Project Muse 907030
Project Muse 907030
Edwin Etieyibo
edwin etieyibo
critical philosophy of race,
University of the Witwatersrand vol. 11, no. 2, 2023
Copyright © 2023 The Pennsylvania
State University, University Park, PA
https://doi.org/10.5325/critphilrace.11.2.0309
Abstract
There are forms of discriminations that are not defensible, and
unjustified discriminations manifest in different forms. One
such manifestation is racism, which involves the use of morally
arbitrary natural and moral constituents (characteristics, abilities,
qualities) to demarcate racial or ethnic groups and consequently
designate some groups as superior and others as inferior. In this
article, I discuss one form of racism (intellectual racism), namely,
racism in relation to color, as a way of highlighting how the notion
of superiority and inferiority of racial or ethnic groups (Caucasian
and Africans) play out in the intellectual landscape and discourse.
Ultimately, my motivations are threefold: one, to signify and
engage with some views of racial coloring and color eliminativ-
ism; two, to make and extend the position that color eliminativism
is not defensible; and three, to highlight and emphasize the claim
that given the notion of a “one-colored humanity,” racial groups
ought not to be classified as superior or inferior.
310 ■ critical philosophy of race
Introduction
Those of us who talk about the African way of life and, quite rightly,
take a pride in maintaining the tradition of hospitality which is so
great a part of it, might do well to remember the Swahili saying:
‘Mgeni siku mbili; siku ya tatu mpe jembe’—or in English, ‘Treat
your guest as a guest for two days; on the third day give him a hoe!’
In actual fact, the guest was likely to ask for the hoe even before his
host had to give him one–for he knew what was expected of him, and
would have been ashamed to remain idle any longer. Thus, working
was part and parcel, was indeed the very basis and justification of this
socialist achievement of which we are so justly proud.3
I will understand the colonial project to include colonialism and its justifi-
cations. The justifications are intellectual in nature and one such justifica-
tions is the notion of the “civilizing mission of colonialism” (CMC) and the
argument provided for it, thereof. The CMC pitches the colonized as the
inferior and the colonizer (West) as the superior. For CMC, the idea of the
superiority of Caucasians and the inferiority of non-Caucasians (or Africa/
Africans) is meant to perpetuate the triumphant narrative of “Western civi-
lization” and to justify civilizing the latter. The summary of the argument
goes thus:
1. Humans share the capacities for reason and self-government (a core
doctrine of liberalism).
2. A society that provides better quality of life (well-being, breadth of
opportunities, extended longevity) is better than one that doesn’t.
313 ■ edwin etieyibo
and these constituents are used to demarcate some groups as superior and
others as inferior.
Jiannbin Shiao and Ashley Woody (2020) have identified a number of
meanings of racism in the sociology of race/ethnicity. They argue that soci-
ologists use “racism” to refer to four constructs: individual attitudes, cul-
tural schema, racial dominance (or preexisting consequential inequalities),
and processes that create or maintain racial dominance.14 Regarding the
first construct—that is, racism as individual attitudes—Shiao and Woody
direct us to consider the ideas of Hochschild et al. (2012), according to
which racism may best be seen as racial attitudes or negative perceptions
of non-Caucasian groups or people.15
And as part of their explication of the thoughts of Levi-Strauss on
racism, Robert Bernasconi and Sybol Cook identify a number of elements
making up the term “racism.” First, as a doctrine, but a doctrine that seeks
to establish false claims. Second, the false claims concern some moral attri-
butes and mental characteristics of a racial group as a whole and the indi-
viduals who are representative of the group.16
From the above, we can take racism to basically mean certain preju-
dicial or discriminatory beliefs and attitudes against some racial or ethnic
group. And the circulation and perpetuation of these beliefs and attitudes
may generally be backed by some form of dominance and power. The defi-
nition of racism above provides us with a number of elements. First, there
is a prejudice (or discrimination or antagonism). Second, the prejudice is
perpetuated by an entity A (individual, group, institution, or community).
Third, the prejudice is directed at or against another entity B. Entity A often
has the power and B is marginalized or typically a minority. Fourth, the
prejudice that B suffers is on the basis of membership in a particular racial/
ethnic group. In the next section, I will show how some of these elements
show up in color branding or racial coloring—an area that I refer to as intel-
lectual racism.
Since my focus is on intellectual racism, it is important for me to
unpack the concept. When the term “intellectual” is used, it is generally
contrasted with emotions or the emotional and employed to stand for
the mental/intellect, theoretical, academic, or rational. The intellectual or
academic in the definition points to something scholarly or educational.
In this sense, I should be understood to be using intellectual racism as
the sort of racism that undermines any aspect of research or scholarship
or regarding a people’s experiences, institutions, values, and presence.17
On this understanding, intellectual racism can be said to involve certain
316 ■ critical philosophy of race
Before I talk about racial coloring or color and racism and color eliminativ-
ism, let me first discuss race and racial eliminativism. Racial eliminativism
is the broad view that race or the use of race in our discourse be eliminated
or dispensed with. That is, it takes race terms to be meaningless and the
need for any race talk to be eliminated from public and private racial dis-
course because there are no natural racial referents. Although racial elimi-
nativists (REs) adopt different stances concerning the idea of jettisoning
race, they subscribe to some or most of the following claims:
• Abandoning the use of the term race in order to achieve holistic identity
formation (a fear that without race one has no meaning or worth)
• The elimination of race is warranted, and it is possible to do so because it
has been proven to be a genetically inaccurate and relatively unimportant
in explaining biological differences
• Racial identification rests on nothing neutral or factual so individuals
have the right to disassociate from it (deracination or self-emancipation)
• Racialization, because it is constructed could be practically transcended
or neutralized.
• The non-abandonment of our racial makeup and seeing race as an
illusion.
319 ■ edwin etieyibo
or logical incoherence between the concept of race and its typical referent.
Accordingly, then, the concept of race, REs argue, must be eliminated.30
be said about white, namely, that there is hardly anyone who can be said to
have the color white. If this is the case, then why are we still using colors
to designate humans? Chimakonam’s calculation and reasoning is that the
use of colors to designate humans is flourishing because it serves some very
expedient or cultural, social, and political purpose for racism, namely, it helps
and facilitates the interests of Caucasians, or those in the West who want to
continue to maintain the illusion of superiority. Chimakonam notes,
Even though Theodore Allen (1994), in his The Invention of the White
Race, explains that the idea of the concept of race is to create and sus-
tain hierarchical boundaries in human species, those hierarchies are
not real; they are mere illusions and as such constitute an immoral
strategy. So, in essence, the Western world feeds on illusion to sus-
tain the perpetuation of the evil of racism on other peoples. The
immorality associated with colour-politic is exactly the main reason
colour-branding of humans should be discontinued.47
It is partly for this reason that Chimakonam contends that racial coloring
ought to be abandoned. Again, I do want us to be nuanced here.
While I agree with the claim that using some color or a monocolor to
represent an entire people or racial/ethnic groups, as for example, reference
to African people as “Black” or their being designated by the color black or
speaking of Caucasian/Europeans as “white” is problematic and mislead-
ing, and thus should be abandoned. However, given the variety in racial and
ethnic groups and the differences in color, one is best served to use a more
general color descriptor to designate the groups, for example, Africans as
people of dark or darker skin and Caucasians/Europeans as being of light or
lighter skin colors. Furthermore, one has to be clear that the use of “black”
or “ebony” or “brown” to describe someone of a particular skin pigmenta-
tion may not be wrong or problematic if such persons do exhibit such colors.
These remarks make me an anticolor eliminativist. My nuanced
position is that color may in some sense be appropriate designators of
racial or ethnic groups or individuals in those groups insofar as such color
picks out aspects of people or an individual that is part of their natural
or personal identity. In other words, racial coloring has to be abandoned
in a context where some monocolor like “black” is applied to an entire racial
or ethnic group or where color is used to pick out racial categories in terms
of superiority and inferiority. But racial coloring in the context of individual
324 ■ critical philosophy of race
and do not denote the same referent even though they may pick out
certain features that are shared by the same entities. This is important in
that while racial discourse on race and racism may implicate color dis-
course or discussions of racism and vice versa, saying that race does or
doesn’t exist or that race talk should be eliminated or not eliminated is not
the same as saying that color does or doesn’t exist or that color talk should
be eliminated or not eliminated. And importantly, for racial eliminativism,
race may not exist biologically, but for color eliminativism, color does exist
biologically—all of us, as humans, do have some color. Furthermore, it is
possible to dispense with race talk, but we will still be saddled with color
talk precisely because they are not coextensive and do not have the same
ontological or metaphysical grounding and the motivations for their elimi-
nations are different. Finally, color may sometimes be used as a placeholder
or marker for race and therefore open up the space for racism, but elimi-
nating color will generally not lead to an end to race or racial discourse or
racism if it is the case that color is just one feature or marker of race.
So, it may be the case that in our world as it is presently constituted,
the continued privileging of light/lighter skin over dark/darker skin will
continue to serve as the most obvious or visible criterion used to determine
how a person is evaluated and judged. And one may attribute this partly to
deeply entrenched racism, whereby the darker a person’s skin is, the more
one is demonized or considered less valuable, and the lighter one’s skin is,
the more one is considered more valuable. This should not lead us to move
toward color eliminativism. For as I have shown, a person’s skin color is an
unquestionable visual fact of that person; it is a brute fact, but race is a con-
structed, quasi-scientific classification of a person. The point then is that if
racism didn’t exist, we will still recognize the existence of color and have
discussions about varying skin hues—discussions that may center on the
aesthetics of the different colors or how to effectively distinguish one hue
from another.
Whatever the motivations are for racial classifications, racism, and racial
discrimination, the notion that one will think of some racial groups as
superior and others as inferior is clearly false. I have highlighted above the
point that Allen (1994) made in The Invention of the White Race regarding
326 ■ critical philosophy of race
Who am I?
I am not you
327 ■ edwin etieyibo
I am me
You are you
We are different
But we are not superior and inferior
You say you are superior to me
And I say you are inferior to me
Conclusion
to designate racial or ethnic groups is apposite as long as the colors pick out
certain aspects of people or individuals that are part of who they are.
Thus, I can be taken to be claiming, on the one hand, that the term
“Black” has not always had the negative meaning it has today and to
side, on the other hand, with those who valorize Africa and (like Tsri and
Chimakonam) oppose the term “Black.” But overall, I am suggesting that
while color can’t be eliminated since every person has some shade of
color, I agree with Tsri and Chimakonam that the use of “Black” to desig-
nate Africans is misleading, since most people in the world and from the
continent are not “black.” Therefore, I should be understood to be engaged
in a conceptual rather than some practical project, which makes some
recommendations on how to end racism. By that I mean that my project
is a response to the prevalence of racism and how color does or doesn’t
serve as one cultural maker of racism and why it is conceptually wrong to
make the case that color should be abandoned. For all one cares, my project
may have no practical consequences for the perpetuation or ending of rac-
ism, but I do believe that this does not diminish its value and relevance.
I now conclude by making some comments that are the upshot of all
that I have done in this article regarding racism and color eliminativism.
First, as humans, we are different in many ways and aspects, and you are
you and I am me. Second, although we are different, we are a “bouquet of
humanity.” Third, as a “bouquet of humanity,” we are one humanity—a
colored humanity. Fourth, as a one-colored humanity, there are no superior
or inferior racial or ethnic groups, or superior and inferior humans. Fifth,
as a one-colored humanity, we are all colored peoples. What follows from
this then is that it is wrong and misleading to classify racial or ethnic groups
or humans into two groups—Caucasians or “white” people and “colored
people.” Since all that exists is a colored humanity, we are all colored peo-
ple no matter what the racial grouping or ethnicity we belong to, whether
Aboriginals, Africans, African Americans, Asians, Berbers, Caribbeans,
Caucasians, Creole, Hispanics, Jewish, Indians, Latinos, Pacific Islanders,
etc. Sixth, in describing any member of the colored humanity, a much more
apposite way of describing them is where they stand in the color spectrum
and in terms of shades of color, such as light/lighter color and dark/darker
color. So, for example, when referring to someone, one may say, “Here
is X from Y racial or ethnic group who is light/lighter colored or has dark/
darker color.”
329 ■ edwin etieyibo
notes
4. Edwin Etieyibo, “African Proverbs,” in African Ethics: A Guide to Key Ideas, ed.
Jonathan O. Chimakonam and Luis Cordeiro-Rodrigues (London: Bloomsbury,
2022), 307–22
5. Although I speak of knock and doors here, which could be taken literally, I could
also be understood metaphorically, say, warmly embracing something. In this
sense, knock, door, and the opening of the door could be taken to mean opening
one’s arms warmly to something, namely, the colonial project. Hopefully, my fur-
ther discussion of the colonial project makes this clearer.
6. I thank the reviewers for helping clarify my thoughts around the nuances of colo-
nialism/the colonial project.
7. See Edwin Etieyibo, “Racism, Colonialism and African Philosophy,” in Africa’s
Radicalisms and Conservativism, vol. 2, Pop Culture, Environment, Colonialism and
Migration, ed. Edwin Etieyibo, Obvious Katsaura, and Muchaparara Musemwa
(Leiden: Brill, 2022a), 256–66.
8. This argument is presented and discussed in Edwin Etieyibo, “Political
Reparationists and the Moral Case for Reparations to Africa for Colonialism,” Africa
Insight 40, no. 4 (2011): 22–34).
9. Anibal Quijano and Michael Ennis, “Coloniality of Power, Eurocentrism, and Latin
America,” Nepantla: Views from South 1, no. 3 (2000): 533–80.
10. Ramón Grosfoguel, “The Structure of Knowledge in Westernized Universities:
Epistemic Racism/Sexism and the Four Genocides/Epistemicides of the Long 16th
Century,” Human Architecture: Journal of the Sociology of Self-Knowledge 11, no. 11
(2013): 82–83.
11. Ibid., 83.
12. Ibid.
13. Ibid., 82.
14. Jiannbin Shiao and Ashley Woody, “The Meaning of ‘Racism,’” Sociological
Perspectives 64, no. 3 (2020): 1–23, https://doi.org/10.1177/0731121420964239.
15. Jennifer Hochschild, Vesla Weaver, and Traci Burch, Creating a New Racial Order:
How Immigration, Multiracialism, Genomics, and the Young Can Remake Race in
America (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2012), 139. See Shiao and
Woody (2020, 3). Hochschild et al., as well as Shiao and Woody, use the term
“non-white,” but I am using “non-Caucasian” for reasons that will become clearer
later.
16. Robert Bernasconi and Sybol Cook, eds., Race and Racism in Continental Philosophy
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2003), 235.
17. For some discussions of intellectual racism, see Robert Staples, “Racial
Ideology and Intellectual Racism: Blacks in Academia,” The Black Scholar:
Journal of Black Studies and Research 15, no. 2 (1984): 2–17; Andrew Billingsley,
“Intellectual Racism,” New Directions 1, no. 2 (1974): Article 9, https://dh.howard.
edu/newdirections/vol1/iss2/9.
18. Billingsley 1974, 28.
331 ■ edwin etieyibo
19. The killing of George Floyd sparked, in 2020, the Black Lives Movement in the
United States and worldwide. On 20 Apr. 2021, Derek Chauvin was convicted of
Floyd’s murder.
20. See Anonymous, 2018. “Kaepernick, from Super Bowl Quarterback to NFL Pariah.” France
24, AFP, 9 Apr. 2018, https://www.france24.com/en/20180904-kaepernick-
super-bowl-quarterback-nfl-pariah; Kyle Wagner, “Colin Kaepernick Is Not
Supposed to Be Unemployed,” FiveThirtyEight, 9 Aug. 2017, https://fivethirtyeight.
com/features/colin-kaepernick-is-not-supposed-to-be-unemployed/.
21. See Patricia Huston, “Intellectual Racism,” Editor’s Page, Canadian Medical
Association Journal 153, no. 9 (1995): 1219; Clara Osei-Yeboh, “How Queen’s
School of Medicine Barred Black Students for 40 Years,” INKspire, 6 April 2020,
https://inkspire.org/post/how-queens-school-of-medicine-barred-black-students-
for-40-years/-M2ix2zV7yw8Y-V--XUQ; OmiSoore Dryden and Onye Nnorom,
“Time to Dismantle Systemic Anti-Black Racism in Medicine in Canada,” Canadian
Medical Association Journal (11 January 2021): 193: E55-7, DOI: 10.1503/cmaj.201579;
D. R. Williams, J. A. Lawrence, and B. A. Davis, “Racism and Health: Evidence and
Needed Research,” Annual Review of Public Health 40 (2019): 105–25.
22. Huston 1995, 1219.
23. See Patarroyo (1995: 1319–21); Tracy Wilkinson, “Profile: Colombian Tackles
Malaria and Skeptics: Maverick Scientist Has Had to Convince Critics Worldwide
That His Synthetic Vaccine Can Deter the Deadly Disease,” Los Angeles Times, 28
June 1994, https://www.latimes.com/archives/la-xpm-1994-06-28-wr-9342-story.
html; Marguerite Holloway, “Profile: Manuel Elkin Patarroyo—The Man Who
Would Conquer Malaria,” Scientific American 275, no. 6 (1996): 52–56; Anonymous,
1995. “Malaria Vaccine Offers Hope. International/Africa.” Vaccine Weekly, 13
(Mar. 1995): 10–11. PMID: 12288959; G. Caba, “Patarroyo and the Strategies to
Develop a Malaria Vaccine,” Microbiologia 13, no. 1 (1997): 89–94, PMID: 9106187.
24. Huston 1995, 1219.
25. Ibid.
26. See Laura Bestle, “Racial Eliminativism,” Critical Race Theory, 16 July 2018, http://
www.laurabestler.org/racial-eliminativism/.
27. For some discussions of race, racial eliminativism, and arguments against racial
eliminativism, see the following: R. O. Andreasen, “Race: Biological Reality or
Social Construct?” Philosophy of Science 67 (Supplement, 2000): S653–66; Adeshei
Jacoby Carter, “Does ‘Race’ Have a Future or Should the Future Have ‘Races’?
Reconstruction or Eliminativism in a Pragmatist Philosophy of Race,” Transactions
of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy 50,
no. 1 (2014): 29–47; W. E. B. Du Bois, The Conservation of Races (Washington, DC:
The American Negro Academy, 1897); Joshua Glasgow, “On the Methodology
of the Race Debate: Conceptual Analysis and Racial Discourse,” Philosophy
and Phenomenological Research 76, no. 2 (2008): 333–58; Ian Hacking, “Why Race
Still Matters.” Daedelus (Fall 2005): 102–16; W. Steven Halady, “The Reality of Race:
Against Racial Eliminativism” (PhD diss., University at Buffalo, State University of
332 ■ critical philosophy of race
29. For a look at some historical baggage or genealogy of racism in the West, see
Delacampagne 1990.
30. See Appiah 1994, 73; Zack 2002, 69; Mallon 2006, 526, 533.
31. Jonathan Chimakonam, “Why the Racial Politic of Colour-Branding Should Be
Discontinued,” Phronimon 20, no. 1 (2019): 1–24.
32. J. L. Sandford, “Turn a Colour with Emotion: A Linguistic Construction of Colour
in English,” Journal of the International Colour Association 13 (2014): 67–83.
33. “Black widow,” used to designate a woman who kills one or more of her lovers,
or a female martyr; and in reference to the black widow spider, a very poisonous
spider that lives in warm areas.
34. “Black market,” which means an illegal, clandestine trade or underground or
shadow economy.
35. “Black mood” denotes sadness, misery, depression, feeling down or gloomy, melan-
choly, having a bad temper, or being angry and irritable.
36. “Blackball” used in reference to negative voting or voting against or to boycott,
ostracize, or exclude socially.
37. “Black sheep” refers to a member of a family or group who is considered an outlier
or a disgrace.
38. “Blackmail” as reference to a criminal act of obtaining financial benefits (money
or material things) from others or forcing them to do something by threatening to
harm them or to reveal some secret of theirs.
39. “Black hole,” in astronomy, means a region of space that has an intense gravita-
tional field that prevents matter or radiation from escaping; and informally, it refers
to a place where money or lost items are said to vanish without a trace.
40. “Black Monday” refers to Monday, October 19, 1987, when there was a massive fall
in the value of stocks on Wall Street, which then caused similar falls in markets
internationally.
41. “Black-hearted” refer to being evil, wicked, or cruel.
42. “Blackout” means loss or absence of lights or electricity or temporary loss of con-
sciousness or a period when all lights are concealed or turned off during an air raid
at night to prevent the enemy from seeing a targeted area.
43. “Black magic” refers to magic involving the invocation or bringing forth of evil
spirits for evil purposes (in contrast to white magic, which is used only for good
purposes).
44. “Black Plague,” sometimes called the “Black Death,” refers to the bubonic plague
or pandemic, which happened in Afro-Eurasia from 1346 to 1353 and was consid-
ered the deadliest disease or pandemic recorded in human history.
45. Kassia St. Clair, The Secret Lives of Colour (London: John Murray, 2016), 261–62.
46. Eva Heller, Psychologie de la couleur—Effets et symboliques (Paris: Pyramyd, 2009),
105–27.
47. Chimakonam 2019, 18.
48. Ibid.
334 ■ critical philosophy of race
49. William Blake (28 Nov. 1757–12 Aug. 1827) is one of the six prominent poets of the
Romantic Age (which is flanked by the Augustan and Victoria ages; there is a dras-
tic shift in literary ideals among these ages). Other Romantic poets are: William
Wordsworth, Samuel T. Coleridge, Percy Bysshe Shelley, John Keats, and Lord
Byron.
50. The expression “bouquet of humanity” is credited to Jerry Blackwell, a member of
the prosecution team that tried the murder case of George Floyd. The prosecution
used it to designate the various color/ethnicities (African Americans, Caucasians,
etc.), social statuses, gender, and ages of the people or bystanders, and who are
in a sense all strangers with nothing in common except that they are all part of one
humanity who witnessed the death of Floyd on May 25, 2020 (and some of whom
recorded the events on their electronic devices). Thus, “bouquet of humanity” is
used generally and in this article to refer to all people who are different but who
are of one or the same humanity. See Keith Ellison, “Today’s Verdict Isn’t ‘Justice,’
But Accountability Is a First Step to Justice,” Guardian, 21 Apr. 2021, https://
www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2021/apr/20/keith-ellison-george-floyd-
speech-minnesota-attorney-general; Anonymous, “Bouquet of Humanity,” Urban
Dictionary, n.d., https://www.urbandictionary.com/define.php?term=bouquet%20
of%20humanity.
51. “I Am Different But Not Inferior” is from a collection of poems by Edwin Etieyibo,
Humanity, unpublished, 2011b.
works cited
Allen, Theodore W. 1994. The Invention of the White Race. Vol. 1, Racial Oppression and
Social Control. London: Verso.
Andreasen, R. O. 2000. “Race: Biological Reality or Social Construct?” Philosophy of
Science 67 (Supplement): S653–66.
Anonymous. 1995. “Malaria Vaccine Offers Hope. International/Africa.” Vaccine Weekly,
13 March, 10–11. PMID: 12288959.
Anonymous. 2018. “Kaepernick, from Super Bowl Quarterback to NFL
Pariah.” France 24. AFP, 9 April. https://www.france24.com/
en/20180904-kaepernick-super-bowl-quarterback-nfl-pariah.
Anonymous. n.d. “Bouquet of Humanity.” Urban Dictionary. https://www.urbandiction-
ary.com/define.php?term=bouquet%20of%20humanity.
Appiah, Kwame Anthony. 1994. “Race, Culture, Identity: Misunderstood Connections.”
The paper was first delivered at the University of California, San Diego, 27
and 28 October 1994, before been published in The Tanner Lectures on Human
Values 17 (1996): 53–136.
———. 1995. “The Uncompleted Argument: DuBois and the Illusion of Race.” Critical
Inquiry 12, no. 1: 21–37.
335 ■ edwin etieyibo
———. 2006. “How to Decide If Races Exist.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society
106:365–82.
Bernasconi, Robert, and Cook Sybol, eds. 2003. Race and Racism in Continental
Philosophy. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.
Bestle, Laura. 2018. “Racial Eliminativism.” Critical Race Theory, 16 July. http://www.
laurabestler.org/racial-eliminativism/.
Billingsley, Andrew. 1974. “Intellectual Racism.” New Directions 1, no. 2: Article 9.
https://dh.howard.edu/newdirections/vol1/iss2/9.
Blum, Lawrence. 2002. “I’m Not a Racist, but . . .”: The Moral Quandary of Race. Ithaca,
NY: Cornell University Press.
———. 2010. “Racialized Groups: The Sociohistorical Consensus.” The Monist 93,
no. 2:298–320.
Caba, G. 1997. “Patarroyo and the Strategies to Develop a Malaria Vaccine.” Microbiologia
13, no. 1: 89–94. PMID: 9106187.
Carter, Adeshei Jacoby. 2014. “Does ‘Race’ Have a Future or Should the Future Have
‘Races’? Reconstruction or Eliminativism in a Pragmatist Philosophy of Race.”
Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American
Philosophy 50, no. 1: 29–47.
Chimakonam, Jonathan. 2018. “Africans Are Not Black: The Case for Conceptual
Liberation: A Review.” African Identities 16, no. 3: 365–69. https://doi.org/10.1
080/14725843.2018.1473149.
———. 2019. “Why the Racial Politic of Colour-Branding Should Be Discontinued.”
Phronimon 20, no. 1:1–24.
Corlett, J. Angelo. 2003. Race, Racism, and Reparations. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University
Press.
Delacampagne, Christian. 1990. “Racism and the West: From Praxis to Logos.” In
Anatomy of Racism, edited by David Theo Goldberg, 83–88. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press.
Dryden, OmiSoore, and Onye Nnorom. 2021. “Time to Dismantle Systemic Anti-Black
Racism in Medicine in Canada.” Canadian Medical Association Journal
(11 January) 193: E55-7. DOI: 10.1503/cmaj.201579.
Du Bois, W. E. B. 1897. The Conservation of Races. Washington, DC: The American Negro
Academy.
Ellison, Keith. 2021. “Today’s Verdict Isn’t ‘Justice,’ But Accountability Is a First Step to Justice.”
Guardian, 21 April. https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2021/
apr/20/keith-ellison-george-floyd-speech-minnesota-attorney-general.
Etieyibo, Edwin. 2011a. “Political Reparationists and the Moral Case for Reparations to
Africa for Colonialism.” Africa Insight 40, no. 4:22–34.
———. 2011b. “I Am Different But Not Inferior.” Humanity. Unpublished.
———. 2016. “African Philosophy and Proverbs: The Case of Logic in Urhobo Proverbs.”
Philosophia Africana 18, no. 1: 21–39.
———. 2022a. “Racism, Colonialism and African Philosophy.” In Africa’s Radicalisms
and Conservativism. Vol. 2, Pop Culture, Environment, Colonialism And
336 ■ critical philosophy of race
Shiao, Jiannbin, and Ashley Woody. 2020. “The Meaning of ‘Racism.’” Sociological
Perspectives 64, no. 3: 1–23. https://doi.org/10.1177/0731121420964239.
St. Clair, Kassia. 2016. The Secret Lives of Colour. London: John Murray.
St Louis, Brett. 2015. “Can Race Be Eradicated? The Postracial Problematic.” In Theories
of Race and Ethnicity: Contemporary Debates and Perspectives, edited by Karim
Murji and John Solomos, 114–37. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Staples, Robert. 1984. “Racial Ideology and Intellectual Racism: Blacks in Academia.”
The Black Scholar: Journal of Black Studies and Research 15, no. 2: 2–17.
Templeton, A. R. 1998. “Human Races: A Genetic and Evolutionary Perspective.”
American Anthropologist 100: 632–50.
Tsri, Kwesi. 2016a. “Africans Are Not Black: Why the Use of the Term ‘Black’ for Africans
Should be Abandoned.” African Identities 14, no. 2: 147–60. https://doi.org/10.
1080/14725843.2015.1113120.
———. 2016b. Africans Are Not Black: The Case for Conceptual Liberation. London:
Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315566085.
Wagner, Kyle. 2017. “Colin Kaepernick Is Not Supposed to Be Unemployed.”
FiveThirtyEight, 9 August. https://fivethirtyeight.com/features/colin-
kaepernick-is-not-supposed-to-be-unemployed/.
Wilkinson, Tracy. 1994. “Profile: Colombian Tackles Malaria and Skeptics: Maverick
Scientist Has Had to Convince Critics Worldwide That His Synthetic Vaccine
Can Deter the Deadly Disease.” Los Angeles Times, 28 June. https://www.lat-
imes.com/archives/la-xpm-1994-06-28-wr-9342-story.html.
Williams, D. R., J. A. Lawrence, and B. A. Davis. 2019. “Racism and Health: Evidence
and Needed Research.” Annual Review of Public Health 40: 105–25.
Zack, Naomi. 1993. Race and Mixed Race. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.
———. 2002. Philosophy of Science and Race. New York: Routledge.