Measure and Integration Theory - 4-06-11-2021!16!20-07_Measure and Integration Theory(20MAT22C2) (2)
Measure and Integration Theory - 4-06-11-2021!16!20-07_Measure and Integration Theory(20MAT22C2) (2)
Semester – II
Paper Code – 20MAT22C2
MEASURE AND
INTEGRATION THEORY
ISBN :
Price : Rs. 325/-
Publisher: Maharshi Dayanand University Press
Publication Year : 2021
MASTER OF SCIENCE (MATHEMATICS)
Measure and Integration Theory (Semester–II)
Paper code: 20MAT22C2
M. Marks = 100
Term End Examination = 80
Time = 3 hrs Assignment = 20
Course Outcomes
Students would be able to:
CO1 Describe the shortcomings of Riemann integral and benefits of Lebesgue integral.
CO2 Understand the fundamental concept of measure and Lebesgue measure.
CO3 Learn about the differentiation of monotonic function, indefinite integral, use of the fundamental
theorem of calculus.
Section - I
Set functions, Intuitive idea of measure, Elementary properties of measure, Measurable sets and their
fundamental properties. Lebesgue measure of a set of real numbers, Algebra of measurable sets, Borel
set, Equivalent formulation of measurable sets in terms of open, Closed, F and G sets, Non measurable
sets.
Section - II
Measurable functions and their equivalent formulations. Properties of measurable functions.
Approximation of a measurable function by a sequence of simple functions, Measurable functions as
nearly continuous functions, Egoroff theorem, Lusin theorem, Convergence in measure and F. Riesz
theorem. Almost uniform convergence.
Section - III
Shortcomings of Riemann Integral, Lebesgue Integral of a bounded function over a set of finite measure
and its properties. Lebesgue integral as a generalization of Riemann integral, Bounded convergence
theorem, Lebesgue theorem regarding points of discontinuities of Riemann integrable functions,
Integral of non-negative functions, Fatou Lemma, Monotone convergence theorem, General Lebesgue
Integral, Lebesgue convergence theorem.
Section - IV
Vitali covering lemma, Differentiation of monotonic functions, Function of bounded variation and its
representation as difference of monotonic functions, Differentiation of indefinite integral, Fundamental
theorem of calculus, Absolutely continuous functions and their properties.
Note : The question paper of each course will consist of five Sections. Each of the sections I to IV will contain
two questions and the students shall be asked to attempt one question from each. Section-V shall be compulsory
and will contain eight short answer type questions without any internal choice covering the entire syllabus.
Books Recommended :
1. Walter Rudin, Principles of Mathematical Analysis (3rd edition) McGraw-Hill, Kogakusha,
1976, International Student Edition.
2. H.L. Royden, Real Analysis, Macmillan Pub. Co., Inc. 4th Edition, New York, 1993.
3. P. K. Jain and V. P. Gupta, Lebesgue Measure and Integration, New Age International (P)
Limited Published, New Delhi, 1986.
4. G.De Barra, Measure Theory and Integration, Wiley Eastern Ltd., 1981.
5. R.R. Goldberg, Methods of Real Analysis, Oxford & IBH Pub. Co. Pvt. Ltd, 1976.
6. R. G. Bartle, The Elements of Real Analysis, Wiley International Edition, 2011.
Contents
SECTION TITLE OF CHAPTER PAGE NO.
1 MEASURABLE SETS 1-27
4 FUNCTIONS OF BOUNDED
VARIATIONS 75-86
SECTION – I
MEASURABLE SETS
Introduction
In measure theory, a branch of mathematics, the concept of Lebesgue measure, was given by French
mathematician Henri Lebesgue in 1901. Sets that can be assigned a Lebesgue measure are called
Lebesgue-measurable; the measure of the Lebesgue-measurable set A is here denoted by m*(A).
Lebesgue Measure
In this section we shall define Lebesgue Measure, which is a generalization of the idea of length.
1.1 Definition. The length (I) of an interval I with end points a and b is defined as the difference of
the end points. In symbols, we write.
= – .
1.2 Definition. A function whose domain of definition is a class of sets is called a Set Function. For
example, length is a set function. The domain being the collection of all intervals.
1.3 Definition. An extended real – valued set function defined on a class E of sets is called
Additive if , , = ,
= +
1.4 Definition. An extended real valued set function defined on a class E of sets is called finitely
additive if for every finite disjoint classes , , … . , of sets in E, whose union is also in E,
we have
= ∑
1.5 Definition. An extended real–valued set function defined on a class E of sets is called
countably additive it for every disjoint sequence of sets in E whose union is also in E, we have
∞
∞
= ∑
1.6 Definition. Length of an open set is defined to be the sum of lengths of the open intervals of
which it is composed of. Thus, if G is an open set, then
= ∑
where
= , 1 2 = .
2 Measure and Integration Theory
1.7 Definition. The Lebesgue Outer Measure or simply the outer measure m* of a set A is defined as
∗ = .
where the infimum is taken over all finite or countable collections of intervals {In} such that
Since the lengths are positive numbers, it follows from the definition of ∗ that ∗ .
1.8 Remark: (i) If ⊆ ,then ∗ ≤ ∗ i.e. outer-measure has monotone property.
Proof: By definition of outer-measure, for each ɛ > , there exist a countable collection of open
interval {In} such that ⊆ and
∗ + ɛ > ...1)
now ⊆ ⊆
=> ⊆
∗ ≤
< ∗ + ɛ
∗ < ∗ + ɛ
but ɛ > is arbitrary, ∗ ≤ ∗ hence proved.
(ii) Outer-measure of a set is always non-negative.
1.9 Theorem. Outer measure is translation invariant.
Proof. Let > be given. Then by definition of outer measure, There exist a countable collection of
intervals such that
∗ + > .
Now,
=> + + ,
=> ∗ + + = [length is translation invariant]
∗ +
Since is arbitrary positive number, we have
(2) ∗ + ∗ (1)
To prove reverse inequality, Let > be given. Then by definition of outer measure, There exist a
countable collection of intervals such that
+
∗ + + > .
Now, +
Measurable Sets 3
−
∗ −
∗ < ∗ + +
∗ ∗ + (2)
Then Combining (1) and (2), the required result follows.
i.e., ∗ = ∗ +
1.10 Theorem. The outer measure of an interval is its length.
Proof. CASE (1) Let us suppose, first I is a closed and bounded interval, say I = [a, b]
To prove: m*(I) = ℓ [a, b] =b - a.
Now for each ɛ> 0, I = [a, b] ⊆ (a - ɛ, b+ ɛ) then
by definition of outer-measure
=> m*(I) ≤ ℓ (a - ɛ, b+ ɛ) ≤ (b+ ɛ- a+ ɛ)
=> m*(I) ≤ b-a + 2 ɛ
since ɛ is an arbitrary, m*(I) ≤ b-a = ℓ (I) (1)
Now to prove, m*(I) = b-a, then it is sufficient to prove m*(I) ≥ b-a. let {In} be a countable collection of
open intervals which covering I i.e.
I ⊆
ℓ ≥ b-a for all n ∈ N so it is sufficient to prove that
inf ℓ ≥ b-a
since I = [a, b] is compact, then by Heine Boral theorem, we can select a finite number of open intervals
from this {In} such that their union contains I.
Let the intervals be J1, J2, ..., Jp such that ⊇ [a, b].
Now it is sufficient to prove ℓ ≥ b-a (2)
Now a ∈ I = [a, b], there exist open interval J1 = (a1, b1) from the above-mentioned finite no. of intervals
such that a1 < a≤ b then b1 ∈ I.
Again, there exist an open interval (a2, b2) from the finite collection J1, J2, ..., Jp such that a2 <b1 < b2.
Continuing this, we get a sequence of open intervals
(a1, b1), (a2, b2), ..., (ap ,bp ) from J1, J2, ..., Jp satisfying ai < bi-1 < bi ,i= 2,3,.....,p since the collection is
finite so the process must stop with an interval satisfying ap < bp-1 < bp and ap <b < bp
ℓ ≥ ℓ = ℓ (a1, b1) + ℓ (a2, b2) +.... ℓ (ap, bp)
= (b1 -a1) + (b2 -a2) + ...+ (bp -ap)
= bp + (bp-1 – ap) +...+b1 -a2 – a1
4 Measure and Integration Theory
> bp – a1
> b-a
=> inf ℓ ≥ b-a
=> m*(I) ≥ b-a (4)
Hence result is proved in the case when I closed and bounded interval.
CASE (2) let I be bounded open interval with end points a and b, then for every real no. ɛ> 0 [a+ ɛ, b- ɛ]
⊂ I ⊂ [a, b]
=> m*[a+ ɛ, b- ɛ] ≤ m*(I) ≤ m* [a, b]
=> ℓ [a+ ɛ, b- ɛ] ≤ m*(I) ≤ ℓ [a, b] (by case 1)
=>b- ɛ -a- ɛ≤ m*(I) ≤b-a
since ɛ is arbitrary,
we get b-a ≤ m*(I) ≤ b-a
=> m*(I) =b-a.
CASE (3) if I is the unbounded interval, then for each real no. r> 0, we can find bounded closed interval
J ⊂ I such that ℓ (J)>r
Now J ⊂ I => m* (J) ≤ m* (I)
=> ℓ (J) ≤ m* (I)
=> m* (I) > r since this hold for each real no. r,
we get m* (I) = ∞ = ℓ(I)
i.e. outer-measure is of an interval equal to its length.
1.11 Theorem. Let be a countable collection of sets of real numbers. Then
∗ ≤ ∗ .
Proof. Proof. If one of the sets has infinite outer measure, the inequality holds trivially. So suppose
∗ is finite. Then, given > , there exists a countable collection , } of open intervals such
that , and
, < ∗ +
by the definition of ∗ .
Now the collection , , = , is countable, being the union of a countable number of
countable collections, and covers . Thus
∗ ⋃ , ,
Measurable Sets 5
= ,
< ( ∗ + )
= ∗ +
= ∗ +
= ∗ +
Since is an arbitrary positive number, it follows that
∗ ≤ ∗ .
1.12 Theorem. Outer-measure of singleton set of reals is zero
Proof: Let = Then, since = , ⊆ ( − , + ) ∀ ∈
∗ ≤ ∗ ( − , + )
∗ ≤
≤ ∗ ≤ for each n.
∗ ≤ ∗ ( − , )
∗ ≤
≤ ∗ ≤ for each n. In limiting case ∗ = .
m* (A ) + m* (A c) = m* ( ) + m* (A R)
= 0 + m* A
= m* A
This implies is measurable.
1.20 Theorem. Prove that R is measurable set.
Proof: Let A be set of reals, then
m* A = m* (A E) + m* (A Ec)
Put E = R
m* (A R) + m* (A Rc) = m* (A) + m* (A )
= m* (A) + m* ()
= m* A + 0
= m* A
This implies R is measurable.
1.21 Theorem. If m* E = 0, then E is measurable.
Proof. Let A be any set. Then A E E and so
m* (A E) m* E = 0 (i)
Also A A Ec, and so
m* A m* (A Ec) = m* (A Ec) + m* (A E)
as m* (A E) = 0 by (i)
Hence E is measurable.
1.22 Theorem. Every subset of E is measurable if m* E = 0.
Proof: Let F be any subset of E, where m* E = 0.
then since ⊆
this implies m* F ≤ m* E
this implies m* F ≤ 0
Also m* F ≥ 0
therefore m* F =0.
this implies F is measurable.
1.23 Theorem. Every singleton set is measurable.
Proof: Since outer measure of singleton set is zero and set of measure zero is measurable. Therefore,
singleton set is measurable.
8 Measure and Integration Theory
1.24 Theorem. Every countable set is measurable.
Proof: Since outer measure of countable set is zero and set of measure zero is measurable. Therefore
countable set is measurable.
1.25 Theorem. If a set E is measurable, then so is its complement Ec.
Proof. The definition is symmetrical with respect to Ec, and so if E is measurable, its complement Ec is
also measurable.
1.26 Theorem. Union of two measurable sets is measurable.
Proof. Let E1 and E2 be two measurable sets and let A be any set. Since E2 is measurable, we have
∗ = ∗ + ∗ (i)
and since = (ii)
Therefore by (ii) we have
∗ ∗ + ∗ (iii)
Thus
∗ + ∗
≤ ∗ + ∗ + ∗
= ∗ + ∗
≤ m* A (since E1 is measurable)
i.e. m* (A (E1 E2)) + m* (A (E1 E2)c) m* A
Hence E1 E2 is measurable.
If E1 and E2 are measurable, then E1 E2 is also measurable.
In fact we note that E1, E2 are measurable ⇒ , are measurable ⇒ is measurable ⇒
= is measurable.
Similarly, it can be shown that if E1 and E2 are measurable, then is also measurable.
1.27 Lemma. Difference of two measurable sets is also measurable.
Proof: Let E1 and E2 be two measurable sets. Then is measurable and hence
₁ ∩ = ₁ – ₂ is measurable, being the intersection of two measurable sets.
1.28 Definition. Algebra or Boolean Algebra: - A collection A of subsets of a set X is called an
algebra of sets or a Boolean Algebra if
(i) A, B A => A B A
(ii) A A => Ac A
(iii) For any two members A and B of A, the intersection A B is in A.
Because of De Morgan’s formulae (i) and (ii) are equivalent to (ii) and(iii).
Measurable Sets 9
It follows from the above definition that the collection M of all measurable sets is an algebra. The proof
is an immediate consequence of Theorems 1.25 and 1.26.
1.29 Definition. By a Boolean - algebra or simply a - algebra or Borel field of a collection of sets,
we mean a Boolean Algebra A of the collection of the sets such that union of any countable collection of
members of this collection is a member of A.
From De Morgan’s formula an algebra of sets is a - algebra or Borel field if and only if the
intersection of any countable collection of members of A is a member of A.
1.30 Lemma. Let A be any set, and , , … . , a finite sequence of disjoint measurable sets. Then
∗ = ∗
Proof. We shall prove this lemma by induction on n. The lemma is trivial for
n = 1. Let n > 1 and suppose that the lemma holds for n – 1 measurable sets Ei.
Since En is measurable, we have
∗
= ∑ ∗
= ∗ .
Hence the lemma.
1.31 Lemma. Let A be an algebra of subsets and a sequence of sets in A. Then there
exists a sequence of disjoint members of A such that
∈ = ∈
10 Measure and Integration Theory
∗ = ∑ ∗
=
∞
∞ ∞
m ⋂ = lm m
→∞
Measurable Sets 13
Proof. Let = ∞
and let = − . Then since {En} is a decreasing sequence. We have
= .
Also we know that if A and B are measurable sets then their difference − = is also
measurable. Therefore each Fi is measurable. Thus {Fi} is a sequence of measurable pairwise disjoint
sets.
∞ ∞
= ∩ ∪
∞
= ∩ ⋂
= ∩
= −
Hence
∞
m ⋃ = m −
∞
⇒ ∑ m = m −
⇒ ∞
m − = m − … (i)
Since = − ∪ , therefore
m = m − + m
⇒ m − m = m − (since m ≤ m < ∞ … (ii)
Again
= − ∪
⇒ m = m − + m
⇒ m − m = m − se ⊂ … (iii)
Therefore (i) reduces to
m − m = ∞
m − m ( us d )
14 Measure and Integration Theory
∞
⇒ m = lm m
→∞
⇒ m∞
= lm m
→∞
1.39 Remark. Show that the condition m(E1) <∞ is necessary in the above theorems.
Solution. Let En = [n, ∞)
Then, E1= [ 1,∞)
⟹m(E1) = m[1, ∞) = ∞
We show that the proposition of decreasing sequence does not hold in this case i.e. we want to show that
m(∩∞
) ≠ lm
→∞
For if, ∩∞ ∞
≠ ⟹ there exists x ∈∩
⟹ m(∩∞
) = 0 … (2)
From (1) and (2), we have
m(∩∞
) ≠
→∞
Measurable Sets 15
S0, theorem does not hold in this case.
1.40 Theorem. Let {En} be an increasing sequence of measurable sets. i.e. a sequence with ⊂
for each n. Let mE1 be finite, then
∞
⋃ = .
→∞
Proof. The sets E1, E2- E1, E3- E2, …, En - En+1 are measurable and are pairwise disjoint . Hence
∪ − ∪ … ∪ − ∪ …
is measurable and
∪ − ∪ … ∪ − ∪ …]
But
∪ − ∪ … ∪ − ∪ … is precisely ∞
Moreover,
=
→∞
1.41 Definition : The symmetric difference of the sets A and B is the union of the sets A-B and B-A .
It is denoted by ∆ .
1.42 Theorem. If ∆ = and E1 is measurable, then E2 is measurable. Moreover mE2 =
mE1 .
Proof . We have
E2 = ∪ − − − …(i)
16 Measure and Integration Theory
By hypothesis, both E2 – E1 and E1 – E2 are measurable and have measure zero. Since E1 and E2-E1 are
disjoint, ∪ − is measurable and
∪ − = + = . But, since
− ⊂ ∪ − ,
it follows from (i) that E2 is measurable and
= ∪ − − −
= − = .
This completes the proof.
1.43Definition. Let x and y be real numbers in [0,1]. The sum modulo 1 of x and y , denoted by
+ , is defined by
+ + <
+ =
+ − + ≥
It can be seen that + is a commutative and associative operation which takespair of numbersin [0,1) into
numbers in [0,1).
If we assign to each ∈ , the angle then addition modulo 1 corresponds to the addition of
angles.
If E is a subset of [0,1), we define the translation modulo 1 of E to be the set
+ = [z = x + y for some x ∈ .
+ + <
+ =
+ − + ≥
Clearly + ∈ ,
Measurable Sets 17
It can be seen that + is a commutative and associative operation which takes pair of numbers in [0,1)
We shall now show that Lebesgue measure is invariant under translation modulo 1.
1.46 Lemma. Let ⊂ , be a measurable set. Then for each ∈ , the set + is measurable
and m ( + = .
Proof. Let E1= E∩ , − and E2 = E ∩ − , . Then E1 and E2 are disjoint measurable sets
whose union is E, and so, mE = mE1 + mE2.
we observe that
+ ={ + : x ∈ }
+ + <
= ∈
+ − + ≥ .
But for x ∈ , we have x + y < 1 and so
+ = + , ∈ = + .
and hence + is measurable. Thus
m ( + = + = ,
since m is translation invariant. Also + = + − and so + is measurable and
m( + = . But
+ = + ∪ +
18 Measure and Integration Theory
And the sets ( + and ( + are disjoint measurable sets. Hence + is measurable and
m ( + = + ∪ +
= + + +
= +
= .
This completes the proof of the lemma.
1.47 Theorem: Prove that there exists a non-measurable set in interval [0,1).
Proof: First we define an equivalence relation in the set I= [0,1), By saying that x and y are equivalent
i.e., ∼ if and only if x-y is a rational number.
If x-y is a rational number, we say that x and y are equivalent and write x-y. It is clear that ∼ ; ∼
⟹ ∼ ∼ , ∼ ⟹ ∼ . Thus ‘ ∼’ is an equivalence relation in I.
Hence the relation ∼ partitions the set I = [0,1) into mutually disjoint equivalence classes, that is, classes
such that any two elements of one class differ by a rational number, while any two elements of different
classes differ by an irrational number.
Construct a set P by choosing exactly one element from each equivalence classes. Now we claim that P
is a non-measurable set.
Let < > be a sequence of the rational numbers in [0,1) with r0 = 0 and define Pi = P + ri.
=
(translation modulo 1 of P)
Then P0 = P.
We further prove that (i) ∩ = ∅, ≠ .
(ii) = ,
Proof: (i) Let ∩ ≠ ∅, ≠ .
Let ∈ ∩ . => ∈ ∈
Then∃ , ∈ = +
= +
Measurable Sets 19
+ = +
x ∈ +
x∈
x is in some .
, ⊆ ⋃
, , = ⋃ .
Now we prove P is non-measurable.
Assume that P is measurable, then clearly each Pi is measurable.
And m(Pi) = m +
∗ ≤ . ∴ ∗ = ∗ ∪ = ∑ ∗
But any point of the cantor set C must be in one of the intervals comprising the union C n, for each n ∈
, and as such ⊂ for all n ∈ . Hence
∗ ≤ ∗ ≤
This being true for each n ∈ , letting → gives ∗ = .
1.49 Example. If E1 and E2 are any measurable sets, show that
∪ + ∩ = + .
Proof. Let A be any set. Since E1 is measurable,
∗ = ∗ ∩ + ∗ ∩ .
We set = ∪ and we have
∗ ∪ = ∗ ∪ ∩ + ∗ ∪ ∩
Adding ∪ to both sides we have
∪ + ∩ = + ∗ ∪ ∩ + ∩ …
But
= ∪ ∩ ∪ ∪ .
Therefore
∪ ∩ ∪ ∪ =
Hence (1) reduces to
∑ < ∗ + ∈ .
∞
= ⋃ .
∗ = ∗ ⋃
∞
≤ ∑ m∗
∞
1.51 Theorem. Let E be a measurable set. Given ∈> , there is an open set
O ⊃ such that m∗ \ < ∈.
Proof. Suppose first that m E < . Then by the above theorem there is an open set O ⊃ such that
m∗ < m∗ + ∈
Since the sets O and E are measurable, we have
m∗ \ = m∗ − m∗ < ∈.
Consider now the case when m E = . Write the set R of real number as a union of disjoint finite
intervals; that is,
∞
= ⋃ .
Then, if En = E ∩ In, m(En) < . We can, thus, find open sets ⊃ such that
∈
m∗ − < .
∞
− = ⋃ − ⋃ ⊂ ⋃ −
∞
∗
m − ≤ ∑ m∗ <∈ .
. :
A set which is countable(finite or infinite) union of closed sets is called an sets. Note: The class of all
sets is denoted by . This F stands for ferme(closed) and for summe(sum).
Example: 1. A closed set.
2. A countable set
3. A countable union of set.
4. An open interval (a, b) since
∞
, = + , − and hence an open set.
- set:
A set which is countable intersection of open sets is a set.
Note: The class of all sets is denoted by This G stands for region and for intersection. The
complement of set is a set and conversely.
Example: 1. An open set in particular an open interval.
2. A closed set
3. A countable intersection of set.
4. A closed interval [a, b] since
, = ∞
− , + .
1.53 Theorem. Let E be any set then
(a) Given ɛ > 0,∃an open set ⊃ such that ∗ < ∗ + ɛ
∃ ⊃ such that m*(E) = m*(G).
Proof: (a) By definition, m* = , where ⊆
if m*(E) = ∞, then clearly result is true. If m*(E) < 0, there is a countable collection {In} of open
intervals such that
⊆ and ∗ + ɛ > (1)
Let = ⊆ , then O is an open set and ⊃
Also ∗ = ∗ ⊆
Measurable Sets 23
≤ ∑ ∗
∗ < ∗ +
Now define = ∪∞
, then G is a set.
= ⋃
Then = ∩
∞
= ⋂ ⋃
∞
= ⋃ ∩
∞
⟹ = ⋃ , = ∩
Let us define = ∞
m*(O-E) ≤ m*(∞
− )
≤ ∞ ∗
−
Measurable Sets 25
≤ ∞
= ɛ
⟹ m*(O-E) < ɛ
Now (ii) ⟹ (iii)
Let (ii) holds, then for each ∈ , ∃an open set ⊃ such that
m*(On-E) <
Let us define = ∞
, then G is a set.
Also since each ⊃
therefore ∞
⊃ this implies ⊃
G-E = ∞
− ⊆ −
m*(G-E) ≤ m*(On-E) <
Since n is arbitrary
m*(G-E) ≤ 0
⟹ m*(G-E) = 0.
Now (iii) ⟹ (i)
Let (iii) holds, then for given set E, ∃ a set ⊃ such that m*(G-E) = 0
⟹ G - E is measurable.
Now E = G- (G-E)
Now E is measurable being difference of two measurable sets.
Thus (i) ⟺ (ii) ⟺ (iii)
Now to show (i) ⟹ (iv)
Let (i) holds, and ɛ > 0 be given
then by (ii), for given set Ec, ∃ an open set ⊃ such that m*(G - Ec) < ɛ
Since ⊃ ⟹ ⊆
Let F = Gc
then F is a closed set contained in E,
Now E-F = ∩ = EՈG = GՈE = G – Ec
Now m*(E-F) = m*(G-Ec) < ɛ
m*(E-F) < ɛ.
To Show (iv) ⟹ (v)
Let (iv) holds, then for each ∈ ,∃a closed set ⊂ such that
26 Measure and Integration Theory
m*(E – Fn ) <
Let us define = ∞
Then F is a set.
Also, since each ⊂ ⟹ ∞
⟹ ⊆
Now E – F = E - ∞
⊆ −
⟹ m*(E-F) ≤ m*(E – Fn ) <
⟹ m*(E-F) ≤
Since n is arbitrary.
m*(E-F) ≤ 0
⟹ m*(E-F) = 0.
Now (v) ⟹ (i)
Let (v) holds, then for general E, ∃ a set F such that m*(E-F) = 0
⟹ E-F is measurable.
= − ∪
⟹ E is measurable.
This completes the proof.
(b) Take ɛ = ∀ ∈
this implies ⊃
⟹ m*(E) ≤ m*(G) ......(2)
Also G = ∞
⊆ ∀
m*(G) ≤ m*(On) for each n < m*(E) + , for each n in limiting case, we have
m*(G) ≤ m*(E)...(3)
Then from (2) and (3), we have
m*(G) = m*(E).
Measurable Sets 27
1.55 Theorem. Let E be a set with m* E < . Then E is measurable iff given > 0 , there is a finite
union B of open intervals such that m*(E B) <
Proof. Suppose E is measurable and let > 0 be given. The (as already shown) there exists an open set
O E such that m* (O- E) < . As m*E is finite, so is m*O. Since the open set O can be written as the
2
union of countable (disjoint) open intervals {Ii}, there exists an n N such that
l(I ) 2
i n 1
i (In fact m* O = l(I )
i n 1
i l(I ) 2
i n 1
i because m* O < )
Conversely, assume that for a given > 0 , there exists a finite union B = . if open intervals with
m* (E B) < . Then using “Let be any set. The given > 0 there exists an open set O E such
that m* O < m* E + there is an open set O E such that
m* O < m* E + (i)
If we can show that m* (O E) is arbitrary small, then the result will follow from “Let E be
set. Then the following are equivalent (i) E is measurable and (ii) given > 0 there is an open set O E
such that m * (O E) < ”. Write S = ∩ . Then S B and so
S E = (E - S) (S - E) (E S) (B E) . However,
E \ S = ( E OC ) ( E BC ) = E B, because E O . Therefore
S E (E B) (B E) = E B , and as such m* (S E) < . However,
E S (S E)
and so m* E < m* S + m* (S E)
<m*S+ ii)
Also,
O E = (O S) (S E)
Therefore
m* (O \ E) < m* O m* S +
< m* E + m* S + (using(i))
< m* S + + m*S + using(ii))
< m*S + + m* S +
=3.
Hence E is measurable.
SECTION – II
MEASURABLE FUNCTIONS
Measurable Function: An extended real valued function f defined on a measurable set E is said to be
measurable function if {x| f(x) > } is measurable for each real number .
2.1 Theorem. A constant function with a measurable domain is measurable.
Proof: Let f be a constant function with a measurable domain E and Let f : E→ be a constant function
i.e., f(x) = k ∀ ∈ .
To show that {x| f(x) > } is measurable for each real number .
, >
{x| f(x) > } = , =
, <
Since both are measurable, it follows that the set {x| f(x) > } and hence f is measurable.
2.2 Theorem. Let f be an extended real valued function defined on a measurable set E, Then f is
said to be measurable (Lebesgue function) if for any real any one of the following four
conditions is satisfied.
(a) {x| f(x) > } is measurable
(b) {x| f(x) ≥ } is measurable
(c) {x| f(x) < } is measurable
(d) {x| f(x) ≤ } is measurable.
Proof: We show that these four conditions are equivalent. First of all we show that (a) and (b) are
equivalent. Since
{x| f(x) > } = {x| f(x) ≤ }c
And also we know that complement of a measurable set is measurable, therefore (a) ⟹(d) and
conversely.
Similarly since (b) and (c) are complement of each other, (c) is measurable if (b) is measurable and
conversely.
Therefore, it is sufficient to prove that (a) ⟹(b) and conversely.
Firstly we show that (b) ⟹ .
The set {x| f(x) ≥ } is given to be measurable.
Now
Measurable Functions 29
{x| f(x) > } = {x| f(x) ≥ + }
n 1
But by (b), {x| f(x) ≥ + } is measurable. Also we know that countable union of measurable sets is
measurable. Hence {x| f(x) > } is measurable which implies that (b) ⟹(a).
Conversely, let (a) holds. We have
{x| f(x) ≥ } = {x| f(x) ≥ − }
n 1
The set {x| f(x) > − } is measurable by (a). Moreover, intersection of measurable sets is also
measurable . Hence {x| f(x) ≥ } is also measurable . Thus (a) ⟹ (b).
Hence the four conditions are equivalent.
2.3 Remark: We can say that f is measurable function if for any real number , any of the four
conditions in the above theorem holds.
2.4 Lemma. If is an extended real number then these four conditions imply that {x| f(x) = } is
also measurable.
Proof. Let be a real number, then
{x| f(x) = } = {x| f(x) ≥ } ∩ {x| f(x) ≤ }.
Since {x| f(x) ≥ } and {x| f(x) ≤ } are measurable by conditions (b) and (d), the set {x| f(x) = } is
measurable being the intersection of measurable sets.
Suppose = . Then {x| f(x) = } = {x| f(x) >
n 1
Which is measurable by the condition (a) and the fact intersection of measurable sets is measurable.
Similarly when = −, then
{x| f(x) = −} = {x| f(x) < −, which is again measurable by conditions (c).Hence the
n 1
results follows.
2.5 Theorem: If f is measurable function on each of the sets in a countable collection {E i} of
disjoint measurable sets, then f is measurable on E = .
Proof: Let E = . Then E is measurable being countable union of measurable sets is measurable.
Let be any real number.
Consider the set {x∈ | f(x) > } = ∈ : > is measurable.
Because f is measurable on each Ei.
∈ : > is measurable.
30 Measure and Integration Theory
{x∈ | f(x) > } is measurable.
Hence f is measurable on E.
2.6 Theorem: If f is measurable function on E and ⊆ is measurable set then f is a measurable
function on E1.
Proof: Let be any real number.
Consider the set {x∈ | f(x) > } = {x∈ | f(x) > }∩ is measurable.
2.7 Theorem. If f and g are measurable functions on a common domain E, then the set
A= {x∈ E: f(x)< g(x)} is measurable.
Proof. For each rational number r, define
= { x∈ E: f(x) < r < g(x)}
Or we can write
= { x∈ E: f(x)< r}∩ {x∈ E: g(x)> r}
Since f and g are measurable on E, so the two sets on R.H.S. are measurable sets is measurable.
Now, we observe that
{x∈E: f(x) <g(x)} = ∈
Since the rationals are countable, so A is countable union of measurable sets and so is measurable.
This proves the theorem.
2.8 Theorem. A continuous function defined on a measurable set is measurable.
Proof. Let f be a continuous function defined on measurable set E. Let be any real number. We now
claim that {x ∈ E : f(x) ≥ } is closed.
Let A= { x ∈ E: f(x) ≥ } (1)
To prove that A is closed, it is sufficient to show that ⊆ . (2)
being derived set of A.
Let ∈ be arbitrary element. Then ∈ implies is limit point of A.
It implies that there exist a sequence { } whose elements ∈ such that
lm =
→∞
Now if f and g are two measurable real valued functions defined on the same domain, we shall show that
f+g is measurable. To show that it is sufficient to show that the set
{x| f(x)+ > } is measurable.
if f(x) +g(x)> , then | f(x) > − and by he cor. of the axiom of Archimedes there is a rational
number r such that − <r<f(x)
since the functions f and g are measurable , the sets {x| f(x) > and {x| f(x) > − } are measurable.
Therefore, there intersection Sr={x| f(x) > − }∩ {x| f(x) > − } also measurable.
It can be shown that {x|f(x)+ > =∪ {Sr | r is rational}
Since the set of rational is countable and countable union of measurable sets is measurable , the set
∪ {Sr | r is rational} and hence {x|f(x)+ > is measurable which proves that
f(x) +g(x) is measurable. From this part it follows that f- g = f (-g) is also measurable, since when g is
measurable (-g) is also measurable. Next we consider fg.
1
The measurability of fg follows that from the identity fg = [( f g ) 2 f 2 g 2 ] , if we prove that f2
2
is measurable when f is measurable. For this it is sufficient to prove that
{x|∈ f2(x) > }, is real number, is measurable.
Let be a negative real number. Then it is clear that the set {xf2(x) > } = E (domain of the
measurable function f). But E is measurable by the definition of f. Hence {xf2(x) > } is measurable
when < .
Now let ≥ , then {xf2(x) > }= {x| f(x) > √} ∪{x| f(x) < −√}.
Since f is measurable, it follows from this equality that {xf2(x) > } is measurable for ≥ .
Hence f2 is also measurable when f is also measurable. Therefore, the theorem follows from the above
identity, since measurability of f and g imply the measurability of f+g.
34 Measure and Integration Theory
Consider (g≠ = f.
First we have to prove that is measurable.
Consider the set ∶ ( ) > = ∶ >
Since g is measurable in each case ,i.e., ∶ ( ) > is measurable.
is measurable.
Since f and are measurable.
is measurable.
Proof. Define a function M(x) = , , … , we shall show that
{x| M(x)> }is measurable. In fact {x| M(x)> }= : >
Measurable Functions 35
Since each fi is measurable, each of the set {x| fi(x)> }is measurable and therefore their union is also
measurable. Hence {x| M(x)> } and so M(x) is measurable. Similarly we define the function m(x) =
inf {f1,f2,,,,fn}, since {x| m(x)< = : < and
since {x| fi(x)< }is measurable on account of the the measurability of fi, it follows that {x| m(x)< }
and so m(x) is measurable . Define a function M’(x) = sup f n ( x) = sup{f1,f2,,,,fn}
n
We shall show that the set {x| M’(x)> } is measurable for any real .
Now {x| M’(x)> }= ∞
: > is measurable, since each fn is measurable.
f ∧g =
Now measurability of f _ measurability of |f|. Also if f and g are measurable, then f+g, f-g are
measurable. Hence f∨g and f ∧g are measurable.
1, x E
2.21 Definition. Characteristic function of a set E is defined by E ( X )
0, x E
This is also known as indicator function.
2.22 Examples of measurable function
1, x E
Example. Let E be a set of rationals in [0,1]. Then the characteristic function E ( X ) is
0, x E
measurable.
1, x E
Proof. For the set of rationals in the given interval, we have E ( X )
0, x E
It is sufficient to prove that { x | E ( X ) > is measurable for any real .
Hence the set { x | E ( X ) > is empty in this very case. But outer measure of any empty set is zero.
Hence for ≥ , the set { x | E ( X ) > and so E ( X ) is measurable .
Lastly, let ≤ . Then { x | E ( X ) > } = [0,1] and therefore measurable. Hence the result.
1, x A
Proof. Let A be measurable. Then A ( x)
0, x A
Hence it is clear from the definition that domain of A is A ∪Ac which is measurable due to the
measurability of A. Therefore, if we prove that the
38 Measure and Integration Theory
But A is given to be measurable. Hence for ≥0. The set {x | A( x ) > } is measurable.
Hence {x | A( x ) > } is measurable for < 0 also, since A ∪AC has been proved to be measurable.
Hence if A is measurable, then A is also measurable. Conversely, let us suppose that A( x ) is
measurable. That is,
the set {x | A( x ) > } is measurable for any real .
Therefore, measurability of{x | A( x ) > } implies that of the set A for ≥0 . Now consider < 0. Then
{x | A( x ) > }= A∪AC
Thus measurability A( x ) of implies measurability of the set A∪AC which imply A is measurable.
2.24 Simple Function: Let f be a real valued function defined on X. If the range of f is finite. We say
that f is a simple function.
1, x E
Let E⊆X and put E ( X )
0, x E
Suppose the range of f consists of the distinct number c1, c2, …, cn.
Let Ei = : = = , , … ,
Then f =
i.e., every simple function is a finite linear combination of characteristic function. It is clear that f is
measurable if and only if the sets E1, E2, …, En are measurable.
2.25 Remarks:
1. Every step function is a simple function.
2. Every simple function is measurable.
Proof: Let f be a simple function defined as above.
Then we have
f(x) = (x)
= 1 + 2 + ⋯ +
∴ = , ∈
= , ∈
∴ = , ∈
Measurable Functions 39
∴ = : =
Since each Ei is measurable. Thus is measurable because is measurable if and only if A is
measurable.
Hence f is measurable.
3. Characteristic function of measurable set is a simple function.
4. Product of the simple function and finite linear combination of simple functions is again a
simple function.
2.26 Theorem. (Approximation Theorem). For every non-negative measurable function f, there
exists a non-negative non-decreasing sequence {fn } of simple functions such that = ,
→
x ∈E
In the general case if we do not assume non-negativeness of f , then we say For every measurable
function f, there exists a sequence {fn }, n ∈N of simple function which converges (pointwise) to f . i.e.
“Every measurable function can be approximated by a sequence of simple functions.”
Proof. Let us assume that f(x) ≥0 and x ∈E . Construct a sequence
, ≤ < = , ,
fn(x) = } for every n ∈N.
, ≥
If we take n = 1, then
, ≤ < = ,
f1 (x) = }
, ≥
, ≤ <
That is, f1(x) = ,
≤ <
≥
Similarly taking n = 2, we obtain
, ≤ < = ,, , ,8
f2(x) = 4 4 4 }
, ≥
That is,
≤ < 4
≤ <
4 4
f2(x)= … … … … … … …
………………..
7 7 ≤ <
4 4
≥
40 Measure and Integration Theory
Similarly we can write f3(x) (x) and so on. Clearly all fn are positive whenever f is positive and also it is
clear that fn ≤ fn+1. Moreover fn takes only a finite number of values. Therefore {fn} is a sequence of
non-negative, non decreasing functions which assume only a finite number of values.
Let us denote
Eni = , = ∈ ≤ <
and
En = . = ∈ ≥
Both of them are measurable. Let
n 2n
i 1
fn n
Eni n En for every n ∈ N .
i 1 2
n 2n
i 1
Now 2
i 1
n
E is measurable, since E
ni ni
has been shown to be measurable and characteristic
measurable. Hence each fn is measurable. Now we prove the convergence of this sequence.
Let f(x) < . That is f is bounded. Then for some n we have
≤ <
- ≤ - <
0 ≤f(x) -
<
0 ≤f(x) – fn(x) <
(by the def of fn (x))
f lim n ''( x) (ii)
n
where ∅ and ∅ are simple functions. Also we have proved already that
f = f −
= lim n ( x)
n
(since the difference of two simple functions is again a simple function). Hence the theorem.
We now introduce the terminology “almost everywhere” which will be frequently used in the Sequel.
2.27 Definition. A statement is said to hold almost everywhere in E if and only if it holds
everywhere in E except possibly at a subset D of measure zero.
(a) Two functions f and g defined on E are said to be equal almost everywhere in E iff
f(x) =g(x) everywhere except a subset D of E of measure zero.
(b) A function defined on E is said to be continuous almost everywhere in E if and only
if ther
2.28 Theorem. (a) If f is a measurable function on the set E and ⊆ is measured set, then f is a
measurable function on .
(b) If f is a measurable function on each of the sets in a countable collection{Ei } of disjoint measurable
sets, then f is measurable.
Proof. (a) For any real , we have {x ∈ , f(x) > } = { x ∈E; f(x) > } ∩E1. The result follows as
the set on the right-hand side is measurable.
(b)Write E = Ei , Clearly, E, being the union of measurable set is measurable. The result now
i 1
E1 – E2 and E2 – E1.
∵ ∈ − ⟹ ∈ ∉
These are subsets of : ≠
> , ≯ ⟹ ≠
But f = g a.e.
m: ≠ = 0
− ⊆ : ≠
m( − ) ≤ m: ≠ = 0
m( − ) ≤ 0 But m( − ) ≥ 0
m( − ) = 0
Similarly m( − ) =0
∴ m( − ) = 0 = m( − )
( − ) and ( − ) are measurable.
E2 = [E1 ∪( E2 – E1)] - ( E1 – E2)
Since E1, E2 – E1 and ( E1 – E2)C are measurable therefore it follows that E2 is measurable. Hence the
theorem is proved.
2.30. Corollary. Let {fn} be a sequence of measurable functions such that lim f n f almost
n
measurable. Also, it is given that lim f n = f a.e. Therefore, using the above theorem, it follows that f is
n
measurable.
2.31 Definition: (Restriction of f to E1)
Let f be a function defined on E, then the function f1 defined on E1 contained in E .i.e., E1 ⊆ E by f1(x) =
f(x), x ∈ E1 is called restriction of f to E1 and denoted by f/ E1.
2.32 Exercise : Let f be a measurable function defined on E, then its restriction to E1 is also
measurable where E1 is a measurable subset of E.
Solution : Let f1 = f/ E1 i.e., f1 is restriction of f to E1.
Let .
{x ∈ : f1(x) > } = { x ∈E1: f(x) > } [∵ = ]
Measurable Functions 43
= { x ∈E: f(x) > } ∩ E1is measurable on E and E1 is also measurable and
intersection of measurable sets is measurable. Hence f1 is measurable on E1.
2.33Exercise: .
.
lm = .
→∞
= .
2.28 Theorem. Let E be a measurable set with finite measure and {fn} be a sequence of measurable
functions converging almost everywhere to a real valued function f defined on a set E. Then given
> 0 and > , there corresponds a measurable subset A of E with m(A) < and an integer N
such that − < ∀ ∈ − ≥ .
Proof: Let F be a set of points of E for which ↛f. Then m(F) = 0.
Since fn (x) →f(x) almost everywhere, then
fn (x) →f(x) ∀ ∈ − =
Now applying the last theorem for the set , we get a set A1 ⊆ E1 with m(A1) < and an integer N
such that − < ∀ ∈ − ≥ .
Now the required result follows if we take
= ∪ .
= ∪ = + = + = <
Also − = − ∪ = ∩ ∪
= ∩ ∩ = ∩ ∩
= − ∩ = ∩ = −
i.e., E-A = −
Hence we have found a set A ⊆ E with m(A) < and an integer N such that − < ∀ ∈
− ≥ .
2.29 Definition: A Sequence {fn} of functions is said to converge almost uniformly everywhere to a
measurable function f defined on a measurable set E if for each >0, ∃ A ⊆ E with
m(A) < such that and an integer N such that − .
2.30 Theorem.(Egoroff’s Theorem). Let {fn} be a sequence of measurable functions defined on a set E
of finite measure such that fn (x) →f(x) almost everywhere. Then to each > 0 there corresponds a
measurable subset A of E such that m (A) < such that fn(x) converges to f(x) uniformly on E-A.
Proof. Applying last theorem with = , = ⁄
We get a measurable subset A1⊆ E with m (A1) < ⁄ and positive integer N1 such that
Then we have
∞
m(A) ≤ ∞ ∞
< ⁄ = . = .
Since , and countable union of open set is open.
⇒ ⇒ .
Lemma 2. Let f: [a, b] → be a measurable function, then given
> , ∃ = , − < .
Clearly D is measurable.
∗ ∗
Therefore m(D) ≤ ∞ ∞
− + −
m(D) < ∞
+ ∞
. .
= + =
⇒ < .
Now E and D are measurable.
E-D is measurable.
Then for given > , ∃ ⊆ − − − <
Now E-F = D∪ − −
m(E-F) = m(D) + m − − < + =
Let h = f/F
To show that h is continuous on F.
For rational number ,
: ≤ = : ≤ ∩
= ∗ ∩ = ∗ − ∗ ∪ ∗ ∩
= ∗ − ∗ ∩ ∪ ∗ ∩
= ∅ ∪ ∗ ∩
= ∗ ∩
48 Measure and Integration Theory
∞ ∞
= ⋃ − ∪ ⋃ ∗ − ∗
∗ ∗
⇒ − ⊂
∵ ⊆ − ⇒ ∩ = ∅.
: ≤ = ∗ ∩
Since ∗ = , .
∗ ∩ .
: ≤ .
By lemma 1, h is continuous.
So f/F is continuous.
Lusin Theorem:(Proof):- We have
f:[a, b]→ is measurable function, then by lemma(2), for given > , ∃ ⊂
− < = .
Now using result “Every real valued continuous function defined on a closed subset of a real
number can be extended continuously to all real numbers.”
So h can be extended to continuous function h*: R→ .
Let g :[a, b]→ ,
∈ , = .
∈ : ≠ ⊆ −
∈ : ≠ ≤ − < .
“Convergence in Measure”
The notion of convergence in measure is introduced by F.Reisz and E.Fisher in 1906-07.
Sometimes it is also called approximate convergence.
2.32 Definition. A sequence < fn > of measurable functions is said to convergence in measure to f on a
set E, written as → ,
If given > 0, ∃ ∈ N such that for all n ≥ , we have
− ≥ < .
Or lm − ≥ =
→∞
This means that for all sufficiently large value of n, functions of the sequence < fn > differ from the
limit function f by a small quantity with the exception of the set of point whose measure is arbitrary
small (<.
2.33 Theorem: If sequence converges in measure to the function f, then it converges in
measure to every function g which is equivalent to the function.
Proof: For each > , we have
: − ≥ ⊂ : ≠ ∪ : − ≥
Measurable Functions 49
Since g is equivalent to f, then we have
: ≠ = .
: − ≥ ≤ : ≠ + : − ≥
≤ : − ≥ <
⇒ → .
Hence the result.
2.34 Theorem: If sequence converges in measure to the function f, then the limit function f is
unique a.e.
Proof: Let g be another function such that → .
Since − ≤ − + −
Now we observe that for each > ,
: − ≥ ⊂ : − ≥ ∪ : − ≥
Since by proper choice of , the measure of both the sets on the right can be made arbitrary small, we
have
: − ≥ =0
f = g almost everywhere. Hence the proof.
2.35 Theorem: Let be a sequence of measurable functions which converges to f a.e. on
X. Then → .
Proof: For each n∈ > ,
= ∈ : − ≥
Let > , ∃ ⊂
With m(A) < and the number N such that
− < ∀ ∈ − ≥
Then it follows that ⊂ ∀ ≥
< < ∀ ≥
lm =
→∞
Hence → .
2.36 Remark: The converse of the above theorem need not be true i.e, convergence in measure is
more general than a.e. infact there are sequence of measurable functions that converges in
measure but fails to converge at any point.
To affect we consider the following example
: , →
+
= , ∈ ,
,
50 Measure and Integration Theory
Let n = + ≤ ≤ .
Let > . Choose an m ∈ <
∵ = + < +
= < [ ] (*)
< . , <
≤ < ∀ ≥
And = ∞
Hence m(E) = 0.
Thus it remains to be verified that the sequence < > converges to f on X-E.
So let ∉ . Then ∉ for some positive integer m.
i.e., ∉ : − ≥ , ≥
⇒ − < , ≥
But → as k→
Lebesgue integration is an alternative way of defining the integral in terms of measure theory that is
used to inte grate a much broader class of functions than the Riemann integral or even the Riemann-
Stieltjes integral. The idea behind the Lebesgue integral is that instead of approximating the total area by
dividing it into vertical strips, one approximates the total area by dividing it into horizontal strips.
3.1 The shortcomings of the Riemann integral suggested the further investigations in the theory of
integration. We give a resume of the Riemann Integral first.
Let f be a bounded real- valued function on the interval [a, b] and let
= ξ < ξ < ⋯ < ξ =
Be a partition of [a, b]. Then for each partition we define the sums
= ξ − ξ
and s = ξ − ξ m
where
= up , m =
ξi1 xξi ξi1 xξi
With the infimum taken over all possible subdivisions of [a, b].
Similarly, we define the lower integral
b
a d = sup s.
The upper integral is always at least as large as the lower integral, and if the two are equal we say that f
is Riemann integrable and call this common value the Riemann integral of f. We shall denote it by
b
a
where = = . This representation for is called the canonical representation and
it is characterized by the fact that the Ai are disjoint and the ai distinct and non- zero.
If vanishes outside a set of finite measure, we define the integral by
∫ d = ∑ m
54 Measure and Integration Theory
when has the canonical representation = χA . we sometimes abbreviate the expression for
i
= ⋃
i aj
= ∑ χA
j
Consequently, we obtain
= m
= m i aj
= i aj m ( Since Ei are disjoint, additivity of measures applies )
∑ m
= ∑ χ
k
The Lebesgue Integral 55
N
ψ = ∑ χ
k
and so
N N
+ ψ = ∑ χ + ∑ χ
k k
N N
= ∑ χ + ∑ χ
k k
N
Therefore
N
= ∑ m + ∑ m
= + ψ .
To prove the second statement, we note that
∫− ∫ψ = ∫ − ψ ≥ ,
Since the integral of a simple function which is greater than or equal to zero almost everywhere is
non- negative by the definition of the integral.
3.6. Remark. We know that for any simple function we have
N
= ∑ χ
i
Suppose that this representation is neither canonical nor the sets Ei’s are disjoint. Then using the fact
that characteristics functions are always simple function we observe that
∫ = ∫ χ + ∫ χ + … + ∫ χ
1 2 n
= χ E + χ E + ⋯ + χ E
1 2 n
= ∑ m
∫ = ∑ m
Let f be a bounded real valued function and E be a measurable set of finite measure. By analogy with the
Riemann integral we consider for simple functions and ψ the numbers
∫ ψ
ψf
and
sup ∫
ϕf
and ask when these two numbers are equal. The answer is given by the following proposition .
3.7. Theorem. Let f be defined and bounded on a measurable set E with mE finite. In order that
For all simple functions and ψ, it is necessary and sufficient that f be measurable.
Proof. Let f be bounded by M and suppose that f is measurable. Then the sets
KM KM
= | ≥ > , − ≤ ≤ ,
∑ m = m
The simple function defined by
ψ = ∑ χ
k
and
= ∑ −χ
k
satisfy
≤ ≤ ψ
The Lebesgue Integral 57
M
Thus ψd ≤ ψ d = m
M
and sup d ≥ d = − m
M M
hence ≤ ψd − sup d ≤ m = m .
m, = . l.
xεk
3.10. Definition. By a measurable partition of E we mean a finite collection P = {E1, E2, …, En} of
measurable subsets of E such that
⋃ =
As in the case of Riemann integral, we can see that every upper sum for f is greater than or equal to
every lower sum for f.
We then define the Lebesgue upper and lower integral of a bounded function f on E by
U; d sup L;
P P
The Lebesgue Integral 59
Respectively taken over all measurable position of E. We denote them respectively by
∫ d ∫
̅
∫ d ∫
̅
∫ ψ = ∑ m
∫ = ∫ ψd
∫ = sup ∫ d
̅
̅
for all simple functions and ψ, it is necessary and sufficient that f is measurable.”
And our definition of Lebesgue integration takes the form :
“ If f is a bounded measurable function defined on a measurable set E with mE finite , we define the
(Lebesgue) integral of f over E by
∫ d = ∫
a a
Proof . Since f is a bounded function defined on [a, b] and is Riemann integrable, therefore,
̅
b b
and
b b
̅
b b
∫ d = ∫ d
a a
b b
⇒ a d = sup a ψd (i)
ϕf ψf
Since + ξ ≤ + ≤ ψ + η , we have
∫ + = ∫ + ∫
∫− ≥
For every simple function ψ ≥ − , we have ψ ≥ almost everywhere in E. This means that ψ ≥
Hence we obtain
= ∫ χA + ∫ χB
A∪B A∪B
= ∫+ ∫
A B
If ≤ on E then ≤ .
Or
Integrals over set of measure zero are zero.
Proof : Since f is bounded on E so there exist constant A and B such that
≤ ≤
Since m(E) = 0 ⇒ =
3.18. Corollary. If f(x) = k a.e. on E then = . m . In particular if f = 0 a.e. on E then =
Therefore =
= -1 + 1 = 0
Clearly ≠ a.e as m ∈ −, ; ≠ = m−, = ≠
So converse is not true.
3.21.Corollary. If = and ≥ on E then f = 0 a.e.
If possible, suppose there is a positive integer N such that m( > .
Then ≥ ≥ m( >
1 N N
⇒ ≤
⇒ lm ≤ … (1)
Now by Fatou’s Lemma ≤ lm … (2)
From (1) and (2), we have
lm ∫ = lm ∫
3.24. Remark : The technique used in above theorem helps us to evaluate the lebesgue integral of non-
negative bounded and unbounded functions.
3.25. Example : Evaluate the Lebesgue integral of the function f : [0,1] →
⁄ < ≤
f(x) = ⁄
=
Clearly f is unbounded, non-negative function defined on [0,1]. Now define a sequence of functions {fn}
on [0,1] as
≤
fn(x) =
<
≥
3
i.e. fn(x) = {
<
3
Clearly {fn} is increasing sequence of non-negative measurable functions such that fn→ . So by
monotone convergence theorem
66 Measure and Integration Theory
∫ = lm ∫ .
→∞
Proof. We shall apply Egoroff’s theorem to prove this theorem. Accordingly for a given ε > , there is
ϵ
an N and a measurable set ⊂ such that m < and for ≥ and ε we have
4M
− <
m
= ∫ − + ∫ −
0 c0
< . m +
m
< + = .
Hence
∫ → ∫
The Lebesgue Integral 67
3.27. Remark : Bounded Convergence Theorem need not be true in Riemann integral .
3.28. Example : Let {ri} be a sequence of all rational numbers in [0,1].
Define = ∶ = ,, … , , ∈
∈
and for each ∈ , consider the function = = , , … ,
∉
clearly each is bounded, also is discontinuous at n-points in [0,1] namely points of
i.e., , , … , .
At =
lm ≠ ≠ lm
x→r
1 x→r1
∵ ∪ = ,
= ∫ d + ∫ d
Sn Scn
= ∫ d + ∫ d = . m =
Sn Scn
⇒ lm ∫ d =
→∞
∫ = sup ∫ ,
hf
∫ ≤ ∫
Proof. The proof of (i) and (iii) follow directly from the theorem concerning properties of the integrals
of bdd functions.
We prove (ii) in detail.
If ≤ and ≤ , we have + ≤ + , and so
∫ + ≤ ∫ +
i.e. + ≤ + .
Taking suprema, we have
(iv) + ≤ +
On the other hand, let ℓ be a bounded measurable function which vanishes outside a set finite measure
and which is not greater than + . Then we define the functions h and k by setting
= m, ℓ
and = ℓ −
we have ≤ ,
≤
while h and k are bounded by the bound ℓ and vanish where ℓ vanishes. Hence
The Lebesgue Integral 69
∫ℓ = ∫+∫ ≤ ∫ +∫
sup ∫ ℓ ≤ ∫ + ∫
ℓfg
That is,
(v) + ≥ +
From (iv) and (v), we have
∫ + = ∫ + ∫
3.31. Fatou’s lemma. If < fn >is a sequence of non-negative measurable functions and fn(x) → f(x)
almost everywhere on a set E, then
∫ ≤ lm ∫
Proof. Let h be a bounded measurable function which is not greater than f and which vanishes outside a
set E’ of finite measure. Define a function hn by setting
hn(x) = min{h(x), fn(x)}
Then hn is bounded but bounds for h and vanishes outside E’ . Now hn(x) →h(x) for each x in E’ .
Therefore by “Bounded Convergence theorem” we have
∫ = ∫ = lm ∫ ≤ lm ∫
∫ ≤ lm ∫
Also R = = +
1 2 1 2
= + = m =
1
So R < lm R
3.33. Fatou’s lemma need not good unless the function fn is non – negative
− ≤ ≤
Let us consider the function fn(x) =
otewse
Hence lm = = a.e ⇒ d =
→∞
Also d = d + d
1 2
⁄
=⁄ − d + = −
Thus lm d = −
3.34. Theorem( Lebesgue Monotone Convergence theorem). Let < fn > be an increasing sequence of
non negative measurable functions and let f = lim fn . Then
∫ = lm ∫
∫ ≤ lm ∫
∫ ≤ ∫
Hence
∫ = ∫
3.35. Definition. A non-negative measurable functions f is called integrable over the measurable over
the measurable set E if
∫ <
The Lebesgue Integral 71
3.36. Theorem. Let f and g be two non-negative measurable functions. If f is integrable over E and
g(x)<f(x) on E, then g is also integrable on E, and
∫ − = ∫ − ∫
Set fn(x) = f(x) if f(x) ≤ n and fn(x) = n otherwise. Then each fn is bounded and fn converges to f at each
point. By the monotone convergence theorem there is an N such that > −
− < .
Choose < . If mA < , we have
∫ = ∫ − + ∫
∫ ≤ ∫ =
< + = .
3.38. The General Lebesgue Integral
We have already defined the positive part and negative part of a function as
= ,
= −,
Also it was shown that
= −
= +
With these notions in mind, we make the following definition.
72 Measure and Integration Theory
3.39. Definition. A measurable function f is said to be integrable over E if and are both integrable
over E. In this case we define
∫ = ∫ − ∫
∫ + = ∫ + ∫
(ii) If ≤ . ., then
∫ ≤ ∫
∫ = ∫ + ∫
∪
∫ = ∫ + − +
= ∫ + − ∫ +
= ∫ + ∫ − ∫ − ∫
= ∫ − ∫ + ∫ − ∫
= ∫ + ∫ = ∫ + ∫
∗It should be noted that f+g is not defined at points where f = and g = − and where f = − and
g = . However, the set of such points must have measure zero, since f and g are integrable. Hence the
integrability and the value of + is independent of the choice of values in these ambiguous cases.
3.41. Theorem. Let f be a measurable function over E. Then f is integrable over E iff is integrable
over E. Moreover, if f is integrable, then
∫ = ∫
Proof. If f is integrable then both and are integrable. But = + . Hence integrability of
and implies the integrability of .
Moreover, if f is integrable, then since ≤ = , the property which states that if ≤
a.e. , then ≤ implies that
∫ ≤ ∫
∫ = ∫
→∞
Proof. Since ≤ for every and f(x) = , we have ≤ . Hence fn and f are
→∞
integrable. The function g – fn is non-negative, therefore by Fatou’s Lemma we have
= ∫ − ∫
Whence ≥ lm
Similarly considering g + fn we get
∫ ≤ lm ∫
The “fundamental theorem of the integral calculus” is that differentiation and integration are inverse
processes. This general principle may be interpreted in two different ways.
If f(x) is integrable, the function
F(x) =
is called the indefinite integral of f(x); and the principle asserts that(i) ́ (x) = f(x) (ii)
On the other hand, if F(x) is a given function, and f(x) is defined by (ii), the principle asserts that
x
a tdt = F(x) − F(a) (iii)
The main object of this chapter is to consider in what sense these theorems are true.
From the theory of Riemann integration (ii) follows from (i) if x is a point of continuity of f. For we can
choose h0 so small that |f(t) −f(x)| < for |t−x| ≤ h0; and the
ℎ xh
− = t − dt ≤ ( |h| < h0) by the mean-value theorem.
ℎ ℎ x
This proves (ii).
We shall show that more generally this relation holds almost everywhere. Thus differentiation is the
inverse of Lebesgue integration.
The problem of deducing (iii) from (ii) is more difficult and even using Lebesgue integral it is true only
for a certain class of functions. We require in the first place that ́ (x)should exist at any rate almost
everywhere and as we shall see this is not necessarily so. Secondly, if ́ (x) exists we require that it
should be integrable.
Differentiation of Monotone Functions
4.1. Definition. Let C be a collection of intervals. Then we say that C covers a set E in the sense of
Vitali, if for each > 0 and x in E there is an interval I ∈ C such that x∈I and l(I) < .
Now we prove the following lemma which will be utilized in proving a result concerning the
differentiation of monotone functions.
4.2. Lemma. (Vitali). Let E be a set of finite outer measure and C a collection of intervals which cover
E in the sense of Vitali. Then given > 0 there is a finite disjoint collection {I1,…, In} of intervals in C
such that
m*[E− ∪
] < .
76 Measure and Integration Theory
Proof. It suffices to prove the lemma in the case that each interval in C is closed, for otherwise we
replace each interval by its closure and observe that the set of endpoints of I1, I2,…, IN has measure zero.
Let O be an open set of finite measure containing E. Since C is a Vitali covering of E, we may suppose
without loss of generality that each I of C is contained in O. We choose a sequence <In > of disjoint
intervals of C by induction as follows :
Let I1 be any interval in C and suppose I1,…, In have already been chosen. Let kn be the supremum of
the lengths of the intervals of C which do not meet any of the intervals I1,…,In .
Since each I is contained in O, we have kn ≤ m O < . Unless, E ⊂ ∪ I we can find In+1 in C
with l(In+1) > kn and In+1 is disjoint from I1, I2,…, In. Thus we have a sequence < In > of disjoint
intervals of C, and since U In ⊂O, we have In) ≤ m < .
Hence we can find an integer N such that ∞
<
Let R=E− ∪
.
It remains to prove that m*R < .
Let x be an arbitrary point of R. Since ∪
is a closed set not containing x, we can find an
interval I in C which contains x and whose length is so small that I does not meet any of the intervals
I1, I2,…, IN . If now I ∩ Ii = ∅ for i ≤ N, we must have l(I) ≤ kN < 2l (IN+1). Since lim l(In) = 0 , the
interval I must meet at least one of the intervals In. Let n be the smallest integer such that I meets In.
We have n > N, and l(I) ≤ kN ≤ 2l (IN+1). Since x is in I, and I has a point in common with In, it follows
that the distance from x to the midpoint of In is at most l(I) + l (IN) ≤ l (IN+1).
Let Jm denote the interval which has the same midpoint as Im and five times the length of Im. Then
we have x ∈ Jm. This proves R ⊂∪∞ J
Hence m* R≤ ∞ ∞
= < .
ffℎ
D f(x) = lm
ℎ→ ℎ
fℎf
D f(x) = lm ℎ→
ℎ
ffℎ
D f(x) = lm ℎ→
ℎ
Differentiation and Integration 77
always exist. These derivatives are known as Dini Derivatives of the function f.
D+ f(x) and D+ f(x) are called upper and lower derivatives on the right and D f(x) and D f(x) are called
upper and lower derivatives on the left. Clearly we have D+ f(x) ≥ D+ f(x) and D f(x) ≥ D f(x).
If D+ f(x) = D+ f(x), the function f is said to have a right hand derivative and if D f(x) = D f(x), the
function is said to have a left hand derivative.
If D+ f(x) = D+ f(x) = D f(x) = D f(x)≠ ∓ we say that f is differentiable at x and define f’(x) to
be the common value of the derivatives at x.
4.3.Theorem. Every non-decreasing function f defined on the interval [a, b] is differentiable almost
everywhere in [a, b]. The derivative f’ is measurable and
b
a d = f(b) − f(a)
Proof. We shall show first that the points x of the open interval (a, b) at which not all of the four Dini-
derivatives of f are equal form a subset of measure zero. It suffices to show that the following four
subsets of (a, b) are of measure zero:
A = {x ∈ (a, b) | D- f(x) < D+ f(x) },
B = {x ∈ (a, b) | D+ f(x) < D- f(x) },
C = {x ∈ (a, b) | D- f(x) < D- f(x) },
D = {x ∈ (a, b) | D+ f(x) < D+ f(x) }. To prove m* A = 0 , consider the subsets
Au,v = {x ∈ (a, b) | D- f(x) < u < v < D+ f(x) }
of A for all rational numbers u and v satisfying u < v. Since A is the union of this countable family
{Au,v}, it is sufficient to prove m* (Au,v) = 0 for all pairs u, v with u < v.
For this purpose, denote = m* (Au,v) and let be any positive real number. Choose an open set
U ⊃ Au,v with m* U < + . Set x be any point of Au,v . Since D- f(x) < u, there are arbitrary small
closed intervals of the form [x-h, x] contained in U such that
f(x) - f(x-h) < uh.
Do this for all x ∈ Au, v and obtain a Vitali cover C of Au,v. Then by Vitali covering theorem there is a
finite subcollection {J1, J2,…, Jn}of disjoint intervals in C such that
m*(Au,v - ∪ J ) <
Summing over these n intervals, we obtain
− <
< u m*U
< u( + )
Suppose that the interiors of the intervals J1, J2,…, Jn cover a subset F of Au,v. Now since
D+ f(y) > v, there are arbitrarily small closed intervals of the form [y, y+k] contained in some of the
intervals Ji (i = 1, 2,…, n) such that
78 Measure and Integration Theory
f(y+k) − f(y) > vk
Do this for all y ∈ F and obtain a Vitali cover D of F. Then again by Vitali covering lemma we can
select a finite subcollection [K1, K2, …, Km] of disjoint intervals in D such that
m* [F− ∪
Ki ] <
Since m*F > − , it follows that the measure of the subset H of F which is covered by the intervals is
greater than − . Summing over these intervals and keeping in mind that each Ki is contained in a Jn,
we have
− − ≥ ]
+ −
> v
> −
So that
where we re-define f(x) = f(b) for x ≥ b. Then gn(x) → g(x) for almost all x and so g is measurable since
every gn is measurable. Since f is non-decreasing, we have gn ≥ 0. Hence, by
Fatou’s Lemma
b
≤ = n a ( + ) − d
1
b b
= n 1
n
d − a d
an
1 1
b b a b
= n a + b n d − a n d − a d
b
= n a ( + ) − d
≤ f(b)-f(a)
(Use of f(x) = f(b) for x ≥ b for first interval and f non-decreasing in the 2nd integral).
Differentiation and Integration 79
This shows that g is integrable and hence finite almost everywhere. Thus f is differentiable almost
everywhere and g(x) = ́ (x) almost everywhere. This proves the theorem.
Functions of Bounded Variation
Let f be a real-valued function defined on the interval [a,b] and let a = x0 < x1 < x2 < … < xn = b be any
partition of [a,b].
By the variation of f over the partition P = {x 0, x1,…, xn} of [a,b], we mean the real number V(f, P)
= −
and then
Vab(f) = sup {V(f,P) for all possible partitions P of [a,b] }
= −
is called the total variation of f over the interval [a,b]. If Vab(f) < then we say that f is a function of
bounded variation and we write f ∈ BV.
4.4. Lemma. Every non-decreasing function f defined on the interval [a,b] is of bounded variation with
total variation
Vab(f) = f(b) − f(a).
Prof. For every partition P = [x0, x1, …, xn} of [a,b], we have
V(f, P) = − = −
= f(b) - f(a)
This implies the lemma.
4.5.Theorem. (Jordan Decomposition Theorem). A function f: [a,b] → R is of bounded variation if and
only if it is the difference of two non-decreasing functions.
Proof. Let f = g-h on [a,b] with g and h increasing. Then for any, subdivision we have
− ≤ − + −
= g(b) − g(a) + h(b) – h(a)
Hence,
Vab(f) ≤ g(b) − g(a) + h(b) – h(a),
which proves that f is of bounded variations.
On the other hand, let f be of bounded variation. Define two functions g, h : [a, b] →R by taking
g(x) = Vax(f), h(x) = Vax(f) − f(x) for every x ∈ [a, b]. Then f(x) = g(x) − h(x).
The function g is clearly non-decreasing. On the other hand, for any two real numbers x and y in [a, b]
with x ≤ y, we have
h(y)−h(x) = [Vax(f) − f(y)] − [Vax(f) − f(x)]
80 Measure and Integration Theory
(4). Since |f(x)− f(a)| ≤ V(f) for every x on [a,b] it is clear that every function of bounded variation is
bounded.
The Differentiation of an Integral
Let f be integrable over [a,b] and let
x
F(x) = a tdt
If f is positive, h > 0 , then we see that
xh
F(x+h) − F(x) = x tdt
Hence, integral of a positive function is non-decreasing.
We shall show first that F is a function of bounded variation. Then, being function of bounded variation,
it will have a finite differential coefficient F’ almost everywhere. Our object is to prove that ́ (x) = f(x)
almost everywhere in [a,b]. We prove the following lemma :
4.7. Lemma. If f is integrable on [a,b], then the function F defined by
x
F(x) = a tdt
is a continuous function of bounded variation on [a,b].
Proof. We first prove continuity of F. Let x0 be an arbitrary point of [a,b]. Then
Differentiation and Integration 81
x
|F(x) − F(x0)| = | tdt |
0
x
≤ ∫ tdt
0
Now the integrability of f implies integrability of |f| over [a,b]. Therefore, given > 0 there is a
> such that for every measurable set A ⊂[a,b] with measure less than , we have A < .Hence
≤ tdt
1
b
=a tdt
b
Thus Vab(f) ≤ a tdt <
∫ =
F
Proof. We know that an integral is of bounded variation over [a,b] and so F’(x) exists for almost all x in
[a,b]. Let |f| ≤ K. We set
FxhFx
=
h
with h = . Then we have
xh x
= a tdt − a tdt
ℎ
xh
= x tdt
ℎ
xh xh
implies | = x tdt ≤ x tdt
ℎ ℎ
xh
≤ x dt
ℎ
K
= .h=K
h
Moreover,
→
Hence by the theorem of bounded convergence, we have
a d = lim a d = lm ℎ a + − d
ℎ→
h
= lm ah d − a d]
ℎ→ ℎ ℎ
h ah
= lm d − a d]
ℎ→ ℎ ℎ
= F(c) –F(a)
=a d
Hence,
a − d = 0
Differentiation and Integration 83
For all c∈[a,b], and so
F’(x)= f(x) a.e.
By using pervious lemma.
Now we extend the above lemma to unbounded functions.
4.10. Theorem. Let f be an integrable function on [a,b] and suppose that
x
F(x) = F(a) +a dt
is an increasing function of x, which must have a derivative almost everywhere and this derivative will
be non-negative. Also by the above lemma, since fn is bounded (by n), we have
x
a = a.e.
Therefore,
x x
F’(x) = a = G + a
x
= G + a ≥ a.e. (using (i))
Also since F(x) is an increasing real valued function on the interval [a,b], we have
b b
a d ≤ F(b) —F(A) = a d
Hence
b b
a d = F(b) —F(A) = a d
b
implies a − d =
Since F’(x) − f(x) ≥0 , this implies that F’(x)− f(x) = 0 a.e. and so F’(x) = f(x) a.e.
84 Measure and Integration Theory
Absolute Continuity
4.11. Definition. A real-valued function f defined on [a,b] is said to be absolutely continuous on [a,b]
if, given > 0 there is a > 0 such that
∑ − <
An absolutely continuous function is continuous, since we can take the above sum to consist of one term
only. Moreover, if
x
F(x) =a tdt
Then
x x
− = a i tdt − a i tdt
x
= x i tdt
i
x
≤ x i tdt = tdt ,
i
′
| − |
′
= | |
Consider − =
′
≤
<
Conversely, Suppose F is absolutely continuous on [a,b]. Then F is of bounded variation and we may
write
F(x) = F1(x) − F2(x),
where the functions Fi are monotone increasing. Hence F’(x) exists almost everywhere and |F’(x)| ≤
F1’(x) + F2’(x)
Thus ’d ≤ F1(b) + F2(b) − F1(a) − F2(a)
and F’(x) is integrable. Let
x
G(x) = a tdt
Then G is absolutely continuous and so is the function f = F−G. But by the above lemma since
f’(x) = ’– G’= 0 a.e., we have f to be a constant function. That is,
F(x) − G(x) = A (constant)
or
x
F(x) = a tdt = A
or
x
F(x) = a tdt + A