seems a more
satisfactory solution since, as before, it leads us to postulate
fewer morphemes that have no overt realization.
In the forms of 24c, 24d, it is possible to argue that the forms a
and some are, respectively, ‘the singular form of the indefinite
article’ and ‘the plural form of the indefinite article’. Evidence for
such an analysis is shown if we compare 26 with:
Article-Noun concord:
sing
SA:NpWindef>-N"[pl
sing sing
Lpl J )
)—N—
SC: NP<Art(indef + Lpl J
NP NP
NP
sing
Figure 82
Lexical rules:
N —> {boy, girl, man, goose, . . .}
V -> {yawn, walk, run, . . .}
Concord rules:
Subject-verb concord:
SI: Np(Art + N + sing) -
Verb(V + non-Past)
SC: Np(Art + N + sing) - _ r , (V + non-past + sing)
Verb
Article-noun concord:
smg
SA: NP(Art(indef) " N Pl
smg sing] x
)-N-
SC: NP<Art<indef - pl Pl V
202 Part two: Morphology
NP VP
Verb
V Tense
YAWN past
| |
(12) (15)
1 1
1 1
some men yawn -ed
NP VP
I I I I
(16) (4) (3) (13) (10) (14)
I I
walk
I
-s
the boy
Technical terms:
agglutinative rules null-realization rules
concord rule ordering
fusional rules tense
number
14 The order of morphs and the
order of morphemes
1 The sentences are represented in the orthographic form. Tone markings have
been omitted, although these are also relevant to a complete description of the
verbal system. This does not affect the point at issue.
206 Part two: Morphology
3 fut(ure) Kofi be-fura ntoma ‘Kofi will put on a
cloth’
4 pret(erite) Kofi fura-a ntoma ‘Kofi put on a cloth’
5 perf(ect) Kofi a-fura ntoma ‘Kofi has put on a
cloth’
The habitual verb form has no affix; there is simply the bare
root jura. For all the other forms there is an affix; it is a prefix in
all cases except the preterite, where it is a suffix. Also note that
all these affixes are mutually exclusive: no form can have more
than one of these affixes - there are no forms *a-re-Jura,
* be-fura-a, etc. It appears that we have here a five-term category,
which we call the category of Aspect. It is clearly most
illuminating to have a rule of the following kind:
7 Preterite hopping:
pret + V -» V + pret
non-past Perf
Figure 86
208 Part two: Morphology
Lexical rule:
Figure 87 V -* {walk, .. .}
8a past + walk
8b past + Perf + walk: past + have + pp + walk
8c past + Perf + Prog + WALK: past + HAVE + pp +
BE + -ing + WALK
8d non-past + Modal + Prog + walk: non-past + will
+ BE + -ing + WALK etc.
To account for the discontinuities we propose a rule:
9 Affix hopping:
Any affix which is found to the left of a verb is to be
moved to the right of that verb. An affix may hop a verb
only once, past, non-past, pp and -ing are affixes; any
The order of morphs and the order of morphemes 209
Note that the first item in the verb group is also the item that
shows tense. Tense and number go together, even in
interrogatives:
19b S A: X - N - pi - non-past - BE - Y
SC: X - N - pi - rr0„co(non-past + pi) - be - Y
Tense
sing
19c SA: X-N — past — BE Y
Pi
sing" sing Is
SC: X - N- BE - Y
Pi J Tensed + pi Y
The summary i-v above is expressed in these rules as
follows, i is shown by the fact that the number morpheme is
adjoined as a sister to tense (and dominated by tense) showing
that the two are cumulated. The generalization is expressed like
this so that in formulating the question rule we can say that tense
hops over the subject NP, and tense brings number along with it
(cf. 14). ii is shown by the fact that modals are specifically
212 Part two: Morphology
NP VP
A A
past neg BE pp Art N Num
Finally we apply the interrogative rule (page 127) and derive the
structure in Figure 92:
Aux NP VP
Al
past neg pi BE
II
DOG pi
I I Ax
pp BITE by NP
Art N Num
sing
Figure 92
affix hopping
cumulation
number agreement
Exercises
1 omu- _C
omw- _V
1 ndigenda I shall go
2 yagenda He went
3 nkyagenda I am going
4 twagenda We went
5 aligenda He will go
6 wagenda You(sg) went
7 baligenda They will go
The order of morphs and the order of morphemes 217
8 mukyagenda You(pl) are going
9 mwagenda You(pl) went
10 tukyagenda We are going
11 baagenda They went
12 nnagenda I went
13 akyarjkuba She is beating me
14 baamukuba They beat him
15 bakyakulaba They are looking at you(sg)
16 yatukuba She beat us
17 ndibagoba 1 shall chase them
18 akyandaba He is looking at me
19 tukyabalaba We are looking at them
20 olitugoba You(sg) will chase us
21 twabalaba We saw you(pl)
22 tulibalaba We shall see you(pl)
23 nnabakuba I beat them
24 mulindaba You(pl) will see me
subject pronouns
in the environment
I
you(sg)
he/she
we
you(pl)
they
218 Part two: Morphology
object pronouns
in the environment
me
you(sg)
him/her
us
you(pl)
(hem
tense/aspect affixes
in the environment
future
past
progressive
Verb stems
in the environment
‘go’
‘beat’
‘chase’
‘see /look
at’
3 Syntactic analysis
Amasela (Thieves)
(a) Make a list of all the verb stems in the data, and gloss each
item (e.g. bona ‘see’). List the stems in the form in which they
occur, or in which you think they would occur, in the simple past
tense form. Do not try to account for forms which are translated
in the free English translation by ‘I am —’, ‘They are —’, ‘I want
—etc.: i.e. forms with the ‘present’ tense (e.g. ndilambile 2,
ndifuna 2 and the forms in 22-4).
(b) Diagram the structure of past tense verb forms in terms of the
morphs that obligatorily and optionally occur. Make a list of
subject and object morphs, and gloss them in some way so that
the relevant concordial relationships are clear.
(c) Diagram the structure of those verb forms that are apparently
(judging from the glosses provided) used to refer to future events
etc. Note that there are two types of form (e.g. in sentence
beginning line 16). Describe their distribution.
(d) There appear to be three different types of locative
expression (they translate such phrases as ‘on the road’, ‘in front
of the wagon’, etc.). Diagram their structure. (Note the following
nouns: umzimba ‘body’; isihlalo ‘seat’; indlela ‘road’.)
(e) Make an analysis of the sentence Uya kukuphakamisa . . .
aqhube inqwelo (lines 16-17) into morphs. Separate the morphs
in each word by hyphens (e.g. u-dyakalashe) and identify each
morph (e.g. Personal name class prefix-jackal). Ignore the word
sakhe.
15 Lexical morphology
Adj
un- Adj
Adj
A -ist
Figure 93 un real
I I
ist ic
when this is not in fact the case. Thus we have aggression, but no * aggress-, butler
and vicar, but no *buttle or *vic (though in fact all of the starred forms can be
found — the latter two in novels by P. G. Wodehouse). The derivational process by
which they are assumed to have been formed is called ‘back formation : the
analogy of think-.thinker suggests the comparable *vic:vicar.
226 Part two: Morphology
separate. The grammatical rules are part of the grammar, and it is
not relevant to the grammar whether a given lexeme is a root or a
derived form. It seems more appropriate to put the lexical
derivation rules in the lexicon.
Thirdly, some of the rules in 1 involve recategorization. Thus,
la, lb, ld-g take a stem of one category and produce a lexeme
that is assigned to another category: so the ‘class changing’ rule
la derives nouns from adjectives. Others of the rules, like lc, lh,
are ‘class maintaining’: the derived category is the same as the
original category. We do not in general wish to have rules like
this within the grammar that change items from one major lexical
category to another.
A fourth reason has to do with the semantic properties of rules
such as those in 1. A derived lexeme generally has some semantic
relation to the lexeme from which it is derived, usually through the
root which both lexemes share. It is not clear, however, what
generalizations can usefully be made about which aspects of the
meaning of the stem are reflected in the derived form - compare
forms like boy '.boyhood; knight'.knighthood; sister'.sisterhood
etc. Similarly the derivational affix often has some general
meaning, but any statement of the meaning of an affix will have
to be stated in extremely general terms, to which there are
exceptions. For example, nouns formed by rule lh are typically
abstract {man'.manhood) the connotations of -hood being ‘state,
quality or rank’ (Partridge 1958, 848), but Partridge also
notes the “resultant secondary senses, ‘concrete instance’ -
as in falsehood, and, from the nuance ‘rank’, ‘collectivity’
as in brotherhood and sisterhood”, A similar example is
remit'.remission'.remittal, noted earlier in the chapter. The two
noun forms clearly share some aspect of the meaning of the
corresponding verb, but the particular aspects of shared meaning
differ in the pairs remit'.remission and remit'.remittal. Such
changes of meaning are more appropriately accounted for in the
lexicon than in the grammar.
The examples considered so far have been examples of word
formation, where a lexical formative has been affixed to a lexical
stem. Another common source of new lexemes is composition or
compounding, illustrated by words like bookmark, teatime,
halfback. The distinction between compounding and derivation
rests on the fact that each part of the compound is itself a lexical
stem, and is typically a free morph - as is the case with book,
Lexical morphology 227
mark, bookmark. By contrast, formatives are always bound
morphs.
In compounding there is often a considerable problem about
word division, and orthographic conventions offer little help:
sometimes compounds are written as a single word (waterfall),
sometimes hyphenated (water-drop), sometimes as two words
(water bottle) - the examples are all from the Shorter Oxford
English Dictionary. A recent history of English (Strang 1970, 39)
treats as ‘morphological units’: middle distance, market research,
cost effectiveness, standing ovation. The criteria used have been
discussed (pages 162-4): typically no further item can be inserted
between the two elements; they cannot be transformationally
separated; one element cannot be pronominalized or be taken as
the antecedent for pronominalization; etc. However, there is
little clarity as to what counts as a compound word and what is a
modifier-head construction where the modifier is a noun. Thus it
is curious that in the Shorter Oxford English Dictionary, of the
forms field mouse and harvest mouse only the latter has an entry
(under harvest)\ Compounding is an extremely productive source
of new lexical items in English, even though its boundaries are
unclear.
As a final consideration, we may ask how far one would wish
to carry the process of derivational analysis within words. Clearly
the basis for analysis is the fact that words share common
phonological material and a common element of meaning. Thus
strawberry is analysed as straw-berry on the analogy of dew-berry,
logan-berry, rasp-berry, etc. One can easily justify the berry
morph, and in the case of strawberry, the straw morph: logan-
and rasp- are more difficult and it would perhaps be best to
consider loganberry and raspberry as simple non-derived forms.
Another problem area involves ‘phonaesthemes’ (formatives with
phonaesthetic properties) in onomatopoeic words. Some analysts
have wished to make an analysis of such words. Thus Bloomfield
(1933, 245) sees ‘intense, symbolic connotations’ associated with
the ‘prefixes’ and ‘affixes’ in such words as:
Exercises
Compare this definition with the definitions given for some of the
parts of speech in classical Greek by Dionysius Thrax, a Greek
grammarian of the first century BC - he is often regarded as the
forerunner of the western tradition of grammatical description
(see Robins 1967, 33):
3 Various derivational affixes are also limited to noun forms - like the -ness in
goodness, helplessness, etc. But since -ness, and others like it, is a lexical formative
and not an inflectional affix, we do not consider such items further here.
Form classes and grammatical categories 235
just, be compared {He only pities the poorest, cf. * He only pities
the most man). Nouns cannot be intensified or compared.
A second solution is to say that POOR is ‘basically’ an
adjective, but can be ‘recategorized’ as a noun in certain types of
structure. A drawback of this solution is that we must then say
that some adjectives can recategorize easily (e.g. POOR,
beautiful, good), that others do not recategorize at all
(e.g. major, ablaze), and that yet others recategorize in
some circumstances (e.g. BLACK, PINK). This seems to involve
adding a statement in the lexicon for each adjective to indicate
the ease with which it can be recategorized.
A third solution is to assert that POOR is an adjective, but that
in certain structures additional material is ‘understood’; with this
solution the poor might derive by a transformational deletion rule
from a structure like those who are poor or those people who are
poor. This solution is attractive in that it sets out a semantic
reading of the usage of POOR concerned, but it has problems if
we extend the principle widely: I want the black might be related
to I want the black dress, I want the black ball (in billiards), I want
the black man, etc.: the ‘understood’ items depend on the context
of utterance.
A final solution is to say that in the poor are always with us
POOR functions as the head of an NP, and to relax our rules on
the structure of NPs to allow adjectives in certain circumstances
to take on this syntactic function. This solution involves
distinguishing the syntactic function of an item (as head of an
NP, etc.) from its syntactic class (as adjective, etc.). This final
solution seems attractive in the case of items like CONCRETE,
noted above, where, in a structure like a concrete floor, it
functions as the modifier of a noun head. Many items we wish to
class as nouns can occur as modifiers (a picnic basket, a bus
station, iron railings, etc.); it does not seem sensible in these cases
to identify either two items (PICNIC(I) an adjective, and
picnic(2) a noun) or to say that picnic has been
recategorized.4 This solution is also attractive in the case of
structures like the down line (a preposition modifier), the very
man (an adverbial modifier). The discussion seems to suggest that
4 This solution is not, however, open to the sort of grammar that we have been
considering so far: we have no satisfactory way of identifying grammatical
‘functions’ like modifier. The grammar is set up to account for the distribution of
categories. We return to this problem on pages 254-60.
238 Part two: Morphology
5 The situation is different in other languages where the verb stem can carry
both tense and aspect categories - see for example the brief exemplification of
Akan on page 60. Such languages often do not have a category of auxiliary verb;
Akan doesn’t.
Form classes and grammatical categories 239
into a group but not *he gathered the man into a group), etc. The
category of number of English controls verb concord and, to a
limited extent, concord within the NP. We saw on pages 186ff.
that co-occurrence restrictions and facts like concord were impor¬
tant in establishing the category of number. Other categories may
be ‘covert’, in that no term in the category can be identified with
a formal marker: on the other hand co-occurrence restrictions or
other grammatical phenomena enable us to establish the exis¬
tence of the category. Thus the French category of gender is a
covert category: nouns, which are assigned to gender classes, are
not themselves usually marked for gender, but the gender is clear
from co-occurrence with, for example, article forms. There is no
overt marker of gender in a noun like chaise but it must co-occur
with the article la rather than le: although the category of gen¬
der is inherent in the noun, the actual formal marking of gender
occurs not on the noun but on the article which it is in construc¬
tion with. Covert categories are no less important in a description
than overt categories.
This particular distinction also brings us into direct confronta¬
tion with problems concerned with the relation between
‘notional’ and ‘formal’ categories. This can be illustrated by con¬
sidering the category of number in English. At first sight it seems
a fairly straightforward matter. The grammatical category of
number is an overt category with two terms, singular and plural,
shown by the alternation between pairs of forms like cat: cats.
The grammatical category correlates, more or less, with a
notional category which we may suppose also has two terms,
‘oneness’ and ‘more-than-oneness’ - we use cat to refer to a
single ‘cat’, and cats to refer to more than one ‘cat’. So far as it
goes this is correct, and the names given to the grammatical
category reflect these semantic facts. Note that the particular dis¬
tinction drawn in English is not universal; we have already noted
that some languages, classical Greek and Arabic for example,
have a three-term number category, with an additional term,
‘dual’, used to refer to things that typically go in pairs (arms, legs).
English has no grammatical category of dual. English can and
does have the means to refer to pairs of items - for example the
lexical items both, neither -but the distinction is not ‘gram-
maticalized’, realized as a formal system in the grammar, but
is rather ‘lexicalized’.
We return to the question of number in English. It can be
242 Part two: Morphology
argued that, prior to any singular:plural distinction, a massrcount
distinction is needed, the number distinction of singular:plural
only applying to count nouns. Consider the following. Count
nouns in general are used to refer to discrete objects that
can be counted - thus two chairs, twenty cigarettes, a hundred
pipers, and so on. Mass nouns, on the other hand, are character¬
istically used to refer to items perceived not in terms of individual
members, but in some mass terms: items like water, sand, butter,
ink, etc. The count:mass distinction is covert, in that nouns in
English are not marked in any way to show their membership of
either sub-class. The distinction can, however, be established on
the basis of the co-occurrence relationships of the two classes of
noun (see discussion in pages 90-1). Mass nouns do not co¬
occur with numerals {*one sand, *two waters, etc.) nor in the
plural (*butters, *inks etc.); they do not co-occur with the indefi¬
nite article (*an ink, *a water), but do occur with the determiner
some (pronounced /sm/) {some butter, some ink). Count nouns
are the opposite: they occur with numerals {one boy); in the
plural form {boys); with the indefinite article {a boy); but not, in
the singular, with /sm/ {*sm boy). We also observe that, for the
purposes of concord, both subject-verb concord and concord
within the NP, mass nouns operate like singular count nouns
{This butter is . . .; * These butter are . . .). There are, of course,
idiosyncracies: a few mass nouns are plural in form and take
plural concord {clothes, guts, suds, etc.); a few are not overtly
plural but take plural concord {gentry, cattle, clergy, etc.); and so
on. These idiosyncracies apart, they offer no particular problems.
The count:mass distinction may be held to be a reflex of a
notional distinction which we call a distinction between ‘individu¬
ated’ and ‘non-individuated’ referents.
The descriptive problem begins to arise when we find nouns
that we might wish to regard as ‘basically’ mass nouns occurring
with the syntax of count nouns:
4 The scrum was not producing enough ball for the backs
5 He is collecting worm for his fishing
6 This room smells of cat
Form classes and grammatical categories 243
vowel change
-5
plural — more-than-
> individuated
6 There are some cases where past tense and past time do correspond: I can
speak French quite well now: I could speak German when I was younger, but this
is not the regular pattern for modal verbs. There is an argument that some
so-called past tense forms among modal verbs are better thought of as simply
separate items. An example is should when used in the sense of ‘duty’, e.g. You
should always give up your seat on the bus to an old lady. Replacing should by
shall produces a sentence of doubtful acceptability! The interested reader is
referred for further discussion to Leech (1971) and Palmer (1971).
Form classes and grammatical categories 247
Next consider sentences with a non-past verb form. They can
sometimes be found with a ‘present’ time reference: Dalglish
shoots and it’s a goal, but, as we have already observed, this is
not the usual way to refer to actions taking place at the time of
utterance. More frequently the simple non-past verb form is used
in a ‘timeless’ sense - Honesty is the best policy, War solves no
problems', to refer to ‘habits’ - I cycle to work every morning, I
always get drunk at Hogmanay; to refer to ‘states’ - I belong to
Glasgow, I speak Chinese', and so on. Non-past verb forms may
also be used to refer to future events - I leave for Paris in the
morning; and indeed to past events (the so-called ‘historic present’)
- Earlier this morning I come into the kitchen and what do I find?;
and past states of affairs - Shakespeare draws his characters from
real life. The correspondence between ‘present time’ and the
non-past form of the verb is even less straightforward than the
correspondence between ‘past time’ and the past form of the verb.
What, then, do we make of characterizations like ‘timeless’,
‘habit’, ‘state’ and so on, characterizations frequently met with in
grammars. There are, to be sure, occasions when the
correspondence between some such category and a term in the
category of tense is reasonably direct: thus ‘timeless’ is typically
realized by a non-past verb form (God was good; Christmas was
on 25 December; Cocks crowed at dawn seem anomalous if they
are to be understood as statements of ‘general truth’ which hold
regardless of time!) Similarly ‘past instantaneous actions’ are
usually realized by a simple past verb form (/ bought a coat this
afternoon; I gave my wife a diamond ring for Christmas). But
usually the relation is less direct, ‘present habits’ usually correlate
with a non-past verb form, but past habits frequently occur, not
with a simple past form, but with a form of USED TO (/ cycle to
work every morning; I used to cycle to work every morning).
Similarly, as we have observed before, ‘present instantaneous’
actions are often realized by the progressive rather than the
simple non-past verb form (I am typing this sentence now). The
relationship between notions like ‘habit, etc. and some formal
overt grammatical category is often indirect, but such notions can
play an important part in controlling other features of the
sentence. Thus, for example, ‘timeless’ statemeftts usually require
a noun of general reference as subject, and are restricted as to
the type of adverbial modifiers they permit: Cocks crow at dawn
can be held to be a timeless statement, but My favourite red
248 Part two: Morphology
rooster crows at dawn most mornings cannot. Similarly ‘past
habits’ impose restrictions on adverbial expressions - one can
hardly say */ used to cycle to work this morning\
Notions like ‘timeless’, ‘habit’, etc. seem to have relevance for
more than the single category of tense. Grammatical features that
can be correlated with such notions extend throughout the sen¬
tence and may be relevant for grammatical selection at various
places. A valuable discussion of some of these notions is Crystal
(1966) to which the reader is referred (see also Leech (1971)).
The difficulty may be summarized thus: categories like
‘timeless’ ‘habit’ ‘unreal condition’, etc. have syntactic
implications in relation to such matters as co-occurrence
restrictions relating to adverbs etc.; on the other hand there is no
single overt category to which they can be tied in any
straightforward way. There is a further problem with respect to
the notional categories - it is not clear how many such categories
we need to postulate, or what the distinctions are between them.
For example, we have suggested a category of ‘state’ - but this is
clearly not a unitary category at all, there are all sorts of states.
We might recognize: inherent states (I am a man); resultant
states (My coffee is cold (now, but it was hot ten minutes ago));
transitory states (It is fine now (but will be raining again in ten
minutes); and so on. It is far from clear that reliable distinctions
can be drawn clearly between them.
This is at least true for English where such categories are not
relatable to a formal distinction in the grammar. In terms of our
former discussion, they are not ‘grammaticalized’. The situation is
different in some other languages. In Finnish the distinction
between ‘transitory’ and ‘inherent’ states is reflected in a
difference in the case form adopted by the noun. In Akan the
distinction between ‘states’ and ‘actions’ is reflected in the
existence of a special ‘stative’ verb form, open only to verbs that
describe states; the distinction between ‘inherent’ and ‘resultant’
states is typically marked by different aspect markers on the verb.
As far as English is concerned, it does not seem profitable to
set up categories like ‘timeless’ as grammatical categories, on a
par with the grammatical category of tense - though attempts
have been made. It would seem more appropriate to account for
such distinctions in terms of a model of description like that
hinted at on page 245, but we shall not pursue this further here.
Form classes and grammatical categories 249
Technical terms
closed category lexical category
collective noun lexical word
count noun mass noun
covert category open category
form word overt category
full word part of speech
grammatical category recategorization
grammatical word
Exercises
In the grammatical analysis of languages words are assigned to word
classes on the formal basis of syntactic behaviour, supplemented and
reinforced by differences of morphological paradigms, so that every
word in a language is a member of a word class. Word class analysis has
long been familiar in Europe under the title "parts of speech’, and since
medieval times grammarians have operated with nine word classes or
parts of speech: noun, verb, pronoun, adjective, adverb, preposition,
conjunction, article and interjection. (R. H. Robins, General Linguistics,
Longmans, 1964)
1
Can you think of some of the principal syntactic environments in
English in which you would find members of the classes usually
named noun, verb and adjective?
2
Can you describe some of the principal morphological charac¬
teristics of these word classes?
To what word classes (in the list given by Robins above) would
you assign the words in the following and why?
4
You will find that the membership of some classes is entirely
English, while that of other classes is partly English and partly
invented. Which classes are open to invented words and which
are not? Why do you think some classes have no invented words?
Part three
Functional relations
-
'
17 Syntagmatic and paradigmatic
relations in syntax
1 Other terms that relate to the same area are structure and system (cf. Aber¬
crombie 1967), chain and choice (cf. Halliday 1963). These relationships are very
general, and can be applied at all levels of linguistic description: they apply
equally to phonological and semantic descriptions as they do to syntactic ones. We
shall, however, only concern ourselves with such relationships in the grammar.
254 Part three: Functional relations
2 It was fashionable at the time for trees to be rooted in the ground rather than
for them to depend from an S node, as is more fashionable today: either way the
information is the same.
260 Part three: Functional relations
particular tree. Such statements of dependency relations are lost
in some more recent descriptive approaches, as they are to a
large extent in earlier transformational grammars.
marks an ‘endocentric’
(unilaterally dependent)
construction
Figure 95
In sentences like
Paraphrases like:
relates to 4.
In English, while adjectives precede the noun, there are also
ordering restrictions on adjectives themselves. Thus, for example,
we will find a nippy little red sports car, but hardly *a red little
nippy sports car. The restrictions in this case relate to sub-classes
of adjectives which can to some extent be defined semantically -
see the exercise on page 48. Sub-classes defined in terms of order
are known as order classes. We noted (pages 73-5) that adverbs
also fall into order classes, though restrictions there are less
rigorous.
11 Gyinamoa ketewa bi
cat small a a small cat
Onipa kesee no
man big the the big man
13 Ofie no ho
house the exterior outside the house
PP^NP^ ^ ^et)^pPreP)pp
Ahina no mu
pot the inside in the pot
opono no so
table the top on the table
me ponkb my horse [_ ~ _ ~]
4 High tones are marked with an acute accent; low tones are unmarked.
Tone-bearing units are; every consonant vowel sequence, and every consonant
and vowel left over (tw is. phonologically. a single consonant; compare sh in
English). Thus Kofi has two tone bearing units, and ponkS has three (po-n-kS).
etc. High tones are realized at a higher pitch than low tones but in a sequence
HLH the second high tone is usually at a slightly lower pitch than the first. The
pitch pattern for the examples is as shown after each example, except that this
‘lowering’ effect is not represented.
266 Part three: Functional relations
genitive
Nsa tumpan beer bottle [_ _ ]
esiam kotokuo flour bag [_ _ ]
adnominal
Nsa tumpan bottle of beer [_~_]
esiam kotokuo bag of flour [_ _]
17 An iolair mhor
the eagle big the big eagle
An coineanach beag
the rabbit little the little rabbit
Am fear beag
the man little the small man
A’ chaileag mhor
the woman big the big woman
5 The variant forms of the article depend on the initial consonant or vowel of
the noun stem they precede.
Syntagmatic and paradigmatic relations in syntax 267
Prepositional phrases in Gaelic
Anns an sporran
in the purse in the purse
(Prep
NP
(Det
NWW
Aig a’ chladach
at the shore at the shore
Air a’ chreig
on the rock on the rock
Tha cu dubh aig Calum, ach tha cat ban aig Mairi
Is dog black at Calum but is cat white at Mary
Adj Art N
Buyiik bir ev
big a house a big house
Sizler igin
you (pi) for for you
25 Miiduriin odasi
director his-room the director’s room
(genitive)
Kizlann odalan
girls their-rooms the girls’ rooms
{gen. plur.)
28a S —> NP + VP
28b VP —» V + NP
29a S —» NP + VP
29b VP —> NP + V
35 S —» NP + VP
VP NP + V
6 There is also the problem that we can find sentences like puellam amat ‘he
loves the girl’, where no separate word is identifiable as the subject. Since the
Latin verb is marked for ‘person’ (amo ‘I love’, amas ‘you love’, amat ‘he loves’,
etc.) the subject is not usually realized as a separate constituent when it is ‘pro¬
nominal’. We do not consider this complication further.
Syntagmatic and paradigmatic relations in syntax 273
constituent structure terms on any language (as by the use of
rules for Gaelic and Latin like those suggested above), but is this
legitimate or appropriate?
A final comment on word order is in order. There appears to
be a tendency in languages for certain types of ordering
restrictions to occur together. In an influential article Greenberg
(1963) writes:
Linguists are. in general, familiar with the notion that certain
languages tend consistently to put modifying or limiting elements before
those modified or limited, while others just as consistently do the oppo¬
site. Turkish, an example of the former type, puts adjectives before the
nouns they modify, places the object of the verb before the verb, the
dependent genitive before the governing noun, adverbs before adjectives
which they modify, etc. Such languages, moreover, tend to have post¬
positions for concepts expressed by prepositions in English. A language
of the opposite type is Thai [or. as we have seen in this section. Gaelic]
in which adjectives follow the noun, the object follows the verb, the
genitive follows the governing noun, and there are prepositions. The
majority of languages, as for example English, are not well marked in
this respect . . .. More detailed consideration of these and other
phenomena of order soon reveals that some factors are closely related to
each other, while others are relatively independent.
Linkage
7 The notion derives from Langacker (1969), who formulates the relation
more precisely. The interested reader is referred to this article for further
discussion of this interesting area of English grammar.
Syntagmatic and paradigmatic relations in syntax 275
S,
S,
S,
S2
39 After John! came into the room, he! took off hisj hat
40 After hej came into the room Johni took off hisj hat
41 John] took off hisj hat after hej came into the room
is ill formed since John does not command he. (Both 42 and 43
are, of course, well formed if he and John are not understood to
be co-referential.) Note that in co-ordinate structures like that
illustrated in Figure 98 forward cross-referencing is possible, by
generalization i; but since neither NP commands the other,
backwards cross-referencing is not:
44a John, came into the room and he, took off his hat
44b *He, came into the room and John! took off his hat
53 puellam amat
girl he loves he loves the girl
is well formed. In such a case we say that the verb has ‘deictic
reference’. This may be to an NP elsewhere in the linguistic
context - in a preceding sentence perhaps - or to an individual in
the non-linguistic context. In those languages in which verbs are
marked in this way, intransitive verbs may, of course, form a
complete single-word sentence - this is the case with many
modern European languages, like Italian. (This causes problems
for a constituent structure grammar of the sort we examined in
Part one.)
We now turn our attention to ‘concord’ or ‘agreement’. Two,
or more, constituents are said to be ‘in concord’ when they are
both, or all, marked for the same grammatical category. Thus in
English demonstratives and the head noun are said to be in
concord within the NP: this book, these books', that book, those
books. The singular form of the demonstrative can only co-occur
with the singular form of the noun, and the plural form of the
demonstrative with the plural form of the noun - there are no
NPs like * these book. In such constructions one constituent is the
‘controller’ of the concord (in the case illustrated above it is the
head noun), and the other constituents are ‘in concord’ with the
controller: so we say that demonstratives in English concord in
number with the head noun within an NP.8 The reasons why the
head noun in English is held to be the controller were explored
on pages 193-6.
8 It is possible to take a different view. We have taken the view that number is
a category of the noun in English, and that other constituents are in concord with
the head noun for number. We might instead assert that number is a category of
the NP as a whole, and that all relevant constituents within the NP must be
marked for this category. To some extent these different views can be accommo¬
dated in different rules. Thus a rule like:
Nnipa no ye kesee (men the are big) the men are big
67a A-li-gi-goba
she (sc. woman) will chase it (sc. chicken)
67b A-li-gu-goba
she (sc. woman) will chase it (sc. snake)
67c Gu-li-mu-goba
it (sc. snake) will chase her (sc. woman)
and so on.
Finally, we discuss a case where the system of concord and
cross-referencing can be used for a particular communicative
effect. When the order of sentence constituents is SVO we have
seen there is no object pronoun within the verb word. Now note
these sentences, where this basic word order is disturbed: pro¬
noun referencing within the verb allows the speaker and his
hearer to keep track, as it were, of ‘who is doing what to whom’.
The English translations are an attempt to indicate the emphasis
etc. that these sentences carry (small capitals indicate stress in
English):
284 Part three: Functional relations
68a Omu-kazi a-li-goba en-koko (SVO)
the woman will chase the chicken
Technical terms
agreement exocentric
bi-lateral dependency government
command linkage
concord marker
controller (of concord) mutual dependency
co-ordinate dependency mutual exclusion
co-reference paradigmatic
cross reference pronominal cross-reference
deictic reference reflexive
dependency syntagmatic
endocentric unilateral dependency
Exercises
These two exercises illustrate concord systems in two languages,
Luganda and Gaelic. Both build on previous exercises: Luganda
on pages 215-17 and Gaelic on pages 67-8.
1 Luganda
All the strings in any one group of sentences have the same
structure, indicated at the head of the groups. All the strings are
morphologically analysed. The numbers 1,2,3 correspond to
classes 1,2,3 in the previous exercises; sg = singular and pi =
plural. As before the noun word can be analysed as consisting of
prefix + stem, the form of the prefix depending on the class of the
Syntagmatic and paradigmatic relations in syntax 285
stem. Adjectives, Demonstratives etc. all bear a prefix concording
with that on the noun stem. The verb also, where appropriate,
has a prefix concording with the subject noun. Fill in the matrix
provided.
Pi
2sg
Pi
3sg
Pi
2 Gaelic
(b) How many gender classes are there in Gaelic? Assign the
Nouns to your gender classes.
(c) In the data given which word class inflects for gender?
Syntagmatic and paradigmatic relations in syntax 287
(d) You will discover that inflexion for gender (as illustrated in
the data) involves changing the initial consonant of some words.
This process is generally known as lenition. Orthographically
lenition is often marked by ‘adding an h’ (e.g. ban:bhan).
Phonologically lenition is manifested in various ways. In the data
the correspondences are as follows - the orthographic forms are
shown first (and in italics), the phonological realizations are
shown in phonemic brackets:
(e) Describe the rule for gender concord within the NP.
(f) What is the rule for concord in these sentences between the
subject noun and the adjective?
On the basis of your analysis to earlier questions, analyse the
following sentences:
(h) Draw two tree diagrams for the final sentence which will
show how the ambiguity arises.
18 Processes and participants
action neutral
agent directed patient
John beat his wife
The cat chased the dog
The vandal slashed the priceless painting
The cat has scratched me
I painted the sitting room
Figure 99
292 Part three: Functional relations
and no further characterization seems necessary; we have noted
that we can describe sharp in 2 as an [attribute].
These observations are summarized in 9-13: we refer to such
characterizations as propositional structures.
22 What happened?
Thus:
Thus:
Thus:
but hardly:
as in:
but not:
We characterize 38 as
40 neutral action
patient inchoative
descriptive
action
action directed
state inchoative causative
descriptive descriptive descriptive
(= 10) (=40) (= 9)
a RIPE RIPEN RIPEN
WIDE WIDEN WIDEN
b YELLOW YELLOW YELLOW
COOL COOL COOL
c TORN TEAR TEAR
CLOSED CLOSE CLOSE
d MOLTEN MELT MELT
ROTTEN ROT ROT
e SHARP — SHARPEN
MOIST — MOISTEN
f LARGE — ENLARGE
BOLD — EMBOLDEN
g PASSIVE — PASSIVIZE
BEAUTIFUL — BEAUTIFY
h DEAD DIE KILL
HIGH RISE RAISE
i — VANISH —
Figure 100
2 This fact may lead one to question the analysis of the passive adopted so far.
Note that the ‘short’ passive form, where the agent is deleted (The shirt was torn {by
John)) is identical to the adjective form. It is usually held that the adjectival and
passive forms can be distinguished by the possibility of inserting an adjective mod¬
ifier in the one but not the other: thus, the shirt was rather torn but *the shirt was
rather torn by John.
3 The sentence The knife is sharpening is not typically found in the inchoative
sense ‘The knife is becoming sharper’. Note that we can find sentences like The
knife sharpens easily. Jespersen (1927) describes such sentences as ‘medio-
passives’, intermediate between an active and a passive use. They are typically
understood in a sense like ‘I find it easy to sharpen this knife’: i.e. a sense involving
an understood [agent]. Such sentences usually require an adverbial expression.
We will not consider them further here.
298 Part three: Functional relations
47 neutral action
patient inchoative
descriptive
4 We may also observe that the attribute tends to denote a ‘result’ rather than a
‘state’. This is particularly noticeable if we consider such sentences with the perfect
verb form: My tea has got cold implies that it is now cold, but once was not cold -
such sentences are sometimes said to involve a ‘resultant state’ (a state reached
after some inchoative process), in contrast to a simple ‘state’, as in the tap water is
cold, where one might suppose either that it never was hot, or that the speaker is
not concerned to make this implication. The sentence the tap water has got cold is
appropriate if the speaker refers to the ‘hot’ tap which is now running ‘cold’ as the
‘hot water’ is no longer ‘hot’, or if the water is colder than usual. This is
perhaps why sentences like the ice has got cold are anomalous, since there is an
apparent and curious implication that ‘the ice’ was once ‘not cold’.
Processes and participants 299
as the [state] sentence corresponding to the English translation given. In this lan¬
guage an [inchoative] sense is realized, much as in English, by the progressive verb
form:
In this respect Akan is a ‘synthetic’ language in a way that English is not: since both
the Akan examples involve intransitive verbs,.
300 Part three: Functional relations
55 What the sun did was make the apples become ripe
6 Both tendencies are very common in English, and may be attested in a much
wider range of examples than we have space for. Thus, for example, there is a
paraphrase relation between the complex expressions in the left-hand column
below, and the corresponding single verbs in the right-hand column.
The process shown is still extremely productive, as can be seen from sentences
like:
In a sentence like:
or
The derivational relationships that can be established are various, and work both
as a ‘verbalizing’ process (e.g .fix with a nail - nail) and as a ‘nominalizing’ process
(e.g. batter - give a battering to). For an interesting and wide-ranging discussion
of such examples see Liefrinck (1973).
7 This feature is even more noticeable with the analytic expressions mentioned
in the previous note. There are no synthetic expressions that can correspond to
‘poke with the forefinger’; ‘travel by the nine o’clock train’; ‘fix with a four inch
rusty nail’; etc.
302 Part three: Functional relations
The problem that examples like 55 pose for the analysis
adopted hitherto is that such sentences clearly involve
embedding. An analysis sometimes suggested looks like:
64 (Sun CAUSE (apples BECOME (apples BE ripe)))
or indeed, if we wish to indicate, the action nature of the
sentence:
65 (Sun DO (sun CAUSE (apples BECOME (apples BE
ripe))))
A formula of this sort quite neatly captures the relationships we
have been discussing, since the successive bracketings represent
the [state] proposition ((apples BE ripe)); the [inchoative]
proposition ((apples BECOME (apples BE ripe))); the [causative]
proposition; etc. We can then suppose that the minimum
amalgamation of the various elements of the representation
would involve the most analytic form - perhaps:
66 The sun did make the apples come to be ripe
(if this is acceptable!) - and the maximum amalgamation of the
various elements results in the most synthetic form:
67 The sun ripened the apples
Such an analysis obviously has its attractions, and many of the
structures we discuss can usefully be examined in this light: some
indeed involve embedding more obviously than the structures we
have been considering.8 We will not, however, pursue such
8 Such analyses also raise questions. For example, how widely can the para¬
phrases involving become, get, make, cause be applied, and what restrictions
are there on such paraphrases? One example will suffice. We have analysed sen¬
tences like the following as containing an [agent] participant:
Furthermore, the paraphrase with make only seems to apply felicitously when we
are dealing with the indirect agent:
Processes and participants 303
analyses further here since our purpose is to take a more
straightforward and taxonomic look at some propositional
structures in English and classify verbs in terms of the
propositional structures, they can enter.
We now turn to some further propositional structures, which,
for reasons of space, are discussed in less detail. We begin with:
68 John had a book
69a Mary gave John a book
69b Mary gave a book to John
Again note a distinction between a [state] process 68, and an
[action] process 69. The [state] process is further characterized as
[possessive], for obvious reasons; and the [action] process ^s
[directed] and [causative], in the senses already discussed.9
As to the participant roles involved, we say that in both
sentences a book realizes a [neutral] role. In 69a John realizes the
participant role of [goal], the book changes hands from Mary, the
[source] of the book, to John, the [goal]. We also say that Mary
realizes an [agent] role, since she is the actor responsible
for the transfer. This description contrasts with the description
appropriate for a sentence like:
If we have:
One reason why vanish is not used as a transitive verb may be that it involves
indirect, rather than direct agency. After all, it is ‘the rabbit’ which ‘does the
vanishing’! A possible answer is to make further subclassifications of the partici¬
pant role [agent], but it is not clear how far this process would have to be taken, or
even if there would be an end to it! We shall continue to recognize a single partici¬
pant agent.
SELL BORROW
LEND RENT
HIRE HIRE
RENT
N St D
GRAB
GET
Some of the verbs that can occur in these structures are set
out in Figure 101.11 Some are in pairs (BUY : SELL;
BORROW: lend) that contrast as to whether they have [agent,
source] or [agent : goal] subjects; some (e.g. take) can occur
in either structure; and others (e.g. GRAB, present) can only
occur in one or the other structure.
This analysis can be extended to cover a number of other
verbs, but a problem is that [neutral] participants are sometimes
obligatorily marked with prepositions: so, for example:
[ St LP A Ac N/P LG A Ac N/P LS
PUT
PLACE
TAKE
Figure 102
293). We will see later (see 109) that sentences like John is sitting
down have two senses: one is a [state] sense (in the state of being
sat down) as is required in the present examples: the other an
[inchoative] sense (in the process of sitting down), which we
discuss later. The other remark we may make is with respect to
the specification [Lgoal] (locative goal) and [Lsource] (locative
source). These specifications remind us of the close connections
between [possessive] and [locative] propositions. Semantically,
the relevant constituents are as much [goal] and [source] here, as
they were in the [possessive] sentences, and some verbs can
enter both [locative] propositional structures and [possessive]
propositional structures:
For now we need merely note that there is some justification for
an apparently similar analysis.
Another set of [locative] sentences, that once again show a
similarity to [possession] propositional structures, can be
illustrated with:
This implication may account for the fact that fill, which
necessarily implies completion, can only occur in a sentence of the
form 102b:
It does not however explain why some verbs do not have any
particular implications associated with either order:
PILE INSCRIBE
STACK A Ac N/P(with) LG
DAUB FILL
PAINT COVER
SPRAY
12 Reflexive structures are those where the agent of the verb carries out the
action of the verb upon himself. This is overtly shown in sentences like John hurt
himself, John killed himself, etc., where the constituent himself is described as a
reflexive pronoun. There are a few verbs in English that permit the reflexive pro¬
noun to be deleted, and yet sentences with these verbs are understood reflexively:
John shaved, John washed, etc. In this latter sense we describe sentences like John
sat down as reflexive. In English such verbs do sometimes appear as overt reflex¬
ives: thus we find Sit yourself down, The man came into the room and sat himself
comfortably in an armchair. We may also observe that in some languages such verbs
are often syntactically ‘reflexive verbs’ cf. French, se raser ‘to have a shave’,
S’asseoir ‘to sit down’.
Processes and participants 313
sentences there is also the possibility of not only an [Lgoal] but also
an [Lsource]; and the locative participant is not obligatory.
120a John pushed the car from his house to his garage
120b John swam from Dover to Cap Gris Nez
1 A Ac 1(LP) 2 A Ac (LG)
l(LG)(LS)
JUMP DESCEND
WALK ENTER
RUN DISAPPEAR
SKIP
LEAP
3 A Ac (LS) 4 N Ac LP
DEPART LIVE
LEAVE STAY
EMERGE
* *
ROLL ROLL
SLIDE SLIDE
FALL DROP
DROP PUSH
DRAG
SHOVE
Examples
Figure 104
314 Part three: Functional relations
This sentence, however, poses an analytic problem. John may quite appropriately
be analysed as realizing an [agent] role. The horse may also appropriately be
analysed as realizing a [patient] role (the object, etc. affected by the action). In this
case, since it is the horse that does the jumping, it should perhaps also be con¬
sidered an [actor]. This suggests we should distinguish between the [agent] (the
instigator or initiator of the action) and the [actor] (the performer of the action).
It might further be observed that for many of the verbs of motion shown in Figure
104, a description as [factor] rather than as [agent] may seem appropriate. The
problem with jump may be more appropriately solved by considering it to realize
an embedded proposition.
Processes and participants 315
Our sentences are once more related as [state] to [action]. The first
two sentences we may describe as involving [identification]: John
is identified as the person who occupies a certain position, or plays
a certain role, that of chairman. The second set of sentences all
describe an action that can cause such a state.
Let us look first at the sentences 128: it is suggested that these
are [identification] sentences. In order to discuss some of the
peculiar characteristics of such sentences we can best compare
them with sentences like 2 (the knife is sharp) where we were
dealing with the attribution of a quality to an object; in the
particular case of 2 we were concerned with the attribution of
‘sharpness’ to ‘the knife’. Here we are concerned with the
identification of ‘John’ as filling the particular role of ‘chairman’.
The distinction between [attribute] and [identification] can be
seen more clearly in a slightly different example:
130 describes my wife; 131 identifies her. Note that 131, but not
130, reasonably answers the questions:
we might find:
A Ac N/P Ro A Ac N Att
ELECT CONSIDER
NOMINATE THINK
CHOOSE ESTEEM
APPOINT
state action
inchoative causative
Examples
Figure 106
[state] verbs, the other two columns [action] verbs with the syntactic
consequences described earlier in the chapter. The [state] and
[inchoative] columns involve one or two participants, neither of
which is [agent]; the [causative] column always introduces a third
participant, which is always [agent]; this too has syntactic
consequences. We can also make some generalizations
about the order of constituents in active declarative sentences.
The verb is always second constituent. There is a hierarchy
among the roles in terms of their ability to occur as subject,
object, etc. The hierarchy is: A:D:N: etc. (where etc. represents
the other roles). Thus, if there is an A it is subject; if there is no
A, then D is subject; otherwise N . . . etc. Similarly in sentences
with an A subject, N takes precedence over other roles as object.
Stated like this, the hierarchy is too crude (and subject to a
number of exceptions), but the notion of a hierarchy seems evi¬
dent, and is also reflected in other languages that can be analysed
in similar terms.
The symmetry of the figure is also somewhat deceptive, and
only seems to apply systematically in the cases noted, and in a
few others. Many propositions do not lend themselves to a com¬
parably neat classification, for example the verbs of motion dis¬
cussed in 117. These do not seem to correlate, in any very straight¬
forward way, with either a [state] or a non-embedded [causative]
proposition. In some cases we can postulate correlations like:
146 He is running
M P
V agent patient
A A
Prep NP Prep NP
M p
past
Figure 109
S instrument M P
Prep NP V patient
/\
0 the door past OPEN
IA Prep
I
with a key past OPEN 0 the door
NP
patient
/\
Prep NP
Figure 113
Figure 114
Figure 113 does not meet the S A. In the same spirit we can derive
and block the following active and passive pairs:
Technical terms
analytic; circumstantial roles; incorporation; proposition;
propositional nucleus; propositional structure.
Process terms
descriptive, possessive, locative, identification, state, action,
inchoative, directed, causative
Exercise
Subject
A distinction is frequently drawn between the ‘grammatical’ sub¬
ject (characterized by grammatical considerations, such as being
the controller of number agreement), the ‘logical’ subject
(characterized by syntactico-semantic considerations - in sen¬
tences with an [agent] NP this is usually held to be the logical
subject) and the ‘thematic’ or ‘psychological’ subject (character¬
ized by textual considerations - ‘this is what the sentence is
about’). These can be illustrated in the sentences la, b, c where
G,L and T indicate respectively the grammatical, logical and
thematic subjects:
3 It is raining
The main verb concords in the singular with the dummy subject
it. It does not, however, have the full range of syntactic possi¬
bilities of a full subject - questioning is impossible; no sense is
made by asking:
5a *What is raining?
5b *What is undeniable that Edinburgh’s New Town is
magnificent?
Sentences like these are called ‘existential’ because they are typi¬
cally used to assert the existence of something. We call this use of
there the ‘existential’ there, distinct from another use of there in
sentences like:
2 The total distribution of existential there is 'fuzzy'. It occurs with the locative
copula BE, and also with verbs like:
Nor is it exactly clear how far this construction can be extended. The following
seem only marginally acceptable with the existential there:
Another item that operates rather like existential there in some constructions is
here'.
Like existential there, this item is usually unstressed and reduced phonologically. It
needs to be distinguished from a ‘locative’ here:
3 As we have remarked before, this volume does not attempt to present a full
account of the formal machinery involved in a transformational grammar. For a full
discussion of this transformation the reader is referred to one of the books listed on
pages 386-7.
336 Part three: Functional relations
cross-refers to John, and another where him refers deictically to
some other individual in the context (see pages 276-7). Let us
suppose that 25 is related to the underlying structure:
him can only have one reading, with deictic reference. It cannot
cross-refer to the subject of expected. But the sentence:
has the other reading: i.e. John is understood not only as the
subject of expected but also as the subject of be chosen. There is,
however, no overt subject present. For the purposes of discussion
we represent this situation like this:
37 Down comes the flag, off goes the gun and away go the
boats
Object
The grammatical object, like the subject, is realized by an NP. In
active declarative sentences with unmarked word order four
grammatical features characterize the object: i it directly follows
the verb; ii it is not in construction with a preposition; iii it can
become the subject of the corresponding passive sentence; and iv
it is an obligatory constituent with transitive verbs.
The most clear-cut cases of objects are those constituents
traditionally referred to as the direct or affected object. These are
NPs that realize what we called (page 290) [neutral, patient]
participant roles in two place propositions where the verb is a verb
of directed action, causative or non-causative, and the other
participant, which must become subject in active sentences is
described as [agent],
SHOOT may occur with two oblique objects, or with a direct and
an oblique object. The semantic effect may be so great here that
the reader may be disinclined to treat all three sentences as
deriving from the same propositional structure.
Indirect object
We now turn to ‘indirect objects’: their status is very ambiva¬
lent. The term is used when a verb is followed by two NPs,
neither of which is associated with a preposition. In these
structures the first NP is the indirect object, and the second the
direct object:
Here the direct object directly follows the verb; what was the
indirect object is now introduced in a prepositional phrase. If the
direct object immediately follows the verb, then the other NP
must be introduced by a prepositional phrase"' - there is no
sentence:
In such cases the paraphrase with to seems preferred to the structure involving IO
and DO: doubtless in order that the semantic relations should be clearly marked.
Further observe that if we pronominalize the DO, then only the first of the
following sentences is grammatical:
344 Part three: Functional relations
a [comitative] in:
are possible. If we pronominalize both NPs then, if both are animate or both
inanimate sentences like-
*John gave it it
*John gave her him
do not seem acceptable. If however one NP is animate and the other inanimate,
then we can have:
and whichever order is used the animate is understood as the IO and the inanimate
as the DO!
Subjects, objects, complements and adjuncts 345
6 All sorts of problems arise in this area if we try to passivize indefinite N Ps.
Thus:
A book was given to Mary by John
seems intuitively less acceptable than:
That book was given to Mary by John
Here we deal only with definite NPs. Indefinite NPs as subjects are discussed on
pages 370-1.
Subjects, objects, complements and adjuncts 347
Complement
Traditional grammars distinguish between a number of different
complement types.7 The names given to them, like the names given
to different types of object, relate to the propositional roles that
they realize. In two place sentences, the primary distinction is
between ‘attributive’, ‘identity’ and ‘locative’ complements: we
discuss each in turn.
The italicized constituents in 87 are attributive complements, so
called because they describe the class membership of the subject
noun, or ascribe an attribute to it:
7 Sometimes all NPs that follow the verb are known as complements. In this
usage, what we have called the ‘direct object' is called an ‘extensive complement’,
to distinguish it from the ‘intensive complement’, which relates back to the subject.
We do not follow this usage.
The term complement is also applied to the sentential objects that are associated
with particular verbs. Thus in the sentence John believed that he was clever the
constituent that he was clever is a sentence complement. The description of that as a
‘complementizer’ (cf. page 134) derives from this usage.
Subjects, objects, complements and adjuncts 349
92 Mary is in bed
This can cause, and has caused, translation problems: in a Bible translation, is
the copula in God is love to be translated with ye (has the attribute) or ne (is to
be identified as) ?
We should also observe that in this language we also find:
Adjuncts
Subjects, objects and complements form the nucleus of a sentence.
They are nuclear in at least two senses, both of which are
complementary. They are the constituents which, in constituent
structure terms, are either obligatory or are introduced by an
expansion of the VP, and hence relevant to strict subcategoriz¬
ation. They are also to be identified with nuclear participants
in the sense discussed in the preceding chapter: many of the names
given to different types of subject and object reflect this.
All other sentence constituents we call adjuncts. Adjuncts are
usually adverbials, whether they are adverb phrases, prepositional
phrases, adverbs or subordinate clauses of time, place, manner,
etc. that distributionally function like adverbials. They are
typically optional sentence constituents, and have a degree of
mobility within the sentence denied to the nuclear constituents.
Adjuncts are clearly a rather ‘mixed bag’, in that syntactically
there are numerous subclasses which have different and over¬
lapping distribution, and they fill a variety of semantic roles, as
354 Part three: Functional relations
can be seen by consulting the discussion of adverbs in any standard
grammar of English - for example Quirk et al. (1972).
Conclusion
In the preceding chapter we characterized sentence constituents in
terms of their syntactico-semantic function within a sentence as
[agent], [patient], and so on. We suggested that a propositional
structure characterized in these terms is an abstract structure
which could be realized by any one of a number of actually
occurring sentences. A given propositional role may occur in a
number of syntactic positions within the sentence without affecting
the way in which the role is characterized, though there will be
other syntactic phenomena that reflect the different sentence
positions the role occupies. We also noted that the
syntactico-semantic characterization can be used to control various
grammatical features, like the ability of some roles to occur with
the progressive auxiliary, its ability to occur in imperative
sentences and so on.
In this chapter we have looked at the functional roles of subject,
object and complement, and at the various syntactic and semantic
properties that can be associated with these functions. Of
particular interest has been the various circumstances that permit
an NP to take on the function of subject, object, etc. From a
transformational point of view, deriving the various different
sentence orders from a single underlying structure, the discussion
may be seen to consider the ways in which sentences can be
provided with subjects and objects.9 Suppose, for example, we
establish a hierarchy of functional roles in outline like this:
9 The transformational account can of itself only deal satisfactorily with the
actual formal operations of providing subjects and objects, etc. It does not handle
the semantic consequences of these operations very satisfactorily, unless additional
interpretive machinery is provided somewhere in the total description to take
account of the semantic consequences of the operations. As we have seen, these
vary from verb to verb and may sometimes be considerable.
Subjects, objects, complements and adjuncts 355
110 John gave the book to Mary (oblique object)
John gave Mary the book (indirect object)
Mary was given the book by John (subject)
Raising produces:
Technical terms
subject - grammatical, logical, thematic
object - affected, cognate, of concern, direct, effected, factitive,
indirect, oblique, of result
complement - attributive, identity, locative, nominal
adjunct
existential sentence
raising
20 Theme, rheme and end focus;
topic and comment;
given and new
1 The term end-focus is taken from Quirk et at. (1972). Their use of the term is
derived from the fact that, in spoken language, the unmarked position for the
intonation centre in an English sentence is the last lexical item in that sentence.
then the sentence is taken to be in some sense marked - the effect is often
emphatic or contrastive. We do not discuss spoken language, except incidentally,
and use the term end-focus simply for the last relevant sentence constituent.
Theme, rheme and end focus 359
2 The usage we are concerned with here is the non-passive one illustrated in
40. Sentences like these offer some analytic interest: although a sentence like 40a
appears to contain a passive verb group, we note the preposition at rather than by.
We can also observe that the item excited here operates more like an adjective
than a ‘true’ passive since we can modify it with ‘intensifiers’ etc.:
59 Mary, I proposed to
60 That soup, I find totally disgusting
61 The kittens, we drowned
75 Up jumped John
where the heavy direct object moves to the end of the sentence.
Or again:
100a Go away!
100b Shut up!
Topics
It is appropriate to complete this chapter by returning briefly to
the notion of topic. The discussion must be brief since a full
examination of the issues involved leads to a consideration of the
structure of text as a whole, and this is not the place for such a
discussion.
Of all the notions discussed topic is the most difficult to come
to grips with. We have suggested that we can view the topic as
being ‘what the sentence is about’, the ‘perspective from which
the sentence is viewed’, etc. In many simple sentences we can
identify the topic by asking what is the implicit request or
question which the sentence would be an appropriate answer to.
Thus, for example we might identify ‘Edinburgh’ as the topic in a
sentence like:
Theme, rheme and end focus 377
111 Edinburgh is
or:
But this seems to introduce three topics, each in turn topic for
one of the succeeding clauses separated by semi-colons. We can
resolve this difficulty by supposing that the sentence could be
dissolved into independent simple sentences (which would
involve some amendment to the text and would destroy its
stylistic characteristics!) each answering one implicit question
(What do scientists mean by fitness? What do scientists mean by
evolution? etc.) We then have the difficulty of identifying an
appropriate topic for the final clause in 113: perhaps it answers
the implicit question, ‘What else can you inherit?’ But this does
not seem helpful, since the function of this sentence is further to
exemplify what is meant by ‘inherit’. The second sentence, 114,
also presents a problem. It seems better to regard both of these
3 The quotations here and in examples 116-118 and 120-121 are from
P. B. Medawar, The Future of Man (1960).
Theme, rheme and end focus 379
and so on. Note that this set of questions refers as much to what
we might call the rhetorical structure of the paragraph as to the
structure of individual sentences. Insofar as it relates to rhetorical
structure, it helps account for a number of facets of sentence
construction, notably the distribution of the binding expressions
noted on pages 149-50.
This approach to the identification of topics may assist in
untangling some of the mysteries of word order. We have already
noted that what is topic is frequently also what is thematic, but
this statement needs to be qualified. The thematic element may
relate to the topic of some unit larger than the sentence (as is
perhaps the case when binding expressions are thematic - they
often identify the function of the sentence (for instance, thus, in
conclusion, etc.)). Equally the thematic element may have
Theme, rheme and end focus 381
nothing to do with the topic, but be some other element of the
message that the speaker wishes to foreground.
Concluding remarks
Technical terms
cleft sentence comment left dislocation
given left-movement rules
‘heavy’ NPs new
382 Part three: Functional relations
Exercise
Each of the following two texts contains much the same
propositional matter; the propositions follow each other in the same
order. Each text too exhibits thematization devices of various sorts.
Identify the types of thematization operations involved. Account
for the fact that while the text A seems to be fairly coherently
structured, text B is decidedly odd.
Introduction
We have not discussed many issues concerned with the nature of
language in general; the reader is directed to Sapir (1921),
Jespersen (1922) and (1929), Bloomfield (1935), Langacker
(1968), Nash (1971) and the introductory chapters of books like
Lyons (1968), Hockett (1958).
Part one
The study of constituent structure (Chapter 1) and of form
classes (Chapter 2) is so basic to any approach to syntax that all
introductory books discuss it. Bolinger (1968), Gleason (1969),
Hockett (1958), Lyons (1968), Palmer (1971), and Robins
(1964) - consult the indexes for the relevant pages - are among
those we have found the most useful. Each has a slightly different
presentation of essentially the same view of constituent structure
that we take in this book. Householder (1972) is a useful
collection of articles, many of which bear on these questions.
While the view of constituent structure expressed in this book is
representative of the views most commonly held in contemporary
linguistics, there are ‘schools’ of linguistics that take a somewhat
different position: we may mention three - ‘Tagmemics’ (see
Cook (1969), Longacre (1964)); ‘Scale and Category grammar’
(see Sinclair (1972)); ‘Systemic grammar’ (see Berry (1975), Muir
(1972)).
Lyons (1968) contains a good, though sometimes difficult,
account of the matters discussed in Chapters 3 and 5-7. The most
interesting discussion of these questions is to be found in works
on Transformational Generative grammar. As noted in the
introduction, this book does not present a fully formalized
account of such a grammar, though many of the ideas it presents
Further reading 387
Part two
The view of morphology presented here derives in the main from
Lyons (1968). A comprehensive and useful discussion is found in
Matthews (1974). The introductory books noted in Part one can
be consulted with profit, but the terminology differs to some
extent from author to author.
Form classes and grammatical categories (Chapter 16) are
discussed in the introductory books. A useful discussion of form
classes in a number of different languages is in Lingua (1967).
Part three
For the subjects discussed in Chapter 17 see particularly Hockett
(1958), Lyons (1968), Palmer (1971), and Robins (1964).
On ‘Processes and participants’ (Chapter 18) see particularly
Brown and Miller (in press), Fillmore (1968), Halliday (1970).
Liefrinck (1973) contains an interesting discussion of some
problems in this area. The works on Tagmemics cited earlier
draw together notions of constituent structure and process and
participants; a comprehensive account is Longacre (1976).
For the matters discussed in Chapters 19 and 20 an interesting
non-technical discussion is Jespersen (1929). Halliday (1970) is
also very approachable. There is some discussion in Lyons
(1968).
Exercises
The following contain useful collection of exercise materials:
Gleason (19556), Langacker (1972), and Nida (1971).
References
count (v. mass), 88, 90-1, 96-7, feature, 86 ff., 289 ff.; syntactic,
242-3 91, 245
covert (v. overt), 240-1 form, bound, 176, 227, 232
creativity, 146 form, free, 176, 226, 232;
cross-classification, 55, 88 minimal, 164—5
cross-reference, 274-7, 281-4, form, word, 166-7, 176
336-7; pronominal, 274-8, form class, 32-9, 60, 231-49, 253
280—4 formation rules: text, 152; word,
cumulation, 210 223 ff.
cycle, 76, 136 formative, lexical, 222
fusion, 189
dative, 304 ff., 338; movement of,
130, 343-7 Gaelic, 62 ff., 232, 266-8, 286-7
daughter, 28 gender, 98, 241, 279, 280
declarative, 112 given, 359-60, 375-6
definite (v. indefinite), 199 goal, 304, 339, 344
deictic reference, 278, 282, 336 government, 256
dependency, 254-60; bi-lateral, grammar: case, 322; formal, 40-7,
255-6; co-ordinate, 258; 60-6; generative, 45;
mutual, 255-6; relations, 154, transformational, 122-9
254-60; unilateral, 257 grammaticality, 45
derivation, 43, 121-3
distribution, 23 ff., 34, 40, 60, head of construction, 137, 237,
164, 233-5 254
do support rule, 116, 127-8 heavy NP. 372-3
domination, 28 hierarchies, 88, 320, 322, 339,
341, 354; see also structure
elision, see ellipsis homography, 166
ellipsis, 151, 237, 243, 336,
359-60, 376 identification, 316, 348-50
embedding, 30, 134-46 imperative, 128, 326, 374
emphasis, 128, 358-9 incorporation, 299
end-focus, 358, 371-3 inchoative, 295 ff., 311, 315
endocentric, 257 infix, 177
entry, lexical, 22, 40-1, 55, 89, insertion, lexical, 43, 94, 96, 97
136, 321 instrument, 139, 293, 322, 338
environment, 34 intensifier, 79, 236
etymeme, 228 interrogative, 112-16, 212-13,
etymology, 228 373-4
exclusion, 258
expansion, 23, 41 labelling, 27, 33
expression: binding, 150, 156, language, figurative, 86
375; level of, 10 left-movement rules, 364, 367-8,
extraposition, 372 369-70
Index 393