Hans Kelsen's Normativism
Hans Kelsen's Normativism
Hans Kelsen’s
Carsten Heidemann
drawing on its varied intellectual traditions Glasgow
in order to showcase the interdisciplinary Gerald J. Postema
dimensions of jurisprudential enquiry, University of
HANS KELSEN’S
NORMATIVISM
Carsten Heidemann
Schleswig-Holstein Bar Association
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
University Printing House, Cambridge CB2 8BS, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108995221
DOI: 10.1017/9781108993661
© Carsten Heidemann 2022
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2022
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
ISBN 978-1-108-99522-1 Paperback
ISSN 2631-5815 (online)
ISSN 2631-5807 (print)
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
DOI: 10.1017/9781108993661
First published online: January 2022
Carsten Heidemann
Schleswig-Holstein Bar Association
Author for correspondence: Carsten Heidemann, [email protected]
Abstract: Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law is the most prominent example
of legal normativism. This Element traces its genesis. In philosophy,
normativism started with Hume’s distinction between Is-and Ought-
propositions. Kant distinguished practical from theoretical judgments,
while resting even the latter on normativity. Following him, Lotze and the
Baden neo-Kantians instrumentalized normativism to secure a sphere of
knowledge which is not subject to the natural sciences. Even in his first
major text, Kelsen claims that law is solely a matter of Ought or normativity.
In the second phase of his writings, he places himself in the neo-Kantian
tradition, holding legal norms to be Ought-judgments of legal science. In
the third phase, he advocates a barely coherent naive normative realism. In
the fourth phase, he supplements the realist view with a strict will theory of
norms, coupled with set pieces from linguistic philosophy; classical
normativism is more or less dismantled.
1 Introduction 1
4 Summary 72
References 75
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 1
1 Introduction*
Normativism is an important strand in philosophy. It can roughly be defined as
having three basic features. First, there is a fundamental mode of Ought, or
normativity, which cannot be reduced to the mode of Is, or factuality. Second,
normativity is in some way objective. Third, normativity is constitutive of
a certain domain, be it ontology, epistemology, language, morality, or law.
In accordance with the third feature, philosophical normativism is not
restricted to securing the objectivity and autonomy of the ‘practical’ sphere; it
also plays an important role in metaphysics. As will be shown (Section 2.2.2),
Kant’s rejection of transcendental realism without succumbing to skepticism
was only possible by his adopting a variety of normativism for his theoretical
philosophy. In present-day philosophy, normativism dominates not only parts of
the theory of meaning in a narrow sense; it is also central to Hilary Putnam’s
internal realism, Jürgen Habermas’s discourse theory, and Robert Brandom’s
inferentialism – to name some prominent examples.
Normativism in legal theory is mainly associated with the writings of Hans
Kelsen (1881–1973). While there is scarcely any legal theorist who would
subscribe to its tenets without restrictions, the Pure Theory of Law gained
worldwide recognition and had an impact on authors like H. L. A. Hart,
Joseph Raz, and Robert Alexy. The normativistic tendencies of current legal
theory are generally due to Kelsen’s immediate or mediated influence. But
Kelsen’s texts represent not only what might be called the ‘historical core’ of
legal normativism; having undergone several changes of paradigm during the
long span of time in which they were published, they also give an overview of
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
* I am grateful to two anonymous reviewers for helpful remarks. Special thanks go to Monika
Zalewska for our enriching discussion of Kelsenian and philosophical topics.
1
On the Kelsen–Schmitt controversy, see Paulson 2017.
2 Philosophy of Law
In the second section of this Element, the development of the Is–Ought dualism
and normativism in philosophy is traced, by sketching some historical ‘land-
marks’ which informed Kelsen’s theory. This is necessary because the meaning
and role of ‘Ought’ can hardly be understood without drafting the history of this
concept – unless one is content with the meagre and apodictic explanation of the
dualism Kelsen gave in the second edition of Pure Theory of Law:
Kelsen’s explicitly neo-Kantian writings from the 1920s, especially Das Problem
der Souveränität, Der soziologische und der juristische Staatsbegriff and
Rechtswissenschaft und Recht, though philosophically his best, are not well
known; they are written in a difficult style and have not been translated into English.
Finally, the fourth section gives a short summary of the findings of sections
two and three.
2
On this topic, see the instructive paper Beiser 2009: 9–37.
3
However, in secondary literature both whether Hume’s text is the origin of the philosophical
tradition of a dualism between Is and Ought and what Hume really meant is contested; see the
seminal paper McIntyre 1959: 451–68.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 3
In every system of morality, which I have hitherto met with, I have always
remarked, that the author proceeds for some time in the ordinary way of
reasoning, and establishes the being of a God, or makes observations con-
cerning human affairs; when of a sudden I am surprised to find, that instead of
the usual copulations of propositions, is, and is not, I meet with no proposition
that is not connected with an ought, or an ought not. This change is imper-
ceptible; but is, however, of the last consequence. For as this ought, or ought
not, expresses some new relation or affirmation, ‘tis necessary that it should
be observed and explained; and at the same time that a reason should be
given, for what seems altogether inconceivable, how this new relation can be
a deduction from others, which are entirely different from it. But as authors do
not commonly use this precaution, I shall presume to recommend it to the
readers; and am persuaded, that this small attention would subvert all the
vulgar systems of morality, and let us see, that the distinction of vice and
virtue is not founded merely on the relations of objects, nor is perceived by
reason. (Hume 2007a: 302)
and more important role in Kant’s philosophy than in Hume’s. His transcen-
dental idealism tries to steer a middle path between empiricism and rational-
ism in order to avoid Humean skepticism, and normativity plays an important
part in this project. Kant points to normativity to strictly separate practical
questions from empirical or theoretical ones. But Kant is also the first major
philosopher to turn the tables and hold not only that Ought-propositions
cannot be reduced to Is-propositions; rather, any kind of theoretical or Is-
cognition presupposes normativity. For him, practical reason has, in several
ways, priority over theoretical reason.
This passage contains some further qualifications of the Ought which are not
important in this context, but which are noteworthy: The Ought goes along with
a kind of necessity, and it expresses a “connection with grounds,” not with
causes.
In another passage in the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant maintains:
Like Hume, in both passages Kant does not further argue for this point, but
seems to take it to be self-evident. Finally, in the Critique of Judgment, regard-
ing the sphere of practical reason, Kant holds:
Now since . . . the objective necessity of the action, as duty, is opposed to that
which it, as an occurrence, would have if its ground lay in nature and not in
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
freedom (i.e., in the causality of reason), and the action which is morally
absolutely necessary can be regarded physically as entirely contingent (i.e.,
what necessarily should happen often does not), it is clear that it depends only
on the subjective constitution of our practical faculty that the moral laws must
be represented as commands (and the actions which are in accord with them
as duties), and that reason expresses this necessity not through a be (happen-
ing) but through a should-be, which would not be the case if reason without
sensibility (as the subjective condition of its application to objects of nature)
were considered, as far as its causality is concerned, as a cause in an intelli-
gible world, corresponding completely with the moral law, where there would
be no distinction between what should be done and what is done, between
a practical law concerning that which is possible through us and the theoret-
ical law concerning that which is actual through us. (Kant 2002: 273 [A 338–
9/B 342-3])
Compared to the previously cited passages, which are pleasantly clear, this
one seems obscure and needs some explanation. What Kant seems to mean, as
far as our topic is concerned, is that the Ought (or the moral law) expresses what
6 Philosophy of Law
Although Is and Ought have to be kept apart, there are, for Kant, at least two
relations between them where the Ought is logically prior to the Is. First, there is
a “primacy” of practical reason over theoretical reason. Second, understand-
ing’s activity of judging presupposes a minimum of autonomy and, thus, of
normativity.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
If practical reason may not assume and think as given anything further than
what speculative reason of itself could offer it from its insight, the latter has
primacy. Supposing, however, that practical reason has of itself original
a priori principles with which certain theoretical positions are inseparably
connected, while these are withdrawn from any possible insight of specula-
tive reason (although they must not contradict it): then the question is, which
interest is supreme (not, which must give way, for one does not necessarily
conflict with the other)?4 (Kant 2015: 97 [A 216])
4
“Interest,” in this context, is defined by Kant as “a principle that contains the condition under
which alone [the] exercise [of a faculty of mind] is promoted” (Kant 2015: 97 [A 216]).
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 7
holds that they are instead the result of an interaction between receptive or
passive sensibility and the spontaneous activity of understanding (Verstand).
Other candidates not being available, this spontaneity is made up by under-
standing’s activity – that is, thinking or judging – being guided by rules, and by
the judging subject’s competence to distinguish correct from incorrect applica-
tions of these rules.
There are quite a number of passages where this indispensable normativist
level of Kant’s theory emerges – for example, when he explains concepts as
rules for uniting representations, or when he defines understanding generally as
the “faculty of rules” (Vermögen der Regeln) (Kant 1998: 242 [A 126]). In fact,
Kant’s theoretical philosophy might presuppose a solution of the third antinomy
(Willaschek 2010: 165–84). That is, in short, the cognitive constitution of the
world of objects might presuppose some form of freedom of will, or
normativity.6
Against this background, it is not astonishing that, for Kant, logic is
concerned with normative rules: “In logic, however, the question is not
about contingent but about necessary rules; not how we do think, but how
we ought to think” (Kant 1992: 529). In a similar vein, borrowing from the
language of jurists, he distinguishes between questions of what is lawful (quid
juris) and questions of fact (quid facti) (Kant 1998: 219–20 [A 84/B 116]), that
is, between empirical questions and questions of justification, or genesis and
validity.
What is noteworthy about this kind of ‘theoretical normativity’ is that, unlike
moral normativity, it does its work implicitly. Kant describes it in a way which is
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The exercise of our powers also takes place according to rules that we follow,
unconscious of them at first, until we gradually arrive at cognition of them
through experiments and lengthy use of our powers, indeed, until we finally
become so familiar with them that it costs us much effort to think them in
abstracto. Thus universal grammar is the form of a language in general, for
example. One speaks without being acquainted with grammar, however; and
6
Cf., in the same direction, Walker 2017: 205: “So, after all, does not theoretical reasoning provide
as sound a basis for presupposing freedom as practical reasoning does? [Kant] seems to be
suggesting this in the Groundwork, when he says ‘one cannot possibly think of a reason that
would consciously receive direction from any other quarter with respect to its judgments, since the
subject would then attribute the determination of his judgment not to his reason but to an impulse.
Reason must regard itself as the author of its principles independently of alien influences,
consequently, as practical reason or as the will of a rational being, it must be regarded of itself
as free.’ This makes it seem as though the same case can be made for autonomy in judging as in
acting, though he is here appealing only to how one must think of oneself. One might wonder why
he never develops the idea.”
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 9
he who speaks without being acquainted with it does actually have a grammar
and speaks according to rules, but ones of which he is not himself conscious.
Like all our powers, the understanding [Verstand] in particular is bound in its
actions to rules, which we can investigate. (Kant 1992: 527 [A 2])
The most remarkable feature of these rules is that, although they can in
principle be made explicit or “thought of in abstracto,” in their basic form
they are not ‘objects’ to be applied in certain situations; rather, they are just
implicit in certain acts: This is the only interpretation that takes care of Kant’s
thesis that you can have a grammar without knowing it. It anticipates
Wittgenstein’s famous dictum: “When I follow the rule, I do not choose.
I follow the rule blindly” (Wittgenstein 2009: 92 [219]).
This interpretation is underpinned by Kant’s text on schematism, where he
discusses the problem of how an intuition might be subsumed under a concept.
That poses a problem because intuitions and concepts are heterogeneous
(ungleichartig), stemming from different cognitive faculties. Concepts – or
the judgments which employ them – are the result of exerting the spontaneous
faculty of understanding, while intuitions stem from the passive faculty of
sensibility. Kant’s solution is that an intuition and a concept can be related to
each other by applying a scheme, which is a
tion to appearances and their mere form, is an art concealed in the depths
of the human soul, whose real modes of activity nature is hardly ever
likely to allow us to discover, and to have open to our gaze. (Kant 1998:
273–4 [A 141/B 180–1])
how we are to subsume under these rules, that is, to distinguish whether
something does or does not come under them, that could only be by means of
another rule. This, in turn, for the very reason that it is a rule, again demands
guidance from judgment. And thus it appears that, though understanding is
capable of being instructed, and of being equipped with rules, judgment is
a peculiar talent which can be practised only, and cannot be taught. (Kant
1998: 268 [A 133/B 172])
10 Philosophy of Law
Now although there is an incalculable gulf fixed between the domain of the
concept of nature, as the sensible, and the domain of the concept of freedom,
as the supersensible, so that from the former to the latter (thus by means of the
theoretical use of reason) no transition is possible, just as if there were so
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 11
many different worlds, the first of which can have no influence on the second:
yet the latter should have an influence on the former, namely the concept of
freedom should make the end that is imposed by its laws real in the sensible
world; and nature must consequently also be able to be conceived in such
a way that the lawfulness of its form is at least in agreement with the
possibility of the ends that are to be realized in it in accordance with the
laws of freedom. (Kant 2002: 63 [A/B XIX])
ground in Germany (as had philosophy in general), natural sciences were more
and more successful, and psychology was getting established as a science.
Lotze’s ambition was to reconcile natural sciences and idealism in a system
which he called “teleological idealism.” And like Kant and Fichte, although in
a different way, Lotze assumes a primacy of practical over theoretical
philosophy.7 In an early text, he defines his position as follows:
[The appearances] come and emerge, held and connected not by some exter-
nal object, but by their interrelation, which a higher power without needing
material forces for its acts has prescribed. Our study has dissolved into this
teleological idealism. . . . [T]he beginning of metaphysics is not in itself, but
in ethics. (Lotze 1841: 329, my translation)
The first part of the quotation sounds almost Kantian; the difference is
that objectivity is not derived from the correct application of the
7
On this topic, see Thieme 1887.
12 Philosophy of Law
It was this assimilation of ‘valid truths’ to Platonic ideas that led some neo-
Kantians, notably Heinrich Rickert, to ascribe validity – as will be shown in
Section 2.3.2 – to “values,” which are not norms directed at human subjectivity,
but which have an objective reality independent from it. Although this does not
seem to be quite in accordance with Lotze’s intentions, he certainly encouraged
it, not only by referring to Plato’s philosophy but also by maintaining that some
“good” or “truth” is the datum from which an Ought can be derived. This seems
14 Philosophy of Law
to imply that validity is not identical with an Ought, but is, after all, some kind of
being.
8
Otto Liebmann enthusiastically ended each chapter of his influential book Kant und die Epigonen
(Schober: Stuttgart, 1865) with this slogan.
9
See Windelband’s harsh dictum: “From the standpoint of epistemology, the thing-in-itself is
a completely meaningless and useless, confusing and annoying fiction” (quoted in Beiser 2014:
524).
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 15
10 11
On this status, see Heidemann 2020: 81–98. On this topic, see further Beiser 2014: 497.
12
Cf. Beiser 2014: 497.
16 Philosophy of Law
13 14
Cf. Beiser 2014: 506–7. See further Köhnke 1993: 361.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 17
That structure which we have in mind when we are talking about the objective
meaning-content is what is sometimes called the “truth” of the judgment, its
content per se which is not immanent to the judging act of the subject but
which must be thought of as something independent of it and attained by it,
and which all of us mean and understand wherever we judge or assert
something as true at all. (Rickert 1921: 143, my translation)
content, as it were. The theoretical value, and with it the objective meaning-
content, does not exist like an object, instead, it is valid. It gives rise to an Ought,
namely, a demand to think in a certain way.
Validity must not be understood as an ideal mode of being of some kind of
nonsensual reality (Rickert 1921: 247); rather, it is the indefinable way in which
normativity is given, and which is prior to any existence:
[The concept of existence is not the only one] under which something can be
subsumed; besides, there is the concept of value. We use this word which
denotes a concept that can be defined just as little as the concept of existence,
for structures that do not exist but which, nevertheless, are “something”, and
this can best be expressed by saying that they are valid. (Rickert 1921: 229–
30, my translation)
Rickert argues in different ways for the case that validity has not only to be
distinguished from existence, but is also prior to it; the most convincing argu-
ment runs as follows:
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 19
by their own nature, they are not normative, but theoretical truths, and as such
they can serve for regulating the activity of judging just as much as truths
from any other disciplines. . . . The anti-psychologists erred in taking the
regulation of cognition as the essence of the laws of logic. . . . It was
overlooked that the so-called logical principles as such are not norms, but
may be used as norms. With respect to this function we got used to speaking
of laws of thinking, and so it seemed as if these laws had a psychological
content, and as if the difference to the so-called laws of psychology was just
that they regulate, while the other laws of psychology do not. On the other
hand, the psychologists erred. . . . It is a matter of course that every general
truth, be it of psychology or not, founds a rule of correct judging; and thus not
only the possibility, but the existence of rules for judging is confirmed, which
are not founded in psychology. (Husserl 1900: 157, my translation)
the pure logic or logic in the narrow sense is usually defined as the theory of
the forms of thinking. But this has to be specified; it is concerned with the
forms of correct thinking, which are a selection from the psychologically
possible forms of moves of mental representations. Logic does not teach how
we really think, but how we ought to think, if we want to think correctly. . . .
One has to keep in mind, however that the validity of these forms has, in the
end, to be totally independent from the quest for knowledge of an empirical
and especially the human consciousness. . . . From this, a fundamental duality
of all logical laws follows: On the one hand, they are rules for empirical
consciousness which all thinking that is directed toward truth should comply
with; on the other hand, their inner and autonomous meaning and being is
quite independent from the question whether there are factual mental pro-
cesses of representing which conform to them. The former might be called
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
their validity in itself [Geltung an sich], the latter their validity for us [Geltung
für uns]; where “us” does not just mean us human beings, but all individual
subjects who – like us – distinguish, in their representations, between true and
false, correct and incorrect. Seen from “us,” logic is an “Ought” – but this
Ought must be grounded in something whose validity subsists in itself, and
which turns into a norm or Ought only if it is related to a consciousness
capable of erring. (Windelband 1912: 17–18, my translation)
The second step is to determine some graspable thing, which is not reducible
to a psychical entity and which, in a way, embodies the transcendent value.
This graspable object, for Rickert, is the true “sentence,” understood as
a series of signs (Rickert 1909: 194). Its meaning is “transcendent,” independ-
ent of cognitive acts, and has to be distinguished from the “immanent”
subjective meaning of these acts. Like Frege, Rickert calls this objective
meaning a “thought” (Gedanke) (Rickert 1909: 196). It is logically prior to
any existence, because – as was shown in Section 2.3.2.2 – for Rickert,
existence presupposes the validity of an objective-meaning content. Being
logically prior to existence, the true thought can only be made sense of as
a “theoretical value,” and, accordingly, the task of cognitive theory is to
determine its presuppositions (Rickert 1909: 207).
There is an obvious objection to this argumentation: Why should it be
possible to get at the transcendent meaning by simply connecting it to the
empirical object of a ‘sentence,’ to a series of signs? After all, the meaning of
a sentence is accessible only via the psychical act of ‘understanding’ it. So,
22 Philosophy of Law
Nevertheless, there might still be concerns about the worth of the transcen-
dental-psychological analysis, especially as regards its ability to bridge the
gap between the world of theoretical values and the psychical acts of think-
ing. To support these doubts, a very radical argument may be brought forward
that at this point the theory of cognition hits upon a problem which cannot be
solved at all. Meaning and being, value and reality, transcendence and
immanence conceptually exclude each other. Philosophy cannot overcome
this dualism, not even by introducing the conception of autonomously recog-
nising the values. (Rickert 1909: 222, my translation)
necessarily connected with the concept of cognition. We cannot even say that
there is this unity, because that would be cognition of the unity as unity, which
is impossible. The unity cannot be thought, it can only be experienced.
(Rickert 1909: 223–4, my translation)
15
The problem of the relation between immanence and transcendence troubles even so late
a descendant of neo-Kantianism as Jürgen Habermas. In Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung he holds
that “it is the aim of all justification to discover a truth which is independent of any justification”
(Habermas 1999: 53, my translation). This sentence is paradoxical not only at first sight.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 23
2.4 Summary
The genesis of normativism as outlined in this section might be summarized as
follows: Hume was the first major philosopher to make the dualism of Is and
Ought explicit, taking the Ought to be a matter of moral, religious, or political
propositions and holding Ought-sentences not to be objective. Kant took the
moral Ought to be expressive of practical reason (and, therefore, to be object-
ive). Although he explicitly dealt only with the moral Ought in an elaborate way,
there is a ‘theoretical’ Ought (recognized in any act of judging) in Kant’s theory
as well. Lotze gave an ontological touch to this theoretical Ought by taking
a truth to be the “content of cogitation” which is valid and from which an Ought,
or rules demanding that a subject should think in a certain way, can be derived.
This interpretation was taken up by Windelband in order to make the normativ-
ity of values the basic philosophical element and to forestall any psychologistic
explanation of cognition (while neglecting the moral or practical Ought).
Rickert systematized and radicalized Windelband’s approach by distinguishing
between the Ought directed at the judging person’s subjectivity and the even
more fundamental value of truth which is valid independent of any subjectivity.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
16
See especially Paulson 1990; see further Kubeš 1980.
24 Philosophy of Law
(Kelsen 1911: VI, 44)20, namely, the cognition of practical jurists and legal
dogmatists. It is reconstructed from the internal perspective; Kelsen aims to
uncover its tacit presuppositions and to criticize its constructions (Kelsen
1911: V).
The methodological assumption underlying this enterprise is the distinction
between an explicative view, employed by causal sciences, and a normative
view, employed by legal science (that is, legal dogmatics). Both views exclude
17
For a detailed depiction of the genesis of Kelsen’s normativism, see Heidemann 1997.
18
He published a book on Dante’s theory of state six years earlier (Hans Kelsen, Die Staatslehre
des Dante Alighieri, Wiener Staatswissenschaftliche Studien, series 6, vol. 3 [1905]), but it does
not contain any traces of the later Pure Theory. Kelsen himself regarded it as “a student’s
unoriginal effort” (see Kelsen 2006: 37).
19
Kelsen takes for granted that the term ‘law’ covers exclusively the positive law, cf. Kelsen 1911:
367.
20
The ‘normative perspective’ of legal dogmatics is, for Kelsen, as much a postulate as a reality.
Calling legal dogmatics a ‘normative’ discipline only means that norms are its subject matter; it
does not mean that it posits norms (Kelsen 1911: VI–VII).
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 25
each other and must not be blended in one and the same science (Kelsen
1911: 6). Therefore, Kelsen aims at restricting juristic construction by eliminat-
ing from it any elements alien to the normative view – especially arguments
from psychology or sociology – in order to get at a logically closed system of
purely juridical fundamental concepts (Kelsen 1911: XI).
This alone, however, would not have been a radical innovation of contem-
porary conceptions of law and state. In fact, Kelsen himself – in a later text,
Allgemeine Staatslehre (1925) – saw his theory in the positivistic tradition of
Gerber and Laband, who applied Begriffsjurisprudenz (conceptual jurispru-
dence) to state law (Kelsen 1925: VII). And stressing the normativity of law
was not new either; Kelsen was preceded, among others, by Georg Jellinek who
was closely related to the Baden school of neo-Kantianism. Kelsen had attended
his seminars at Heidelberg.
So what was actually new about Kelsen’s approach? On the one hand, it
was the radicality with which he defined the dualism of Is and Ought and
attempted to exclude any ‘Is-elements’ from law. On the other hand, it was
his ‘semi-reductionism’ concerning legal concepts, that is, his attempt to
construct these concepts from the one central normative element of law, the
Rechtssatz.
The basis of the distinction between the explicative and the normative point of
view is the dualism between Is and Ought. Accordingly, Kelsen emphasizes the
importance of separating these elements. He does not develop a fully fledged
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
(1) Both the ways an Ought comes into existence and is ‘destroyed’ are part of
the sphere of Is (Kelsen 1911: 10). An example of this phenomenon is Jellinek’s
formula of the “normative force of the factual,” according to which custom can
produce a consciousness of Ought (Kelsen 1911: 9). However, it is not possible
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 27
(2) Is and Ought are related insofar as the Ought “aims”at an Is. It “wants to
bring about” changes in the sphere of Is. Accordingly, the “demands of the
Ought” (Sollanforderungen) are motives for the will, and these demands are
complied with by the ones they are directed at, or they can be “applied” by other
individuals (Kelsen 1911: 14).
(3) There is a close relation between the Ought and the will. Willing is
a factual psychical process belonging to the sphere of Is. It is relevant to the
Ought in two different ways: as the will of somebody who posits an Ought-
demand, and as the will of somebody who the Ought-demand is directed at. In
both cases, the Ought must be strictly separated from the act of will; for it is
possible that the process of willing has terminated while the Ought is still valid
(Kelsen 1911: 10–11). Kelsen, however, is not clear on the point whether there
can be an Ought without any volitional procedure founding it.21
(4) Kelsen holds that Is and Ought can have a content which is “comparable”
(Kelsen 1911: 69); this content or point of reference of both Is and Ought is
a “notion” (Vorstellung) (Kelsen 1911: 7). But he also maintains that the relation
between Is and Ought is a relation between content and form (Kelsen 1911: 10);
this would mean that the content of an Ought is an Is.
(5) Norms, the units of Ought, exist in reality by evoking a certain behavior.
A norm is “efficacious” if it is complied with, that is, if it really determines the
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
22
See the extensive discussion in Kelsen 1911: 313–46.
23
Although he was one of the first legal theorists to introduce formulas for describing legal
relations (cf. Kelsen 1925: 49), Kelsen does not yet use any of them in the Hauptprobleme. He
defines the norm-subject as “dasjenige, was soll” (the one who ought to do something) and the
norm-object as “dasjenige, was gesollt wird” (that which ought to be done); Kelsen 1911: 71–2.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 29
this term not only to denominate the relation between the abstract elements
inside the norm, but also to denote the relation between certain elements of
factual reality, a human being and some factual act or process, which are related
as the result of an application of the norm (Kelsen 1911: 72). The difference can
be illustrated as follows: Originally, imputation connects ‘help the needy’ with
‘everybody’ in the norm ‘Everybody ought to help the needy’; but it also
connects the factual process of helping a needy human being with the one
who is helping him. This ambiguity will accompany the notion of Zurechnung
in Kelsen’s later phases.
Normativism in law was provisionally defined in Section 1 as the view that law
is exclusively a system of (normative) rules which are objective, impersonal,
and independent of any factuality. Accordingly, for Kelsen, the law consists of
norms; and what makes his view normativistic is that it contains nothing but
norms. It follows that every concept that is relevant for law must be derived
from a legal norm, its parts, or the set of all legal norms. It is a construction; that
is why Stanley L. Paulson’s description of this phase of Kelsen’s writings as
“critical constructivism” (Paulson 1990: 24–8) is appropriate.
(Kelsen 1911: 36–7). Kelsen identifies the legal norm with the Rechtssatz (Kelsen
1911: 3) – a hypothetical judgment (in a logical sense) about the will of the state.
It is not “given” to legal dogmatics; rather, it has to be put together by lawyers
from the fragmented empirical material supplied by the legislative procedure; so
it is, on a different level, a “construction,” as well. The hypothetical judgment is
the “logical” or “ideal” form of the legal norm. This further distinguishes the legal
norm from the moral norm, which is an imperative (Kelsen 1911: 236–7).
Every Rechtssatz can be formulated as “Under conditions c, the state wants to
act in the way a” (Kelsen 1911: 207, 211–12). Like the norm in general, it is
a rule of imputation. But while the norm in general relates to a certain act or state
of affairs for a norm-subject as something which she ought to do or bring about,
the Rechtssatz is a law imputing an act to the state as being willed by it. The
Rechtssatz in a wider sense may impute any act to the state; in a narrow sense it
imputes coercion to the state – the state not being a given entity, but a unifying
construct.
30 Philosophy of Law
This definition of the legal norm raises questions: On the one hand, the
formulation of the Rechtssatz seems to be a pure stipulation; on the other
hand, the Ought seems to be lost somehow – at least it does not appear in the
formula. With regard to the first point, Kelsen argues that law is necessarily the
will of the state; but a will cannot be directed at somebody else’s behavior,
which can only be wished for; so the will of the state can only be directed at ‘its
own’ behavior. Regarding the second point, Kelsen holds that the Ought is
somehow connected with the hypothetical judgment about the will of the state,
but he does not settle in a satisfactory way how this connection might be
conceived. The most relevant passage runs as follows:
If the norm drapes itself in the form of a judgment, then it raises a general
claim to truth, and it repeats itself in anybody who hears it, like any judgment.
As a judgment, the proposition: If somebody steals, then the state wills to
commit him to prison, is as true and universally – i.e. for any reasonable
being – valid as the proposition: The state is powerful, or: The horse is
a mammal. But this logical universal validity is of no consequence for the
validity of the norm posited together with the judgment. (Kelsen 1911: 259,
my translation)
This explanation is, at best, ambiguous: On the one hand, the judgment is the
“form” of the norm; on the other, there is a difference between the logical validity
of the hypothetical judgment of the Rechtssatz and the validity of the Ought,
which is somehow connected to the judgment. And it almost seems as if the norm
is “posited” together with the judgment. This does not go together well.
The source of the validity of a single legal norm is, in this early phase, tabooed
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
by Kelsen. He maintains that, for legal dogmatics, it is not permissible to ask why
a single norm is valid because this question concerns its own presuppositions. To
ask it would mean, for the jurist, “to saw off the bough he is sitting on” (Kelsen
1911: 353). To illustrate the analogous problem of ‘Is-science’ to ascertain a final
ground of the world, Kelsen cites Franz Grillparzer: “Geläng’ es mir, des Weltalls
Grund, / somit auch meinen auszusagen, / so könnt’ ich auch zur selben Stund’ /
mich selbst auf meinen Armen tragen” (Should I succeed the reason to name / of
the universe, and, thus, mine own, / I could – it would be just the same – / carry
myself on my arms alone) (Kelsen 1911: 466).
This quaintly expressed ‘taboo’ is a congenial placeholder for the basic norm,
which will be introduced only in the next phase.
The will of the state – or the state as a person, which is nothing else but this
will – is not an empirical entity; it exists just as a “point of imputation” which is
constituted by the Rechtssätze. It is something quite different from the empirical
will which might be part of the legislative procedures but which is, inside the
law, irrelevant. The same applies to the concepts of will and person in general:
Both elements only exist as reference points, that is, as constructed points of the
imputation of acts by legal norms (Kelsen 1911: 145–6). The concepts of “duty”
and “(subjective) right” can be shown to be constructions from the Rechtssatz as
well: A duty of the state is the result of a “subjectification” of the Rechtssatz
(this procedure is not further explained by Kelsen) (Kelsen 1911: 435). Besides,
there is a duty for a citizen if the Rechtssatz says that, under certain conditions,
the state wants the citizen to be sanctioned (Kelsen 1911: 447). And somebody
has a right to a certain act of somebody else if he is able to ‘trigger’ the state’s
will to sanction this somebody else in case he omits this act (Kelsen 1911:
618–29).
his theses in a rather apodictic way without elaborating the foundations of his
theory.
In secondary literature, it is sometimes suspected that Kelsen’s neo-
Kantianism is no more than a pretentious label. This is, however, only justified
as far as his writings from 1940 onward are concerned. For the 1920s, there can
be no doubt that Kelsen really is a true-blue neo-Kantian.
But what is neo-Kantian about Kelsen’s theory in this phase? According to
Kelsen himself, he was not aware of the affinities between his theory and neo-
Kantianism until 1912, when he read a review of his Hauptprobleme in the
Kant-Studien by Oscar Ewald (Kelsen 1998a: 15 [Kelsen 1923: XVII]). Ewald
pointed specifically to his treatment of the concept of will, which he thought was
“remarkably in accord” with what Cohen had advocated in his Ethik des Reinen
Willens. And he appreciated the book as an attempt to introduce the “transcen-
dental method” into the theory of state law. The review spurred Kelsen to focus
on neo-Kantian philosophy. This had two main impacts on his theory: First,
Kelsen conceived his legal theory as a neo-Kantian transcendental philosophy
of law, that is, as a theory of legal science as embodied by legal
dogmatics; second, Kelsen identified the legal norm with the hypothetical
judgment of legal science.
they might be ‘in themselves’; rather, it deals with the necessary rules guiding
cognition: Ontology turns into epistemology (understood as a theory of cogni-
tive validity).
While the legal norm, in Hauptprobleme, was necessarily connected with the
Rechtssatz, these elements were nevertheless not identical: The validity or
existence of the legal norm was different from the validity of the hypothet-
ical judgment constructed from the legislative material given to legal dog-
matics. Or so Kelsen maintained. Now, in his neo-Kantian phase, Kelsen
explicitly identifies the legal norm with the hypothetical judgment of legal
science; the validity of a legal norm is its validity as a cognitive judgment.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
[Sander fails to see] that legal science may “create” its object – law as
embodied by legal rules [Rechtssätze], by judgments – just as natural
science may “create” its object, the nature of natural science, nature as
a system of synthetic judgments without in the least running any danger of
becoming a “source” of law. . . . Though “created” by science itself, the
synthetic judgments of natural science are determined by the material
which they unify (therefore, they are judgments “about” [über] nature)
just as the synthetic judgments of legal science, the legal rules, in which
the material given to legal science . . . is formed, formed into legal rules in
the same way as the perceptual material is formed in the synthetic judg-
ments of natural science. . . . If we are inclined to qualify the acts which are
24
The fight against methodological syncretism, or against the ‘metabasis eis allo genos,’ is
a central theme for neo-Kantian anti-psychologists and for Kelsen; see Kelsen 1920: V;
Kelsen 1922b: 34, 45.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 35
the material of the legal rules as acts of will [Willensakte], then the legal
rules as judgments “about” them have to be expressed by an Ought. In
cognition, i.e. in the judgments of legal science appearing as legal rules, the
willing [Wollen], which is objectified in the sphere of judgment, expresses
itself as an Ought. Only in this sphere can we talk of law as an object of
legal science. As the object of legal science, law is a system of judgments
about law, just as nature as the object of natural science is a system of
judgments about nature. (Kelsen 1922a: 181–2, my translation)
Accordingly, “[both the state and the law are] normative order[s], i.e. system[s]
of norms which are linguistically expressed by Ought-sentences and logically
in hypothetical judgments in which the condition is connected to the conse-
quence by the ‘Ought’ (if a, then b ought to be)” (Kelsen 1922b: 75, my
translation).
The above may be summarized as follows: Cognition creates its objects by
synthesizing judgments. These judgments are objectively valid without corres-
ponding to something ‘given’ to them by being in accordance with the rules that
guide cognition. ‘Nature’ as the object of knowledge is not a conglomeration of
knowledge-independent ‘things,’ but a system of synthetic judgments. In these
judgments the category of causality is applied to perceptual material. In an
analogous way, the law as the object of legal science is identical with the system
of judgments created by legal science. It is not the task of legal science to
‘passively’ describe norms given by the legislator; rather it applies the Ought to
a nonnormative substratum consisting of the legislator’s acts of will (or their
content), thus constituting hypothetical normative judgments which are identi-
cal with the legal norms.25
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
It was shown in Section 2 that Hume thought the dualism of Is and Ought to be
one between objective analytical or empirical sentences, and subjective prac-
tical sentences. Kant, by contrast, took practical sentences to be objective, and
introduced normativity into epistemology, so that there was a bifurcation of the
dualism of Is and Ought. The neo-Kantians concentrated on the epistemological
part of the dualism, equating the theoretical Ought with a cognitive judgment’s
validity.
It is not easy to locate Kelsen’s version of the dualism in this context. He still
maintains that the reason or ground (Grund) for the validity of a norm can only
be another norm (Kelsen 1920: 95). Besides, there is another ‘formal–logical’
explanation of the dualism which is more precise than what Kelsen brought
25
This summary is mainly taken from Heidemann 1999: 348.
36 Philosophy of Law
[T]he norm as a judgment of Ought is contrasted with the law of nature, and
the Rechtssatz, which is qualified as a norm, is contrasted with the specific
causal law of sociology. Therefore, my main concern is the Rechtssatz seen as
an expression of the specific legal autonomy [Rechtsgesetzlichkeit]; and from
this perspective the law of legal science is a system of Rechtssätze, a system
of judgments, just as nature as the object of natural science is – for transcen-
dental philosophy – a system of judgments. The difference lies simply in that
the latter judgments express the causal relation of the system of nature
whereas in the Rechtssatz the specific normativity of law manifests itself.
Both in the judgment, which is the causal law, and in the Rechtssatz, a certain
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
This connection to causality, the analogon in the sphere of law, is the specific
legal Ought. Kelsen dubs it “periphere Zurechnung” (peripheral imputation)
(Kelsen 1992: 50 [Kelsen 1934: 57];27 it must be distinguished from “zentrale
Zurechnung” (central imputation) which consists in linking an act to a person.
The background to this version of the dualism is Kelsen’s specific brand of
26
It is more precise because the terms ‘ableiten’/derive or ‘(be-)gründen’/ground (which Kelsen
uses) are not well defined. A sophisticated formulation of the dualism might run as follows: “It is
impossible to deduce a nontrivial pure normative sentence from a consistent set of sentences
which does not contain any pure or mixed normative sentences.” But that does not seem to say
more, for this impossibility seems to be given exactly if Is-judgments and Ought-judgments
cannot contradict each other.
27
As far as I can see, Kelsen never explained why he called this central normative function
“peripheral imputation” and denoted the rather unimportant ascription of an act to a person (a
person being just a reification of a set of norms) as “central imputation.”
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 37
an issue that will become a major problem in Kelsen’s third and fourth
phases.28
Kelsen, like Kant, takes Ought-judgments to be objectively valid, that is,
genuine cognition. But, as noted in Section 2.2, Kant has it that practical
cognition, cognition of Ought, is a special function of reason, while empirical
cognition is the result of an interplay of understanding with intuition, of
concepts with nonobjective perceptual material delivered by the senses. By
contrast, Kelsen’s conception of legal cognition is an exact analogy to empirical
cognition. The Ought, for him, is not a concept of reason, but a category of
relation, constituting a judgment which processes empirical material, guided by
the rules determined in a “higher” norm:
28
See Section 3.3.5 for the third phase and Section 3.4.6 for the fourth phase.
38 Philosophy of Law
norm, while questioning the content of the legal rule, i.e. asking why a single
legal rule of a specific legal system has just this and no other content, leads to
the legislative acts or judicial judgments which constitute the “material” of
the Rechtssätze. This distinction is analogous to the distinction between
concept and perception, between the logical form and its perceptual material,
made in transcendental philosophy. I have distinguished between the “con-
tent”, meaning the material still to be formed, and “validity”, meaning the
form of the material when construed into a valid logical judgment. . . . The
logical creation of the law . . . from the basic norm proceeds step by step and
under constant reference to a parallel fact. (Kelsen 1922a: 214–5, my
translation)
This is one of Kelsen’s first depictions of the legal hierarchy, the Stufenbau of
law. It is noteworthy that the higher legal norms do not employ the category of
imputation; rather, they are meta-rules stating empirical criteria for lower norms
to be valid. I will come back to this point later (Section 3.2.5). For now, it
suffices to say that peripheral imputation, for Kelsen, is identical with the legal
Ought; it is a purely formal category of relation employed in the hypothetical
judgments of legal science whose content and validity depend on factual acts
which are named as criteria for the norm’s validity in “higher” rules.
3.2.4.2 Nature and Mind, Reality and Ideology, Nature and Society
Kelsen’s most prominent and coherent interpretation of the dualism of Is and
Ought in his neo-Kantian phase has it that these elements are identical with
causality, in the sphere of nature, and (peripheral) imputation, in the sphere of
law. However, Kelsen brings forward several other explanations of the dualism.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The conditions, stemming from the sphere of causally ordered events, for the
genesis of certain representations (understood as psychic acts) of norms
might be called the “real substructure” on which the norms and systems of
norms, as specific ideal contents, rise like a superstructure, as “ideologies”
which are autonomous vis-à-vis the natural laws governing the substructure.
But this is just an image, borrowed from the terminology of the materialist
conception of history, for the relation between the systems of nature and
mind, and, hence, between the systems of “reality” and of value, of which the
relation between nature and society is a special case. (Kelsen 1925: 21, my
translation)
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 39
29
In secondary literature, Kelsen’s concept of validity is widely held to be obscure, covering
different things, like the existence of the norm, its binding force, its being a member of the legal
system, etc. (see, e.g. Nino 1998 and the papers by E. Bulygin and E. G. Valdés in the same
volume). This is not justified; the core of Kelsen’s conception of validity is clear throughout all
the phases: The norm, that one ought to do a, is valid (i.e. in the neo-Kantian context, is a valid
ought-judgment) exactly if one ‘really’ ought to do a, or, which means the same, if the sentence
“one ought to do a” is true. In a similar way, the question whether the legal Ought is
a “legitimate” or “justified” Ought is idle (on this question, see, e.g. Paulson 2012). The legal
norm is “binding,” “legitimate,” or “justified,” exactly if it is valid, that is – again – if one ‘really’
ought to do what the norm says. But this validity is relative to the frame of reference of the
established practice of legal dogmatics; as a matter of course, a legal norm can only decree what
ought to be done legally. Inside the autonomous ‘language game’ of law, one ‘really’ ought to do
what the law says. But there might still be reasons for not letting this language game determine
how one acts.
40 Philosophy of Law
independent from the validity of the judgment that this something is, was, will
be, or even can be. This independence of Ought-validity from Is-validity, i.e.,
the validity of the being of nature, must by necessity exclude any reference to
the actual wanting or wishing, recognising or acting of the content of the
Ought on the part of the human being at whom the Ought is “directed”. The
Ought . . . in the judgments of legal science, i.e., the legal rule, is no more
directed at a human being than the law of nature is. . . . Striving for a non-
psychological meaning of the legal norm as an Ought-judgment, I am in the
same situation as the logicians vis-à-vis the logical norm. In his Prinzipien
der Logik, Windelband says about the pure logic: “It does not teach how one
really thinks, but how one ought to think if one wants to think correctly. This
common definition suffices to express the principal demarcation of logic
against psychology: But it must not be overlooked that the formulation
makes allowance for the fundamental fact of empirical thinking, mentioned
above, that it is prone to the possibility of error, . . . so that one has to take
care that the validity of these forms is in the last instance completely
independent from the striving of empirical and especially human conscious-
ness for knowledge. . . . From this it follows that all laws of logic have
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 41
a double status: On the one hand, they are rules for empirical consciousness,
which all thinking ought to comply with, if striving for truth. On the other
hand, their inner meaning and being is completely independent from the
question whether there are any mental processes which are in accordance
with them or not. The latter might be called their validity per se, the former,
their validity for us. . . . From ‘our’ perspective, logic is an ‘Ought’. But this
Ought must ground in something whose validity exists per se and which
becomes a norm, an Ought, only by being related to a consciousness capable
of error.” The double meaning of the logical norm, its validity per se, that is
its “objective” validity, . . . and its validity for us corresponds to the objective
validity of the legal norm claimed by me, and its subjective validity which
might better be called “efficacy”. . . . The Ought is the suitable expression
precisely for this objective validity of the logical law, the validity per se;
accordingly, Windelband himself emphasizes that this Ought expresses the
demarcation of logic against psychology. (Kelsen 1922a: 206–8, my transla-
tion, italics added)
values. Both run the danger of falling prey to Platonism; this problem was
discussed in the first part.30 Not so Kelsen: For him, the Ought is an adequate
expression of this kind of objective normativity; he thinks that the psychological
connotations of the Ought are taken care of by distinguishing between norma-
tive validity and factual efficacy (in the special sense of the meaning-content
being in sufficient degree embodied in psychic acts). He adds that there is no
individual who the legal norm is directed at, anyway; after all, the hypothetical
normative judgment of legal science has no addressee.
I tend to think that Kelsen is right. There is, however, a problem. Equating the
Ought with normative validity results in a peculiar duplication of the Ought. On
the one hand, the legal Ought is identical with the cognitive category of
peripheral imputation, which is at work inside the hypothetical judgment of
the Rechtssatz. On the other hand, the Ought is identical with the validity of the
Rechtssatz as a judgment, which is a matter of its logical existence. This kind of
30
See Section 2.3.3
42 Philosophy of Law
Kelsen does not clearly distinguish between these two types of Ought; and he
sometimes, as in the passages cited above, seems to hold that the validity-Ought
is quite enough to guarantee the autonomy of legal science.31 This is distantly
echoed in some less characteristic passages where Kelsen maintains that the
Ought is just a formal marker, the ladder to get into the legal system; once you
are inside, it makes no sense to speak of Ought and of the dualism of Is and
Ought.32 That, in turn, is vaguely reminiscent of the neo-Kantian notion that law
as a social and cognitive practice is ‘given,’ that is, ‘always there,’ and that the
legal Ought is problematic only ‘from the outside,’ or from the level of meta-
theory.
thinks that you ought to act in a certain way; rather, you really ought to act in
a certain way. Thus, validity and objectivity of the norm coincide.
This seems, at first sight, to be at odds with Kelsen’s assumption that there
can be no objective morality, that is, no objective ‘absolute’ Ought. For he is
quite adamant on this point. In Reine Rechtslehre, he holds that, from the
perspective of rational cognition, justice as part of social morality is just
a compromise between conflicting interests. This compromise is a matter of
will, not of reason (Kelsen 1992: 16–18 [Kelsen 1934: 15–16]). There is no
practical reason, and there can be no absolute morality.
31
When dealing with Max Weber in Staatsbegriff, however, Kelsen seems to argue (not quite
convincingly) the other way round: Validity is not Ought1, rather, Ought2 is validity, so that the
normative meaning of an ideology seems to guarantee its validity; see Kelsen 1922b: 162.
32
Cf. Kelsen 1920: 10 fn. (It is a peculiarity of Problem der Souveränität that the footnotes are
often more significant than the main text. Kelsen had the text more or less finished in 1916, but
publication was delayed until 1920, and some of the notes seem to have been added in the
meantime. So the book mirrors Kelsen’s ‘thought in progress.’)
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 43
The judgments of legal science are the best we can get, if we want to find out
what the law is, and if the judgments of legal science are valid, certain
presuppositions hold.
3.2.5 Relations between Norms: the Legal Hierarchy and the Basic Norm
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
33
Kelsen calls it “Grundnorm” but actually, in the hierarchy of meta-levels, it is the highest norm of
the legal system – if it belongs to the legal system at all.
44 Philosophy of Law
general norms, in turn, are valid if they are issued in accordance with the
constitution. The validity of a given constitution may be derived from its being
issued in accordance with an earlier constitution; but once the justifying
process arrives at the historically first constitution, it will be impossible to
find a higher ‘positive’ norm which might invest it with validity. In this case,
Kelsen says, any jurist presupposes a norm which is the ground for the validity
of the highest positive legal norm. This nonpositive presupposed norm is
called “Grundnorm,” that is, basic norm.
Neither conception originated with Kelsen alone. Even though there were
indications of it in Kelsen’s earlier work, the conception of a basic norm was
mainly developed by Alfred Verdross and Leonid Pitamic, while the
Stufenbautheorie was developed by Adolf J. Merkl – as Kelsen himself
acknowledges (Kelsen 1998a: 13 [Kelsen 1923: XV]). Ironically, both theorems
are, on the one hand, often regarded as major achievements of Kelsen’s theory,
and on the other, they do not work flawlessly – they are not part of the Pure
Theory ‘at its best.’ They are not, however, necessary ingredients of Kelsen’s
normativism; so I will confine myself to a few remarks.
Both conceptions are expressive of Begründungsdenken, or the principle of
sufficient reason. Even in the first phase, Kelsen maintained that there are in
principle endless chains of deriving an Is, via causal laws, from another Is, and
of deriving an Ought from another Ought. But he did not elaborate this, and he
did not explain how an Ought might be derived from another Ought. This
explanation seems, for the legal sphere, to be achieved by the theory of the
Stufenbau. But is it?
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
a true judgment in a logical sense is the same as a fact,34 and there is nothing
against saying that one can bring about (normative) facts. In this case, the higher
norm is a meta-level rule. Simplified, it has a form somewhat like:
and validity, meaning the form of the material when construed into a valid
logical judgment. The logical creation of the law (meaning, of course, the law
of legal science, the Rechtssätze) from the basic norm proceeds step by step
and under constant reference to a parallel fact. (Kelsen 1922a: 214–15, my
translation)
And Kelsen even employs the specific Kantian terminology of the norm as
a “Schema” for interpreting empirical material given to legal science (although
he seems to have borrowed the term from Max Weber) (Kelsen 1992: 10
[Kelsen 1934: 5]).
A problem with this version is that Kelsen sometimes comes close to saying
that the empirical law-giving act, as a performative, is somehow transformed
into a norm by applying the higher norm as an interpretive scheme (Kelsen
1925: 249). This is not, of course, the case; the performative is just ‘triggering’
34
Cf. Frege 1986: 33: “Was ist eine Tatsache? Eine Tatsache ist ein Gedanke, der wahr ist” (What is
a fact? A fact is a thought which is true.)
46 Philosophy of Law
the norm. The fact which is interpreted as giving rise to law is part of evaluated
reality; it is a ‘legal act,’ but not a norm.
But no matter which version we prefer, is the Stufenbau of law really a matter
of deriving one norm from another, a question of a ‘chain’ of validity or Ought?
In the case of Is, or causality, it is indeed possible to construct a chain by stating
that a causes b, b causes c, c causes d, and so on. But there seems to be no
equivalent for such a chain in the legal sphere.35 The lower norm is not
determined or ‘grounded’ by the higher norm alone. Without the performative
of the law-giving act, there would be no ‘derived’ norm. Accordingly, the Is-
sphere and the Ought-sphere seem to mingle. Kelsen tries to get out of this
predicament by saying that all empirical factors can just be the conditio sine qua
non for the norm’s validity, while the higher norm is the conditio per quam
(Kelsen 1920: VI); but this is not really convincing. If the higher norm were
a sufficient condition for the lower norm’s validity (that is, existence), then it
would be possible to deduce the lower norm from the higher norm. It is more
plausible when Kelsen maintains, as in the passage cited above, that the lower
norm gets its content from empirical acts, while it gets its validity from a higher
norm. But this is metaphorical and vague, and in the end it comes down to the
meta-level conception of the legal hierarchy: The higher norm is a meta-rule
according to which, under certain conditions, the content of certain utterances or
performatives is, or contributes to, a valid norm. It is a ‘bridging principle,’
sewing together Is and Ought.
Another major innovation in this phase is the introduction of the basic norm.
There is abundant literature concerning this specific concept,36 but as it is not
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
35
In fact, Kelsen holds the endless causal chain to be the analogue of the chain of central
imputation (imputing an act to a person, see Section 3.2.7); central imputation, however, always
ends somewhere (Kelsen 1968a: 134–5).
36
For two prominent examples, see Paulson 2000 and Raz 1974.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 47
a norm comes to an end for the lack of another higher positive criterion for valid
norms, presupposes a norm according to which the content of a performative –
be it custom or the intentional act of someone or a group exerting factual
power – counts as the highest legal norm, that is, as constitution (Kelsen
1992: 56–7 [Kelsen 1934: 65–6]). But why should this be necessary?
Famously, H. L. A. Hart held the basic norm to be a needless reduplication
(Hart 1961: 246). If the neo-Kantian task of the Pure Theory is to reconstruct the
intellectual content of a given sociocultural practice claiming normativity and
objectivity, why not just say that inside this practice the constitution (or, what
amounts to the same thing, its validity) is regarded as an axiom, that is, as an
assumed nonverifiable judgment naming the highest criteria for validity inside
the system?
For Kelsen, there are several possible reasons why this might not be suffi-
cient. First, law, according to Kelsen, is only positive law; that is, any legal norm
must get its content from a factual act which is in accordance with a ‘higher’
norm. So, for the constitution to be positive law, it must ‘rest’ on a performative,
which fulfills the conditions for being norm-triggering, named in a yet higher
norm; this higher norm cannot be a positive norm, it can only be presupposed as
a basic norm. Second, the practice legal cognition is embedded in only takes the
constitution to be valid if it adheres to a legal system which is effective and
regularly applied in a way that takes the constitution to contain the highest
criteria of legal validity. So the basic norm is necessary to capture the legal
system’s being conditioned by its efficacy – sometimes Kelsen even seems to
identify it with the principle of efficacy.37 Third, the ‘positive’ constitution often
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
consists of disparate provisions, posited both by those who had the power to do
so and by custom. To unify these provisions and, thus, the law, it is necessary to
presuppose a norm under whose antecedent they can be subsumed as highest
criteria for legal validity. This, in turn, is necessary so that law is a system and
possible object of science.
On the other hand, and this is mainly responsible for the vast literature concern-
ing the basic norm, Kelsen holds that it is the (or a) “transcendental-logical
condition” (transzendental-logische Bedingung) for legal cognition, and thus for
law; or a “hypothesis” in the sense of Cohen and Plato, that is, a fundamental
constitutive element (Grundlegung) posited by cognition (Kelsen 1998b: 174).
This is argued for by Kelsen in the following well-known passage:
In formulating the basic norm, the Pure Theory of Law . . . aims simply to
raise to the level of consciousness what all jurists are doing (for the most part
unwittingly) when, in conceptualizing their object of enquiry, they reject
37
See Section 3.2.6.
48 Philosophy of Law
natural law as the basis of the validity of positive law, but nevertheless
understand the positive law as a valid system, that is, as norm, and not merely
as factual contingencies of motivation. With the doctrine of the basic norm,
the Pure Theory analyses the actual process of the long-standing method of
cognizing positive law, in an attempt simply to reveal the transcendental
logical conditions of that method. (Kelsen 1992: 58 [Kelsen 1934: 67–8])
Is this rather high-flown claim justified? In part, it is, and in part, it is not. For
Kantian philosophy, transcendental-logical conditions are those conditions of cog-
nition which make reference to objects possible. They are the categories of
understanding which might be found, according to Kant, by taking the table of
judgments as a guideline; so, for Kelsen, who levels out the difference between
cognitive judgment and cognitional object and only takes into account hypothetical
judgments, they are identical with the ‘connector’ inside these judgments.
Peripheral imputation, the specific legal Ought constituting the hypothetical judg-
ment of the Rechtssatz, is such a category of relation. It might truly be said to be
a transcendental-logical condition. The basic norm, on the other hand, is not
identical with the category of Ought; rather, it is a presupposed, most fundamental
rule offering criteria for legal validity. And if one takes a closer look, it is not really
an applicable criteria-rule, but just a necessary go-along if one takes the constitution
to be valid. There is no real equivalent for this function in Kantian philosophy, and
to call the basic norm a transcendental-logical condition is at least oblique. Yet, as
shown, neo-Kantianism tends to downgrade transcendental philosophy to a critical
meta-theory of scientifical practice, that is, a critical analysis of the presuppositions
of the established sciences – those implicit nonfactual conditions which are neces-
sary to make it possible. Nothing speaks against taking the basic norm to be
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Is-elements are the conditio sine qua non of Ought-elements, but not their
conditio per quam (Kelsen 1920: 97 fn.; Kelsen 1925: 14). The empirical acts
which ‘bear’ the abstract meaning-contents are “parallel phenomena” in a different
dimension which necessarily conditions them (Kelsen 1920: 16). Talk of necessary
and sufficient conditions, in this context, is again a bit awkward; the problem of
“parallel phenomena” in different dimensions can be more aptly captured by the
notion of ‘supervenience’: An element a supervenes upon an element b, if there
cannot be a difference in a without a difference in b.38 Applied to law, and put
somewhat sloppily: There cannot be a change in the legal sphere without a change
in empirical reality.39 More importantly, Kelsen would probably have done better to
distinguish, in this context, not only two, but three different phenomena: the
abstract content as such, the empirical (neurological or psychical) act as such,
and the immanent content of the psychical act – in the way Rickert did, and in spite
of the (solvable) problems Rickert had. No doubt, the immanent content is always
accompanied by the act itself; and we cannot imagine any difference in it while the
psychic act, or its neurological counterpart, remains the same. But does Pythagoras’
theorem really ‘disappear’ when it is not thought of, and can we not imagine that it
is accompanied by very different psychical or neurological processes?
(2) A legal norm comes into existence, that is, gains validity, only as the result of
empirical norm-positing acts. Either there must be a custom, a habitual applica-
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
(3) The validity of legal norms is conditioned by the fact that the legal system
as a whole is effective (or, rather, not ineffective); either the majority of norms
should be complied with in general, or the norms should be applied by the
bodies responsible to exert coercion.40 Kelsen’s argument why this should be
38
See, for example, Bennett and McLaughlin 2018.
39
Recently, Monika Zalewska applied supervenience theory specifically to Pure Theory concep-
tions. In Zalewska 2020a: 87–8, she interprets the relation between the basic norm and the
efficacy of the fundamental rules of the legal system as one of supervenience; in Zalewska
2020b, she interprets peripheral imputation (208–10) and the connection between act of will and
legal norm (211) as relations of supervenience. She couples these interpretations with an
ambitious attempt to gain material results from them, like the principle of equality.
40
It is not easy to explain how a ‘higher norm’ validating a lower norm might be efficacious;
possibly, the best solution is to say that it is efficacious if it is used by the individuals empowered
by the legal system to posit norms and to execute sanctions as an interpretive scheme for
validating norms.
50 Philosophy of Law
the case is, however, rather diffuse. In Problem der Souveränität, he maintains
that the principle of efficacy follows from an extralegal principle, namely, the
principle of economy of thought (Kelsen 1920: 98–9). This principle demands
that using a legal system to interpret human actions must find that most actions are
in accordance with it; otherwise, it could not function as an interpretive scheme.
The problem with this argument is that it cannot explain why law, which Kelsen
takes to be an autonomous normative structure, must be used as an interpretive
scheme in this way at all. In the first edition of Reine Rechtslehre he circumvents
this problem in a peculiar way by pointing to the fact that the principle of efficacy
is part of international law; so, as a positive norm of international law, it is at the
same time the basic norm of any municipal order (Kelsen 1992: 61 [Kelsen 1934:
70–2]). And sometimes Kelsen insinuates, quite correctly, that the efficacy
condition is due to legal dogmatics choosing to deal only with those legal orders
that are effective (Kelsen 1920: 94).
(6) There are, however, two cases where, contraintuitively, Ought and Is are not
related. First, the Ought does not ‘aim’ at an Is. The system of legal norms is
self-contained and neither capable nor in need of being realised (Kelsen 1922a:
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 51
[T]he view of the legal theorist, which is just as much diverted from the
proper object of his cognizance – the legal norm – to other areas of cognition
as it is marred by hypostatizations and fictions causing pseudo-problems,
cannot get at its original object which is veiled by the desire for visualization,
habitual ways of thinking and complacency of thought. Metaphors are solidi-
fied into independent entities, mere protheses of thought are posited as
realities. They are like ghosts obstructing juridical cognition. (Kelsen 1920:
IV, my translation)
If one deprives the norm or the “ought” of meaning, then there will be no
meaning in the assertions that something is legally allowed, something is
legally prescribed, this belongs to me, that belongs to you, X has a right to do
this, Y is obligated to do that, and so on. In short, all the thousands of
statements in which the life of the law is manifest daily will have lost their
significance. (Kelsen 1992: 33 [Kelsen 1934: 35])
41
See especially Kelsen 1941.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 53
To see what the turn in Kelsen’s theory around 1940 amounts to, it is instructive
to compare two short programmatic writings, one from the neo-Kantian phase
and one from the realist phase: Kelsen’s foreword to the second edition of
Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre (1923), on the one hand, and The Pure
Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence (1941), on the other (both are
easily accessible in English). According to its foreword, Hauptprobleme
takes as its point of departure the fundamental dichotomy between Sollen and
Sein [Ought and Is]. . . . Following Wilhelm Windelband’s and Georg
Simmel’s interpretation of Kant, I take the “ought” as the expression for the
autonomy of law – with the law to be determined by legal science – in
contradistinction to a social “is” that can be comprehended “sociologically”.
The norm qua ought-judgment, then, is contrasted with the law of nature, and
the reconstructed legal norm (Rechtssatz), understood as a norm qua ought-
judgment, is contrasted with the law of causality that is specific to sociology.
42
See Paulson 1988a.
54 Philosophy of Law
For me, therefore, the core problem becomes the reconstructed legal norm,
understood as the expression of the specific lawfulness, the autonomy, of the
law. . . . And from this point of view, the law that is the subject-matter of legal
science emerges as a system of reconstructed legal norms, that is to say, as
a series of judgments. In the same way, nature – the subject-matter of natural
science – represents for transcendental philosophy a system of judgments.
(Kelsen 1998a: 4–5)43
According to the earlier text, legal norms are constituted by, or identical with,
the normative judgments of legal science. According to the later text, it is of the
“greatest importance” to confine jurisprudence to “describing” the legal norms
which are “given” to it.
But it is not only commonsense realism which is the more or less tacit
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
43
There is a caveat concerning Paulson’s translation: Rendering “Rechtssatz” as “reconstructed
legal norm” conceals the fact that the Rechtssatz, though identical with the legal norm, is
constituted as a logical judgment by legal science and that there is no normativity prior to the
Rechtssatz; so it is not a matter of reconstruction, but of constitution. For my own translation see
Section 3.2.4.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 55
(2) The status of the legal norm becomes hazy. Although Kelsen defines ‘norm’ as
the meaning of an intentional act directed at human behavior (Kelsen 2005: 4–5
[Kelsen 1960: 4]), he neither explains what ‘meaning’ comes up to in a realist
context, nor elucidates how the (objective) meaning of an intentional act can
become the object of a cognitive judgment. Besides, the counterpart of the legal
norm in the sphere of Is becomes doubtful. In the neo-Kantian phase, the (general)
legal norm and the causal law, as hypothetical judgments, were juxtaposed. Now it
seems as if the empirical fact from causally ordered reality is the equivalent of the
norm in the sphere of Is, while the natural law is part of the cognitive level – its
counterpart in the Ought-sphere is the Rechtssatz, which is now defined as the
judgment of legal science describing the legal norm.44
(3) The possibility of a logic of norms gets problematic. Kelsen assumes that the
rules of logic are effective between norms “indirectly,” that is, mediated by the
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
sentences describing the norms (Kelsen 2005: 205–6 [Kelsen 1960: 210]); but this
solution is rather absurd. It seems to be a remnant of the neo-Kantian epistemology,
but it is not compatible with holding that norms are “given” to cognition.
(4) The status of the basic norm becomes ambivalent: On the one hand, it is part of
the sphere of objects, because it is a norm which is described by the major premise
of a syllogism establishing the validity of the constitution;45 on the other hand, it
does not rest on an intentional act directed toward human behavior, but on an act of
thinking, and it is not the object, but a presupposition of legal cognition (Kelsen
2005: 9–10, 23 [Kelsen 1960: 9, 23]). These aspects are scarcely compatible with
each other; the basic norm does not make much sense in a realist context.
44
This is not clear, however. See Kelsen 2005: 76 (Kelsen 1960: 80), for the natural law being
placed on the cognitive level, and Kelsen 2005: 75 (Kelsen 1960: 78), for the causal principle
being at work in nature.
45
See Section 3.3.5.
56 Philosophy of Law
(5) In addition, the role of legal science becomes questionable. On the one hand,
it is restricted to describing the legal norms given to it; on the other hand, the
legal norms are just the result of an interpretation by the legal scientist (Kelsen
2005: 45–7 [Kelsen 1960: 46–8]). It is difficult to see how these tenets might go
together.
Even though Kelsen’s engagement with the results of modern physics and cultural
history had shattered his belief that causality and imputation were original and
equal-ranking categories of cognition, he does not express his doubts in the main
text of this period, Reine Rechtslehre (1960). And the dualism, for him, is still one
of the manifestations of the more fundamental dualism of Is and Ought. But it
loses importance and, without its defining neo-Kantian context, is somehow an
alien element in Kelsen’s theory. He has difficulty in ascribing imputation either
to the sphere of objects or to the level of cognition. According to some passages, it
is a connection on the level of the norms themselves (Kelsen 2005: 77–8 [Kelsen
1960: 81]); in other places, it appears to be a connection on the level of norma-
tively interpreted reality (Kelsen 2005: 76 [Kelsen 1960: 79]). According to
a third explanation, imputation is a principle which is applied when describing
a normative order of human behavior (Kelsen 2005: 76 [Kelsen 1960: 79]), while
causality rather connects the elements making up nature and is described by the
natural laws (Kelsen 2005: 75 [Kelsen 1960: 78]). Yet this would not be coherent.
If cognition is just a descriptive isomorphous reproduction of a world ‘given’ to it,
then a description of a norm cannot employ the principle of imputation, unless
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
46
Thus, other than in the second phase, the legal norm has an addressee.
47
On this topic, see especially Paulson 1988b.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 57
Basically, the general norm says that, under certain conditions, somebody
is empowered to exert coercion. How can somebody be empowered to exert
coercion? Kelsen distinguishes two ways of conceiving the general norm
(Kelsen 2005: 57, 231 [Kelsen 1960: 57–8, 237]). From a “dynamic” per-
spective, the law is a hierarchy of norms. General norms constitute just one
of several levels; they decree that under certain conditions a judge is
empowered to issue an individual norm. “Empowerment” in this case
means that the judge is able to bring about the conditions for the individual
norm (the sentence she pronounces) to be valid; so this empowerment does
not directly concern the exercise of coercion as a brute act but only the
ordering of an act of coercion. From a “static” perspective, comparable to
the conception of Hauptprobleme, there is just one level of law, the level of
heavily inflated (because they contain all conditions for legally exercising
coercion) general norms that run, in simplified form, something like:
tive function of legal norms. There is a direct line from attributing an act – as
a legal act – to the constructed person of the state as ‘willed’ by it, in the first
phase of Kelsen’s theory, via peripheral imputation, as the relation between
condition and sanction inside the Rechtssatz in the second phase, to
empowerment, as bestowing the capacity to bring about the conditions to
make a lower norm valid or to vest an act with the property of being a legal
act.
distinction is scarcely argued for, and Kelsen does not make a similar differ-
entiation for the sphere of Is.48
Another differentiation makes more sense. Kelsen distinguishes
a “subjective” Ought from an “objective” Ought. This distinction is an
advancement of a similar differentiation from the neo-Kantian phase:
According to Kelsen’s writings before 1940, the nonnormative material
given to legal cognition to be formed into a norm is the content of some
human act which claims to have normative impact according to its “self-
interpretation.” This is its “subjective” meaning. Its “objective” meaning,
that is, whether it really gives rise to an Ought, is a matter of its interpretation
in the light of a valid norm (Kelsen 1992: 9–10 [Kelsen 1934: 2–5]). In
a similar vein, the “objective Ought,” according to Kelsen in 1960, is the
“valid” ought, the “real” Ought, which is given if it is not only claimed that
something ought to be done, but if something really ought to be done.49 The
subjective Ought is given – this is the most plausible interpretation if one
considers the genesis of this conception – if it is (only) claimed that something
ought to be done. According to another interpretation, a subjective Ought is
given if someone wants somebody else to behave in a certain way.50 The
subjective Ought is bound to an intentional act, whose meaning it is, while the
objective Ought is valid even if it is no longer backed by an intentional act
(Kelsen 2005: 7–8 [Kelsen 1960: 7]).
So, the underdetermined concept of validity indeed seems to bear the brunt in
dragging Kelsen’s notion of “objective normativity” through the realist phase
without succumbing either to naturalism or to Platonism. This is reminiscent of
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
48
The distinction makes sense on a linguistic level: A prescriptive Ought might, cum grano salis,
be said to be involved in those performatives which are uttered in order to bring a norm in to
existence, while the descriptive Ought would be contained in assertions of a valid norm which do
not aim to ‘bring it about.’
49
Kelsen 2005: 7–8 (Kelsen 1960: 7–8). The German original contains a footnote in which Kelsen
declares that he could also have chosen the expression “real Ought” to denote the objective
Ought, if it had not been for the connotation of the expression “real” (tatsächlich) which point to
the sphere of Is.
50
This is implied by Kelsen’s most famous example of a (solely) subjective Ought: the command
of a criminal to hand over money; cf. Kelsen 2005: 44 (Kelsen 1960: 46).
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 59
describing the relation between higher and lower norm, and he maintains that this
relation can be captured in the form of a syllogism. On the other hand, he brings
forward the odd thesis, mentioned in Section 3.3.2, that logical relations are at work
between the given norms not directly, but indirectly, mediated by the judgments or
statements about the norms. The (statement of the) higher norm plays the role of the
major premise in this syllogism, determining factual conditions for the existence or
validity of the lower norm. The minor premise is the (statement of the) fact
fulfilling these conditions; the conclusion is the (statement of the) lower norm. In
Kelsen's own words:
The foundation of the validity of a positive norm, that is, one established by
an act of will and prescribing a certain behaviour, is the result of a syllogistic
procedure. In this syllogism, the major premise is the assertion about a norm
regarded as objectively valid, according to which one ought to obey the
commands of a certain person, that is, one ought to behave according to the
subjective meaning of these commands; the minor premise is the assertion of
the fact that this person has commanded to behave in a certain way; and the
conclusion is the assertion of the validity of the norm: that one ought to
behave in this particular way. Thus the norm whose validity is stated in the
major premise legitimizes the subjective meaning of the command, whose
existence is asserted in the minor premise, as the command’s objective
meaning. (Kelsen 2005: 202 [Kelsen 1960: 205])
The main flaw of this passage has been mentioned: The idea of an “indirect”
logic of norms is absurd; there is no way that a norm understood as
a nonpropositional entity in a realist sense could be subjected to a propositional
calculus. This apart, there are two possible ways of reconstructing the syllogism.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
According to the first, the major premise, simplified, would run as follows:
This is comparable to the conception of the preceding phase: The higher norm
would not be a norm in the usual sense, but a rule of a meta-level that states
criteria for a lower norm to be valid, or, what amounts to the same, for a statement
about a norm to be true. According to the second reconstruction, the higher norm
does not just state general validity conditions; rather, it directly establishes an
Ought for the addressees of the lower norms. Simplified, it runs as follows:
If the legislator (or some other body) has, under certain conditions,
commanded you to do a, then you ought to do a.
This sounds more like a genuine norm. However, either the lower norm is
superfluous or the Ought is, again, reduplicated. If ‘Oa’ can be inferred from '(If c,
then Oa), and c,’ then there is no normative surplus in it. After all, a syllogism
60 Philosophy of Law
does not create ‘new’ truths; it just makes explicit conceptual relations. This
seems to be different in the meta-level reconstruction, because the meta-level rule
does not contain an Ought. Besides, only the meta-level reconstruction seems to
capture the feature that the Ought-function, on all levels of the hierarchy, is
empowering (not commanding).
Anyway, neither reconstruction really corresponds to what one would nor-
mally expect a derivation of an Ought from another Ought to look like, and both
express the necessary role of ‘higher’ rules – no matter whether they are norms
or meta-rules – in naming factual criteria for the existence of lower norms.
Positivistic normativism is not possible without such rules.
Even though the basic norm, as the highest (or most fundamental) norm,
survives Kelsen’s turn to realism seemingly unscathed, it is, like imputation, an
alien element in the realist phase. It is described by the major premise of the
most fundamental syllogism in the legal hierarchy, establishing the validity of
the constitution. It is still called a “hypothesis” (Kelsen 1957b: 260–2) and
a “transcendental-logical condition,” the latter with the restriction that this term
is used per analogiam (Kelsen 2005: 201–2 [Kelsen 1960: 203–5]). But it is
difficult to see what this analogy might look like. Transcendental-logical con-
ditions are only conceivable as necessary conditions of cognition; having
a system of ‘given’ legal norms depend on a presupposition of cognition is,
however, contradictory. Either the norms are given to cognition, but then they
cannot depend on a quasi-transcendental-logical condition; or they depend on
a condition of thinking, but then they are not ‘given’ to cognition.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Compared to the second phase, there are several changes concerning possible
relations between Is and Ought.
First, the theory of the “indifferent substrate” is not dropped, but neglected.
Kelsen just vaguely talks of a “something” which either might be the case, or
ought to be the case, as the possible common or comparable content of Is and
Ought (Kelsen 2005: 6 [Kelsen 1960: 6]).
Second, the norm, as an objective meaning-content, is conditioned by, or the
meaning of, an intentional act, which belongs to the Is-sphere and is directed at
somebody else’s behavior (Kelsen 2005: 4–6 [Kelsen 1960: 4–6]). It is not quite
clear what Kelsen means by an “intentional act.” Considering his philosophical
background, one might reasonably assume that the term is borrowed from
Husserl’s philosophy. For Husserl, an intentional act is a psychic act directed
at some (propositional or nonpropositional) object. So a norm is the meaning of
a psychic act directed at the propositional object “that someone acts in a certain
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 61
way.”51 Sometimes, Kelsen seems to hold that such an act is an act of will. But
this would contradict his former theses that one might only will one’s own
behavior, that norms are not necessarily connected with a ‘real’ act of will, and
that possibly there is no psychic function of willing at all which is not
a normative construct.52 And Kelsen does not maintain that being the meaning
of an act of will is a necessary feature of any norm. Apart from the possibility of
deducing norms from other norms, there is the counterexample of the basic
norm which is the meaning of an “act of thinking” (Kelsen 1960: 9).53 Besides,
it is not reasonable to condition the legal norm on an internal act of will; it is
more plausible to condition it on the expression of a corresponding will. And
this is exactly what Kelsen does in several passages.54
However this may be, the norm, as an Ought, has to be strictly distinguished
from the act whose meaning it is. The statement that somebody ought to do a,
cannot, for Kelsen, be reduced to the statement that somebody else wants this
somebody to do a (Kelsen 2005: 5 [Kelsen 1960: 4]). And Kelsen maintains that
This passage marks a central point where Kelsen’s writings of the third phase
differ from those of the fourth phase: He considers it possible to think of a norm
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
51
It must be noted, though, that this interpretation is at odds with Kelsen’s position, in this phase, of
avoiding tagging the norm as an abstract entity.
52
On Kelsen’s changing opinions concerning the concept of will, see Section 3.4.4.
53
Kelsen changed the relevant passage for the English translation which was published during the
previous phase; in Kelsen 2005: 9–10, he maintains that it is impossible to think of a norm
without thinking, along with it, of the act of will whose meaning it is.
54
Cf. Kelsen 2005: 5 (Kelsen 1960: 4): “If an individual by his acts expresses a will directed at
a certain behaviour of another, that is to say if he commands, permits or authorizes such
behaviour – then the meaning of his acts cannot be described by the statement that the other
individual will (future tense) behave in that way, but only that he ought to behave in that way”
(my emphasis).
62 Philosophy of Law
it was not subsequently carried out. This problem seems to be related to the
problem of how Kelsen can account for customary law in his theory; however, it
need not be pursued in this context.
Fourth, as shown, other than in the second phase, the (primary, independent)
legal norm has an addressee, namely, the empowered individual.
might be possible that logical rules define the relations not only between judg-
ments about norms, but also, mediated by these judgments, between the norms
themselves (Kelsen and Klug 1981: 48–9). Independently from the exchange with
Klug, he also abandoned the thesis that a norm might be the meaning-content of
an act of thinking, and tied the norm strictly to an act of will: “no norm without an
act of will whose meaning it is” (Kelsen 1991: 234 [Kelsen 1979: 187]).
But there are more changes. Kelsen seems to have realized around 1960 that
his philosophical background might need to be updated and expanded, and he
gathered material from innumerable contemporary sources – especially from
linguistic philosophy, moral philosophy, and logics – to undergird his
conceptions.55 But his theory remains something of a patchwork. This is, in
part, due to the fact that there is no comprehensive monograph dealing with it as
a whole. An exception seems to be Allgemeine Theorie der Normen (General
55
On the literature studied by Kelsen, see Opałek 1980: 11–18.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 63
3.4.1 Foundations
The times of philosophical austerity are past; the foundations of the Pure
Theory are fleshed out, once more, albeit in different directions. First, Kelsen
sticks to the commonsensical realism from the third phase – again, without
elaborating it: “As a science, legal science can only know and describe the
norms which are given to it” (Kelsen 1991: 153 [Kelsen 1979: 123]). But at the
same time, the sphere of ideality is rehabilitated; Kelsen no longer avoids
calling the validity of the norm its “ideal” existence (Kelsen 1968c: 150).
Second, Kelsen undergirds his theory with a theory of speech-acts on the one
hand, according to which norms are based on acts of “commanding” (Kelsen
1991: ch. 10 [Kelsen 1979: ch. 10]), and a theory of intentional acts, according
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
to which norms are based on psychic acts of will (Kelsen 1991: ch. 9 [Kelsen
1979: ch. 9]), on the other. This is supplemented by a semantic theory,
according to which norms and assertions are the meaning-contents of different
types of sentences.
(1) Sometimes Kelsen still denotes Is and Ought as “categories,” but he does not
explain these elements in terms of neo-Kantian philosophy. Instead, citing
Henry Sidgwick, he calls them “undefinable basic concepts.” And he still relies
on the “logical principle” that it is not possible to deduce a statement about
a norm from a statement about a fact (Kelsen 1991: 58 [Kelsen 1979: 44]).
64 Philosophy of Law
commanding, how could there possibly be some surplus quality which trans-
forms it into an ‘objective’ Ought, that is, morphs it into ‘one really ought to act
like this’? And what, actually, does it mean, in the will theory of norms, to say
that one ‘really’ ought to act in a certain way? Second, and connected with the
first point, what does ‘empowering’ mean if it does not somehow ‘legitimize’
the Ought claimed by someone; and can a ‘legitimate’ Ought mean anything but
that one ‘really’ ought to act in the way prescribed, so that the objective Ought
would, after all, be more fundamental?
Kelsen’s explanation of the concept of empowerment is rather ambiguous.
On the one hand, he still thinks that it is, in law, the primary normative function
(Kelsen 1991: 97 [Kelsen 1979: 77]); and he defines it as “conferring on an
individual the power to posit or apply norms” (Kelsen 1991: 102 [Kelsen 1979:
82–4]). But this seems to conflict with his general definition of the Ought as the
56
This follows from the thesis that every norm includes and is determined by a command; Kelsen
1991: 233–4 [Kelsen 1979: 186–7].
66 Philosophy of Law
There seem to be three ways of interpreting this passage: The first interpretation
is that the legal system consists of just one command, contained in the constitution
(or even in the basic norm), saying that one ought to obey the legislator (or the
authors of the constitution); all other norms are simply ‘technical rules’ stating what
one has to do if one wants to obey the constitution (or the basic norm). Or, on
a second interpretation, we have a curious duplication of commands; it is not only
the lawgivers who command that, for example, theft ought to be punished, but also
the authors of the constitution. Both reconstructions seem to be slightly strange, but
they are possible, of course. In both cases, empowerment could be reduced to the
function of commanding. Yet, in neither case would it make sense to distinguish
between a subjective and an objective Ought. Besides, as commanding or prescrib-
ing, in law, is just the function of secondary norms, there seems to be a logical
circle: The normative function of primary norms, empowering, can be reduced to
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Validity is not a property of the norm, but its existence” (Kelsen 1991: 171
[Kelsen 1979: 137]). And, as mentioned, Kelsen no longer avoids calling this
kind of existence “ideal.” It consists in that the norm should be complied with
or applied – independent of its recognition by the person to whom it is
addressed.57
All this is in accordance with most of what Kelsen said in the preceding
phases, but it is scarcely compatible with his strict will theory of norms. A norm
exists or is valid if one ‘really’ ought to act in the way it prescribes. This implies,
again, that the ‘objective’ Ought is the genuine Ought, while the subjective
Ought is just a purported or claimed Ought. In contradistinction, according to
the will theory the subjective Ought is fundamental; and the objective Ought is
a specially qualified subjective Ought.
This opaqueness is partly due to Kelsen not really offering a clear-cut concept
of an act of will; so this topic deserves a short digression. Three questions, in
particular, connected with the concept of will, are not answered clearly in any of
the phases of the Pure Theory:
(1) Is the act of will an internal psychic act, or is it the external expression of
someone to the effect that she wishes somebody to do something?
(2) Is the act of will necessary for the existence of the norm in the sense that the
norm only exists as long as there is an act of will as its ‘bearer,’ or is the act
of will just necessary to ‘trigger’ the existence of the norm, so that it is
possible that the norm exists while the act of will is no longer extant?
(3) Is the act of will part of the definition of the norm, or is it just a condition of
its existence?
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The most plausible solution, at least for the sake of reconstructing law, is
that the act of will is an external act, and that it is necessary only to ‘trigger’
the norm. The problem is that Kelsen, in this phase, sees a much closer
connection between Ought and will. Even in the neo-Kantian phase, he had
an ambiguous understanding of the concept of will. Sometimes he doubted
whether there could be something like a will which is not a normative con-
struct (Kelsen 1922b: 241–5). So the will might be reducible to normativity. In
other places, he took the will to be a purely psychic category (Kelsen 1922a:
182). In that case, will and Ought would be conceptually independent from
each other. Then again, he defined the Ought as an impersonal objective
willing (Kelsen 1920: 9 fn.), so that the will seems to at least partly define
the Ought.
57
But not independent of recognition altogether, cf. Kelsen, 1991: 3, 50–1 (Kelsen 1979: 3, 39–40).
68 Philosophy of Law
But if we take seriously Kelsen’s thesis from General Theory of Norms, that
‘Ought’ means that someone wants somebody else to act in a certain way, the
conclusion that Ought and willing are conceptually interwoven can hardly be
avoided. If we accept that, however, it would not make much sense to talk of
‘validity’ and of an ‘objective’ Ought; and the nature of empowerment would be
a mystery. Normativism, as propagated by Kelsen in the 1920s, would finally
have evaporated.
Further problems, where the status of empowerment is involved, are the relation
between a “higher” and a “lower” norm in the legal hierarchy, and the status of
the basic norm. On the one hand, Kelsen abandons the conception of an
“indirect” logic of norms – a logic that is mediated by the logic of the assertions
describing the norms; on the other hand, both his will theory of norms and the
conception of the norm as a nonpropositional object given to cognition seem to
58
That is how I read the chapter concerning Sigwart, see Kelsen 1991: 151–3 (Kelsen 1979: 121–
3).
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 69
make it impossible that there can be logical relations between norms at all
(Kelsen 1991: 211, 217 [Kelsen 1979: 166, 171]).59
Kelsen describes the relation between a higher and a lower norm vaguely as
one of “correspondence.” His explanation of the relation between a general
norm and an individual norm is instructive. Imagine a general norm as follows:
(2) But there is another individual norm involved. If the judge has ascertained
that Jones committed a theft, then it seems that she – or anyone – might at least
‘logically’ conclude, using modus ponens and the rule of substitution, that she
ought to decide that Jones ought to be imprisoned, so that there is a second
individual norm:
The judge ought to decide that Jones ought to be imprisoned for one to five
years.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
59
I cannot delve into the conception of the relation between norms and logic according to the
General Theory of Norms here. In short: Norms, in principle, are neither subject to the law of
noncontradiction nor to the rules of inference. But there can be logical relations between
concepts contained in norms, so that it is possible to derive a less general norm from a more
general norm. And hypothetical norms have a logical ‘if-then-structure’ (which apparently
doesn’t allow for the modus ponens to be applied; also, Kelsen is not quite clear on the point
whether this structure is part of the norm’s content or whether [the validity of] the norm itself is
conditioned). See Kelsen 1991: 249–50, 266–7 [Kelsen 1979: 201, 215–16].
60
For a depiction of this problem, see Heidemann 2000: 275–8.
70 Philosophy of Law
what Kelsen said when explaining the concept of validity; in that context, he
maintained that the norm’s validity was independent of its acceptance by the
individual subjected to it. Besides, it is scarcely compatible either with
normativism or with the way jurists talk about law and ascertain its validity;
it is ultimately expressive of a recognition theory of law.61
Finally, the basic norm is probably what first comes to the mind of most
legal theorists when asked what radical change occurred in Kelsen’s theory
after 1960. For Kelsen abandons the idea that the basic norm might be
a hypothesis, resting on an act of thought, and instead maintains that it is
a fiction in the sense of Hans Vaihinger’s philosophy of “As if,”62
a pragmatic mental tool to enable the grasp of phenomena that cannot be
understood by employing the given conceptual apparatus. Judgments pre-
supposing the existence of a fictive object are false, but they can be justified
by their pragmatic function. A “full fiction,” according to Vaihinger, contra-
dicts reality and, besides, it is self-contradictory. Kelsen holds that the basic
norm contradicts reality because there is no such thing; his new will theory
of norms affords that any norm is based on a real act of will, and there is
nothing like that to support the basic norm. It is also self-contradictory
because it authorizes a highest legal authority while, as a norm, presuppos-
ing a higher authority on whose (empowered) act of will it rests (Kelsen
1991: 256 [Kelsen 1979: 206–7]).
In this context, it is not necessary to deal with Vaihinger’s highly idiosyn-
cratic philosophy. A few remarks must suffice. First, the change is less
serious than it might appear at first sight. In Kelsen’s third phase, the basic
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
norm somehow oscillated between the cognitive level and the object level;
now it is taken to be a ‘feigned object,’ which is a clarification. Yet even as
a fiction, the basic norm is a presupposition of legal thinking; and Kelsen
does not stop labelling it as a transcendental-logical condition of legal
cognition (Kelsen 1968d: 1976). Regarding it as a fiction was occasioned
by the need to accommodate the act of will necessarily connected with every
norm. That is not an important matter; the real upheaval took place when
Kelsen started seeing a necessary connection between any Ought and
a factual act of will. Second, it is only the act of will the basic norm is
61
To be fair, this problem is not just brought about by the strict will theory of norms. It is also
a product of the combination, existent even in the third phase, of the thesis that the validity of
each single norm is dependent on its efficacy, and the problem of how an empowerment norm
might be effective.
62
Hans Vaihinger (1852–1933) started as a neo-Kantian. He wrote Die Philosophie des Als Ob over
several decades. The book, published in 1911 was a success; ten editions were produced (the last
in 1927). Like many neo-Kantian texts, it is slightly quixotic (indeed, on the brink of dubious-
ness), combining pragmatism, positivism, and idealism.
Hans Kelsen’s Normativism 71
supposed to rest upon which is not given in (natural) reality. So the (assump-
tion of the) basic norm contradicts reality only if the latter incorporates this
act of will in a way that it is part of the Is-and Ought-spheres at the same
time.63 Third, as norms, according to Kelsen in this phase, are not capable of
logical relations, how could the basic norm be self-contradictory? At best,
its content could be self-contradictory. But that would presuppose that
“being legitimized by a higher authority” was part of its content – which is
difficult to construct. It is more plausible to say that asserting the validity of
a basic norm contradicts normative reality64 and is self-contradictory,
because it entails that there is a norm which establishes a highest authority
while at the same time being legitimized by a yet higher authority. But even
in this interpretation, it is doubtful whether the basic norm is a full fiction.
For it just establishes the highest authority of positive law; nothing speaks
against it being theoretically validated by a yet higher nonlegal authority.
The most relevant new element in Kelsen’s theory on the relations between
Is and Ought has already been discussed: the tight conceptual connection
between the norm and an act of will. Besides, Kelsen still maintains that the
validity both of legal systems and of individual legal norms is conditioned by
their efficacy (Kelsen 1991: 139–40 [Kelsen 1979: 112–13]). The theory of
the “indifferent substrate,” developed in the second phase and somewhat
neglected in the third phase, is elaborated in the final phase. Discussing
authors such as Edmund Husserl, Richard M. Hare, and Jørgen Jørgensen,
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Kelsen maintains that this substrate is the meaning of an act of thinking that
is different from an assertion or a proposition. It is not modally formed and
must not be understood as being “descriptive” or “indicative.” An example
of a modally indifferent substrate would be a behavior that might actually be
the case (an Is-content) or which ought to be the case (an Ought-content)
(Kelsen 1991: 58-61 [Kelsen 1979: 44-7]): “‘Being-the-content-of-an-
Ought’ is the property of behaviour as modally indifferent substrate (just
as it is the property of a cherry-stone to be contained in a cherry” (Kelsen
1991: 61 [Kelsen 1979: 47]).
63
To be sure, if the act of will is not only a condition of the norm’s existence, but part of the concept
of a norm, then every norm would be a ‘chimera,’ a hybrid of an Ought-element and an Is-
element – something that Kelsen abhorred throughout his earlier writings.
64
This would, however, deviate from Kelsen’s conception which takes reality – in this phase, and
in the context of the basic norm – to be natural reality (Kelsen maintains that the basic norm
contradicts reality because the act of will connected with it is not given in reality).
72 Philosophy of Law
4 Summary
It is time for a short summary. Legal normativism may be defined as the view
that law is exclusively a system of (normative) rules which are objective and
impersonal, and which cannot be derived from any factuality. It is based on the
dualism of Is and Ought. Hume might be regarded as the progenitor of general
normativism because he pointed to the logical independence of (subjective)
practical sentences from empirical or theoretical sentences. Kant followed suit,
but he took practical sentences to be subjected to reason and, therefore, to be
objective. In addition, he saw a primacy of practical reason over theoretical
reason, and introduced normativity as indispensable for the operations of
understanding, that is, for the cognition of objects. Lotze gave an ontological
touch to this kind of theoretical Ought by holding that there are valid truths from
which an Ought, or rules to think in a certain way, emanate. This interpretation
was adopted by Windelband who took normativity in the form of values to be
a basic philosophical element, and excluded any psychologistic explanation of
cognition; at the same time, Windelband rather neglected the moral or practical
Ought. Rickert systematized Windelband’s approach. Ultimately, however, his
theory foundered on the antagonism between immanent Ought and transcendent
value.
In Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre (1911), Kelsen presents his theory
as a methodology of legal dogmatics. He distinguishes Ought from Is and
takes law to be completely a matter of Ought: Law is norm, and only those
legal concepts which can be shown to be constructions on the basis of legal
norms are legitimate. Kelsen identifies just one level of legal norms, the
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
The writings of the fourth phase, lasting until Kelsen’s death in 1973, can be
seen as an attempt to resolve the inconsistencies of the third phase. They are
characterized by a strict will theory of norms. For the first time in his career,
Kelsen maintains that any Ought or norm is impossible without an act of will as
its bearer. The will even seems to be part of the definition of the Ought. But this
is at odds with Kelsen’s assumption that the Ought is objective. Furthermore,
partly because of his will theory of norms and partly because of his sticking to
the thesis that norms are objects “given” to cognition, Kelsen abandons the
notion that there may be any direct or indirect logical relations between norms.
Normativism, which flourished abundantly in Kelsen’s neo-Kantian period, is
practically gone.
Finally, a very short appraisal. I hope to have shown that the general philo-
sophical normativistic approach can be well argued for. As Kant demonstrated,
in respect of the aim of preserving objectivity of cognition, it is the least
demanding alternative to an untenable position of philosophical realism accord-
ing to which cognition deals with a “world-in-itself.” Furthermore, normativism
74 Philosophy of Law
with its critical attitude, make up the never-ending topicality and fertility of the
Pure Theory.
References
Beiser, F. C. (2009). Normativity in Neo-Kantianism: Its Rise and Fall.
International Journal of Philosophical Studies (17), 9–27.
Beiser, F. C. (2013). Late German Idealism: Trendelenburg & Lotze. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Beiser, F. C. (2014). The Genesis of Neo-Kantianism, 1796–1880. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Bennett, K. and McLaughlin, B. (2018). Supervenience. In Stanford
Encyclopedia of Philosophy, https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/superveni
ence/ (accessed October 14, 2020).
Frege, G. (1986). Der Gedanke. In Gottlob Frege, Logische Untersuchungen,
ed. by G. Patzig, 3rd ed. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 30–53.
Habermas, J. (1999). Wahrheit und Rechtfertigung. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
Hart, H. L. A. (1961). The Concept of Law. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Heidemann, C. (1997). Die Norm als Tatsache. Zur Normentheorie Hans
Kelsens. Baden-Baden: Nomos Verlag.
Heidemann, C. (1999). Norms, Facts, and Judgments. A Reply to S. L. Paulson.
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies (19), 345–50.
Heidemann, C. (2000). The Creation of Normative Facts. Law and Philosophy
(19), 263–81.
Heidemann, C. (2007). Noch einmal: Stanley L. Paulson und Kelsens
urteilstheoretischer Normbegriff. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
(93), 345–62.
Heidemann, C. (2020). Das Faktum der Rechtswissenschaft bei Hans Kelsen. In
M. Jestaedt, R. Poscher, and J. Kammerhofer, eds., Die Reine Rechtslehre auf
dem Prüfstand. Hans Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law: Conceptions and
Misconceptions. Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag, 81–98.
Hoeschen, A. (1999). Das “Dostojewsky”-Projekt. Lukács neukantianisches
Frühwerk in seinem ideengeschichtlichen Kontext. Tübingen: de Gruyter.
Hume, D. (2007a). A Treatise of Human Nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hume, D. (2007b). An Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Husserl, E. (1900). Logische Untersuchungen, Vol. 1. Leipzig: Veit & Comp.
Kant, I. (1992). The Jäsche logic. In I. Kant, Lectures on Logic, trans. and ed. by
J. M. Young. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 521–640.
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of Pure Reason, trans. and ed. by P. Guyer and
A. W. Wood. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
76 References
Kant, I. (2002). Critique of the Power of Judgment, trans. and ed. by P. Guyer
and E. Matthews. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2004). Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics, trans. and ed. by
G. Hatfield. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kant, I. (2015). Critique of Practical Reason, trans. and ed. by M. Gregor,
revised ed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kelsen, H. (1911). Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre. Tübingen: Mohr.
Kelsen, H. (1920). Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des
Völkerrechts. Tübingen: Mohr.
Kelsen, H. (1922a). Rechtswissenschaft und Recht. Erledigung eines Versuchs
zur Überwindung der “Rechtsdogmatik.” ZöR (3), 103–235.
Kelsen, H. (1922b). Der soziologische und der juristische Staatsbegriff.
Tübingen: Mohr.
Kelsen, H. (1923). Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre, 2nd ed. Tübingen: Mohr.
Kelsen, H. (1925). Allgemeine Staatslehre. Berlin: Springer.
Kelsen, H. (1928a). Die philosophischen Grundlagen der Naturrechtslehre und
des Rechtspositivismus. Berlin: Pan-Verlag.
Kelsen, H. (1928b). Rechtsgeschichte gegen Rechtsphilosophie? Eine
Erwiderung. Vienna: Julius Springer.
Kelsen, H. (1934). Reine Rechtslehre. Einleitung in die rechtswissenschaftliche
Problematik. Leipzig and Vienna: Deuticke.
Kelsen, H. (1939). Die Entstehung des Kausalgesetzes aus dem
Vergeltungsprinzip. The Journal of Unified Science (Erkenntnis) 8, 69–130.
Kelsen, H. (1941). Vergeltung und Kausalität. The Hague: W. P. van Stockum.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Kelsen, H. (1968c). Die Problematik der Reinen Rechtslehre. ÖZöR (18), 143–84.
Kelsen, H. (1968d). Die Funktion der Verfassung. In H. Klecatsky, R. Marcic,
and H. Schambeck, eds., Die Wiener Rechtstheoretische Schule. Vienna:
Europa-Verlag, 1615–22.
Kelsen, H. (1979). Allgemeine Theorie der Normen, ed. by K. Ringhofer and
R. Walter. Viena: Manz.
Kelsen, H. (1991). General Theory of Norms, trans. by M. Hartney. Oxford:
Clarendon Press.
Kelsen, H. (1992). Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory, trans. and ed.
by B. Litschewski Paulson and S. L. Paulson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kelsen, H. (1998a). Foreword to Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre, trans. by
S. L. Paulson. In S. L. Paulson and B. Litschewski Paulson, eds., Normativity
and Norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 3–22.
Kelsen, H. (1998b) A Letter to Renato Treves, trans. by S. L. Paulson. In
S. L. Paulson and B. Litschewski Paulson, eds., Normativity and Norms.
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 169–76.
Kelsen, H. (2005). The Pure Theory of Law, trans. from the 2nd ed. by
M. Knight. Clark, NJ: The Lawbook Exchange.
Kelsen, H. (2006). Autobiographie (1947). In M. Jestaedt, ed., Hans Kelsen im
Selbstzeugnis. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Kelsen, H. and Klug, U. (1981). Rechtsnormen und logische Analyse. Ein
Briefwechsel 1959 bis 1965. Vienna: Deuticke.
Köhnke, K. C. (1993). Entstehung und Aufstieg des Neukantianismus.
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
Kubeš, V. (1980). Das neueste Werk Hans Kelsens über die allgemeine Theorie
der Normen und die Zukunft der Reinen Rechtslehre. ÖZöR (31), 155–99.
Lotze, H. (1841). Metaphysik. Leipzig: Weidmann’sche Buchhandlung.
Lotze, H. (1884). Logics, trans. and ed. by B. Bosanquet. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
McIntyre, A. C. (1959). Hume on “Is” and “Ought.” The Philosophical Review
(68), 451–68.
Merkl, A. J. (1917). Das Recht im Lichte seiner Auslegung. Deutsche
Richterzeitung (9), 162–76.
Nino, C. S. (1998). Some Confusions Surrounding Kelsen’s Concept of
Validity. In S. L. Paulson and B. Litschewski Paulson, eds., Normativity
and Norms. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 253–62.
Opałek, K. (1980). Überlegungen zu Hans Kelsens “Allgemeiner Theorie der
Normen.” Vienna: Manz.
Paulson, S. L. (1988a). Die Rezeption Kelsens in Amerika. In O. Weinberger
and W. Krawietz, eds., Die Reine Rechtslehre im Spiegel ihrer Fortsetzer und
Kritiker. Vienna and New York: Springer, 179–202.
78 References
Series Editors
George Pavlakos
University of Glasgow
George Pavlakos is Professor of Law and Philosophy at the School of Law, University of
Glasgow. He has held visiting posts at the universities of Kiel and Luzern, the European
University Institute, the UCLA Law School, the Cornell Law School and the Beihang Law
School in Beijing. He is the author of Our Knowledge of the Law (2007) and more recently has
co-edited Agency, Negligence and Responsibility (2021) and Reasons and Intentions in Law
and Practical Agency (2015).
Gerald J. Postema
University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill
Gerald J. Postema is Professor Emeritus of Philosophy at the University of North Carolina at
Chapel Hill. Among his publications count Utility, Publicity, and Law: Bentham’s Moral and
Legal Philosophy (2019); On the Law of Nature, Reason, and the Common Law: Selected
Jurisprudential Writings of Sir Matthew Hale (2017); Legal Philosophy in the Twentieth
Century: The Common Law World (2011), Bentham and the Common Law Tradition,
2nd edition (2019).
Kenneth M. Ehrenberg
University of Surrey
Kenneth M. Ehrenberg is Reader in Public Law and Legal Theory at the University of Surrey
School of Law and Co-Director of the Surrey Centre for Law and Philosophy. He is the author
of The Functions of Law (2016) and numerous articles on the nature of law, jurisprudential
methodology, the relation of law to morality, practical authority, and the epistemology of
https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108993661 Published online by Cambridge University Press
evidence law.
Associate Editor
Sally Zhu
University of Sheffield
Sally Zhu is a Lecturer in Property Law at University of Sheffield. Her research is on property
and private law aspects of platform and digital economies.