The Comprehensive Categories of Life
The Comprehensive Categories of Life
net/publication/242449142
Article
CITATIONS READS
0 1,437
1 author:
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by Stephen William Wood on 22 August 2014.
STEPHEN WOOD
21B Gwendolen Avenue, Putney, London SW15 6ET
[email protected]
06/03/2005
A second comes into relation with a first, and a third mediates between
the two. The first is the beginning; the second is the end. The third is the
process, the journey from one to the other. ‘… the whole organism of
logic may be mentally evolved from the three conceptions of first,
second, and third, or more precisely, An, Other, Medium’ (Peirce in
Hoopes, 1991: 184). ‘The starting point of the universe, God, the
Creator, is the Absolute First; the terminus of the universe, God
completely revealed, is the Absolute Second; every state of the universe
at a measurable point in time is the third’ (Peirce in Hoopes, 1991: 192).
‘First and Second, Agent and Patient, Yes and No, are categories which
enable us roughly to describe the facts of experience, and they satisfy the
mind for a very long time. But at last they are found inadequate, and the
Third is the conception which is then called for. The Third is that which
bridges over the chasm between absolute first and last, and brings them
into relationship’ (Peirce in Hoopes, 1991: 190). Thirdness is the
maturity that denies neither freshness nor experience and incorporates
both into its own habits of wisdom and thought.
3. KOESTLER’S EXAMPLE
Arthur Koestler gave an early account of hierarchy theory in The Ghost in
the Machine (1967). A journalist and acclaimed novelist, Koestler also
published in experimental psychology. In The Ghost in the Machine, he
attempted to find a third way between Gestalt psychology and
Behaviourism. The Gestalt school looked for the monads of experience,
wholes that could not be further broken down. Behaviourism divided all
interaction into dyads of stimulus and response. A conversation, for
example, can be reduced to a chain of mutually determining
stimulus/response units.
Koestler has drawn attention to the interpretant and the whole network of
other signs that bring meaning to the conversation and make it alive for
its participants.
4. LIFE = SIGN = MIND
Or, the Difference between a Thermostat and a Living Cell
Cells have the ability to move towards or away from light, to sense and
avoid heat, and to move towards sources of food. These responses are
called taxes. What is their significance?
In each cell, there is a web of molecular interactions that gives the cell its
life. This dynamic web is the way the cell makes itself, perpetuates itself
and defines itself, i.e. creates its own boundary. This is the autopoietic
organization of the cell (Maturana and Varela, 1987: 43-47).
Different substances enter into the life of the cell in different ways.
Heterotrophic organisms, such as the bacterium Escherichia coli, obtain
energy from external sources of food. Phototrophic organisms, such as
the alga Chlamydomonas, obtain energy from light. E. coli swims
towards high concentrations of glucose, a molecule on which it feeds.
Chlamydomonas orientates itself in the direction of blue-green light, but
not to red light, which it is unable to utilise.
1 m
In the slime mould Physarum (Maturana and Varela, 1987: figure 20),
spores grow into flagellate cells when conditions are moist, but into
amoeboid cells when conditions are dry. The coupling with the
environment involves different structural changes depending on the
external trigger. When food begins to run out, the cells aggregate. Their
cell membranes break down and they form a single plasmodial mass.
Here we have coupling not only with the environment, but between the
cells themselves. Structural changes in one cell – movement, dissolution
of the cell membrane – must be synchronised with similar changes in the
other cells. Here we see the birth of a new level of organization. A cell
is a first-order unity, which maintains its own boundary and undergoes
exchanges across that boundary. Metacellulars, such as Physarum, are
second-order unities. Here structural transformations of the cells are
coordinated into an ontogeny of the whole.
This taste for the monad has influenced the classification of other groups,
for example, the whales and the birds. Carolus Linnaeus, the father of
modern taxonomy, placed birds as one of five divisions of animals. The
whales he isolate in a separate order of mammals, the Mutica. (He was
unaware that they could sing.)
A preference for dyadic relations led naturalists to say that humans are
more perfect than chimpanzees or gorillas. Indeed, the whole of creation
was arranged into a ladder of perfection, from the lowliest amoebae to the
most elevated humans – white, European males, of course. This language
of higher and lower still persists, for example, in the distinction between
lower vertebrates (fish, reptiles and amphibians) and higher vertebrates
(birds and mammals).
1. Monadic: ‘X exists’
2. Dyadic: ‘X is related to Y’
3. Triadic: ‘X is more closely related to Y than either is to Z’
The monadic and dyadic relations listed hardly qualify as the basis of
classification. Any two organisms can be related in some way. Only
when we introduce a third do we have a classification. Classifications of
more than three organisms are to be composed of a number of triadic
relations. Nelson and Platnick’s cladogram isolates this triadic aspect of
a classification: for an example, see figure 6.
‘See the figure [figure 7], where I have drawn the termini as self-
returning roads, in order to introduce nothing beyond the road itself.
Thus, the three essential elements of a network of roads are road about a
terminus, roadway-connection and branching; and in like manner, the
three fundamental categories of fact are, fact about an object, fact about
two objects (relation), fact about several objects (synthetic fact)’ (Peirce
in Hoopes, 1991: 182-3). Peirce’s fundamental categories are equivalent
to the three founding relations of classification (Wood, 1996, 2002),
namely features, similarities and homologies. Features are firsts; they
exist in one species considered alone. Similarities are seconds; they
relate one species to another. Homologies are thirds; they show that two
species are more closely related to one another than they are to a third.
The third species reveals the thirdness of the sister species; it provides the
context within which the other two find their relationship.
G H
A
B
Root
C
D
F E
In the derivative stage (figure 11), different specimens are brought into
relation. Hence the features of the oviraptor Caudipteryx and living birds
signify that the two are similar in an object ‘having true feathers’. The
interpretant here is the whole data matrix, which described the
distribution of similarities across the whole study group. This character
matrix forms the basis of the cladistic analysis of relationships, often
performed with the aid of computerised algorithms.
In the general stage (figure 12), the analysis of the data matrix reveals
that certain similarities function as homologies at some level of
generality. In other words, these similarities identify sister groups
relationships and define taxa within the classification.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I thank Basil Hiley for his comments on an early exposition of Peirce’s
ideas. Louis Gidney and Adam Parker Rhodes gave useful feedback to
my talk at ANPA 26.
REFERENCES
Burn, D. M. (1980, ed.) The Colour Encyclopaedia of the Animal
Kingdom. Peerage.
Capra, F. (1996) The Web of Life: A New Synthesis Of Mind And Matter.
HarperCollins.
Darwin, C. (1859) The Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection,
or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life.
Murray.
Darwin, C. (1872) Expression of the Emotions in Man and Animals.
Murray.
Esposito, J. L. (1980) Evolutionary Metaphysics : The Development of
Peirce's Theory of Categories. Ohio University Press.
Haeckel, E. (1866) Generelle Morphologie der Organismen: Allgemeine
Grundzüge der organischen Formen-wissenschaft, mechanisch
begründet durch die von Charles Darwin reformirte Descendenz-
Theorie. 2 vols. Reimer.
Hennig, W. (1966) Phylogenetic Systematics. University of Illinois
Press.
Hoopes, J. (1991) Peirce on Signs : Writings on Semiotic. University of
North Carolina Press.
Koestler, A. (1967) The Ghost in the Machine. Hutchinson.
Liszka, J. J. (1996) A General Introduction to the Semeiotic Of Charles
Sanders Peirce. Indiana University Press.
Maturana, H. R. and Varela, F. J. (1987) The Tree of Knowledge: The
Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Shambala.
Merrell, F. (1991) Signs Becoming Signs: Our Perfusive, Pervasive
Universe. Indiana University Press.
Nelson, G. J. and Platnick, N. I. (1981) Systematics and Biogeography:
Cladistics and Vicariance. Columbia University Press.
Owen, R. (1858) On the characters, principles of division and primary
groups of the Mammalia. Journal of the Proceedings of the
Linnean Society (Zoology) 2: 1-37.
Padian, K. (2000) Dinosaurs and birds – an update. Reports of the
National Center for Science Education 20(5): 28-31.
Salthe, S. N. (1985) Evolving Hierarchical Systems: Their Structure and
Representation. Columbia University Press.
Salthe, S. N. (1993) Development and Evolution: Complexity and Change
in Biology. MIT Press.
Schrödinger, E. (1944) What is Life? Cambridge University Press.
Wilber, K. (1996) Up from Eden: A Transpersonal View of Human
Evolution. Quest.
Wood, S. W. (1996) Systematics of the Macrourid Fishes. University of
Cambridge, doctoral dissertation. iii+155 pp., 4 tables, 57 figures.
Wood, S.W. (2002) The holographic principle in biological development
and quantum physics. In Bowden, K. G. (ed.), pp. 199-245,
Correlations: Proceedings of ANPA 23. Alternative Natural
Philosophy Association.