Weiming JenLivingMetaphor 1981
Weiming JenLivingMetaphor 1981
Author(s): Tu Wei-ming
Source: Philosophy East and West , Jan., 1981, Vol. 31, No. 1 (Jan., 1981), pp. 45-54
Published by: University of Hawai'i Press
REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
https://www.jstor.org/stable/1399065?seq=1&cid=pdf-
reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
University of Hawai'i Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to Philosophy East and West
To the modern inquirer who has been steeped in the art of arg
Confucius may appear to be "a prosaic and parochial moraliz
collected sayings "an archaic irrelevance." This initial response
become an unreflective fixity, if the inquirer is mainly concerned w
gical issues as matters of fact.4 Needless to say, a study geared only to
the stylistic nuances of the original text leaves many questions u
since "unasked questions are unlikely to be answered," the imp
Confucius was an outmoded ethical teacher, the study of whom
torically significant,6 will remain persistent. In what sense can C
understood and appreciated as, for example, in Fingarette's word
with profound insight and with an imaginative vision of man
grandeur to any I know" ?7
To begin, I would suggest that the mode of articulation in the
form of what Wayne C. Booth has forcefully argued for as "the
assent."8 In such a rhetorical situation, the internal lines of com
are predicated on a view of human nature significantly different fr
the scientismic assertion that ideally man is a rational atomic m
a universe that is value-free. Rather, the basic assumptions are
human beings come into existence through symbolic interchan
[T]he images of the inner man and of his inner conflict are not
concept of man as a being whose dignity is the consummation
subtlety and sophistication, a life in which human conduct can
in natural terms and yet be attuned to the sacred, a life in which t
the intellectual and the spiritual are equally revered and are h
in the one act-the act of li. 11
Although Confucius "rarely spoke of profit, fate, orjen," (9: 1) his recorded
remarks onjen by far surpass his comments on any other virtues in the Analects.
Of course, each recorded articulation on the subject is but a clue to the all-
inclusive virtue, or in Waley's words, the "mystic entity." 25 Among the hundred
and five references to jen in 58 out of 499 chapters of the Analects,26 there are,
to be sure, statements that appear to be conflicting or paradoxical assertions.
A mechanistic cataloging of these statements is not likely to develop a coherent
interpretation ofjen. A more elaborate strategy is certainly required.
First, we must not pass lightly over what seem to be only cliche virtues
either adversity or prosperity and that those who are jen rest con
those who are chih pursuejen with facility (4:2). The necessity forjen t
chih and the desirability for chih to reach jen is shown in a crucial pas
"even if a man's chili is sufficient for him to attain it, without jen to
will lose it again" (15:32).
Suggestively chih in the Analects may occasionally be put in a negati
to mean fragmented or nonessential knowledge (15:33); sometimes
of chih can convey a sense of receptivity and flexibility (9:7), and even
site, yii (stupidity or folly), may in extraordinary situations be a
a demonstration of inner strength (5:20). Jen, by contrast, is always u
as "Goodness" (Arthus Waley), "Human-heartedness" (E. R. Hughes),
"Love" (Derk Bodde), ."Benevolent Love" (H. H. Dubs), "Virtue" (H. G.
Creel), and "Humanity" (W. T. Chan). The practice of qualifying jen with
such adjectives as "false" (chia) and "womanish," (fJ-jen chih jen) which do
appear in later writings in ancient China, is completely absent in the Analects.
In the light of the preceding discussion, it seems that, while jen and chih do
appear as mutually complementary virtues in Confucian symbolism, jen is
unquestionably a more essential characterization of the Confucian Way.
Therefore, it may not be farfetched to suggest thatjen is in a subtle way linked
up with virtually all other basic Confucian concepts. Yet its relation to any of
them is neither obscure nor mystical. I believe that a systematic inquiry into
each occurrence of the linkage problem should eventually yield the fruit of
a coherent semiotic structure of jen. The matter involved is no less complex
than what the scholarly tradition of ko-i has demonstrated. But through
"matching concepts" or more dramatically, through a series of wrestlings
with the meanings of each pair of ideas in terms of comparative analysis, jen's
true face should not be concealed for long.
At the present juncture, we may tentatively conclude: Confucius refused
to grant jen to Tzu-lu despite his talents in political leadership and to Jan
Ch'iu despite his virtuosity in state rituals (5:7); he also resisted the temptation
to characterize the loyalty (chung) of Tzu-wen and the purity (ch'ing) of Ch'en
Wen Tzu as jen (5:18), not because jen implies "an inner mysterious realm"
but because jen symbolizes a holistic manifestation of humanity in its com-
monest and highest state of perfection.
heavy burden to be shouldered throughout one's entire life (8:7). Indeed, jen
can be realized only after one has done what is difficult (6:20).
The paradoxical situation in which jen presents itself both as a given reality
and as an inaccessible ideal is further complicated by a group of passages in
the Analects, orienting our thoughts to the absolute seriousness with which
jen is articulated. Thus, the chiin tzu (profound person) is instructed never to
abandonjen "even for the lapse of a single meal"; instead, "he is never so harried
but that he cleaves to this; never so tottering but that he cleaves to this" (4:5).
Jen must come before any other consideration (4:6); it is a supreme value more
precious than one's own life and therefore an idea worth dying for (15:8).
Yet the pursuit of jen is never a lonely struggle. It is not a quest for inner
truth or spiritual purity isolatable from an "outer" or public realm. From the
jen perspective, "a man of humanity, wishing to establish his own character,
also establishes the character of others, and wishing to fully manifest himself,
also helps others to fully manifest themselves. The ability to take what is near
at hand as an example may be called the method of realizing jen" (6:28). For
the task of jen, far from being an internal, subjectivistic search for one's own
individuality, depends as much on meaningful communal inquiry as on self-
scrutiny.
Tseng Tzu's daily self-examination is a case in point. The effort of personal
cultivation certainly suggests a spiritual-moral dimension not reducible to
social considerations, but the three areas of concern-loyalty to others, faith-
fulness to friends, and commitment to learning (1:4), are so much an integral
part of the "symbolic interchange" mentioned earlier that Master Tseng's
message is clearly in the realm of human relations. The self so conceived is a
kind of value-creating field in which the fiduciary community exists and is
realized by a tradition of selves in continuous interaction with selves. It is in
this connection, I believe, that Confucius insisted that true learning be specified
as learning for the sake of the self (14:25).
However, an essential characterization of jen impels us to go beyond the
behavioristic approach, no matter how comprehensive it purports to be. In
fact, the reason jen seems to be "surrounded with paradox and mystery in the
Analects" 32 is also relevant here. The four-word phrase, "ke-chifu-li," wrongly
rendered by Arthur Waley as "he who can himself submit to ritual,"33 clearly
shows that the attainment of jen involves both self-mastery and returning to
ritual. The interpretation that "the man who can submit himself to li is jen"
misses the point in a fundamental way.34 And, by implication, the portrayal
of jen as a disposition "after one has mastered the skills of action required by
li" is probably an inadequate view of the linkage problem.35 Jen is not simply
"a matter of the person's deciding to submit to li (once he has the objective
skill to do so);" 36 rather, it is a matter of inner strength and self-knowledge,
symbolizing an inexhaustible source for creative communal expression.
The primacy of jen over li and the inseparability of li from jen, a thesis I
is in doubt (2:18). Along the same line of thinking, Confucius can speak of
himself as so joyful and eager in learning and teaching that he forgets yu and
that he is unaware of the onset of old age (7:18), precisely because he is yu with
regard to the Tao and not to his private lot (15:31).42
The absence of the language and imagery of a purely psychological nature,
or for that matter of a purely sociological nature, should not trouble us in the
least. After all, recent developments in psychology and sociology as well as
in philosophy in the West have already rendered the sharp contrast between
"individual" and "society" not only undesirable but empirically unsound.
NOTES